This is a modern-English version of The Soul of Man under Socialism, originally written by Wilde, Oscar. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.



THE
SOUL OF MAN

 

LONDON
ARTHUR L. HUMPREYS
1900

LONDON
ARTHUR L. HUMPHREYS
1900

 

Second Impression

Second Impression

p. 1THE SOUL OF MAN

The chief advantage that would result from the establishment of Socialism is, undoubtedly, the fact that Socialism would relieve us from that sordid necessity of living for others which, in the present condition of things, presses so hardly upon almost everybody.  In fact, scarcely anyone at all escapes.

The main benefit of establishing Socialism is clearly that it would free us from the grim need to live for others, which, in the current situation, weighs heavily on nearly everyone. In reality, hardly anyone escapes this burden.

Now and then, in the course of the century, a great man of science, like Darwin; a great poet, like Keats; a fine critical spirit, like M. Renan; a supreme artist, like Flaubert, has been able to isolate himself, to keep himself out of reach of the clamorous claims of others, to stand ‘under the shelter of the wall,’ as Plato puts it, p. 2and so to realise the perfection of what was in him, to his own incomparable gain, and to the incomparable and lasting gain of the whole world.  These, however, are exceptions.  The majority of people spoil their lives by an unhealthy and exaggerated altruism—are forced, indeed, so to spoil them.  They find themselves surrounded by hideous poverty, by hideous ugliness, by hideous starvation.  It is inevitable that they should be strongly moved by all this.  The emotions of man are stirred more quickly than man’s intelligence; and, as I pointed out some time ago in an article on the function of criticism, it is much more easy to have sympathy with suffering than it is to have sympathy with thought.  Accordingly, with admirable, though misdirected intentions, they very seriously and very sentimentally set themselves to the task of remedying the evils that they see.  But their remedies do not p. 3cure the disease: they merely prolong it.  Indeed, their remedies are part of the disease.

Now and then, over the course of the century, a brilliant scientist, like Darwin; a great poet, like Keats; an insightful critic, like M. Renan; or an exceptional artist, like Flaubert, has managed to distance themselves, to remain out of reach of the loud demands of others, to stand ‘under the shelter of the wall,’ as Plato puts it, p. 2and in doing so, fully realize the greatness within them, benefiting themselves immensely and providing a lasting benefit to the world. However, these are exceptions. Most people ruin their lives with an unhealthy and exaggerated altruism—they are, in fact, compelled to do so. They find themselves surrounded by horrific poverty, ugliness, and starvation. It’s unavoidable that they feel deeply affected by all of this. Human emotions respond more quickly than human intellect; and, as I mentioned some time ago in an article about the role of criticism, it is much easier to empathize with suffering than it is to empathize with thought. As a result, with admirable but misguided intentions, they earnestly and sentimentally take on the task of fixing the problems they see. But their solutions do not p. 3cure the disease: they only prolong it. In fact, their solutions are part of the problem.

They try to solve the problem of poverty, for instance, by keeping the poor alive; or, in the case of a very advanced school, by amusing the poor.

They try to tackle the issue of poverty, for example, by ensuring the poor stay alive; or, in the case of a highly developed institution, by entertaining the poor.

But this is not a solution: it is an aggravation of the difficulty.  The proper aim is to try and reconstruct society on such a basis that poverty will be impossible.  And the altruistic virtues have really prevented the carrying out of this aim.  Just as the worst slave-owners were those who were kind to their slaves, and so prevented the horror of the system being realised by those who suffered from it, and understood by those who contemplated it, so, in the present state of things in England, the people who do most harm are the people who try to do most good; and at last we have had the spectacle of men who have really studied the problem p. 4and know the life—educated men who live in the East End—coming forward and imploring the community to restrain its altruistic impulses of charity, benevolence, and the like.  They do so on the ground that such charity degrades and demoralises.  They are perfectly right.  Charity creates a multitude of sins.

But this isn't a solution; it's just making the problem worse. The real goal should be to rebuild society in a way that makes poverty impossible. Surprisingly, the well-meaning virtues of kindness have actually hindered this goal. Just like the worst slave owners were often the ones who were nice to their slaves, which helped hide the terrible nature of the system from those who suffered and those who thought about it, now in England, the people who do the most harm are the ones who try to do the most good. We've reached a point where educated men who truly understand the issue—living in the East End—are stepping forward and asking the community to hold back its urges for charity, kindness, and similar acts. They argue that such charity degrades and demoralizes people. And they're absolutely correct. Charity leads to many sins.

There is also this to be said.  It is immoral to use private property in order to alleviate the horrible evils that result from the institution of private property.  It is both immoral and unfair.

There’s also this to consider. It’s wrong to use private property to fix the terrible problems that come from having private property in the first place. It’s both unethical and unjust.

Under Socialism all this will, of course, be altered.  There will be no people living in fetid dens and fetid rags, and bringing up unhealthy, hunger-pinched children in the midst of impossible and absolutely repulsive surroundings.  The security of society will not depend, as it does now, on the state of the weather.  If a frost comes we shall not have a hundred p. 5thousand men out of work, tramping about the streets in a state of disgusting misery, or whining to their neighbours for alms, or crowding round the doors of loathsome shelters to try and secure a hunch of bread and a night’s unclean lodging.  Each member of the society will share in the general prosperity and happiness of the society, and if a frost comes no one will practically be anything the worse.

Under Socialism, all of this will definitely change. There won't be people living in filthy places and worn-out clothes, raising unhealthy, starving children in totally appalling conditions. Society's safety won't depend, like it does now, on the weather. If a frost hits, we won't have a hundred thousand people out of work, wandering the streets in utter misery, begging their neighbors for help, or crowding around the doors of dreadful shelters trying to get a piece of bread and a dirty place to sleep. Everyone in society will benefit from its shared prosperity and happiness, and if a frost comes, it won't negatively affect anyone.

Upon the other hand, Socialism itself will be of value simply because it will lead to Individualism.

On the other hand, Socialism will be valuable simply because it will lead to Individualism.

Socialism, Communism, or whatever one chooses to call it, by converting private property into public wealth, and substituting co-operation for competition, will restore society to its proper condition of a thoroughly healthy organism, and insure the material well-being of each member of the community.  It will, in fact, give Life its proper basis and its proper p. 6environment.  But for the full development of Life to its highest mode of perfection, something more is needed.  What is needed is Individualism.  If the Socialism is Authoritarian; if there are Governments armed with economic power as they are now with political power; if, in a word, we are to have Industrial Tyrannies, then the last state of man will be worse than the first.  At present, in consequence of the existence of private property, a great many people are enabled to develop a certain very limited amount of Individualism.  They are either under no necessity to work for their living, or are enabled to choose the sphere of activity that is really congenial to them, and gives them pleasure.  These are the poets, the philosophers, the men of science, the men of culture—in a word, the real men, the men who have realised themselves, and in whom all Humanity gains a partial p. 7realisation.  Upon the other hand, there are a great many people who, having no private property of their own, and being always on the brink of sheer starvation, are compelled to do the work of beasts of burden, to do work that is quite uncongenial to them, and to which they are forced by the peremptory, unreasonable, degrading Tyranny of want.  These are the poor, and amongst them there is no grace of manner, or charm of speech, or civilisation, or culture, or refinement in pleasures, or joy of life.  From their collective force Humanity gains much in material prosperity.  But it is only the material result that it gains, and the man who is poor is in himself absolutely of no importance.  He is merely the infinitesimal atom of a force that, so far from regarding him, crushes him: indeed, prefers him crushed, as in that case he is far more obedient.

Socialism, Communism, or whatever you want to call it, by turning private property into public wealth and promoting cooperation over competition, will bring society back to its rightful condition as a healthy organism and ensure the material well-being of every member of the community. It will, in fact, give Life its proper foundation and its proper p. 6environment. However, to fully develop Life to its highest level of perfection, we need something more. What’s needed is Individualism. If Socialism becomes Authoritarian; if we have Governments wielding economic power just like they do political power; if we end up with Industrial Tyrannies, then humanity's situation will become worse than before. Right now, because of private property, many people can develop a limited form of Individualism. They either aren't forced to work for a living, or they can choose work that they actually enjoy and find fulfilling. These are the poets, the philosophers, the scientists, the cultured individuals—in short, the real people, the ones who have realized their potential, and through whom all Humanity gains a partial p. 7realization. On the other hand, a lot of people, who don’t have any private property and are always on the edge of starvation, are forced to do menial work that doesn't suit them, compelled by the harsh, unreasonable, and dehumanizing Tyranny of need. These are the poor, and among them, there’s a lack of grace, charm, culture, refinement, or joy in life. Humanity benefits in material wealth from their collective effort. But it only gains material results, and a poor person is essentially of no significance. They are just a tiny part of a force that, instead of recognizing them, crushes them; in fact, it prefers them crushed since that makes them more obedient.

Of course, it might be said that the p. 8Individualism generated under conditions of private property is not always, or even as a rule, of a fine or wonderful type, and that the poor, if they have not culture and charm, have still many virtues.  Both these statements would be quite true.  The possession of private property is very often extremely demoralising, and that is, of course, one of the reasons why Socialism wants to get rid of the institution.  In fact, property is really a nuisance.  Some years ago people went about the country saying that property has duties.  They said it so often and so tediously that, at last, the Church has begun to say it.  One hears it now from every pulpit.  It is perfectly true.  Property not merely has duties, but has so many duties that its possession to any large extent is a bore.  It involves endless claims upon one, endless attention to business, endless bother.  If property had simply pleasures, we could stand p. 9it; but its duties make it unbearable.  In the interest of the rich we must get rid of it.  The virtues of the poor may be readily admitted, and are much to be regretted.  We are often told that the poor are grateful for charity.  Some of them are, no doubt, but the best amongst the poor are never grateful.  They are ungrateful, discontented, disobedient, and rebellious.  They are quite right to be so.  Charity they feel to be a ridiculously inadequate mode of partial restitution, or a sentimental dole, usually accompanied by some impertinent attempt on the part of the sentimentalist to tyrannise over their private lives.  Why should they be grateful for the crumbs that fall from the rich man’s table?  They should be seated at the board, and are beginning to know it.  As for being discontented, a man who would not be discontented with such surroundings and such a low mode of life would be a perfect brute.  Disobedience, p. 10in the eyes of anyone who has read history, is man’s original virtue.  It is through disobedience that progress has been made, through disobedience and through rebellion.  Sometimes the poor are praised for being thrifty.  But to recommend thrift to the poor is both grotesque and insulting.  It is like advising a man who is starving to eat less.  For a town or country labourer to practise thrift would be absolutely immoral.  Man should not be ready to show that he can live like a badly-fed animal.  He should decline to live like that, and should either steal or go on the rates, which is considered by many to be a form of stealing.  As for begging, it is safer to beg than to take, but it is finer to take than to beg.  No: a poor man who is ungrateful, unthrifty, discontented, and rebellious, is probably a real personality, and has much in him.  He is at any rate a healthy protest.  As for the virtuous p. 11poor, one can pity them, of course, but one cannot possibly admire them.  They have made private terms with the enemy, and sold their birthright for very bad pottage.  They must also be extraordinarily stupid.  I can quite understand a man accepting laws that protect private property, and admit of its accumulation, as long as he himself is able under those conditions to realise some form of beautiful and intellectual life.  But it is almost incredible to me how a man whose life is marred and made hideous by such laws can possibly acquiesce in their continuance.

Of course, it could be argued that the p. 8individualism that arises from private property isn't usually a great or admirable kind, and that the poor, while they may lack culture and charm, still have many virtues. Both claims are quite valid. Owning private property often leads to moral decay, which is one reason Socialism aims to eliminate it. In reality, property can be quite a hassle. Not long ago, people traveled around saying that property entails responsibilities. They repeated this so often and so boringly that eventually the Church started echoing it. You now hear it from every pulpit. It’s absolutely true. Property not only comes with responsibilities, but those responsibilities can become so overwhelming that owning a lot of it becomes tedious. It requires constant claims on your attention, endless business dealings, and ongoing frustrations. If property only brought enjoyment, we could manage it; however, its responsibilities make it intolerable. For the sake of the wealthy, we need to eliminate it. The virtues of the poor are acknowledged and deeply missed. We often hear that the poor are grateful for charity. Some might be, but the best among them are rarely thankful. They are ungrateful, discontent, defiant, and rebellious—rightly so. Charity feels to them like a pathetically insufficient attempt at partial restitution, or a sentimental handout often accompanied by some intrusive effort from the giver to control their private lives. Why should they be thankful for scraps that fall from the rich man’s table? They deserve a seat at the table, and they are starting to realize it. As for their discontent, anyone who wouldn't be discontent with such conditions and a meager way of life would be a complete brute. Disobedience, p. 10for those who know history, is man's original virtue. Progress has been made through disobedience and rebellion. Sometimes the poor are praised for being frugal. But urging thriftiness upon the poor is both absurd and insulting. It’s like telling a starving man to eat less. For a laborer in a town or country to practice thrift would be utterly immoral. A person shouldn't show he can live like a poorly fed animal. He should refuse to live that way and either steal or rely on welfare, which many consider a form of stealing. As for begging, it's safer to ask for help than to take, but taking is nobler than begging. No, a poor person who is ungrateful, unfrugal, discontent, and rebellious likely has a strong character and is full of potential. At the very least, he represents a healthy resistance. As for the virtuous p. 11poor, one can feel pity for them, but admiration is impossible. They’ve made a deal with the enemy and sold their right to a better life for a very poor reward. They must also be incredibly foolish. I can understand a person accepting laws that protect private property and allow it to accumulate, as long as they can find some form of beautiful and intellectual life under those conditions. But it’s almost unbelievable to me how someone whose life is marred and made miserable by those laws could possibly agree to let them continue.

However, the explanation is not really difficult to find.  It is simply this.  Misery and poverty are so absolutely degrading, and exercise such a paralysing effect over the nature of men, that no class is ever really conscious of its own suffering.  They have to be told of it by other people, and they often entirely disbelieve them.  p. 12What is said by great employers of labour against agitators is unquestionably true.  Agitators are a set of interfering, meddling people, who come down to some perfectly contented class of the community, and sow the seeds of discontent amongst them.  That is the reason why agitators are so absolutely necessary.  Without them, in our incomplete state, there would be no advance towards civilisation.  Slavery was put down in America, not in consequence of any action on the part of the slaves, or even any express desire on their part that they should be free.  It was put down entirely through the grossly illegal conduct of certain agitators in Boston and elsewhere, who were not slaves themselves, nor owners of slaves, nor had anything to do with the question really.  It was, undoubtedly, the Abolitionists who set the torch alight, who began the whole thing.  And it is curious to p. 13note that from the slaves themselves they received, not merely very little assistance, but hardly any sympathy even; and when at the close of the war the slaves found themselves free, found themselves indeed so absolutely free that they were free to starve, many of them bitterly regretted the new state of things.  To the thinker, the most tragic fact in the whole of the French Revolution is not that Marie Antoinette was killed for being a queen, but that the starved peasant of the Vendée voluntarily went out to die for the hideous cause of feudalism.

However, the explanation isn’t really hard to find. It’s simply this: misery and poverty are so degrading and have such a paralyzing effect on people that no group is ever truly aware of its own suffering. They need others to point it out, and they often completely disbelieve them. p. 12 What employers of labor say about agitators is undeniably true. Agitators are a group of intrusive, meddlesome individuals who come into a perfectly content community and plant the seeds of discontent among them. That’s why agitators are absolutely necessary. Without them, in our incomplete state, there would be no progress toward civilization. Slavery was abolished in America, not because of any action from the slaves or any genuine desire on their part to be free. It was solely due to the grossly illegal actions of certain agitators in Boston and elsewhere, who themselves were neither slaves nor slave owners, nor did they truly have anything to do with the issue. It was undoubtedly the Abolitionists who set things in motion. Interestingly, p. 13 they received not just very little assistance but hardly any sympathy from the slaves themselves; and when, at the end of the war, the slaves found themselves free—so completely free that they were free to starve—many regretted their new situation. To a thoughtful person, the most tragic aspect of the entire French Revolution isn’t that Marie Antoinette was killed for being a queen, but that the starving peasants of the Vendée willingly went out to die for the grotesque cause of feudalism.

It is clear, then, that no Authoritarian Socialism will do.  For while under the present system a very large number of people can lead lives of a certain amount of freedom and expression and happiness, under an industrial-barrack system, or a system of economic tyranny, nobody would be able to have any such freedom p. 14at all.  It is to be regretted that a portion of our community should be practically in slavery, but to propose to solve the problem by enslaving the entire community is childish.  Every man must be left quite free to choose his own work.  No form of compulsion must be exercised over him.  If there is, his work will not be good for him, will not be good in itself, and will not be good for others.  And by work I simply mean activity of any kind.

It’s clear that Authoritarian Socialism won't work. While a large number of people can have a certain degree of freedom, expression, and happiness under the current system, in an industrial-barrack system or a system of economic oppression, no one would have any freedom at all. It’s unfortunate that part of our community lives in conditions close to slavery, but suggesting that we fix this by enslaving everyone is foolish. Everyone should have the freedom to choose their own work. No one should be forced into it. If there is, their work won't be fulfilling for them, won’t be good in itself, and won’t benefit others. By work, I simply mean any form of activity.

I hardly think that any Socialist, nowadays, would seriously propose that an inspector should call every morning at each house to see that each citizen rose up and did manual labour for eight hours.  Humanity has got beyond that stage, and reserves such a form of life for the people whom, in a very arbitrary manner, it chooses to call criminals.  But I confess that many of the socialistic views that I have come across p. 15seem to me to be tainted with ideas of authority, if not of actual compulsion.  Of course, authority and compulsion are out of the question.  All association must be quite voluntary.  It is only in voluntary associations that man is fine.

I seriously doubt that any Socialist today would actually suggest that an inspector should show up at every house each morning to ensure that every citizen gets up and does manual labor for eight hours. Humanity has moved past that, and only reserves that kind of life for those who are arbitrarily labeled as criminals. However, I must admit that many of the socialist ideas I've encountered p. 15seem to carry a sense of authority, if not outright coercion. Obviously, authority and coercion are not acceptable. All cooperation must be completely voluntary. It's only in voluntary associations that people truly excel.

But it may be asked how Individualism, which is now more or less dependent on the existence of private property for its development, will benefit by the abolition of such private property.  The answer is very simple.  It is true that, under existing conditions, a few men who have had private means of their own, such as Byron, Shelley, Browning, Victor Hugo, Baudelaire, and others, have been able to realise their personality more or less completely.  Not one of these men ever did a single day’s work for hire.  They were relieved from poverty.  They had an immense advantage.  The question is whether it would be for the good of Individualism p. 16that such an advantage should be taken away.  Let us suppose that it is taken away.  What happens then to Individualism?  How will it benefit?

But you might wonder how Individualism, which currently relies on private property for its growth, would gain from the abolition of private property. The answer is quite straightforward. It’s true that, under the current circumstances, a few individuals who had their own private resources, like Byron, Shelley, Browning, Victor Hugo, Baudelaire, and others, managed to fully realize their personalities. None of these men worked a single day for wages. They were free from financial struggles. They had a significant advantage. The question is whether it would benefit Individualism that such an advantage is removed. Let’s assume that it is removed. What then happens to Individualism? How will it benefit?

It will benefit in this way.  Under the new conditions Individualism will be far freer, far finer, and far more intensified than it is now.  I am not talking of the great imaginatively-realised Individualism of such poets as I have mentioned, but of the great actual Individualism latent and potential in mankind generally.  For the recognition of private property has really harmed Individualism, and obscured it, by confusing a man with what he possesses.  It has led Individualism entirely astray.  It has made gain not growth its aim.  So that man thought that the important thing was to have, and did not know that the important thing is to be.  The true perfection of man lies, not in what man has, but in what man is.  p. 17Private property has crushed true Individualism, and set up an Individualism that is false.  It has debarred one part of the community from being individual by starving them.  It has debarred the other part of the community from being individual by putting them on the wrong road, and encumbering them.  Indeed, so completely has man’s personality been absorbed by his possessions that the English law has always treated offences against a man’s property with far more severity than offences against his person, and property is still the test of complete citizenship.  The industry necessary for the making money is also very demoralising.  In a community like ours, where property confers immense distinction, social position, honour, respect, titles, and other pleasant things of the kind, man, being naturally ambitious, makes it his aim to accumulate this property, and goes on wearily and tediously p. 18accumulating it long after he has got far more than he wants, or can use, or enjoy, or perhaps even know of.  Man will kill himself by overwork in order to secure property, and really, considering the enormous advantages that property brings, one is hardly surprised.  One’s regret is that society should be constructed on such a basis that man has been forced into a groove in which he cannot freely develop what is wonderful, and fascinating, and delightful in him—in which, in fact, he misses the true pleasure and joy of living.  He is also, under existing conditions, very insecure.  An enormously wealthy merchant may be—often is—at every moment of his life at the mercy of things that are not under his control.  If the wind blows an extra point or so, or the weather suddenly changes, or some trivial thing happens, his ship may go down, his speculations may go wrong, and he finds himself a poor p. 19man, with his social position quite gone.  Now, nothing should be able to harm a man except himself.  Nothing should be able to rob a man at all.  What a man really has, is what is in him.  What is outside of him should be a matter of no importance.

It will benefit in this way. Under the new conditions, individualism will be much freer, finer, and more intense than it is now. I’m not talking about the rich, creatively-expressed individualism of poets I’ve mentioned, but about the significant, actual individualism that lies latent and potential in humanity as a whole. The acknowledgment of private property has harmed individualism, obscuring it by confusing a person with what they own. It has completely misled individualism. It has made accumulation, rather than personal growth, the goal. So, people think the important thing is to have, not realizing the essential thing is to be. The true perfection of a person lies not in what they have, but in who they are. p. 17 Private property has crushed true individualism, establishing a false version of it. It has prevented one part of the community from being individuals by leaving them impoverished. It has hindered another part by leading them down the wrong path and burdening them. Indeed, so completely has a person's identity merged with their possessions that English law has always treated crimes against a person’s property far more severely than crimes against their person, and property remains the measure of full citizenship. The effort needed to make money is also very demoralizing. In a society like ours, where property brings great distinction, social status, honor, respect, titles, and other desirable things, people, naturally ambitious, aim to acquire property, often accumulating it long after they have more than they need, can use, enjoy, or even know about. People will work themselves to death to secure property, and honestly, given the vast advantages property provides, it’s hardly surprising. What’s regrettable is that society is built on such a foundation that people are forced into a rut where they can’t freely develop the wonderful, fascinating, and delightful aspects of themselves—in which they miss the true pleasure and joy of living. They are also, in these current conditions, very insecure. An extremely wealthy merchant may be—often is—at the mercy of factors beyond their control at any moment. If the wind shifts a bit, or the weather suddenly changes, or some minor event occurs, their ship might sink, their investments might fail, and they find themselves poor p. 19 with their social status completely gone. Now, nothing should harm a person except themselves. Nothing should be able to rob a person at all. What a person truly has is what’s within them. What’s outside of them should not matter.

With the abolition of private property, then, we shall have true, beautiful, healthy Individualism.  Nobody will waste his life in accumulating things, and the symbols for things.  One will live.  To live is the rarest thing in the world.  Most people exist, that is all.

With the end of private property, we will achieve true, beautiful, healthy Individualism. No one will waste their life hoarding possessions and their symbols. People will actually live. Living is the rarest thing in the world. Most people just exist, and that's it.

It is a question whether we have ever seen the full expression of a personality, except on the imaginative plane of art.  In action, we never have.  Cæsar, says Mommsen, was the complete and perfect man.  But how tragically insecure was Cæsar!  Wherever there is a man who exercises authority, there is a man who resists authority.  Cæsar was very perfect, p. 20but his perfection travelled by too dangerous a road.  Marcus Aurelius was the perfect man, says Renan.  Yes; the great emperor was a perfect man.  But how intolerable were the endless claims upon him!  He staggered under the burden of the empire.  He was conscious how inadequate one man was to bear the weight of that Titan and too vast orb.  What I mean by a perfect man is one who develops under perfect conditions; one who is not wounded, or worried or maimed, or in danger.  Most personalities have been obliged to be rebels.  Half their strength has been wasted in friction.  Byron’s personality, for instance, was terribly wasted in its battle with the stupidity, and hypocrisy, and Philistinism of the English.  Such battles do not always intensify strength: they often exaggerate weakness.  Byron was never able to give us what he might have given us.  Shelley escaped better.  Like Byron, he got out of p. 21England as soon as possible.  But he was not so well known.  If the English had had any idea of what a great poet he really was, they would have fallen on him with tooth and nail, and made his life as unbearable to him as they possibly could.  But he was not a remarkable figure in society, and consequently he escaped, to a certain degree.  Still, even in Shelley the note of rebellion is sometimes too strong.  The note of the perfect personality is not rebellion, but peace.

It's debatable whether we've ever truly witnessed the complete expression of a personality, except in the creative realm of art. In real life, we haven't. Cæsar, according to Mommsen, was the ideal man. But how tragically insecure was Cæsar! Wherever there's someone in power, there's also someone who opposes them. Cæsar was very perfect, p. 20 but his perfection came via a perilous path. Marcus Aurelius was the perfect man, Renan says. Yes, the great emperor was indeed a perfect man. But how overwhelming were the constant demands placed on him! He struggled under the weight of the empire. He understood how one person couldn’t handle the enormous pressure of that Titan and vast sphere. What I mean by a perfect man is someone who develops under ideal conditions; someone who isn’t hurt, worried, crippled, or in jeopardy. Most personalities have had to become rebels. A lot of their energy has been lost in conflict. Byron’s personality, for example, was severely diminished in its struggle against the ignorance, hypocrisy, and narrow-mindedness of the English. Such conflicts don’t always boost strength; often, they amplify weaknesses. Byron was never able to provide us with what he could have. Shelley had a better escape. Like Byron, he left p. 21 England as soon as he could. But he wasn’t as well known. If the English had realized what a great poet he was, they would have attacked him fiercely and made his life as miserable as possible. But since he wasn't a prominent figure in society, he managed to evade some of that pressure. Still, even in Shelley, the rebellious tone can sometimes be too strong. The essence of the perfect personality is not rebellion, but peace.

It will be a marvellous thing—the true personality of man—when we see it.  It will grow naturally and simply, flowerlike, or as a tree grows.  It will not be at discord.  It will never argue or dispute.  It will not prove things.  It will know everything.  And yet it will not busy itself about knowledge.  It will have wisdom.  Its value will not be measured by material things.  It will have nothing.  And yet it will have everything, and whatever p. 22one takes from it, it will still have, so rich will it be.  It will not be always meddling with others, or asking them to be like itself.  It will love them because they will be different.  And yet while it will not meddle with others, it will help all, as a beautiful thing helps us, by being what it is.  The personality of man will be very wonderful.  It will be as wonderful as the personality of a child.

It will be an incredible thing—the true essence of humanity—when we finally see it. It will grow naturally and effortlessly, like a flower or a tree. It won’t be in conflict. It will never argue or dispute. It won’t need to prove anything. It will simply know everything. Yet, it won’t be preoccupied with knowledge. It will possess wisdom. Its worth won’t be determined by material possessions. It will have nothing. And yet, it will have everything, and whatever p. 22is taken from it, it will still have, so rich will it be. It won't constantly interfere with others or try to make them like itself. It will love them for their differences. And while it won’t meddle, it will assist everyone, like a beautiful thing does, just by being itself. The essence of humanity will be truly remarkable. It will be as remarkable as the spirit of a child.

In its development it will be assisted by Christianity, if men desire that; but if men do not desire that, it will develop none the less surely.  For it will not worry itself about the past, nor care whether things happened or did not happen.  Nor will it admit any laws but its own laws; nor any authority but its own authority.  Yet it will love those who sought to intensify it, and speak often of them.  And of these Christ was one.

In its development, it will be supported by Christianity, if people want that; but if they don’t, it will still progress just as surely. It won’t concern itself with the past or worry about whether things happened or didn’t happen. It won’t accept any laws but its own, or any authority but its own. Still, it will appreciate those who tried to enhance it and will often talk about them. Among them, Christ was one.

p. 23‘Know thyself’ was written over the portal of the antique world.  Over the portal of the new world, ‘Be thyself’ shall be written.  And the message of Christ to man was simply ‘Be thyself.’  That is the secret of Christ.

p. 23“Know yourself” was inscribed over the entrance to the ancient world. Over the entrance to the modern world, “Be yourself” will be written. And the essence of Christ's message to humanity was simply “Be yourself.” That is the secret of Christ.

When Jesus talks about the poor he simply means personalities, just as when he talks about the rich he simply means people who have not developed their personalities.  Jesus moved in a community that allowed the accumulation of private property just as ours does, and the gospel that he preached was not that in such a community it is an advantage for a man to live on scanty, unwholesome food, to wear ragged, unwholesome clothes, to sleep in horrid, unwholesome dwellings, and a disadvantage for a man to live under healthy, pleasant, and decent conditions.  Such a view would have been wrong there and then, and would, of course, be still p. 24more wrong now and in England; for as man moves northward the material necessities of life become of more vital importance, and our society is infinitely more complex, and displays far greater extremes of luxury and pauperism than any society of the antique world.  What Jesus meant, was this.  He said to man, ‘You have a wonderful personality.  Develop it.  Be yourself.  Don’t imagine that your perfection lies in accumulating or possessing external things.  Your affection is inside of you.  If only you could realise that, you would not want to be rich.  Ordinary riches can be stolen from a man.  Real riches cannot.  In the treasury-house of your soul, there are infinitely precious things, that may not be taken from you.  And so, try to so shape your life that external things will not harm you.  And try also to get rid of personal property.  It involves sordid preoccupation, endless industry, continual wrong.  Personal p. 25property hinders Individualism at every step.’  It is to be noted that Jesus never says that impoverished people are necessarily good, or wealthy people necessarily bad.  That would not have been true.  Wealthy people are, as a class, better than impoverished people, more moral, more intellectual, more well-behaved.  There is only one class in the community that thinks more about money than the rich, and that is the poor.  The poor can think of nothing else.  That is the misery of being poor.  What Jesus does say is that man reaches his perfection, not through what he has, not even through what he does, but entirely through what he is.  And so the wealthy young man who comes to Jesus is represented as a thoroughly good citizen, who has broken none of the laws of his state, none of the commandments of his religion.  He is quite respectable, in the ordinary sense of that extraordinary word.  Jesus says p. 26to him, ‘You should give up private property.  It hinders you from realising your perfection.  It is a drag upon you.  It is a burden.  Your personality does not need it.  It is within you, and not outside of you, that you will find what you really are, and what you really want.’  To his own friends he says the same thing.  He tells them to be themselves, and not to be always worrying about other things.  What do other things matter?  Man is complete in himself.  When they go into the world, the world will disagree with them.  That is inevitable.  The world hates Individualism.  But that is not to trouble them.  They are to be calm and self-centred.  If a man takes their cloak, they are to give him their coat, just to show that material things are of no importance.  If people abuse them, they are not to answer back.  What does it signify?  The things people say of a man do not alter a man.  He is what he is.  p. 27Public opinion is of no value whatsoever.  Even if people employ actual violence, they are not to be violent in turn.  That would be to fall to the same low level.  After all, even in prison, a man can be quite free.  His soul can be free.  His personality can be untroubled.  He can be at peace.  And, above all things, they are not to interfere with other people or judge them in any way.  Personality is a very mysterious thing.  A man cannot always be estimated by what he does.  He may keep the law, and yet be worthless.  He may break the law, and yet be fine.  He may be bad, without ever doing anything bad.  He may commit a sin against society, and yet realise through that sin his true perfection.

When Jesus speaks about the poor, he’s referring to personal qualities, just as when he discusses the rich, he’s talking about people who haven’t fully developed themselves. Jesus lived in a community that allowed private property, just like ours, and the gospel he preached wasn’t that it's better for a person to live on meager, unhealthy food, wear tattered and unclean clothes, or sleep in terrible, unhealthy places, while it's worse for someone to live in healthy, nice, and decent conditions. Such a belief would have been misguided back then and is, of course, even more misguided now, especially in England; as people move north, the basic needs of life become more crucial, and our society is far more complex, showing much greater extremes of wealth and poverty than any ancient society. What Jesus really meant was this: He told people, ‘You have a fantastic personality. Cultivate it. Be true to yourself. Don’t think your fulfillment lies in acquiring or owning external things. Your true value is within you. If you could truly understand that, you wouldn’t desire to be rich. Physical wealth can be taken from a person. True wealth cannot. In the treasury of your soul, there are priceless things that cannot be taken away from you. So, strive to shape your life in a way that external things won’t harm you. Also, try to rid yourself of personal possessions. They bring dirty distractions, endless effort, and constant wrongdoings. Personal property blocks Individualism at every turn.’ It’s important to note that Jesus never claims that poor people are necessarily good or that wealthy people are necessarily bad. That wouldn’t be true. Wealthy individuals, as a group, are often better than the poor—more moral, more educated, more well-behaved. The only group in society that thinks about money more than the rich is the poor. The poor can’t think of anything else. That’s the tragedy of being poor. What Jesus says is that a person achieves their true self, not through what they own or even what they do, but solely through who they are. Thus, the wealthy young man who approaches Jesus is portrayed as a thoroughly good citizen, who hasn’t broken any of the laws of his country or the commandments of his faith. He is quite respectable in the conventional sense of that word. Jesus tells him, ‘You should let go of personal possessions. They prevent you from seeing your true self. They hold you back. Your personality doesn’t need them. You will find your true self and what you truly desire within you, not outside of you.’ He shares the same message with his friends, encouraging them to be themselves and not constantly fret over external matters. What do those matters really mean? A person is whole in themselves. When they venture into the world, it’s inevitable that the world will oppose them. The world despises Individualism. But that shouldn’t trouble them. They should remain calm and centered. If someone takes their cloak, they should give him their coat as well, to show that material possessions aren’t important. If people insult them, they shouldn’t retaliate. What does it matter? What others say about a person doesn’t change who they are. They are who they are. Public opinion holds no real value. Even if people resort to physical violence, they shouldn’t respond with violence. That would just bring them down to the same low level. After all, even in prison, a person can still be free. Their soul can be free. Their personality can remain undisturbed. They can find peace. And above all, they shouldn’t interfere with others or judge them in any way. Personality is a very complex thing. A person can’t always be judged by their actions. They may abide by the law and still be worthless. They may break the law and yet be admirable. They may be bad without ever doing anything wrong. They might commit a societal sin and still achieve their true perfection through that wrongdoing.

There was a woman who was taken in adultery.  We are not told the history of her love, but that love must have been very great; for Jesus said that her sins were forgiven her, p. 28not because she repented, but because her love was so intense and wonderful.  Later on, a short time before his death, as he sat at a feast, the woman came in and poured costly perfumes on his hair.  His friends tried to interfere with her, and said that it was an extravagance, and that the money that the perfume cost should have been expended on charitable relief of people in want, or something of that kind.  Jesus did not accept that view.  He pointed out that the material needs of Man were great and very permanent, but that the spiritual needs of Man were greater still, and that in one divine moment, and by selecting its own mode of expression, a personality might make itself perfect.  The world worships the woman, even now, as a saint.

There was a woman caught in adultery. We don't know her backstory, but her love must have been immense; Jesus said her sins were forgiven, not because she repented, but because her love was so profound and beautiful. Later, just before his death, while he was at a feast, the woman came in and poured expensive perfume on his hair. His friends tried to stop her, arguing that it was a waste and that the money spent on the perfume should have gone to help those in need or something similar. Jesus disagreed. He pointed out that while people's physical needs are significant and ongoing, their spiritual needs are even greater, and in a single divine moment, through its chosen form of expression, a person can achieve perfection. The world still honors the woman as a saint.

Yes; there are suggestive things in Individualism.  Socialism annihilates family life, for instance.  With the p. 29abolition of private property, marriage in its present form must disappear.  This is part of the programme.  Individualism accepts this and makes it fine.  It converts the abolition of legal restraint into a form of freedom that will help the full development of personality, and make the love of man and woman more wonderful, more beautiful, and more ennobling.  Jesus knew this.  He rejected the claims of family life, although they existed in his day and community in a very marked form.  ‘Who is my mother?  Who are my brothers?’ he said, when he was told that they wished to speak to him.  When one of his followers asked leave to go and bury his father, ‘Let the dead bury the dead,’ was his terrible answer.  He would allow no claim whatsoever to be made on personality.

Yes; there are suggestive ideas in Individualism. Socialism destroys family life, for example. With the abolition of private property, marriage in its current form has to go. This is part of the plan. Individualism acknowledges this and celebrates it. It transforms the removal of legal restrictions into a type of freedom that will promote the full development of personality and make the love between a man and a woman more wonderful, more beautiful, and more uplifting. Jesus understood this. He dismissed the importance of family life, even though it was very prominent in his time and community. "Who is my mother? Who are my brothers?" he asked when told they wanted to speak to him. When one of his followers asked to go and bury his father, his harsh reply was, "Let the dead bury the dead." He wouldn’t allow any claims to be made on personality.

And so he who would lead a Christlike life is he who is perfectly and absolutely himself.  He may be a p. 30great poet, or a great man of science; or a young student at a University, or one who watches sheep upon a moor; or a maker of dramas, like Shakespeare, or a thinker about God, like Spinoza; or a child who plays in a garden, or a fisherman who throws his net into the sea.  It does not matter what he is, as long as he realises the perfection of the soul that is within him.  All imitation in morals and in life is wrong.  Through the streets of Jerusalem at the present day crawls one who is mad and carries a wooden cross on his shoulders.  He is a symbol of the lives that are marred by imitation.  Father Damien was Christlike when he went out to live with the lepers, because in such service he realised fully what was best in him.  But he was not more Christlike than Wagner when he realised his soul in music; or than Shelley, when he realised his soul in song.  There is no one type for man.  p. 31There are as many perfections as there are imperfect men.  And while to the claims of charity a man may yield and yet be free, to the claims of conformity no man may yield and remain free at all.

So, someone who wants to live a Christlike life is someone who is fully and completely themselves. They could be a p. 30great poet, a brilliant scientist, a college student, a shepherd on a moor, a playwright like Shakespeare, a philosopher like Spinoza, a child playing in a garden, or a fisherman casting his net into the sea. It doesn’t really matter what they do, as long as they recognize the perfection of the soul within them. Imitating others in morals and life is wrong. Currently, through the streets of Jerusalem, there's someone who is mad and carries a wooden cross on their shoulders. They symbolize lives that are damaged by imitation. Father Damien was Christlike when he chose to live with the lepers because, in that service, he fully realized what was best in him. But he wasn’t more Christlike than Wagner when he expressed his soul through music, or than Shelley when he expressed his soul through song. There isn’t just one way to be human. p. 31There are as many forms of perfection as there are imperfect people. While a person may yield to the demands of charity and still be free, no one can yield to the demands of conformity and remain free at all.

Individualism, then, is what through Socialism we are to attain to.  As a natural result the State must give up all idea of government.  It must give it up because, as a wise man once said many centuries before Christ, there is such a thing as leaving mankind alone; there is no such thing as governing mankind.  All modes of government are failures.  Despotism is unjust to everybody, including the despot, who was probably made for better things.  Oligarchies are unjust to the many, and ochlocracies are unjust to the few.  High hopes were once formed of democracy; but democracy means simply the bludgeoning of the people by the people for the people.  It has been found out.  I must say p. 32that it was high time, for all authority is quite degrading.  It degrades those who exercise it, and degrades those over whom it is exercised.  When it is violently, grossly, and cruelly used, it produces a good effect, by creating, or at any rate bringing out, the spirit of revolt and Individualism that is to kill it.  When it is used with a certain amount of kindness, and accompanied by prizes and rewards, it is dreadfully demoralising.  People, in that case, are less conscious of the horrible pressure that is being put on them, and so go through their lives in a sort of coarse comfort, like petted animals, without ever realising that they are probably thinking other people’s thoughts, living by other people’s standards, wearing practically what one may call other people’s second-hand clothes, and never being themselves for a single moment.  ‘He who would be free,’ says a fine thinker, ‘must not conform.’  And authority, p. 33by bribing people to conform, produces a very gross kind of over-fed barbarism amongst us.

Individualism is what we should achieve through Socialism. As a natural consequence, the State must abandon any idea of governance. It must do this because, as a wise person remarked many centuries before Christ, there's a way to leave people alone, but there's no real way to govern them. All forms of government fail. Despotism is unfair to everyone, including the despot, who was probably meant for better things. Oligarchies are unfair to the majority, and ochlocracies are unfair to the minority. Great hopes were once pinned on democracy; yet democracy is simply the oppression of the people by their own kind for the sake of the people. This has been realized. I must say p. 32 it was about time, as all authority is degrading. It degrades those who wield it and those it is wielded over. When it is used violently, crudely, and cruelly, it can have a beneficial effect by sparking the spirit of revolt and Individualism that aims to destroy it. When it's applied with a degree of kindness and paired with rewards, it becomes incredibly demoralizing. In such cases, people are less aware of the awful pressure exerted on them, and they drift through life in a sort of dull comfort, like pampered pets, oblivious to the fact that they are likely thinking other people's thoughts, living by other people's standards, and essentially wearing what could be called other people's cast-offs, never being themselves even for a second. ‘He who wishes to be free,’ says an insightful thinker, ‘must not conform.’ And authority, p. 33 by bribing people to conform, creates a very crude form of over-indulged barbarism among us.

With authority, punishment will pass away.  This will be a great gain—a gain, in fact, of incalculable value.  As one reads history, not in the expurgated editions written for school-boys and passmen, but in the original authorities of each time, one is absolutely sickened, not by the crimes that the wicked have committed, but by the punishments that the good have inflicted; and a community is infinitely more brutalised by the habitual employment of punishment, than it is by the occurrence of crime.  It obviously follows that the more punishment is inflicted the more crime is produced, and most modern legislation has clearly recognised this, and has made it its task to diminish punishment as far as it thinks it can.  Wherever it has really diminished it, the results have always been extremely p. 34good.  The less punishment, the less crime.  When there is no punishment at all, crime will either cease to exist, or, if it occurs, will be treated by physicians as a very distressing form of dementia, to be cured by care and kindness.  For what are called criminals nowadays are not criminals at all.  Starvation, and not sin, is the parent of modern crime.  That indeed is the reason why our criminals are, as a class, so absolutely uninteresting from any psychological point of view.  They are not marvellous Macbeths and terrible Vautrins.  They are merely what ordinary, respectable, commonplace people would be if they had not got enough to eat.  When private property is abolished there will be no necessity for crime, no demand for it; it will cease to exist.  Of course, all crimes are not crimes against property, though such are the crimes that the English law, valuing what a man has more than what a p. 35man is, punishes with the harshest and most horrible severity, if we except the crime of murder, and regard death as worse than penal servitude, a point on which our criminals, I believe, disagree.  But though a crime may not be against property, it may spring from the misery and rage and depression produced by our wrong system of property-holding, and so, when that system is abolished, will disappear.  When each member of the community has sufficient for his wants, and is not interfered with by his neighbour, it will not be an object of any interest to him to interfere with anyone else.  Jealousy, which is an extraordinary source of crime in modern life, is an emotion closely bound up with our conceptions of property, and under Socialism and Individualism will die out.  It is remarkable that in communistic tribes jealousy is entirely unknown.

With authority, punishment will disappear. This will be a huge benefit—actually, a benefit of immeasurable value. When you read history, not in the sanitized versions meant for school kids and mediocrities, but in the original sources of each era, you become genuinely sickened, not by the crimes committed by the wicked, but by the punishments inflicted by the good; and a community is far more brutalized by the regular use of punishment than it is by the occurrence of crime. It’s clear that the more punishment is handed out, the more crime is generated, and most modern law has recognized this clearly, making it its mission to reduce punishment as much as it thinks it can. Wherever punishment has genuinely been reduced, the results have always been extremely p. 34positive. The less punishment there is, the less crime there is. When there’s no punishment at all, crime will either disappear or, if it happens, will be viewed by doctors as a troubling form of mental illness, to be treated with care and kindness. The so-called criminals of today aren’t really criminals at all. Starvation, not sin, is the root of modern crime. That’s why our criminals are, as a group, so utterly unremarkable from a psychological standpoint. They aren’t extraordinary figures like Macbeth or terrible characters like Vautrin. They are just what ordinary, respectable, everyday people would be if they didn’t have enough to eat. When private property is abolished, there will be no need for crime, no demand for it; it will cease to exist. Of course, not all crimes are against property, although those are the crimes that English law, valuing what a man owns more than who he is, punishes with the harshest and most terrible severity, except for the crime of murder, which we consider worse than long-term imprisonment—on this point, I believe our criminals disagree. But even if a crime isn’t against property, it can arise from the misery, anger, and despair created by our flawed system of property ownership, and therefore will vanish when that system is eradicated. When every member of the community has enough to meet their needs and isn’t interfered with by their neighbor, they won’t have any interest in interfering with anyone else. Jealousy, which is a major source of crime in modern life, is an emotion tightly linked to our views on property, and will fade away under Socialism and Individualism. It’s noteworthy that in communistic societies, jealousy is completely unheard of.

Now as the State is not to govern, p. 36it may be asked what the State is to do.  The State is to be a voluntary association that will organise labour, and be the manufacturer and distributor of necessary commodities.  The State is to make what is useful.  The individual is to make what is beautiful.  And as I have mentioned the word labour, I cannot help saying that a great deal of nonsense is being written and talked nowadays about the dignity of manual labour.  There is nothing necessarily dignified about manual labour at all, and most of it is absolutely degrading.  It is mentally and morally injurious to man to do anything in which he does not find pleasure, and many forms of labour are quite pleasureless activities, and should be regarded as such.  To sweep a slushy crossing for eight hours, on a day when the east wind is blowing is a disgusting occupation.  To sweep it with mental, moral, or physical dignity seems to p. 37me to be impossible.  To sweep it with joy would be appalling.  Man is made for something better than disturbing dirt.  All work of that kind should be done by a machine.

Now that the State isn’t meant to govern, p. 36 you might wonder what the State is supposed to do. The State should be a voluntary association that organizes labor and manages the production and distribution of essential goods. The State is meant to create what is useful. The individual is meant to create what is beautiful. And since I mentioned labor, I can’t help but point out that a lot of nonsense is being written and said these days about the dignity of manual labor. There’s nothing inherently dignified about manual labor, and much of it is actually degrading. It’s mentally and morally harmful for a person to do anything that doesn’t bring them joy, and many types of labor are completely joyless and should be seen as such. Sweeping a muddy crossing for eight hours on a day when the east wind is blowing is a disgusting job. Maintaining it with any kind of mental, moral, or physical dignity seems to p. 37 me to be impossible. To sweep it with joy would be horrifying. People are meant for something better than dealing with dirt. All work of that sort should be done by a machine.

And I have no doubt that it will be so.  Up to the present, man has been, to a certain extent, the slave of machinery, and there is something tragic in the fact that as soon as man had invented a machine to do his work he began to starve.  This, however, is, of course, the result of our property system and our system of competition.  One man owns a machine which does the work of five hundred men.  Five hundred men are, in consequence, thrown out of employment, and, having no work to do, become hungry and take to thieving.  The one man secures the produce of the machine and keeps it, and has five hundred times as much as he should have, and probably, which is of much more importance, a great p. 38deal more than he really wants.  Were that machine the property of all, every one would benefit by it.  It would be an immense advantage to the community.  All unintellectual labour, all monotonous, dull labour, all labour that deals with dreadful things, and involves unpleasant conditions, must be done by machinery.  Machinery must work for us in coal mines, and do all sanitary services, and be the stoker of steamers, and clean the streets, and run messages on wet days, and do anything that is tedious or distressing.  At present machinery competes against man.  Under proper conditions machinery will serve man.  There is no doubt at all that this is the future of machinery, and just as trees grow while the country gentleman is asleep, so while Humanity will be amusing itself, or enjoying cultivated leisure—which, and not labour, is the aim of man—or making beautiful things, or reading beautiful p. 39things, or simply contemplating the world with admiration and delight, machinery will be doing all the necessary and unpleasant work.  The fact is, that civilisation requires slaves.  The Greeks were quite right there.  Unless there are slaves to do the ugly, horrible, uninteresting work, culture and contemplation become almost impossible.  Human slavery is wrong, insecure, and demoralising.  On mechanical slavery, on the slavery of the machine, the future of the world depends.  And when scientific men are no longer called upon to go down to a depressing East End and distribute bad cocoa and worse blankets to starving people, they will have delightful leisure in which to devise wonderful and marvellous things for their own joy and the joy of everyone else.  There will be great storages of force for every city, and for every house if required, and this force man will convert into heat, p. 40light, or motion, according to his needs.  Is this Utopian?  A map of the world that does not include Utopia is not worth even glancing at, for it leaves out the one country at which Humanity is always landing.  And when Humanity lands there, it looks out, and, seeing a better country, sets sail.  Progress is the realisation of Utopias.

And I have no doubt that it will be so. Up to now, humans have been somewhat enslaved by machinery, and it’s tragic that as soon as we invented machines to do our work, we started to starve. This is, of course, a result of our property system and competition. One person owns a machine that can do the work of five hundred people. As a result, five hundred people lose their jobs and, with nothing to do, they become hungry and turn to stealing. The owner of that machine benefits from its output, keeping far more than their fair share—and much more importantly, they probably have much more than they actually need. If that machine belonged to everyone, everyone would benefit. That would be a huge advantage for the community. All the unskilled labor, all the monotonous and boring work, all the jobs dealing with unpleasant tasks and conditions should be performed by machines. Machines should work for us in coal mines, take care of sanitation, stoke steam engines, clean the streets, run errands on rainy days, and handle anything tedious or distressing. Right now, machinery competes against humans. Under the right conditions, machines will serve humans. There’s no doubt that this is the future of machinery, and just as trees grow while the country gentleman sleeps, humanity will be enjoying itself or relaxing— which, not labor, is the goal of life—creating beautiful things, reading great literature, or simply admiring and enjoying the world, while machines take care of all the necessary and unpleasant tasks. The truth is, civilization needs slaves. The Greeks had it right. Without slaves to do the dirty, awful, and boring work, culture and contemplation become nearly impossible. Human slavery is wrong, unstable, and destructive. The future of the world depends on mechanical slavery, on the slavery of machines. When scientific minds no longer have to go to a dismal East End to distribute bad cocoa and even worse blankets to starving people, they will have the leisure to come up with wonderful and amazing things for their own happiness and the joy of everyone else. There will be great sources of energy for every city, and for every home if needed, and humans will convert this energy into heat, light, or motion, according to their needs. Is this Utopian? A map of the world that doesn’t include Utopia isn’t worth even looking at, as it leaves out the one place humanity is always reaching for. And when humanity arrives there, it looks out and sees a better land and sets sail for it. Progress is the realization of Utopias.

Now, I have said that the community by means of organisation of machinery will supply the useful things, and that the beautiful things will be made by the individual.  This is not merely necessary, but it is the only possible way by which we can get either the one or the other.  An individual who has to make things for the use of others, and with reference to their wants and their wishes, does not work with interest, and consequently cannot put into his work what is best in him.  Upon the other hand, whenever a community or a p. 41powerful section of a community, or a government of any kind, attempts to dictate to the artist what he is to do, Art either entirely vanishes, or becomes stereotyped, or degenerates into a low and ignoble form of craft.  A work of art is the unique result of a unique temperament.  Its beauty comes from the fact that the author is what he is.  It has nothing to do with the fact that other people want what they want.  Indeed, the moment that an artist takes notice of what other people want, and tries to supply the demand, he ceases to be an artist, and becomes a dull or an amusing craftsman, an honest or a dishonest tradesman.  He has no further claim to be considered as an artist.  Art is the most intense mode of Individualism that the world has known.  I am inclined to say that it is the only real mode of Individualism that the world has known.  Crime, which, under certain conditions, may seem p. 42to have created Individualism, must take cognisance of other people and interfere with them.  It belongs to the sphere of action.  But alone, without any reference to his neighbours, without any interference, the artist can fashion a beautiful thing; and if he does not do it solely for his own pleasure, he is not an artist at all.

Now, I’ve said that the community, through organized systems, will provide useful things, and that beautiful things will be created by individuals. This isn’t just necessary; it’s the only way we can achieve either one. When an individual has to create things geared to others’ needs and desires, they won’t work with passion, and thus can’t put their best effort into their work. On the flip side, when a community, a powerful segment of it, or any government tries to dictate what an artist should do, Art either disappears entirely, becomes rigid, or turns into a lower, less noble craft. A work of art is the distinct result of a unique temperament. Its beauty stems from the fact that the creator is who they are. It doesn’t relate to what other people want. In fact, the moment an artist pays attention to what others desire and tries to meet that demand, they stop being an artist and start being a dull or entertaining craftsman, an honest or dishonest trader. They no longer have the right to be called an artist. Art represents the most profound form of Individualism the world has known. I’d argue it’s the only true form of Individualism that exists. Crime, which might seem to foster Individualism under certain circumstances, must consider other people and interfere with them. It operates within the realm of action. But on their own, without considering their neighbors or interference, an artist can create something beautiful; and if they’re not doing it solely for their own enjoyment, then they’re not an artist at all.

And it is to be noted that it is the fact that Art is this intense form of Individualism that makes the public try to exercise over it in an authority that is as immoral as it is ridiculous, and as corrupting as it is contemptible.  It is not quite their fault.  The public has always, and in every age, been badly brought up.  They are continually asking Art to be popular, to please their want of taste, to flatter their absurd vanity, to tell them what they have been told before, to show them what they ought to be tired of seeing, to amuse them when they feel heavy after eating too much, and to distract p. 43their thoughts when they are wearied of their own stupidity.  Now Art should never try to be popular.  The public should try to make itself artistic.  There is a very wide difference.  If a man of science were told that the results of his experiments, and the conclusions that he arrived at, should be of such a character that they would not upset the received popular notions on the subject, or disturb popular prejudice, or hurt the sensibilities of people who knew nothing about science; if a philosopher were told that he had a perfect right to speculate in the highest spheres of thought, provided that he arrived at the same conclusions as were held by those who had never thought in any sphere at all—well, nowadays the man of science and the philosopher would be considerably amused.  Yet it is really a very few years since both philosophy and science were subjected to brutal popular control, to authority in fact—p. 44the authority of either the general ignorance of the community, or the terror and greed for power of an ecclesiastical or governmental class.  Of course, we have to a very great extent got rid of any attempt on the part of the community, or the Church, or the Government, to interfere with the individualism of speculative thought, but the attempt to interfere with the individualism of imaginative art still lingers.  In fact, it does more than linger; it is aggressive, offensive, and brutalising.

It's important to note that Art's intense form of Individualism is what drives the public to exert an authority over it that is as immoral as it is ridiculous, and as corrupting as it is contemptible. It's not entirely their fault. The public has always, in every era, been poorly educated. They constantly ask Art to be popular, to satisfy their lack of taste, to stroke their absurd vanity, to tell them what they've heard before, to show them what they should be tired of seeing, to entertain them when they feel sluggish after overeating, and to distract their thoughts when they tire of their own stupidity. Art should never aim to be popular. The public should work on cultivating its own artistic sensibilities. There’s a significant difference. If a scientist were told that the results of his experiments and his conclusions should be such that they wouldn't challenge popular beliefs, disturb public opinion, or offend the feelings of those who know nothing about science; or if a philosopher were told that he could speculate in the deepest realms of thought as long as he arrived at the same conclusions held by people who had never thought deeply at all—it would certainly amuse today's scientist and philosopher. Yet, it wasn't long ago that both philosophy and science were under harsh popular control, governed by the ignorance of the community or the fear and desire for power of a religious or governmental class. While we've largely freed ourselves from attempts by the community, the Church, or the Government to interfere with the individualism of speculative thought, the interference with the individualism of imaginative art still persists. In fact, it does more than persist; it is aggressive, offensive, and brutalizing.

In England, the arts that have escaped best are the p. 45arts in which the public take no interest.  Poetry is an instance of what I mean.  We have been able to have fine poetry in England because the public do not read it, and consequently do not influence it.  The public like to insult poets because they are individual, but once they have insulted them, they leave them alone.  In the case of the novel and the drama, arts in which the public do take an interest, the result of the exercise of popular authority has been absolutely ridiculous.  No country produces such badly-written fiction, such tedious, common work in the novel form, such silly, vulgar plays as England.  It must necessarily be so.  The popular standard is of such a character that no artist can get to it.  It is at once too easy and too difficult to be a popular novelist.  It is too easy, because the requirements of the public as far as plot, style, psychology, treatment of life, and treatment of literature are concerned are within the reach of the very meanest capacity and the most uncultivated mind.  It is too difficult, because to meet such requirements the artist would have to do violence to his temperament, would have to write not for the artistic joy of writing, but for the amusement of half-educated people, and so would have to suppress his individualism, p. 46forget his culture, annihilate his style, and surrender everything that is valuable in him.  In the case of the drama, things are a little better: the theatre-going public like the obvious, it is true, but they do not like the tedious; and burlesque and farcical comedy, the two most popular forms, are distinct forms of art.  Delightful work may be produced under burlesque and farcical conditions, and in work of this kind the artist in England is allowed very great freedom.  It is when one comes to the higher forms of the drama that the result of popular control is seen.  The one thing that the public dislike is novelty.  Any attempt to extend the subject-matter of art is extremely distasteful to the public; and yet the vitality and progress of art depend in a large measure on the continual extension of subject-matter.  The public dislike novelty because they are afraid of it.  It represents to them a mode of Individualism, an assertion p. 47on the part of the artist that he selects his own subject, and treats it as he chooses.  The public are quite right in their attitude.  Art is Individualism, and Individualism is a disturbing and disintegrating force.  Therein lies its immense value.  For what it seeks to disturb is monotony of type, slavery of custom, tyranny of habit, and the reduction of man to the level of a machine.  In Art, the public accept what has been, because they cannot alter it, not because they appreciate it.  They swallow their classics whole, and never taste them.  They endure them as the inevitable, and as they cannot mar them, they mouth about them.  Strangely enough, or not strangely, according to one’s own views, this acceptance of the classics does a great deal of harm.  The uncritical admiration of the Bible and Shakespeare in England is an instance of what I mean.  With regard to the Bible, considerations of ecclesiastical p. 48authority enter into the matter, so that I need not dwell upon the point.

In England, the arts that have thrived are the p. 45arts that the public ignores. Poetry is a good example. We have produced great poetry in England because the public doesn't read it, and therefore doesn't influence it. The public likes to mock poets for being unique, but once they've done that, they leave them alone. In contrast, for the novel and drama—arts that the public cares about—the effect of public opinion has been completely absurd. No country creates such poorly-written fiction, such tedious, average novels, or such silly, vulgar plays as England. It has to be this way. The public's standards are such that no artist can meet them. It's both too easy and too hard to be a popular novelist. It's too easy because the public's expectations regarding plot, style, character development, life portrayal, and literature treatment are within reach of the most basic writers and the least sophisticated minds. It's too hard because to meet these expectations, an artist would have to compromise their temperament, writing not for the joy of creation but for the entertainment of undereducated people, and thus have to suppress their individuality, p. 46forget their education, obliterate their style, and give up everything valuable about themselves. In the theater, things are a bit better: while the audience prefers the obvious, they do not enjoy the dull; burlesque and farcical comedy, the two most popular forms, are distinct art forms. Wonderful work can emerge from burlesque and farce, granting artists in England considerable freedom. However, when it comes to more sophisticated drama, the effects of public control become apparent. The one thing the public dislikes is novelty. Any effort to broaden the themes of art is highly unwelcome; yet the energy and evolution of art largely depend on the continuous expansion of its themes. The public resists novelty because it scares them. It signifies a form of Individualism, a declaration p. 47from the artist that they choose their own subject and interpret it freely. The public is justified in their stance. Art is Individualism, and Individualism disrupts and disassembles norms. That’s where its great value lies. For what it seeks to challenge is the monotony of type, the bondage of customs, the oppression of habits, and the reduction of humanity to the status of a machine. In Art, the public accepts what exists because they can't change it, not because they appreciate it. They consume their classics in whole and never savor them. They tolerate them as inevitable, and since they can’t alter them, they only talk about them. Oddly enough, or perhaps not so oddly, depending on one’s perspective, this unquestioning acceptance of the classics is quite damaging. The uncritical reverence for the Bible and Shakespeare in England exemplifies what I mean. Regarding the Bible, considerations of ecclesiastical p. 48authority come into play, so I won't elaborate on this point.

But in the case of Shakespeare it is quite obvious that the public really see neither the beauties nor the defects of his plays.  If they saw the beauties, they would not object to the development of the drama; and if they saw the defects, they would not object to the development of the drama either.  The fact is, the public make use of the classics of a country as a means of checking the progress of Art.  They degrade the classics into authorities.  They use them as bludgeons for preventing the free expression of Beauty in new forms.  They are always asking a writer why he does not write like somebody else, or a painter why he does not paint like somebody else, quite oblivious of the fact that if either of them did anything of the kind he would cease to be an artist.  A fresh mode of Beauty is absolutely distasteful to them, and whenever it appears p. 49they get so angry, and bewildered that they always use two stupid expressions—one is that the work of art is grossly unintelligible; the other, that the work of art is grossly immoral.  What they mean by these words seems to me to be this.  When they say a work is grossly unintelligible, they mean that the artist has said or made a beautiful thing that is new; when they describe a work as grossly immoral, they mean that the artist has said or made a beautiful thing that is true.  The former expression has reference to style; the latter to subject-matter.  But they probably use the words very vaguely, as an ordinary mob will use ready-made paving-stones.  There is not a single real poet or prose-writer of this century, for instance, on whom the British public have not solemnly conferred diplomas of immorality, and these diplomas practically take the place, with us, of what in France, is the formal recognition of an Academy p. 50of Letters, and fortunately make the establishment of such an institution quite unnecessary in England.  Of course, the public are very reckless in their use of the word.  That they should have called Wordsworth an immoral poet, was only to be expected.  Wordsworth was a poet.  But that they should have called Charles Kingsley an immoral novelist is extraordinary.  Kingsley’s prose was not of a very fine quality.  Still, there is the word, and they use it as best they can.  An artist is, of course, not disturbed by it.  The true artist is a man who believes absolutely in himself, because he is absolutely himself.  But I can fancy that if an artist produced a work of art in England that immediately on its appearance was recognised by the public, through their medium, which is the public press, as a work that was quite intelligible and highly moral, he would begin to seriously question whether in its creation p. 51he had really been himself at all, and consequently whether the work was not quite unworthy of him, and either of a thoroughly second-rate order, or of no artistic value whatsoever.

But in Shakespeare’s case, it’s clear that the public doesn’t really see either the beauty or the flaws in his plays. If they recognized the beauty, they wouldn't mind the development of drama; and if they noticed the flaws, they wouldn't mind it either. The truth is, the public uses a country’s classics to measure the progress of art. They turn the classics into authorities. They wield them like blunt instruments to prevent the free expression of beauty in new forms. They always ask a writer why he doesn’t write like someone else, or a painter why he doesn’t paint like someone else, completely unaware that if either of them did that, they would stop being artists. A new kind of beauty is completely off-putting to them, and whenever it shows up p. 49, they get so angry and confused that they resort to two ridiculous phrases—one being that the artwork is overly unintelligible; the other is that the artwork is excessively immoral. What they mean by these phrases seems to be this: when they say a work is overly unintelligible, they mean that the artist has created something beautiful and new; when they call a work excessively immoral, they mean that the artist has created something beautiful and true. The first phrase refers to style; the second to content. But they likely use these words quite vaguely, like a crowd using pre-made paving stones. There isn't a single genuine poet or prose writer from this century, for example, to whom the British public hasn’t ceremoniously awarded diplomas of immorality, and these diplomas effectively replace, for us, what in France is the formal acknowledgment of an Academy p. 50of Letters, making the establishment of such an institution quite unnecessary in England. Of course, the public is careless with the term. That they labeled Wordsworth an immoral poet was to be expected. Wordsworth was a poet. But that they called Charles Kingsley an immoral novelist is remarkable. Kingsley’s prose wasn’t of very high quality. Still, the term is out there, and they use it as best they can. An artist, however, is not bothered by it. The true artist is someone who believes completely in himself because he is truly himself. But I can imagine that if an artist produced a work of art in England that was immediately recognized by the public, through their channel, which is the public press, as a work that was perfectly clear and highly moral, he would start to seriously question whether, in creating it p. 51, he had truly been himself at all, and whether the work was not completely unworthy of him, either being of a thoroughly second-rate nature or devoid of any artistic value whatsoever.

Perhaps, however, I have wronged the public in limiting them to such words as ‘immoral,’ ‘unintelligible,’ ‘exotic,’ and ‘unhealthy.’  There is one other word that they use.  That word is ‘morbid.’  They do not use it often.  The meaning of the word is so simple that they are afraid of using it.  Still, they use it sometimes, and, now and then, one comes across it in popular newspapers.  It is, of course, a ridiculous word to apply to a work of art.  For what is morbidity but a mood of emotion or a mode of thought that one cannot express?  The public are all morbid, because the public can never find expression for anything.  The artist is never morbid.  He expresses everything.  He stands outside his subject, and through its p. 52medium produces incomparable and artistic effects.  To call an artist morbid because he deals with morbidity as his subject-matter is as silly as if one called Shakespeare mad because he wrote ‘King Lear.’

Maybe I’ve done the public a disservice by limiting their descriptions to words like 'immoral,' 'unintelligible,' 'exotic,' and 'unhealthy.' There's one more word they use: 'morbid.' They don't use it often because its meaning is so straightforward that it intimidates them. Still, it's used occasionally, and now and then, you see it in popular newspapers. It's really absurd to label a work of art as morbid. After all, what is morbidity but an emotional state or a way of thinking that’s hard to articulate? The public is all morbid because they can never express anything fully. The artist is never morbid. They express everything. The artist stands apart from their subject and, through its medium, creates unique and artistic effects. To call an artist morbid just because they explore morbidity is as foolish as calling Shakespeare insane for writing ‘King Lear.’

On the whole, an artist in England gains something by being attacked.  His individuality is intensified.  He becomes more completely himself.  Of course, the attacks are very gross, very impertinent, and very contemptible.  But then no artist expects grace from the vulgar mind, or style from the suburban intellect.  Vulgarity and stupidity are two very vivid facts in modern life.  One regrets them, naturally.  But there they are.  They are subjects for study, like everything else.  And it is only fair to state, with regard to modern journalists, that they always apologise to one in private for what they have written against one in public.

Overall, an artist in England benefits from being criticized. Their individuality becomes stronger. They become more authentically themselves. Sure, the criticisms can be quite rude, impertinent, and despicable. But no artist expects kindness from the common mind or sophistication from the suburban intellect. Vulgarity and ignorance are two very prominent aspects of modern life. Naturally, one wishes they weren't there. But they exist. They can be studied, like everything else. And it's only fair to mention that, regarding modern journalists, they always apologize to you in private for what they’ve said about you in public.

Within the last few years two other p. 53adjectives, it may be mentioned, have been added to the very limited vocabulary of art-abuse that is at the disposal of the public.  One is the word ‘unhealthy,’ the other is the word ‘exotic.’  The latter merely expresses the rage of the momentary mushroom against the immortal, entrancing, and exquisitely lovely orchid.  It is a tribute, but a tribute of no importance.  The word ‘unhealthy,’ however, admits of analysis.  It is a rather interesting word.  In fact, it is so interesting that the people who use it do not know what it means.

In the last few years, two additional p. 53adjectives have been added to the very limited vocabulary of art criticism available to the public. One is “unhealthy,” and the other is “exotic.” The latter simply reflects the temporary outrage of a fleeting trend against the timeless, captivating, and beautifully delicate orchid. It’s a tribute, but it holds little significance. The word “unhealthy,” on the other hand, is open to interpretation. It’s quite an interesting word. In fact, it’s so interesting that those who use it often don’t really understand what it means.

What does it mean?  What is a healthy, or an unhealthy work of art?  All terms that one applies to a work of art, provided that one applies them rationally, have reference to either its style or its subject, or to both together.  From the point of view of style, a healthy work of art is one whose style recognises the beauty of the material it employs, be that material one of words p. 54or of bronze, of colour or of ivory, and uses that beauty as a factor in producing the æsthetic effect.  From the point of view of subject, a healthy work of art is one the choice of whose subject is conditioned by the temperament of the artist, and comes directly out of it.  In fine, a healthy work of art is one that has both perfection and personality.  Of course, form and substance cannot be separated in a work of art; they are always one.  But for purposes of analysis, and setting the wholeness of æsthetic impression aside for a moment, we can intellectually so separate them.  An unhealthy work of art, on the other hand, is a work whose style is obvious, old-fashioned, and common, and whose subject is deliberately chosen, not because the artist has any pleasure in it, but because he thinks that the public will pay him for it.  In fact, the popular novel that the public calls healthy is always a thoroughly unhealthy production; p. 55and what the public call an unhealthy novel is always a beautiful and healthy work of art.

What does it mean? What makes a work of art healthy or unhealthy? Any descriptors used for a work of art, as long as they are applied logically, refer to either its style, its subject, or both. From a stylistic perspective, a healthy work of art is one that appreciates the beauty of the material it uses, whether that material is words p. 54 or bronze, color or ivory, and incorporates that beauty into the overall aesthetic effect. When considering the subject, a healthy work has a subject that is shaped by the artist's temperament and emerges directly from it. In essence, a healthy work of art possesses both perfection and individuality. Of course, form and content cannot be separated in a work of art; they are always one. However, for analysis purposes, we can mentally distinguish between them. Conversely, an unhealthy work of art exhibits a style that is obvious, outdated, and ordinary, and its subject is chosen not from the artist's genuine interest but because they believe it will sell. In reality, the popular novel that the public deems healthy is often a completely unhealthy creation; p. 55 and what the public considers an unhealthy novel is usually a beautiful and healthy work of art.

I need hardly say that I am not, for a single moment, complaining that the public and the public press misuse these words.  I do not see how, with their lack of comprehension of what Art is, they could possibly use them in the proper sense.  I am merely pointing out the misuse; and as for the origin of the misuse and the meaning that lies behind it all, the explanation is very simple.  It comes from the barbarous conception of authority.  It comes from the natural inability of a community corrupted by authority to understand or appreciate Individualism.  In a word, it comes from that monstrous and ignorant thing that is called Public Opinion, which, bad and well-meaning as it is when it tries to control action, is infamous and of evil meaning when it tries to control Thought or Art.

I barely need to say that I'm not complaining, even for a second, about how the public and the media misuse these words. Honestly, I don't see how, given their lack of understanding of what Art truly is, they could ever use them correctly. I'm just pointing out the misuse; and when it comes to the root of this misuse and the meaning behind it, the answer is pretty straightforward. It stems from a harsh view of authority. It comes from the natural inability of a community corrupted by authority to grasp or appreciate Individualism. In short, it arises from that terrible and ignorant thing called Public Opinion, which, whether misguided or well-intentioned when it tries to influence actions, is truly reprehensible and harmful when it attempts to control Thought or Art.

p. 56Indeed, there is much more to be said in favour of the physical force of the public than there is in favour of the public’s opinion.  The former may be fine.  The latter must be foolish.  It is often said that force is no argument.  That, however, entirely depends on what one wants to prove.  Many of the most important problems of the last few centuries, such as the continuance of personal government in England, or of feudalism in France, have been solved entirely by means of physical force.  The very violence of a revolution may make the public grand and splendid for a moment.  It was a fatal day when the public discovered that the pen is mightier than the paving-stone, and can be made as offensive as the brickbat.  They at once sought for the journalist, found him, developed him, and made him their industrious and well-paid servant.  It is greatly to be regretted, for both their sakes.  p. 57Behind the barricade there may be much that is noble and heroic.  But what is there behind the leading-article but prejudice, stupidity, cant, and twaddle?  And when these four are joined together they make a terrible force, and constitute the new authority.

p. 56Indeed, there’s a lot more to support the physical force of the public than the public’s opinion. The former can be valuable, while the latter often seems foolish. It’s commonly said that force isn’t an argument. However, it really depends on what you want to prove. Many significant issues over the last few centuries, like the persistence of personal government in England or feudalism in France, have been resolved entirely through physical force. The sheer violence of a revolution can make the public seem grand and impressive, at least for a moment. It was a turning point when the public realized that the pen is mightier than the paving stone and can be as damaging as a thrown brick. They immediately sought out the journalist, found him, nurtured him, and turned him into their hardworking and well-compensated servant. This is very regrettable for both sides. p. 57Behind the barricade, there may be much that is noble and heroic. But what lies behind the editorial piece? Just prejudice, ignorance, hypocrisy, and nonsense. And when these four come together, they create a formidable force and form the new authority.

In old days men had the rack.  Now they have the press.  That is an improvement certainly.  But still it is very bad, and wrong, and demoralising.  Somebody—was it Burke?—called journalism the fourth estate.  That was true at the time, no doubt.  But at the present moment it really is the only estate.  It has eaten up the other three.  The Lords Temporal say nothing, the Lords Spiritual have nothing to say, and the House of Commons has nothing to say and says it.  We are dominated by Journalism.  In America the President reigns for four years, and Journalism governs for ever and ever.  Fortunately p. 58in America Journalism has carried its authority to the grossest and most brutal extreme.  As a natural consequence it has begun to create a spirit of revolt.  People are amused by it, or disgusted by it, according to their temperaments.  But it is no longer the real force it was.  It is not seriously treated.  In England, Journalism, not, except in a few well-known instances, having been carried to such excesses of brutality, is still a great factor, a really remarkable power.  The tyranny that it proposes to exercise over people’s private lives seems to me to be quite extraordinary.  The fact is, that the public have an insatiable curiosity to know everything, except what is worth knowing.  Journalism, conscious of this, and having tradesman-like habits, supplies their demands.  In centuries before ours the public nailed the ears of journalists to the pump.  That was quite hideous.  In this century journalists have nailed their p. 59own ears to the keyhole.  That is much worse.  And what aggravates the mischief is that the journalists who are most to blame are not the amusing journalists who write for what are called Society papers.  The harm is done by the serious, thoughtful, earnest journalists, who solemnly, as they are doing at present, will drag before the eyes of the public some incident in the private life of a great statesman, of a man who is a leader of political thought as he is a creator of political force, and invite the public to discuss the incident, to exercise authority in the matter, to give their views, and not merely to give their views, but to carry them into action, to dictate to the man upon all other points, to dictate to his party, to dictate to his country; in fact, to make themselves ridiculous, offensive, and harmful.  The private lives of men and women should not be told to the public.  The public have nothing to p. 60do with them at all.  In France they manage these things better.  There they do not allow the details of the trials that take place in the divorce courts to be published for the amusement or criticism of the public.  All that the public are allowed to know is that the divorce has taken place and was granted on petition of one or other or both of the married parties concerned.  In France, in fact, they limit the journalist, and allow the artist almost perfect freedom.  Here we allow absolute freedom to the journalist, and entirely limit the artist.  English public opinion, that is to say, tries to constrain and impede and warp the man who makes things that are beautiful in effect, and compels the journalist to retail things that are ugly, or disgusting, or revolting in fact, so that we have the most serious journalists in the world, and the most indecent newspapers.  It is no exaggeration to talk of compulsion.  There p. 61are possibly some journalists who take a real pleasure in publishing horrible things, or who, being poor, look to scandals as forming a sort of permanent basis for an income.  But there are other journalists, I feel certain, men of education and cultivation, who really dislike publishing these things, who know that it is wrong to do so, and only do it because the unhealthy conditions under which their occupation is carried on oblige them to supply the public with what the public wants, and to compete with other journalists in making that supply as full and satisfying to the gross popular appetite as possible.  It is a very degrading position for any body of educated men to be placed in, and I have no doubt that most of them feel it acutely.

In the past, people were tortured on the rack. Now they are subjected to the press. That’s definitely an improvement, but it’s still very bad, wrong, and demoralizing. Someone—was it Burke?—called journalism the fourth estate. That was true back then, no doubt. But right now, journalism is really the only estate. It has absorbed the other three. The Lords Temporal have nothing to say, the Lords Spiritual are silent, and the House of Commons doesn’t really contribute anything meaningful. We're dominated by journalism. In America, the President may serve a four-year term, but journalism governs forever. Thankfully, in America, journalism has taken its power to an extreme level. Naturally, this has sparked a spirit of rebellion. People either find it entertaining or are disgusted by it, depending on their personalities. But it’s no longer taken seriously. In England, journalism, not having reached such brutal extremes except in a few notable cases, remains a significant factor and a genuinely remarkable power. The control it seeks to exert over people’s private lives is quite extraordinary. The truth is that the public has an insatiable curiosity about everything except what truly matters. Journalism, aware of this and having a business mindset, feeds this demand. In earlier centuries, the public would punish journalists by forcing them to listen to their grievances. That was truly awful. In this century, journalists have trapped themselves by prying into private matters. That’s far worse. What makes it worse is that the journalists most at fault aren’t the entertaining ones who write for so-called Society papers. The real damage is done by serious, thoughtful journalists who, like they are doing now, parade the personal lives of influential politicians before the public, inviting them to comment, take action, and even dictate terms to these leaders and their parties, making themselves look ridiculous, offensive, and harmful. The private lives of individuals shouldn’t be public knowledge. The public has no business knowing about them at all. In France, they handle these matters more responsibly. They don’t allow the details of divorce trials to be published for public amusement or scrutiny. All the public is permitted to know is that a divorce has been granted at the request of one or both married parties. In France, they restrict journalists while allowing artists almost complete freedom. Here, we grant absolute freedom to journalists and severely limit artists. In other words, English public opinion tries to control and distort the artist who creates beautiful work, while forcing journalists to share things that are ugly, disgusting, or offensive. As a result, we have the most serious journalists and the most indecent newspapers in the world. It’s no exaggeration to say there is pressure involved. Some journalists might actually enjoy publishing terrible things, or, being financially constrained, view scandals as a way to secure a steady income. But I believe there are other journalists, well-educated and cultured individuals, who dislike publishing such things, know it’s wrong, and only do so because the toxic conditions of their work force them to give the public what it wants and compete with other journalists in satisfying the insatiable appetite for sensationalism. It's a degrading situation for any group of educated individuals, and I have no doubt most of them feel the weight of it strongly.

However, let us leave what is really a very sordid side of the subject, and return to the question of popular control in the matter of Art, by which p. 62I mean Public Opinion dictating to the artist the form which he is to use, the mode in which he is to use it, and the materials with which he is to work.  I have pointed out that the arts which have escaped best in England are the arts in which the public have not been interested.  They are, however, interested in the drama, and as a certain advance has been made in the drama within the last ten or fifteen years, it is important to point out that this advance is entirely due to a few individual artists refusing to accept the popular want of taste as their standard, and refusing to regard Art as a mere matter of demand and supply.  With his marvellous and vivid personality, with a style that has really a true colour-element in it, with his extraordinary power, not over mere mimicry but over imaginative and intellectual creation, Mr Irving, had his sole object been to give the public what they wanted, could have produced p. 63the commonest plays in the commonest manner, and made as much success and money as a man could possibly desire.  But his object was not that.  His object was to realise his own perfection as an artist, under certain conditions, and in certain forms of Art.  At first he appealed to the few: now he has educated the many.  He has created in the public both taste and temperament.  The public appreciate his artistic success immensely.  I often wonder, however, whether the public understand that that success is entirely due to the fact that he did not accept their standard, but realised his own.  With their standard the Lyceum would have been a sort of second-rate booth, as some of the popular theatres in London are at present.  Whether they understand it or not the fact however remains, that taste and temperament have, to a certain extent been created in the public, and that p. 64the public is capable of developing these qualities.  The problem then is, why do not the public become more civilised?  They have the capacity.  What stops them?

However, let’s set aside what is really a pretty ugly side of the topic and go back to the issue of public control in art—specifically, how public opinion dictates to artists the form they should use, how they should use it, and what materials they should work with. I've pointed out that the arts that have thrived the most in England are those that the public hasn't taken much interest in. However, they do care about theater, and since there’s been some progress in drama over the last ten to fifteen years, it’s important to note that this improvement is entirely thanks to a few individual artists who have refused to measure their work against popular tastes and who reject the idea of art being just a matter of supply and demand. If Mr. Irving had only aimed to give the public what they wanted, with his amazing and vibrant personality, and with a style that truly incorporates color, he could have produced the most ordinary plays in the most typical way and achieved as much success and money as anyone could wish for. But that wasn’t his goal. His aim was to pursue his own perfection as an artist, under specific conditions and within certain forms of art. Initially, he appealed to a few, but now he has educated the many. He has developed taste and temperament in the public. They greatly appreciate his artistic success. I often wonder, though, whether the public realizes that this success is entirely because he didn’t embrace their standards but instead realized his own. Had he followed their standards, the Lyceum would have been just another second-rate venue, like some of the popular theaters in London today. Whether they understand this or not, the reality is that taste and temperament have, to some extent, been fostered in the public, and that the public is capable of further developing these qualities. The question then is, why don’t the public become more civilized? They have the ability. What holds them back?

The thing that stops them, it must be said again, is their desire to exercise authority over the artist and over works of art.  To certain theatres, such as the Lyceum and the Haymarket, the public seem to come in a proper mood.  In both of these theatres there have been individual artists, who have succeeded in creating in their audiences—and every theatre in London has its own audience—the temperament to which Art appeals.  And what is that temperament?  It is the temperament of receptivity.  That is all.

What holds them back, it has to be said again, is their desire to control the artist and the art itself. At certain theaters, like the Lyceum and the Haymarket, the audience seems to arrive in the right mindset. In both of these theaters, there have been individual artists who have managed to create in their audiences—and every theater in London has its own audience—the mindset that Art appeals to. And what is that mindset? It's the mindset of being open and receptive. That’s it.

If a man approaches a work of art with any desire to exercise authority over it and the artist, he approaches it in such a spirit that he cannot receive any artistic impression from it at all.  The work of art is to dominate p. 65the spectator: the spectator is not to dominate the work of art.  The spectator is to be receptive.  He is to be the violin on which the master is to play.  And the more completely he can suppress his own silly views, his own foolish prejudices, his own absurd ideas of what Art should be, or should not be, the more likely he is to understand and appreciate the work of art in question.  This is, of course, quite obvious in the case of the vulgar theatre-going public of English men and women.  But it is equally true of what are called educated people.  For an educated person’s ideas of Art are drawn naturally from what Art has been, whereas the new work of art is beautiful by being what Art has never been; and to measure it by the standard of the past is to measure it by a standard on the rejection of which its real perfection depends.  A temperament capable of receiving, through an imaginative medium, and under imaginative p. 66conditions, new and beautiful impressions, is the only temperament that can appreciate a work of art.  And true as this is in the case of the appreciation of sculpture and painting, it is still more true of the appreciation of such arts as the drama.  For a picture and a statue are not at war with Time.  They take no count of its succession.  In one moment their unity may be apprehended.  In the case of literature it is different.  Time must be traversed before the unity of effect is realised.  And so, in the drama, there may occur in the first act of the play something whose real artistic value may not be evident to the spectator till the third or fourth act is reached.  Is the silly fellow to get angry and call out, and disturb the play, and annoy the artists?  No.  The honest man is to sit quietly, and know the delightful emotions of wonder, curiosity, and suspense.  He is not to go to the play to lose a vulgar p. 67temper.  He is to go to the play to realise an artistic temperament.  He is to go to the play to gain an artistic temperament.  He is not the arbiter of the work of art.  He is one who is admitted to contemplate the work of art, and, if the work be fine, to forget in its contemplation and the egotism that mars him—the egotism of his ignorance, or the egotism of his information.  This point about the drama is hardly, I think, sufficiently recognised.  I can quite understand that were ‘Macbeth’ produced for the first time before a modern London audience, many of the people present would strongly and vigorously object to the introduction of the witches in the first act, with their grotesque phrases and their ridiculous words.  But when the play is over one realises that the laughter of the witches in ‘Macbeth’ is as terrible as the laughter of madness in ‘Lear,’ more terrible than the laughter of Iago in the tragedy of the p. 68Moor.  No spectator of art needs a more perfect mood of receptivity than the spectator of a play.  The moment he seeks to exercise authority he becomes the avowed enemy of Art and of himself.  Art does not mind.  It is he who suffers.

If a man approaches a work of art with any desire to control it or the artist, he does so in a way that prevents him from gaining any artistic insight from it at all. The work of art should dominate the viewer; the viewer shouldn't dominate the work of art. The viewer needs to be open. He should be the instrument that the master plays. The more he can set aside his own narrow views, foolish biases, and absurd ideas of what Art should be, the more likely he is to understand and appreciate the art piece in question. This is, of course, pretty obvious with the common theater-going audience of English men and women. But it applies equally to those considered educated. An educated person’s thoughts on Art are usually based on what Art has been, while the new work of art is beautiful by being something Art has never been; therefore, evaluating it against past standards undermines its true perfection. A mindset capable of receiving new and beautiful impressions through imaginative means is the only one that can truly appreciate a work of art. While this holds true for appreciating sculpture and painting, it’s even more applicable to the appreciation of forms like drama. A painting or statue doesn’t fight against Time. They don't consider its passage. Their unity can be grasped in a single moment. Literature, however, is different. One must journey through Time before realizing its unity of effect. In drama, something in the first act may not reveal its artistic value until the third or fourth act. Should the ignorant person get mad and shout out, disrupting the play and annoying the artists? No. The sensible person should sit quietly, experiencing feelings of wonder, curiosity, and suspense. He doesn’t go to the play to lose himself in a narrow mindset. He goes to cultivate an artistic sensibility. He is not the judge of the work of art; he is someone allowed to reflect on it, and if the work is exceptional, to forget his own ego—the ego stemming from his ignorance or the ego of his knowledge. This aspect of drama is often not recognized enough. I can easily imagine that if ‘Macbeth’ were performed for the first time in front of a modern London audience, many would object strongly to the witches' introduction in the first act with their bizarre phrases and absurd words. But once the play ends, one realizes that the witches' laughter in 'Macbeth' is as terrifying as the madness in 'Lear,' even more so than Iago's laughter in the tragedy of the Moor. No observer of art needs a more heightened sense of receptivity than the one watching a play. The moment he tries to assert control, he becomes the outright enemy of Art and of himself. Art remains unaffected. He is the one who suffers.

With the novel it is the same thing.  Popular authority and the recognition of popular authority are fatal.  Thackeray’s ‘Esmond’ is a beautiful work of art because he wrote it to please himself.  In his other novels, in ‘Pendennis,’ in ‘Philip,’ in ‘Vanity Fair’ even, at times, he is too conscious of the public, and spoils his work by appealing directly to the sympathies of the public, or by directly mocking at them.  A true artist takes no notice whatever of the public.  The public are to him non-existent.  He has no poppied or honeyed cakes through which to give the monster sleep or sustenance.  He leaves that to the popular novelist.  One incomparable novelist we have p. 69now in England, Mr George Meredith.  There are better artists in France, but France has no one whose view of life is so large, so varied, so imaginatively true.  There are tellers of stories in Russia who have a more vivid sense of what pain in fiction may be.  But to him belongs philosophy in fiction.  His people not merely live, but they live in thought.  One can see them from myriad points of view.  They are suggestive.  There is soul in them and around them.  They are interpretative and symbolic.  And he who made them, those wonderful quickly-moving figures, made them for his own pleasure, and has never asked the public what they wanted, has never cared to know what they wanted, has never allowed the public to dictate to him or influence him in any way but has gone on intensifying his own personality, and producing his own individual work.  At first none came to him.  That did not matter.  Then the few came to p. 70him.  That did not change him.  The many have come now.  He is still the same.  He is an incomparable novelist.

It's the same with novels. Popular approval and the awareness of it can be deadly. Thackeray’s 'Esmond' is a masterpiece because he wrote it just for himself. In his other novels, like 'Pendennis,' 'Philip,' and sometimes even 'Vanity Fair,' he is overly aware of his audience and undermines his work by appealing too directly to their feelings or by mocking them. A true artist ignores the audience altogether. To him, the public doesn’t exist. He doesn’t provide sweet treats to lull the monster into sleep or to keep it content. That’s the job of the popular novelist. We currently have one extraordinary novelist in England, Mr. George Meredith. There may be better artists in France, but France lacks anyone with such a broad, varied, and imaginatively truthful perspective on life. There are storytellers in Russia who capture the essence of pain in fiction more vividly. But Meredith brings philosophy into fiction. His characters don't just exist; they think. You can view them from countless angles. They are thought-provoking. There’s depth in them and surrounding them. They are interpretive and symbolic. He, the creator of those amazing, dynamic figures, made them for his own enjoyment, never asked the public what they wanted, never cared to find out, and never allowed the public to dictate or influence him. Instead, he focused on developing his own identity and producing his own unique work. Initially, no one came to him. That didn’t matter. Then a few did. That didn’t change him. Now many have come. He remains the same. He is an unparalleled novelist.

With the decorative arts it is not different.  The public clung with really pathetic tenacity to what I believe were the direct traditions of the Great Exhibition of international vulgarity, traditions that were so appalling that the houses in which people lived were only fit for blind people to live in.  Beautiful things began to be made, beautiful colours came from the dyer’s hand, beautiful patterns from the artist’s brain, and the use of beautiful things and their value and importance were set forth.  The public were really very indignant.  They lost their temper.  They said silly things.  No one minded.  No one was a whit the worse.  No one accepted the authority of public opinion.  And now it is almost impossible to enter any modern house without seeing some recognition of good taste, some recognition of the value of lovely surroundings, p. 71some sign of appreciation of beauty.  In fact, people’s houses are, as a rule, quite charming nowadays.  People have been to a very great extent civilised.  It is only fair to state, however, that the extraordinary success of the revolution in house-decoration and furniture and the like has not really been due to the majority of the public developing a very fine taste in such matters.  It has been chiefly due to the fact that the craftsmen of things so appreciated the pleasure of making what was beautiful, and woke to such a vivid consciousness of the hideousness and vulgarity of what the public had previously wanted, that they simply starved the public out.  It would be quite impossible at the present moment to furnish a room as rooms were furnished a few years ago, without going for everything to an auction of second-hand furniture from some third-rate lodging-house.  The things are no longer made.  However they p. 72may object to it, people must nowadays have something charming in their surroundings.  Fortunately for them, their assumption of authority in these art-matters came to entire grief.

The decorative arts aren’t any different. The public clung to what I think were the direct traditions of the Great Exhibition of international tackiness, traditions that were so dreadful that the homes people lived in were only suitable for blind people. Beautiful things started to be created, vibrant colors emerged from the dyer's hands, stunning patterns came from the artist's imagination, and the importance and value of beautiful things were highlighted. The public was genuinely outraged. They lost their cool. They said ridiculous things, but no one cared. No one was worse off for it. No one accepted the authority of public opinion. Now, it’s nearly impossible to enter any modern home without seeing some acknowledgment of good taste, some recognition of lovely surroundings, p. 71and some sign of appreciation for beauty. In fact, people’s homes are generally quite charming these days. Society has become significantly more refined. However, it’s only fair to mention that the remarkable success of the revolution in home decoration and furniture hasn’t really been because the majority of the public developed a great taste in these things. It’s mainly because the craftsmen appreciated the joy of creating what was beautiful and became so aware of the ugliness and tackiness of what the public had previously wanted that they simply cut off the public’s supply. Nowadays, it would be impossible to furnish a room like the way rooms were decorated just a few years ago without sourcing everything from an auction of second-hand furniture from some rundown boarding house. Those items are no longer made. However, no matter how much they object, people today must have something beautiful in their surroundings. Thankfully, their claim to authority in these art matters came to a total failure. p. 72

It is evident, then, that all authority in such things is bad.  People sometimes inquire what form of government is most suitable for an artist to live under.  To this question there is only one answer.  The form of government that is most suitable to the artist is no government at all.  Authority over him and his art is ridiculous.  It has been stated that under despotisms artists have produced lovely work.  This is not quite so.  Artists have visited despots, not as subjects to be tyrannised over, but as wandering wonder-makers, as fascinating vagrant personalities, to be entertained and charmed and suffered to be at peace, and allowed to create.  There is this to be said in favour of the despot, that he, being an individual, p. 73may have culture, while the mob, being a monster, has none.  One who is an Emperor and King may stoop down to pick up a brush for a painter, but when the democracy stoops down it is merely to throw mud.  And yet the democracy have not so far to stoop as the emperor.  In fact, when they want to throw mud they have not to stoop at all.  But there is no necessity to separate the monarch from the mob; all authority is equally bad.

It's clear that all authority in these matters is harmful. People often ask what type of government is best for an artist. The answer is simple: the best government for an artist is no government at all. Having authority over him and his art is absurd. It's been said that artists have created beautiful work under despotic regimes. This isn't entirely accurate. Artists have approached despots not as subjects to be oppressed, but as wandering creators, intriguing individuals, to be entertained, appreciated, left in peace, and allowed to create. It can be argued that a despot, being one person, may possess culture, while the masses, as a whole, do not. An emperor or king might lower himself to pick up a brush for a painter, but when democracy bends down, it's only to throw mud. And yet, the masses don’t have to bend as deeply as the emperor. In fact, when they want to throw mud, they don’t have to bend at all. However, there’s no need to separate the monarch from the masses; all forms of authority are equally detrimental.

There are three kinds of despots.  There is the despot who tyrannises over the body.  There is the despot who tyrannises over the soul.  There is the despot who tyrannises over the soul and body alike.  The first is called the Prince.  The second is called the Pope.  The third is called the People.  The Prince may be cultivated.  Many Princes have been.  Yet in the Prince there is danger.  One thinks of Dante at the bitter feast p. 74in Verona, of Tasso in Ferrara’s madman’s cell.  It is better for the artist not to live with Princes.  The Pope may be cultivated.  Many Popes have been; the bad Popes have been.  The bad Popes loved Beauty, almost as passionately, nay, with as much passion as the good Popes hated Thought.  To the wickedness of the Papacy humanity owes much.  The goodness of the Papacy owes a terrible debt to humanity.  Yet, though the Vatican has kept the rhetoric of its thunders, and lost the rod of its lightning, it is better for the artist not to live with Popes.  It was a Pope who said of Cellini to a conclave of Cardinals that common laws and common authority were not made for men such as he; but it was a Pope who thrust Cellini into prison, and kept him there till he sickened with rage, and created unreal visions for himself, and saw the gilded sun enter his room, and grew so enamoured of p. 75it that he sought to escape, and crept out from tower to tower, and falling through dizzy air at dawn, maimed himself, and was by a vine-dresser covered with vine leaves, and carried in a cart to one who, loving beautiful things, had care of him.  There is danger in Popes.  And as for the People, what of them and their authority?  Perhaps of them and their authority one has spoken enough.  Their authority is a thing blind, deaf, hideous, grotesque, tragic, amusing, serious, and obscene.  It is impossible for the artist to live with the People.  All despots bribe.  The people bribe and brutalise.  Who told them to exercise authority?  They were made to live, to listen, and to love.  Someone has done them a great wrong.  They have marred themselves by imitation of their inferiors.  They have taken the sceptre of the Prince.  How should they use it?  They have taken the triple tiara of the Pope.  How should p. 76they carry its burden?  They are as a clown whose heart is broken.  They are as a priest whose soul is not yet born.  Let all who love Beauty pity them.  Though they themselves love not Beauty, yet let them pity themselves.  Who taught them the trick of tyranny?

There are three types of despots. There’s the despot who controls the body. There’s the despot who controls the soul. Then there’s the despot who controls both the soul and body. The first is called the Prince. The second is known as the Pope. The third is called the People. The Prince can be refined. Many Princes have been. Yet there’s danger in the Prince. One thinks of Dante at the bitter feast in Verona, or Tasso in the madman’s cell of Ferrara. It’s better for the artist not to associate with Princes. The Pope can be educated. Many Popes have been; there have also been bad Popes. The bad Popes loved Beauty, almost as fervently, indeed, with as much passion as the good Popes despised Thought. Humanity owes much to the wickedness of the Papacy. The goodness of the Papacy owes a heavy debt to humanity. Yet, although the Vatican still uses the language of its thunders, and has lost the power of its lightning, it’s better for the artist not to associate with Popes. It was a Pope who told a conclave of Cardinals that common laws and common authority were not meant for men like Cellini; but it was a Pope who imprisoned Cellini, keeping him there until he was consumed by rage, creating unreal visions for himself, and saw the gilded sun enter his room, growing so enamored of it that he tried to escape, crawling from tower to tower, falling through dizzy air at dawn, injuring himself, and being covered with vine leaves by a vine-dresser, then taken in a cart to someone who cared for beautiful things. There’s danger with Popes. And as for the People, what about them and their authority? Perhaps enough has been said about them and their authority. Their authority is blind, deaf, hideous, grotesque, tragic, funny, serious, and obscene. It’s impossible for the artist to live with the People. All despots corrupt. The people corrupt and are brutal. Who told them to assume authority? They were meant to live, to listen, and to love. Someone has wronged them greatly. They have disfigured themselves by mimicking their inferiors. They have taken the scepter of the Prince. How can they wield it? They have taken the triple tiara of the Pope. How can they bear its weight? They are like a clown with a broken heart. They are like a priest whose soul hasn’t yet been born. Let all who cherish Beauty feel sorry for them. Even though they themselves do not love Beauty, they should pity themselves. Who taught them the art of tyranny?

There are many other things that one might point out.  One might point out how the Renaissance was great, because it sought to solve no social problem, and busied itself not about such things, but suffered the individual to develop freely, beautifully, and naturally, and so had great and individual artists, and great and individual men.  One might point out how Louis XIV., by creating the modern state, destroyed the individualism of the artist, and made things monstrous in their monotony of repetition, and contemptible in their conformity to rule, and destroyed throughout all France all those fine freedoms of expression p. 77that had made tradition new in beauty, and new modes one with antique form.  But the past is of no importance.  The present is of no importance.  It is with the future that we have to deal.  For the past is what man should not have been.  The present is what man ought not to be.  The future is what artists are.

There are many other things that people could mention. One could say that the Renaissance was amazing because it didn't try to solve social issues and focused instead on allowing individuals to develop freely, beautifully, and naturally, leading to the emergence of great artists and remarkable individuals. One might also highlight how Louis XIV, by establishing the modern state, crushed the individuality of artists, resulting in a tedious monotony and a disdain for creative rules that wiped out the freedoms of expression throughout France. These freedoms had made tradition fresh and beautiful, blending new styles with classical forms. But the past doesn’t matter. The present doesn’t matter. We need to focus on the future. The past is what humanity should not have been. The present is what humanity ought not to be. The future is what artists truly are.

It will, of course, be said that such a scheme as is set forth here is quite unpractical, and goes against human nature.  This is perfectly true.  It is unpractical, and it goes against human nature.  This is why it is worth carrying out, and that is why one proposes it.  For what is a practical scheme?  A practical scheme is either a scheme that is already in existence, or a scheme that could be carried out under existing conditions.  But it is exactly the existing conditions that one objects to; and any scheme that could accept these conditions is wrong and foolish.  The conditions will be p. 78done away with, and human nature will change.  The only thing that one really knows about human nature is that it changes.  Change is the one quality we can predicate of it.  The systems that fail are those that rely on the permanency of human nature, and not on its growth and development.  The error of Louis XIV. was that he thought human nature would always be the same.  The result of his error was the French Revolution.  It was an admirable result.  All the results of the mistakes of governments are quite admirable.

It will definitely be said that a plan like the one presented here is impractical and goes against human nature. This is completely true. It is impractical and it contradicts human nature. That's exactly why it's worth trying out, and that's why it’s being proposed. What qualifies as a practical plan? A practical plan is either one that's already in place or one that could be implemented under current conditions. But it's precisely these current conditions that people have issues with; any plan that could accept these conditions is misguided and foolish. The conditions will be p. 78eliminated, and human nature will evolve. The only thing we truly know about human nature is that it changes. Change is the one characteristic we can expect from it. The systems that fail are those that depend on the permanence of human nature, rather than its growth and development. The mistake Louis XIV made was believing human nature would always remain the same. The outcome of that mistake was the French Revolution. It was an admirable outcome. All the results of government errors are quite admirable.

It is to be noted also that Individualism does not come to man with any sickly cant about duty, which merely means doing what other people want because they want it; or any hideous cant about self-sacrifice, which is merely a survival of savage mutilation.  In fact, it does not come to man with any claims upon him at all.  It comes naturally p. 79and inevitably out of man.  It is the point to which all development tends.  It is the differentiation to which all organisms grow.  It is the perfection that is inherent in every mode of life, and towards which every mode of life quickens.  And so Individualism exercises no compulsion over man.  On the contrary, it says to man that he should suffer no compulsion to be exercised over him.  It does not try to force people to be good.  It knows that people are good when they are let alone.  Man will develop Individualism out of himself.  Man is now so developing Individualism.  To ask whether Individualism is practical is like asking whether Evolution is practical.  Evolution is the law of life, and there is no evolution except towards Individualism.  Where this tendency is not expressed, it is a case of artificially-arrested growth, or of disease, or of death.

It's also important to note that Individualism doesn't come to people with any weak talk about duty, which just means doing what others want because they want it; or any ugly talk about self-sacrifice, which is just a leftover from primitive harm. In fact, it doesn't come to people with any demands at all. It naturally and inevitably emerges from within. It is the goal toward which all development strives. It is the uniqueness that all organisms pursue. It is the perfection inherent in every form of life, and towards which every form of life moves. Therefore, Individualism doesn't force anything on people. On the contrary, it tells people that they shouldn't have to endure any pressure to conform. It doesn't try to make people behave well. It understands that people are good when they are left to their own devices. Individuals will develop Individualism from within themselves. People are currently doing just that. Asking whether Individualism is practical is like asking if Evolution is practical. Evolution is the law of life, and there is no evolution that doesn't lead to Individualism. When this tendency isn't expressed, it's a sign of artificially halted growth, or of illness, or of death.

Individualism will also be unselfish p. 80and unaffected.  It has been pointed out that one of the results of the extraordinary tyranny of authority is that words are absolutely distorted from their proper and simple meaning, and are used to express the obverse of their right signification.  What is true about Art is true about Life.  A man is called affected, nowadays, if he dresses as he likes to dress.  But in doing that he is acting in a perfectly natural manner.  Affectation, in such matters, consists in dressing according to the views of one’s neighbour, whose views, as they are the views of the majority, will probably be extremely stupid.  Or a man is called selfish if he lives in the manner that seems to him most suitable for the full realisation of his own personality; if, in fact, the primary aim of his life is self-development.  But this is the way in which everyone should live.  Selfishness is not living as one wishes to live, it is p. 81asking others to live as one wishes to live.  And unselfishness is letting other people’s lives alone, not interfering with them.  Selfishness always aims at creating around it an absolute uniformity of type.  Unselfishness recognises infinite variety of type as a delightful thing, accepts it, acquiesces in it, enjoys it.  It is not selfish to think for oneself.  A man who does not think for himself does not think at all.  It is grossly selfish to require of ones neighbour that he should think in the same way, and hold the same opinions.  Why should he?  If he can think, he will probably think differently.  If he cannot think, it is monstrous to require thought of any kind from him.  A red rose is not selfish because it wants to be a red rose.  It would be horribly selfish if it wanted all the other flowers in the garden to be both red and roses.  Under Individualism people will be quite natural and absolutely unselfish, p. 82and will know the meanings of the words, and realise them in their free, beautiful lives.  Nor will men be egotistic as they are now.  For the egotist is he who makes claims upon others, and the Individualist will not desire to do that.  It will not give him pleasure.  When man has realised Individualism, he will also realise sympathy and exercise it freely and spontaneously.  Up to the present man has hardly cultivated sympathy at all.  He has merely sympathy with pain, and sympathy with pain is not the highest form of sympathy.  All sympathy is fine, but sympathy with suffering is the least fine mode.  It is tainted with egotism.  It is apt to become morbid.  There is in it a certain element of terror for our own safety.  We become afraid that we ourselves might be as the leper or as the blind, and that no man would have care of us.  It is curiously limiting, too.  One should sympathise with p. 83the entirety of life, not with life’s sores and maladies merely, but with life’s joy and beauty and energy and health and freedom.  The wider sympathy is, of course, the more difficult.  It requires more unselfishness.  Anybody can sympathise with the sufferings of a friend, but it requires a very fine nature—it requires, in fact, the nature of a true Individualist—to sympathise with a friend’s success.

Individualism will also be unselfish p. 80and natural. It has been noted that one of the effects of the extreme tyranny of authority is that words are completely twisted from their accurate and simple meaning, and are used to convey the opposite of what they truly signify. What applies to Art applies to Life. A man is considered affected these days if he dresses how he wants to dress. But in doing that, he is acting in a perfectly natural way. Affectation, in these cases, is dressing based on what others think, whose opinions, since they reflect the majority, will likely be quite foolish. Or a man is labeled selfish if he lives in a way that feels most right for him to fully express himself; if, in fact, his main goal in life is personal development. But this is how everyone should live. Selfishness is not about living how one wants; it is p. 81asking others to live how one desires. Unselfishness is allowing others to live their lives without interference. Selfishness always aims to create a complete uniformity in types around it. Unselfishness recognizes the endless variety of types as something wonderful, accepts it, goes along with it, and enjoys it. It is not selfish to think for oneself. A person who does not think for themselves doesn't think at all. It is extremely selfish to ask a neighbor to think the same way and hold the same opinions. Why should they? If they can think, they will likely think differently. If they cannot think, it is outrageous to demand any form of thought from them. A red rose is not selfish for wanting to be a red rose. It would be shockingly selfish if it wanted all the other flowers in the garden to be both red and roses. Under Individualism, people will be completely natural and truly unselfish, p. 82and will understand the meanings of words, realizing them in their free, beautiful lives. Men won’t be egotistical as they are now. The egotist makes demands on others, and the Individualist won't want to do that. It won’t bring him joy. Once a person realizes Individualism, they will also understand sympathy and actively practice it. So far, people have hardly developed sympathy at all. They only show sympathy for pain, and sympathy for pain is not the highest form of empathy. While all sympathy is valuable, sympathy for suffering is the least admirable type. It carries a hint of egotism. It can become morbid. There is a fear of how our own safety might be at risk. We begin to worry that we could end up like the leper or the blind, and that no one would care for us. It is also strangely limiting. One should empathize with p. 83the entirety of life, not just with life’s wounds and ailments, but with life’s joy, beauty, energy, health, and freedom. The broader the sympathy, of course, the more challenging it is. It requires more unselfishness. Anyone can empathize with the suffering of a friend, but it takes a truly refined character—it actually requires the spirit of a true Individualist—to empathize with a friend’s success.

In the modern stress of competition and struggle for place, such sympathy is naturally rare, and is also very much stifled by the immoral ideal of uniformity of type and conformity to rule which is so prevalent everywhere, and is perhaps most obnoxious in England.

In today’s competitive environment and the fight for status, that kind of empathy is hard to find and is often suppressed by the unethical expectation of sameness and following the rules that is widespread everywhere, and is probably most irritating in England.

Sympathy with pain there will, of course, always be.  It is one of the first instincts of man.  The animals which are individual, the higher animals, that is to say, share it with us.  But it must be remembered that p. 84while sympathy with joy intensifies the sum of joy in the world, sympathy with pain does not really diminish the amount of pain.  It may make man better able to endure evil, but the evil remains.  Sympathy with consumption does not cure consumption; that is what Science does.  And when Socialism has solved the problem of poverty, and Science solved the problem of disease, the area of the sentimentalists will be lessened, and the sympathy of man will be large, healthy, and spontaneous.  Man will have joy in the contemplation of the joyous life of others.

There will always be sympathy for pain, of course. It’s one of humanity's first instincts. Higher animals, those that are more individual, share this feeling with us. However, it's important to remember that while sympathy for joy amplifies the joy in the world, sympathy for pain doesn't really reduce the amount of pain. It might help people endure suffering better, but the suffering still exists. Sympathy for illness doesn't cure it; that’s the job of Science. And when Socialism addresses poverty and Science tackles disease, the space for sentimentalism will shrink, and human sympathy will become broader, healthier, and more genuine. People will find happiness in witnessing the joy of others.

For it is through joy that the Individualism of the future will develop itself.  Christ made no attempt to reconstruct society, and consequently the Individualism that he preached to man could be realised only through pain or in solitude.  The ideals that we owe to Christ are the ideals of the man who abandons society entirely, or of the man p. 85who resists society absolutely.  But man is naturally social.  Even the Thebaid became peopled at last.  And though the cenobite realises his personality, it is often an impoverished personality that he so realises.  Upon the other hand, the terrible truth that pain is a mode through which man may realise himself exercises a wonderful fascination over the world.  Shallow speakers and shallow thinkers in pulpits and on platforms often talk about the world’s worship of pleasure, and whine against it.  But it is rarely in the world’s history that its ideal has been one of joy and beauty.  The worship of pain has far more often dominated the world.  Mediævalism, with its saints and martyrs, its love of self-torture, its wild passion for wounding itself, its gashing with knives, and its whipping with rods—Mediævalism is real Christianity, and the mediæval Christ is the real Christ.  When the Renaissance dawned upon the world, and brought p. 86with it the new ideals of the beauty of life and the joy of living, men could not understand Christ.  Even Art shows us that.  The painters of the Renaissance drew Christ as a little boy playing with another boy in a palace or a garden, or lying back in his mother’s arms, smiling at her, or at a flower, or at a bright bird; or as a noble, stately figure moving nobly through the world; or as a wonderful figure rising in a sort of ecstasy from death to life.  Even when they drew him crucified they drew him as a beautiful God on whom evil men had inflicted suffering.  But he did not preoccupy them much.  What delighted them was to paint the men and women whom they admired, and to show the loveliness of this lovely earth.  They painted many religious pictures—in fact, they painted far too many, and the monotony of type and motive is wearisome, and was bad for art.  It was the result of the authority of the public in art-matters, and is to be deplored.  But p. 87their soul was not in the subject.  Raphael was a great artist when he painted his portrait of the Pope.  When he painted his Madonnas and infant Christs, he is not a great artist at all.  Christ had no message for the Renaissance, which was wonderful because it brought an ideal at variance with his, and to find the presentation of the real Christ we must go to mediæval art.  There he is one maimed and marred; one who is not comely to look on, because Beauty is a joy; one who is not in fair raiment, because that may be a joy also: he is a beggar who has a marvellous soul; he is a leper whose soul is divine; he needs neither property nor health; he is a God realising his perfection through pain.

For it is through joy that individualism in the future will evolve. Christ didn't try to reshape society, so the individualism he preached could only be realized through suffering or in solitude. The ideals we attribute to Christ are those of a person who completely rejects society, or of someone who strictly opposes it. However, humans are naturally social beings. Even the Thebaid eventually became populated. While the hermit may find his own identity, it is often a limited identity he uncovers. On the other hand, the harsh reality that pain can be a way for people to understand themselves is deeply fascinating to the world. Superficial speakers and thinkers from pulpits and platforms frequently complain about society's obsession with pleasure. Yet, throughout history, the prevailing ideal has rarely been about joy and beauty. Instead, the worship of pain has often dominated. Medievalism—with its saints and martyrs, its obsession with self-harm, its intense desire to inflict wounds, its cutting with knives and whipping with rods—is the true Christianity, and the medieval Christ is the real Christ. When the Renaissance began and introduced new ideals celebrating the beauty of life and the joy of living, people struggled to comprehend Christ. Even art reflects this. Renaissance painters depicted Christ as a young boy playing with another child in a palace or a garden, or relaxing in his mother’s arms, smiling at her, a flower, or a bright bird; or as a noble figure moving gracefully through life; or as a magnificent being rising from death to life in ecstasy. Even when they depicted him crucified, he was shown as a beautiful God suffering at the hands of evil men. But he didn't captivate them much. What thrilled them was painting the men and women they admired and capturing the beauty of this lovely earth. They created numerous religious paintings—in fact, too many, leading to a monotonous style that became tiresome and damaging to art. This resulted from the public's influence over artistic matters, which is unfortunate. Yet their hearts weren't in the subject. Raphael was a great artist when he painted the Pope's portrait. But when he painted his Madonnas and infant Christs, he wasn't a great artist at all. Christ had no message for the Renaissance, which was remarkable because it offered ideals that conflicted with his. To find the true presentation of Christ, we must look to medieval art, where he is depicted as damaged and scarred; not pleasant to look at, because beauty is associated with joy; not dressed in fine clothes, as that can also bring joy: he is a beggar with a marvelous soul; he is a leper with a divine spirit; he requires neither wealth nor health; he is a God achieving his perfection through suffering.

The evolution of man is slow.  The injustice of men is great.  It was necessary that pain should be put forward as a mode of self-realisation.  Even now, in some places in the world, the message of Christ is necessary.  No one who lived p. 88in modern Russia could possibly realise his perfection except by pain.  A few Russian artists have realised themselves in Art; in a fiction that is mediæval in character, because its dominant note is the realisation of men through suffering.  But for those who are not artists, and to whom there is no mode of life but the actual life of fact, pain is the only door to perfection.  A Russian who lives happily under the present system of government in Russia must either believe that man has no soul, or that, if he has, it is not worth developing.  A Nihilist who rejects all authority, because he knows authority to be evil, and welcomes all pain, because through that he realises his personality, is a real Christian.  To him the Christian ideal is a true thing.

The evolution of humanity is slow. The injustices of people are significant. It was necessary for pain to be seen as a way to achieve self-realization. Even today, in some parts of the world, Christ's message is essential. No one living in modern Russia can truly recognize their own perfection without experiencing pain. A few Russian artists have found their identity in Art, creating stories that feel medieval because they emphasize the realization of individuals through suffering. However, for those who are not artists and have no way of life other than the stark reality of existence, pain is the only path to perfection. A Russian who lives contently under the current government must either believe that humans have no soul or that, if they do, it isn't worth nurturing. A Nihilist who rejects all authority, knowing it to be corrupt, and welcomes all pain as a means of realizing their true self, embodies a genuine Christian. For them, the Christian ideal is a genuine truth.

And yet, Christ did not revolt against authority.  He accepted the imperial authority of the Roman Empire and paid tribute.  He endured the ecclesiastical authority of the Jewish p. 89Church, and would not repel its violence by any violence of his own.  He had, as I said before, no scheme for the reconstruction of society.  But the modern world has schemes.  It proposes to do away with poverty and the suffering that it entails.  It desires to get rid of pain, and the suffering that pain entails.  It trusts to Socialism and to Science as its methods.  What it aims at is an Individualism expressing itself through joy.  This Individualism will be larger, fuller, lovelier than any Individualism has ever been.  Pain is not the ultimate mode of perfection.  It is merely provisional and a protest.  It has reference to wrong, unhealthy, unjust surroundings.  When the wrong, and the disease, and the injustice are removed, it will have no further place.  It will have done its work.  It was a great work, but it is almost over.  Its sphere lessens every day.

And yet, Christ did not rebel against authority. He accepted the power of the Roman Empire and paid taxes. He tolerated the authority of the Jewish Church and refused to respond to its violence with violence of his own. As I mentioned before, he had no plan for rebuilding society. But the modern world has plans. It aims to eliminate poverty and the suffering that comes with it. It wants to eradicate pain, along with the suffering that pain brings. It relies on Socialism and Science as its tools. What it seeks is an Individualism that expresses itself through joy. This Individualism will be broader, richer, and more beautiful than any that has ever existed. Pain is not the ultimate form of perfection. It is merely temporary and a form of protest. It relates to wrong, unhealthy, and unjust conditions. Once the wrongs, the sickness, and the injustices are addressed, pain will no longer have a place. It will have fulfilled its role. It has been significant, but its time is almost up. Its influence diminishes every day.

Nor will man miss it.  For what man p. 90has sought for is, indeed, neither pain nor pleasure, but simply Life.  Man has sought to live intensely, fully, perfectly.  When he can do so without exercising restraint on others, or suffering it ever, and his activities are all pleasurable to him, he will be saner, healthier, more civilised, more himself.  Pleasure is Nature’s test, her sign of approval.  When man is happy, he is in harmony with himself and his environment.  The new Individualism, for whose service Socialism, whether it wills it or not, is working, will be perfect harmony.  It will be what the Greeks sought for, but could not, except in Thought, realise completely, because they had slaves, and fed them; it will be what the Renaissance sought for, but could not realise completely except in Art, because they had slaves, and starved them.  It will be complete, and through it each man will attain to his perfection.  The new Individualism is the new Hellenism.

Nor will man miss it. For what man p. 90 has truly sought is not pain or pleasure, but simply Life. Man has aimed to live intensely, fully, and perfectly. When he can achieve that without holding back others or having to endure it himself, and when all his activities bring him joy, he will be saner, healthier, more civilized, and more himself. Pleasure is Nature’s test, her sign of approval. When a man is happy, he is in harmony with himself and his surroundings. The new Individualism, which Socialism is supporting whether it intends to or not, will be perfect harmony. It will be what the Greeks aspired to but couldn’t fully achieve, except in Thought, because they had slaves to support; it will be what the Renaissance hoped for but could only partially realize in Art, because they had slaves whom they starved. It will be complete, and through it, each person will reach their own perfection. The new Individualism is the new Hellenism.

 

p. 91Reprinted from theFortnightly Review,’
by permission of Messrs Chapman and Hall.

p. 91Reprinted from theFortnightly Review,’
by permission of Messrs Chapman and Hall.


Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!