This is a modern-English version of Utilitarianism, originally written by Mill, John Stuart.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
UTILITARIANISM
BY
JOHN STUART MILL
REPRINTED FROM 'FRASER'S MAGAZINE'
REPRINTED FROM 'FRASER'S MAGAZINE'
SEVENTH EDITION
7th Edition
LONDON
LONDON
LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO.
LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO.
1879
1879
CONTENTS.
UTILITARIANISM.
CHAPTER I.
There are few circumstances among those which make up the present condition of human knowledge, more unlike what might have been expected, or more significant of the backward state in which speculation on the most important subjects still lingers, than the little progress which has been made in the decision of the controversy respecting the criterion of right and wrong. From the dawn of philosophy, the question concerning the summum bonum, or, what is the same thing, concerning the foundation of morality, has been accounted the main problem in speculative thought, has occupied the most gifted intellects, and divided them into sects and schools, carrying on a vigorous warfare against one another. And after more than two thousand years the same discussions continue, philosophers are still ranged under the same contending banners, and neither thinkers nor mankind at large seem nearer to being unanimous on the subject, than when the youth Socrates listened to the old Protagoras, and asserted (if Plato's dialogue be grounded on a real conversation) the theory of utilitarianism against the popular morality of the so-called sophist.
There are few situations in today's understanding of human knowledge that are more surprising or indicative of how behind we are in our thinking on important topics than the little progress made in the debate over what defines right and wrong. Since the beginning of philosophy, the question of the summum bonum, or the basis of morality, has been seen as the central problem in philosophical inquiry. It has engaged the most talented minds and split them into various groups and schools, all actively fighting against each other. Even after more than two thousand years, these same discussions go on; philosophers are still aligned under the same opposing camps, and neither scholars nor society at large seem any closer to agreeing on the issue than they were when a young Socrates listened to the old Protagoras and argued (if Plato's dialogue reflects a real conversation) in favor of utilitarianism against the popular moral views of the so-called sophists.
It is true that similar confusion and uncertainty, and in some cases similar discordance, exist respecting the first principles of all the sciences, not excepting that which is deemed the most certain of them, mathematics; without much impairing, generally indeed without impairing at all, the trustworthiness of the conclusions of those sciences. An apparent anomaly, the explanation of which is, that the detailed doctrines of a science are not usually deduced from, nor depend for their evidence upon, what are called its first principles. Were it not so, there would be no science more precarious, or whose conclusions were more insufficiently made out, than algebra; which derives none of its certainty from what are commonly taught to learners as its elements, since these, as laid down by some of its most eminent teachers, are as full of fictions as English law, and of mysteries as theology. The truths which are ultimately accepted as the first principles of a science, are really the last results of metaphysical analysis, practised on the elementary notions with which the science is conversant; and their relation to the science is not that of foundations to an edifice, but of roots to a tree, which may perform their office equally well though they be never dug down to and exposed to light. But though in science the particular truths precede the general theory, the contrary might be expected to be the case with a practical art, such as morals or legislation. All action is for the sake of some end, and rules of action, it seems natural to suppose, must take their whole character and colour from the end to which they are subservient. When we engage in a pursuit, a clear and precise conception of what we are pursuing would seem to be the first thing we need, instead of the last we are to look forward to. A test of right and wrong must be the means, one would think, of ascertaining what is right or wrong, and not a consequence of having already ascertained it.
It’s true that there’s a lot of confusion and uncertainty, and sometimes even disagreement, about the basic principles of all sciences, including the one thought to be the most certain, mathematics. Yet, this doesn’t usually affect the reliability of the conclusions of those sciences. It seems contradictory, but the reason is that the detailed doctrines of a science are not typically derived from, nor do they rely on, what are known as its basic principles. If that were the case, algebra would be the most unstable science, with its conclusions barely established, because it doesn’t get its certainty from what is usually taught as its foundational elements. Those elements, as articulated by some of its best teachers, are just as fictional as English law and as mysterious as theology. The truths that are ultimately recognized as the basic principles of a science are actually the final results of a deep analysis of the fundamental ideas that the science deals with. Their connection to the science isn’t like a building’s foundation, but rather like a tree’s roots, which can serve their purpose just as well even if they’re never dug up or exposed to the light. However, while in science, the specific truths come before the general theory, one might expect the opposite to be true in practical fields, like ethics or law. Every action is aimed at some goal, and it seems natural to think that action rules should be shaped entirely by the end they serve. When we start a pursuit, having a clear and precise understanding of what we’re going after should be the first thing we need, not the last thing to look forward to. A measure of right and wrong should help us determine what is right or wrong, rather than coming after we’ve already figured it out.
The difficulty is not avoided by having recourse to the popular theory of a natural faculty, a sense or instinct, informing us of right and wrong. For—besides that the existence of such a moral instinct is itself one of the matters in dispute—those believers in it who have any pretensions to philosophy, have been obliged to abandon the idea that it discerns what is right or wrong in the particular case in hand, as our other senses discern the sight or sound actually present. Our moral faculty, according to all those of its interpreters who are entitled to the name of thinkers, supplies us only with the general principles of moral judgments; it is a branch of our reason, not of our sensitive faculty; and must be looked to for the abstract doctrines of morality, not for perception of it in the concrete. The intuitive, no less than what may be termed the inductive, school of ethics, insists on the necessity of general laws. They both agree that the morality of an individual action is not a question of direct perception, but of the application of a law to an individual case. They recognise also, to a great extent, the same moral laws; but differ as to their evidence, and the source from which they derive their authority. According to the one opinion, the principles of morals are evident à priori, requiring nothing to command assent, except that the meaning of the terms be understood. According to the other doctrine, right and wrong, as well as truth and falsehood, are questions of observation and experience. But both hold equally that morality must be deduced from principles; and the intuitive school affirm as strongly as the inductive, that there is a science of morals. Yet they seldom attempt to make out a list of the à priori principles which are to serve as the premises of the science; still more rarely do they make any effort to reduce those various principles to one first principle, or common ground of obligation. They either assume the ordinary precepts of morals as of à priori authority, or they lay down as the common groundwork of those maxims, some generality much less obviously authoritative than the maxims themselves, and which has never succeeded in gaining popular acceptance. Yet to support their pretensions there ought either to be some one fundamental principle or law, at the root of all morality, or if there be several, there should be a determinate order of precedence among them; and the one principle, or the rule for deciding between the various principles when they conflict, ought to be self-evident.
The difficulty isn't resolved by relying on the popular idea of a natural ability, a sense or instinct, that tells us right from wrong. Because—aside from the fact that the existence of such a moral instinct is itself a point of contention—those who believe in it and consider themselves philosophical have had to give up the notion that it determines what is right or wrong in specific situations, like our other senses identify the sights or sounds that are actually present. Our moral faculty, according to all those interpreters deserving to be called thinkers, only provides us with the general principles of moral judgments; it’s a part of our reasoning, not our sensory perception; it should guide us on abstract moral doctrines, not on recognizing morality in specific cases. The intuitive school and the inductive school of ethics both stress the necessity of general laws. They agree that the morality of a specific action isn't a matter of direct perception but of applying a law to an individual situation. They also largely acknowledge the same moral laws but disagree on their justification and the source of their authority. One viewpoint asserts that the principles of morality are clear à priori, needing nothing to be accepted other than an understanding of the terminology. According to the other view, right and wrong, along with truth and falsehood, come from observation and experience. However, both agree that morality must be inferred from principles; and the intuitive school insists just as firmly as the inductive school that there is a science of morals. Yet they rarely try to list the à priori principles that should be the basis of this science; even less often do they attempt to boil those various principles down to one fundamental principle or common basis of obligation. They either take the usual moral precepts as having à priori authority or establish a common foundation for those maxims with a generality that is far less obviously authoritative than the maxims themselves and that has never truly gained widespread acceptance. Yet to validate their claims, there should be a single fundamental principle or law at the base of all morality, or if there are multiple ones, there should be a clear hierarchy among them; and that single principle, or the rule for resolving conflicts between different principles, should be self-evident.
To inquire how far the bad effects of this deficiency have been mitigated in practice, or to what extent the moral beliefs of mankind have been vitiated or made uncertain by the absence of any distinct recognition of an ultimate standard, would imply a complete survey and criticism of past and present ethical doctrine. It would, however, be easy to show that whatever steadiness or consistency these moral beliefs have attained, has been mainly due to the tacit influence of a standard not recognised. Although the non-existence of an acknowledged first principle has made ethics not so much a guide as a consecration of men's actual sentiments, still, as men's sentiments, both of favour and of aversion, are greatly influenced by what they suppose to be the effects of things upon their happiness, the principle of utility, or as Bentham latterly called it, the greatest happiness principle, has had a large share in forming the moral doctrines even of those who most scornfully reject its authority. Nor is there any school of thought which refuses to admit that the influence of actions on happiness is a most material and even predominant consideration in many of the details of morals, however unwilling to acknowledge it as the fundamental principle of morality, and the source of moral obligation. I might go much further, and say that to all those à priori moralists who deem it necessary to argue at all, utilitarian arguments are indispensable. It is not my present purpose to criticise these thinkers; but I cannot help referring, for illustration, to a systematic treatise by one of the most illustrious of them, the Metaphysics of Ethics, by Kant. This remarkable man, whose system of thought will long remain one of the landmarks in the history of philosophical speculation, does, in the treatise in question, lay down an universal first principle as the origin and ground of moral obligation; it is this:—'So act, that the rule on which thou actest would admit of being adopted as a law by all rational beings.' But when he begins to deduce from this precept any of the actual duties of morality, he fails, almost grotesquely, to show that there would be any contradiction, any logical (not to say physical) impossibility, in the adoption by all rational beings of the most outrageously immoral rules of conduct. All he shows is that the consequences of their universal adoption would be such as no one would choose to incur.
To examine how much the negative effects of this deficiency have been reduced in practice, or how much human moral beliefs have been undermined or made uncertain by the lack of a clear recognition of an ultimate standard, would require a thorough review and critique of both past and current ethical theories. However, it would be easy to demonstrate that the stability or consistency of these moral beliefs has largely come from the unacknowledged influence of a standard that isn’t recognized. Although the absence of a recognized first principle has made ethics less of a guide and more a reflection of people's actual feelings, since people's feelings of approval and disapproval are heavily influenced by what they believe are the effects of things on their happiness, the principle of utility, or what Bentham later termed the greatest happiness principle, has played a significant role in shaping moral doctrines, even among those who vehemently reject its authority. Moreover, there isn’t any school of thought that denies that the impact of actions on happiness is a significant and even primary consideration in many moral details, even if they are reluctant to accept it as the foundational principle of morality and the source of moral obligation. I could go much further and say that for all those a priori moralists who believe it is necessary to argue at all, utilitarian arguments are essential. I don’t intend to critique these thinkers here, but I can’t help referencing a systematic work by one of the most renowned among them, the *Metaphysics of Ethics* by Kant. This remarkable individual, whose system of thought will remain a significant reference point in the history of philosophical speculation, sets out a universal first principle as the basis and source of moral obligation: 'Act in such a way that the rule guiding your action could be adopted as a law by all rational beings.' However, when he tries to derive any actual moral duties from this principle, he almost hilariously fails to demonstrate that there would be any contradiction, any logical (or even physical) impossibility, in all rational beings adopting the most shockingly immoral rules of conduct. All he shows is that the consequences of their universal acceptance would be something no one would want to face.
On the present occasion, I shall, without further discussion of the other theories, attempt to contribute something towards the understanding and appreciation of the Utilitarian or Happiness theory, and towards such proof as it is susceptible of. It is evident that this cannot be proof in the ordinary and popular meaning of the term. Questions of ultimate ends are not amenable to direct proof. Whatever can be proved to be good, must be so by being shown to be a means to something admitted to be good without proof. The medical art is proved to be good, by its conducing to health; but how is it possible to prove that health is good? The art of music is good, for the reason, among others, that it produces pleasure; but what proof is it possible to give that pleasure is good? If, then, it is asserted that there is a comprehensive formula, including all things which are in themselves good, and that whatever else is good, is not so as an end, but as a mean, the formula may be accepted or rejected, but is not a subject of what is commonly understood by proof. We are not, however, to infer that its acceptance or rejection must depend on blind impulse, or arbitrary choice. There is a larger meaning of the word proof, in which this question is as amenable to it as any other of the disputed questions of philosophy. The subject is within the cognizance of the rational faculty; and neither does that faculty deal with it solely in the way of intuition. Considerations may be presented capable of determining the intellect either to give or withhold its assent to the doctrine; and this is equivalent to proof.
On this occasion, I will, without diving into other theories, try to add to the understanding and appreciation of the Utilitarian or Happiness theory, as well as any proof it might have. It’s clear that this can’t be proof in the usual sense of the word. Questions about ultimate goals can’t be directly proven. Anything that can be shown to be good must be demonstrated as a means to something else that is accepted as good without needing proof. For example, the medical field is seen as good because it leads to health; but how can we prove that health is good? The art of music is considered good, partly because it brings pleasure; but what proof can we offer that pleasure is good? Therefore, if it is claimed that there is a broad formula that encompasses everything that is inherently good, and that anything else that is good is not an end in itself but a means to an end, this formula can be accepted or rejected, but it isn’t something that fits the usual idea of proof. However, we shouldn’t think that its acceptance or rejection has to rely on blind instinct or random choice. There’s a broader interpretation of proof, in which this question is just as subject to it as any other philosophical debate. The topic is within the realm of rational thought; and this faculty doesn’t only engage with it through intuition. Arguments can be made that can lead the mind to either agree or disagree with the doctrine; and this is equivalent to proof.
We shall examine presently of what nature are these considerations; in what manner they apply to the case, and what rational grounds, therefore, can be given for accepting or rejecting the utilitarian formula. But it is a preliminary condition of rational acceptance or rejection, that the formula should be correctly understood. I believe that the very imperfect notion ordinarily formed of its meaning, is the chief obstacle which impedes its reception; and that could it be cleared, even from only the grosser misconceptions, the question would be greatly simplified, and a large proportion of its difficulties removed. Before, therefore, I attempt to enter into the philosophical grounds which can be given for assenting to the utilitarian standard, I shall offer some illustrations of the doctrine itself; with the view of showing more clearly what it is, distinguishing it from what it is not, and disposing of such of the practical objections to it as either originate in, or are closely connected with, mistaken interpretations of its meaning. Having thus prepared the ground, I shall afterwards endeavour to throw such light as I can upon the question, considered as one of philosophical theory.
We will currently look at the nature of these considerations; how they apply to the case, and what logical reasons can be provided for accepting or rejecting the utilitarian formula. However, a key first step in rationally accepting or rejecting it is that the formula should be understood correctly. I believe that the very limited understanding most people have of its meaning is the main obstacle to its acceptance; if we could clear up just the more obvious misunderstandings, the question would become much simpler, and many of its difficulties would be resolved. Before I dive into the philosophical reasons for agreeing with the utilitarian standard, I will provide some examples of the doctrine itself to clarify what it is, differentiate it from what it isn’t, and address some of the practical objections that arise from, or are closely tied to, misinterpretations of its meaning. Having laid this groundwork, I will then try to shed some light on the question as a matter of philosophical theory.
CHAPTER II.
A passing remark is all that needs be given to the ignorant blunder of supposing that those who stand up for utility as the test of right and wrong, use the term in that restricted and merely colloquial sense in which utility is opposed to pleasure. An apology is due to the philosophical opponents of utilitarianism, for even the momentary appearance of confounding them with any one capable of so absurd a misconception; which is the more extraordinary, inasmuch as the contrary accusation, of referring everything to pleasure, and that too in its grossest form, is another of the common charges against utilitarianism: and, as has been pointedly remarked by an able writer, the same sort of persons, and often the very same persons, denounce the theory "as impracticably dry when the word utility precedes the word pleasure, and as too practicably voluptuous when the word pleasure precedes the word utility." Those who know anything about the matter are aware that every writer, from Epicurus to Bentham, who maintained the theory of utility, meant by it, not something to be contradistinguished from pleasure, but pleasure itself, together with exemption from pain; and instead of opposing the useful to the agreeable or the ornamental, have always declared that the useful means these, among other things. Yet the common herd, including the herd of writers, not only in newspapers and periodicals, but in books of weight and pretension, are perpetually falling into this shallow mistake. Having caught up the word utilitarian, while knowing nothing whatever about it but its sound, they habitually express by it the rejection, or the neglect, of pleasure in some of its forms; of beauty, of ornament, or of amusement. Nor is the term thus ignorantly misapplied solely in disparagement, but occasionally in compliment; as though it implied superiority to frivolity and the mere pleasures of the moment. And this perverted use is the only one in which the word is popularly known, and the one from which the new generation are acquiring their sole notion of its meaning. Those who introduced the word, but who had for many years discontinued it as a distinctive appellation, may well feel themselves called upon to resume it, if by doing so they can hope to contribute anything towards rescuing it from this utter degradation.[A]
A brief comment is all that's needed about the mistaken belief that people who advocate for utility as the measure of right and wrong use the term in a limited and casual way, where utility is seen as the opposite of pleasure. Those who argue against utilitarianism deserve an apology for even being hinted at as having such a ridiculous misunderstanding; this is especially surprising since the opposite accusation—that everything refers to pleasure, particularly in its most crude form—is also a frequent criticism of utilitarianism. As noted by a skilled writer, the very same people often criticize the theory as "impractically dry" when the word utility comes before pleasure, and then as "too practicably indulgent" when pleasure comes before utility. Anyone who knows anything about this topic is aware that every thinker, from Epicurus to Bentham, who supported the theory of utility meant it as pleasure itself, along with freedom from pain; and instead of contrasting the useful with the enjoyable or decorative, they have always declared that being useful includes all of these aspects. Yet the general public, including many writers in newspapers, magazines, and weighty books, consistently falls into this superficial error. They have picked up the term utilitarian without understanding its meaning, and they often use it to dismiss or overlook pleasure in various forms, such as beauty, decoration, or fun. This term is misused not only in a negative way but also sometimes positively, as if it suggests an elevation above triviality and momentary pleasures. Unfortunately, this twisted usage is the only one widely recognized, and from it, the new generation is learning their sole understanding of the term. Those who originally introduced the word, but have long since stopped using it as a specific label, may feel the need to revive it if there's any chance of helping restore it from this complete degradation.[A]
The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, Utility, or the Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure. To give a clear view of the moral standard set up by the theory, much more requires to be said; in particular, what things it includes in the ideas of pain and pleasure; and to what extent this is left an open question. But these supplementary explanations do not affect the theory of life on which this theory of morality is grounded—namely, that pleasure, and freedom from pain, are the only things desirable as ends; and that all desirable things (which are as numerous in the utilitarian as in any other scheme) are desirable either for the pleasure inherent in themselves, or as means to the promotion of pleasure and the prevention of pain.
The belief that bases morals on Utility, or the Greatest Happiness Principle, asserts that actions are right if they promote happiness and wrong if they lead to unhappiness. Happiness means pleasure and the absence of pain, while unhappiness refers to pain and the lack of pleasure. To clearly explain the moral standard established by this theory, much more needs to be addressed, especially regarding what is included in the definitions of pain and pleasure, and to what extent this question remains open. However, these additional explanations do not impact the life theory that underpins this moral theory—specifically, that pleasure and freedom from pain are the only things that are inherently desirable as ends, and that all desirable things (which are just as many in utilitarianism as in any other framework) are desirable either for the pleasure they bring or as a means to promote pleasure and prevent pain.
Now, such a theory of life excites in many minds, and among them in some of the most estimable in feeling and purpose, inveterate dislike. To suppose that life has (as they express it) no higher end than pleasure—no better and nobler object of desire and pursuit—they designate as utterly mean and grovelling; as a doctrine worthy only of swine, to whom the followers of Epicurus were, at a very early period, contemptuously likened; and modern holders of the doctrine are occasionally made the subject of equally polite comparisons by its German, French, and English assailants.
Now, this idea about life sparks strong dislike in many people, including some who are very good-natured and well-intentioned. The thought that life has no higher purpose than pleasure—no better or nobler goal to strive for—is seen as completely low and base; they view it as a belief only fit for pigs, much like how the followers of Epicurus were dismissed a long time ago. Today, proponents of this idea are sometimes met with equally dismissive comparisons from critics in Germany, France, and England.
When thus attacked, the Epicureans have always answered, that it is not they, but their accusers, who represent human nature in a degrading light; since the accusation supposes human beings to be capable of no pleasures except those of which swine are capable. If this supposition were true, the charge could not be gainsaid, but would then be no longer an imputation; for if the sources of pleasure were precisely the same to human beings and to swine, the rule of life which is good enough for the one would be good enough for the other. The comparison of the Epicurean life to that of beasts is felt as degrading, precisely because a beast's pleasures do not satisfy a human being's conceptions of happiness. Human beings have faculties more elevated than the animal appetites, and when once made conscious of them, do not regard anything as happiness which does not include their gratification. I do not, indeed, consider the Epicureans to have been by any means faultless in drawing out their scheme of consequences from the utilitarian principle. To do this in any sufficient manner, many Stoic, as well as Christian elements require to be included. But there is no known Epicurean theory of life which does not assign to the pleasures of the intellect; of the feelings and imagination, and of the moral sentiments, a much higher value as pleasures than to those of mere sensation. It must be admitted, however, that utilitarian writers in general have placed the superiority of mental over bodily pleasures chiefly in the greater permanency, safety, uncostliness, &c., of the former—that is, in their circumstantial advantages rather than in their intrinsic nature. And on all these points utilitarians have fully proved their case; but they might have taken the other, and, as it may be called, higher ground, with entire consistency. It is quite compatible with the principle of utility to recognise the fact, that some kinds of pleasure are more desirable and more valuable than others. It would be absurd that while, in estimating all other things, quality is considered as well as quantity, the estimation of pleasures should be supposed to depend on quantity alone.
When attacked, the Epicureans have always responded that it's not them, but their critics, who portray human nature in a negative light; because the accusation assumes that humans can only experience the same pleasures as pigs. If that assumption were true, the accusation would be valid, but it wouldn’t be an insult; if the sources of pleasure were exactly the same for both humans and pigs, then the lifestyle that works for one would work for the other. The comparison of the Epicurean way of life to that of animals is seen as degrading because an animal's pleasures don’t satisfy a human’s idea of happiness. Humans have higher faculties than mere animal instincts, and once they become aware of them, they don’t consider anything as happiness that doesn’t fulfill those higher needs. I don’t think the Epicureans were perfect in fully developing their consequences from the utilitarian principle. To do this adequately, they would need to include many Stoic and Christian elements. But there's no known Epicurean view of life that doesn't give higher value to the pleasures of the intellect, feelings, imagination, and moral sentiments compared to just physical sensations. However, it must be acknowledged that most utilitarian writers emphasize the superiority of mental pleasures mainly based on their greater permanence, safety, affordability, etc., which are circumstantial benefits rather than intrinsic qualities. On all these points, utilitarians have made their case effectively; but they could have taken the other, arguably more profound stance with complete consistency. It aligns with the principle of utility to recognize that some types of pleasure are more desirable and valuable than others. It would be ridiculous that while assessing everything else, both quality and quantity are considered, the assessment of pleasures is assumed to depend solely on quantity.
If I am asked, what I mean by difference of quality in pleasures, or what makes one pleasure more valuable than another, merely as a pleasure, except its being greater in amount, there is but one possible answer. Of two pleasures, if there be one to which all or almost all who have experience of both give a decided preference, irrespective of any feeling of moral obligation to prefer it, that is the more desirable pleasure. If one of the two is, by those who are competently acquainted with both, placed so far above the other that they prefer it, even though knowing it to be attended with a greater amount of discontent, and would not resign it for any quantity of the other pleasure which their nature is capable of, we are justified in ascribing to the preferred enjoyment a superiority in quality, so far outweighing quantity as to render it, in comparison, of small account.
If you ask me what I mean by the difference in quality of pleasures or what makes one pleasure more valuable than another, aside from the amount of pleasure, there’s really only one answer. When comparing two pleasures, if there’s one that almost everyone who has experienced both clearly prefers, regardless of any sense of moral duty to choose it, that is the more desirable pleasure. If those who are truly familiar with both pleasures rank one so much higher than the other that they choose it, even knowing it comes with more discontent, and wouldn’t give it up for any amount of the other pleasure they could have, we can justifiably say that the preferred pleasure has a higher quality, so much so that its quantity becomes relatively insignificant.
Now it is an unquestionable fact that those who are equally acquainted with, and equally capable of appreciating and enjoying, both, do give a most marked preference to the manner of existence which employs their higher faculties. Few human creatures would consent to be changed into any of the lower animals, for a promise of the fullest allowance of a beast's pleasures; no intelligent human being would consent to be a fool, no instructed person would be an ignoramus, no person of feeling and conscience would be selfish and base, even though they should be persuaded that the fool, the dunce, or the rascal is better satisfied with his lot than they are with theirs. They would not resign what they possess more than he, for the most complete satisfaction of all the desires which they have in common with him. If they ever fancy they would, it is only in cases of unhappiness so extreme, that to escape from it they would exchange their lot for almost any other, however undesirable in their own eyes. A being of higher faculties requires more to make him happy, is capable probably of more acute suffering, and is certainly accessible to it at more points, than one of an inferior type; but in spite of these liabilities, he can never really wish to sink into what he feels to be a lower grade of existence. We may give what explanation we please of this unwillingness; we may attribute it to pride, a name which is given indiscriminately to some of the most and to some of the least estimable feelings of which mankind are capable; we may refer it to the love of liberty and personal independence, an appeal to which was with the Stoics one of the most effective means for the inculcation of it; to the love of power, or to the love of excitement, both of which do really enter into and contribute to it: but its most appropriate appellation is a sense of dignity, which all human beings possess in one form or other, and in some, though by no means in exact, proportion to their higher faculties, and which is so essential a part of the happiness of those in whom it is strong, that nothing which conflicts with it could be, otherwise than momentarily, an object of desire to them. Whoever supposes that this preference takes place at a sacrifice of happiness-that the superior being, in anything like equal circumstances, is not happier than the inferior-confounds the two very different ideas, of happiness, and content. It is indisputable that the being whose capacities of enjoyment are low, has the greatest chance of having them fully satisfied; and a highly-endowed being will always feel that any happiness which he can look for, as the world is constituted, is imperfect. But he can learn to bear its imperfections, if they are at all bearable; and they will not make him envy the being who is indeed unconscious of the imperfections, but only because he feels not at all the good which those imperfections qualify. It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied. And if the fool, or the pig, is of a different opinion, it is because they only know their own side of the question. The other party to the comparison knows both sides.
Now it’s a well-established fact that those who truly understand and can appreciate both sides tend to favor a way of life that engages their higher faculties. Few people would agree to be transformed into any lower animal, even for the chance to experience a beast's full range of pleasures; no intelligent person would choose to be a fool, no educated individual would want to be ignorant, and no person with feelings and a conscience would want to be selfish and immoral, even if they were convinced that the fool, the dunce, or the scoundrel is happier than they are. They wouldn’t give up what they have, which is more than what those others possess, for the complete satisfaction of all shared desires. If they ever think they would, it would only be in extreme unhappiness, when they might trade their situation for almost any other, regardless of how undesirable. A person with higher faculties needs more to be happy, may suffer more acutely, and is definitely more vulnerable to suffering than someone of a lower type; but despite these challenges, they can never genuinely wish to descend into what they perceive as a lower form of existence. We can offer whatever explanations we like for this resistance; we can attribute it to pride, a term used broadly to describe both admirable and less admirable feelings that humans are capable of; we can link it to the desire for freedom and personal independence, which the Stoics considered one of the most effective principles for promoting it; to the desire for power, or to the craving for excitement, both of which contribute to it. However, the most fitting description is a sense of dignity that all human beings possess in one form or another, somehow correlated to their higher faculties. This sense of dignity is such a vital part of the happiness of those who possess it strongly that nothing conflicting with it could be truly desired, except fleetingly. Anyone who thinks this preference comes at the cost of happiness—that a superior being, under similar conditions, is not happier than an inferior one—confuses two very different concepts: happiness and contentment. It’s undeniable that a being with low capacities for enjoyment has the greatest chance of those capacities being fully satisfied; a highly endowed being will always feel that the happiness available to them in the current world is insufficient. However, they can learn to tolerate its imperfections if they are at all bearable, and those imperfections won’t make them envy the being who is blissfully unaware of them, simply because they don’t experience the good that those imperfections diminish. It’s better to be a dissatisfied human than a satisfied pig; better to be a dissatisfied Socrates than a satisfied fool. And if the fool or the pig thinks differently, it’s because they only see their own perspective. The person making the comparison understands both sides.
It may be objected, that many who are capable of the higher pleasures, occasionally, under the influence of temptation, postpone them to the lower. But this is quite compatible with a full appreciation of the intrinsic superiority of the higher. Men often, from infirmity of character, make their election for the nearer good, though they know it to be the less valuable; and this no less when the choice is between two bodily pleasures, than when it is between bodily and mental. They pursue sensual indulgences to the injury of health, though perfectly aware that health is the greater good. It may be further objected, that many who begin with youthful enthusiasm for everything noble, as they advance in years sink into indolence and selfishness. But I do not believe that those who undergo this very common change, voluntarily choose the lower description of pleasures in preference to the higher. I believe that before they devote themselves exclusively to the one, they have already become incapable of the other. Capacity for the nobler feelings is in most natures a very tender plant, easily killed, not only by hostile influences, but by mere want of sustenance; and in the majority of young persons it speedily dies away if the occupations to which their position in life has devoted them, and the society into which it has thrown them, are not favourable to keeping that higher capacity in exercise. Men lose their high aspirations as they lose their intellectual tastes, because they have not time or opportunity for indulging them; and they addict themselves to inferior pleasures, not because they deliberately prefer them, but because they are either the only ones to which they have access, or the only ones which they are any longer capable of enjoying. It may be questioned whether any one who has remained equally susceptible to both classes of pleasures, ever knowingly and calmly preferred the lower; though many, in all ages, have broken down in an ineffectual attempt to combine both.
Some might argue that many people who are capable of experiencing greater pleasures sometimes, under temptation, choose to go for lesser ones instead. However, this doesn’t contradict the idea that they fully recognize the inherent superiority of the greater pleasures. People often, due to weaknesses in their character, opt for the more immediate gratification, even when they know it's less worthwhile; this happens just as much when comparing two physical pleasures as when comparing physical and mental ones. They chase after sensual pleasures to the detriment of their health, even though they are fully aware that good health is far more valuable. Additionally, it could be argued that many who start out with youthful enthusiasm for noble pursuits tend to drift into laziness and selfishness as they grow older. However, I don't think those who experience this common change consciously choose lesser pleasures over the greater ones. I believe that by the time they focus solely on one type, they have already lost the ability to appreciate the other. The capacity for higher feelings is, in most people, a fragile thing, easily destroyed not just by negative influences, but also by a simple lack of nourishment; for most young people, it quickly fades away if their life circumstances and the society they find themselves in don't support the development of that higher capacity. People lose their lofty aspirations just as they lose their intellectual interests because they no longer have the time or opportunities to indulge in them; they turn to lower pleasures not because they really prefer them, but because those are the only ones available to them or the only ones they can still enjoy. It’s debatable whether anyone who has maintained an equal susceptibility to both types of pleasures has ever knowingly and calmly chosen the lesser ones; although many throughout history have struggled in vain to find a way to enjoy both.
From this verdict of the only competent judges, I apprehend there can be no appeal. On a question which is the best worth having of two pleasures, or which of two modes of existence is the most grateful to the feelings, apart from its moral attributes and from its consequences, the judgment of those who are qualified by knowledge of both, or, if they differ, that of the majority among them, must be admitted as final. And there needs be the less hesitation to accept this judgment respecting the quality of pleasures, since there is no other tribunal to be referred to even on the question of quantity. What means are there of determining which is the acutest of two pains, or the intensest of two pleasurable sensations, except the general suffrage of those who are familiar with both? Neither pains nor pleasures are homogeneous, and pain is always heterogeneous with pleasure. What is there to decide whether a particular pleasure is worth purchasing at the cost of a particular pain, except the feelings and judgment of the experienced? When, therefore, those feelings and judgment declare the pleasures derived from the higher faculties to be preferable in kind, apart from the question of intensity, to those of which the animal nature, disjoined from the higher faculties, is susceptible, they are entitled on this subject to the same regard.
From this verdict of the only qualified judges, I understand there can be no appeal. When deciding which of two pleasures is better or which of two ways of living is more satisfying in terms of feelings, not considering moral aspects or consequences, the judgment of those who truly understand both, or the majority opinion among them, must be accepted as final. There is even less reason to hesitate in accepting this judgment about the quality of pleasures since there's no other authority to consult, even regarding quantity. What other way is there to determine which of two pains is sharper or which of two pleasurable experiences is stronger, except through the collective opinion of those who have experienced both? Neither pain nor pleasure is the same across the board, and pain is always different from pleasure. What determines whether a specific pleasure is worth the price of a specific pain, other than the feelings and opinions of those who have experienced both? Therefore, when those feelings and opinions indicate that the pleasures coming from higher faculties are better in kind, regardless of intensity, than those available to our animal nature, separate from those higher faculties, they deserve equal consideration on this topic.
I have dwelt on this point, as being a necessary part of a perfectly just conception of Utility or Happiness, considered as the directive rule of human conduct. But it is by no means an indispensable condition to the acceptance of the utilitarian standard; for that standard is not the agent's own greatest happiness, but the greatest amount of happiness altogether; and if it may possibly be doubted whether a noble character is always the happier for its nobleness, there can be no doubt that it makes other people happier, and that the world in general is immensely a gainer by it. Utilitarianism, therefore, could only attain its end by the general cultivation of nobleness of character, even if each individual were only benefited by the nobleness of others, and his own, so far as happiness is concerned, were a sheer deduction from the benefit. But the bare enunciation of such an absurdity as this last, renders refutation superfluous.
I have focused on this point as it is a crucial aspect of a complete understanding of Utility or Happiness, viewed as the guiding principle of human behavior. However, it is not an essential requirement for accepting the utilitarian standard; that standard is not focused on the individual's own greatest happiness but rather on the greatest overall happiness. While it's debatable whether a noble character is always happier due to its nobility, it’s clear that such character brings happiness to others, and that society as a whole benefits immensely from it. Therefore, utilitarianism can only achieve its purpose through the widespread promotion of noble character, even if each person gains only from the nobility of others, and their own happiness is a direct result of that benefit. However, simply stating such an absurdity makes further argument unnecessary.
According to the Greatest Happiness Principle, as above explained, the ultimate end, with reference to and for the sake of which all other things are desirable (whether we are considering our own good or that of other people), is an existence exempt as far as possible from pain, and as rich as possible in enjoyments, both in point of quantity and quality; the test of quality, and the rule for measuring it against quantity, being the preference felt by those who, in their opportunities of experience, to which must be added their habits of self-consciousness and self-observation, are best furnished with the means of comparison. This, being, according to the utilitarian opinion, the end of human action, is necessarily also the standard of morality; which may accordingly be defined, the rules and precepts for human conduct, by the observance of which an existence such as has been described might be, to the greatest extent possible, secured to all mankind; and not to them only, but, so far as the nature of things admits, to the whole sentient creation.
According to the Greatest Happiness Principle, as explained above, the ultimate goal—considering both our own well-being and that of others—is to live a life as free from pain as possible and rich in enjoyment, both in quantity and quality. The measure of quality, and how it compares to quantity, is determined by the preferences of those who have the best opportunities for experience, along with their habits of self-awareness and self-observation. This, according to utilitarian thought, is the purpose of human action and also serves as the basis for morality. Thus, morality can be defined as the rules and guidelines for human behavior that help secure the kind of existence described for everyone; and not just for people, but for all sentient beings, as much as reality allows.
Against this doctrine, however, arises another class of objectors, who say that happiness, in any form, cannot be the rational purpose of human life and action; because, in the first place, it is unattainable: and they contemptuously ask, What right hast thou to be happy? a question which Mr. Carlyle clenches by the addition, What right, a short time ago, hadst thou even to be? Next, they say, that men can do without happiness; that all noble human beings have felt this, and could not have become noble but by learning the lesson of Entsagen, or renunciation; which lesson, thoroughly learnt and submitted to, they affirm to be the beginning and necessary condition of all virtue.
Against this belief, however, a different group of critics argues that happiness, in any form, cannot be the rational purpose of human life and actions; because, first of all, it’s unattainable: and they scornfully ask, What right do you have to be happy? a question that Mr. Carlyle emphasizes by adding, What right, not long ago, did you have even to be? Next, they argue that people can do without happiness; that all noble individuals have experienced this, and could not have become noble without learning the lesson of Entsagen, or renunciation; which lesson, thoroughly learned and accepted, they claim to be the starting point and essential condition of all virtue.
The first of these objections would go to the root of the matter were it well founded; for if no happiness is to be had at all by human beings, the attainment of it cannot be the end of morality, or of any rational conduct. Though, even in that case, something might still be said for the utilitarian theory; since utility includes not solely the pursuit of happiness, but the prevention or mitigation of unhappiness; and if the former aim be chimerical, there will be all the greater scope and more imperative need for the latter, so long at least as mankind think fit to live, and do not take refuge in the simultaneous act of suicide recommended under certain conditions by Novalis. When, however, it is thus positively asserted to be impossible that human life should be happy, the assertion, if not something like a verbal quibble, is at least an exaggeration. If by happiness be meant a continuity of highly pleasurable excitement, it is evident enough that this is impossible. A state of exalted pleasure lasts only moments, or in some cases, and with some intermissions, hours or days, and is the occasional brilliant flash of enjoyment, not its permanent and steady flame. Of this the philosophers who have taught that happiness is the end of life were as fully aware as those who taunt them. The happiness which they meant was not a life of rapture, but moments of such, in an existence made up of few and transitory pains, many and various pleasures, with a decided predominance of the active over the passive, and having as the foundation of the whole, not to expect more from life than it is capable of bestowing. A life thus composed, to those who have been fortunate enough to obtain it, has always appeared worthy of the name of happiness. And such an existence is even now the lot of many, during some considerable portion of their lives. The present wretched education, and wretched social arrangements, are the only real hindrance to its being attainable by almost all.
The first of these objections would really get to the heart of the matter if it were valid; because if humans can’t achieve any happiness at all, then seeking it can’t be the ultimate goal of morality or any logical behavior. However, even in that scenario, there could still be some merit to the utilitarian theory, since utility involves not just the pursuit of happiness, but also the prevention or reduction of unhappiness. If the first goal is impossible, then there would be an even greater need for the latter, as long as people choose to live and don’t resort to the simultaneous act of suicide that Novalis suggested under certain circumstances. When it is emphatically claimed that it’s impossible for human life to be happy, that claim is, at the very least, an exaggeration if not a verbal trick. If happiness is defined as a continuous state of intense pleasure, it’s clear that this is unattainable. A state of intense pleasure lasts only moments, or sometimes, with breaks, a few hours or days; it’s a fleeting burst of enjoyment, not a steady, ongoing state. The philosophers who argued that happiness is the goal of life were just as aware of this as those who criticize them. The happiness they referred to wasn’t a life filled with ecstasy, but rather moments of it in a life characterized by few short pains, many and varied pleasures, with a definite emphasis on actively engaging with life rather than being passive, and with the understanding that one shouldn’t expect more from life than it can actually provide. For those fortunate enough to achieve such a life, it has always seemed deserving of the title of happiness. And many still experience such a life during significant parts of their existence. The current miserable education system and poor social structures are the only real obstacles preventing almost everyone from attaining it.
The objectors perhaps may doubt whether human beings, if taught to consider happiness as the end of life, would be satisfied with such a moderate share of it. But great numbers of mankind have been satisfied with much less. The main constituents of a satisfied life appear to be two, either of which by itself is often found sufficient for the purpose: tranquillity, and excitement. With much tranquillity, many find that they can be content with very little pleasure: with much excitement, many can reconcile themselves to a considerable quantity of pain. There is assuredly no inherent impossibility in enabling even the mass of mankind to unite both; since the two are so far from being incompatible that they are in natural alliance, the prolongation of either being a preparation for, and exciting a wish for, the other. It is only those in whom indolence amounts to a vice, that do not desire excitement after an interval of repose; it is only those in whom the need of excitement is a disease, that feel the tranquillity which follows excitement dull and insipid, instead of pleasurable in direct proportion to the excitement which preceded it. When people who are tolerably fortunate in their outward lot do not find in life sufficient enjoyment to make it valuable to them, the cause generally is, caring for nobody but themselves. To those who have neither public nor private affections, the excitements of life are much curtailed, and in any case dwindle in value as the time approaches when all selfish interests must be terminated by death: while those who leave after them objects of personal affection, and especially those who have also cultivated a fellow-feeling with the collective interests of mankind, retain as lively an interest in life on the eve of death as in the vigour of youth and health. Next to selfishness, the principal cause which makes life unsatisfactory, is want of mental cultivation. A cultivated mind—I do not mean that of a philosopher, but any mind to which the fountains of knowledge have been opened, and which has been taught, in any tolerable degree, to exercise its faculties—finds sources of inexhaustible interest in all that surrounds it; in the objects of nature, the achievements of art, the imaginations of poetry, the incidents of history, the ways of mankind past and present, and their prospects in the future. It is possible, indeed, to become indifferent to all this, and that too without having exhausted a thousandth part of it; but only when one has had from the beginning no moral or human interest in these things, and has sought in them only the gratification of curiosity.
The objectors might wonder if people, taught to see happiness as the main goal in life, would really be happy with just a little of it. But many people have found contentment with much less. The key components of a fulfilling life seem to be two: peace and excitement. Many people find that with enough peace, they can be happy with minimal pleasure; and with enough excitement, they can accept a fair amount of pain. There's definitely no inherent reason why most people can't have both, as they complement each other naturally—enjoying one often sets the stage for wanting the other. It’s only those whose laziness borders on a vice who don’t crave excitement after a period of rest, and only those who experience the need for excitement as a problem who find the calm that follows dull and uninspiring, rather than satisfying in proportion to the excitement they just had. When people who have decent circumstances in life don’t find enough enjoyment to make it worthwhile, it’s usually because they only care about themselves. Those who lack both public and personal connections have their experiences of life significantly reduced, and they lose value as they get closer to the end of their lives when all selfish interests must cease; while those who leave behind loved ones, especially those who also share a concern for the collective interests of humanity, maintain a vibrant interest in life even as they approach death, just like when they were young and healthy. Next to selfishness, another major reason life feels unsatisfactory is a lack of mental growth. An educated mind—I don't mean a philosopher's mind, but any mind that has been opened to knowledge and has learned, in some reasonable way, to engage its capabilities—finds endless sources of fascination in everything around it: in nature, in art, in poetry, in historical events, in the behaviors of people throughout history and today, and in future possibilities. It is certainly possible to become indifferent to all of this without having fully explored even a small portion, but that can only happen if one has never had any moral or human interest in these matters and has only pursued them out of mere curiosity.
Now there is absolutely no reason in the nature of things why an amount of mental culture sufficient to give an intelligent interest in these objects of contemplation, should not be the inheritance of every one born in a civilized country. As little is there an inherent necessity that any human being should be a selfish egotist, devoid of every feeling or care but those which centre in his own miserable individuality. Something far superior to this is sufficiently common even now, to give ample earnest of what the human species may be made. Genuine private affections, and a sincere interest in the public good, are possible, though in unequal degrees, to every rightly brought-up human being. In a world in which there is so much to interest, so much to enjoy, and so much also to correct and improve, every one who has this moderate amount of moral and intellectual requisites is capable of an existence which may be called enviable; and unless such a person, through bad laws, or subjection to the will of others, is denied the liberty to use the sources of happiness within his reach, he will not fail to find this enviable existence, if he escape the positive evils of life, the great sources of physical and mental suffering—such as indigence, disease, and the unkindness, worthlessness, or premature loss of objects of affection. The main stress of the problem lies, therefore, in the contest with these calamities, from which it is a rare good fortune entirely to escape; which, as things now are, cannot be obviated, and often cannot be in any material degree mitigated. Yet no one whose opinion deserves a moment's consideration can doubt that most of the great positive evils of the world are in themselves removable, and will, if human affairs continue to improve, be in the end reduced within narrow limits. Poverty, in any sense implying suffering, may be completely extinguished by the wisdom of society, combined with the good sense and providence of individuals. Even that most intractable of enemies, disease, may be indefinitely reduced in dimensions by good physical and moral education, and proper control of noxious influences; while the progress of science holds out a promise for the future of still more direct conquests over this detestable foe. And every advance in that direction relieves us from some, not only of the chances which cut short our own lives, but, what concerns us still more, which deprive us of those in whom our happiness is wrapt up. As for vicissitudes of fortune, and other disappointments connected with worldly circumstances, these are principally the effect either of gross imprudence, of ill-regulated desires, or of bad or imperfect social institutions. All the grand sources, in short, of human suffering are in a great degree, many of them almost entirely, conquerable by human care and effort; and though their removal is grievously slow—though a long succession of generations will perish in the breach before the conquest is completed, and this world becomes all that, if will and knowledge were not wanting, it might easily be made—yet every mind sufficiently intelligent and generous to bear a part, however small and unconspicuous, in the endeavour, will draw a noble enjoyment from the contest itself, which he would not for any bribe in the form of selfish indulgence consent to be without.
Now, there's no reason why everyone born in a civilized country can't have a level of mental culture that allows for a genuine interest in these subjects of contemplation. There's also no inherent necessity for anyone to be a selfish egotist, focused only on their own miserable existence. Something much better is already fairly common, showing what the human species can achieve. Genuine personal attachments and a sincere interest in the public good are achievable, albeit to varying degrees, for anyone who is raised properly. In a world full of things to interest us, enjoy, and also correct and improve, anyone with a moderate level of moral and intellectual qualities can have a life that's enviable. Unless this person is prevented from using the sources of happiness available to them due to bad laws or the will of others, they will likely find this enviable existence, as long as they can escape life’s harsh realities, which are major sources of physical and mental suffering—like poverty, illness, and the unkindness, worthlessness, or premature loss of loved ones. The main challenge lies in dealing with these hardships, which it's rare to completely avoid; these can't be entirely eliminated and often can't even be significantly reduced with current circumstances. Yet, no one whose opinion matters can doubt that many of the major evils in the world can be removed and will eventually be minimized if human affairs continue to improve. Poverty, in any sense that involves suffering, can be completely eradicated through the wisdom of society combined with individuals’ good sense and foresight. Even the most stubborn enemy, disease, can be significantly reduced through proper physical and moral education and controlling harmful influences; meanwhile, scientific progress promises even more direct victories over this terrible foe. Each step forward not only decreases the chances of cutting our own lives short but, more importantly, helps protect those whose happiness is tied to ours. As for the ups and downs of fortune and other disappointments linked to worldly circumstances, these mainly stem from poor judgment, poorly regulated desires, or flawed social institutions. Essentially, the primary sources of human suffering are largely, and in many cases almost entirely, conquerable through human care and effort. Although their removal is painfully slow—many generations may suffer before the conquest is achieved, and this world becomes what it could easily be with enough will and knowledge—every mind that is intelligent and generous enough to contribute, no matter how small and unnoticeable, will find noble enjoyment in the struggle itself, something they wouldn't trade for any selfish indulgence.
And this leads to the true estimation of what is said by the objectors concerning the possibility, and the obligation, of learning to do without happiness. Unquestionably it is possible to do without happiness; it is done involuntarily by nineteen-twentieths of mankind, even in those parts of our present world which are least deep in barbarism; and it often has to be done voluntarily by the hero or the martyr, for the sake of something which he prizes more than his individual happiness. But this something, what is it, unless the happiness of others, or some of the requisites of happiness? It is noble to be capable of resigning entirely one's own portion of happiness, or chances of it: but, after all, this self-sacrifice must be for some end; it is not its own end; and if we are told that its end is not happiness, but virtue, which is better than happiness, I ask, would the sacrifice be made if the hero or martyr did not believe that it would earn for others immunity from similar sacrifices? Would it be made, if he thought that his renunciation of happiness for himself would produce no fruit for any of his fellow creatures, but to make their lot like his, and place them also in the condition of persons who have renounced happiness? All honour to those who can abnegate for themselves the personal enjoyment of life, when by such renunciation they contribute worthily to increase the amount of happiness in the world; but he who does it, or professes to do it, for any other purpose, is no more deserving of admiration than the ascetic mounted on his pillar. He may be an inspiriting proof of what men can do, but assuredly not an example of what they should.
And this brings us to the real assessment of what the critics say about the possibility and obligation of learning to live without happiness. Clearly, it's possible to live without happiness; most people do it involuntarily, even in the parts of our world that are least primitive; and often, it has to be done voluntarily by heroes or martyrs for something they value more than their personal happiness. But what is that something, if not the happiness of others, or some essential components of happiness? It's admirable to completely give up one’s own happiness or chances of it, but in the end, this self-sacrifice must serve a purpose; it’s not an end in itself. If we are told that the purpose is not happiness but virtue—which is considered better than happiness—I ask if that sacrifice would still happen if the hero or martyr didn’t believe it would spare others from similar sacrifices? Would they still make it if they thought that their giving up happiness for themselves would lead to no benefit for anyone else, but rather make their situation just like theirs, leaving them also without happiness? All respect to those who can renounce their personal enjoyment of life when such a sacrifice genuinely helps increase happiness in the world; but someone who does this, or claims to do it, for any other reason is no more worthy of admiration than the ascetic sitting on his pillar. He may be an uplifting example of what humans can do, but definitely not a model of what they should do.
Though it is only in a very imperfect state of the world's arrangements that any one can best serve the happiness of others by the absolute sacrifice of his own, yet so long as the world is in that imperfect state, I fully acknowledge that the readiness to make such a sacrifice is the highest virtue which can be found in man. I will add, that in this condition of the world, paradoxical as the assertion may be, the conscious ability to do without happiness gives the best prospect of realizing such happiness as is attainable. For nothing except that consciousness can raise a person above the chances of life, by making him feel that, let fate and fortune do their worst, they have not power to subdue him: which, once felt, frees him from excess of anxiety concerning the evils of life, and enables him, like many a Stoic in the worst times of the Roman Empire, to cultivate in tranquillity the sources of satisfaction accessible to him, without concerning himself about the uncertainty of their duration, any more than about their inevitable end.
Even though it's only in a very flawed state of the world that someone can truly serve the happiness of others by completely sacrificing their own, I completely recognize that the willingness to make such a sacrifice is the highest virtue a person can possess. I will also add that in this flawed state of the world, no matter how paradoxical it may sound, the awareness of being able to get by without happiness provides the best chance of achieving whatever happiness is possible. Because nothing besides that awareness can elevate a person above life's uncertainties, making them feel that, no matter what fate or fortune throws at them, those forces cannot bring them down: and once someone feels that, it frees them from excessive worry about life's hardships and allows them, like many Stoics during the toughest times of the Roman Empire, to calmly nurture the sources of satisfaction available to them without worrying about how long they will last or their inevitable end.
Meanwhile, let utilitarians never cease to claim the morality of self-devotion as a possession which belongs by as good a right to them, as either to the Stoic or to the Transcendentalist. The utilitarian morality does recognise in human beings the power of sacrificing their own greatest good for the good of others. It only refuses to admit that the sacrifice is itself a good. A sacrifice which does not increase, or tend to increase, the sum total of happiness, it considers as wasted. The only self-renunciation which it applauds, is devotion to the happiness, or to some of the means of happiness, of others; either of mankind collectively, or of individuals within the limits imposed by the collective interests of mankind.
Meanwhile, utilitarians should never stop asserting that the morality of selflessness is just as much theirs as it is for the Stoics or the Transcendentalists. Utilitarian morality recognizes that people have the ability to sacrifice their own greatest good for the benefit of others. It simply refuses to acknowledge that the sacrifice itself is a good thing. A sacrifice that doesn’t increase, or doesn’t aim to increase, overall happiness is considered wasted. The only kind of self-denial it praises is devotion to the happiness, or to some means of happiness, of others; either for humanity as a whole or for individuals within the boundaries set by the collective interests of humanity.
I must again repeat, what the assailants of utilitarianism seldom have the justice to acknowledge, that the happiness which forms the utilitarian standard of what is right in conduct, is not the agent's own happiness, but that of all concerned. As between his own happiness and that of others, utilitarianism requires him to be as strictly impartial as a disinterested and benevolent spectator. In the golden rule of Jesus of Nazareth, we read the complete spirit of the ethics of utility. To do as one would be done by, and to love one's neighbour as oneself, constitute the ideal perfection of utilitarian morality. As the means of making the nearest approach to this ideal, utility would enjoin, first, that laws and social arrangements should place the happiness, or (as speaking practically it may be called) the interest, of every individual, as nearly as possible in harmony with the interest of the whole; and secondly, that education and opinion, which have so vast a power over human character, should so use that power as to establish in the mind of every individual an indissoluble association between his own happiness and the good of the whole; especially between his own happiness and the practice of such modes of conduct, negative and positive, as regard for the universal happiness prescribes: so that not only he may be unable to conceive the possibility of happiness to himself, consistently with conduct opposed to the general good, but also that a direct impulse to promote the general good may be in every individual one of the habitual motives of action, and the sentiments connected therewith may fill a large and prominent place in every human being's sentient existence. If the impugners of the utilitarian morality represented it to their own minds in this its true character, I know not what recommendation possessed by any other morality they could possibly affirm to be wanting to it: what more beautiful or more exalted developments of human nature any other ethical system can be supposed to foster, or what springs of action, not accessible to the utilitarian, such systems rely on for giving effect to their mandates.
I must say again what critics of utilitarianism often fail to recognize: the happiness at the center of the utilitarian standard for what is right in behavior isn't just the happiness of the individual, but that of everyone involved. When it comes to their own happiness versus that of others, utilitarianism demands that individuals be as impartial as a neutral and caring observer. The essence of utilitarian ethics can be found in the golden rule of Jesus of Nazareth. To treat others as you would want to be treated and to love your neighbor as yourself represents the ideal perfection of utilitarian morality. To get as close as possible to this ideal, utility suggests that laws and social arrangements should align the happiness—or, in practical terms, the interests—of each individual with the interests of the whole. Additionally, education and public opinion, which have a huge influence on human behavior, should use that influence to create a strong connection in everyone's mind between their own happiness and the well-being of the whole; especially linking their happiness to behaviors—both negative and positive—that promote universal happiness: so that they not only can't imagine being happy while acting against the general good, but also feel a natural drive to support the common good as one of their fundamental motives for action, with feelings related to this drive taking a significant and noticeable place in everyone's emotional life. If opponents of utilitarian morality understood it in this true light, I don't know what advantages any other moral system could claim that utilitarianism lacks: what more beautiful or elevated aspects of human nature could any other ethical system possibly encourage, or what sources of motivation, not available to utilitarianism, could those systems rely on to enforce their principles.
The objectors to utilitarianism cannot always be charged with representing it in a discreditable light. On the contrary, those among them who entertain anything like a just idea of its disinterested character, sometimes find fault with its standard as being too high for humanity. They say it is exacting too much to require that people shall always act from the inducement of promoting the general interests of society. But this is to mistake the very meaning of a standard of morals, and to confound the rule of action with the motive of it. It is the business of ethics to tell us what are our duties, or by what test we may know them; but no system of ethics requires that the sole motive of all we do shall be a feeling of duty; on the contrary, ninety-nine hundredths of all our actions are done from other motives, and rightly so done, if the rule of duty does not condemn them. It is the more unjust to utilitarianism that this particular misapprehension should be made a ground of objection to it, inasmuch as utilitarian moralists have gone beyond almost all others in affirming that the motive has nothing to do with the morality of the action, though much with the worth of the agent. He who saves a fellow creature from drowning does what is morally right, whether his motive be duty, or the hope of being paid for his trouble: he who betrays the friend that trusts him, is guilty of a crime, even if his object be to serve another friend to whom he is under greater obligations.[B] But to speak only of actions done from the motive of duty, and in direct obedience to principle: it is a misapprehension of the utilitarian mode of thought, to conceive it as implying that people should fix their minds upon so wide a generality as the world, or society at large. The great majority of good actions are intended, not for the benefit of the world, but for that of individuals, of which the good of the world is made up; and the thoughts of the most virtuous man need not on these occasions travel beyond the particular persons concerned, except so far as is necessary to assure himself that in benefiting them he is not violating the rights—that is, the legitimate and authorized expectations—of any one else. The multiplication of happiness is, according to the utilitarian ethics, the object of virtue: the occasions on which any person (except one in a thousand) has it in his power to do this on an extended scale, in other words, to be a public benefactor, are but exceptional; and on these occasions alone is he called on to consider public utility; in every other case, private utility, the interest or happiness of some few persons, is all he has to attend to. Those alone the influence of whose actions extends to society in general, need concern themselves habitually about so large an object. In the case of abstinences indeed—of things which people forbear to do, from moral considerations, though the consequences in the particular case might be beneficial—it would be unworthy of an intelligent agent not to be consciously aware that the action is of a class which, if practised generally, would be generally injurious, and that this is the ground of the obligation to abstain from it. The amount of regard for the public interest implied in this recognition, is no greater than is demanded by every system of morals; for they all enjoin to abstain from whatever is manifestly pernicious to society.
Objectors to utilitarianism can't always be accused of portraying it unfairly. In fact, some of them who understand its selfless nature genuinely argue that its standards are too high for humanity. They claim it’s unrealistic to expect people to always act with the goal of promoting society's general interests. However, this misunderstands what a moral standard really is, mixing up the rules for action with the motivations behind them. Ethics is meant to guide us on what our duties are or how we can identify them, but no ethical system demands that the only reason for our actions must be a sense of duty. In reality, the vast majority of our actions stem from other motivations—and that’s perfectly fine as long as these actions aren't condemned by the duty rule. It's particularly unfair to utilitarianism to use this misunderstanding as a criticism, especially since utilitarian moralists emphasize that the motivation doesn't determine the morality of an action, although it does affect the character of the person acting. A person who saves another from drowning is doing the right thing morally, regardless of whether they are motivated by duty or the hope of payment. Conversely, someone betraying a friend is committing a crime, even if their goal is to help another friend to whom they owe more. But focusing only on actions driven by duty and strict adherence to principles misrepresents the utilitarian viewpoint; it doesn't suggest that individuals should think about such broad concepts as the world or society as a whole. Most good actions are aimed at benefiting individuals, who together make up the good of the world. In these cases, even the most virtuous person doesn’t need to consider anything beyond the specific individuals involved, except to ensure that in helping them, they're not violating anyone else's rights—that is, their rightful and legitimate expectations. According to utilitarian ethics, increasing overall happiness is the goal of virtue; however, the opportunities for any individual (excluding one in a thousand) to do this on a large scale, in other words, to be a public benefactor, are rare. Only in these instances are they required to think about public utility; in all other situations, their focus should be on private utility—the well-being or happiness of a select few individuals. Only those whose actions affect society as a whole need to regularly concern themselves with such a broad objective. In cases of abstaining from actions due to moral beliefs—even when abstaining may seem beneficial in a specific instance—it would be unreasonable for a thoughtful person not to recognize that the action belongs to a category that, if generally practiced, would be harmful overall, and that this is why there is a duty to refrain from it. The degree of consideration for the public interest contained in this acknowledgment is no greater than what’s required by every system of morals since they all insist on refraining from anything clearly damaging to society.
The same considerations dispose of another reproach against the doctrine of utility, founded on a still grosser misconception of the purpose of a standard of morality, and of the very meaning of the words right and wrong. It is often affirmed that utilitarianism renders men cold and unsympathizing; that it chills their moral feelings towards individuals; that it makes them regard only the dry and hard consideration of the consequences of actions, not taking into their moral estimate the qualities from which those actions emanate. If the assertion means that they do not allow their judgment respecting the rightness or wrongness of an action to be influenced by their opinion of the qualities of the person who does it, this is a complaint not against utilitarianism, but against having any standard of morality at all; for certainly no known ethical standard decides an action to be good or bad because it is done by a good or a bad man, still less because done by an amiable, a brave, or a benevolent man or the contrary. These considerations are relevant, not to the estimation of actions, but of persons; and there is nothing in the utilitarian theory inconsistent with the fact that there are other things which interest us in persons besides the rightness and wrongness of their actions. The Stoics, indeed, with the paradoxical misuse of language which was part of their system, and by which they strove to raise themselves above all concern about anything but virtue, were fond of saying that he who has that has everything; that he, and only he, is rich, is beautiful, is a king. But no claim of this description is made for the virtuous man by the utilitarian doctrine. Utilitarians are quite aware that there are other desirable possessions and qualities besides virtue, and are perfectly willing to allow to all of them their full worth. They are also aware that a right action does not necessarily indicate a virtuous character, and that actions which are blameable often proceed from qualities entitled to praise. When this is apparent in any particular case, it modifies their estimation, not certainly of the act, but of the agent. I grant that they are, notwithstanding, of opinion, that in the long run the best proof of a good character is good actions; and resolutely refuse to consider any mental disposition as good, of which the predominant tendency is to produce bad conduct. This makes them unpopular with many people; but it is an unpopularity which they must share with every one who regards the distinction between right and wrong in a serious light; and the reproach is not one which a conscientious utilitarian need be anxious to repel.
The same thoughts clear up another criticism of the utility principle, which is based on a misunderstanding of the purpose of a moral standard and what the terms right and wrong actually mean. People often claim that utilitarianism makes individuals cold and lacking empathy; that it dulls their moral sentiments toward others; that it leads them to focus solely on the bare facts and consequences of actions, ignoring the qualities from which those actions arise. If this argument suggests that they don't let their views about a person's character influence their judgment of whether an action is right or wrong, then that's a complaint against having any moral standard at all; because no recognized ethical guideline determines whether an action is good or bad simply based on whether it's performed by a good or bad person, let alone by someone amiable, brave, or kind, or the opposite. These considerations are relevant to evaluating people, not actions; and there’s nothing in utilitarian theory that contradicts the idea that there are other qualities in people that we care about beyond the rightness and wrongness of their actions. The Stoics, with their somewhat contradictory use of language as part of their philosophy, liked to say that whoever has virtue has everything; that only they are truly wealthy, beautiful, or a ruler. However, the utilitarian doctrine doesn’t make such claims for virtuous individuals. Utilitarians fully recognize that there are other valuable traits and attributes besides virtue, and they acknowledge each of them their rightful value. They also understand that a right action doesn’t always reflect a virtuous character, and that blameworthy actions can sometimes stem from admirable qualities. When this is evident in a specific situation, it affects how they view the agent, though not necessarily the action itself. I admit that they believe that, in the long run, the best evidence of a good character is good actions, and they firmly reject considering any mental disposition as good if its main tendency produces bad behavior. This viewpoint makes them unpopular with many, but this unpopularity is something they share with anyone who takes the distinction between right and wrong seriously; and it’s not a criticism that a principled utilitarian needs to feel compelled to counter.
If no more be meant by the objection than that many utilitarians look on the morality of actions, as measured by the utilitarian standard, with too exclusive a regard, and do not lay sufficient stress upon the other beauties of character which go towards making a human being loveable or admirable, this may be admitted. Utilitarians who have cultivated their moral feelings, but not their sympathies nor their artistic perceptions, do fall into this mistake; and so do all other moralists under the same conditions. What can be said in excuse for other moralists is equally available for them, namely, that if there is to be any error, it is better that it should be on that side. As a matter of fact, we may affirm that among utilitarians as among adherents of other systems, there is every imaginable degree of rigidity and of laxity in the application of their standard: some are even puritanically rigorous, while others are as indulgent as can possibly be desired by sinner or by sentimentalist. But on the whole, a doctrine which brings prominently forward the interest that mankind have in the repression and prevention of conduct which violates the moral law, is likely to be inferior to no other in turning the sanctions of opinion against such violations. It is true, the question, What does violate the moral law? is one on which those who recognise different standards of morality are likely now and then to differ. But difference of opinion on moral questions was not first introduced into the world by utilitarianism, while that doctrine does supply, if not always an easy, at all events a tangible and intelligible mode of deciding such differences.
If the objection is just that many utilitarians focus too much on the morality of actions according to the utilitarian standard and don’t pay enough attention to the other qualities that make someone lovable or admirable, then this can be accepted. Utilitarians who have developed their moral feelings but not their empathy or artistic sensibilities do make this mistake, and so do all other moralists in the same situation. The justification for other moralists applies to them too; if there has to be a mistake, it’s better to err in that direction. In reality, we can say that among utilitarians, as well as supporters of other systems, there is a wide range of strictness and leniency in how they apply their standard: some are very strict, while others are as forgiving as anyone could want. Overall, a doctrine that emphasizes the importance of preventing and punishing conduct that violates moral law is likely as effective as any other in rallying public opinion against such violations. It’s true that the question, “What violates moral law?” is one where those who recognize different moral standards might disagree from time to time. But moral disagreements didn’t start with utilitarianism; that doctrine does offer a way, even if not always simple, to understand and address such differences.
It may not be superfluous to notice a few more of the common misapprehensions of utilitarian ethics, even those which are so obvious and gross that it might appear impossible for any person of candour and intelligence to fall into them: since persons, even of considerable mental endowments, often give themselves so little trouble to understand the bearings of any opinion against which they entertain a prejudice, and men are in general so little conscious of this voluntary ignorance as a defect, that the vulgarest misunderstandings of ethical doctrines are continually met with in the deliberate writings of persons of the greatest pretensions both to high principle and to philosophy. We not uncommonly hear the doctrine of utility inveighed against as a godless doctrine. If it be necessary to say anything at all against so mere an assumption, we may say that the question depends upon what idea we have formed of the moral character of the Deity. If it be a true belief that God desires, above all things, the happiness of his creatures, and that this was his purpose in their creation, utility is not only not a godless doctrine, but more profoundly religious than any other. If it be meant that utilitarianism does not recognise the revealed will of God as the supreme law of morals, I answer, that an utilitarian who believes in the perfect goodness and wisdom of God, necessarily believes that whatever God has thought fit to reveal on the subject of morals, must fulfil the requirements of utility in a supreme degree. But others besides utilitarians have been of opinion that the Christian revelation was intended, and is fitted, to inform the hearts and minds of mankind with a spirit which should enable them to find for themselves what is right, and incline them to do it when found, rather than to tell them, except in a very general way, what it is: and that we need a doctrine of ethics, carefully followed out, to interpret to us the will of God. Whether this opinion is correct or not, it is superfluous here to discuss; since whatever aid religion, either natural or revealed, can afford to ethical investigation, is as open to the utilitarian moralist as to any other. He can use it as the testimony of God to the usefulness or hurtfulness of any given course of action, by as good a right as others can use it for the indication of a transcendental law, having no connexion with usefulness or with happiness.
It might be helpful to point out a few more of the common misunderstandings of utilitarian ethics, even those that are so clear and obvious that it seems impossible for any reasonable and intelligent person to believe them. People, even those with considerable intelligence, often put in so little effort to understand the nuances of any opinion they’re biased against, and most people are so unaware of this deliberate ignorance as a flaw that the most basic misunderstandings of ethical principles frequently appear in the writings of those who claim to have high morals and a grasp of philosophy. We often hear the doctrine of utility criticized as a godless doctrine. If we need to respond to such a simplistic claim, we can argue that it depends on our understanding of the moral character of God. If we truly believe that God desires, above all else, the happiness of His creations and that this was His purpose for creating them, then utilitarianism is not only not a godless doctrine but is also more deeply religious than any other. If it's suggested that utilitarianism doesn’t acknowledge the revealed will of God as the highest moral law, I would point out that a utilitarian who believes in the complete goodness and wisdom of God must also believe that whatever God has chosen to reveal about morality must meet the standards of utility to the highest degree. However, others besides utilitarians believe that the Christian revelation was meant to inspire people to discover for themselves what is right and encourage them to act accordingly, rather than simply stating, except in a very general sense, what that right action is. They argue that we need a well-developed ethical doctrine to interpret for us the will of God. Whether this viewpoint is valid or not is not necessary to discuss here; whatever guidance religion, whether natural or revealed, can provide for ethical inquiry is just as accessible to the utilitarian moralist as it is to anyone else. He can use it as evidence from God regarding the usefulness or harmfulness of any given action, just as well as others can use it to point to a transcendent law that has no connection to usefulness or happiness.
Again, Utility is often summarily stigmatized as an immoral doctrine by giving it the name of Expediency, and taking advantage of the popular use of that term to contrast it with Principle. But the Expedient, in the sense in which it is opposed to the Right, generally means that which is expedient for the particular interest of the agent himself: as when a minister sacrifices the interest of his country to keep himself in place. When it means anything better than this, it means that which is expedient for some immediate object, some temporary purpose, but which violates a rule whose observance is expedient in a much higher degree. The Expedient, in this sense, instead of being the same thing with the useful, is a branch of the hurtful. Thus, it would often be expedient, for the purpose of getting over some momentary embarrassment, or attaining some object immediately useful to ourselves or others, to tell a lie. But inasmuch as the cultivation in ourselves of a sensitive feeling on the subject of veracity, is one of the most useful, and the enfeeblement of that feeling one of the most hurtful, things to which our conduct can be instrumental; and inasmuch as any, even unintentional, deviation from truth, does that much towards weakening the trustworthiness of human assertion, which is not only the principal support of all present social well-being, but the insufficiency of which does more than any one thing that can be named to keep back civilisation, virtue, everything on which human happiness on the largest scale depends; we feel that the violation, for a present advantage, of a rule of such transcendent expediency, is not expedient, and that he who, for the sake of a convenience to himself or to some other individual, does what depends on him to deprive mankind of the good, and inflict upon them the evil, involved in the greater or less reliance which they can place in each other's word, acts the part of one of their worst enemies. Yet that even this rule, sacred as it is, admits of possible exceptions, is acknowledged by all moralists; the chief of which is when the withholding of some fact (as of information from a male-factor, or of bad news from a person dangerously ill) would preserve some one (especially a person other than oneself) from great and unmerited evil, and when the withholding can only be effected by denial. But in order that the exception may not extend itself beyond the need, and may have the least possible effect in weakening reliance on veracity, it ought to be recognized, and, if possible, its limits defined; and if the principle of utility is good for anything, it must be good for weighing these conflicting utilities against one another, and marking out the region within which one or the other preponderates.
Again, Utility is often unfairly labeled as an immoral belief by calling it Expediency, using the common understanding of that term to set it against Principle. However, Expedient, in the sense that it is contrasted with the Right, usually refers to actions that benefit the agent's personal interests—like when a politician puts their own job security above the needs of their country. When it’s seen as something better, it refers to what is useful for a specific short-term goal but goes against a rule that is significantly more beneficial to uphold. In this light, the Expedient isn't the same as the useful; it’s actually a form of harmful behavior. For instance, it might seem convenient to lie to get through a tough situation or achieve a goal that benefits us or others in the short run. However, nurturing a strong sense of honesty is one of the most valuable traits, while weakening that sense is one of the most damaging actions we can take. Any deviation from the truth, even if unintentional, chips away at people’s trust in one another, which is crucial for our social well-being. A lack of trust hinders civilization, virtue, and everything that contributes to widespread human happiness. Therefore, violating a crucial rule for immediate gain is not truly expedient. Those who prioritize their own convenience by harming the trust we place in each other’s words become some of humanity's worst enemies. Yet even this vital principle, as sacred as it is, can have exceptions acknowledged by all moral philosophers. The main exception is when withholding certain information (like not informing a criminal or shielding someone seriously ill from bad news) can save someone—particularly someone other than ourselves—from significant and undeserved harm, and this can only be done through denial. To ensure that these exceptions don’t expand beyond what’s necessary and have minimal impact on our trust in honesty, they should be recognized and, if possible, their boundaries defined. If the principle of utility has any merit, it must be valuable for balancing these competing utilities against each other and identifying where one outweighs the other.
Again, defenders of utility often find themselves called upon to reply to such objections as this—that there is not time, previous to action, for calculating and weighing the effects of any line of conduct on the general happiness. This is exactly as if any one were to say that it is impossible to guide our conduct by Christianity, because there is not time, on every occasion on which anything has to be done, to read through the Old and New Testaments. The answer to the objection is, that there has been ample time, namely, the whole past duration of the human species. During all that time mankind have been learning by experience the tendencies of actions; on which experience all the prudence, as well as all the morality of life, is dependent. People talk as if the commencement of this course of experience had hitherto been put off, and as if, at the moment when some man feels tempted to meddle with the property or life of another, he had to begin considering for the first time whether murder and theft are injurious to human happiness. Even then I do not think that he would find the question very puzzling; but, at all events, the matter is now done to his hand. It is truly a whimsical supposition, that if mankind were agreed in considering utility to be the test of morality, they would remain without any agreement as to what is useful, and would take no measures for having their notions on the subject taught to the young, and enforced by law and opinion. There is no difficulty in proving any ethical standard whatever to work ill, if we suppose universal idiocy to be conjoined with it, but on any hypothesis short of that, mankind must by this time have acquired positive beliefs as to the effects of some actions on their happiness; and the beliefs which have thus come down are the rules of morality for the multitude, and for the philosopher until he has succeeded in finding better. That philosophers might easily do this, even now, on many subjects; that the received code of ethics is by no means of divine right; and that mankind have still much to learn as to the effects of actions on the general happiness, I admit, or rather, earnestly maintain. The corollaries from the principle of utility, like the precepts of every practical art, admit of indefinite improvement, and, in a progressive state of the human mind, their improvement is perpetually going on. But to consider the rules of morality as improvable, is one thing; to pass over the intermediate generalizations entirely, and endeavour to test each individual action directly by the first principle, is another. It is a strange notion that the acknowledgment of a first principle is inconsistent with the admission of secondary ones. To inform a traveller respecting the place of his ultimate destination, is not to forbid the use of landmarks and direction-posts on the way. The proposition that happiness is the end and aim of morality, does not mean that no road ought to be laid down to that goal, or that persons going thither should not be advised to take one direction rather than another. Men really ought to leave off talking a kind of nonsense on this subject, which they would neither talk nor listen to on other matters of practical concernment. Nobody argues that the art of navigation is not founded on astronomy, because sailors cannot wait to calculate the Nautical Almanack. Being rational creatures, they go to sea with it ready calculated; and all rational creatures go out upon the sea of life with their minds made up on the common questions of right and wrong, as well as on many of the far more difficult questions of wise and foolish. And this, as long as foresight is a human quality, it is to be presumed they will continue to do. Whatever we adopt as the fundamental principle of morality, we require subordinate principles to apply it by: the impossibility of doing without them, being common to all systems, can afford no argument against any one in particular: but gravely to argue as if no such secondary principles could be had, and as if mankind had remained till now, and always must remain, without drawing any general conclusions from the experience of human life, is as high a pitch, I think, as absurdity has ever reached in philosophical controversy.
Once again, supporters of utility often have to respond to objections like this: that there isn't enough time before taking action to figure out and weigh the effects of any course of action on overall happiness. This is just as if someone were to argue that it's impossible to guide our actions by Christianity because there's no time to read through the Old and New Testaments every time something needs to be done. The answer to this objection is that there has been plenty of time—namely, the entire history of humankind. Throughout that time, people have learned through experience the consequences of their actions, and this experience is what morality and prudence in life depend on. It’s as if people believe that the beginning of this learning process has been postponed, and that whenever someone is tempted to harm another's property or life, they have to start considering for the first time whether murder and theft are bad for human happiness. Even then, I don't think they'd find that question particularly confusing; however, the knowledge is already at their fingertips. It's quite a strange idea to think that if humanity agreed on using utility as the moral standard, they’d still disagree on what is considered useful and would take no steps to teach their ideas on the topic to the young or enforce them through laws and societal norms. It’s not hard to show that any ethical system could fail if we assume universal stupidity accompanies it, but aside from that, humanity must have by now developed clear beliefs about the effects of certain actions on their happiness; and these beliefs have shaped the moral rules for most people, and for philosophers until they find something better. I acknowledge, or rather passionately assert, that philosophers could easily find better moral guidelines on many topics even now, that the accepted moral code isn’t some divine decree, and that humanity still has a lot to learn about how actions impact general happiness. The principles derived from utility, like the guidelines of any practical discipline, can always be improved, and in a progressive society, this improvement is ongoing. However, treating the rules of morality as flexible is one thing; ignoring the broader generalizations altogether and trying to evaluate every single action based on a fundamental principle is another. It's a peculiar notion that recognizing a foundational principle is incompatible with accepting secondary ones. Telling a traveler where their ultimate destination is doesn't mean they shouldn't use landmarks and signs along the way. The idea that happiness is the goal of morality doesn’t imply that no paths should be laid out to reach that goal, or that individuals heading there shouldn't be guided to take certain directions. People really need to stop spouting nonsense on this issue, which they wouldn’t dare discuss about other important matters. Nobody argues that navigation isn’t based on astronomy just because sailors can't pause to calculate the Nautical Almanack. As rational beings, they head out to sea with calculations already made; and all rational beings step into the sea of life with established views on right and wrong, as well as on many of the more complex questions of wisdom. As long as foresight remains a human trait, we can assume this will continue. Whatever we choose as the fundamental principle of morality, we need subordinate principles to apply it: the fact that we can’t do without them is true for all systems and doesn’t discredit any one principle in particular. But to seriously argue that secondary principles are unattainable, as if humanity has remained and will always remain without drawing broad conclusions from life's experiences, is, I believe, the highest level of absurdity ever reached in philosophical debate.
The remainder of the stock arguments against utilitarianism mostly consist in laying to its charge the common infirmities of human nature, and the general difficulties which embarrass conscientious persons in shaping their course through life. We are told that an utilitarian will be apt to make his own particular case an exception to moral rules, and, when under temptation, will see an utility in the breach of a rule, greater than he will see in its observance. But is utility the only creed which is able to furnish us with excuses for evil doing, and means of cheating our own conscience? They are afforded in abundance by all doctrines which recognise as a fact in morals the existence of conflicting considerations; which all doctrines do, that have been believed by sane persons. It is not the fault of any creed, but of the complicated nature of human affairs, that rules of conduct cannot be so framed as to require no exceptions, and that hardly any kind of action can safely be laid down as either always obligatory or always condemnable. There is no ethical creed which does not temper the rigidity of its laws, by giving a certain latitude, under the moral responsibility of the agent, for accommodation to peculiarities of circumstances; and under every creed, at the opening thus made, self-deception and dishonest casuistry get in. There exists no moral system under which there do not arise unequivocal cases of conflicting obligation. These are the real difficulties, the knotty points both in the theory of ethics, and in the conscientious guidance of personal conduct. They are overcome practically with greater or with less success according to the intellect and virtue of the individual; but it can hardly be pretended that any one will be the less qualified for dealing with them, from possessing an ultimate standard to which conflicting rights and duties can be referred. If utility is the ultimate source of moral obligations, utility may be invoked to decide between them when their demands are incompatible. Though the application of the standard may be difficult, it is better than none at all: while in other systems, the moral laws all claiming independent authority, there is no common umpire entitled to interfere between them; their claims to precedence one over another rest on little better than sophistry, and unless determined, as they generally are, by the unacknowledged influence of considerations of utility, afford a free scope for the action of personal desires and partialities. We must remember that only in these cases of conflict between secondary principles is it requisite that first principles should be appealed to. There is no case of moral obligation in which some secondary principle is not involved; and if only one, there can seldom be any real doubt which one it is, in the mind of any person by whom the principle itself is recognized.
The remaining arguments against utilitarianism mainly focus on the flaws of human nature and the general challenges that conscientious people face when trying to navigate their lives. People argue that a utilitarian is likely to view their own specific situation as an exception to moral rules and, when tempted, will find a greater utility in breaking a rule than in following it. But is utility the only philosophy that offers excuses for wrongdoing and ways to deceive our own conscience? All doctrines acknowledging the reality of conflicting moral considerations provide plenty of excuses, and this applies to all beliefs held by rational people. It’s not the belief system's fault, but rather the complex nature of human affairs, that conduct rules cannot be made without exceptions and that almost no action can be deemed always mandatory or always wrong. There's no ethical belief that doesn't soften the strictness of its laws by allowing some flexibility, under the moral responsibility of the individual, to adapt to specific circumstances; and in this flexibility, self-deception and dishonest reasoning often slip in. Every moral system encounters clear cases of conflicting obligations. These are the real challenges, the tricky issues both in ethics theory and in guiding personal behavior. They can be addressed practically with varying degrees of success, depending on the individual's intellect and character; however, it's hard to argue that having a final standard to refer conflicting rights and duties to doesn't help someone manage these issues. If utility is the ultimate basis for moral obligations, it can be called upon to resolve conflicts when their demands clash. While applying this standard may be challenging, it’s better than having no standard at all. In other systems, where moral laws claim independent authority, there’s no common referee to resolve disputes; their competing claims often rely on little more than clever reasoning, and unless resolved—typically through unacknowledged utility considerations—they allow personal desires and biases to dictate actions. We must keep in mind that it’s only in cases of conflict between secondary principles that we need to appeal to first principles. There is no moral obligation case that doesn’t involve some secondary principle; and if there's only one, there’s usually little doubt about which one it is for anyone who recognizes that principle.
FOOTNOTES:
FOOTNOTES:
The author of this essay has reason for believing himself to be the first person who brought the word utilitarian into use. He did not invent it, but adopted it from a passing expression in Mr. Galt's Annals of the Parish. After using it as a designation for several years, he and others abandoned it from a growing dislike to anything resembling a badge or watchword of sectarian distinction. But as a name for one single opinion, not a set of opinions—to denote the recognition of utility as a standard, not any particular way of applying it—the term supplies a want in the language, and offers, in many cases, a convenient mode of avoiding tiresome circumlocution.
The author of this essay believes he was the first to use the term "utilitarian." He didn’t create the word but took it from a fleeting mention in Mr. Galt's Annals of the Parish. After a few years of using it to describe a specific idea, he and others stopped using it because they grew to dislike anything that felt like a label or slogan for a particular group. However, as a term for a single idea—not a whole set of beliefs—it's useful for acknowledging utility as a standard without being tied to a specific application. The term fills a gap in the language and often provides an easier way to avoid lengthy explanations.
An opponent, whose intellectual and moral fairness it is a pleasure to acknowledge (the Rev. J. Llewellyn Davis), has objected to this passage, saying, "Surely the rightness or wrongness of saving a man from drowning does depend very much upon the motive with which it is done. Suppose that a tyrant, when his enemy jumped into the sea to escape from him, saved him from drowning simply in order that he might inflict upon him more exquisite tortures, would it tend to clearness to speak of that rescue as 'a morally right action?' Or suppose again, according to one of the stock illustrations of ethical inquiries, that a man betrayed a trust received from a friend, because the discharge of it would fatally injure that friend himself or some one belonging to him, would utilitarianism compel one to call the betrayal 'a crime' as much as if it had been done from the meanest motive?"
An opponent, whose intellectual and moral fairness it's a pleasure to acknowledge (the Rev. J. Llewellyn Davis), has raised an objection to this passage, saying, "Surely, whether saving someone from drowning is right or wrong depends a lot on the motive behind it. Imagine a tyrant who saves his enemy from drowning simply to inflict even more terrible tortures later—would it be clear to call that rescue 'a morally right action?' Or let's consider another common ethical scenario: if a person betrays a trust given by a friend because fulfilling that trust would seriously harm the friend or someone they care about, would utilitarianism really force us to label that betrayal 'a crime' just as much as if it had been done from the worst possible motives?"
I submit, that he who saves another from drowning in order to kill him by torture afterwards, does not differ only in motive from him who does the same thing from duty or benevolence; the act itself is different. The rescue of the man is, in the case supposed, only the necessary first step of an act far more atrocious than leaving him to drown would have been. Had Mr. Davis said, "The rightness or wrongness of saving a man from drowning does depend very much"—not upon the motive, but—"upon the intention" no utilitarian would have differed from him. Mr. Davis, by an oversight too common not to be quite venial, has in this case confounded the very different ideas of Motive and Intention. There is no point which utilitarian thinkers (and Bentham pre-eminently) have taken more pains to illustrate than this. The morality of the action depends entirely upon the intention—that is, upon what the agent wills to do. But the motive, that is, the feeling which makes him will so to do, when it makes no difference in the act, makes none in the morality: though it makes a great difference in our moral estimation of the agent, especially if it indicates a good or a bad habitual disposition—a bent of character from which useful, or from which hurtful actions are likely to arise.
I argue that someone who saves another from drowning just to torture him later doesn't differ only in motive from someone who saves him out of duty or kindness; the action itself is different. In the scenario mentioned, rescuing the person is only the necessary first step toward an act far more horrific than just letting him drown. If Mr. Davis had said, "The rightness or wrongness of saving a man from drowning depends greatly"—not on the motive, but—"on the intention," no utilitarian would have disagreed with him. Mr. Davis, through a common oversight that isn't too serious, has confused the very different concepts of Motive and Intention. There is no issue that utilitarian thinkers (and Bentham above all) have worked harder to clarify than this. The morality of the action relies entirely on the intention—that is, on what the agent wants to do. But the motive, which is the feeling that drives him to act, doesn't change the morality of the action when it doesn't alter the act itself; however, it does greatly influence how we morally evaluate the agent, especially if it reflects a good or bad habitual disposition—a character trait that is likely to lead to useful or harmful actions.
CHAPTER III.
The question is often asked, and properly so, in regard to any supposed moral standard—What is its sanction? what are the motives to obey it? or more specifically, what is the source of its obligation? whence does it derive its binding force? It is a necessary part of moral philosophy to provide the answer to this question; which, though frequently assuming the shape of an objection to the utilitarian morality, as if it had some special applicability to that above others, really arises in regard to all standards. It arises, in fact, whenever a person is called on to adopt a standard or refer morality to any basis on which he has not been accustomed to rest it. For the customary morality, that which education and opinion have consecrated, is the only one which presents itself to the mind with the feeling of being in itself obligatory; and when a person is asked to believe that this morality derives its obligation from some general principle round which custom has not thrown the same halo, the assertion is to him a paradox; the supposed corollaries seem to have a more binding force than the original theorem; the superstructure seems to stand better without, than with, what is represented as its foundation. He says to himself, I feel that I am bound not to rob or murder, betray or deceive; but why am I bound to promote the general happiness? If my own happiness lies in something else, why may I not give that the preference?
The question is often asked, and rightly so, about any supposed moral standard—What supports it? What motivates us to follow it? Or more specifically, what is the source of its obligation? Where does its authority come from? It's essential for moral philosophy to answer this question, which often takes the form of a challenge to utilitarian ethics, as if it applies more to that than to others. In reality, it pertains to all moral standards. It comes up whenever someone is asked to accept a standard or base morality on something they haven't used before. The moral standards we’re used to, those shaped by education and societal beliefs, are the only ones that seem inherently obligatory. When someone is asked to believe that this morality derives its obligation from some broader principle not surrounded by the same respect, it appears paradoxical to them; the supposed conclusions seem stronger than the original idea. The whole structure seems to stand better without the foundation that's supposed to support it. They think to themselves, I feel that I must not steal or kill, betray or deceive; but why must I work towards the overall happiness? If my own happiness lies elsewhere, why shouldn’t I prioritize that?
If the view adopted by the utilitarian philosophy of the nature of the moral sense be correct, this difficulty will always present itself, until the influences which form moral character have taken the same hold of the principle which they have taken of some of the consequences—until, by the improvement of education, the feeling of unity with our fellow creatures shall be (what it cannot be doubted that Christ intended it to be) as deeply rooted in our character, and to our own consciousness as completely a part of our nature, as the horror of crime is in an ordinarily well-brought-up young person. In the mean time, however, the difficulty has no peculiar application to the doctrine of utility, but is inherent in every attempt to analyse morality and reduce it to principles; which, unless the principle is already in men's minds invested with as much sacredness as any of its applications, always seems to divest them of a part of their sanctity.
If the view taken by utilitarian philosophy regarding the moral sense is correct, this problem will always exist until the influences that shape moral character have the same impact on the principle as they do on some of the consequences—until, through improved education, the feeling of connection with our fellow humans becomes as deeply ingrained in our character and consciousness, as much a part of our nature, as the aversion to crime is in a normally well-raised young person. In the meantime, though, this challenge isn't unique to the doctrine of utility; it's a fundamental issue in every attempt to analyze morality and break it down into principles. Unless the principle is already held in people's minds with as much reverence as any of its applications, it tends to strip away some of their sacredness.
The principle of utility either has, or there is no reason why it might not have, all the sanctions which belong to any other system of morals. Those sanctions are either external or internal. Of the external sanctions it is not necessary to speak at any length. They are, the hope of favour and the fear of displeasure from our fellow creatures or from the Ruler of the Universe, along with whatever we may have of sympathy or affection for them or of love and awe of Him, inclining us to do His will independently of selfish consequences. There is evidently no reason why all these motives for observance should not attach themselves to the utilitarian morality, as completely and as powerfully as to any other. Indeed, those of them which refer to our fellow creatures are sure to do so, in proportion to the amount of general intelligence; for whether there be any other ground of moral obligation than the general happiness or not, men do desire happiness; and however imperfect may be their own practice, they desire and commend all conduct in others towards themselves, by which they think their happiness is promoted. With regard to the religious motive, if men believe, as most profess to do, in the goodness of God, those who think that conduciveness to the general happiness is the essence, or even only the criterion, of good, must necessarily believe that it is also that which God approves. The whole force therefore of external reward and punishment, whether physical or moral, and whether proceeding from God or from our fellow men, together with all that the capacities of human nature admit, of disinterested devotion to either, become available to enforce the utilitarian morality, in proportion as that morality is recognized; and the more powerfully, the more the appliances of education and general cultivation are bent to the purpose.
The principle of utility has, or could have, all the same reasons for compliance as any other moral system. These reasons can be external or internal. We don't need to go into detail about external reasons. They include the hope for approval and the fear of disapproval from others or from a higher power, along with any feelings of empathy, affection, or love and respect we have for them or for God, which motivate us to follow His will regardless of selfish outcomes. There's clearly no reason why these motivations shouldn't be associated with utilitarian morality as effectively and strongly as with any other system. In fact, those motivations relating to our fellow humans are likely to do so in line with the level of overall understanding; because whether or not there is any other basis for moral obligation apart from general happiness, people do want happiness. Despite their own imperfect actions, they want and support behavior in others that they believe will enhance their own happiness. Regarding religious motivation, if people believe, as most claim to, in the goodness of God, those who think that promoting general happiness is the core or even just the standard of what is good must also believe that this is what God approves of. Therefore, the whole weight of external rewards and punishments—whether physical or moral, from God or from other people—along with all that human nature allows in terms of selfless devotion, can be used to support utilitarian morality as that morality gains recognition; and the stronger the influence, the more education and personal development are focused on this goal.
So far as to external sanctions. The internal sanction of duty, whatever our standard of duty may be, is one and the same—a feeling in our own mind; a pain, more or less intense, attendant on violation of duty, which in properly cultivated moral natures rises, in the more serious cases, into shrinking from it as an impossibility. This feeling, when disinterested, and connecting itself with the pure idea of duty, and not with some particular form of it, or with any of the merely accessory circumstances, is the essence of Conscience; though in that complex phenomenon as it actually exists, the simple fact is in general all encrusted over with collateral associations, derived from sympathy, from love, and still more from fear; from all the forms of religious feeling; from the recollections of childhood and of all our past life; from self-esteem, desire of the esteem of others, and occasionally even self-abasement. This extreme complication is, I apprehend, the origin of the sort of mystical character which, by a tendency of the human mind of which there are many other examples, is apt to be attributed to the idea of moral obligation, and which leads people to believe that the idea cannot possibly attach itself to any other objects than those which, by a supposed mysterious law, are found in our present experience to excite it. Its binding force, however, consists in the existence of a mass of feeling which must be broken through in order to do what violates our standard of right, and which, if we do nevertheless violate that standard, will probably have to be encountered afterwards in the form of remorse. Whatever theory we have of the nature or origin of conscience, this is what essentially constitutes it.
As for external pressures, the internal sense of duty, regardless of what our standard of duty is, is a consistent feeling in our minds; it's a discomfort, varying in intensity, that accompanies the breach of duty. In well-developed moral individuals, this discomfort can escalate to a point where it feels impossible to act against it. When this feeling is altruistic and tied to the pure concept of duty, rather than to a specific instance or any peripheral circumstances, it embodies Conscience. However, in reality, this straightforward fact is usually covered with various external associations from empathy, love, and especially fear; from different expressions of religious sentiment; from childhood memories and our entire past; from self-worth, the desire for others' approval, and sometimes even from feelings of humility. This complex mixture is, I believe, the source of the somewhat mystical quality that people tend to attribute to the idea of moral obligation. It creates the notion that this idea can only relate to certain objects that, by some mysterious law, trigger it in our current experiences. Nevertheless, its compelling nature comes from a deep emotional weight that we must confront when violating our sense of right, and if we choose to disregard it, we will likely face remorse later on. Whatever our beliefs about the nature or origin of conscience may be, this is its core essence.
The ultimate sanction, therefore, of all morality (external motives apart) being a subjective feeling in our own minds, I see nothing embarrassing to those whose standard is utility, in the question, what is the sanction of that particular standard? We may answer, the same as of all other moral standards—the conscientious feelings of mankind. Undoubtedly this sanction has no binding efficacy on those who do not possess the feelings it appeals to; but neither will these persons be more obedient to any other moral principle than to the utilitarian one. On them morality of any kind has no hold but through the external sanctions. Meanwhile the feelings exist, a feet in human nature, the reality of which, and the great power with which they are capable of acting on those in whom they have been duly cultivated, are proved by experience. No reason has ever been shown why they may not be cultivated to as great intensity in connection with the utilitarian, as with any other rule of morals.
The ultimate basis of all morality (aside from external influences) being a subjective feeling in our minds, I see nothing awkward for those whose standard is utility in the question of what supports that specific standard. We can reply that it’s the same as for all other moral standards—the conscientious feelings of humanity. This foundation clearly doesn’t have any compelling effect on those who don’t share the feelings it addresses; however, these individuals won’t be any more compliant with any other moral principle than with the utilitarian one. For them, morality of any kind only influences them through external pressures. Meanwhile, those feelings exist as a fact of human nature, the reality of which, and the significant impact they can have on people who have properly developed them, is proven by experience. No evidence has ever been provided to suggest that they can’t be cultivated to the same intensity in relation to utilitarianism as with any other moral guideline.
There is, I am aware, a disposition to believe that a person who sees in moral obligation a transcendental fact, an objective reality belonging to the province of "Things in themselves," is likely to be more obedient to it than one who believes it to be entirely subjective, having its seat in human consciousness only. But whatever a person's opinion may be on this point of Ontology, the force he is really urged by is his own subjective feeling, and is exactly measured by its strength. No one's belief that Duty is an objective reality is stronger than the belief that God is so; yet the belief in God, apart from the expectation of actual reward and punishment, only operates on conduct through, and in proportion to, the subjective religious feeling. The sanction, so far as it is disinterested, is always in the mind itself; and the notion, therefore, of the transcendental moralists must be, that this sanction will not exist in the mind unless it is believed to have its root out of the mind; and that if a person is able to say to himself, That which is restraining me, and which is called my conscience, is only a feeling in my own mind, he may possibly draw the conclusion that when the feeling ceases the obligation ceases, and that if he find the feeling inconvenient, he may disregard it, and endeavour to get rid of it. But is this danger confined to the utilitarian morality? Does the belief that moral obligation has its seat outside the mind make the feeling of it too strong to be got rid of? The fact is so far otherwise, that all moralists admit and lament the ease with which, in the generality of minds, conscience can be silenced or stifled. The question, Need I obey my conscience? is quite as often put to themselves by persons who never heard of the principle of utility, as by its adherents. Those whose conscientious feelings are so weak as to allow of their asking this question, if they answer it affirmatively, will not do so because they believe in the transcendental theory, but because of the external sanctions.
I know there's a tendency to think that someone who views moral obligation as a universal truth, an objective reality that exists outside of our perception, is more likely to follow it than someone who sees it as purely subjective and rooted only in human consciousness. However, regardless of what someone believes about this philosophical point, the force that truly drives them is their own personal feelings, which are measured by how strong those feelings are. No one’s belief that Duty is an objective reality is stronger than the belief that God is; yet the belief in God, aside from the expectation of actual rewards or punishments, only influences behavior to the extent that it is tied to individual religious feelings. The motivation, as long as it is selfless, is always rooted in the mind itself, so transcendental moralists must think that this motivation won’t exist in the mind unless it is believed to have a source outside of it. If someone tells themselves that what holds them back, known as their conscience, is just a feeling in their own mind, they might conclude that when that feeling goes away, so does the obligation, and if they find that feeling bothersome, they might try to ignore it and rid themselves of it. But is this risk limited to utilitarian morality? Does believing that moral obligation exists outside of our minds make the feeling of it too strong to discard? In reality, it’s quite the opposite; all moralists recognize and regret how easily, in most people, conscience can be silenced or suppressed. The question, "Do I need to obey my conscience?" is frequently asked by individuals who have never heard of utilitarian principles, just as much as by those who support them. Those whose sense of conscience is weak enough to allow them to ask this question will affirmatively answer not because they believe in transcendental theories, but rather because of external incentives.
It is not necessary, for the present purpose, to decide whether the feeling of duty is innate or implanted. Assuming it to be innate, it is an open question to what objects it naturally attaches itself; for the philosophic supporters of that theory are now agreed that the intuitive perception is of principles of morality, and not of the details. If there be anything innate in the matter, I see no reason why the feeling which is innate should not be that of regard to the pleasures and pains of others. If there is any principle of morals which is intuitively obligatory, I should say it must be that. If so, the intuitive ethics would coincide with the utilitarian, and there would be no further quarrel between them. Even as it is, the intuitive moralists, though they believe that there are other intuitive moral obligations, do already believe this to be one; for they unanimously hold that a large portion of morality turns upon the consideration due to the interests of our fellow creatures. Therefore, if the belief in the transcendental origin of moral obligation gives any additional efficacy to the internal sanction, it appears to me that the utilitarian principle has already the benefit of it.
It's not necessary, for our current purpose, to determine whether the sense of duty is something we’re born with or something we learn. Assuming it’s something we’re born with, it’s unclear what it naturally connects to; philosophically, supporters of that idea agree that this intuitive understanding involves principles of morality rather than specifics. If there is anything innate in this regard, I don’t see why the innate feeling shouldn’t be related to the pleasures and pains of others. If there’s any moral principle that’s intuitively binding, I would say it has to be that. If that’s the case, intuitive ethics would overlap with utilitarianism, and there wouldn’t be any more conflict between them. Even now, intuitive moralists, while believing in other intuitive moral obligations, agree that this is one of them; they all believe that a significant part of morality hinges on considering the interests of our fellow beings. So, if the belief in the higher origin of moral obligation adds any extra force to the internal sense of duty, it seems that the utilitarian principle already benefits from it.
On the other hand, if, as is my own belief, the moral feelings are not innate, but acquired, they are not for that reason the less natural. It is natural to man to speak, to reason, to build cities, to cultivate the ground, though these are acquired faculties. The moral feelings are not indeed a part of our nature, in the sense of being in any perceptible degree present in all of us; but this, unhappily, is a fact admitted by those who believe the most strenuously in their transcendental origin. Like the other acquired capacities above referred to, the moral faculty, if not a part of our nature, is a natural outgrowth from it; capable, like them, in a certain small degree, of springing up spontaneously; and susceptible of being brought by cultivation to a high degree of development. Unhappily it is also susceptible, by a sufficient use of the external sanctions and of the force of early impressions, of being cultivated in almost any direction: so that there is hardly anything so absurd or so mischievous that it may not, by means of these influences, be made to act on the human mind with all the authority of conscience. To doubt that the same potency might be given by the same means to the principle of utility, even if it had no foundation in human nature, would be flying in the face of all experience.
On the other hand, if, as I believe, moral feelings are not innate but learned, it doesn't mean they're any less natural. It's natural for people to speak, think, build cities, and farm, even though those are learned skills. Moral feelings aren't inherently part of our nature, in the sense that they aren’t present to any noticeable extent in everyone; sadly, this is a fact recognized even by those who strongly believe in their transcendental origin. Like the other learned skills mentioned, the moral sense, even if it's not part of our nature, grows naturally from it; it can, like them, spontaneously develop to a small extent and can be cultivated to reach a high level of development. Unfortunately, it can also be shaped in almost any direction through external influences and the impact of early experiences, allowing almost anything, no matter how absurd or harmful, to be instilled in the human mind with the authority of conscience. To doubt that the same potential could be applied to the principle of utility, even if it has no basis in human nature, would be to ignore all experience.
But moral associations which are wholly of artificial creation, when intellectual culture goes on, yield by degrees to the dissolving force of analysis: and if the feeling of duty, when associated with utility, would appear equally arbitrary; if there were no leading department of our nature, no powerful class of sentiments, with which that association would harmonize, which would make us feel it congenial, and incline us not only to foster it in others (for which we have abundant interested motives), but also to cherish it in ourselves; if there were not, in short, a natural basis of sentiment for utilitarian morality, it might well happen that this association also, even after it had been implanted by education, might be analysed away.
But moral connections that are entirely created by society gradually fade away under the pressure of analysis as intellectual culture develops. If the sense of duty, when linked to usefulness, seemed just as random; if there were no primary aspect of our nature, no strong set of feelings that would align with that connection and make it feel natural, leading us not only to encourage it in others (for which we have plenty of personal reasons) but also to value it in ourselves; if there weren't, in summary, a natural emotional foundation for utilitarian morality, it could very well happen that this connection, even after being instilled through education, might be broken down through analysis.
But there is this basis of powerful natural sentiment; and this it is which, when once the general happiness is recognized as the ethical standard, will constitute the strength of the utilitarian morality. This firm foundation is that of the social feelings of mankind; the desire to be in unity with our fellow creatures, which is already a powerful principle in human nature, and happily one of those which tend to become stronger, even without express inculcation, from the influences of advancing civilization. The social state is at once so natural, so necessary, and so habitual to man, that, except in some unusual circumstances or by an effort of voluntary abstraction, he never conceives himself otherwise than as a member of a body; and this association is riveted more and more, as mankind are further removed from the state of savage independence. Any condition, therefore, which is essential to a state of society, becomes more and more an inseparable part of every person's conception of the state of things which he is born into, and which is the destiny of a human being. Now, society between human beings, except in the relation of master and slave, is manifestly impossible on any other footing than that the interests of all are to be consulted. Society between equals can only exist on the understanding that the interests of all are to be regarded equally. And since in all states of civilization, every person, except an absolute monarch, has equals, every one is obliged to live on these terms with somebody; and in every age some advance is made towards a state in which it will be impossible to live permanently on other terms with anybody. In this way people grow up unable to conceive as possible to them a state of total disregard of other people's interests. They are under a necessity of conceiving themselves as at least abstaining from all the grosser injuries, and (if only for their own protection.) living in a state of constant protest against them. They are also familiar with the fact of co-operating with others, and proposing to themselves a collective, not an individual, interest, as the aim (at least for the time being) of their actions. So long as they are co-operating, their ends are identified with those of others; there is at least a temporary feeling that the interests of others are their own interests. Not only does all strengthening of social ties, and all healthy growth of society, give to each individual a stronger personal interest in practically consulting the welfare of others; it also leads him to identify his feelings more and more with their good, or at least with an ever greater degree of practical consideration for it. He comes, as though instinctively, to be conscious of himself as a being who of course pays regard to others. The good of others becomes to him a thing naturally and necessarily to be attended to, like any of the physical conditions of our existence. Now, whatever amount of this feeling a person has, he is urged by the strongest motives both of interest and of sympathy to demonstrate it, and to the utmost of his power encourage it in others; and even if he has none of it himself, he is as greatly interested as any one else that others should have it. Consequently, the smallest germs of the feeling are laid hold of and nourished by the contagion of sympathy and the influences of education; and a complete web of corroborative association is woven round it, by the powerful agency of the external sanctions. This mode of conceiving ourselves and human life, as civilization goes on, is felt to be more and more natural. Every step in political improvement renders it more so, by removing the sources of opposition of interest, and levelling those inequalities of legal privilege between individuals or classes, owing to which there are large portions of mankind whose happiness it is still practicable to disregard. In an improving state of the human mind, the influences are constantly on the increase, which tend to generate in each individual a feeling of unity with all the rest; which feeling, if perfect, would make him never think of, or desire, any beneficial condition for himself, in the benefits of which they are not included. If we now suppose this feeling of unity to be taught as a religion, and the whole force of education, of institutions, and of opinion, directed, as it once was in the case of religion, to make every person grow up from infancy surrounded on all sides both by the profession and by the practice of it, I think that no one, who can realize this conception, will feel any misgiving about the sufficiency of the ultimate sanction for the Happiness morality. To any ethical student who finds the realization difficult, I recommend, as a means of facilitating it, the second of M. Comte's two principal works, the Système de Politique Positive. I entertain the strongest objections to the system of politics and morals set forth in that treatise; but I think it has superabundantly shown the possibility of giving to the service of humanity, even without the aid of belief in a Providence, both the physical power and the social efficacy of a religion; making it take hold of human life, and colour all thought, feeling, and action, in a manner of which the greatest ascendency ever exercised by any religion may be but a type and foretaste; and of which the danger is, not that it should be insufficient, but that it should be so excessive as to interfere unduly with human freedom and individuality.
But there's a strong natural feeling at the core of this. Once general happiness is recognized as the ethical standard, it will form the basis of utilitarian morality. This solid foundation is the social feelings of humanity—the desire to connect with others, which is already a powerful aspect of human nature and one of those things that tends to grow stronger, even without deliberate teaching, as civilization advances. The social state is so natural, necessary, and habitual for humans that, except in unusual circumstances or through a deliberate act of abstraction, we can hardly imagine ourselves as anything other than members of a community. This connection deepens as people move further away from a state of wild independence. Therefore, any condition essential to society becomes an inseparable part of how each person sees the world they are born into, and what is expected of a human life. Now, relationships between people, except in master/slave dynamics, are clearly impossible unless everyone's interests are taken into account. Societies made up of equals can only exist when everyone's interests are valued equally. Since, in all civilized states, every person except an absolute monarch has equals, everyone has to interact with others on these terms; and with each passing era, progress is made toward a situation where it's impossible to live in any other way. This way, people grow up unable to imagine a complete disregard for other people’s interests. They are compelled to see themselves as at least refraining from major harm to others, and (if only for their own safety) living in a state of ongoing opposition to such harm. They are also used to cooperating with others and aiming for a collective, rather than just individual, interest (at least temporarily). As long as they are working together, their goals align with those of others, leading to at least a temporary feeling that what benefits others also benefits them. Not only does strengthening social bonds and fostering healthy societal growth offer each individual an increased personal stake in considering the welfare of others, it also encourages them to align their feelings more closely with the well-being of others, or at least to be more practically aware of it. They come, almost instinctively, to understand themselves as beings who just naturally take others into account. The welfare of others becomes something they recognize as essential, like any of the basic conditions for our existence. Now, regardless of how much of this feeling a person has, they are motivated by both self-interest and sympathy to express it and, as much as possible, encourage it in others; even if they possess none of it themselves, they are just as invested as anyone else in ensuring that others do. Consequently, even the smallest traces of this feeling are supported and nurtured by the contagious nature of sympathy and the effects of education; and a complete network of supportive connections is woven around it by the strong influence of external sanctions. This way of seeing ourselves and human existence feels increasingly natural as civilization progresses. Each step in political improvement makes it feel more so by eliminating sources of conflicting interests and leveling legal privileges between individuals or classes, which allows for segments of humanity whose happiness can still be overlooked. As the human mind improves, influences that encourage a feeling of unity with all others continually increase; a feeling that, if fully realized, would eliminate any thought or desire for personal gain that doesn’t include the benefits of everyone else. Now, if we consider this feeling of unity to be taught as a religion, with all the power of education, institutions, and societal opinion directed towards making every individual grow up surrounded by both its practice and proclamation, I believe no one who can envision this will doubt the adequacy of the ultimate incentive for happiness-based morality. For any ethical student struggling with this realization, I suggest the second of M. Comte's two main works, the Système de Politique Positive. I have strong objections to the political and moral system presented in that work, but I think it clearly demonstrates the possibility of dedicating oneself to humanity's service, even without belief in a higher power, while still wielding both the physical strength and social effectiveness of religion; it can shape human life and influence all thoughts, feelings, and actions in a way that the greatest power ever displayed by any religion might only signal what’s possible; and the concern isn’t that it’ll be inadequate, but that it could become so overwhelming that it interferes with human freedom and individuality.
Neither is it necessary to the feeling which constitutes the binding force of the utilitarian morality on those who recognize it, to wait for those social influences which would make its obligation felt by mankind at large. In the comparatively early state of human advancement in which we now live, a person cannot indeed feel that entireness of sympathy with all others, which would make any real discordance in the general direction of their conduct in life impossible; but already a person in whom the social feeling is at all developed, cannot bring himself to think of the rest of his fellow creatures as struggling rivals with him for the means of happiness, whom he must desire to see defeated in their object in order that he may succeed in his. The deeply-rooted conception which every individual even now has of himself as a social being, tends to make him feel it one of his natural wants that there should be harmony between his feelings and aims and those of his fellow creatures. If differences of opinion and of mental culture make it impossible for him to share many of their actual feelings-perhaps make him denounce and defy those feelings-he still needs to be conscious that his real aim and theirs do not conflict; that he is not opposing himself to what they really wish for, namely, their own good, but is, on the contrary, promoting it. This feeling in most individuals is much inferior in strength to their selfish feelings, and is often wanting altogether. But to those who have it, it possesses all the characters of a natural feeling. It does not present itself to their minds as a superstition of education, or a law despotically imposed by the power of society, but as an attribute which it would not be well for them to be without. This conviction is the ultimate sanction of the greatest-happiness morality. This it is which makes any mind, of well-developed feelings, work with, and not against, the outward motives to care for others, afforded by what I have called the external sanctions; and when those sanctions are wanting, or act in an opposite direction, constitutes in itself a powerful internal binding force, in proportion to the sensitiveness and thoughtfulness of the character; since few but those whose mind is a moral blank, could bear to lay out their course of life on the plan of paying no regard to others except so far as their own private interest compels.
It's not necessary for the feeling that creates the binding force of utilitarian morality for those who understand it to wait for social influences that would make its obligation felt by everyone. In the relatively early stage of human development that we live in now, a person can't feel complete sympathy with everyone else, which would eliminate any real discord in their general behavior in life; however, a person who has any level of social feeling can't think of his fellow humans as competitors for happiness, hoping to see them fail so he can succeed. The deep-rooted idea that everyone has of themselves as social beings makes them feel it's a natural need for there to be harmony between their feelings and goals and those of others. Even if differences in opinion and knowledge make it hard for him to share many of their feelings—maybe even cause him to criticize or reject those feelings—he still needs to be aware that his true aim does not conflict with theirs; he is not opposing what they genuinely wish for, which is their own well-being, but is, in fact, supporting it. This feeling is often much weaker than their self-interested feelings and can sometimes be completely absent. But for those who do feel it, it has all the qualities of a natural feeling. They don't see it as a superstition from education or a law imposed by society’s power, but as something essential they wouldn’t want to be without. This belief is the ultimate foundation of the greatest-happiness morality. It causes any mind with well-developed feelings to work with, rather than against, the external motivations to care for others, provided by what I’ve referred to as external sanctions; and when those sanctions are missing or work in the opposite direction, it creates a strong internal force, proportional to how sensitive and thoughtful the character is—since few, except those whose minds are completely lacking in morality, could choose to live life with no regard for others, except as far as their own interests require.
CHAPTER IV.
It has already been remarked, that questions of ultimate ends do not admit of proof, in the ordinary acceptation of the term. To be incapable of proof by reasoning is common to all first principles; to the first premises of our knowledge, as well as to those of our conduct. But the former, being matters of fact, may be the subject of a direct appeal to the faculties which judge of fact—namely, our senses, and our internal consciousness. Can an appeal be made to the same faculties on questions of practical ends? Or by what other faculty is cognizance taken of them?
It has already been noted that questions about ultimate purposes cannot be proven in the usual sense of the term. The inability to be proven through reasoning is a characteristic of all first principles; this applies to the foundational premises of our knowledge as well as our actions. However, the former, being matters of fact, can be directly appealed to the faculties that assess facts—namely, our senses and our internal awareness. Can we appeal to the same faculties regarding questions of practical purposes? Or what other faculty is used to understand them?
Questions about ends are, in other words, questions what things are desirable. The utilitarian doctrine is, that happiness is desirable, and the only thing desirable, as an end; all other things being only desirable as means to that end. What ought to be required of this doctrine—what conditions is it requisite that the doctrine should fulfil—to make good its claim to be believed?
Questions about ends are, in other words, questions about what things are desirable. The utilitarian doctrine states that happiness is desirable and the only thing that is desirable as an end; everything else is only desirable as a means to that end. What should we expect from this doctrine—what conditions must it meet—to justify its claim to be believed?
The only proof capable of being given that an object is visible, is that people actually see it. The only proof that a sound is audible, is that people hear it: and so of the other sources of our experience. In like manner, I apprehend, the sole evidence it is possible to produce that anything is desirable, is that people do actually desire it. If the end which the utilitarian doctrine proposes to itself were not, in theory and in practice, acknowledged to be an end, nothing could ever convince any person that it was so. No reason can be given why the general happiness is desirable, except that each person, so far as he believes it to be attainable, desires his own happiness. This, however, being a fact, we have not only all the proof which the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, that happiness is a good: that each person's happiness is a good to that person, and the general happiness, therefore, a good to the aggregate of all persons. Happiness has made out its title as one of the ends of conduct, and consequently one of the criteria of morality.
The only proof that something is visible is that people can actually see it. The only proof that a sound is audible is that people can hear it, and the same goes for other sources of our experience. Similarly, I believe the only evidence we can provide for anything being desirable is that people actually desire it. If the goal that utilitarianism aims for wasn’t recognized as a goal both in theory and practice, nothing could convince anyone that it is. There’s no reason to say that general happiness is desirable, except that each person, as long as they believe it’s achievable, wants their own happiness. However, since this is a fact, we have all the proof we need that happiness is a good: that each person's happiness is good for them, and thus general happiness is good for everyone as a whole. Happiness has established itself as one of the goals of conduct, and therefore one of the standards of morality.
But it has not, by this alone, proved itself to be the sole criterion. To do that, it would seem, by the same rule, necessary to show, not only that people desire happiness, but that they never desire anything else. Now it is palpable that they do desire things which, in common language, are decidedly distinguished from happiness. They desire, for example, virtue, and the absence of vice, no less really than pleasure and the absence of pain. The desire of virtue is not as universal, but it is as authentic a fact, as the desire of happiness. And hence the opponents of the utilitarian standard deem that they have a right to infer that there are other ends of human action besides happiness, and that happiness is not the standard of approbation and disapprobation.
But this alone doesn’t prove that it’s the only standard. To do that, it seems necessary to show not only that people want happiness, but that they never want anything else. It’s clear that people do want things that are, in common language, clearly different from happiness. They want, for instance, virtue and the absence of vice, just as much as they want pleasure and the absence of pain. The desire for virtue isn’t as universal, but it’s just as real as the desire for happiness. Therefore, the critics of the utilitarian standard believe they have a valid reason to conclude that there are other goals of human action beyond happiness, and that happiness isn’t the standard for approval and disapproval.
But does the utilitarian doctrine deny that people desire virtue, or maintain that virtue is not a thing to be desired? The very reverse. It maintains not only that virtue is to be desired, but that it is to be desired disinterestedly, for itself. Whatever may be the opinion of utilitarian moralists as to the original conditions by which virtue is made virtue; however they may believe (as they do) that actions and dispositions are only virtuous because they promote another end than virtue; yet this being granted, and it having been decided, from considerations of this description, what is virtuous, they not only place virtue at the very head of the things which are good as means to the ultimate end, but they also recognise as a psychological fact the possibility of its being, to the individual, a good in itself, without looking to any end beyond it; and hold, that the mind is not in a right state, not in a state conformable to Utility, not in the state most conducive to the general happiness, unless it does love virtue in this manner—as a thing desirable in itself, even although, in the individual instance, it should not produce those other desirable consequences which it tends to produce, and on account of which it is held to be virtue. This opinion is not, in the smallest degree, a departure from the Happiness principle. The ingredients of happiness are very various, and each of them is desirable in itself, and not merely when considered as swelling an aggregate. The principle of utility does not mean that any given pleasure, as music, for instance, or any given exemption from pain, as for example health, are to be looked upon as means to a collective something termed happiness, and to be desired on that account. They are desired and desirable in and for themselves; besides being means, they are a part of the end. Virtue, according to the utilitarian doctrine, is not naturally and originally part of the end, but it is capable of becoming so; and in those who love it disinterestedly it has become so, and is desired and cherished, not as a means to happiness, but as a part of their happiness.
But does the utilitarian belief deny that people want virtue, or insist that virtue isn’t something to be desired? Quite the opposite. It argues not only that virtue is to be desired, but that it should be desired for its own sake. Regardless of what utilitarian moralists think about how virtue is established; no matter how they believe (and they do) that actions and dispositions are only virtuous because they contribute to another end beyond virtue; even if we accept this, and it is determined, based on these considerations, what is virtuous, they not only place virtue at the forefront of the things that are good as means to the ultimate goal, but they also acknowledge as a psychological fact the possibility of it being, for the individual, a good in itself, without looking for any purpose beyond it; and argue that a mind is not in the right state, not aligned with Utility, nor in the state most likely to promote general happiness, unless it loves virtue in this way—as something desirable in itself, even if, in that particular case, it doesn’t produce those other desirable outcomes which it typically does, and for which it's considered virtue. This belief does not, in any way, deviate from the Happiness principle. The components of happiness are quite diverse, and each one is desirable in itself, not just when seen as contributing to an overall total. The principle of utility does not imply that any specific pleasure, like music, for example, or any specific relief from pain, such as health, should be regarded as means to a collective concept known as happiness, and thus desired for that reason. They are desired and valued in and of themselves; in addition to being means, they are part of the end. According to the utilitarian doctrine, virtue is not inherently and originally part of the end, but it has the potential to become so; and in those who appreciate it selflessly, it has indeed become so, and is desired and treasured, not as a means to happiness, but as a part of their happiness.
To illustrate this farther, we may remember that virtue is not the only thing, originally a means, and which if it were not a means to anything else, would be and remain indifferent, but which by association with what it is a means to, comes to be desired for itself, and that too with the utmost intensity. What, for example, shall we say of the love of money? There is nothing originally more desirable about money than about any heap of glittering pebbles. Its worth is solely that of the things which it will buy; the desires for other things than itself, which it is a means of gratifying. Yet the love of money is not only one of the strongest moving forces of human life, but money is, in many cases, desired in and for itself; the desire to possess it is often stronger than the desire to use it, and goes on increasing when all the desires which point to ends beyond it, to be compassed by it, are falling off. It may be then said truly, that money is desired not for the sake of an end, but as part of the end. From being a means to happiness, it has come to be itself a principal ingredient of the individual's conception of happiness. The same may be said of the majority of the great objects of human life—power, for example, or fame; except that to each of these there is a certain amount of immediate pleasure annexed, which has at least the semblance of being naturally inherent in them; a thing which cannot be said of money. Still, however, the strongest natural attraction, both of power and of fame, is the immense aid they give to the attainment of our other wishes; and it is the strong association thus generated between them and all our objects of desire, which gives to the direct desire of them the intensity it often assumes, so as in some characters to surpass in strength all other desires. In these cases the means have become a part of the end, and a more important part of it than any of the things which they are means to. What was once desired as an instrument for the attainment of happiness, has come to be desired for its own sake. In being desired for its own sake it is, however, desired as part of happiness. The person is made, or thinks he would be made, happy by its mere possession; and is made unhappy by failure to obtain it. The desire of it is not a different thing from the desire of happiness, any more than the love of music, or the desire of health. They are included in happiness. They are some of the elements of which the desire of happiness is made up. Happiness is not an abstract idea, but a concrete whole; and these are some of its parts. And the utilitarian standard sanctions and approves their being so. Life would be a poor thing, very ill provided with sources of happiness, if there were not this provision of nature, by which things originally indifferent, but conducive to, or otherwise associated with, the satisfaction of our primitive desires, become in themselves sources of pleasure more valuable than the primitive pleasures, both in permanency, in the space of human existence that they are capable of covering, and even in intensity. Virtue, according to the utilitarian conception, is a good of this description. There was no original desire of it, or motive to it, save its conduciveness to pleasure, and especially to protection from pain. But through the association thus formed, it may be felt a good in itself, and desired as such with as great intensity as any other good; and with this difference between it and the love of money, of power, or of fame, that all of these may, and often do, render the individual noxious to the other members of the society to which he belongs, whereas there is nothing which makes him so much a blessing to them as the cultivation of the disinterested, love of virtue. And consequently, the utilitarian standard, while it tolerates and approves those other acquired desires, up to the point beyond which they would be more injurious to the general happiness than promotive of it, enjoins and requires the cultivation of the love of virtue up to the greatest strength possible, as being above all things important to the general happiness.
To explain this further, we should remember that virtue is not just an end in itself; it started as a means to something else. If it weren't a means to something more, it would be indifferent, but through its connection to what it leads to, it becomes something we desire for its own sake, and often with great intensity. Take the love of money, for example. There’s nothing inherently more desirable about money than about a pile of shiny pebbles; its value comes solely from what it can buy, satisfying our desires for things beyond itself. However, the love of money is one of the strongest motivators in human life, and often, money is desired for its own sake. The desire to have it can outweigh the desire to use it, and it tends to grow even when other desires for what it can provide diminish. Thus, it can be accurately said that money is desired not just as a means to an end, but as part of the end itself. What began as a way to achieve happiness has transformed into a key part of an individual’s idea of happiness. The same applies to many major objectives in life—like power or fame—though each also offers a certain immediate pleasure that seems somewhat inherent. However, the main attraction of both power and fame lies in the significant help they provide in achieving our other desires; it’s this strong connection that intensifies the direct desire for them, often making it stronger than all other desires. In these situations, the means have become an essential component of the end, sometimes more important than the actual goals they help achieve. What was once sought as a tool for happiness is now sought for its own sake. Yet, when it is desired for its own sake, it’s still viewed as part of happiness. A person feels, or believes they would feel, happy just by possessing it, and unhappy if they fail to get it. The desire for it isn't separate from the desire for happiness, just like the love of music or the desire for health isn’t. They form part of happiness. Happiness is not an abstract notion, but a tangible whole, and these are its components. The utilitarian standard supports and validates this view. Life would lack significant sources of happiness if nature didn’t provide a way for things that are initially indifferent but help fulfill our basic desires to become sources of pleasure that are often more valuable than those basic pleasures in terms of their durability, the range of human existence they encompass, and even their intensity. Virtue, in the utilitarian view, fits this description. There was no original desire for it, nor any motivation to pursue it, other than its ability to lead to pleasure and particularly to protect from pain. But through the connections formed, it can be seen as a good in itself, desired with the same intensity as any other good; and with this distinction from the love of money, power, or fame: all of these can, and often do, harm others in society, while the cultivation of a selfless love of virtue is what makes one a blessing to others. Consequently, the utilitarian standard not only accepts and endorses those other learned desires, as long as they don't harm general happiness more than they promote it, but also encourages and demands the strong cultivation of the love of virtue, considering it vital for overall happiness.
It results from the preceding considerations, that there is in reality nothing desired except happiness. Whatever is desired otherwise than as a means to some end beyond itself, and ultimately to happiness, is desired as itself a part of happiness, and is not desired for itself until it has become so. Those who desire virtue for its own sake, desire it either because the consciousness of it is a pleasure, or because the consciousness of being without it is a pain, or for both reasons united; as in truth the pleasure and pain seldom exist separately, but almost always together, the same person feeling pleasure in the degree of virtue attained, and pain in not having attained more. If one of these gave him no pleasure, and the other no pain, he would not love or desire virtue, or would desire it only for the other benefits which it might produce to himself or to persons whom he cared for.
It follows from the previous points that, in reality, the only thing people truly want is happiness. Anything sought after for reasons other than as a means to achieve something beyond itself—ultimately happiness— is desired because it is part of happiness itself and isn't valued for what it is until it becomes so. Those who seek virtue for its own sake do so either because the awareness of it brings them pleasure or because the awareness of lacking it causes them pain, or for both reasons together; in truth, pleasure and pain usually coexist rather than being separate. The same person feels joy in the level of virtue they've achieved while also feeling pain from not having reached a higher level. If one of these feelings didn’t bring pleasure and the other didn’t bring pain, they wouldn’t care about virtue or would only want it for the other benefits it might bring to themselves or to people they care about.
We have now, then, an answer to the question, of what sort of proof the principle of utility is susceptible. If the opinion which I have now stated is psychologically true—if human nature is so constituted as to desire nothing which is not either a part of happiness or a means of happiness, we can have no other proof, and we require no other, that these are the only things desirable. If so, happiness is the sole end of human action, and the promotion of it the test by which to judge of all human conduct; from whence it necessarily follows that it must be the criterion of morality, since a part is included in the whole.
We now have an answer to the question of what kind of proof is associated with the principle of utility. If what I’ve just stated is psychologically accurate—if human nature is such that we only desire things that contribute to happiness or are means to achieve happiness—then we have no other proof, nor do we need any other, that these are the only things worth wanting. If this is the case, happiness is the ultimate goal of human actions, and promoting it is the standard by which we should evaluate all human behavior; this leads to the conclusion that it must be the foundation of morality, since a part is included in the whole.
And now to decide whether this is really so; whether mankind do desire nothing for itself but that which is a pleasure to them, or of which the absence is a pain; we have evidently arrived at a question of fact and experience, dependent, like all similar questions, upon evidence. It can only be determined by practised self-consciousness and self-observation, assisted by observation of others. I believe that these sources of evidence, impartially consulted, will declare that desiring a thing and finding it pleasant, aversion to it and thinking of it as painful, are phenomena entirely inseparable, or rather two parts of the same phenomenon; in strictness of language, two different modes of naming the same psychological fact: that to think of an object as desirable (unless for the sake of its consequences), and to think of it as pleasant, are one and the same thing; and that to desire anything, except in proportion as the idea of it is pleasant, is a physical and metaphysical impossibility.
And now we need to decide if this is really true; whether humanity desires nothing for itself but what brings them pleasure, or that which, if absent, causes pain. We have reached a question of fact and experience, which, like all similar questions, relies on evidence. It can only be answered through practiced self-awareness and self-observation, along with observing others. I believe that these sources of evidence, when looked at without bias, will show that desiring something and finding it enjoyable, as well as having an aversion to it and seeing it as painful, are completely intertwined, or rather two aspects of the same thing; strictly speaking, two different ways of describing the same psychological fact: that to view something as desirable (unless for its outcomes) and to perceive it as enjoyable are essentially the same; and that to want anything, except in proportion to how pleasant the idea of it is, is a physical and metaphysical impossibility.
So obvious does this appear to me, that I expect it will hardly be disputed: and the objection made will be, not that desire can possibly be directed to anything ultimately except pleasure and exemption from pain, but that the will is a different thing from desire; that a person of confirmed virtue, or any other person whose purposes are fixed, carries out his purposes without any thought of the pleasure he has in contemplating them, or expects to derive from their fulfilment; and persists in acting on them, even though these pleasures are much diminished, by changes in his character or decay of his passive sensibilities, or are outweighed by the pains which the pursuit of the purposes may bring upon him. All this I fully admit, and have stated it elsewhere, as positively and emphatically as any one. Will, the active phenomenon, is a different thing from desire, the state of passive sensibility, and though originally an offshoot from it, may in time take root and detach itself from the parent stock; so much so, that in the case of an habitual purpose, instead of willing the thing because we desire it, we often desire it only because we will it. This, however, is but an instance of that familiar fact, the power of habit, and is nowise confined to the case of virtuous actions. Many indifferent things, which men originally did from a motive of some sort, they continue to do from habit. Sometimes this is done unconsciously, the consciousness coming only after the action: at other times with conscious volition, but volition which has become habitual, and is put into operation by the force of habit, in opposition perhaps to the deliberate preference, as often happens with those who have contracted habits of vicious or hurtful indulgence. Third and last comes the case in which the habitual act of will in the individual instance is not in contradiction to the general intention prevailing at other times, but in fulfilment of it; as in the case of the person of confirmed virtue, and of all who pursue deliberately and consistently any determinate end. The distinction between will and desire thus understood, is an authentic and highly important psychological fact; but the fact consists solely in this—that will, like all other parts of our constitution, is amenable to habit, and that we may will from habit what we no longer desire for itself, or desire only because we will it. It is not the less true that will, in the beginning, is entirely produced by desire; including in that term the repelling influence of pain as well as the attractive one of pleasure. Let us take into consideration, no longer the person who has a confirmed will to do right, but him in whom that virtuous will is still feeble, conquerable by temptation, and not to be fully relied on; by what means can it be strengthened? How can the will to be virtuous, where it does not exist in sufficient force, be implanted or awakened? Only by making the person desire virtue—by making him think of it in a pleasurable light, or of its absence in a painful one. It is by associating the doing right with pleasure, or the doing wrong with pain, or by eliciting and impressing and bringing home to the person's experience the pleasure naturally involved in the one or the pain in the other, that it is possible to call forth that will to be virtuous, which, when confirmed, acts without any thought of either pleasure or pain. Will is the child of desire, and passes out of the dominion of its parent only to come under that of habit. That which is the result of habit affords no presumption of being intrinsically good; and there would be no reason for wishing that the purpose of virtue should become independent of pleasure and pain, were it not that the influence of the pleasurable and painful associations which prompt to virtue is not sufficiently to be depended on for unerring constancy of action until it has acquired the support of habit. Both in feeling and in conduct, habit is the only thing which imparts certainty; and it is because of the importance to others of being able to rely absolutely on one's feelings and conduct, and to oneself of being able to rely on one's own, that the will to do right ought to be cultivated into this habitual independence. In other words, this state of the will is a means to good, not intrinsically a good; and does not contradict the doctrine that nothing is a good to human beings but in so far as it is either itself pleasurable, or a means of attaining pleasure or averting pain.
This seems so obvious to me that I doubt anyone will argue against it. The objection will not be that desire can point to anything other than pleasure and relief from pain, but rather that will is different from desire. A person of established virtue, or anyone with fixed intentions, follows through on their goals without thinking of the pleasure they get from contemplating them or expect to gain from their completion. They continue to act on these goals even if the pleasure has diminished because of changes in their character or because their sensitivity has decreased, or if the pain that comes from pursuing these goals outweighs the pleasure. I completely agree with this and have expressed it elsewhere as strongly as anyone could. The will, as an action, is different from desire, which is a passive state. Though it originally stems from desire, over time it can grow and separate from its source; in the case of a habitual goal, we sometimes desire something not because we want it but simply because we have willed it. This is just an example of the common fact of habit and is not limited to virtuous actions. Many neutral actions that people initially performed for some reason are continued out of habit. Sometimes this happens unconsciously, with the awareness coming only after the action; other times it happens with conscious intention but has become habitual, driven by habit even if it goes against a thoughtful preference, as often occurs with those who have developed negative or harmful habits. The final scenario involves a habitual act of will that aligns with the general intention at other times, as seen in someone of established virtue, or anyone who consistently pursues a specific goal. The distinction between will and desire, as understood here, is a real and important psychological fact; however, it is solely that will, like all other aspects of our nature, is subject to habit, leading us to will what we no longer desire for its own sake or desire only because we will it. It remains true that will, in the beginning, is entirely driven by desire, which includes the repulsive force of pain as well as the attractive force of pleasure. Let's shift our focus not to someone with a strong will to do good, but to someone whose virtuous will is still weak, easily swayed by temptation, and not fully reliable. How can this will be strengthened? How can the will to be good, when it is not strong enough, be instilled or awakened? Only by making the person desire virtue—by encouraging them to view it positively or to see its absence negatively. It's by connecting doing good with pleasure and doing wrong with pain, or by helping the person experience the pleasure associated with the right action and the pain of the wrong one, that we can encourage a will to be virtuous, which, once established, acts without thinking about pleasure or pain. Will is a product of desire and moves out from its influence only to come under the influence of habit. What results from habit does not guarantee it is inherently good; and there’s no reason to wish for the purpose of virtue to become independent of pleasure and pain unless the influence of those pleasurable and painful associations that encourage virtue is not reliable enough for consistent actions until it gains the backing of habit. In both feelings and actions, habit is the only thing that brings certainty; and because it's important for others to absolutely rely on one's feelings and actions, and for oneself to rely on their own, the will to do good should be developed into this habitual independence. In other words, this state of will is a means to achieve good, not inherently good itself, and it does not contradict the idea that nothing benefits humans unless it is either pleasurable in itself or a means to achieve pleasure or avoid pain.
But if this doctrine be true, the principle of utility is proved. Whether it is so or not, must now be left to the consideration of the thoughtful reader.
But if this idea is true, then the principle of utility is confirmed. Whether that's the case or not must now be left for the thoughtful reader to consider.
CHAPTER V.
In all ages of speculation, one of the strongest obstacles to the reception of the doctrine that Utility or Happiness is the criterion of right and wrong, has been drawn from the idea of Justice, The powerful sentiment, and apparently clear perception, which that word recalls with a rapidity and certainty resembling an instinct, have seemed to the majority of thinkers to point to an inherent quality in things; to show that the Just must have an existence in Nature as something absolute-generically distinct from every variety of the Expedient, and, in idea, opposed to it, though (as is commonly acknowledged) never, in the long run, disjoined from it in fact.
Throughout the ages of thought, one of the biggest challenges to accepting the idea that Utility or Happiness is the standard for right and wrong has come from the concept of Justice. The strong feeling and seemingly clear understanding that the word evokes with a speed and certainty like instinct have made most thinkers believe it points to something inherent in reality; it suggests that Justice must exist in Nature as something absolute—distinct from any form of the Convenient, and, in theory, opposed to it, even though (as is widely recognized) they are never ultimately separated in practice.
In the case of this, as of our other moral sentiments, there is no necessary connexion between the question of its origin, and that of its binding force. That a feeling is bestowed on us by Nature, does not necessarily legitimate all its promptings. The feeling of justice might be a peculiar instinct, and might yet require, like our other instincts, to be controlled and enlightened by a higher reason. If we have intellectual instincts, leading us to judge in a particular way, as well as animal instincts that prompt us to act in a particular way, there is no necessity that the former should be more infallible in their sphere than the latter in theirs: it may as well happen that wrong judgments are occasionally suggested by those, as wrong actions by these. But though it is one thing to believe that we have natural feelings of justice, and another to acknowledge them as an ultimate criterion of conduct, these two opinions are very closely connected in point of fact. Mankind are always predisposed to believe that any subjective feeling, not otherwise accounted for, is a revelation of some objective reality. Our present object is to determine whether the reality, to which the feeling of justice corresponds, is one which needs any such special revelation; whether the justice or injustice of an action is a thing intrinsically peculiar, and distinct from all its other qualities, or only a combination of certain of those qualities, presented under a peculiar aspect. For the purpose of this inquiry, it is practically important to consider whether the feeling itself, of justice and injustice, is sui generis like our sensations of colour and taste, or a derivative feeling, formed by a combination of others. And this it is the more essential to examine, as people are in general willing enough to allow, that objectively the dictates of justice coincide with a part of the field of General Expediency; but inasmuch as the subjective mental feeling of Justice is different from that which commonly attaches to simple expediency, and, except in extreme cases of the latter, is far more imperative in its demands, people find it difficult to see, in Justice, only a particular kind or branch of general utility, and think that its superior binding force requires a totally different origin.
In this case, just like with our other moral feelings, there's no necessary connection between where those feelings come from and how binding they are. Just because a feeling is given to us by nature doesn’t mean that all its prompts are justified. The feeling of justice could be a unique instinct that still needs to be guided and clarified by a higher reason, similar to our other instincts. If we have intellectual instincts that lead us to judge in specific ways and animal instincts that drive us to act in certain ways, there's no guarantee that the first group is more reliable than the second. It's possible for both to occasionally suggest wrong judgments or wrong actions. While believing in natural feelings of justice is one thing, recognizing them as the ultimate guide for behavior is another; however, these two views are closely linked in reality. People are generally inclined to think that any subjective feeling, unless explained otherwise, reveals some objective truth. Our goal here is to determine whether the reality that the feeling of justice corresponds to truly requires such a special revelation; whether the justice or injustice of an action is something inherently unique and separate from its other qualities or just a mix of certain qualities presented in a particular way. For this inquiry, it's important to consider whether the feeling of justice and injustice is sui generis, like our sensations of color and taste, or a derivative feeling formed from a combination of others. This examination is essential, as people are usually willing to accept that, objectively, the principles of justice align with part of the field of General Expediency. However, because the subjective mental feeling of Justice differs from the one usually associated with simple expediency, and is much more compelling in its demands, people struggle to see Justice as just a specific kind or branch of general utility, believing instead that its greater binding force must have a different origin.
To throw light upon this question, it is necessary to attempt to ascertain what is the distinguishing character of justice, or of injustice: what is the quality, or whether there is any quality, attributed in common to all modes of conduct designated as unjust (for justice, like many other moral attributes, is best defined by its opposite), and distinguishing them from such modes of conduct as are disapproved, but without having that particular epithet of disapprobation applied to them. If, in everything which men are accustomed to characterize as just or unjust, some one common attribute or collection of attributes is always present, we may judge whether this particular attribute or combination of attributes would be capable of gathering round it a sentiment of that peculiar character and intensity by virtue of the general laws of our emotional constitution, or whether the sentiment is inexplicable, and requires to be regarded as a special provision of Nature. If we find the former to be the case, we shall, in resolving this question, have resolved also the main problem: if the latter, we shall have to seek for some other mode of investigating it.
To shed light on this question, we need to figure out what defines justice and injustice: what quality, if any, is common to all actions commonly seen as unjust (since justice, like many other moral traits, is often defined by its opposite), and how these actions differ from others that are disapproved of but don’t carry that specific label of disapproval. If there is a common attribute or set of attributes always present in what people usually define as just or unjust, we can determine whether this specific attribute or combination of attributes can evoke a certain type and intensity of feeling based on our emotional makeup, or if the feeling is so unique that it must be seen as a special aspect of Nature. If we find the first to be true, we will have answered the main question; if not, we will need to try another approach to investigate it.
To find the common attributes of a variety of objects, it is necessary to begin, by surveying the objects themselves in the concrete. Let us therefore advert successively to the various modes of action, and arrangements of human affairs, which are classed, by universal or widely spread opinion, as Just or as Unjust. The things well known to excite the sentiments associated with those names, are of a very multifarious character. I shall pass them rapidly in review, without studying any particular arrangement.
To identify the shared characteristics of different objects, we need to start by examining the objects themselves directly. Let's then look at the various ways people act and how human interactions are perceived, which are generally labeled as Just or Unjust. The things that are commonly known to provoke feelings connected to these terms are quite diverse. I will quickly go through them without following any specific order.
In the first place, it is mostly considered unjust to deprive any one of his personal liberty, his property, or any other thing which belongs to him by law. Here, therefore, is one instance of the application of the terms just and unjust in a perfectly definite sense, namely, that it is just to respect, unjust to violate, the legal rights of any one. But this judgment admits of several exceptions, arising from the other forms in which the notions of justice and injustice present themselves. For example, the person who suffers the deprivation may (as the phrase is) have forfeited the rights which he is so deprived of: a case to which we shall return presently. But also,
In the first place, it is generally seen as unjust to take away someone’s personal freedom, property, or anything else that legally belongs to them. So, here’s an example of how we define the terms just and unjust: it is just to respect, and unjust to violate, the legal rights of anyone. However, this judgment has several exceptions, which arise from the different ways we understand justice and injustice. For instance, the person who experiences this deprivation may (as the saying goes) have forfeited the rights they are being denied: a scenario we will discuss shortly. But also,
Secondly; the legal rights of which he is deprived, may be rights which ought not to have belonged to him; in other words, the law which confers on him these rights, may be a bad law. When it is so, or when (which is the same thing for our purpose) it is supposed to be so, opinions will differ as to the justice or injustice of infringing it. Some maintain that no law, however bad, ought to be disobeyed by an individual citizen; that his opposition to it, if shown at all, should only be shown in endeavouring to get it altered by competent authority. This opinion (which condemns many of the most illustrious benefactors of mankind, and would often protect pernicious institutions against the only weapons which, in the state of things existing at the time, have any chance of succeeding against them) is defended, by those who hold it, on grounds of expediency; principally on that of the importance, to the common interest of mankind, of maintaining inviolate the sentiment of submission to law. Other persons, again, hold the directly contrary opinion, that any law, judged to be bad, may blamelessly be disobeyed, even though it be not judged to be unjust, but only inexpedient; while others would confine the licence of disobedience to the case of unjust laws: but again, some say, that all laws which are inexpedient are unjust; since every law imposes some restriction on the natural liberty of mankind, which restriction is an injustice, unless legitimated by tending to their good. Among these diversities of opinion, it seems to be universally admitted that there may be unjust laws, and that law, consequently, is not the ultimate criterion of justice, but may give to one person a benefit, or impose on another an evil, which justice condemns. When, however, a law is thought to be unjust, it seems always to be regarded as being so in the same way in which a breach of law is unjust, namely, by infringing somebody's right; which, as it cannot in this case be a legal right, receives a different appellation, and is called a moral right. We may say, therefore, that a second case of injustice consists in taking or withholding from any person that to which he has a moral right.
Secondly, the legal rights that he is denied may be rights that shouldn't have belonged to him; in other words, the law that grants him these rights may be a flawed law. When that is the case, or when it is presumed to be so (which is essentially the same for our discussion), opinions will vary on the fairness or unfairness of challenging it. Some argue that no law, no matter how bad, should be disobeyed by an individual citizen; that if they oppose it at all, it should only be in efforts to have it changed by the appropriate authority. This view (which criticizes many of the most notable benefactors of society, and would often shield harmful institutions from the only means that might effectively oppose them at the time) is defended by those who believe it on the basis of practicality; mainly due to the importance of maintaining the shared belief in obeying the law for the common good of humanity. On the other hand, there are people who hold the completely opposite view that any law deemed bad can be disobeyed without blame, even if it is not thought to be unjust, just impractical; while others would restrict the right to disobey to situations involving unjust laws. However, some argue that all laws that are impractical are unjust; as every law imposes some limit on the natural freedom of individuals, which limitation is unjust unless it is justified by promoting their well-being. Among these differing opinions, it seems widely accepted that there can be unjust laws, and therefore, law is not the final measure of justice, as it can grant one person a benefit while imposing harm on another, which justice would condemn. When a law is considered unjust, it is typically seen as unjust in the same way that breaking a law is unjust, namely, by violating someone’s right; which, since it cannot be a legal right in this context, is termed a moral right. Therefore, we can say that a second instance of injustice consists of taking or withholding from any person what they have a moral right to.
Thirdly, it is universally considered just that each person should obtain that (whether good or evil) which he deserves; and unjust that he should obtain a good, or be made to undergo an evil, which he does not deserve. This is, perhaps, the clearest and most emphatic form in which the idea of justice is conceived by the general mind. As it involves the notion of desert, the question arises, what constitutes desert? Speaking in a general way, a person is understood to deserve good if he does right, evil if he does wrong; and in a more particular sense, to deserve good from those to whom he does or has done good, and evil from those to whom he does or has done evil. The precept of returning good for evil has never been regarded as a case of the fulfilment of justice, but as one in which the claims of justice are waived, in obedience to other considerations.
Thirdly, it's universally accepted that everyone should get what they deserve, whether that's good or bad, and it's unfair for someone to receive good or face bad consequences they haven't earned. This is probably the clearest and most powerful way that people think about justice. Since it relates to the idea of deserving, the question comes up: what does it mean to deserve? Generally speaking, a person is seen as deserving good if they do the right thing and bad if they do the wrong thing. More specifically, one deserves good from those they've treated well and bad from those they've wronged. The idea of returning good for evil has never been considered a fulfillment of justice; instead, it's viewed as a situation where justice claims are set aside in favor of other factors.
Fourthly, it is confessedly unjust to break faith with any one: to violate an engagement, either express or implied, or disappoint expectations raised by our own conduct, at least if we have raised those expectations knowingly and voluntarily. Like the other obligations of justice already spoken of, this one is not regarded as absolute, but as capable of being overruled by a stronger obligation of justice on the other side; or by such conduct on the part of the person concerned as is deemed to absolve us from our obligation to him, and to constitute a forfeiture of the benefit which he has been led to expect.
Fourthly, it’s clearly unfair to break faith with anyone: to go back on a promise, whether it’s stated or implied, or to let down expectations created by our own actions, especially if we knowingly and voluntarily raised those expectations. Like other justice obligations we've discussed, this one isn't seen as absolute; it can be overridden by a stronger obligation of justice on the other side or by actions taken by the individual in question that are considered to release us from our duty to them and result in a forfeiture of the benefits they were led to expect.
Fifthly, it is, by universal admission, inconsistent with justice to be partial; to show favour or preference to one person over another, in matters to which favour and preference do not properly apply. Impartiality, however, does not seem to be regarded as a duty in itself, but rather as instrumental to some other duty; for it is admitted that favour and preference are not always censurable, and indeed the cases in which they are condemned are rather the exception than the rule. A person would be more likely to be blamed than applauded for giving his family or friends no superiority in good offices over strangers, when he could do so without violating any other duty; and no one thinks it unjust to seek one person in preference to another as a friend, connexion, or companion. Impartiality where rights are concerned is of course obligatory, but this is involved in the more general obligation of giving to every one his right. A tribunal, for example, must be impartial, because it is bound to award, without regard to any other consideration, a disputed object to the one of two parties who has the right to it. There are other cases in which impartiality means, being solely influenced by desert; as with those who, in the capacity of judges, preceptors, or parents, administer reward and punishment as such. There are cases, again, in which it means, being solely influenced by consideration for the public interest; as in making a selection among candidates for a Government employment. Impartiality, in short, as an obligation of justice, may be said to mean, being exclusively influenced by the considerations which it is supposed ought to influence the particular case in hand; and resisting the solicitation of any motives which prompt to conduct different from what those considerations would dictate.
Fifthly, it's universally acknowledged that it's unjust to be partial; to show favoritism or preference for one person over another in situations where such favoritism or preference shouldn't apply. However, impartiality doesn't seem to be seen as a duty in itself but rather as a means to fulfill another duty. It's recognized that favoritism and preference aren't always wrong, and the situations in which they are criticized are more the exception than the rule. People are generally more likely to be criticized than praised for not giving their family or friends any advantage in good deeds over strangers when they could do so without breaking any other duty. No one considers it unjust to choose one person over another as a friend, connection, or companion. When it comes to rights, impartiality is obviously required, but this is part of the broader obligation to give everyone their due. For instance, a court must be impartial because it has to award a disputed object to the party who is right, regardless of any other considerations. There are other instances where impartiality means being solely guided by merit, as with judges, teachers, or parents who administer rewards and punishments. There are also cases where it means being driven solely by the public good, such as when selecting candidates for government jobs. In summary, impartiality as a duty of justice can be understood as being exclusively guided by the factors that should influence the specific case at hand and resisting any motives that would lead to behavior contrary to those guiding factors.
Nearly allied to the idea of impartiality, is that of equality; which often enters as a component part both into the conception of justice and into the practice of it, and, in the eyes of many persons, constitutes its essence. But in this, still more than in any other case, the notion of justice varies in different persons, and always conforms in its variations to their notion of utility. Each person maintains that equality is the dictate of justice, except where he thinks that expediency requires inequality. The justice of giving equal protection to the rights of all, is maintained by those who support the most outrageous inequality in the rights themselves. Even in slave countries it is theoretically admitted that the rights of the slave, such as they are, ought to be as sacred as those of the master; and that a tribunal which fails to enforce them with equal strictness is wanting in justice; while, at the same time, institutions which leave to the slave scarcely any rights to enforce, are not deemed unjust, because they are not deemed inexpedient. Those who think that utility requires distinctions of rank, do not consider it unjust that riches and social privileges should be unequally dispensed; but those who think this inequality inexpedient, think it unjust also. Whoever thinks that government is necessary, sees no injustice in as much inequality as is constituted by giving to the magistrate powers not granted to other people. Even among those who hold levelling doctrines, there are as many questions of justice as there are differences of opinion about expediency. Some Communists consider it unjust that the produce of the labour of the community should be shared on any other principle than that of exact equality; others think it just that those should receive most whose needs are greatest; while others hold that those who work harder, or who produce more, or whose services are more valuable to the community, may justly claim a larger quota in the division of the produce. And the sense of natural justice may be plausibly appealed to in behalf of every one of these opinions.
Almost related to the idea of fairness is the concept of equality; this often plays a role in both the idea of justice and its application, and for many, it represents its core. However, even more so than in other cases, the understanding of justice varies among different people and always aligns with their views on practicality. Each individual insists that equality is a requirement of justice, unless they believe that practical reasons justify inequality. The principle of giving equal protection to everyone’s rights is defended by those who uphold significant inequalities in those rights themselves. Even in societies that permit slavery, it is theoretically acknowledged that the rights of slaves, however limited, should be as respected as those of their masters; and that a court failing to enforce them with equal rigor lacks justice; while, at the same time, institutions that grant slaves hardly any rights are not seen as unjust, simply because they are not viewed as impractical. Those who believe that practicality warrants distinctions in social ranks don’t find it unjust that wealth and social privileges are distributed unequally; however, those who view this inequality as impractical also see it as unjust. Anyone who thinks that government is necessary doesn’t find injustice in the inequality that arises from granting magistrates powers not given to others. Even among those who advocate for equality, there are as many questions about justice as there are different opinions on practicality. Some Communists argue that it’s unjust for the community's labor output to be shared on any basis other than complete equality; others believe it’s fair that those with the greatest needs should receive the most; while some maintain that those who work harder, produce more, or whose services are more valuable to the community should justly receive a larger share of the output. And the idea of natural justice can be convincingly used to support each of these viewpoints.
Among so many diverse applications of the term Justice, which yet is not regarded as ambiguous, it is a matter of some difficulty to seize the mental link which holds them together, and on which the moral sentiment adhering to the term essentially depends. Perhaps, in this embarrassment, some help may be derived from the history of the word, as indicated by its etymology.
Among the many different ways the term Justice is used, which is not seen as unclear, it can be somewhat challenging to identify the mental connection that ties them together, and on which the moral feelings associated with the term fundamentally rely. Perhaps, in this confusion, some insight can be gained from the history of the word, as suggested by its origin.
In most, if not in all languages, the etymology of the word which corresponds to Just, points to an origin connected either with positive law, or with that which was in most cases the primitive form of law-authoritative custom. Justum is a form of jussum, that which has been ordered. Jus is of the same origin. Dichanou comes from dichae, of which the principal meaning, at least in the historical ages of Greece, was a suit at law. Originally, indeed, it meant only the mode or manner of doing things, but it early came to mean the prescribed manner; that which the recognized authorities, patriarchal, judicial, or political, would enforce. Recht, from which came right and righteous, is synonymous with law. The original meaning, indeed, of recht did not point to law, but to physical straightness; as wrong and its Latin equivalents meant twisted or tortuous; and from this it is argued that right did not originally mean law, but on the contrary law meant right. But however this may be, the fact that recht and droit became restricted in their meaning to positive law, although much which is not required by law is equally necessary to moral straightness or rectitude, is as significant of the original character of moral ideas as if the derivation had been the reverse way. The courts of justice, the administration of justice, are the courts and the administration of law. La justice, in French, is the established term for judicature. There can, I think, be no doubt that the idée mère, the primitive element, in the formation of the notion of justice, was conformity to law. It constituted the entire idea among the Hebrews, up to the birth of Christianity; as might be expected in the case of a people whose laws attempted to embrace all subjects on which precepts were required, and who believed those laws to be a direct emanation from the Supreme Being. But other nations, and in particular the Greeks and Romans, who knew that their laws had been made originally, and still continued to be made, by men, were not afraid to admit that those men might make bad laws; might do, by law, the same things, and from the same motives, which, if done by individuals without the sanction of law, would be called unjust. And hence the sentiment of injustice came to be attached, not to all violations of law, but only to violations of such laws as ought to exist, including such as ought to exist but do not; and to laws themselves, if supposed to be contrary to what ought to be law. In this manner the idea of law and of its injunctions was still predominant in the notion of justice, even when the laws actually in force ceased to be accepted as the standard of it.
In almost every language, the origin of the word corresponding to "Just" is connected to either positive law or what was often the original form of law—authoritative custom. Justum is a form of jussum, meaning that which has been ordered. Jus has the same origin. Dichanou comes from dichae, which primarily referred to a legal case in historical Greece. Initially, it simply meant the method or manner of doing things, but it quickly came to mean the prescribed manner that recognized authorities, whether patriarchal, judicial, or political, would enforce. Recht, from which we get right and righteous, is synonymous with law. The original meaning of recht didn't relate to law, but to physical straightness; while wrong and its Latin equivalents signified twisted or tortuous. This leads to the argument that right didn't originally mean law; instead, law meant right. Nonetheless, the fact that recht and droit became limited to positive law, even though much that's not legally required is essential for moral honesty or rectitude, is significant of the original character of moral ideas as if the derivation had been reversed. The courts of justice and the administration of justice refer to the courts and the administration of law. La justice in French is the established term for the judiciary. I believe there is no doubt that the idée mère, the fundamental element in forming the concept of justice, was conformity to law. This concept was the entirety of the idea among the Hebrews up until the birth of Christianity, which makes sense for a people whose laws aimed to cover all subjects requiring precepts and who believed those laws came directly from the Supreme Being. However, other nations, particularly the Greeks and Romans, recognized that their laws were originally created by people, and continued to be created by people, without fear of admitting that those people could create bad laws; they could enact through law the same actions and motives that would be deemed unjust if carried out by individuals without legal sanction. Therefore, the feeling of injustice became linked not to every violation of law, but specifically to violations of laws that ought to exist, including those that should exist but don’t; and to laws themselves if they are believed to contradict what should be considered law. Thus, the idea of law and its mandates remained dominant in the concept of justice, even when the laws currently enforced were no longer seen as the standard for it.
It is true that mankind consider the idea of justice and its obligations as applicable to many things which neither are, nor is it desired that they should be, regulated by law. Nobody desires that laws should interfere with the whole detail of private life; yet every one allows that in all daily conduct a person may and does show himself to be either just or unjust. But even here, the idea of the breach of what ought to be law, still lingers in a modified shape. It would always give us pleasure, and chime in with our feelings of fitness, that acts which we deem unjust should be punished, though we do not always think it expedient that this should be done by the tribunals. We forego that gratification on account of incidental inconveniences. We should be glad to see just conduct enforced and injustice repressed, even in the minutest details, if we were not, with reason, afraid of trusting the magistrate with so unlimited an amount of power over individuals. When we think that a person is bound in justice to do a thing, it is an ordinary form of language to say, that he ought to be compelled to do it. We should be gratified to see the obligation enforced by anybody who had the power. If we see that its enforcement by law would be inexpedient, we lament the impossibility, we consider the impunity given to injustice as an evil, and strive to make amends for it by bringing a strong expression of our own and the public disapprobation to bear upon the offender. Thus the idea of legal constraint is still the generating idea of the notion of justice, though undergoing several transformations before that notion, as it exists in an advanced state of society, becomes complete.
It's true that people see the concept of justice and its responsibilities as relevant to many aspects that should not, and are not desired to be, governed by law. No one wants laws to interfere with every little detail of personal life; yet everyone acknowledges that in everyday actions, a person can show themselves to be either just or unjust. However, even in this context, the idea of violating what should be lawful persists in a modified way. It always makes us feel good and aligns with our sense of what’s right that actions we consider unjust should be punished, even if we don't always think it's practical for the courts to do so. We give up that satisfaction because of potential issues that could arise. We would appreciate seeing just behavior upheld and injustice addressed, even in the smallest details, if we weren't justifiably worried about giving authorities too much power over individuals. When we believe someone has a just obligation to do something, it’s common to say that they should be forced to do it. We would feel pleased to see that obligation enforced by anyone with the authority to do so. If we realize that enforcing it through law wouldn’t be practical, we regret that impossibility, view the lack of accountability for injustice as a problem, and try to remedy it by expressing our strong disapproval, both personally and publicly, towards the wrongdoer. Thus, the idea of legal enforcement remains a foundational element of the concept of justice, even though it undergoes various changes before this concept, as it exists in a more developed society, becomes fully realized.
The above is, I think, a true account, as far as it goes, of the origin and progressive growth of the idea of justice. But we must observe, that it contains, as yet, nothing to distinguish that obligation from moral obligation in general. For the truth is, that the idea of penal sanction, which is the essence of law, enters not only into the conception of injustice, but into that of any kind of wrong. We do not call anything wrong, unless we mean to imply that a person ought to be punished in some way or other for doing it; if not by law, by the opinion of his fellow creatures; if not by opinion, by the reproaches of his own conscience. This seems the real turning point of the distinction between morality and simple expediency. It is a part of the notion of Duty in every one of its forms, that a person may rightfully be compelled to fulfil it. Duty is a thing which may be exacted from a person, as one exacts a debt. Unless we think that it might be exacted from him, we do not call it his duty. Reasons of prudence, or the interest of other people, may militate against actually exacting it; but the person himself, it is clearly understood, would not be entitled to complain. There are other things, on the contrary, which we wish that people should do, which we like or admire them for doing, perhaps dislike or despise them for not doing, but yet admit that they are not bound to do; it is not a case of moral obligation; we do not blame them, that is, we do not think that they are proper objects of punishment. How we come by these ideas of deserving and not deserving punishment, will appear, perhaps, in the sequel; but I think there is no doubt that this distinction lies at the bottom of the notions of right and wrong; that we call any conduct wrong, or employ instead, some other term of dislike or disparagement, according as we think that the person ought, or ought not, to be punished for it; and we say that it would be right to do so and so, or merely that it would be desirable or laudable, according as we would wish to see the person whom it concerns, compelled or only persuaded and exhorted, to act in that manner.[C]
The above is, I think, an accurate account, at least to some extent, of how the idea of justice originated and developed. However, we must note that it still doesn’t differentiate that obligation from moral obligation in general. The truth is, the concept of penal sanction, which is the essence of law, is tied not only to the idea of injustice but also to any kind of wrong. We don’t label something as wrong unless we imply that a person should face some kind of punishment for it; if not by law, then by societal opinion; if not by opinion, then by their own conscience’s reproaches. This seems to be the real turning point in distinguishing between morality and mere self-interest. It’s part of the notion of Duty in all its forms that a person may justifiably be compelled to meet it. Duty is something that can be exacted from someone, just like one would collect a debt. Unless we believe it can be demanded from them, we don’t call it their duty. While reasons of caution or the interests of others might discourage actually enforcing it, the person, it’s clearly understood, wouldn’t have the right to complain. Conversely, there are other things we wish people would do, that we appreciate or admire them for doing, or perhaps dislike or scorn them for not doing, but we acknowledge that they aren’t obligated to do it; it’s not a case of moral obligation; we don’t judge them, meaning we don’t think they should be punished. How we acquire these ideas of deserving and not deserving punishment will become clearer later, but I believe there’s no doubt that this distinction is fundamental to our ideas of right and wrong; we deem any behavior wrong, or we use another term of disapproval, based on whether we think the person should or shouldn’t face punishment for it; and we say it would be right to do this or that, or merely that it would be desirable or commendable, based on whether we want to see the person involved compelled or just encouraged and advised to act that way.[C]
This, therefore, being the characteristic difference which marks off, not justice, but morality in general, from the remaining provinces of Expediency and Worthiness; the character is still to be sought which distinguishes justice from other branches of morality. Now it is known that ethical writers divide moral duties into two classes, denoted by the ill-chosen expressions, duties of perfect and of imperfect obligation; the latter being those in which, though the act is obligatory, the particular occasions of performing it are left to our choice; as in the case of charity or beneficence, which we are indeed bound to practise, but not towards any definite person, nor at any prescribed time. In the more precise language of philosophic jurists, duties of perfect obligation are those duties in virtue of which a correlative right resides in some person or persons; duties of imperfect obligation are those moral obligations which do not give birth to any right. I think it will be found that this distinction exactly coincides with that which exists between justice and the other obligations of morality. In our survey of the various popular acceptations of justice, the term appeared generally to involve the idea of a personal right—a claim on the part of one or more individuals, like that which the law gives when it confers a proprietary or other legal right. Whether the injustice consists in depriving a person of a possession, or in breaking faith with him, or in treating him worse than he deserves, or worse than other people who have no greater claims, in each case the supposition implies two things—a wrong done, and some assignable person who is wronged. Injustice may also be done by treating a person better than others; but the wrong in this case is to his competitors, who are also assignable persons. It seems to me that this feature in the case—a right in some person, correlative to the moral obligation—constitutes the specific difference between justice, and generosity or beneficence. Justice implies something which it is not only right to do, and wrong not to do, but which some individual person can claim from us as his moral right. No one has a moral right to our generosity or beneficence, because we are not morally bound to practise those virtues towards any given individual. And it will be found, with respect to this as with respect to every correct definition, that the instances which seem to conflict with it are those which most confirm it. For if a moralist attempts, as some have done, to make out that mankind generally, though not any given individual, have a right to all the good we can do them, he at once, by that thesis, includes generosity and beneficence within the category of justice. He is obliged to say, that our utmost exertions are due to our fellow creatures, thus assimilating them to a debt; or that nothing less can be a sufficient return for what society does for us, thus classing the case as one of gratitude; both of which are acknowledged cases of justice. Wherever there is a right, the case is one of justice, and not of the virtue of beneficence: and whoever does not place the distinction between justice and morality in general where we have now placed it, will be found to make no distinction between them at all, but to merge all morality in justice.
This is the key difference that sets apart not just justice, but morality as a whole, from the other areas of Expediency and Worthiness. We still need to identify what distinguishes justice from other aspects of morality. It is known that ethical writers categorize moral duties into two types, referred to with the awkward terms duties of perfect and imperfect obligation. The latter refers to situations where the action is necessary, but the specific times to carry it out are up to us; for example, our obligation to be charitable or to help others, which we should practice, but not toward any specific person or at any set time. In clearer terms used by legal theorists, duties of perfect obligation are those that create a corresponding right in someone, while duties of imperfect obligation do not give rise to any such right. This distinction matches precisely with the difference between justice and other moral obligations. In our examination of how justice is generally understood, the term often suggests a personal right—a claim from one or more individuals similar to the legal rights granted by the law. Whether injustice involves taking away someone's possessions, breaking a promise to someone, or treating a person worse than they deserve or worse than others who have no greater claims, each situation implies two things: a wrong that has been done, and a specific individual who has been wronged. Injustice can also occur by treating someone better than others; however, the wrong in this case is committed against their competitors, who are also identifiable individuals. It seems to me that this characteristic—a right that belongs to some person, connected to the moral obligation—defines the key difference between justice and generosity or kindness. Justice involves something that it is not just right to do and wrong not to do, but which an individual can claim from us as their moral right. No one has a moral right to our generosity or kindness because we are not morally required to extend those virtues to any particular individual. In relation to this, just like with any accurate definition, the examples that appear to contradict it actually reinforce it. For instance, if a moralist argues, as some do, that humanity as a whole, but not any specific individual, has a right to all our good deeds, they inadvertently place generosity and kindness under justice. They are compelled to claim that our greatest efforts are owed to our fellow humans, making it akin to a debt; or that nothing less can adequately repay what society does for us, putting this scenario in the realm of gratitude—both recognized forms of justice. Wherever there is a right, the matter is one of justice, not merely of the virtue of kindness. Anyone who does not recognize the distinction between justice and general morality as we have outlined will likely fail to see any difference between them and will instead merge all morality into justice.
Having thus endeavoured to determine the distinctive elements which enter into the composition of the idea of justice, we are ready to enter on the inquiry, whether the feeling, which accompanies the idea, is attached to it by a special dispensation of nature, or whether it could have grown up, by any known laws, out of the idea itself; and in particular, whether it can have originated in considerations of general expediency.
Having worked to identify the unique elements that make up the idea of justice, we are now prepared to explore whether the emotion that comes with this idea is a result of a special design of nature, or if it could have developed, through any known principles, from the idea itself; and specifically, if it might have originated from considerations of overall usefulness.
I conceive that the sentiment itself does not arise from anything which would commonly, or correctly, be termed an idea of expediency; but that, though the sentiment does not, whatever is moral in it does.
I believe that the feeling itself doesn’t come from anything that would usually or accurately be called a practical idea; however, while the feeling doesn’t, everything that is moral about it does.
We have seen that the two essential ingredients in the sentiment of justice are, the desire to punish a person who has done harm, and the knowledge or belief that there is some definite individual or individuals to whom harm has been done.
We have seen that the two key elements in the feeling of justice are the desire to punish someone who has caused harm and the understanding or belief that there is a specific person or people who have been harmed.
Now it appears to me, that the desire to punish a person who has done harm to some individual, is a spontaneous outgrowth from two sentiments, both in the highest degree natural, and which either are or resemble instincts; the impulse of self-defence, and the feeling of sympathy.
Now it seems to me that the urge to punish someone who has harmed another person comes from two very natural feelings, which are either instincts or similar to them: the instinct of self-defense and the feeling of sympathy.
It is natural to resent, and to repel or retaliate, any harm done or attempted against ourselves, or against those with whom we sympathize. The origin of this sentiment it is not necessary here to discuss. Whether it be an instinct or a result of intelligence, it is, we know, common to all animal nature; for every animal tries to hurt those who have hurt, or who it thinks are about to hurt, itself or its young. Human beings, on this point, only differ from other animals in two particulars. First, in being capable of sympathizing, not solely with their offspring, or, like some of the more noble animals, with some superior animal who is kind to them, but with all human, and even with all sentient beings. Secondly, in having a more developed intelligence, which gives a wider range to the whole of their sentiments, whether self-regarding or sympathetic. By virtue of his superior intelligence, even apart from his superior range of sympathy, a human being is capable of apprehending a community of interest between himself and the human society of which he forms a part, such that any conduct which threatens the security of the society generally, is threatening to his own, and calls forth his instinct (if instinct it be) of self-defence. The same superiority of intelligence, joined to the power of sympathizing with human beings generally, enables him to attach himself to the collective idea of his tribe, his country, or mankind, in such a manner that any act hurtful to them rouses his instinct of sympathy, and urges him to resistance.
It's natural to feel resentment and to push back or retaliate against any harm done or attempted against us, or against those we care about. We don't need to discuss where this feeling comes from. Whether it’s an instinct or a result of intelligence, we know it’s common across all animals; every animal tries to hurt those who have harmed them or who they believe are about to hurt them or their young. Humans differ from other animals in two main ways. First, we can empathize not just with our own offspring or, like some noble animals, with superior beings who are kind to us, but with all humans and even all sentient beings. Second, we have a more developed intelligence, which gives our feelings—both self-centered and empathetic—a broader range. Thanks to our superior intelligence, even apart from our wider capacity for empathy, we can understand a shared interest with the human society we are part of. Thus, any actions that threaten the safety of society as a whole also threaten our own safety and trigger our instinct (if it is indeed an instinct) for self-defense. This same intelligence, combined with the ability to empathize with all humans, allows us to connect deeply with the collective idea of our tribe, country, or humanity as a whole, so that any harmful action toward them stirs our empathy and motivates us to resist.
The sentiment of justice, in that one of its elements which consists of the desire to punish, is thus, I conceive, the natural feeling of retaliation or vengeance, rendered by intellect and sympathy applicable to those injuries, that is, to those hurts, which wound us through, or in common with, society at large. This sentiment, in itself, has nothing moral in it; what is moral is, the exclusive subordination of it to the social sympathies, so as to wait on and obey their call. For the natural feeling tends to make us resent indiscriminately whatever any one does that is disagreeable to us; but when moralized by the social feeling, it only acts in the directions conformable to the general good; just persons resenting a hurt to society, though not otherwise a hurt to themselves, and not resenting a hurt to themselves, however painful, unless it be of the kind which society has a common interest with them in the repression of.
The feeling of justice, particularly in its desire to punish, is, I believe, a natural instinct of retaliation or revenge, shaped by our intellect and empathy to respond to those injuries that affect us or society as a whole. This feeling, on its own, isn’t moral; what is moral is its alignment with social empathy, meaning it waits for and follows their guidance. The natural instinct might make us react negatively to anything we find unpleasant, but when it is guided by our social instincts, it only acts in ways that benefit the greater good. Just people will respond to a harm done to society, even if it doesn’t directly hurt them, and they won’t react to personal harm, no matter how painful, unless it involves something that society collectively cares about suppressing.
It is no objection against this doctrine to say, that when we feel our sentiment of justice outraged, we are not thinking of society at large, or of any collective interest, but only of the individual case. It is common enough certainly, though the reverse of commendable, to feel resentment merely because we have suffered pain; but a person whose resentment is really a moral feeling, that is, who considers whether an act is blameable before he allows himself to resent it—such a person, though he may not say expressly to himself that he is standing up for the interest of society, certainly does feel that he is asserting a rule which is for the benefit of others as well as for his own. If he is not feeling this—if he is regarding the act solely as it affects him individually—he is not consciously just; he is not concerning himself about the justice of his actions. This is admitted even by anti-utilitarian moralists. When Kant (as before remarked) propounds as the fundamental principle of morals, 'So act, that thy rule of conduct might be adopted as a law by all rational beings,' he virtually acknowledges that the interest of mankind collectively, or at least of mankind indiscriminately, must be in the mind of the agent when conscientiously deciding on the morality of the act. Otherwise he uses words without a meaning: for, that a rule even of utter selfishness could not possibly be adopted by all rational beings—that there is any insuperable obstacle in the nature of things to its adoption—cannot be even plausibly maintained. To give any meaning to Kant's principle, the sense put upon it must be, that we ought to shape our conduct by a rule which all rational beings might adopt with benefit to their collective interest.
It’s not a valid argument against this idea to say that when we feel our sense of justice is violated, we aren’t thinking about society as a whole or any collective interest, but only about the specific situation. It’s quite common, though not admirable, to feel resentment simply because we’ve been hurt; however, a person whose resentment is genuinely a moral reaction—someone who considers whether an action is wrong before allowing themselves to feel resentful—such a person, even if they don’t explicitly think of it as standing up for society’s interest, definitely feels that they are advocating for a rule that benefits others just as much as themselves. If they aren’t feeling this—if they view the action only in relation to how it affects them personally—they aren’t being consciously just; they aren’t reflecting on the justice of their actions. This is something even anti-utilitarian moralists agree on. When Kant states, as noted before, the fundamental principle of morals, “Act in such a way that your rule of conduct could be a law for all rational beings,” he is essentially acknowledging that the interests of humanity collectively, or at least indiscriminately, must be in the mind of the person when they carefully evaluate the morality of an action. Otherwise, he is using words that lack meaning: the idea that a rule based purely on selfishness could ever be adopted by all rational beings—that there is an insurmountable barrier to its adoption in the nature of things—can’t even be argued convincingly. To give any meaning to Kant’s principle, it must be understood that we should shape our behavior by a rule that all rational beings could adopt with benefits to their collective interest.
To recapitulate: the idea of justice supposes two things; a rule of conduct, and a sentiment which sanctions the rule. The first must be supposed common to all mankind, and intended for their good. The other (the sentiment) is a desire that punishment may be suffered by those who infringe the rule. There is involved, in addition, the conception of some definite person who suffers by the infringement; whose rights (to use the expression appropriated to the case) are violated by it. And the sentiment of justice appears to me to be, the animal desire to repel or retaliate a hurt or damage to oneself, or to those with whom one sympathizes, widened so as to include all persons, by the human capacity of enlarged sympathy, and the human conception of intelligent self-interest. From the latter elements, the feeling derives its morality; from the former, its peculiar impressiveness, and energy of self-assertion.
To sum up: the concept of justice includes two things: a rule of behavior and a feeling that supports that rule. The first should be understood as common to all humanity and aimed at their welfare. The second (the feeling) is the wish that those who break the rule should face consequences. Additionally, there’s the idea of a specific individual who suffers because of the violation; their rights (using a term specific to this situation) are being infringed upon. The sentiment of justice appears to me as a natural urge to push back against or retaliate for harm done to oneself or to those one cares about, expanded to include everyone through our human ability for broader empathy and an understanding of rational self-interest. From these factors, the feeling gains its ethical dimension; from the former, it gets its unique significance and assertive power.
I have, throughout, treated the idea of a right residing in the injured person, and violated by the injury, not as a separate element in the composition of the idea and sentiment, but as one of the forms in which the other two elements clothe themselves. These elements are, a hurt to some assignable person or persons on the one hand, and a demand for punishment on the other. An examination of our own minds, I think, will show, that these two things include all that we mean when we speak of violation of a right. When we call anything a person's right, we mean that he has a valid claim on society to protect him in the possession of it, either by the force of law, or by that of education and opinion. If he has what we consider a sufficient claim, on whatever account, to have something guaranteed to him by society, we say that he has a right to it. If we desire to prove that anything does not belong to him by right, we think this done as soon as it is admitted that society ought not to take measures for securing it to him, but should leave it to chance, or to his own exertions. Thus, a person is said to have a right to what he can earn in fair professional competition; because society ought not to allow any other person to hinder him from endeavouring to earn in that manner as much as he can. But he has not a right to three hundred a-year, though he may happen to be earning it; because society is not called on to provide that he shall earn that sum. On the contrary, if he owns ten thousand pounds three per cent. stock, he has a right to three hundred a-year; because society has come under an obligation to provide him with an income of that amount.
I have always viewed the idea of a right belonging to the person who was harmed, and violated by the injury, not as a distinct part of the concept and feeling, but as one of the ways the other two elements express themselves. These elements are a harm to a specific individual or individuals on one side, and a demand for punishment on the other. I believe that examining our own thoughts will show that these two things cover everything we mean when we refer to a violation of a right. When we label something as a person's right, we're saying that they have a legitimate claim on society to protect their possession of it, whether through the force of law or through education and public opinion. If they have what we consider a sufficient claim for society to guarantee something to them, we say that they have a right to it. If we want to argue that something doesn’t rightfully belong to them, we think that’s established as soon as we agree that society shouldn’t take steps to ensure they receive it, but should leave it to chance or their own efforts. For example, a person is said to have a right to what they can earn in fair professional competition because society should not allow others to stop them from trying to earn as much as they can in that way. However, they do not have a right to an income of three hundred a year, even if they are currently making that amount, because society is not obligated to ensure they earn that figure. In contrast, if they own ten thousand pounds worth of three percent stock, they have a right to three hundred a year because society has taken on the obligation to provide them with that income.
To have a right, then, is, I conceive, to have something which society ought to defend me in the possession of. If the objector goes on to ask why it ought, I can give him no other reason than general utility. If that expression does not seem to convey a sufficient feeling of the strength of the obligation, nor to account for the peculiar energy of the feeling, it is because there goes to the composition of the sentiment, not a rational only but also an animal element, the thirst for retaliation; and this thirst derives its intensity, as well as its moral justification, from the extraordinarily important and impressive kind of utility which is concerned. The interest involved is that of security, to every one's feelings the most vital of all interests. Nearly all other earthly benefits are needed by one person, not needed by another; and many of them can, if necessary, be cheerfully foregone, or replaced by something else; but security no human being can possibly do without; on it we depend for all our immunity from evil, and for the whole value of all and every good, beyond the passing moment; since nothing but the gratification of the instant could be of any worth to us, if we could be deprived of everything the next instant by whoever was momentarily stronger than ourselves. Now this most indispensable of all necessaries, after physical nutriment, cannot be had, unless the machinery for providing it is kept unintermittedly in active play. Our notion, therefore, of the claim we have on our fellow creatures to join in making safe for us the very groundwork of our existence, gathers feelings round it so much more intense than those concerned in any of the more common cases of utility, that the difference in degree (as is often the case in psychology) becomes a real difference in kind. The claim assumes that character of absoluteness, that apparent infinity, and incommensurability with all other considerations, which constitute the distinction between the feeling of right and wrong and that of ordinary expediency and inexpediency. The feelings concerned are so powerful, and we count so positively on finding a responsive feeling in others (all being alike interested), that ought and should grow into must, and recognized indispensability becomes a moral necessity, analogous to physical, and often not inferior to it in binding force.
To have a right means, I believe, to have something that society should protect for me. If someone asks why it should, I have no other answer than that it benefits everyone. If that phrase doesn’t seem to fully capture the strength of the obligation or the unique intensity of the feeling, it’s because this sentiment isn’t only rational; it also includes a primal element—an urge for revenge. This urge gains its intensity and moral justification from the extremely important type of benefit involved. The interest at stake is security, which is the most vital of all interests for everyone. Most other earthly goods might be important to one person but not to another; many of them can be willingly sacrificed or replaced. But no one can live without security; we rely on it for our protection from harm and for the overall value of everything good we have, beyond the present moment. Without security, only instant gratification would hold any value for us, as we could be stripped of everything in the next moment by someone stronger. This essential need for security, after physical nourishment, can’t be met unless the systems in place to provide it are constantly maintained. Our belief in our right to ask others to help keep the very foundation of our existence safe generates feelings that are much more intense than those related to everyday benefits, creating a real difference in nature. This claim possesses a kind of absolute quality, an apparent infinity, and cannot be weighed against other considerations, which distinguishes the feeling of right and wrong from that of ordinary practicality. The emotions involved are so strong, and we trust that others will share this feeling (since we all have the same interest), that what we say we “ought” to do becomes a “must,” and this recognized necessity turns into a moral obligation, comparable to physical needs, often with equal binding force.
If the preceding analysis, or something resembling it, be not the correct account of the notion of justice; if justice be totally independent of utility, and be a standard per se, which the mind can recognize by simple introspection of itself; it is hard to understand why that internal oracle is so ambiguous, and why so many things appear either just or unjust, according to the light in which they are regarded. We are continually informed that Utility is an uncertain standard, which every different person interprets differently, and that there is no safety but in the immutable, ineffaceable, and unmistakeable dictates of Justice, which carry their evidence in themselves, and are independent of the fluctuations of opinion. One would suppose from this that on questions of justice there could be no controversy; that if we take that for our rule, its application to any given case could leave us in as little doubt as a mathematical demonstration. So far is this from being the fact, that there is as much difference of opinion, and as fierce discussion, about what is just, as about what is useful to society. Not only have different nations and individuals different notions of justice, but, in the mind of one and the same individual, justice is not some one rule, principle, or maxim, but many, which do not always coincide in their dictates, and in choosing between which, he is guided either by some extraneous standard, or by his own personal predilections.
If the previous analysis, or something like it, isn't the right explanation of justice; if justice exists completely apart from utility and is a standard per se, which the mind can recognize through simple introspection; it’s hard to see why that internal guide is so unclear, and why so many things seem either just or unjust, depending on how they're viewed. We're constantly told that utility is an unreliable standard, interpreted differently by everyone, and that the only reliable source is the unchanging, clear, and unmistakable principles of justice, which carry their own proof and aren’t swayed by public opinion. One would think that on matters of justice, there would be no debate; that if we use that as our guideline, its application to any specific case would leave us as certain as a math proof. This is far from the truth, as there is just as much disagreement and intense debate about what is just as there is about what benefits society. Not only do different countries and individuals have different views of justice, but even within the same person, justice isn’t just one rule, principle, or maxim; it’s many, which don’t always agree with one another, and when choosing between them, a person is guided either by some outside standard or by their own personal preferences.
For instance, there are some who say, that it is unjust to punish any one for the sake of example to others; that punishment is just, only when intended for the good of the sufferer himself. Others maintain the extreme reverse, contending that to punish persons who have attained years of discretion, for their own benefit, is despotism and injustice, since if the matter at issue is solely their own good, no one has a right to control their own judgment of it; but that they may justly be punished to prevent evil to others, this being an exercise of the legitimate right of self-defence. Mr. Owen, again, affirms that it is unjust to punish at all; for the criminal did not make his own character; his education, and the circumstances which surround him, have made him a criminal, and for these he is not responsible. All these opinions are extremely plausible; and so long as the question is argued as one of justice simply, without going down to the principles which lie under justice and are the source of its authority, I am unable to see how any of these reasoners can be refuted. For, in truth, every one of the three builds upon rules of justice confessedly true. The first appeals to the acknowledged injustice of singling out an individual, and making him a sacrifice, without his consent, for other people's benefit. The second relies on the acknowledged justice of self-defence, and the admitted injustice of forcing one person to conform to another's notions of what constitutes his good. The Owenite invokes the admitted principle, that it is unjust to punish any one for what he cannot help. Each is triumphant so long as he is not compelled to take into consideration any other maxims of justice than the one he has selected; but as soon as their several maxims are brought face to face, each disputant seems to have exactly as much to say for himself as the others. No one of them can carry out his own notion of justice without trampling upon another equally binding. These are difficulties; they have always been felt to be such; and many devices have been invented to turn rather than to overcome them. As a refuge from the last of the three, men imagined what they called the freedom of the will; fancying that they could not justify punishing a man whose will is in a thoroughly hateful state, unless it be supposed to have come into that state through no influence of anterior circumstances. To escape from the other difficulties, a favourite contrivance has been the fiction of a contract, whereby at some unknown period all the members of society engaged to obey the laws, and consented to be punished for any disobedience to them; thereby giving to their legislators the right, which it is assumed they would not otherwise have had, of punishing them, either for their own good or for that of society. This happy thought was considered to get rid of the whole difficulty, and to legitimate the infliction of punishment, in virtue of another received maxim of justice, volenti non fit injuria; that is not unjust which is done with the consent of the person who is supposed to be hurt by it. I need hardly remark, that even if the consent were not a mere fiction, this maxim is not superior in authority to the others which it is brought in to supersede. It is, on the contrary, an instructive specimen of the loose and irregular manner in which supposed principles of justice grow up. This particular one evidently came into use as a help to the coarse exigencies of courts of law, which are sometimes obliged to be content with very uncertain presumptions, on account of the greater evils which would often arise from any attempt on their part to cut finer. But even courts of law are not able to adhere consistently to the maxim, for they allow voluntary engagements to be set aside on the ground of fraud, and sometimes on that of mere mistake or misinformation.
For example, some people argue that it’s unfair to punish someone just to set an example for others; that punishment is only justified when it’s meant to benefit the person being punished. Others argue the opposite, claiming that punishing mature individuals for their own good is a form of tyranny and injustice since, if the issue is purely about their own welfare, no one has the right to control their judgment. However, they can justly be punished to prevent harm to others, which is seen as a legitimate exercise of self-defense. Mr. Owen, meanwhile, asserts that punishing anyone is unjust because the criminal didn’t create their own character; their upbringing and circumstances have shaped them into a criminal, and they aren’t to blame for that. All these views sound quite reasonable, and as long as the debate focuses on justice alone, without exploring the underlying principles that support it and provide its authority, I can’t see how any of these arguments can be disproven. In truth, each of the three relies on accepted rules of justice. The first highlights the recognized injustice of targeting an individual and making them a sacrifice, without their consent, for the benefit of others. The second relies on the well-accepted idea of self-defense and the acknowledged injustice of forcing one person to adhere to another's view of what constitutes their good. The Owenite appeals to the accepted principle that it’s unjust to punish someone for something beyond their control. Each of them seems to win as long as they don't have to consider any other principles of justice than the one they've chosen; but as soon as their various principles are put against each other, it becomes clear that each debater has as strong a case as the others. None of them can fully uphold their own concept of justice without violating another equally valid principle. These are challenges that have always been recognized as such, and many strategies have been devised to navigate rather than resolve them. To sidestep the last of the three challenges, people imagined something called free will, believing that they could only justify punishing someone whose will is completely corrupt if they assume it reached that state without any prior influences. To tackle the other challenges, a common solution has been the idea of a social contract, where, at some unknown time, all members of society agreed to follow the laws and consented to face punishment for any disobedience, thus granting their lawmakers the right to punish them, either for their own good or for the benefit of society. This clever notion was thought to resolve the entire dilemma and legitimize punishment based on another accepted principle of justice, volenti non fit injuria; that is, it’s not unjust if the person who is supposedly harmed consents to it. I should mention that even if consent weren’t a mere fiction, this principle isn’t more authoritative than the others it’s intended to replace. Instead, it’s a clear example of how supposed principles of justice can emerge in a loose and irregular fashion. This specific principle likely came into existence as a response to the practical needs of courts of law, which sometimes have to rely on uncertain assumptions due to the greater harms that could arise from attempting to be more precise. Yet even courts of law struggle to consistently uphold this principle, allowing voluntary agreements to be voided due to fraud, and sometimes even due to simple mistakes or misinformation.
Again, when the legitimacy of inflicting punishment is admitted, how many conflicting conceptions of justice come to light in discussing the proper apportionment of punishment to offences. No rule on this subject recommends itself so strongly to the primitive and spontaneous sentiment of justice, as the lex talionis, an eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth. Though this principle of the Jewish and of the Mahomedan law has been generally abandoned in Europe as a practical maxim, there is, I suspect, in most minds, a secret hankering after it; and when retribution accidentally falls on an offender in that precise shape, the general feeling of satisfaction evinced, bears witness how natural is the sentiment to which this repayment in kind is acceptable. With many the test of justice in penal infliction is that the punishment should be proportioned to the offence; meaning that it should be exactly measured by the moral guilt of the culprit (whatever be their standard for measuring moral guilt): the consideration, what amount of punishment is necessary to deter from the offence, having nothing to do with the question of justice, in their estimation: while there are others to whom that consideration is all in all; who maintain that it is not just, at least for man, to inflict on a fellow creature, whatever may be his offences, any amount of suffering beyond the least that will suffice to prevent him from repeating, and others from imitating, his misconduct.
Again, when we accept that punishment can be justified, many conflicting ideas about justice emerge when we discuss how to appropriately assign punishment for offenses. No rule on this topic resonates more with our basic and instinctive sense of justice than the lex talionis, an eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth. Although this principle from Jewish and Islamic law has mostly been set aside in Europe as a practical guideline, I suspect that many people secretly long for it; and when retribution happens to be delivered in that exact form, the widespread sense of satisfaction that follows shows how natural this desire for direct repayment is. For many, the measure of justice in punishment is that it should match the offense, meaning it should be precisely aligned with the moral guilt of the offender (regardless of the criteria they use to assess moral guilt): the idea of how much punishment is needed to deter future offenses is unconnected to their view of justice. Meanwhile, others prioritize that deterrent effect above all else, arguing that it's unjust for a person to endure any more suffering than what is necessary to prevent them from repeating their actions, and to stop others from copying their behavior.
To take another example from a subject already once referred to. In a co-operative industrial association, is it just or not that talent or skill should give a title to superior remuneration? On the negative side of the question it is argued, that whoever does the best he can, deserves equally well, and ought not in justice to be put in a position of inferiority for no fault of his own; that superior abilities have already advantages more than enough, in the admiration they excite, the personal influence they command, and the internal sources of satisfaction attending them, without adding to these a superior share of the world's goods; and that society is bound in justice rather to make compensation to the less favoured, for this unmerited inequality of advantages, than to aggravate it. On the contrary side it is contended, that society receives more from the more efficient labourer; that his services being more useful, society owes him a larger return for them; that a greater share of the joint result is actually his work, and not to allow his claim to it is a kind of robbery; that if he is only to receive as much as others, he can only be justly required to produce as much, and to give a smaller amount of time and exertion, proportioned to his superior efficiency. Who shall decide between these appeals to conflicting principles of justice? Justice has in this case two sides to it, which it is impossible to bring into harmony, and the two disputants have chosen opposite sides; the one looks to what it is just that the individual should receive, the other to what it is just that the community should give. Each, from his own point of view, is unanswerable; and any choice between them, on grounds of justice, must be perfectly arbitrary. Social utility alone can decide the preference.
To take another example from a subject we've already discussed. In a cooperative industrial association, is it fair or not that talent or skill should lead to higher pay? On the negative side of the argument, it is claimed that anyone who does their best deserves equal treatment and shouldn’t be unfairly placed in a lower position through no fault of their own; that exceptional abilities already have plenty of advantages, like the admiration they receive, the influence they have, and the personal satisfaction that comes with them, without needing a larger share of wealth; and that society should justly compensate those who are less fortunate for this unearned inequality of advantages rather than making it worse. On the other side, it is argued that society benefits more from the more efficient worker; that since their services are more valuable, society owes them a greater return; that a larger portion of the collective output is their contribution, and not recognizing this claim is a kind of theft; that if they are only going to earn what others do, they can only be fairly expected to produce at the same level and can afford to put in less time and effort relative to their greater efficiency. Who gets to decide between these conflicting principles of justice? Justice here has two sides that can’t be reconciled, and the two disputants are on opposite sides; one focuses on what is fair for the individual to receive, while the other considers what is fair for the community to provide. Each is correct from their own perspective, and any choice between them based on justice is entirely arbitrary. Only social utility can determine the preference.
How many, again, and how irreconcileable, are the standards of justice to which reference is made in discussing the repartition of taxation. One opinion is, that payment to the State should be in numerical proportion to pecuniary means. Others think that justice dictates what they term graduated taxation; taking a higher percentage from those who have more to spare. In point of natural justice a strong case might be made for disregarding means altogether, and taking the same absolute sum (whenever it could be got) from every one: as the subscribers to a mess, or to a club, all pay the same sum for the same privileges, whether they can all equally afford it or not. Since the protection (it might be said) of law and government is afforded to, and is equally required by, all, there is no injustice in making all buy it at the same price. It is reckoned justice, not injustice, that a dealer should charge to all customers the same price for the same article, not a price varying according to their means of payment. This doctrine, as applied to taxation, finds no advocates, because it conflicts strongly with men's feelings of humanity and perceptions of social expediency; but the principle of justice which it invokes is as true and as binding as those which can be appealed to against it. Accordingly, it exerts a tacit influence on the line of defence employed for other modes of assessing taxation. People feel obliged to argue that the State does more for the rich than for the poor, as a justification for its taking more from them: though this is in reality not true, for the rich would be far better able to protect themselves, in the absence of law or government, than the poor, and indeed would probably be successful in converting the poor into their slaves. Others, again, so far defer to the same conception of justice, as to maintain that all should pay an equal capitation tax for the protection of their persons (these being of equal value to all), and an unequal tax for the protection of their property, which is unequal. To this others reply, that the all of one man is as valuable to him as the all of another. From these confusions there is no other mode of extrication than the utilitarian.
How many, and how irreconcilable, are the standards of justice referred to when discussing the distribution of taxes. One viewpoint is that payment to the State should be proportional to financial resources. Others argue that fairness requires what they call graduated taxation, taking a higher percentage from those who have more. In terms of natural justice, a strong argument could be made for disregarding financial means altogether and requiring the same fixed amount (whenever possible) from everyone, like members of a club who all pay the same fee for the same benefits, regardless of their ability to pay. Since the protection of law and government is provided to, and is equally necessary for, everyone, there is no injustice in having everyone pay the same price for it. It's generally accepted as fair, not unfair, for a seller to charge all customers the same price for the same item, rather than pricing it according to their ability to pay. This idea, when applied to taxes, has no supporters because it clashes with people's sense of humanity and social necessity; however, the principle of justice it appeals to is as valid and compelling as those that can be used against it. Therefore, it subtly influences the defense strategies used for other ways of assessing taxes. People feel compelled to argue that the State provides more for the wealthy than for the poor as a justification for taking more from them: although this isn't actually true, since the wealthy would be much better equipped to protect themselves without law or government than the poor, and could likely succeed in forcing the poor into servitude. Others, meanwhile, align with this same idea of justice, suggesting that everyone should pay the same head tax for the protection of their own lives (which are equally valuable to all), and a varied tax for the protection of their assets, which are not equal. To this, some respond that what one person possesses is as valuable to him as what another has. From these muddles, there is no other way to resolve it than through a utilitarian approach.
Is, then, the difference between the Just and the Expedient a merely imaginary distinction? Have mankind been under a delusion in thinking that justice is a more sacred thing than policy, and that the latter ought only to be listened to after the former has been satisfied? By no means. The exposition we have given of the nature and origin of the sentiment, recognises a real distinction; and no one of those who profess the most sublime contempt for the consequences of actions as an element in their morality, attaches more importance to the distinction than I do. While I dispute the pretensions of any theory which sets up an imaginary standard of justice not grounded on utility, I account the justice which is grounded on utility to be the chief part, and incomparably the most sacred and binding part, of all morality. Justice is a name for certain classes of moral rules, which concern the essentials of human well-being more nearly, and are therefore of more absolute obligation, than any other rules for the guidance of life; and the notion which we have found to be of the essence of the idea of justice, that of a right residing in an individual, implies and testifies to this more binding obligation.
Is the difference between what is Just and what is Expedient just a made-up distinction? Have people been misled into thinking that justice is a more sacred concept than policy, and that policy should only be considered after justice has been fulfilled? Absolutely not. Our explanation of the nature and origin of this sentiment acknowledges a real distinction; and no one who claims to have a lofty disdain for the consequences of actions in their moral reasoning values that distinction more than I do. While I challenge any theory that proposes an unrealistic standard of justice not based on utility, I consider the justice that is based on utility to be the most important and undeniably the most sacred and binding aspect of morality. Justice represents certain categories of moral rules that relate more closely to the essentials of human well-being and are therefore of greater obligation than any other guidelines for living; and the idea that we have identified as central to the concept of justice—the idea of an individual's right—demonstrates this stronger obligation.
The moral rules which forbid mankind to hurt one another (in which we must never forget to include wrongful interference with each other's freedom) are more vital to human well-being than any maxims, however important, which only point out the best mode of managing some department of human affairs. They have also the peculiarity, that they are the main element in determining the whole of the social feelings of mankind. It is their observance which alone preserves peace among human beings: if obedience to them were not the rule, and disobedience the exception, every one would see in every one else a probable enemy, against whom he must be perpetually guarding himself. What is hardly less important, these are the precepts which mankind have the strongest and the most direct inducements for impressing upon one another. By merely giving to each other prudential instruction or exhortation, they may gain, or think they gain, nothing: in inculcating on each other the duty of positive beneficence they have an unmistakeable interest, but far less in degree: a person may possibly not need the benefits of others; but he always needs that they should not do him hurt. Thus the moralities which protect every individual from being harmed by others, either directly or by being hindered in his freedom of pursuing his own good, are at once those which he himself has most at heart, and those which he has the strongest interest in publishing and enforcing by word and deed. It is by a person's observance of these, that his fitness to exist as one of the fellowship of human beings, is tested and decided; for on that depends his being a nuisance or not to those with whom he is in contact. Now it is these moralities primarily, which compose the obligations of justice. The most marked cases of injustice, and those which give the tone to the feeling of repugnance which characterizes the sentiment, are acts of wrongful aggression, or wrongful exercise of power over some one; the next are those which consist in wrongfully withholding from him something which is his due; in both cases, inflicting on him a positive hurt, either in the form of direct suffering, or of the privation of some good which he had reasonable ground, either of a physical or of a social kind, for counting upon.
The moral rules that prevent people from hurting each other (which must include any wrongful interference with each other's freedom) are essential for human well-being, more so than any principles that merely suggest the best ways to handle specific aspects of human life. They also uniquely shape the overall social feelings of humanity. Following these rules is what keeps peace among people: if obeying them weren’t the norm and disobeying them the exception, everyone would see others as potential threats needing constant vigilance. Just as important, these are the guidelines that people have the strongest motivation to teach one another. By simply giving each other practical advice or encouragement, they might gain nothing or believe they gain nothing. But by instilling the obligation of doing good for each other, they have a clear interest, albeit less so: someone might not need the help of others, but they always need others not to cause them harm. Therefore, the moral guidelines that protect each individual from being harmed by others, either directly or by restricting their freedom to pursue their own happiness, are those that matter most to them and those they have the greatest interest in promoting and enforcing through words and actions. A person's adherence to these guidelines determines their ability to coexist with others; it affects whether they are seen as a nuisance by those they interact with. These moral guidelines form the foundation of justice obligations. The clearest examples of injustice, which evoke a strong feeling of repulsion, are acts of wrongful aggression or the wrongful use of power over someone. The next category includes wrongfully denying someone something that rightfully belongs to them, resulting in a real harm, either through direct suffering or the loss of a benefit they reasonably expected, whether physical or social.
The same powerful motives which command the observance of these primary moralities, enjoin the punishment of those who violate them; and as the impulses of self-defence, of defence of others, and of vengeance, are all called forth against such persons, retribution, or evil for evil, becomes closely connected with the sentiment of justice, and is universally included in the idea. Good for good is also one of the dictates of justice; and this, though its social utility is evident, and though it carries with it a natural human feeling, has not at first sight that obvious connexion with hurt or injury, which, existing in the most elementary cases of just and unjust, is the source of the characteristic intensity of the sentiment. But the connexion, though less obvious, is not less real. He who accepts benefits, and denies a return of them when needed, inflicts a real hurt, by disappointing one of the most natural and reasonable of expectations, and one which he must at least tacitly have encouraged, otherwise the benefits would seldom have been conferred. The important rank, among human evils and wrongs, of the disappointment of expectation, is shown in the fact that it constitutes the principal criminality of two such highly immoral acts as a breach of friendship and a breach of promise. Few hurts which human beings can sustain are greater, and none wound more, than when that on which they habitually and with full assurance relied, fails them in the hour of need; and few wrongs are greater than this mere withholding of good; none excite more resentment, either in the person suffering, or in a sympathizing spectator. The principle, therefore, of giving to each what they deserve, that is, good for good as well as evil for evil, is not only included within the idea of Justice as we have defined it, but is a proper object of that intensity of sentiment, which places the Just, in human estimation, above the simply Expedient.
The same powerful motivations that demand adherence to these basic moral principles also require punishing those who break them. The impulses of self-defense, defending others, and seeking revenge all come into play against such individuals, linking retribution, or an eye for an eye, closely with the feeling of justice, which is universally part of the concept. Doing good for good is also a principle of justice; although its social value is clear and it carries a natural human sentiment, it doesn’t have that immediate connection to harm or injury, which is present in the most basic examples of right and wrong and gives the sentiment its distinctive strength. However, this connection, while less apparent, is still very real. When someone accepts benefits but refuses to reciprocate when needed, they inflict a real hurt by disappointing one of the most natural and reasonable expectations—one they must have at least indirectly encouraged; otherwise, those benefits wouldn’t have been offered in the first place. The significant position of the disappointment of expectation among human evils and wrongs is evident in how it represents the main wrongdoing in extremely immoral acts like breaking a friendship or breaking a promise. Few harms are greater than when people fail to get support they have relied on and trusted during tough times; withholding good is one of the greatest wrongs and arouses more resentment, both in the person affected and in any sympathetic observer. Therefore, the principle of giving to each what they deserve, meaning good for good as well as evil for evil, not only fits within the definition of Justice we’ve provided but is also a fitting subject of that intense sentiment which holds the Just in higher regard than merely the Expedient.
Most of the maxims of justice current in the world, and commonly appealed to in its transactions, are simply instrumental to carrying into effect the principles of justice which we have now spoken of. That a person is only responsible for what he has done voluntarily, or could voluntarily have avoided; that it is unjust to condemn any person unheard; that the punishment ought to be proportioned to the offence, and the like, are maxims intended to prevent the just principle of evil for evil from being perverted to the infliction of evil without that justification. The greater part of these common maxims have come into use from the practice of courts of justice, which have been naturally led to a more complete recognition and elaboration than was likely to suggest itself to others, of the rules necessary to enable them to fulfil their double function, of inflicting punishment when due, and of awarding to each person his right.
Most of the principles of justice that are accepted in society today and often referenced in various situations are primarily designed to implement the principles of justice we've just discussed. For example, the idea that a person is only accountable for actions they've taken willingly or could have avoided, that it’s unfair to judge someone without giving them a chance to speak, and that punishment should fit the crime are principles meant to ensure that the concept of "an eye for an eye" doesn’t get twisted into causing harm without proper justification. Most of these widely accepted principles have emerged from the practices of courts, which have naturally developed a more thorough understanding and clarification of the rules necessary for them to carry out their dual role: punishing wrongdoing when appropriate and ensuring everyone receives what they’re entitled to.
That first of judicial virtues, impartiality, is an obligation of justice, partly for the reason last mentioned; as being a necessary condition of the fulfilment of the other obligations of justice. But this is not the only source of the exalted rank, among human obligations, of those maxims of equality and impartiality, which, both in popular estimation and in that of the most enlightened, are included among the precepts of justice. In one point of view, they may be considered as corollaries from the principles already laid down. If it is a duty to do to each according to his deserts, returning good for good as well as repressing evil by evil, it necessarily follows that we should treat all equally well (when no higher duty forbids) who have deserved equally well of us, and that society should treat all equally well who have deserved equally well of it, that is, who have deserved equally well absolutely. This is the highest abstract standard of social and distributive justice; towards which all institutions, and the efforts of all virtuous citizens, should be made in the utmost possible degree to converge. But this great moral duty rests upon a still deeper foundation, being a direct emanation from the first principle of morals, and not a mere logical corollary from secondary or derivative doctrines. It is involved in the very meaning of Utility, or the Greatest-Happiness Principle. That principle is a mere form of words without rational signification, unless one person's happiness, supposed equal in degree (with the proper allowance made for kind), is counted for exactly as much as another's. Those conditions being supplied, Bentham's dictum, 'everybody to count for one, nobody for more than one,' might be written under the principle of utility as an explanatory commentary.[D] The equal claim of everybody to happiness in the estimation of the moralist and the legislator, involves an equal claim to all the means of happiness, except in so far as the inevitable conditions of human life, and the general interest, in which that of every individual is included, set limits to the maxim; and those limits ought to be strictly construed. As every other maxim of justice, so this, is by no means applied or held applicable universally; on the contrary, as I have already remarked, it bends to every person's ideas of social expediency. But in whatever case it is deemed applicable at all, it is held to be the dictate of justice. All persons are deemed to have a right to equality of treatment, except when some recognised social expediency requires the reverse. And hence all social inequalities which have ceased to be considered expedient, assume the character not of simple inexpediency, but of injustice, and appear so tyrannical, that people are apt to wonder how they ever could have been tolerated; forgetful that they themselves perhaps tolerate other inequalities under an equally mistaken notion of expediency, the correction of which would make that which they approve seem quite as monstrous as what they have at last learnt to condemn. The entire history of social improvement has been a series of transitions, by which one custom or institution after another, from being a supposed primary necessity of social existence, has passed into the rank of an universally stigmatized injustice and tyranny. So it has been with the distinctions of slaves and freemen, nobles and serfs, patricians and plebeians; and so it will be, and in part already is, with the aristocracies of colour, race, and sex.
The first of the judicial virtues, impartiality, is a necessary part of justice, partly for the reason mentioned earlier; it is essential for fulfilling other obligations of justice. However, this isn’t the only reason why the principles of equality and impartiality hold such a high status among human responsibilities. In some ways, they can be seen as conclusions drawn from previously established principles. If it's our duty to treat everyone according to what they deserve, rewarding good with good and preventing evil with evil, then it follows that we should treat everyone equally well (unless a higher duty says otherwise) who has deserved equally well from us. Likewise, society should equally treat all who have deserved equally well from it, meaning those who have deserved equally well in an absolute sense. This is the ultimate standard of social and distributive justice, toward which all institutions and the efforts of virtuous citizens should strive to converge. But this significant moral duty is based on an even deeper principle; it arises directly from the foundational principle of morals and is not just a logical conclusion from secondary doctrines. It is inherent in the very meaning of Utility, or the Greatest-Happiness Principle. That principle has no real significance unless one person's happiness, considered equal in degree (with appropriate allowance for kind), is valued as much as another's. Once those conditions are met, Bentham's saying, "everybody counts for one, nobody counts for more than one," could serve as a clear explanation of the principle of utility. The equal claim of everyone to happiness, from the perspective of moralists and lawmakers, includes an equal claim to all means of happiness, except where the unavoidable conditions of human life and the overall interest—which includes the interest of every individual—set limits to this idea; and these limits should be interpreted strictly. Like any other principle of justice, this one is not universally applied; instead, as I have noted before, it adapts to each person's views on social necessity. Yet, in any situation where it is considered applicable, it is regarded as a matter of justice. All individuals are recognized to have a right to equal treatment unless some acknowledged social necessity demands otherwise. Consequently, all social inequalities that are no longer seen as necessary come to be viewed not just as undesirable but as unjust, appearing so oppressive that people often wonder how they were ever accepted. They forget that they themselves might be tolerating other inequalities under a similarly misguided view of necessity, the correction of which would make what they accept seem as monstrous as what they have finally come to condemn. The entire history of social progress has been a series of shifts, where one custom or institution after another, once thought essential for social existence, has gradually been recognized as a universally condemned injustice and tyranny. This has been true for the distinctions between slaves and free people, nobles and serfs, patricians and plebeians; and it will also be for, and partly already is, the hierarchies based on color, race, and gender.
It appears from what has been said, that justice is a name for certain moral requirements, which, regarded collectively, stand higher in the scale of social utility, and are therefore of more paramount obligation, than any others; though particular cases may occur in which some other social duty is so important, as to overrule any one of the general maxims of justice. Thus, to save a life, it may not only be allowable, but a duty, to steal, or take by force, the necessary food or medicine, or to kidnap, and compel to officiate, the only qualified medical practitioner. In such cases, as we do not call anything justice which is not a virtue, we usually say, not that justice must give way to some other moral principle, but that what is just in ordinary cases is, by reason of that other principle, not just in the particular case. By this useful accommodation of language, the character of indefeasibility attributed to justice is kept up, and we are saved from the necessity of maintaining that there can be laudable injustice.
It seems from what has been discussed that justice is a term for certain moral requirements that, when considered together, are more significant in terms of social usefulness and thus carry a greater obligation than others. However, there may be specific situations where another social duty is so crucial that it overrides one of the general principles of justice. For instance, to save a life, it might not only be acceptable but a responsibility to steal or forcibly obtain the necessary food or medicine, or to kidnap and make the only qualified doctor provide treatment. In these situations, since we don't consider anything to be justice that isn't a virtue, we typically say that justice doesn't necessarily yield to another moral principle, but rather that what is just in usual circumstances isn't considered just in this specific case because of that other principle. This way of using language helps maintain the idea that justice is inviolable, and it spares us from having to argue that there can be a commendable form of injustice.
The considerations which have now been adduced resolve, I conceive, the only real difficulty in the utilitarian theory of morals. It has always been evident that all cases of justice are also cases of expediency: the difference is in the peculiar sentiment which attaches to the former, as contradistinguished from the latter. If this characteristic sentiment has been sufficiently accounted for; if there is no necessity to assume for it any peculiarity of origin; if it is simply the natural feeling of resentment, moralized by being made coextensive with the demands of social good; and if this feeling not only does but ought to exist in all the classes of cases to which the idea of justice corresponds; that idea no longer presents itself as a stumbling-block to the utilitarian ethics. Justice remains the appropriate name for certain social utilities which are vastly more important, and therefore more absolute and imperative, than any others are as a class (though not more so than others may be in particular cases); and which, therefore, ought to be, as well as naturally are, guarded by a sentiment not only different in degree, but also in kind; distinguished from the milder feeling which attaches to the mere idea of promoting human pleasure or convenience, at once by the more definite nature of its commands, and by the sterner character of its sanctions.
The points I've mentioned clarify, I believe, the main challenge in the utilitarian theory of ethics. It's always been clear that all issues of justice are also issues of practicality; the difference lies in the unique feeling associated with the former, as opposed to the latter. If this specific feeling has been adequately explained; if there's no need to think of it as having a special origin; if it’s just the natural feeling of resentment, shaped by being aligned with the needs of social good; and if this feeling exists and should exist in all the situations that relate to the concept of justice; then that concept no longer poses a challenge to utilitarian ethics. Justice remains the proper term for certain social benefits that are far more crucial, and therefore more absolute and urgent, than any others in general (though not necessarily more so in specific cases); and that should be, as well as naturally are, protected by a feeling that is not only stronger but also fundamentally different; set apart from the gentler feeling tied to simply promoting human happiness or convenience, marked by the clearer nature of its demands and by the stricter nature of its consequences.
THE END.
THE END.
FOOTNOTES:
FOOTNOTES:
See this point enforced and illustrated by Professor Bain, in an admirable chapter (entitled "The Ethical Emotions, or the Moral Sense") of the second of the two treatises composing his elaborate and profound work on the Mind.
See this point emphasized and demonstrated by Professor Bain in an excellent chapter (titled "The Ethical Emotions, or the Moral Sense") of the second of the two treatises that make up his detailed and insightful work on the Mind.
This implication, in the first principle of the utilitarian scheme, of perfect impartiality between persons, is regarded by Mr. Herbert Spencer (in his Social Statics) as a disproof of the pretentions of utility to be a sufficient guide to right; since (he says) the principle of utility presupposes the anterior principle, that everybody has an equal right to happiness. It may be more correctly described as supposing that equal amounts of happiness are equally desirable, whether felt by the same or by different persons. This, however, is not a pre-supposition; not a premise needful to support the principle of utility, but the very principle itself; for what is the principle of utility, if it be not that 'happiness' and 'desirable' are synonymous terms? If there is any anterior principle implied, it can be no other than this, that the truths of arithmetic are applicable to the valuation of happiness, as of all other measurable quantities.
This implication in the first principle of the utilitarian scheme, which calls for complete impartiality among individuals, is seen by Mr. Herbert Spencer (in his Social Statics) as evidence against the idea that utility can be a complete guide to what is right. He argues that the principle of utility assumes the prior idea that everyone has an equal right to happiness. It might be more accurately described as assuming that equal amounts of happiness are equally valuable, whether experienced by the same person or by different people. However, this isn't really a presupposition; it's not a needed premise to support the principle of utility, but rather the principle itself. After all, what is the principle of utility, if not the idea that 'happiness' and 'desirable' are the same thing? If there is any prior principle suggested, it can only be that the truths of arithmetic apply to the assessment of happiness, just as they do for all other measurable quantities.
[Mr. Herbert Spencer, in a private communication on the subject of the preceding Note, objects to being considered an opponent of Utilitarianism; and states that he regards happiness as the ultimate end of morality; but deems that end only partially attainable by empirical generalizations from the observed results of conduct, and completely attainable only by deducing, from the laws of life and the conditions of existence, what kinds of action necessarily tend to produce happiness, and what kinds to produce unhappiness. With the exception of the word "necessarily," I have no dissent to express from this doctrine; and (omitting that word) I am not aware that any modern advocate of utilitarianism is of a different opinion. Bentham, certainly, to whom in the Social Statics Mr. Spencer particularly referred, is, least of all writers, chargeable with unwillingness to deduce the effect of actions on happiness from the laws of human nature and the universal conditions of human life. The common charge against him is of relying too exclusively upon such deductions, and declining altogether to be bound by the generalizations from specific experience which Mr. Spencer thinks that utilitarians generally confine themselves to. My own opinion (and, as I collect, Mr. Spencer's) is, that in ethics, as in all other branches of scientific study, the consilience of the results of both these processes, each corroborating and verifying the other, is requisite to give to any general proposition the kind and degree of evidence which constitutes scientific proof.]
[Mr. Herbert Spencer, in a private message regarding the previous note, disagrees with being labeled an opponent of Utilitarianism. He states that he sees happiness as the ultimate goal of morality, but believes that this goal is only partly achievable through empirical generalizations based on observed outcomes of behavior, and can only be completely achieved by deducing from the laws of life and the conditions of existence which types of actions tend to produce happiness and which tend to produce unhappiness. Aside from the word "necessarily," I do not have any disagreement with this doctrine; and (excluding that word) I believe that no modern supporter of utilitarianism holds a different view. Bentham, certainly, to whom Mr. Spencer specifically referred in the Social Statics, is one of the least likely authors to be accused of being unwilling to deduce the effects of actions on happiness from the principles of human nature and the universal conditions of human life. The common criticism against him is that he relies too heavily on such deductions and completely ignores the generalizations from specific experiences that Mr. Spencer thinks utilitarians typically adhere to. My own view (and, as I gather, Mr. Spencer's) is that in ethics, as in all other fields of scientific study, the convergence of the results from both of these approaches, each supporting and validating the other, is necessary to provide any general statement with the kind and level of evidence that constitutes scientific proof.]
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!