This is a modern-English version of Selections From the Works of John Ruskin, originally written by Ruskin, John.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
Riverside College Classics
SELECTIONS
FROM THE WORKS OF
JOHN RUSKIN
EDITED WITH INTRODUCTION AND NOTES BY
CHAUNCEY B. TINKER, Ph.D.
Professor of English in Yale College
BOSTON—NEW YORK—CHICAGO—SAN FRANCISCO
HOUGHTON MIFFLIN COMPANY
The Riverside Press Cambridge
1908
BY HOUGHTON MIFFLIN COMPANY
The Riverside Press
CAMBRIDGE—MASSACHUSETTS
PRINTED IN THE U.S.A.
PREFACE
In making the following selections, I have tried to avoid the appearance of such a volume as used to be entitled Elegant Extracts. Wherever practicable, entire chapters or lectures are given, or at least passages of sufficient length to insure a correct notion of the general complexion of Ruskin's work. The text is in all cases that of the first editions, unless these were later revised by Ruskin himself. The original spelling and punctuation are preserved, but a few minor changes have been made for the sake of uniformity among the various extracts. For similar reasons, Ruskin's numbering of paragraphs is dispensed with.
In making the following selections, I aimed to avoid creating a volume like those once called Elegant Extracts. Wherever possible, I’ve included entire chapters or lectures, or at least passages that are long enough to give a clear idea of the overall tone of Ruskin's work. The text is always from the first editions, unless they were later revised by Ruskin himself. The original spelling and punctuation have been kept, but a few minor adjustments have been made for consistency across the different extracts. For the same reasons, Ruskin's paragraph numbering has been omitted.
I have aimed not to multiply notes. Practically all Ruskin's own annotation is given, with the exception of one or two very long and somewhat irrelevant notes from Stones of Venice. It has not been deemed necessary to give the dates of every painter or to explain every geographical reference. On the other hand, the sources of most of the quotations are indicated. In the preparation of these notes, the magnificent library edition of Messrs. Cook and Wedderburn has inevitably been of considerable assistance; but all their references have been verified, many errors have been corrected, and much has of course been added.
I have tried to keep the notes to a minimum. Almost all of Ruskin's own annotations are included, except for a couple of very long and somewhat irrelevant notes from Stones of Venice. It didn't seem necessary to provide the dates for every painter or to clarify every geographical reference. On the flip side, the sources for most of the quotes are listed. In putting together these notes, the excellent library edition by Messrs. Cook and Wedderburn has been really helpful; however, all their references have been checked, many mistakes have been fixed, and quite a bit has, of course, been added.
In closing I wish to express my obligation to my former colleague, Dr. Lucius H. Holt, without whose assistance this volume would never have appeared. He wrote a number of the notes, including the short prefaces to the various selections, and prepared the manuscript for the printer.
In closing, I want to express my gratitude to my former colleague, Dr. Lucius H. Holt, without whose help this book would never have been published. He wrote several of the notes, including the brief introductions to the different selections, and prepared the manuscript for printing.
C.B.T.
September, 1908.
C.B.T.
September 1908.
CONTENTS
ILLUSTRATIONS
- JOHN RUSKIN IN 1857
- TURNER'S FIGHTING TÉMÉRAIRE
- CHURCH OF ST. MARK, VENICE
- ST. MARK'S: CENTRAL ARCH OF FAÇADE
Introduction
Intro
Two conflicting tendencies in Ruskin.
Two opposing tendencies in Ruskin.
It is distinctive of the nineteenth century that in its passion for criticising everything in heaven and earth it by no means spared to criticise itself. Alike in Carlyle's fulminations against its insincerity, in Arnold's nice ridicule of Philistinism, and in Ruskin's repudiation of everything modern, we detect that fine dissatisfaction with the age which is perhaps only proof of its idealistic trend. For the various ills of society, each of these men had his panacea. What Carlyle had found in hero-worship and Arnold in Hellenic culture, Ruskin sought in the study of art; and it is of the last importance to remember that throughout his work he regarded himself not merely as a writer on painting or buildings or myths or landscape, but as the appointed critic of the age. For there existed in him, side by side with his consuming love of the beautiful, a rigorous Puritanism which was constantly correcting any tendency toward a mere cult of the aesthetic. It is with the interaction of these two forces that any study of the life and writings of Ruskin should be primarily concerned.
It’s characteristic of the nineteenth century that, in its eagerness to criticize everything under the sun, it also directed some of that criticism at itself. In Carlyle's fierce rants about insincerity, Arnold's clever mockery of Philistinism, and Ruskin's rejection of everything modern, we see a deep dissatisfaction with the era that likely reflects its idealistic nature. Each of these thinkers offered their own solutions to society's problems. Carlyle found his answer in hero-worship, Arnold in Hellenic culture, and Ruskin in the study of art. It’s crucial to remember that throughout his work, Ruskin saw himself not just as someone writing about painting, architecture, myths, or landscapes, but as the appointed critic of his time. Alongside his passionate love for beauty, he had a strict Puritanism that was always keeping in check any drift toward simply celebrating aesthetics. Any exploration of Ruskin’s life and writings should focus on the interaction of these two dynamics.
I
THE LIFE OF RUSKIN
Ancestry.
Heritage.
It is easy to trace in the life of Ruskin these two forces tending respectively toward the love of beauty and toward the contempt of mere beauty. They are, indeed, present from the beginning. He inherited from his Scotch parents that upright fearlessness which has always characterized the race. His stern mother "devoted him to God before he was born,"[1] and she guarded her gift with unremitting but perhaps misguided caution. The child was early taught to find most of his entertainment within himself, and when he did not, he was whipped. He had no playmates and few toys. His chief story-book was the Bible, which he read many times from cover to cover at his mother's knee. His father, the "perfectly honest wine-merchant," seems to have been the one to foster the boy's aesthetic sense; he was in the habit of reading aloud to his little family, and his son's apparently genuine appreciation of Scott, Pope, and Homer dates from the incredibly early age of five. It was his father, also, to whom he owed his early acquaintance with the finest landscape, for the boy was his companion in yearly business trips about Britain, and later visited, in his parents' company, Belgium, western Germany, and the Alps.
It is easy to trace in the life of Ruskin these two forces tending respectively toward the love of beauty and toward the contempt of mere beauty. They are, indeed, present from the beginning. He inherited from his Scotch parents that upright fearlessness which has always characterized the race. His stern mother "devoted him to God before he was born,"[1] and she guarded her gift with unremitting but perhaps misguided caution. The child was early taught to find most of his entertainment within himself, and when he did not, he was whipped. He had no playmates and few toys. His chief story-book was the Bible, which he read many times from cover to cover at his mother's knee. His father, the "perfectly honest wine-merchant," seems to have been the one to foster the boy's aesthetic sense; he was in the habit of reading aloud to his little family, and his son's apparently genuine appreciation of Scott, Pope, and Homer dates from the incredibly early age of five. It was his father, also, to whom he owed his early acquaintance with the finest landscape, for the boy was his companion in yearly business trips about Britain, and later visited, in his parents' company, Belgium, western Germany, and the Alps.
Early education.
Early learning.
All this of course developed the child's precocity. He was early suffered and even encouraged to compose verses;[2] by ten he had written a play, which has unfortunately been preserved. The hot-house rearing which his parents believed in, and his facility in teaching himself, tended to make a regular course of schooling a mere annoyance; such schooling as he had did not begin till he was fifteen, and lasted less than two years, and was broken by illness. But the chief effect of the sheltered life and advanced education to which he was subjected was to endow him with depth at the expense of breadth, and to deprive him of a possibly vulgar, but certainly healthy, contact with his kind, which, one must believe, would have checked a certain disposition in him to egotism, sentimentality, and dogmatic vehemence. "The bridle and blinkers were never taken off me," he writes.[3]
All this of course developed the child's precocity. He was early suffered and even encouraged to compose verses;[2] by ten he had written a play, which has unfortunately been preserved. The hot-house rearing which his parents believed in, and his facility in teaching himself, tended to make a regular course of schooling a mere annoyance; such schooling as he had did not begin till he was fifteen, and lasted less than two years, and was broken by illness. But the chief effect of the sheltered life and advanced education to which he was subjected was to endow him with depth at the expense of breadth, and to deprive him of a possibly vulgar, but certainly healthy, contact with his kind, which, one must believe, would have checked a certain disposition in him to egotism, sentimentality, and dogmatic vehemence. "The bridle and blinkers were never taken off me," he writes.[3]
Student at Oxford.
Student at Oxford University.
Traveling in Europe.
Traveling in Europe.
At Oxford—whither his cautious mother pursued him—Ruskin seems to have been impressed in no very essential manner by curriculum or college mates. With learning per se he was always dissatisfied and never had much to do; his course was distinguished not so much by erudition as by culture. He easily won the Newdigate prize in poetry; his rooms in Christ Church were hung with excellent examples of Turner's landscapes,—the gift of his art-loving father,—of which he had been an intimate student ever since the age of thirteen. But his course was interrupted by an illness, apparently of a tuberculous nature, which necessitated total relaxation and various trips in Italy and Switzerland, where he seems to have been healed by walking among his beloved Alps. For many years thereafter he passed months of his time in these two countries, accompanied sometimes by his parents and sometimes rather luxuriously, it seems, by valet and guide.
At Oxford—where his cautious mother followed him—Ruskin didn't seem to be significantly impacted by the curriculum or his college peers. He was always dissatisfied with learning for its own sake and didn’t engage much; his experience there was marked more by culture than by academic achievement. He easily won the Newdigate prize for poetry; his rooms at Christ Church were decorated with stunning examples of Turner's landscapes—the gift from his art-loving father—of which he had been a dedicated student since he was thirteen. However, his studies were interrupted by an illness, seemingly related to tuberculosis, which required him to take a complete break and travel through Italy and Switzerland, where he appeared to recover by hiking among his beloved Alps. For many years afterward, he spent months in these two countries, sometimes accompanied by his parents and other times, it seemed, traveling rather comfortably with a valet and guide.
Career as an author begins.
Author career begins.
Meanwhile he had commenced his career as author with the first volume of Modern Painters, begun, the world knows, as a short defense of Turner, originally intended for nothing more than a magazine article. But the role of art-critic and law-giver pleased the youth,—he was only twenty-four when the volume appeared,—and having no desire to realize the ambition of his parents and become a bishop, and even less to duplicate his father's career as vintner, he gladly seized the opportunity thus offered him to develop his aesthetic vein and to redeem the public mind from its vulgar apathy thereby. He continued his work on Modern Painters, with some intermissions, for eighteen years, and supplemented it with the equally famous Seven Lamps of Architecture in 1849, and The Stones of Venice in 1853.
Meanwhile, he started his career as an author with the first volume of Modern Painters, which, as everyone knows, began as a brief defense of Turner, originally meant to be just a magazine article. But the role of art critic and authority excited the young man—he was only twenty-four when the volume came out—and with no interest in following his parents' wishes to become a bishop, and even less desire to continue his father's path as a winemaker, he eagerly took the chance to explore his artistic side and inspire the public to rise above its dull indifference. He worked on Modern Painters for eighteen years, with some breaks, and also produced the equally renowned Seven Lamps of Architecture in 1849 and The Stones of Venice in 1853.
Domestic troubles.
Family issues.
This life of zealous work and brilliant recognition was interrupted in 1848 by Ruskin's amazing marriage to Miss Euphemia Gray, a union into which he entered at the desire of his parents with a docility as stupid as it was stupendous. Five years later the couple were quietly divorced, that Mrs. Ruskin might marry Millais. All the author's biographers maintain an indiscreet reserve in discussing the affair, but there can be no concealment of the fact that its effect upon Ruskin was profound in its depression. Experiences like this and his later sad passion for Miss La Touche at once presage and indicate his mental disorder, and no doubt had their share—a large one—in causing Ruskin's dissatisfaction with everything, and above all with his own life and work. Be this as it may, it is at this time in the life of Ruskin that we must begin to reckon with the decline of his aesthetic and the rise of his ethical impulse; his interest passes from art to conduct. It is also the period in which he began his career as lecturer, his chief interest being the social life of his age.
This busy life filled with hard work and great recognition was interrupted in 1848 by Ruskin's surprising marriage to Miss Euphemia Gray, a union he entered into at his parents' request with a naivety that was both foolish and remarkable. Five years later, the couple quietly divorced so that Mrs. Ruskin could marry Millais. All of the author’s biographers maintain a discreet silence when discussing the affair, but it’s clear that it profoundly depressed Ruskin. Experiences like this, along with his later unrequited love for Miss La Touche, both foreshadow and signify his mental struggles, and undoubtedly contributed significantly to Ruskin's discontent with everything, especially with his own life and work. Regardless, it is at this point in Ruskin's life that we must begin to observe the decline of his artistic focus and the emergence of his ethical concerns; his interests shifted from art to morality. This is also the time when he started his career as a lecturer, focusing primarily on the social life of his time.
Ruskin's increasing interest in social questions.
Ruskin's growing interest in social issues.
By 1860, he was publishing the papers on political economy, later called Unto this Last, which roused so great a storm of protest when they appeared in the Cornhill Magazine that their publication had to be suspended. The attitude of the public toward such works as these,—its alternate excitement and apathy,—the death of his parents, combined with the distressing events mentioned above, darkened Ruskin's life and spoiled his interest in everything that did not tend to make the national life more thoughtfully solemn.
By 1860, he was publishing papers on political economy, later titled Unto this Last, which sparked such a huge backlash when they came out in the Cornhill Magazine that their publication had to be halted. The public's reaction to works like these—its mix of excitement and indifference—the death of his parents, along with the troubling events mentioned earlier, cast a shadow over Ruskin's life and dampened his interest in anything that didn’t contribute to making national life more seriously reflective.
"It seems to me that now ... the thoughts of the true nature of our life, and of its powers and responsibilities should present themselves with absolute sadness and sternness."[4]
"It seems to me that now ... the thoughts of the true nature of our life, and of its powers and responsibilities should present themselves with absolute sadness and sternness."[4]
His lectures as Slade Professor of Art at Oxford, a post which he held at various times from 1870 to 1883, failed to re-establish his undistracted interest in things beautiful.
His lectures as Slade Professor of Art at Oxford, a position he held at different times from 1870 to 1883, did not restore his unwavering passion for beautiful things.
Triumph of the reformer over the art-critic.
Triumph of the reformer over the art critic.
The complete triumph of the reformer over the art-critic is marked by Fors Clavigera, a series of letters to workingmen, begun New Year's Day, 1871, in which it was proposed to establish a model colony of peasants, whose lives should be made simple, honest, happy, and even cultured, by a return to more primitive methods of tilling the soil and of making useful and beautiful objects. The Guild of St. George, established to "slay the dragon of industrialism," to dispose of machinery, slums, and discontent, consumed a large part of Ruskin's time and money. He had inherited a fortune of approximately a million dollars, and he now began to dispose of it in various charitable schemes,—establishing tea-shops, supporting young painters, planning model tenements, but, above all, in elaborating his ideas for the Guild. The result of it all—whatever particular reforms were effected or manual industries established—was, to Ruskin's view, failure, and his mind, weakening under the strain of its profound disappointments, at last crashed in ruin.
The complete victory of the reformer over the art critic is highlighted by Fors Clavigera, a series of letters to workers that started on New Year's Day, 1871. In these letters, there was a proposal to create a model community of peasants, whose lives would be made simple, honest, happy, and even cultured by going back to more basic farming methods and creating useful and beautiful objects. The Guild of St. George was formed to "slay the dragon of industrialism," aiming to deal with problems like machinery, slums, and discontent, which took up a significant amount of Ruskin's time and money. He had inherited around a million dollars and began to invest it in various charitable projects—opening tea shops, supporting young artists, planning model housing, but most importantly, developing his ideas for the Guild. In Ruskin's eyes, the end result—regardless of the specific reforms made or industries created—was a failure, and his mind, increasingly burdened by deep disappointments, eventually fell apart.
Death in 1900.
Death in 1900.
It is needless to follow the broken author through the desolation of his closing years to his death in 1900. Save for his charming reminiscences, Præterita, his work was done; the long struggle was over, the struggle of one man to reduce the complexities of a national life to an apostolic simplicity, to make it beautiful and good,
It’s unnecessary to trace the troubled author through the bleakness of his final years until his death in 1900. Aside from his delightful memories in Præterita, his work was complete; the long battle was finished, the battle of one man to simplify the complexities of a national life into an almost saintly clarity, to make it beautiful and good,
Till the high God behold it from beyond,
Till the high God sees it from above,
And enter it.
And go for it.
II
THE UNITY OF RUSKIN'S WRITINGS
Diversity of his writings.
Variety in his writings.
Ruskin is often described as an author of bewildering variety, whose mind drifted waywardly from topic to topic—from painting to political economy, from architecture to agriculture—with a license as illogical as it was indiscriminating. To this impression, Ruskin himself sometimes gave currency. He was, for illustration, once announced to lecture on crystallography, but, as we are informed by one present,[5] he opened by asserting that he was really about to lecture on Cistercian architecture; nor did it greatly matter what the title was; "for," said he, "if I had begun to speak about Cistercian abbeys, I should have been sure to get on crystals presently; and if I had begun upon crystals, I should soon have drifted into architecture." Those who conceive of Ruskin as being thus a kind of literary Proteus like to point to the year 1860, that of the publication of his tracts on economics, as witnessing the greatest and suddenest of his changes, that from reforming art to reforming society; and it is true that this year affords a simple dividing-line between Ruskin's earlier work, which is sufficiently described by the three titles, Modern Painters, The Seven Lamps of Architecture, and The Stones of Venice, and his later work, chiefly on social subjects such as are discussed in Unto This Last, The Crown of Wild Olive, and Fors Clavigera. And yet we cannot insist too often on the essential unity of this work, for, viewed in the large, it betrays one continuous development. The seeds of Fors are in The Stones of Venice.
Ruskin is often described as an author of bewildering variety, whose mind drifted waywardly from topic to topic—from painting to political economy, from architecture to agriculture—with a license as illogical as it was indiscriminating. To this impression, Ruskin himself sometimes gave currency. He was, for illustration, once announced to lecture on crystallography, but, as we are informed by one present,[5] he opened by asserting that he was really about to lecture on Cistercian architecture; nor did it greatly matter what the title was; "for," said he, "if I had begun to speak about Cistercian abbeys, I should have been sure to get on crystals presently; and if I had begun upon crystals, I should soon have drifted into architecture." Those who conceive of Ruskin as being thus a kind of literary Proteus like to point to the year 1860, that of the publication of his tracts on economics, as witnessing the greatest and suddenest of his changes, that from reforming art to reforming society; and it is true that this year affords a simple dividing-line between Ruskin's earlier work, which is sufficiently described by the three titles, Modern Painters, The Seven Lamps of Architecture, and The Stones of Venice, and his later work, chiefly on social subjects such as are discussed in Unto This Last, The Crown of Wild Olive, and Fors Clavigera. And yet we cannot insist too often on the essential unity of this work, for, viewed in the large, it betrays one continuous development. The seeds of Fors are in The Stones of Venice.
Underlying idea in all his works.
Underlying idea in all his works.
The governing idea of Ruskin's first published work, Modern Painters, Volume I, was a moral idea. The book was dedicated to the principle that that art is greatest which deals with the greatest number of greatest ideas,—those, we learn presently, which reveal divine truth; the office of the painter, we are told,[6] is the same as that of the preacher, for "the duty of both is to take for each discourse one essential truth." As if recalling this argument that the painter is a preacher, Carlyle described The Stones of Venice as a "sermon in stones." In the idea that all art, when we have taken due account of technique and training, springs from a moral character, we find the unifying principle of Ruskin's strangely diversified work. The very title The Seven Lamps of Architecture, with its chapters headed "Sacrifice," "Obedience," etc., is a sufficient illustration of Ruskin's identification of moral principles with aesthetic principles. A glance at the following pages of this book will show how Ruskin is for ever halting himself to demand the moral significance of some fair landscape, gorgeous painting, heaven-aspiring cathedral. In "Mountain Glory," for example, he refers to the mountains as "kindly in simple lessons to the workman," and inquires later at what times mankind has offered worship in these mountain churches; of the English cathedral he says, "Weigh the influence of those dark towers on all who have passed through the lonely square at their feet for centuries";[7] of St. Mark's, "And what effect has this splendour on those who pass beneath it?"—and it will be noticed on referring to "The Two Boyhoods," that, in seeking to define the difference between Giorgione and Turner, the author instinctively has recourse to distinguishing the religious influences exerted on the two in youth.
The governing idea of Ruskin's first published work, Modern Painters, Volume I, was a moral idea. The book was dedicated to the principle that that art is greatest which deals with the greatest number of greatest ideas,—those, we learn presently, which reveal divine truth; the office of the painter, we are told,[6] is the same as that of the preacher, for "the duty of both is to take for each discourse one essential truth." As if recalling this argument that the painter is a preacher, Carlyle described The Stones of Venice as a "sermon in stones." In the idea that all art, when we have taken due account of technique and training, springs from a moral character, we find the unifying principle of Ruskin's strangely diversified work. The very title The Seven Lamps of Architecture, with its chapters headed "Sacrifice," "Obedience," etc., is a sufficient illustration of Ruskin's identification of moral principles with aesthetic principles. A glance at the following pages of this book will show how Ruskin is for ever halting himself to demand the moral significance of some fair landscape, gorgeous painting, heaven-aspiring cathedral. In "Mountain Glory," for example, he refers to the mountains as "kindly in simple lessons to the workman," and inquires later at what times mankind has offered worship in these mountain churches; of the English cathedral he says, "Weigh the influence of those dark towers on all who have passed through the lonely square at their feet for centuries";[7] of St. Mark's, "And what effect has this splendour on those who pass beneath it?"—and it will be noticed on referring to "The Two Boyhoods," that, in seeking to define the difference between Giorgione and Turner, the author instinctively has recourse to distinguishing the religious influences exerted on the two in youth.
Underlying idea a moral one.
Underlying idea is a moral one.
Now it is clear that a student of the relation of art to life, of work to the character of the workman and of his nation, may, and in fact inevitably must, be led in time to attend to the producer rather than to the product, to the cause rather than to the effect; and if we grant, with Ruskin, that the sources of art, namely, the national life, are denied, it will obviously be the part, not only of humanity but of common sense, for such a student to set about purifying the social life of the nation. Whether the reformation proposed by Ruskin be the proper method of attack is not the question we are here concerned with; our only object at present being to call attention to the fact that such a lecture as that on "Traffic" in The Crown of Wild Olive is the logical outgrowth of such a chapter as "Ideas of Beauty" in the first volume of Modern Painters. Between the author who wrote in 1842, of the necessity of revealing new truths in painting, "This, if it be an honest work of art, it must have done, for no man ever yet worked honestly without giving some such help to his race. God appoints to every one of his creatures a separate mission, and if they discharge it honourably ... there will assuredly come of it such burning as, in its appointed mode and measure, shall shine before men, and be of service constant and holy,"[8] and the author who wrote, "That country is the richest which nourishes the greatest number of noble and happy human beings,"[9] or, "The beginning of art is in getting our country clean, and our people beautiful,"[10]—between these two, I say, there is no essential difference. They are not contradictory but consistent.
Now it is clear that a student of the relation of art to life, of work to the character of the workman and of his nation, may, and in fact inevitably must, be led in time to attend to the producer rather than to the product, to the cause rather than to the effect; and if we grant, with Ruskin, that the sources of art, namely, the national life, are denied, it will obviously be the part, not only of humanity but of common sense, for such a student to set about purifying the social life of the nation. Whether the reformation proposed by Ruskin be the proper method of attack is not the question we are here concerned with; our only object at present being to call attention to the fact that such a lecture as that on "Traffic" in The Crown of Wild Olive is the logical outgrowth of such a chapter as "Ideas of Beauty" in the first volume of Modern Painters. Between the author who wrote in 1842, of the necessity of revealing new truths in painting, "This, if it be an honest work of art, it must have done, for no man ever yet worked honestly without giving some such help to his race. God appoints to every one of his creatures a separate mission, and if they discharge it honourably ... there will assuredly come of it such burning as, in its appointed mode and measure, shall shine before men, and be of service constant and holy,"[8] and the author who wrote, "That country is the richest which nourishes the greatest number of noble and happy human beings,"[9] or, "The beginning of art is in getting our country clean, and our people beautiful,"[10]—between these two, I say, there is no essential difference. They are not contradictory but consistent.
Art dependent upon personal and national greatness.
Art relies on individual and national greatness.
Amidst the maze of subjects, then, which Ruskin, with kaleidoscopic suddenness and variety, brings before the astonished gaze of his readers, let them confidently hold this guiding clue. They will find that Ruskin's "facts" are often not facts at all; they will discover that many of Ruskin's choicest theories have been dismissed to the limbo of exploded hypotheses; but they will seek long before they find a more eloquent and convincing plea for the proposition that all great art reposes upon a foundation of personal and national greatness. Critics of Ruskin will show you that he began Modern Painters while he was yet ignorant of the classic Italians; that he wrote The Stones of Venice without realizing the full indebtedness of the Venetian to the Byzantine architecture; that he proposed to unify the various religious sects although he had no knowledge of theology; that he attempted a reconstruction of society though he had had no scientific training in political economy; but in all this neglect of mere fact the sympathetic reader will discover that contempt for the letter of the law which was characteristic of the nineteenth-century prophet,—of Carlyle, of Arnold, and of Emerson,—and which, if it be blindness, is that produced by an excess of light.
In the midst of the range of topics that Ruskin presents with vivid suddenness and variety, readers should keep this guiding clue in mind. They’ll see that Ruskin's "facts" often aren't facts at all; they'll find that many of his best theories have been dismissed as outdated ideas. However, they will search for a long time before they find a more compelling and persuasive argument for the idea that all great art is built on a foundation of personal and national greatness. Critics of Ruskin will point out that he started Modern Painters while still unfamiliar with classical Italian art; that he wrote The Stones of Venice without fully understanding how much Venetian architecture owed to Byzantine influences; that he aimed to unify various religious sects without any knowledge of theology; and that he tried to reconstruct society despite lacking formal education in political economy. But in all this disregard for established facts, the sympathetic reader will find a disdain for the strict letter of the law that was typical of nineteenth-century thinkers—like Carlyle, Arnold, and Emerson—which, if it can be seen as blindness, is a blindness caused by too much light.
III
RUSKIN'S STYLE
Sensuous-
ness of his style.
Sensuousness of his style.
Many people regard the style of Ruskin as his chief claim to greatness. If the time ever come when men no longer study him for sermons in stones, they will nevertheless turn to his pages to enjoy one of the most gorgeous prose styles of the nineteenth century. For a parallel to the sensuous beauties of Ruskin's essays on art, one turns instinctively to poetry; and of all the poets Ruskin is perhaps likest Keats. His sentences, like the poet's, are thick-set with jeweled phrases; they are full of subtle harmonies that respond, like a Stradivarius, to the player's every mood. In its ornateness Ruskin's style is like his favorite cathedral of Amiens, in the large stately, in detail exquisite, profuse, and not without a touch of the grotesque. It is the style of an artist.
Many people consider Ruskin's style to be his main claim to greatness. If the day comes when people no longer study him for "sermons in stones," they will still turn to his writings to enjoy one of the most stunning prose styles of the nineteenth century. To find a comparison to the vivid beauty of Ruskin's essays on art, one naturally thinks of poetry; and of all the poets, Ruskin is probably most similar to Keats. His sentences, like the poet's, are packed with beautiful phrases; they are filled with subtle harmonies that react, like a Stradivarius, to the player's every emotion. In its elaborate nature, Ruskin's style resembles his favorite cathedral of Amiens, grand in its overall form, exquisite in its details, abundant, and with a hint of the grotesque. It is the style of an artist.
Ruskin's method of construction in description.
Ruskin's method for building descriptions.
A critical fancy may even discover in the construction of his finest descriptions a method not unlike that of a painter at work upon his canvas. He blocks them out in large masses, then sketches and colors rapidly for general effects, treating detail at first more or less vaguely and collectively, but passing in the end to the elaboration of detail in the concrete, touching the whole with an imaginative gleam that lends a momentary semblance of life to the thing described, after the manner of the "pathetic fallacy." Thus it is in the famous description of St. Mark's:[11] we are given first the largest general impression, the "long, low pyramid of coloured light," which the artist proceeds to "hollow beneath into five great vaulted porches," whence he leads the eye slowly upwards amidst a mass of bewildering detail—"a confusion of delight"—from which there slowly emerge those concrete details with which the author particularly wishes to impress us, "the breasts of the Greek horses blazing in their breadth of golden strength and St. Mark's lion lifted on a blue field covered with stars." In lesser compass we are shown the environs of Venice,[12] the general impression of the "long, low, sad-coloured line," being presently broken by the enumeration of unanalyzed detail, "tufted irregularly with brushwood and willows," and passing to concrete detail in the hills of Arqua, "a dark cluster of purple pyramids." In the still more miniature description of the original site of Venice[13] we have the same method:
A critical fancy may even discover in the construction of his finest descriptions a method not unlike that of a painter at work upon his canvas. He blocks them out in large masses, then sketches and colors rapidly for general effects, treating detail at first more or less vaguely and collectively, but passing in the end to the elaboration of detail in the concrete, touching the whole with an imaginative gleam that lends a momentary semblance of life to the thing described, after the manner of the "pathetic fallacy." Thus it is in the famous description of St. Mark's:[11] we are given first the largest general impression, the "long, low pyramid of coloured light," which the artist proceeds to "hollow beneath into five great vaulted porches," whence he leads the eye slowly upwards amidst a mass of bewildering detail—"a confusion of delight"—from which there slowly emerge those concrete details with which the author particularly wishes to impress us, "the breasts of the Greek horses blazing in their breadth of golden strength and St. Mark's lion lifted on a blue field covered with stars." In lesser compass we are shown the environs of Venice,[12] the general impression of the "long, low, sad-coloured line," being presently broken by the enumeration of unanalyzed detail, "tufted irregularly with brushwood and willows," and passing to concrete detail in the hills of Arqua, "a dark cluster of purple pyramids." In the still more miniature description of the original site of Venice[13] we have the same method:
"The black desert of their shore lies in its nakedness beneath the night, pathless, comfortless, infirm, lost in dark languor and fearful silence, except where the salt runlets plash into the tideless pools and the sea-birds flit from their margins with a questioning cry."
"The black desert of their shore lies bare beneath the night, with no paths, no comfort, weak and lost in dark stillness and eerie silence, except where the salty streams splash into the still pools and the sea-birds dart from their edges with a questioning call."
His love of color.
His love for color.
Equally characteristic of the painter is the ever-present use of color. It is interesting merely to count the number and variety of colors used in the descriptions. It will serve at least to call the reader's attention to the felicitous choice of words used in describing the opalescence of St. Mark's or the skillful combination of the colors characteristic of the great Venetians in such a sentence as, "the low bronzed gleaming of sea-rusted armor shot angrily under their blood-red mantle-folds"[14]—a glimpse of a Giorgione.
Equally characteristic of the painter is the ever-present use of color. It is interesting merely to count the number and variety of colors used in the descriptions. It will serve at least to call the reader's attention to the felicitous choice of words used in describing the opalescence of St. Mark's or the skillful combination of the colors characteristic of the great Venetians in such a sentence as, "the low bronzed gleaming of sea-rusted armor shot angrily under their blood-red mantle-folds"[14]—a glimpse of a Giorgione.
His love of prose rhythm.
His passion for prose rhythm.
He is even more attentive to the ear than to the eye. He loves the sentence of stately rhythms and long-drawn harmonies, and he omits no poetic device that can heighten the charm of sound,—alliteration, as in the famous description of the streets of Venice,
He pays more attention to sound than to visuals. He loves sentences with grand rhythms and extended harmonies, and he doesn’t skip any poetic techniques that can enhance the beauty of sound—like alliteration, as in the well-known depiction of the streets of Venice,
"Far as the eye could reach, still the soft moving of stainless waters proudly pure; as not the flower, so neither the thorn nor the thistle could grow in those glancing fields";[15]
"Far as the eye could reach, still the soft moving of stainless waters proudly pure; as not the flower, so neither the thorn nor the thistle could grow in those glancing fields";[15]
the balanced close for some long period,
the balanced close for a long time,
"to write her history on the white scrolls of the sea-surges and to word it in their thunder, and to gather and give forth, in the world-wide pulsation, the glory of the West and of the East, from the burning heart of her Fortitude and splendour";[16]
"to write her history on the white scrolls of the sea-surges and to word it in their thunder, and to gather and give forth, in the world-wide pulsation, the glory of the West and of the East, from the burning heart of her Fortitude and splendour";[16]
and the tendency, almost a mannerism, to add to the music of his own rhythm, the deep organ-notes of Biblical text and paraphrase. But if we wish to see how aptly Ruskin's style responds to the tone of his subject, we need but remark the rich liquid sentence descriptive of Giorgione's home,
and the tendency, almost a habit, to enhance the music of his own rhythm with the deep organ-like sounds of Biblical text and paraphrase. But if we want to see how well Ruskin's style matches the tone of his subject, we only have to note the beautifully flowing sentence describing Giorgione's home,
"brightness out of the north and balm from the south, and the stars of evening and morning clear in the limitless light of arched heaven and circling sea,"[17]
"brightness out of the north and balm from the south, and the stars of evening and morning clear in the limitless light of arched heaven and circling sea,"[17]
which he has set over against the harsh explosiveness of
which he has placed in contrast to the harsh explosiveness of
"Near the south-west corner of Covent Garden, a square brick pit or wall is formed by a close-set block of house to the back windows of which it admits a few rays of light—"
"Near the southwest corner of Covent Garden, a square brick pit or wall is created by a tightly packed group of houses, allowing just a few rays of light to reach the back windows."
the birthplace of Turner.
Turner's birthplace.
His beauty of style often distracts from the thought.
His beautiful style often distracts from the idea.
But none knew better than Ruskin that a style so stiff with ornament was likely to produce all manner of faults. In overloading his sentences with jewelry he frequently obscures the sense; his beauties often degenerate into mere prettiness; his sweetness cloys. His free indulgence of the emotions, often at the expense of the intellect, leads to a riotous extravagance of superlative. But, above all, his richness distracts attention from matter to manner. In the case of an author so profoundly in earnest, this could not but be unfortunate; nothing enraged him more than to have people look upon the beauties of his style rather than ponder the substance of his book. In a passage of complacent self-scourging he says:
But no one understood better than Ruskin that a style overloaded with decoration was likely to create all kinds of issues. By packing his sentences with embellishments, he often obscured their meaning; his beauties often turned into mere prettiness; his sweetness became overwhelming. His tendency to indulge emotions, sometimes at the cost of intellect, led to an over-the-top use of superlatives. But most importantly, his richness shifted focus from content to style. For an author so deeply serious, this was undoubtedly unfortunate; nothing upset him more than when people admired the beauty of his style instead of reflecting on the substance of his book. In a moment of self-reflection, he states:
"For I have had what, in many respects, I boldly call the misfortune, to set my words sometimes prettily together; not without a foolish vanity in the poor knack that I had of doing so, until I was heavily punished for this pride by finding that many people thought of the words only, and cared nothing for their meaning. Happily, therefore, the power of using such language—if indeed it ever were mine—is passing away from me; and whatever I am now able to say at all I find myself forced to say with great plainness."[18]
"For I have had what, in many respects, I boldly call the misfortune, to set my words sometimes prettily together; not without a foolish vanity in the poor knack that I had of doing so, until I was heavily punished for this pride by finding that many people thought of the words only, and cared nothing for their meaning. Happily, therefore, the power of using such language—if indeed it ever were mine—is passing away from me; and whatever I am now able to say at all I find myself forced to say with great plainness."[18]
His picturesque extravagance of style.
His beautiful and extravagant style.
But Ruskin's decision to speak with "great plainness" by no means made the people of England attend to what he said rather than the way he said it. He could be, and in his later work he usually was, strong and clear; but the old picturesqueness and exuberance of passion were with him still. The public discovered that it enjoyed Ruskin's denunciations of machinery much as it had enjoyed his descriptions of mountains, and, without obviously mending its ways, called loudly for more. Lecture-rooms were crowded and editions exhausted by the ladies and gentlemen of England, whose nerves were pleasantly thrilled with a gentle surprise on being told that they had despised literature, art, science, nature, and compassion, and that what they thought upon any subject was "a matter of no serious importance"; that they could not be said to have any thoughts at all—indeed, no right to think.[19] The fiercer his anathemas, the greater the applause; the louder he shouted, the better he pleased. Let him split the ears of the groundlings, let him out-Herod Herod,—the judicious might grieve, but all would be excitedly attentive. Their Jeremiah seemed at times like to become a jester,—there was a suggestion of the ludicrous in the sudden passage from birds to Greek coins, to mills, to Walter Scott, to millionaire malefactors,—a suggestion of acrobatic tumbling and somersault; but he always got a hearing. In lecturing to the students of a military academy he had the pleasing audacity to begin:
But Ruskin's decision to speak with "great plainness" by no means made the people of England attend to what he said rather than the way he said it. He could be, and in his later work he usually was, strong and clear; but the old picturesqueness and exuberance of passion were with him still. The public discovered that it enjoyed Ruskin's denunciations of machinery much as it had enjoyed his descriptions of mountains, and, without obviously mending its ways, called loudly for more. Lecture-rooms were crowded and editions exhausted by the ladies and gentlemen of England, whose nerves were pleasantly thrilled with a gentle surprise on being told that they had despised literature, art, science, nature, and compassion, and that what they thought upon any subject was "a matter of no serious importance"; that they could not be said to have any thoughts at all—indeed, no right to think.[19] The fiercer his anathemas, the greater the applause; the louder he shouted, the better he pleased. Let him split the ears of the groundlings, let him out-Herod Herod,—the judicious might grieve, but all would be excitedly attentive. Their Jeremiah seemed at times like to become a jester,—there was a suggestion of the ludicrous in the sudden passage from birds to Greek coins, to mills, to Walter Scott, to millionaire malefactors,—a suggestion of acrobatic tumbling and somersault; but he always got a hearing. In lecturing to the students of a military academy he had the pleasing audacity to begin:
"Young soldiers, I do not doubt but that many of you came unwillingly to-night, and many of you in merely contemptuous curiosity, to hear what a writer on painting could possibly say, or would venture to say, respecting your great art of war";[20]
"Young soldiers, I do not doubt but that many of you came unwillingly to-night, and many of you in merely contemptuous curiosity, to hear what a writer on painting could possibly say, or would venture to say, respecting your great art of war";[20]
after which stinging challenge, one has no doubt, any feeling of offense was swallowed up in admiration of the speaker's physical courage.
after that stinging challenge, there's no doubt that any feeling of offense was overshadowed by admiration for the speaker's physical bravery.
Influence of Carlyle upon Ruskin.
Carlyle's influence on Ruskin.
The unity of Ruskin's style.
The cohesiveness of Ruskin's style.
There can be little doubt that this later manner in which Ruskin allowed his Puritan instincts to defeat his aestheticism, and indulged to an alarming degree his gift of vituperation, was profoundly influenced by his "master," Carlyle, who had long since passed into his later and raucous manner. Carlyle's delight in the disciple's diatribes probably encouraged the younger man in a vehemence of invective to which his love of dogmatic assertion already rendered him too prone. At his best, Ruskin, like Carlyle, reminds us of a major prophet; at his worst he shrieks and heats the air. His high indignations lead him into all manner of absurdity and self-contradiction. An amusing instance of this may be given from Sesame and Lilies. In the first lecture, which, it will be recalled, was given in aid of a library fund, we find[21] the remark, "We are filthy and foolish enough to thumb one another's books out of circulating libraries." His friends and his enemies, the clergy (who "teach a false gospel for hire") and the scientists, the merchants and the universities, Darwin and Dante, all had their share in the indignant lecturer's indiscriminate abuse. And yet in all the tropical luxuriance of his inconsistency, one can never doubt the man's sincerity. He never wrote for effect. He may dazzle us, but his fire is never pyrotechnical; it always springs from the deep volcanic heart of him. His was a fervor too easily stirred and often ill-directed, but its wild brilliance cannot long be mistaken for the sky-rocket's; it flares madly in all directions, now beautifying, now appalling, the night, the fine ardor of the painter passing into the fierce invective of the prophet. But in the end it is seen that Ruskin's style, like his subject-matter, is a unity,—an emanation from a divine enthusiasm making for "whatsoever things are lovely, whatsoever things are pure, whatsoever things are of good report."
There can be little doubt that this later manner in which Ruskin allowed his Puritan instincts to defeat his aestheticism, and indulged to an alarming degree his gift of vituperation, was profoundly influenced by his "master," Carlyle, who had long since passed into his later and raucous manner. Carlyle's delight in the disciple's diatribes probably encouraged the younger man in a vehemence of invective to which his love of dogmatic assertion already rendered him too prone. At his best, Ruskin, like Carlyle, reminds us of a major prophet; at his worst he shrieks and heats the air. His high indignations lead him into all manner of absurdity and self-contradiction. An amusing instance of this may be given from Sesame and Lilies. In the first lecture, which, it will be recalled, was given in aid of a library fund, we find[21] the remark, "We are filthy and foolish enough to thumb one another's books out of circulating libraries." His friends and his enemies, the clergy (who "teach a false gospel for hire") and the scientists, the merchants and the universities, Darwin and Dante, all had their share in the indignant lecturer's indiscriminate abuse. And yet in all the tropical luxuriance of his inconsistency, one can never doubt the man's sincerity. He never wrote for effect. He may dazzle us, but his fire is never pyrotechnical; it always springs from the deep volcanic heart of him. His was a fervor too easily stirred and often ill-directed, but its wild brilliance cannot long be mistaken for the sky-rocket's; it flares madly in all directions, now beautifying, now appalling, the night, the fine ardor of the painter passing into the fierce invective of the prophet. But in the end it is seen that Ruskin's style, like his subject-matter, is a unity,—an emanation from a divine enthusiasm making for "whatsoever things are lovely, whatsoever things are pure, whatsoever things are of good report."
Selections from Modern Painters
Selections from Modern Painters
The five volumes of Modern Painters appeared at various intervals between 1843 and 1860, from the time Ruskin was twenty-four until he was forty. The first volume was published in May, 1843; the second, in April, 1846; the third, January 15, 1856; the fourth, April 14, 1856; the last, in June, 1860. As his knowledge of his subject broadened and deepened, we find the later volumes differing greatly in viewpoint and style from the earlier; but, as stated in the preface to the last volume, "in the main aim and principle of the book there is no variation, from its first syllable to its last." Ruskin himself maintained that the most important influence upon his thought in preparation for his work in Modern Painters was not from his "love of art, but of mountains and seas"; and all the power of judgment he had obtained in art, he ascribed to his "steady habit of always looking for the subject principally, and for the art only as the means of expressing it." The first volume was published as the work of "a graduate of Oxford," Ruskin "fearing that I might not obtain fair hearing if the reader knew my youth." The author's proud father did not allow the secret to be kept long. The title Ruskin originally chose for the volume was Turner and the Ancients. To this Smith, Elder & Co., his publishers, objected, and the substitution of Modern Painters was their suggestion The following is the title-page of the first volume in the original edition:
The five volumes of Modern Painters were released at different times between 1843 and 1860, covering the period from when Ruskin was twenty-four to when he was forty. The first volume came out in May 1843; the second in April 1846; the third on January 15, 1856; the fourth on April 14, 1856; and the final one in June 1860. As his understanding of the subject expanded and deepened, the later volumes varied significantly in perspective and style from the earlier ones; however, as mentioned in the preface to the last volume, "in the main aim and principle of the book there is no variation, from its first syllable to its last." Ruskin himself claimed that the greatest influence on his thinking while preparing for Modern Painters came not from his "love of art, but of mountains and seas"; and he credited all of his artistic judgment to his "consistent habit of always focusing on the subject primarily, and viewing art only as a way to express it." The first volume was published under the name of "a graduate of Oxford," as Ruskin "feared that I might not obtain fair hearing if the reader knew my youth." The author's proud father did not keep this secret for long. The title Ruskin originally chose for the volume was Turner and the Ancients. To this, Smith, Elder & Co., his publishers, objected, and the title Modern Painters was their suggestion. The following is the title page of the first volume from the original edition:
MODERN PAINTERS:
Their Superiority
In the Art of Landscape Painting
To all
The Ancient Masters
proved by examples of
The True, the Beautiful, and the Intellectual,
From the
Works of Modern Artists, especially
From those of J.M.W. Turner,
Esq., R.A.
By a Graduate of Oxford
(Quotation from Wordsworth)
London: Smith, Elder & Co., 65 Cornhill.
1843.
MODERN PAINTERS:
Their Superiority
In the Art of Landscape Painting
To all
The Ancient Masters
proven through examples of
The True, the Beautiful, and the Intellectual,
From the
Works of Modern Artists, especially
From those of J.M.W. Turner,
Esq., R.A.
By a Graduate of Oxford
(Quotation from Wordsworth)
London: Smith, Elder & Co., 65 Cornhill.
1843.
THE EARTH-VEIL
VOLUME V, CHAPTER I
That, then, was to be our work. Alas! what work have we set ourselves upon instead! How have we ravaged the garden instead of kept it—feeding our war-horses with its flowers, and splintering its trees into spear-shafts!
That was supposed to be our task. Unfortunately! What have we done instead? We have destroyed the garden instead of taking care of it—feeding our war horses with its flowers and turning its trees into spear shafts!
Is its flame quenchless? and are those gates that keep the way indeed passable no more? or is it not rather that we no more desire to enter? For what can we conceive of that first Eden which we might not yet win back, if we chose? It was a place full of flowers, we say. Well: the flowers are always striving to grow wherever we suffer them; and the fairer, the closer. There may, indeed, have been a Fall of Flowers, as a Fall of Man; but assuredly creatures such as we are can now fancy nothing lovelier than roses and lilies, which would grow for us side by side, leaf overlapping leaf, till the Earth was white and red with them, if we cared to have it so. And Paradise was full of pleasant shades and fruitful avenues. Well: what hinders us from covering as much of the world as we like with pleasant shade, and pure blossom, and goodly fruit? Who forbids its valleys to be covered over with corn till they laugh and sing? Who prevents its dark forests, ghostly and uninhabitable, from being changed into infinite orchards, wreathing the hills with frail-floreted snow, far away to the half-lighted horizon of April, and flushing the face of all the autumnal earth with glow of clustered food? But Paradise was a place of peace, we say, and all the animals were gentle servants to us. Well: the world would yet be a place of peace if we were all peacemakers, and gentle service should we have of its creatures if we gave them gentle mastery. But so long as we make sport of slaying bird and beast, so long as we choose to contend rather with our fellows than with our faults, and make battlefield of our meadows instead of pasture—so long, truly, the Flaming Sword will still turn every way, and the gates of Eden remain barred close enough, till we have sheathed the sharper flame of our own passions, and broken down the closer gates of our own hearts.
Is its flame unquenchable? And are those gates that lead the way really impossible to pass? Or is it more that we simply no longer want to enter? What can we imagine about that first Eden that we couldn’t reclaim if we wanted? It was a place full of flowers, we say. Well, flowers always try to grow wherever we let them; and the prettier, the closer. There may have been a Fall of Flowers, just like a Fall of Man; but surely, beings like us can only imagine nothing lovelier than roses and lilies, which would grow for us side by side, leaves overlapping leaves, until the Earth was covered in white and red with them, if we wanted it that way. And Paradise was filled with pleasant shade and fruitful paths. So what stops us from covering as much of the world as we want with pleasant shade, pure blossoms, and good fruits? Who forbids its valleys from being filled with grain until they laugh and sing? Who prevents its dark forests, spooky and unlivable, from being transformed into endless orchards, draping the hills in delicate floral snow, stretching far to the half-lit horizon of April, and brightening the face of all the autumn earth with clusters of food? But we say Paradise was a peaceful place, and all the animals were gentle companions to us. Well, the world could still be a place of peace if we were all peacemakers, and we would have gentle service from its creatures if we offered them gentle leadership. But as long as we delight in killing bird and beast, as long as we choose to struggle against our fellow humans rather than our flaws, and turn our meadows into battlefields instead of pastures—truly, the Flaming Sword will continue to turn in every direction, and the gates of Eden will remain locked tight, until we have sheathed the sharper flames of our own desires and broken down the locked gates of our own hearts.
I have been led to see and feel this more and more, as I consider the service which the flowers and trees, which man was at first appointed to keep, were intended to render to him in return for his care; and the services they still render to him, as far as he allows their influence, or fulfils his own task towards them. For what infinite wonderfulness there is in this vegetation, considered, as indeed it is, as the means by which the earth becomes the companion of man—his friend and his teacher! In the conditions which we have traced in its rocks, there could only be seen preparation for his existence;—the characters which enable him to live on it safely, and to work with it easily—in all these it has been inanimate and passive; but vegetation is to it as an imperfect soul, given to meet the soul of man. The earth in its depths must remain dead and cold, incapable except of slow crystalline change; but at its surface, which human beings look upon and deal with, it ministers to them through a veil of strange intermediate being: which breathes, but has no voice; moves, but cannot leave its appointed place; passes through life without consciousness, to death without bitterness; wears the beauty of youth, without its passion; and declines to the weakness of age, without its regret.
I’ve come to see and feel this more and more as I think about the way flowers and trees, which humans were originally meant to care for, were intended to give back to them in return for that care; and the services they still provide, as much as people allow their influence or fulfill their part in caring for them. There’s so much wonder in this plant life, seen as the way the earth becomes a companion to humans—both a friend and a teacher! In the conditions we've observed in its rocks, we only see preparation for human existence;—the qualities that enable people to live safely on it and work with it easily—through all this, it has been lifeless and passive; but plant life is like an imperfect soul, created to connect with the soul of humanity. The depths of the earth remain dead and cold, capable only of slow crystalline change; but at its surface, which humans interact with, it serves them through a veil of strange intermediate existence: it breathes but has no voice; it moves but cannot leave its designated spot; it goes through life without awareness, facing death without bitterness; it displays the beauty of youth without its passion; and it declines into the frailty of old age without regret.
And in this mystery of intermediate being, entirely subordinate to us, with which we can deal as we choose, having just the greater power as we have the less responsibility for our treatment of the unsuffering creature, most of the pleasures which we need from the external world are gathered, and most of the lessons we need are written, all kinds of precious grace and teaching being united in this link between the Earth and Man; wonderful in universal adaptation to his need, desire, and discipline; God's daily preparation of the earth for him, with beautiful means of life. First, a carpet to make it soft for him; then, a coloured fantasy of embroidery thereon; then, tall spreading of foliage to shade him from sun heat, and shade also the fallen rain; that it may not dry quickly back into the clouds, but stay to nourish the springs among the moss. Stout wood to bear this leafage: easily to be cut, yet tough and light, to make houses for him, or instruments (lance-shaft, or plough-handle, according to his temper); useless, it had been, if harder; useless, if less fibrous; useless, if less elastic. Winter comes, and the shade of leafage falls away, to let the sun warm the earth; the strong boughs remain, breaking the strength of winter winds. The seeds which are to prolong the race, innumerable according to the need, are made beautiful and palatable, varied into infinitude of appeal to the fancy of man, or provision for his service: cold juice, or glowing spice, or balm, or incense, softening oil, preserving resin, medicine of styptic, febrifuge, or lulling charm: and all these presented in forms of endless change. Fragility or force, softness and strength, in all degrees and aspects; unerring uprightness, as of temple pillars, or unguided wandering of feeble tendrils on the ground; mighty resistances of rigid arm and limb to the storms of ages, or wavings to and fro with faintest pulse of summer streamlet. Roots cleaving the strength of rock, or binding the transience of the sand; crests basking in sunshine of the desert, or hiding by dripping spring and lightless cave; foliage far tossing in entangled fields beneath every wave of ocean—clothing, with variegated, everlasting films, the peaks of the trackless mountains, or ministering at cottage doors to every gentlest passion and simplest joy of humanity.
And in this mystery of being that exists between what’s real and what’s not, completely dependent on us, which we can handle however we choose, having more power and less responsibility for how we treat the innocent creature, most of the pleasures we need from the outside world are collected, and most of the lessons we need are recorded. All kinds of valuable grace and teaching come together in this connection between Earth and humanity; it’s amazing how perfectly it adapts to our needs, desires, and growth; it's God's daily preparation of the earth for us, providing beautiful resources for life. First, there’s a soft carpet for comfort; then, a colorful design like embroidery on top; then, tall branches provide shade from the heat of the sun, as well as sheltering the rain that falls, so it doesn’t quickly evaporate back into the clouds, but stays to nourish the springs in the moss. Sturdy wood supports this foliage: easy to cut, yet strong and light, perfect for building homes or making tools (like a lance-shaft or a plough-handle, depending on his needs); it would be useless if it were harder, less fibrous, or less elastic. Winter arrives, and the foliage disappears to allow the sun to warm the ground; the strong branches remain, blocking the fierce winter winds. The seeds needed for the continuation of the species, countless in number according to need, are made beautiful and tasty, varying endlessly to appeal to human whims or serve his purposes: cold juice, vibrant spice, balm, or incense, soothing oil, preserving resin, medicine for stopping bleeding, fever reducer, or calming charm: all presented in constantly changing forms. There’s fragility or strength, softness and toughness, in all shapes and sizes; unyielding uprightness, like temple pillars, or the aimless sway of weak tendrils on the ground; mighty resistance of stiff limbs against the storms throughout the ages, or gentle swaying with the slightest pulse of a summer stream. Roots hold onto the strength of rocks, or anchor the shifting sands; peaks bask under the desert sun, or hide near dripping springs and dark caves; foliage sways amid tangled fields beneath every wave of the ocean—clothing the peaks of the uncharted mountains with colorful, everlasting layers, or serving at the doors of cottages to fulfill every gentle passion and simple joy of humanity.
Being thus prepared for us in all ways, and made beautiful, and good for food, and for building, and for instruments in our hands, this race of plants, deserving boundless affection and admiration from us, becomes, in proportion to their obtaining it, a nearly perfect test of our being in right temper of mind and way of life; so that no one can be far wrong in either who loves the trees enough, and every one is assuredly wrong in both who does not love them, if his life has brought them in his way. It is clearly possible to do without them, for the great companionship of the sea and sky are all that sailors need; and many a noble heart has been taught the best it had to learn between dark stone walls. Still if human life be cast among trees at all, the love borne to them is a sure test of its purity. And it is a sorrowful proof of the mistaken ways of the world that the "country," in the simple sense of a place of fields and trees, has hitherto been the source of reproach to its inhabitants, and that the words "countryman, rustic, clown, paysan, villager," still signify a rude and untaught person, as opposed to the words "townsman" and "citizen". We accept this usage of words, or the evil which it signifies, somewhat too quietly; as if it were quite necessary and natural that country-people should be rude, and townspeople gentle. Whereas I believe that the result of each mode of life may, in some stages of the world's progress, be the exact reverse; and that another use of words may be forced upon us by a new aspect of facts, so that we may find ourselves saying: "Such and such a person is very gentle and kind—he is quite rustic; and such and such another person is very rude and ill-taught—he is quite urbane."
Being prepared for us in every way, and beautiful, and good for food, and for building, and for tools in our hands, this group of plants, deserving our endless love and admiration, becomes, as they receive it, a nearly perfect measure of our mindset and way of life; so that no one can be too far off in either if they love the trees enough, and everyone is definitely wrong in both if they don’t love them, if they have come into their lives. It’s definitely possible to live without them, since the vast companionship of the sea and sky is all that sailors need; and many noble hearts have learned their best lessons between dark stone walls. Still, if human life is among trees at all, the love we have for them is a reliable test of its purity. It’s a sad testament to the mistaken views of the world that “country,” simply understood as a place of fields and trees, has historically been seen as a source of shame for its inhabitants, and that the words “countryman, rustic, clown, paysan, villager” still imply a rough and uneducated person, in contrast to the words “townsman” and “citizen.” We accept this language, or the negativity it represents, a bit too quietly; as if it were completely necessary and natural for country people to be crude and for townspeople to be refined. However, I believe that the outcome of each way of life may, in some stages of the world’s development, be just the opposite; and that we may be forced to adopt a different use of words due to new realities, so that we might find ourselves saying: “This person is very gentle and kind—he is quite rustic; and that person is very rude and unrefined—he is quite urbane.”
At all events, cities have hitherto gained the better part of their good report through our evil ways of going on in the world generally; chiefly and eminently through our bad habit of fighting with each other. No field, in the Middle Ages, being safe from devastation, and every country lane yielding easier passage to the marauders, peacefully-minded men necessarily congregated in cities, and walled themselves in, making as few cross-country roads as possible: while the men who sowed and reaped the harvests of Europe were only the servants or slaves of the barons. The disdain of all agricultural pursuits by the nobility, and of all plain facts by the monks, kept educated Europe in a state of mind over which natural phenomena could have no power; body and intellect being lost in the practice of war without purpose, and the meditation of words without meaning. Men learned the dexterity with sword and syllogism, which they mistook for education, within cloister and tilt-yard; and looked on all the broad space of the world of God mainly as a place for exercise of horses, or for growth of food.
In any case, cities have mostly gained their positive reputation thanks to our bad behavior in the world overall; especially our terrible habit of fighting amongst ourselves. No area was safe from destruction during the Middle Ages, and every country road made it easier for marauders to invade. Peaceful people had no choice but to gather in cities and build walls around themselves, creating as few cross-country roads as possible. Meanwhile, those who farmed and harvested Europe were merely the servants or slaves of the barons. The nobility's disdain for agriculture and the monks' disregard for straightforward truths kept educated Europe in a mindset untouched by natural events; both body and mind were trapped in pointless warfare and meaningless pondering. Men developed skills in swordplay and logic, which they confused for education, within the confines of monasteries and tournament fields, viewing the vastness of God's world mainly as a place for horse exercise or food production.
There is a beautiful type of this neglect of the perfectness of the Earth's beauty, by reason of the passions of men, in that picture of Paul Uccello's of the battle of Sant' Egidio,[23] in which the armies meet on a country road beside a hedge of wild roses; the tender red flowers tossing above the helmets, and glowing beneath the lowered lances. For in like manner the whole of Nature only shone hitherto for man between the tossing of helmet-crests; and sometimes I cannot but think of the trees of the earth as capable of a kind of sorrow, in that imperfect life of theirs, as they opened their innocent leaves in the warm springtime, in vain for men; and all along the dells of England her beeches cast their dappled shade only where the outlaw drew his bow, and the king rode his careless chase; and by the sweet French rivers their long ranks of poplar waved in the twilight, only to show the flames of burning cities on the horizon, through the tracery of their stems; amidst the fair defiles of the Apennines, the twisted olive-trunks hid the ambushes of treachery; and on their valley meadows, day by day, the lilies which were white at the dawn were washed with crimson at sunset.
There is a beautiful type of this neglect of the perfectness of the Earth's beauty, by reason of the passions of men, in that picture of Paul Uccello's of the battle of Sant' Egidio,[23] in which the armies meet on a country road beside a hedge of wild roses; the tender red flowers tossing above the helmets, and glowing beneath the lowered lances. For in like manner the whole of Nature only shone hitherto for man between the tossing of helmet-crests; and sometimes I cannot but think of the trees of the earth as capable of a kind of sorrow, in that imperfect life of theirs, as they opened their innocent leaves in the warm springtime, in vain for men; and all along the dells of England her beeches cast their dappled shade only where the outlaw drew his bow, and the king rode his careless chase; and by the sweet French rivers their long ranks of poplar waved in the twilight, only to show the flames of burning cities on the horizon, through the tracery of their stems; amidst the fair defiles of the Apennines, the twisted olive-trunks hid the ambushes of treachery; and on their valley meadows, day by day, the lilies which were white at the dawn were washed with crimson at sunset.
And indeed I had once purposed, in this work, to show what kind of evidence existed respecting the possible influence of country life on men; it seeming to me, then, likely that here and there a reader would perceive this to be a grave question, more than most which we contend about, political or social, and might care to follow it out with me earnestly.
And I had originally planned, in this work, to demonstrate what kind of evidence there is regarding the potential impact of rural living on people; it seemed to me that some readers would see this as an important question, more significant than most of the political or social debates we engage in, and might want to explore it with me seriously.
The day will assuredly come when men will see that it is a grave question; at which period, also, I doubt not, there will arise persons able to investigate it. For the present, the movements of the world seem little likely to be influenced by botanical law; or by any other considerations respecting trees, than the probable price of timber. I shall limit myself, therefore, to my own simple woodman's work, and try to hew this book into its final shape, with the limited and humble aim that I had in beginning it, namely, to prove how far the idle and peaceable persons, who have hitherto cared about leaves and clouds, have rightly seen, or faithfully reported of them.
The day will definitely come when people will realize that it is a serious issue; at that time, I'm sure there will be individuals capable of exploring it. For now, it seems unlikely that the movements of the world will be affected by botanical principles, or by any other concerns regarding trees, beyond the potential price of lumber. So, I will focus on my own straightforward task as a woodsman and work to shape this book into its final form, with the simple and humble goal I had when I started it, which is to show how accurately the idle and peaceful people, who have been interested in leaves and clouds, have perceived or reported on them.
THE MOUNTAIN GLORY
VOLUME IV, CHAPTER 20
I have dwelt, in the foregoing chapter, on the sadness of the hills with the greater insistence that I feared my own excessive love for them might lead me into too favourable interpretation of their influences over the human heart; or, at least, that the reader might accuse me of fond prejudice, in the conclusions to which, finally, I desire to lead him concerning them. For, to myself, mountains are the beginning and the end of all natural scenery; in them, and in the forms of inferior landscape that lead to them, my affections are wholly bound up; and though I can look with happy admiration at the lowland flowers, and woods, and open skies, the happiness is tranquil and cold, like that of examining detached flowers in a conservatory, or reading a pleasant book; and if the scenery be resolutely level, insisting upon the declaration of its own flatness in all the detail of it, as in Holland, or Lincolnshire, or Central Lombardy, it appears to me like a prison, and I cannot long endure it. But the slightest rise and fall in the road,—a mossy bank at the side of a crag of chalk, with brambles at its brow, overhanging it,—a ripple over three or four stones in the stream by the bridge,—above all, a wild bit of ferny ground under a fir or two, looking as if, possibly, one might see a hill if one got to the other side of the trees, will instantly give me intense delight, because the shadow, or the hope, of the hills is in them.
I talked in the previous chapter about the sadness of the hills, emphasizing my concern that my deep affection for them might make me interpret their impact on the human heart too positively. I also worried that readers might think I have a biased view in the conclusions I want to guide them toward regarding these landscapes. To me, mountains represent the beginning and end of all natural beauty; my feelings are completely tied to them and to the lesser landscapes that lead up to them. While I can admire lowland flowers, woods, and open skies with a sense of calm happiness, it feels more like observing flowers in a greenhouse or reading a nice book. If the scenery is completely flat, making its lack of elevation clear in every detail, as seen in places like Holland, Lincolnshire, or Central Lombardy, it feels like a prison, and I can’t stand it for long. However, even the slightest rise and fall in the road—a mossy bank next to a chalk cliff with brambles on top, a ripple over a few stones in a stream by a bridge, or a wild patch of ferns under a couple of fir trees that makes me think I might see a hill if I go around the trees—brings me immense joy, because the shadow or the promise of the hills is present in them.
And thus, although there are few districts of Northern Europe, however apparently dull or tame, in which I cannot find pleasure, though the whole of Northern France (except Champagne), dull as it seems to most travellers, is to me a perpetual Paradise; and, putting Lincolnshire, Leicestershire, and one or two such other perfectly flat districts aside, there is not an English county which I should not find entertainment in exploring the cross-roads of, foot by foot; yet all my best enjoyment would be owing to the imagination of the hills, colouring, with their far-away memories, every lowland stone and herb. The pleasant French coteau, green in the sunshine, delights me, either by what real mountain character it has in itself (for in extent and succession of promontory the flanks of the French valleys have quite the sublimity of true mountain distances), or by its broken ground and rugged steps among the vines, and rise of the leafage above, against the blue sky, as it might rise at Vevay or Como. There is not a wave of the Seine but is associated in my mind with the first rise of the sandstones and forest pines of Fontaine-bleau; and with the hope of the Alps, as one leaves Paris with the horses' heads to the south-west, the morning sun flashing on the bright waves at Charenton. If there be no hope or association of this kind, and if I cannot deceive myself into fancying that perhaps at the next rise of the road there may be seen the film of a blue hill in the gleam of sky at the horizon, the landscape, however beautiful, produces in me even a kind of sickness and pain; and the whole view from Richmond Hill or Windsor Terrace,—nay, the gardens of Alcinous, with their perpetual summer,—or of the Hesperides (if they were flat, and not close to Atlas), golden apples and all,—I would give away in an instant, for one mossy granite stone a foot broad, and two leaves of lady-fern.[24]
And thus, although there are few districts of Northern Europe, however apparently dull or tame, in which I cannot find pleasure, though the whole of Northern France (except Champagne), dull as it seems to most travellers, is to me a perpetual Paradise; and, putting Lincolnshire, Leicestershire, and one or two such other perfectly flat districts aside, there is not an English county which I should not find entertainment in exploring the cross-roads of, foot by foot; yet all my best enjoyment would be owing to the imagination of the hills, colouring, with their far-away memories, every lowland stone and herb. The pleasant French coteau, green in the sunshine, delights me, either by what real mountain character it has in itself (for in extent and succession of promontory the flanks of the French valleys have quite the sublimity of true mountain distances), or by its broken ground and rugged steps among the vines, and rise of the leafage above, against the blue sky, as it might rise at Vevay or Como. There is not a wave of the Seine but is associated in my mind with the first rise of the sandstones and forest pines of Fontaine-bleau; and with the hope of the Alps, as one leaves Paris with the horses' heads to the south-west, the morning sun flashing on the bright waves at Charenton. If there be no hope or association of this kind, and if I cannot deceive myself into fancying that perhaps at the next rise of the road there may be seen the film of a blue hill in the gleam of sky at the horizon, the landscape, however beautiful, produces in me even a kind of sickness and pain; and the whole view from Richmond Hill or Windsor Terrace,—nay, the gardens of Alcinous, with their perpetual summer,—or of the Hesperides (if they were flat, and not close to Atlas), golden apples and all,—I would give away in an instant, for one mossy granite stone a foot broad, and two leaves of lady-fern.[24]
I know that this is in great part idiosyncrasy; and that I must not trust to my own feelings, in this respect, as representative of the modern landscape instinct: yet I know it is not idiosyncrasy, in so far as there may be proved to be indeed an increase of the absolute beauty of all scenery in exact proportion to its mountainous character, providing that character be healthily mountainous. I do not mean to take the Col de Bonhomme as representative of hills, any more than I would take Romney Marsh as representative of plains; but putting Leicestershire or Staffordshire fairly beside Westmoreland, and Lombardy or Champagne fairly beside the Pays de Vaud or the Canton Berne, I find the increase in the calculable sum of elements of beauty to be steadily in proportion to the increase of mountainous character; and that the best image which the world can give of Paradise is in the slope of the meadows, orchards, and corn-fields on the sides of a great Alp, with its purple rocks and eternal snows above; this excellence not being in any wise a matter referable to feeling, or individual preferences, but demonstrable by calm enumeration of the number of lovely colours on the rocks, the varied grouping of the trees, and quantity of noble incidents in stream, crag, or cloud, presented to the eye at any given moment.
I realize that this is mostly just my personal opinion; and that I shouldn't rely on my own feelings as a representation of modern landscape instinct: still, I believe it's not just personal opinion since it can be shown that there really is an increase in the overall beauty of all scenery in direct relation to its mountainous features, as long as those features are healthily mountainous. I don't mean to use the Col de Bonhomme as an example of hills, any more than I would use Romney Marsh as an example of plains; but when I compare Leicestershire or Staffordshire with Westmoreland, and Lombardy or Champagne with the Pays de Vaud or the Canton Berne, I see that the measurable sum of beauty steadily increases in proportion to the prominence of mountainous characteristics. The best image of paradise that the world can present is the slope of meadows, orchards, and cornfields on the sides of a grand Alp, with its purple rocks and eternal snows above; this excellence isn't really about feelings or personal preferences, but can be clearly demonstrated by a calm analysis of the lovely colors on the rocks, the varied arrangement of the trees, and the numerous beautiful details in streams, cliffs, or clouds that we can see at any moment.
For consider, first, the difference produced in the whole tone of landscape colour by the introductions of purple, violet, and deep ultramarine blue, which we owe to mountains. In an ordinary lowland landscape we have the blue of the sky; the green of grass, which I will suppose (and this is an unnecessary concession to the lowlands) entirely fresh and bright; the green of trees; and certain elements of purple, far more rich and beautiful than we generally should think, in their bark and shadows (bare hedges and thickets, or tops of trees, in subdued afternoon sunshine, are nearly perfect purple, and of an exquisite tone), as well as in ploughed fields, and dark ground in general. But among mountains, in addition to all this, large unbroken spaces of pure violet and purple are introduced in their distances; and even near, by films of cloud passing over the darkness of ravines or forests, blues are produced of the most subtle tenderness; these azures and purples[25] passing into rose-colour of otherwise wholly unattainable delicacy among the upper summits, the blue of the sky being at the same time purer and deeper than in the plains. Nay, in some sense, a person who has never seen the rose-colour of the rays of dawn crossing a blue mountain twelve or fifteen miles away, can hardly be said to know what tenderness in colour means at all; bright tenderness he may, indeed, see in the sky or in a flower, but this grave tenderness of the far-away hill-purples he cannot conceive.
For consider, first, the difference produced in the whole tone of landscape colour by the introductions of purple, violet, and deep ultramarine blue, which we owe to mountains. In an ordinary lowland landscape we have the blue of the sky; the green of grass, which I will suppose (and this is an unnecessary concession to the lowlands) entirely fresh and bright; the green of trees; and certain elements of purple, far more rich and beautiful than we generally should think, in their bark and shadows (bare hedges and thickets, or tops of trees, in subdued afternoon sunshine, are nearly perfect purple, and of an exquisite tone), as well as in ploughed fields, and dark ground in general. But among mountains, in addition to all this, large unbroken spaces of pure violet and purple are introduced in their distances; and even near, by films of cloud passing over the darkness of ravines or forests, blues are produced of the most subtle tenderness; these azures and purples[25] passing into rose-colour of otherwise wholly unattainable delicacy among the upper summits, the blue of the sky being at the same time purer and deeper than in the plains. Nay, in some sense, a person who has never seen the rose-colour of the rays of dawn crossing a blue mountain twelve or fifteen miles away, can hardly be said to know what tenderness in colour means at all; bright tenderness he may, indeed, see in the sky or in a flower, but this grave tenderness of the far-away hill-purples he cannot conceive.
Together with this great source of pre-eminence in mass of colour, we have to estimate the influence of the finished inlaying and enamel-work of the colour-jewellery on every stone; and that of the continual variety in species of flower; most of the mountain flowers being, besides, separately lovelier than the lowland ones. The wood hyacinth and wild rose are, indeed, the only supreme flowers that the lowlands can generally show; and the wild rose is also a mountaineer, and more fragrant in the hills, while the wood hyacinth, or grape hyacinth, at its best cannot match even the dark bell-gentian, leaving the light-blue star-gentian in its uncontested queenliness, and the Alpine rose and Highland heather wholly without similitude. The violet, lily of the valley, crocus, and wood anemone are, I suppose, claimable partly by the plains as well as the hills; but the large orange lily and narcissus I have never seen but on hill pastures, and the exquisite oxalisis pre-eminently a mountaineer.[26]
Together with this great source of pre-eminence in mass of colour, we have to estimate the influence of the finished inlaying and enamel-work of the colour-jewellery on every stone; and that of the continual variety in species of flower; most of the mountain flowers being, besides, separately lovelier than the lowland ones. The wood hyacinth and wild rose are, indeed, the only supreme flowers that the lowlands can generally show; and the wild rose is also a mountaineer, and more fragrant in the hills, while the wood hyacinth, or grape hyacinth, at its best cannot match even the dark bell-gentian, leaving the light-blue star-gentian in its uncontested queenliness, and the Alpine rose and Highland heather wholly without similitude. The violet, lily of the valley, crocus, and wood anemone are, I suppose, claimable partly by the plains as well as the hills; but the large orange lily and narcissus I have never seen but on hill pastures, and the exquisite oxalisis pre-eminently a mountaineer.[26]
To this supremacy in mosses and flowers we have next to add an inestimable gain in the continual presence and power of water. Neither in its clearness, its colour, its fantasy of motion, its calmness of space, depth, and reflection, or its wrath, can water be conceived by a lowlander, out of sight of sea. A sea wave is far grander than any torrent—but of the sea and its influences we are not now speaking; and the sea itself, though it can be clear, is never calm, among our shores, in the sense that a mountain lake can be calm. The sea seems only to pause; the mountain lake to sleep, and to dream. Out of sight of the ocean a lowlander cannot be considered ever to have seen water at all. The mantling of the pools in the rock shadows, with the golden flakes of light sinking down through them like falling leaves, the ringing of the thin currents among the shallows, the flash and the cloud of the cascade, the earthquake and foam-fire of the cataract, the long lines of alternate mirror and mist that lull the imagery of the hills reversed in the blue of morning,—all these things belong to those hills as their undivided inheritance.
To the dominance of mosses and flowers, we must also add the invaluable benefit of the constant presence and power of water. A lowlander, out of sight of the sea, can’t fully grasp water in all its clarity, color, movement, tranquility, depth, reflection, or fury. A sea wave is much more impressive than any river, but we’re not discussing the sea and its effects right now; and the sea itself, while it can be clear, is never calm along our shores in the same way a mountain lake can be calm. The sea seems to merely pause, while the mountain lake appears to sleep and dream. A lowlander, away from the ocean, can never truly say they’ve experienced water at all. The way light dances on the pools in rocky shadows like falling leaves, the sound of gentle currents in the shallows, the burst of a waterfall, the chaos of rapids, and the long stretches of shimmering reflections and mist that soothe the mirrored images of hills in the morning blue—these elements belong to those hills as their exclusive legacy.
To this supremacy in wave and stream is joined a no less manifest pre-eminence in the character of trees. It is possible among plains, in the species of trees which properly belong to them, the poplars of Amiens, for instance, to obtain a serene simplicity of grace, which, as I said, is a better help to the study of gracefulness, as such, than any of the wilder groupings of the hills; so, also, there are certain conditions of symmetrical luxuriance developed in the park and avenue, rarely rivalled in their way among mountains; and yet the mountain superiority in foliage is, on the whole, nearly as complete as it is in water: for exactly as there are some expressions in the broad reaches of a navigable lowland river, such as the Loire or Thames, not, in their way, to be matched among the rock rivers, and yet for all that a lowlander cannot be said to have truly seen the element of water at all; so even in the richest parks and avenues he cannot be said to have truly seen trees. For the resources of trees are not developed until they have difficulty to contend with; neither their tenderness of brotherly love and harmony, till they are forced to choose their ways of various life where there is contracted room for them, talking to each other with their restrained branches. The various action of trees rooting themselves in inhospitable rocks, stooping to look into ravines, hiding from the search of glacier winds, reaching forth to the rays of rare sunshine, crowding down together to drink at sweetest streams, climbing hand in hand among the difficult slopes, opening in sudden dances round the mossy knolls, gathering into companies at rest among the fragrant fields, gliding in grave procession over the heavenward ridges—nothing of this can be conceived among the unvexed and unvaried felicities of the lowland forest: while to all these direct sources of greater beauty are added, first the power of redundance,—the mere quantity of foliage visible in the folds and on the promontories of a single Alp being greater than that of an entire lowland landscape (unless a view from some cathedral tower); and to this charm of redundance, that of clearer visibility,—tree after tree being constantly shown in successive height, one behind another, instead of the mere tops and flanks of masses, as in the plains; and the forms of multitudes of them continually defined against the clear sky, near and above, or against white clouds entangled among their branches, instead of being confused in dimness of distance.
To this dominance in water and rivers is added a clear superiority in the characteristics of trees. It's possible, in flat areas, to find certain types of trees that belong there—like the poplars of Amiens—that offer a calm simplicity of grace. As I mentioned, this is more beneficial for studying grace than the wilder arrangements found in the hills. Similarly, there are conditions of balanced richness created in parks and along avenues, which are rarely matched by mountains. Yet, the advantage of mountains in terms of foliage is almost as substantial as it is in water. Just as there are some unique features in the wide stretches of navigable lowland rivers, like the Loire or Thames, that can’t be compared with the rocky rivers, a lowland resident still can’t claim to have fully experienced the essence of water. Likewise, even in the most beautiful parks and avenues, they can't say they have truly seen trees. The full qualities of trees emerge only when they face challenges; their gentle sense of community and harmony doesn't appear until they have to navigate tight spaces, communicating with each other through their constrained branches. The various ways trees establish themselves in harsh rocks, lean to peer into ravines, seek shelter from glacier winds, stretch towards scarce sunlight, gather to drink from the sweetest streams, climb together up steep slopes, burst into sudden dances around mossy knolls, form groups at rest in fragrant fields, and move in serious lines across the rising ridges—none of this can be imagined in the uncomplicated and consistent joys of lowland forests. Moreover, to all these direct sources of enhanced beauty, we add the sheer abundance: the amount of foliage visible in the folds and peaks of a single Alp surpasses that of an entire lowland landscape (unless viewed from a cathedral tower). Coupled with this charm of abundance is the clarity of visibility—with tree after tree showcased in layers, one behind another, rather than just the tops and sides of masses like in the plains. Additionally, the forms of numerous trees are continuously outlined against the clear sky, both close and above, or against white clouds tangled in their branches, rather than fading away into obscurity due to distance.
Finally, to this supremacy in foliage we have to add the still less questionable supremacy in clouds. There is no effect of sky possible in the lowlands which may not in equal perfection be seen among the hills; but there are effects by tens of thousands, for ever invisible and inconceivable to the inhabitant of the plains, manifested among the hills in the course of one day. The mere power of familiarity with the clouds, of walking with them and above them, alters and renders clear our whole conception of the baseless architecture of the sky; and for the beauty of it, there is more in a single wreath of early cloud, pacing its way up an avenue of pines, or pausing among the points of their fringes, than in all the white heaps that fill the arched sky of the plains from one horizon to the other. And of the nobler cloud manifestations,—the breaking of their troublous seas against the crags, their black spray sparkling with lightning; or the going forth of the morning[27] along their pavements of moving marble, level-laid between dome and dome of snow;—of these things there can be as little imagination or understanding in an inhabitant of the plains as of the scenery of another planet than his own.
Finally, to this supremacy in foliage we have to add the still less questionable supremacy in clouds. There is no effect of sky possible in the lowlands which may not in equal perfection be seen among the hills; but there are effects by tens of thousands, for ever invisible and inconceivable to the inhabitant of the plains, manifested among the hills in the course of one day. The mere power of familiarity with the clouds, of walking with them and above them, alters and renders clear our whole conception of the baseless architecture of the sky; and for the beauty of it, there is more in a single wreath of early cloud, pacing its way up an avenue of pines, or pausing among the points of their fringes, than in all the white heaps that fill the arched sky of the plains from one horizon to the other. And of the nobler cloud manifestations,—the breaking of their troublous seas against the crags, their black spray sparkling with lightning; or the going forth of the morning[27] along their pavements of moving marble, level-laid between dome and dome of snow;—of these things there can be as little imagination or understanding in an inhabitant of the plains as of the scenery of another planet than his own.
And, observe, all these superiorities are matters plainly measurable and calculable, not in any wise to be referred to estimate of sensation. Of the grandeur or expression of the hills I have not spoken; how far they are great, or strong, or terrible, I do not for the moment consider, because vastness, and strength, and terror, are not to all minds subjects of desired contemplation. It may make no difference to some men whether a natural object be large or small, whether it be strong or feeble. But loveliness of colour, perfectness of form, endlessness of change, wonderfulness of structure, are precious to all undiseased human minds; and the superiority of the mountains in all these things to the lowland is, I repeat, as measurable as the richness of a painted window matched with a white one, or the wealth of a museum compared with that of a simply furnished chamber. They seem to have been built for the human race, as at once their schools and cathedrals; full of treasures of illuminated manuscript for the scholar, kindly in simple lessons to the worker, quiet in pale cloisters for the thinker, glorious in holiness for the worshipper. And of these great cathedrals of the earth, with their gates of rock, pavements of cloud, choirs of stream and stone, altars of snow, and vaults of purple traversed by the continual stars,—of these, as we have seen,[28] it was written, nor long ago, by one of the best of the poor human race for whom they were built, wondering in himself for whom their Creator could have made them, and thinking to have entirely discerned the Divine intent in them—"They are inhabited by the Beasts."[29]
And, observe, all these superiorities are matters plainly measurable and calculable, not in any wise to be referred to estimate of sensation. Of the grandeur or expression of the hills I have not spoken; how far they are great, or strong, or terrible, I do not for the moment consider, because vastness, and strength, and terror, are not to all minds subjects of desired contemplation. It may make no difference to some men whether a natural object be large or small, whether it be strong or feeble. But loveliness of colour, perfectness of form, endlessness of change, wonderfulness of structure, are precious to all undiseased human minds; and the superiority of the mountains in all these things to the lowland is, I repeat, as measurable as the richness of a painted window matched with a white one, or the wealth of a museum compared with that of a simply furnished chamber. They seem to have been built for the human race, as at once their schools and cathedrals; full of treasures of illuminated manuscript for the scholar, kindly in simple lessons to the worker, quiet in pale cloisters for the thinker, glorious in holiness for the worshipper. And of these great cathedrals of the earth, with their gates of rock, pavements of cloud, choirs of stream and stone, altars of snow, and vaults of purple traversed by the continual stars,—of these, as we have seen,[28] it was written, nor long ago, by one of the best of the poor human race for whom they were built, wondering in himself for whom their Creator could have made them, and thinking to have entirely discerned the Divine intent in them—"They are inhabited by the Beasts."[29]
Was it then indeed thus with us, and so lately? Had mankind offered no worship in their mountain churches? Was all that granite sculpture and floral painting done by the angels in vain?
Was it really like that for us, not long ago? Had people not worshipped in their mountain churches? Was all that stone carving and flower painting done by the angels for nothing?
Not so. It will need no prolonged thought to convince us that in the hills the purposes of their Maker have indeed been accomplished in such measure as, through the sin or folly of men, He ever permits them to be accomplished. It may not seem, from the general language held concerning them, or from any directly traceable results, that mountains have had serious influence on human intellect; but it will not, I think, be difficult to show that their occult influence has been both constant and essential to the progress of the race.
Not really. It doesn’t take long to realize that in the hills, the intentions of their Creator have indeed been fulfilled to the extent that He allows, given the mistakes or stupidity of people. It might not seem, based on the common talk about them or from any obvious outcomes, that mountains have significantly impacted human thought; however, I believe it won't be hard to demonstrate that their hidden influence has been both steady and crucial to the advancement of humanity.
SUNRISE ON THE ALPS[30]
VOLUME I, SECTION 3, PART 2, CHAPTER 4
Stand upon the peak of some isolated mountain at daybreak, when the night mists first rise from off the plains, and watch their white and lake-like fields, as they float in level bays and winding gulfs about the islanded summits of the lower hills, untouched yet by more than dawn, colder and more quiet than a windless sea under the moon of midnight; watch when the first sunbeam is sent upon the silver channels, how the foam of their undulating surface parts and passes away, and down under their depths the glittering city and green pasture lie like Atlantis,[31] between the white paths of winding rivers; the flakes of light falling every moment faster and broader among the starry spires, as the wreathed surges break and vanish above them, and the confused crests and ridges of the dark hills shorten their grey shadows upon the plain.... Wait a little longer, and you shall see those scattered mists rallying in the ravines, and floating up towards you, along the winding valleys, till they crouch in quiet masses, iridescent with the morning light,[32] upon the broad breasts of the higher hills, whose leagues of massy undulation will melt back and back into that robe of material light, until they fade away, lost in its lustre, to appear again above, in the serene heaven, like a wild, bright, impossible dream, foundationless and inaccessible, their very bases vanishing in the unsubstantial and mocking blue of the deep lake below.[33]... Wait yet a little longer, and you shall see those mists gather themselves into white towers, and stand like fortresses along the promontories, massy and motionless, only piled with every instant higher and higher into the sky, and casting longer shadows athwart the rocks; and out of the pale blue of the horizon you will see forming and advancing a troop of narrow, dark, pointed vapours, which will cover the sky, inch by inch, with their grey network, and take the light off the landscape with an eclipse which will stop the singing of the birds and the motion of the leaves, together; and then you will see horizontal bars of black shadow forming under them, and lurid wreaths create themselves, you know not how, along the shoulders of the hills; you never see them form, but when you look back to a place which was clear an instant ago, there is a cloud on it, hanging by the precipices, as a hawk pauses over his prey.... And then you will hear the sudden rush of the awakened wind, and you will see those watch-towers of vapour swept away from their foundations, and waving curtains of opaque rain let down to the valleys, swinging from the burdened clouds in black bending fringes, or pacing in pale columns along the lake level, grazing its surface into foam as they go. And then, as the sun sinks, you shall see the storm drift for an instant, from off the hills, leaving their broad sides smoking, and loaded yet with snow-white, torn, steam-like rags of capricious vapour, now gone, now gathered again; while the smouldering sun, seeming not far away, but burning like a red-hot ball beside you, and as if you could reach it, plunges through the rushing wind and rolling cloud with headlong fall, as if it meant to rise no more, dyeing all the air about it with blood.... And then you shall hear the fainting tempest die in the hollow of the night, and you shall see a green halo kindling on the summit of the eastern hills, brighter—brighter yet, till the large white circle of the slow moon is lifted up among the barred clouds, step by step, line by line; star after star she quenches with her kindling light, setting in their stead an army of pale, penetrable, fleecy wreaths in the heaven, to give light upon the earth, which move together, hand in hand, company by company, troop by troop, so measured in their unity of motion, that the whole heaven seems to roll with them, and the earth to reel under them.... And then wait yet for one hour, until the east again becomes purple, and the heaving mountains, rolling against it in darkness, like waves of a wild sea, are drowned one by one in the glory of its burning: watch the white glaciers blaze in their winding paths about the mountains, like mighty serpents with scales of fire: watch the columnar peaks of solitary snow, kindling downwards, chasm by chasm, each in itself a new morning; their long avalanches cast down in keen streams brighter than the lightning, sending each his tribute of driven snow, like altar-smoke, up to the heaven; the rose-light of their silent domes flushing that heaven about them and above them, piercing with purer light through its purple lines of lifted cloud, casting a new glory on every wreath as it passes by, until the whole heaven, one scarlet canopy, is interwoven with a roof of waving flame, and tossing, vault beyond vault, as with the drifted wings of many companies of angels: and then, when you can look no more for gladness, and when you are bowed down with fear and love of the Maker and Doer of this, tell me who has best delivered this His message unto men![34]
Stand upon the peak of some isolated mountain at daybreak, when the night mists first rise from off the plains, and watch their white and lake-like fields, as they float in level bays and winding gulfs about the islanded summits of the lower hills, untouched yet by more than dawn, colder and more quiet than a windless sea under the moon of midnight; watch when the first sunbeam is sent upon the silver channels, how the foam of their undulating surface parts and passes away, and down under their depths the glittering city and green pasture lie like Atlantis,[31] between the white paths of winding rivers; the flakes of light falling every moment faster and broader among the starry spires, as the wreathed surges break and vanish above them, and the confused crests and ridges of the dark hills shorten their grey shadows upon the plain.... Wait a little longer, and you shall see those scattered mists rallying in the ravines, and floating up towards you, along the winding valleys, till they crouch in quiet masses, iridescent with the morning light,[32] upon the broad breasts of the higher hills, whose leagues of massy undulation will melt back and back into that robe of material light, until they fade away, lost in its lustre, to appear again above, in the serene heaven, like a wild, bright, impossible dream, foundationless and inaccessible, their very bases vanishing in the unsubstantial and mocking blue of the deep lake below.[33]... Wait yet a little longer, and you shall see those mists gather themselves into white towers, and stand like fortresses along the promontories, massy and motionless, only piled with every instant higher and higher into the sky, and casting longer shadows athwart the rocks; and out of the pale blue of the horizon you will see forming and advancing a troop of narrow, dark, pointed vapours, which will cover the sky, inch by inch, with their grey network, and take the light off the landscape with an eclipse which will stop the singing of the birds and the motion of the leaves, together; and then you will see horizontal bars of black shadow forming under them, and lurid wreaths create themselves, you know not how, along the shoulders of the hills; you never see them form, but when you look back to a place which was clear an instant ago, there is a cloud on it, hanging by the precipices, as a hawk pauses over his prey.... And then you will hear the sudden rush of the awakened wind, and you will see those watch-towers of vapour swept away from their foundations, and waving curtains of opaque rain let down to the valleys, swinging from the burdened clouds in black bending fringes, or pacing in pale columns along the lake level, grazing its surface into foam as they go. And then, as the sun sinks, you shall see the storm drift for an instant, from off the hills, leaving their broad sides smoking, and loaded yet with snow-white, torn, steam-like rags of capricious vapour, now gone, now gathered again; while the smouldering sun, seeming not far away, but burning like a red-hot ball beside you, and as if you could reach it, plunges through the rushing wind and rolling cloud with headlong fall, as if it meant to rise no more, dyeing all the air about it with blood.... And then you shall hear the fainting tempest die in the hollow of the night, and you shall see a green halo kindling on the summit of the eastern hills, brighter—brighter yet, till the large white circle of the slow moon is lifted up among the barred clouds, step by step, line by line; star after star she quenches with her kindling light, setting in their stead an army of pale, penetrable, fleecy wreaths in the heaven, to give light upon the earth, which move together, hand in hand, company by company, troop by troop, so measured in their unity of motion, that the whole heaven seems to roll with them, and the earth to reel under them.... And then wait yet for one hour, until the east again becomes purple, and the heaving mountains, rolling against it in darkness, like waves of a wild sea, are drowned one by one in the glory of its burning: watch the white glaciers blaze in their winding paths about the mountains, like mighty serpents with scales of fire: watch the columnar peaks of solitary snow, kindling downwards, chasm by chasm, each in itself a new morning; their long avalanches cast down in keen streams brighter than the lightning, sending each his tribute of driven snow, like altar-smoke, up to the heaven; the rose-light of their silent domes flushing that heaven about them and above them, piercing with purer light through its purple lines of lifted cloud, casting a new glory on every wreath as it passes by, until the whole heaven, one scarlet canopy, is interwoven with a roof of waving flame, and tossing, vault beyond vault, as with the drifted wings of many companies of angels: and then, when you can look no more for gladness, and when you are bowed down with fear and love of the Maker and Doer of this, tell me who has best delivered this His message unto men![34]
THE GRAND STYLE[35]
VOLUME III, CHAPTER I
In taking up the clue of an inquiry, now intermitted for nearly ten years, it may be well to do as a traveller would, who had to recommence an interrupted journey in a guideless country; and, ascending, as it were, some little hill beside our road, note how far we have already advanced, and what pleasantest ways we may choose for farther progress.
In picking up the thread of an investigation that’s been paused for nearly ten years, it might be helpful to do what a traveler would do when restarting a journey in an unfamiliar place. So, let’s take a moment to pause, like climbing a small hill by the side of our path, and reflect on how far we’ve come and what the best routes are for moving forward.
I endeavoured, in the beginning of the first volume, to divide the sources of pleasure open to us in Art into certain groups, which might conveniently be studied in succession. After some preliminary discussion, it was concluded that these groups were, in the main, three; consisting, first, of the pleasures taken in perceiving simple resemblance to Nature (Ideas of Truth); secondly, of the pleasures taken in the beauty of the things chosen to be painted (Ideas of Beauty); and, lastly, of pleasures taken in the meanings and relations of these things (Ideas of Relation).
I tried, at the start of the first volume, to categorize the sources of pleasure we find in Art into specific groups that could be easily studied one after another. After some initial discussion, we decided that these groups were basically three: first, the pleasure we get from seeing a straightforward resemblance to Nature (Ideas of Truth); second, the pleasure we get from the beauty of the things we choose to paint (Ideas of Beauty); and finally, the pleasure we get from the meanings and relationships of these things (Ideas of Relation).
The first volume, treating of the ideas of Truth, was chiefly occupied with an inquiry into the various success with which different artists had represented the facts of Nature,—an inquiry necessarily conducted very imperfectly, owing to the want of pictorial illustration.
The first volume, focused on the concept of Truth, mainly explored how successfully different artists portrayed the facts of Nature—an exploration that was necessarily incomplete due to the lack of visual examples.
The second volume merely opened the inquiry into the nature of ideas of Beauty and Relation, by analysing (as far as I was able to do so) the two faculties of the human mind which mainly seized such ideas; namely, the contemplative and imaginative faculties.
The second volume just started the investigation into the concepts of Beauty and Relation by examining (as much as I could) the two main mental faculties that grasp these ideas, which are the contemplative and imaginative faculties.
It remains for us to examine the various success of artists, especially of the great landscape-painter whose works have been throughout our principal subject, in addressing these faculties of the human mind, and to consider who among them has conveyed the noblest ideas of beauty, and touched the deepest sources of thought.
It’s time for us to look at the different successes of artists, particularly the great landscape painter whose works have been our main focus, in appealing to these aspects of the human mind. We should consider who among them has expressed the most profound ideas of beauty and tapped into the deepest wells of thought.
I do not intend, however, now to pursue the inquiry in a method so laboriously systematic; for the subject may, it seems to me, be more usefully treated by pursuing the different questions which rise out of it just as they occur to us, without too great scrupulousness in marking connections, or insisting on sequences. Much time is wasted by human beings, in general, on establishment of systems; and it often takes more labour to master the intricacies of an artificial connection, than to remember the separate facts which are so carefully connected. I suspect that system-makers, in general, are not of much more use, each in his own domain, than, in that of Pomona, the old women who tie cherries upon sticks, for the more convenient portableness of the same. To cultivate well, and choose well, your cherries, is of some importance; but if they can be had in their own wild way of clustering about their crabbed stalk, it is a better connection for them than any other; and, if they cannot, then, so that they be not bruised, it makes to a boy of a practical disposition not much difference whether he gets them by handfuls, or in beaded symmetry on the exalting stick. I purpose, therefore, henceforward to trouble myself little with sticks or twine, but to arrange my chapters with a view to convenient reference, rather than to any careful division of subjects, and to follow out, in any by-ways that may open, on right hand or left, whatever question it seems useful at any moment to settle.
I don't plan to dive into this topic in such a painstakingly systematic way anymore; instead, I think we can handle it more effectively by addressing the various questions that come up as they arise, without being overly careful about connections or insisting on specific sequences. People generally waste a lot of time trying to establish systems, and it often takes more effort to navigate the complexities of an artificial connection than to simply remember the individual facts that are so meticulously linked. I suspect that system creators, in general, aren't much more useful in their fields than the old women in Pomona who tie cherries onto sticks for easier carrying. It's important to cultivate and choose your cherries well, but if they can grow in their natural clusters around their gnarly stalks, that's a better arrangement for them than anything else. And if they can't, then, as long as they aren't bruised, it doesn't make much difference to a practical boy whether he gets them in handfuls or arranged neatly on a stick. So, from now on, I plan to focus less on sticks or twine and more on organizing my chapters for easy reference, rather than meticulously dividing subjects, and to explore whatever questions seem useful to address at any moment, whether to the right or left.
And, in the outset, I find myself met by one which I ought to have touched upon before—one of especial interest in the present state of the Arts. I have said that the art is greatest which includes the greatest ideas; but I have not endeavoured to define the nature of this greatness in the ideas themselves. We speak of great truths, of great beauties, great thoughts. What is it which makes one truth greater than another, one thought greater than another? This question is, I repeat, of peculiar importance at the present time; for, during a period now of some hundred and fifty years, all writers on Art who have pretended to eminence, have insisted much on a supposed distinction between what they call the Great and the Low Schools; using the terms "High Art," "Great or Ideal Style," and other such, as descriptive of a certain noble manner of painting, which it was desirable that all students of Art should be early led to reverence and adopt; and characterizing as "vulgar," or "low," or "realist," another manner of painting and conceiving, which it was equally necessary that all students should be taught to avoid.
And at the beginning, I find I need to address something I should have mentioned earlier—something particularly relevant in today's artistic landscape. I've stated that the greatest art is the one that encompasses the greatest ideas; however, I haven't tried to define what makes these ideas great. We talk about great truths, great beauties, and great thoughts. What makes one truth greater than another or one thought greater than another? This question is, as I mentioned, especially important right now; for over the last hundred and fifty years, all notable writers on art have emphasized a supposed distinction between what they refer to as the Great and the Low Schools. They've used terms like "High Art," "Great or Ideal Style," and others to describe a certain noble way of painting that they believed all art students should be encouraged to respect and adopt; meanwhile, they've labeled other styles of painting and thinking as "vulgar," "low," or "realist," which they argued all students should be taught to avoid.
But lately this established teaching, never very intelligible, has been gravely called in question. The advocates and self-supposed practisers of "High Art" are beginning to be looked upon with doubt, and their peculiar phraseology to be treated with even a certain degree of ridicule. And other forms of Art are partly developed among us, which do not pretend to be high, but rather to be strong, healthy, and humble. This matter of "highness" in Art, therefore, deserves our most careful consideration. Has it been, or is it, a true highness, a true princeliness, or only a show of it, consisting in courtly manners and robes of state? Is it rocky height or cloudy height, adamant or vapour, on which the sun of praise so long has risen and set? It will be well at once to consider this.
But recently, this established idea, which was never very clear, has come under serious scrutiny. Supporters and self-proclaimed practitioners of "High Art" are starting to be viewed with skepticism, and their unique language is even being treated with a certain degree of mockery. Other forms of art are emerging among us that don't claim to be high but rather aim to be strong, healthy, and humble. Therefore, the concept of "highness" in art deserves our careful attention. Has it ever been, or is it, a genuine highness, a true nobility, or just a facade made up of elegant manners and elaborate attire? Is it a solid foundation or merely an illusion, something substantial or just hot air, upon which the sun of approval has risen and set for so long? It’s important to consider this right away.
And first, let us get, as quickly as may be, at the exact meaning with which the advocates of "High Art" use that somewhat obscure and figurative term.
And first, let’s quickly get to the exact meaning of how the supporters of "High Art" use that somewhat vague and figurative term.
I do not know that the principles in question are anywhere more distinctly expressed than in two papers in the Idler, written by Sir Joshua Reynolds, of course under the immediate sanction of Johnson; and which may thus be considered as the utterance of the views then held upon the subject by the artists of chief skill, and critics of most sense, arranged in a form so brief and clear as to admit of their being brought before the public for a morning's entertainment. I cannot, therefore, it seems to me, do better than quote these two letters, or at least the important parts of them, examining the exact meaning of each passage as it occurs. There are, in all, in the Idler three letters on painting, Nos. 76, 79, and 82; of these, the first is directed only against the impertinences of pretended connoisseurs, and is as notable for its faithfulness as for its wit in the description of the several modes of criticism in an artificial and ignorant state of society: it is only, therefore, in the two last papers that we find the expression of the doctrines which it is our business to examine.
I don't think the principles in question are stated more clearly anywhere than in two articles in the Idler, written by Sir Joshua Reynolds, certainly with Johnson's direct approval. These can be seen as a reflection of the views held at that time by the most skilled artists and the most sensible critics, presented in a concise and clear format suitable for a morning's read. Therefore, I believe the best approach is to quote these two letters, or at least the key parts of them, while examining the exact meaning of each passage as it comes up. In total, there are three letters on painting in the Idler: Nos. 76, 79, and 82. The first one mainly addresses the nonsense of fake connoisseurs and is notable for its accuracy as well as its wit in describing various modes of criticism in a superficial and uninformed society. Thus, it is only in the last two papers that we find the explanations of the doctrines we need to analyze.
No. 79 (Saturday, October 20, 1759) begins, after a short preamble, with the following passage:—
No. 79 (Saturday, October 20, 1759) starts, after a brief introduction, with this passage:—
"Amongst the Painters, and the writers on Painting, there is one maxim universally admitted and continually inculcated. Imitate nature is the invariable rule; but I know none who have explained in what manner this rule is to be understood; the consequence of which is, that everyone takes it in the most obvious sense—that objects are represented naturally, when they have such relief that they seem real. It may appear strange, perhaps, to hear this sense of the rule disputed; but it must be considered, that, if the excellency of a Painter consisted only in this kind of imitation, Painting must lose its rank, and be no longer considered as a liberal art, and sister to Poetry: this imitation being merely mechanical, in which the slowest intellect is always sure to succeed best; for the Painter of genius cannot stoop to drudgery, in which the understanding has no part; and what pretence has the Art to claim kindred with Poetry but by its power over the imagination? To this power the Painter of genius directs him; in this sense he studies Nature, and often arrives at his end, even by being unnatural in the confined sense of the word.
"Among painters and those who write about painting, there’s one principle that’s universally accepted and constantly taught. Imitate nature is the unchanging rule; however, I’m not aware of anyone who has explained what this rule actually means. As a result, everyone interprets it in the most straightforward way—that objects are depicted naturally when they have such depth that they seem real. It may seem odd to challenge this interpretation of the rule, but it should be understood that if the greatness of a painter was solely based on this type of imitation, painting would lose its status and wouldn’t be viewed as a fine art, akin to poetry. This imitation is merely mechanical, where even the most basic intellect would excel, because a talented painter can’t lower themselves to mere labor that doesn’t involve understanding. What claim does the art have to be related to poetry if not for its power over the imagination? It’s this power that a skilled painter focuses on; in this way, they study nature and often achieve their goal, even by being unconventional in a limited sense of the word."
"The grand style of Painting requires this minute attention to be carefully avoided, and must be kept as separate from it as the style of Poetry from that of History. (Poetical ornaments destroy that air of truth and plainness which ought to characterize History; but the very being of Poetry consists in departing from this plain narrative, and adopting every ornament that will warm the imagination.)[36] To desire to see the excellences of each style united—to mingle the Dutch with the Italian school, is to join contrarieties which cannot subsist together, and which destroy the efficacy of each other."
"The grand style of Painting requires this minute attention to be carefully avoided, and must be kept as separate from it as the style of Poetry from that of History. (Poetical ornaments destroy that air of truth and plainness which ought to characterize History; but the very being of Poetry consists in departing from this plain narrative, and adopting every ornament that will warm the imagination.)[36] To desire to see the excellences of each style united—to mingle the Dutch with the Italian school, is to join contrarieties which cannot subsist together, and which destroy the efficacy of each other."
We find, first, from this interesting passage, that the writer considers the Dutch and Italian masters as severally representative of the low and high schools; next, that he considers the Dutch painters as excelling in a mechanical imitation, "in which the slowest intellect is always sure to succeed best"; and, thirdly, that he considers the Italian painters as excelling in a style which corresponds to that of imaginative poetry in literature, and which has an exclusive right to be called the grand style.
We see, first, from this engaging passage, that the author views the Dutch and Italian masters as representing the low and high schools, respectively; next, that he believes Dutch painters excel in mechanical imitation, "where even the slowest mind is likely to succeed best"; and, third, that he thinks Italian painters stand out in a style that parallels imaginative poetry in literature and rightfully deserves to be called the grand style.
I wish that it were in my power entirely to concur with the writer, and to enforce this opinion thus distinctly stated. I have never been a zealous partisan of the Dutch School, and should rejoice in claiming Reynolds's authority for the assertion, that their manner was one "in which the slowest intellect is always sure to succeed best." But before his authority can be so claimed, we must observe exactly the meaning of the assertion itself, and separate it from the company of some others not perhaps so admissible. First, I say, we must observe Reynolds's exact meaning, for (though the assertion may at first appear singular) a man who uses accurate language is always more liable to misinterpretation than one who is careless in his expressions. We may assume that the latter means very nearly what we at first suppose him to mean, for words which have been uttered without thought may be received without examination. But when a writer or speaker may be fairly supposed to have considered his expressions carefully, and, after having revolved a number of terms in his mind, to have chosen the one which exactly means the thing he intends to say, we may be assured that what costs him time to select, will require from us time to understand, and that we shall do him wrong, unless we pause to reflect how the word which he has actually employed differs from other words which it seems he might have employed. It thus constantly happens that persons themselves unaccustomed to think clearly, or speak correctly, misunderstand a logical and careful writer, and are actually in more danger of being misled by language which is measured and precise, than by that which is loose and inaccurate.
I wish I had the power to completely agree with the writer and to support this opinion as clearly stated. I've never been a strong supporter of the Dutch School and would be glad to use Reynolds's authority to back up the claim that their style is one "in which the slowest intellect is always sure to succeed best." However, before we can claim his authority in this way, we need to closely examine what the assertion really means and distinguish it from others that may not be as valid. First, we must understand Reynolds's exact meaning because, although it might seem unusual at first, a person who uses precise language is often more likely to be misunderstood than someone who speaks carelessly. We can assume that the latter generally means what we initially think he means, as words spoken thoughtlessly can be accepted without scrutiny. But when a writer or speaker has clearly put thought into their choice of words and selected one that precisely conveys their intended meaning, we should realize that what took them time to select will require us to take time to understand. We do them a disservice if we don’t reflect on how the word they chose differs from other words they *could* have used. As a result, individuals who are not used to thinking clearly or speaking accurately often misinterpret a logical and careful writer. They are actually more at risk of being confused by measured and precise language than by language that is loose and inaccurate.
Now, in the instance before us, a person not accustomed to good writing might very rashly conclude that when Reynolds spoke of the Dutch School as one "in which the slowest intellect was sure to succeed best," he meant to say that every successful Dutch painter was a fool. We have no right to take his assertion in that sense. He says, the slowest intellect. We have no right to assume that he meant the weakest. For it is true, that in order to succeed in the Dutch style, a man has need of qualities of mind eminently deliberate and sustained. He must be possessed of patience rather than of power; and must feel no weariness in contemplating the expression of a single thought for several months together. As opposed to the changeful energies of the imagination, these mental characters may be properly spoken of as under the general term—slowness of intellect. But it by no means follows that they are necessarily those of weak or foolish men.
Now, in this situation, someone who isn't used to good writing might quickly jump to the conclusion that when Reynolds referred to the Dutch School as one "in which the slowest intellect was sure to succeed best," he was suggesting that every successful Dutch painter was a fool. We shouldn't interpret his statement that way. He mentioned the slowest intellect. We can't assume that he meant the weakest. It's true that to succeed in the Dutch style, a person needs to have qualities of mind that are incredibly deliberate and sustained. They must have patience rather than just raw talent and should not tire of contemplating the expression of a single thought for several months at a time. Compared to the ever-changing energies of imagination, these mental traits can be accurately described using the general term—slowness of intellect. But that doesn't mean they are necessarily characteristics of weak or foolish people.
We observe, however, farther, that the imitation which Reynolds supposes to be characteristic of the Dutch School is that which gives to objects such relief that they seem real, and that he then speaks of this art of realistic imitation as corresponding to history in literature.
We notice, however, further, that the imitation Reynolds believes defines the Dutch School is the type that makes objects appear so lifelike that they seem real, and he then refers to this art of realistic imitation as corresponding to history in literature.
Reynolds, therefore, seems to class these dull works of the Dutch School under a general head, to which they are not commonly referred—that of historical painting; while he speaks of the works of the Italian School not as historical, but as poetical painting. His next sentence will farther manifest his meaning.
Reynolds, therefore, appears to categorize these uninteresting works of the Dutch School under a broad category that they aren't usually associated with—that of historical painting; while he describes the works of the Italian School not as historical, but as poetical painting. His next sentence will further clarify his point.
"The Italian attends only to the invariable, the great and general ideas which are fixed and inherent in universal Nature; the Dutch, on the contrary, to literal truth and a minute exactness in the detail, as I may say, of Nature modified by accident. The attention to these petty peculiarities is the very cause of this naturalness so much admired in the Dutch pictures, which, if we suppose it to be a beauty, is certainly of a lower order, which ought to give place to a beauty of a superior kind, since one cannot be obtained but by departing from the other.
"The Italian focuses on the unchanging, the grand and universal concepts that are inherent in nature; the Dutch, on the other hand, pay close attention to literal truth and the precise details of nature as influenced by chance. This focus on these small specifics is what creates the naturalness that is so admired in Dutch paintings, which, if seen as a form of beauty, is definitely of a lesser kind. This should be replaced by a higher kind of beauty, as one cannot achieve the former without moving away from the latter."
"If my opinion was asked concerning the works of Michael Angelo, whether they would receive any advantage from possessing this mechanical merit, I should not scruple to say, they would not only receive no advantage, but would lose, in a great measure, the effect which they now have on every mind susceptible of great and noble ideas. His works may be said to be all genius and soul; and why should they be loaded with heavy matter, which can only counteract his purpose by retarding the progress of the imagination?"
"If someone asked me about the works of Michael Angelo and whether they would benefit from having this mechanical skill, I wouldn't hesitate to say that they wouldn’t only not benefit but would actually lose much of their impact on anyone who appreciates great and noble ideas. His works can be seen as pure genius and emotion; so why should they be weighed down with something heavy that would only hinder the imagination?"
Examining carefully this and the preceding passage, we find the author's unmistakable meaning to be, that Dutch painting is history; attending to literal truth and "minute exactness in the details of nature modified by accident." That Italian painting is poetry, attending only to the invariable; and that works which attend only to the invariable are full of genius and soul; but that literal truth and exact detail are "heavy matter which retards the progress of the imagination."
Examining this passage and the one before it closely, we can see the author's clear point: Dutch painting is history; it focuses on literal truth and "minute exactness in the details of nature modified by accident." Italian painting is poetry; it concentrates only on what is constant. Works that focus solely on the constant are full of genius and spirit, but literal truth and precise detail are "heavy matter that slows down the imagination."
This being then indisputably what Reynolds means to tell us, let us think a little whether he is in all respects right. And first, as he compares his two kinds of painting to history and poetry, let us see how poetry and history themselves differ, in their use of variable and invariable details. I am writing at a window which commands a view of the head of the Lake of Geneva; and as I look up from my paper, to consider this point, I see, beyond it, a blue breadth of softly moving water, and the outline of the mountains above Chillon, bathed in morning mist. The first verses which naturally come into my mind are—
This is clearly what Reynolds is trying to tell us, so let's take a moment to consider if he's right in every way. First, as he compares his two types of painting to history and poetry, let's look at how poetry and history differ in their use of variable and invariable details. I'm writing at a window with a view of the head of Lake Geneva; and as I lift my eyes from my paper to think about this, I see, beyond it, a wide expanse of gently moving water and the outline of the mountains above Chillon, shrouded in morning mist. The first lines that come to mind are—
A thousand feet in depth below
A thousand feet deep below
The massy waters meet and flow;
The heavy waters come together and flow;
So far the fathom line was sent
So far, the depth line was sent
From Chillon's snow-white battlement.[37]
From Chillon's bright white battlement.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Let us see in what manner this poetical statement is distinguished from a historical one.
Let’s examine how this poetic statement differs from a historical one.
It is distinguished from a truly historical statement, first, in being simply false. The water under the Castle of Chillon is not a thousand feet deep, nor anything like it.[38] Herein, certainly, these lines fulfil Reynolds's first requirement in poetry, "that it should be inattentive to literal truth and minute exactness in detail." In order, however, to make our comparison more closely in other points, let us assume that what is stated is indeed a fact, and that it was to be recorded, first historically, and then poetically.
It is distinguished from a truly historical statement, first, in being simply false. The water under the Castle of Chillon is not a thousand feet deep, nor anything like it.[38] Herein, certainly, these lines fulfil Reynolds's first requirement in poetry, "that it should be inattentive to literal truth and minute exactness in detail." In order, however, to make our comparison more closely in other points, let us assume that what is stated is indeed a fact, and that it was to be recorded, first historically, and then poetically.
Historically stating it, then, we should say: "The lake was sounded from the walls of the Castle of Chillon, and found to be a thousand feet deep."
Historically speaking, we should say: "The lake was measured from the walls of the Castle of Chillon and found to be a thousand feet deep."
Now, if Reynolds be right in his idea of the difference between history and poetry, we shall find that Byron leaves out of this statement certain unnecessary details, and retains only the invariable,—that is to say, the points which the Lake of Geneva and Castle of Chillon have in common with all other lakes and castles.
Now, if Reynolds is correct about the difference between history and poetry, we'll see that Byron skips some unnecessary details and focuses only on the constants—that is, the aspects that the Lake of Geneva and the Castle of Chillon share with all other lakes and castles.
Let us hear, therefore.
Let's hear it, then.
A thousand feet in depth below.
A thousand feet deep underground.
"Below"? Here is, at all events, a word added (instead of anything being taken away); invariable, certainly in the case of lakes, but not absolutely necessary.
"Below"? Here is, in any case, an added word (instead of removing anything); it's constant, definitely in the case of lakes, but not completely essential.
The massy waters meet and flow.
The heavy waters come together and flow.
"Massy"! why massy? Because deep water is heavy. The word is a good word, but it is assuredly an added detail, and expresses a character, not which the Lake of Geneva has in common with all other lakes, but which it has in distinction from those which are narrow, or shallow.
"Massy"! Why massy? Because deep water is heavy. The word is a good one, but it's definitely an extra detail, expressing a quality that the Lake of Geneva has, setting it apart from all other lakes, specifically those that are narrow or shallow.
"Meet and flow." Why meet and flow? Partly to make up a rhyme; partly to tell us that the waters are forceful as well as massy, and changeful as well as deep. Observe, a farther addition of details, and of details more or less peculiar to the spot, or, according to Reynolds's definition, of "heavy matter, retarding the progress of the imagination."
"Meet and flow." Why meet and flow? Partly to create a rhyme; partly to remind us that the waters are powerful as well as substantial, and variable as well as deep. Notice, an additional layer of details, details that are more or less specific to the location, or, following Reynolds's definition, of "heavy matter, slowing down the progress of the imagination."
So far the fathom line was sent.
So far, the depth line has been sent.
Why fathom line? All lines for sounding are not fathom lines. If the lake was ever sounded from Chillon, it was probably sounded in mètres, not fathoms. This is an addition of another particular detail, in which the only compliance with Reynolds's requirement is, that there is some chance of its being an inaccurate one.
Why use fathom lines? Not all lines for measuring depth are fathom lines. If the lake was ever measured from Chillon, it was probably done in meters, not fathoms. This adds another detail, where the only way to meet Reynolds's requirement is that there's some chance it could be inaccurate.
From Chillon's snow-white battlement.
From Chillon's white battlements.
Why snow-white? Because castle battlements are not usually snow-white. This is another added detail, and a detail quite peculiar to Chillon, and therefore exactly the most striking word in the whole passage.
Why snow-white? Because castle battlements are not typically snow-white. This is another added detail, and a detail quite unique to Chillon, making it the most striking word in the entire passage.
"Battlement"! Why battlement? Because all walls have not battlements, and the addition of the term marks the castle to be not merely a prison, but a fortress.
"Battlement"! Why battlement? Because not all walls have battlements, and the use of the term indicates that the castle is not just a prison, but a fortress.
This is a curious result. Instead of finding, as we expected, the poetry distinguished from the history by the omission of details, we find it consist entirely in the addition of details; and instead of being characterized by regard only of the invariable, we find its whole power to consist in the clear expression of what is singular and particular!
This is an interesting outcome. Instead of discovering, as we anticipated, that poetry is marked by the absence of details when compared to history, we find it is made up entirely of the addition of details; and rather than being defined solely by focusing on the constant, we see that its entire strength lies in the clear expression of what is unique and specific!
The reader may pursue the investigation for himself in other instances. He will find in every case that a poetical is distinguished from a merely historical statement, not by being more vague, but more specific; and it might, therefore, at first appear that our author's comparison should be simply reversed, and that the Dutch School should be called poetical, and the Italian historical. But the term poetical does not appear very applicable to the generality of Dutch painting; and a little reflection will show us, that if the Italians represent only the invariable, they cannot be properly compared even to historians. For that which is incapable of change has no history, and records which state only the invariable need not be written, and could not be read.
The reader can explore this study for themselves in other examples. In every case, they will see that a poetic statement is different from a purely historical one, not by being more vague, but by being more specific; it may therefore seem at first that our author's comparison should be simply flipped, with the Dutch School labeled as poetic and the Italian as historical. However, the term poetic doesn't really fit the majority of Dutch painting; and with some thought, we can see that if the Italians depict only the unchanging, they can't be properly compared even to historians. Because what cannot change has no history, and records that only describe the unchanging don't need to be written down, nor could they be read.
It is evident, therefore, that our author has entangled himself in some grave fallacy, by introducing this idea of invariableness as forming a distinction between poetical and historical art. What the fallacy is, we shall discover as we proceed; but as an invading army should not leave an untaken fortress in its rear, we must not go on with our inquiry into the views of Reynolds until we have settled satisfactorily the question already suggested to us, in what the essence of poetical treatment really consists. For though, as we have seen, it certainly involves the addition of specific details, it cannot be simply that addition which turns the history into poetry. For it is perfectly possible to add any number of details to a historical statement, and to make it more prosaic with every added word. As, for instance, "The lake was sounded out of a flat-bottomed boat, near the crab-tree at the corner of the kitchen-garden, and was found to be a thousand feet nine inches deep, with a muddy bottom." It thus appears that it is not the multiplication of details which constitutes poetry; nor their subtraction which constitutes history, but that there must be something either in the nature of the details themselves, or the method of using them, which invests them with poetical power or historical propriety.
It’s clear, then, that our author has gotten himself caught up in a serious mistake by introducing the idea of unchangingness as a way to differentiate between poetic and historical art. We’ll uncover what this mistake is as we move forward; however, just like an invading army shouldn’t leave an unseized fortress behind, we shouldn’t continue exploring Reynolds’ views until we’ve clearly answered the question of what the essence of poetic treatment really is. Though, as we’ve seen, it definitely includes the addition of specific details, it can’t just be that extra detail that turns history into poetry. It’s entirely possible to add as many details as you want to a historical account, making it even more mundane with each added word. For example, “The lake was sounded from a flat-bottomed boat, near the crab-apple tree at the edge of the vegetable garden, and was found to be a thousand feet nine inches deep, with a muddy bottom.” It appears that it’s not just the abundance of details that makes something poetry, nor the removal of details that makes it history, but there must be something in the nature of the details themselves or the way they’re used that gives them poetic strength or historical relevance.
It seems to me, and may seem to the reader, strange that we should need to ask the question, "What is poetry?" Here is a word we have been using all our lives, and, I suppose, with a very distinct idea attached to it; and when I am now called upon to give a definition of this idea, I find myself at a pause. What is more singular, I do not at present recollect hearing the question often asked, though surely it is a very natural one; and I never recollect hearing it answered, or even attempted to be answered. In general, people shelter themselves under metaphors, and while we hear poetry described as an utterance of the soul, an effusion of Divinity, or voice of nature, or in other terms equally elevated and obscure, we never attain anything like a definite explanation of the character which actually distinguishes it from prose.
It seems to me, and might seem to the reader, strange that we need to ask the question, "What is poetry?" Here is a word we've been using all our lives, and I suppose we have a clear idea of what it means; yet when I’m now asked to define this idea, I find myself at a loss. What’s even stranger is that I can’t recall hearing this question asked often, even though it’s a very natural one; and I’ve never heard it answered, or even attempted to be answered. Generally, people hide behind metaphors, and while we hear poetry described as the expression of the soul, a divine outpouring, or the voice of nature, or in other equally grand and vague terms, we never really arrive at a clear explanation of what actually sets it apart from prose.
I come, after some embarrassment, to the conclusion, that poetry is "the suggestion, by the imagination, of noble grounds for the noble emotions."[39] I mean, by the noble emotions, those four principal sacred passions—Love, Veneration, Admiration, and Joy (this latter especially, if unselfish); and their opposites—Hatred, Indignation (or Scorn), Horror, and Grief,—this last, when unselfish, becoming Compassion. These passions in their various combinations constitute what is called "poetical feeling," when they are felt on noble grounds, that is, on great and true grounds. Indignation, for instance, is a poetical feeling, if excited by serious injury; but it is not a poetical feeling if entertained on being cheated out of a small sum of money. It is very possible the manner of the cheat may have been such as to justify considerable indignation; but the feeling is nevertheless not poetical unless the grounds of it be large as well as just. In like manner, energetic admiration may be excited in certain minds by a display of fireworks, or a street of handsome shops; but the feeling is not poetical, because the grounds of it are false, and therefore ignoble. There is in reality nothing to deserve admiration either in the firing of packets of gunpowder, or in the display of the stocks of warehouses. But admiration excited by the budding of a flower is a poetical feeling, because it is impossible that this manifestation of spiritual power and vital beauty can ever be enough admired.
I come, after some embarrassment, to the conclusion, that poetry is "the suggestion, by the imagination, of noble grounds for the noble emotions."[39] I mean, by the noble emotions, those four principal sacred passions—Love, Veneration, Admiration, and Joy (this latter especially, if unselfish); and their opposites—Hatred, Indignation (or Scorn), Horror, and Grief,—this last, when unselfish, becoming Compassion. These passions in their various combinations constitute what is called "poetical feeling," when they are felt on noble grounds, that is, on great and true grounds. Indignation, for instance, is a poetical feeling, if excited by serious injury; but it is not a poetical feeling if entertained on being cheated out of a small sum of money. It is very possible the manner of the cheat may have been such as to justify considerable indignation; but the feeling is nevertheless not poetical unless the grounds of it be large as well as just. In like manner, energetic admiration may be excited in certain minds by a display of fireworks, or a street of handsome shops; but the feeling is not poetical, because the grounds of it are false, and therefore ignoble. There is in reality nothing to deserve admiration either in the firing of packets of gunpowder, or in the display of the stocks of warehouses. But admiration excited by the budding of a flower is a poetical feeling, because it is impossible that this manifestation of spiritual power and vital beauty can ever be enough admired.
Farther, it is necessary to the existence of poetry that the grounds of these feelings should be furnished by the imagination. Poetical feeling, that is to say, mere noble emotion, is not poetry. It is happily inherent in all human nature deserving the name, and is found often to be purest in the least sophisticated. But the power of assembling, by the help of the imagination, such images as will excite these feelings, is the power of the poet or literally of the "Maker."[40]
Farther, it is necessary to the existence of poetry that the grounds of these feelings should be furnished by the imagination. Poetical feeling, that is to say, mere noble emotion, is not poetry. It is happily inherent in all human nature deserving the name, and is found often to be purest in the least sophisticated. But the power of assembling, by the help of the imagination, such images as will excite these feelings, is the power of the poet or literally of the "Maker."[40]
Now this power of exciting the emotions depends of course on the richness of the imagination, and on its choice of those images which, in combination, will be most effective, or, for the particular work to be done, most fit. And it is altogether impossible for a writer not endowed with invention to conceive what tools a true poet will make use of, or in what way he will apply them, or what unexpected results he will bring out by them; so that it is vain to say that the details of poetry ought to possess, or ever do possess, any definite character. Generally speaking, poetry runs into finer and more delicate details than prose; but the details are not poetical because they are more delicate, but because they are employed so as to bring out an affecting result. For instance, no one but a true poet would have thought of exciting our pity for a bereaved father by describing his way of locking the door of his house:
Now, the ability to stir emotions relies on the richness of imagination and the selection of images that will be most impactful or suitable for the specific piece of work. A writer lacking creativity cannot grasp what tools a true poet will use, how they will apply them, or what surprising outcomes they will create; therefore, it’s pointless to claim that the details of poetry should have, or ever truly have, any definite characteristics. Typically, poetry delves into finer and more intricate details than prose; however, these details are not poetic simply because they are more refined, but because they are used to evoke an emotional response. For example, only a true poet would think to evoke our sympathy for a grieving father by describing how he locks the door of his house:
Perhaps to himself at that moment he said,
Perhaps at that moment he said to himself,
The key I must take, for my Ellen is dead;
The key I need to take, because my Ellen is gone;
But of this in my ears not a word did he speak;
But he didn't say a word of this to me;
In like manner, in painting, it is altogether impossible to say beforehand what details a great painter may make poetical by his use of them to excite noble emotions: and we shall, therefore, find presently that a painting is to be classed in the great or inferior schools, not according to the kind of details which it represents, but according to the uses for which it employs them.
In the same way, in painting, it's completely impossible to predict what details a great painter might transform into something poetic to evoke strong emotions. Therefore, we will soon see that a painting is categorized into great or lesser schools, not by the type of details it shows, but by the purpose for which it uses them.
It is only farther to be noticed, that infinite confusion has been introduced into this subject by the careless and illogical custom of opposing painting to poetry, instead of regarding poetry as consisting in a noble use, whether of colours or words. Painting is properly to be opposed to speaking or writing, but not to poetry. Both painting and speaking are methods of expression. Poetry is the employment of either for the noblest purposes.
It should also be noted that a lot of confusion has been caused by the careless and illogical habit of pitting painting against poetry, instead of seeing poetry as a beautiful use of either colors or words. Painting should be compared to speaking or writing, but not to poetry. Both painting and speaking are forms of expression. Poetry is the use of either for the highest purposes.
This question being thus far determined, we may proceed with our paper in the Idler.
This question being settled for now, we can continue with our paper in the Idler.
"It is very difficult to determine the exact degree of enthusiasm that the arts of Painting and Poetry may admit. There may, perhaps, be too great indulgence as well as too great a restraint of imagination; if the one produces incoherent monsters, the other produces what is full as bad, lifeless insipidity. An intimate knowledge of the passions, and good sense, but not common sense, must at last determine its limits. It has been thought, and I believe with reason, that Michael Angelo sometimes transgressed those limits; and, I think, I have seen figures of him of which it was very difficult to determine whether they were in the highest degree sublime or extremely ridiculous. Such faults may be said to be the ebullitions of genius; but at least he had this merit, that he never was insipid; and whatever passion his works may excite, they will always escape contempt.
"It’s really hard to figure out just how much enthusiasm the arts of Painting and Poetry can handle. Sometimes there might be too much freedom for the imagination, while other times there could be too much restraint; the former can lead to chaotic monstrosities, while the latter can result in dullness that’s just as bad. A deep understanding of human emotions and good judgement, not just common sense, should ultimately define the boundaries. Some believe, and I agree, that Michelangelo occasionally crossed those lines; I’ve seen some of his figures that are tough to classify as either incredibly sublime or downright ridiculous. These faults could be seen as bursts of genius, but at least he had the quality of never being dull; no matter what emotions his works stir up, they will always avoid being dismissed."
"What I have had under consideration is the sublimest style, particularly that of Michael Angelo, the Homer of painting. Other kinds may admit of this naturalness, which of the lowest kind is the chief merit; but in painting, as in poetry, the highest style has the least of common nature."
"What I've been thinking about is the highest style, especially that of Michelangelo, the Homer of painting. Other styles might allow for this naturalness, which, at its most basic level, is its main strength; but in painting, just like in poetry, the greatest style has the least in common with ordinary nature."
From this passage we gather three important indications of the supposed nature of the Great Style. That it is the work of men in a state of enthusiasm. That it is like the writing of Homer; and that it has as little as possible of "common nature" in it.
From this passage, we gather three important insights into the supposed nature of the Great Style. First, that it is the work of people in a state of enthusiasm. Second, that it resembles the writing of Homer; and third, that it contains as little "common nature" as possible.
First, it is produced by men in a state of enthusiasm. That is, by men who feel strongly and nobly; for we do not call a strong feeling of envy, jealousy, or ambition, enthusiasm. That is, therefore, by men who feel poetically. This much we may admit, I think, with perfect safety. Great art is produced by men who feel acutely and nobly; and it is in some sort an expression of this personal feeling. We can easily conceive that there may be a sufficiently marked distinction between such art, and that which is produced by men who do not feel at all, but who reproduce, though ever so accurately, yet coldly, like human mirrors, the scenes which pass before their eyes.
First, it’s created by people who are really passionate. Those are the people who feel strongly and nobly; we don’t refer to a strong feeling of envy, jealousy, or ambition as passion. So, it’s created by those who feel with an artistic heart. I think we can safely agree on this. Great art comes from individuals who feel deeply and nobly; it’s a kind of expression of their personal emotions. We can easily imagine there’s a clear difference between that kind of art and art made by people who don’t feel anything at all but instead replicate, no matter how accurately, yet coldly, like human mirrors, the scenes happening around them.
Secondly, Great Art is like the writing of Homer, and this chiefly because it has little of "common nature" in it. We are not clearly informed what is meant by common nature in this passage. Homer seems to describe a great deal of what is common:—cookery, for instance, very carefully in all its processes.[42] I suppose the passage in the Iliad which, on the whole, has excited most admiration, is that which describes a wife's sorrow at parting from her husband, and a child's fright at its father's helmet;[43] and I hope, at least, the former feeling may be considered "common nature." But the true greatness of Homer's style is, doubtless, held by our author to consist in his imaginations of things not only uncommon but impossible (such as spirits in brazen armour, or monsters with heads of men and bodies of beasts), and in his occasional delineations of the human character and form in their utmost, or heroic, strength and beauty. We gather then on the whole, that a painter in the Great Style must be enthusiastic, or full of emotion, and must paint the human form in its utmost strength and beauty, and perhaps certain impossible forms besides, liable by persons not in an equally enthusiastic state of mind to be looked upon as in some degree absurd. This I presume to be Reynolds's meaning, and to be all that he intends us to gather from his comparison of the Great Style with the writings of Homer. But if that comparison be a just one in all respects, surely two other corollaries ought to be drawn from it, namely,—first, that these Heroic or Impossible images are to be mingled with others very unheroic and very possible; and, secondly, that in the representation of the Heroic or Impossible forms, the greatest care must be taken in finishing the details, so that a painter must not be satisfied with painting well the countenance and the body of his hero, but ought to spend the greatest part of his time (as Homer the greatest number of verses) in elaborating the sculptured pattern on his shield.
Secondly, Great Art is like the writing of Homer, and this chiefly because it has little of "common nature" in it. We are not clearly informed what is meant by common nature in this passage. Homer seems to describe a great deal of what is common:—cookery, for instance, very carefully in all its processes.[42] I suppose the passage in the Iliad which, on the whole, has excited most admiration, is that which describes a wife's sorrow at parting from her husband, and a child's fright at its father's helmet;[43] and I hope, at least, the former feeling may be considered "common nature." But the true greatness of Homer's style is, doubtless, held by our author to consist in his imaginations of things not only uncommon but impossible (such as spirits in brazen armour, or monsters with heads of men and bodies of beasts), and in his occasional delineations of the human character and form in their utmost, or heroic, strength and beauty. We gather then on the whole, that a painter in the Great Style must be enthusiastic, or full of emotion, and must paint the human form in its utmost strength and beauty, and perhaps certain impossible forms besides, liable by persons not in an equally enthusiastic state of mind to be looked upon as in some degree absurd. This I presume to be Reynolds's meaning, and to be all that he intends us to gather from his comparison of the Great Style with the writings of Homer. But if that comparison be a just one in all respects, surely two other corollaries ought to be drawn from it, namely,—first, that these Heroic or Impossible images are to be mingled with others very unheroic and very possible; and, secondly, that in the representation of the Heroic or Impossible forms, the greatest care must be taken in finishing the details, so that a painter must not be satisfied with painting well the countenance and the body of his hero, but ought to spend the greatest part of his time (as Homer the greatest number of verses) in elaborating the sculptured pattern on his shield.
Let us, however, proceed with our paper.
Let’s go ahead with our paper.
"One may very safely recommend a little more enthusiasm to the modern Painters; too much is certainly not the vice of the present age. The Italians seem to have been continually declining in this respect, from the time of Michael Angelo to that of Carlo Maratti,[44] and from thence to the very bathos of insipidity to which they are now sunk; so that there is no need of remarking, that where I mentioned the Italian painters in opposition to the Dutch, I mean not the moderns, but the heads of the old Roman and Bolognian schools; nor did I mean to include, in my idea of an Italian painter, the Venetian school, which may be said to be the Dutch part of the Italian genius. I have only to add a word of advice to the Painters,—that, however excellent they may be in painting naturally, they would not flatter themselves very much upon it; and to the Connoisseurs, that when they see a cat or a fiddle painted so finely, that, as the phrase is, it looks as if you could take it up, they would not for that reason immediately compare the Painter to Raffaelle and Michael Angelo."
"One may very safely recommend a little more enthusiasm to the modern Painters; too much is certainly not the vice of the present age. The Italians seem to have been continually declining in this respect, from the time of Michael Angelo to that of Carlo Maratti,[44] and from thence to the very bathos of insipidity to which they are now sunk; so that there is no need of remarking, that where I mentioned the Italian painters in opposition to the Dutch, I mean not the moderns, but the heads of the old Roman and Bolognian schools; nor did I mean to include, in my idea of an Italian painter, the Venetian school, which may be said to be the Dutch part of the Italian genius. I have only to add a word of advice to the Painters,—that, however excellent they may be in painting naturally, they would not flatter themselves very much upon it; and to the Connoisseurs, that when they see a cat or a fiddle painted so finely, that, as the phrase is, it looks as if you could take it up, they would not for that reason immediately compare the Painter to Raffaelle and Michael Angelo."
In this passage there are four points chiefly to be remarked. The first, that in the year 1759 the Italian painters were, in our author's opinion, sunk in the very bathos of insipidity. The second, that the Venetian painters, i.e. Titian, Tintoret, and Veronese, are, in our author's opinion, to be classed with the Dutch; that is to say, are painters in a style "in which the slowest intellect is always sure to succeed best." Thirdly, that painting naturally is not a difficult thing, nor one on which a painter should pride himself. And, finally, that connoisseurs, seeing a cat or a fiddle successfully painted, ought not therefore immediately to compare the painter to Raphael or Michael Angelo.
In this passage, there are four main points to note. First, in 1759, the Italian painters were, according to our author, stuck in a really boring phase. Second, the Venetian painters—like Titian, Tintoretto, and Veronese—are, in the author's view, comparable to the Dutch painters; meaning they work in a style that anyone, even with the slowest intellect, can succeed at. Third, painting itself isn’t inherently difficult, nor should a painter take pride in it. Finally, when connoisseurs see a painting of a cat or a fiddle done well, they shouldn’t automatically compare the painter to Raphael or Michelangelo.
Yet Raphael painted fiddles very carefully in the foreground of his St. Cecilia,—so carefully, that they quite look as if they might be taken up. So carefully, that I never yet looked at the picture without wishing that somebody would take them up, and out of the way. And I am under a very strong persuasion that Raphael did not think painting "naturally" an easy thing. It will be well to examine into this point a little; and for the present, with the reader's permission, we will pass over the first two statements in this passage (touching the character of Italian art in 1759, and of Venetian art in general), and immediately examine some of the evidence existing as to the real dignity of "natural" painting—that is to say, of painting carried to the point at which it reaches a deceptive appearance of reality.
Yet Raphael painted fiddles very carefully in the foreground of his St. Cecilia—so carefully that they look as if you could pick them up. So carefully that I’ve never looked at the painting without wishing someone *would* pick them up and move them out of the way. I’m convinced that Raphael didn’t think painting "naturally" was an easy task. It’s worth exploring this idea a bit; and for now, with the reader’s permission, we'll skip over the first two statements in this passage (about Italian art in 1759 and Venetian art in general) and directly examine some of the evidence regarding the true dignity of "natural" painting—that is, painting taken to the point where it creates a convincing illusion of reality.
OF REALIZATION
VOLUME III, CHAPTER 2
In the outset of this inquiry, the reader must thoroughly understand that we are not now considering what is to be painted, but how far it is to be painted. Not whether Raphael does right in representing angels playing upon violins, or whether Veronese does right in allowing cats and monkeys to join the company of kings: but whether, supposing the subjects rightly chosen, they ought on the canvas to look like real angels with real violins, and substantial cats looking at veritable kings; or only like imaginary angels with soundless violins, ideal cats, and unsubstantial kings.
At the beginning of this discussion, the reader needs to completely understand that we are not currently considering what should be painted, but how far it should be painted. It’s not about whether Raphael is correct in depicting angels playing violins, or whether Veronese is right to include cats and monkeys among kings: but whether, assuming the subjects are chosen correctly, they should appear on the canvas as real angels with actual violins, and real cats looking at genuine kings; or just as imaginary angels with silent violins, ideal cats, and illusionary kings.
Now, from the first moment when painting began to be a subject of literary inquiry and general criticism, I cannot remember any writer, not professedly artistical, who has not, more or less, in one part of his book or another, countenanced the idea that the great end of art is to produce a deceptive resemblance of reality. It may be, indeed, that we shall find the writers, through many pages, explaining principles of ideal beauty, and professing great delight in the evidences of imagination. But whenever a picture is to be definitely described,—whenever the writer desires to convey to others some impression of an extraordinary excellence, all praise is wound up with some such statements as these: "It was so exquisitely painted that you expected the figures to move and speak; you approached the flowers to enjoy their smell, and stretched your hand towards the fruit which had fallen from the branches. You shrunk back lest the sword of the warrior should indeed descend, and turned away your head that you might not witness the agonies of the expiring martyr."
Now, from the very first moment painting became a topic of literary exploration and general critique, I can't recall any writer, not specifically focused on art, who hasn’t, to some extent, supported the idea that the main purpose of art is to create a misleading likeness of reality. It may be that we’ll find writers spending many pages discussing the principles of ideal beauty and expressing great enjoyment in the signs of imagination. But whenever a painting is to be specifically described—whenever the writer wants to share with others the impression of exceptional quality—all praise is summed up with statements like these: "It was painted so beautifully that you expected the figures to move and speak; you leaned in to enjoy the smell of the flowers and reached out for the fruit that had fallen from the branches. You flinched back, fearing the warrior’s sword might really fall, and turned your head away so you wouldn't have to witness the agony of the dying martyr."
In a large number of instances, language such as this will be found to be merely a clumsy effort to convey to others a sense of the admiration, of which the writer does not understand the real cause in himself. A person is attracted to a picture by the beauty of its colour, interested by the liveliness of its story, and touched by certain countenances or details which remind him of friends whom he loved, or scenes in which he delighted. He naturally supposes that what gives him so much pleasure must be a notable example of the painter's skill; but he is ashamed to confess, or perhaps does not know, that he is so much a child as to be fond of bright colours and amusing incidents; and he is quite unconscious of the associations which have so secret and inevitable a power over his heart. He casts about for the cause of his delight, and can discover no other than that he thought the picture like reality.
In many cases, language like this is just a clumsy attempt to express the admiration that the writer doesn't fully understand in themselves. A person is drawn to a painting by its beautiful colors, intrigued by its engaging story, and moved by certain faces or details that remind them of loved ones or enjoyable experiences. They naturally assume that what brings them so much joy must be a significant example of the artist's talent; however, they are embarrassed to admit, or perhaps don't realize, that they're so childlike in their fondness for bright colors and entertaining stories. They don't recognize the powerful, hidden connections that influence their feelings. They look for the reason behind their enjoyment and can only conclude that they thought the painting resembled reality.
In another, perhaps, a still larger number of cases, such language will be found to be that of simple ignorance—the ignorance of persons whose position in life compels them to speak of art, without having any real enjoyment of it. It is inexcusably required from people of the world, that they should see merit in Claudes[45] and Titians; and the only merit which many persons can either see or conceive in them is, that they must be "like nature."
In another, perhaps, a still larger number of cases, such language will be found to be that of simple ignorance—the ignorance of persons whose position in life compels them to speak of art, without having any real enjoyment of it. It is inexcusably required from people of the world, that they should see merit in Claudes[45] and Titians; and the only merit which many persons can either see or conceive in them is, that they must be "like nature."
In other cases, the deceptive power of the art is really felt to be a source of interest and amusement. This is the case with a large number of the collectors of Dutch pictures. They enjoy seeing what is flat made to look round, exactly as a child enjoys a trick of legerdemain: they rejoice in flies which the spectator vainly attempts to brush away,[46] and in dew which he endeavours to dry by putting the picture in the sun. They take it for the greatest compliment to their treasures that they should be mistaken for windows; and think the parting of Abraham and Hagar adequately represented if Hagar seems to be really crying.[47]
In other cases, the deceptive power of the art is really felt to be a source of interest and amusement. This is the case with a large number of the collectors of Dutch pictures. They enjoy seeing what is flat made to look round, exactly as a child enjoys a trick of legerdemain: they rejoice in flies which the spectator vainly attempts to brush away,[46] and in dew which he endeavours to dry by putting the picture in the sun. They take it for the greatest compliment to their treasures that they should be mistaken for windows; and think the parting of Abraham and Hagar adequately represented if Hagar seems to be really crying.[47]
It is against critics and connoisseurs of this latter stamp (of whom, in the year 1759, the juries of art were for the most part composed) that the essay of Reynolds, which we have been examining, was justly directed. But Reynolds had not sufficiently considered that neither the men of this class, nor of the two other classes above described, constitute the entire body of those who praise Art for its realization; and that the holding of this apparently shallow and vulgar opinion cannot, in all cases, be attributed to the want either of penetration, sincerity, or sense. The collectors of Gerard Dows and Hobbimas may be passed by with a smile; and the affectations of Walpole and simplicities of Vasari[48] dismissed with contempt or with compassion. But very different men from these have held precisely the same language; and, one amongst the rest, whose authority is absolutely, and in all points, overwhelming.
It is against critics and connoisseurs of this latter stamp (of whom, in the year 1759, the juries of art were for the most part composed) that the essay of Reynolds, which we have been examining, was justly directed. But Reynolds had not sufficiently considered that neither the men of this class, nor of the two other classes above described, constitute the entire body of those who praise Art for its realization; and that the holding of this apparently shallow and vulgar opinion cannot, in all cases, be attributed to the want either of penetration, sincerity, or sense. The collectors of Gerard Dows and Hobbimas may be passed by with a smile; and the affectations of Walpole and simplicities of Vasari[48] dismissed with contempt or with compassion. But very different men from these have held precisely the same language; and, one amongst the rest, whose authority is absolutely, and in all points, overwhelming.
There was probably never a period in which the influence of art over the minds of men seemed to depend less on its merely imitative power, than the close of the thirteenth century. No painting or sculpture at that time reached more than a rude resemblance of reality. Its despised perspective, imperfect chiaroscuro, and unrestrained flights of fantastic imagination, separated the artist's work from nature by an interval which there was no attempt to disguise, and little to diminish. And yet, at this very period, the greatest poet of that, or perhaps of any other age, and the attached friend of its greatest painter,[49] who must over and over again have held full and free conversation with him respecting the objects of his art, speaks in the following terms of painting, supposed to be carried to its highest perfection:
There was probably never a period in which the influence of art over the minds of men seemed to depend less on its merely imitative power, than the close of the thirteenth century. No painting or sculpture at that time reached more than a rude resemblance of reality. Its despised perspective, imperfect chiaroscuro, and unrestrained flights of fantastic imagination, separated the artist's work from nature by an interval which there was no attempt to disguise, and little to diminish. And yet, at this very period, the greatest poet of that, or perhaps of any other age, and the attached friend of its greatest painter,[49] who must over and over again have held full and free conversation with him respecting the objects of his art, speaks in the following terms of painting, supposed to be carried to its highest perfection:
Qual di pennel fu maestro, e di stile
Qual di pennel fu maestro, e di stile
Che ritraesse l'ombre, e i tratti, chi' ivi
Che ritraesse l'ombre, e i tratti, chi' ivi
Mirar farieno uno ingegno sottile?
Look at a clever device?
Morti li morti, e i vivi parean vivi:
Mortals are dead, and the living seem alive:
Non vide me' di me, chi vide il vero,
Non vide me' di me, chi vide il vero,
Quant' io calcai, fin che chinato givi.
Quant' io calcai, fin che chinato givi.
DANTE, Purgatorio, canto xii. 1. 64.
DANTE, Purgatorio, canto 12. 1. 64.
What master of the pencil, or the style,
What master of the pencil or the pen,
Had traced the shades and lines that might have made
Had traced the shapes and lines that could have formed
The subtlest workman wonder? Dead, the dead,
The subtlest workman wonder? Dead, the dead,
The living seemed alive; with clearer view
The living felt vibrant; with a clearer perspective
His eye beheld not, who beheld the truth,
His eye did not see, who saw the truth,
Than mine what I did tread on, while I went
Than mine what I stepped on while I walked
Low bending.
Low bend.
—CARY.
—CARY.
Dante has here clearly no other idea of the highest art than that it should bring back, as in a mirror or vision, the aspect of things passed or absent. The scenes of which he speaks are, on the pavement, for ever represented by angelic power, so that the souls which traverse this circle of the rock may see them, as if the years of the world had been rolled back, and they again stood beside the actors in the moment of action. Nor do I think that Dante's authority is absolutely necessary to compel us to admit that such art as this might, indeed, be the highest possible. Whatever delight we may have been in the habit of taking in pictures, if it were but truly offered to us, to remove at our will the canvas from the frame, and in lieu of it to behold, fixed for ever, the image of some of those mighty scenes which it has been our way to make mere themes for the artist's fancy; if, for instance, we could again behold the Magdalene receiving her pardon at Christ's feet, or the disciples sitting with Him at the table of Emmaus; and this not feebly nor fancifully, but as if some silver mirror that had leaned against the wall of the chamber, had been miraculously commanded to retain for ever the colours that had flashed upon it for an instant,—would we not part with our picture—Titian's or Veronese's though it might be?
Dante clearly sees the highest art as something that should reflect the appearance of things that have passed or are absent, like a mirror or vision. The scenes he describes are forever portrayed on the pavement by angelic power, allowing the souls that travel this circle of the rock to see them as if the years had rolled back, and they were once again present with the actors at the moment of action. I also believe that we don’t need Dante's authority to agree that such art could indeed be the highest form of expression. No matter how much we enjoy looking at paintings, if it were truly possible for us to remove the canvas from the frame and instead witness, forever captured, the image of some of those powerful scenes that we normally consider mere subjects for the artist's imagination—like seeing the Magdalene receiving her forgiveness at Christ's feet, or the disciples sharing a meal with Him at Emmaus—and not just in a weak or fanciful way, but as if a silver mirror propped against the wall had been miraculously commanded to hold onto the colors that briefly flashed upon it—would we not choose to give up our painting, whether it's a Titian or a Veronese?
Yes, the reader answers, in the instance of such scenes as these, but not if the scene represented were uninteresting. Not, indeed, if it were utterly vulgar or painful; but we are not yet certain that the art which represents what is vulgar or painful is itself of much value; and with respect to the art whose aim is beauty, even of an inferior order, it seems that Dante's idea of its perfection has still much evidence in its favour. For among persons of native good sense, and courage enough to speak their minds, we shall often find a considerable degree of doubt as to the use of art, in consequence of their habitual comparison of it with reality. "What is the use, to me, of the painted landscape?" they will ask: "I see more beautiful and perfect landscapes every day of my life in my forenoon walk." "What is the use, to me, of the painted effigy of hero or beauty? I can see a stamp of higher heroism, and light of purer beauty, on the faces round me, utterly inexpressible by the highest human skill." Now, it is evident that to persons of this temper the only valuable picture would, indeed, be mirrors, reflecting permanently the images of the things in which they took delight, and of the faces that they loved. "Nay," but the reader interrupts (if he is of the Idealist school), "I deny that more beautiful things are to be seen in nature than in art; on the contrary, everything in nature is faulty, and art represents nature as perfected." Be it so. Must, therefore, this perfected nature be imperfectly represented? Is it absolutely required of the painter, who has conceived perfection, that he should so paint it as to look only like a picture? Or is not Dante's view of the matter right even here, and would it not be well that the perfect conception of Pallas should be so given as to look like Pallas herself, rather than merely like the picture of Pallas?[50]
Yes, the reader answers, in the instance of such scenes as these, but not if the scene represented were uninteresting. Not, indeed, if it were utterly vulgar or painful; but we are not yet certain that the art which represents what is vulgar or painful is itself of much value; and with respect to the art whose aim is beauty, even of an inferior order, it seems that Dante's idea of its perfection has still much evidence in its favour. For among persons of native good sense, and courage enough to speak their minds, we shall often find a considerable degree of doubt as to the use of art, in consequence of their habitual comparison of it with reality. "What is the use, to me, of the painted landscape?" they will ask: "I see more beautiful and perfect landscapes every day of my life in my forenoon walk." "What is the use, to me, of the painted effigy of hero or beauty? I can see a stamp of higher heroism, and light of purer beauty, on the faces round me, utterly inexpressible by the highest human skill." Now, it is evident that to persons of this temper the only valuable picture would, indeed, be mirrors, reflecting permanently the images of the things in which they took delight, and of the faces that they loved. "Nay," but the reader interrupts (if he is of the Idealist school), "I deny that more beautiful things are to be seen in nature than in art; on the contrary, everything in nature is faulty, and art represents nature as perfected." Be it so. Must, therefore, this perfected nature be imperfectly represented? Is it absolutely required of the painter, who has conceived perfection, that he should so paint it as to look only like a picture? Or is not Dante's view of the matter right even here, and would it not be well that the perfect conception of Pallas should be so given as to look like Pallas herself, rather than merely like the picture of Pallas?[50]
It is not easy for us to answer this question rightly, owing to the difficulty of imagining any art which should reach the perfection supposed. Our actual powers of imitation are so feeble that wherever deception is attempted, a subject of a comparatively low or confined order must be chosen. I do not enter at present into the inquiry how far the powers of imitation extend; but assuredly up to the present period they have been so limited that it is hardly possible for us to conceive a deceptive art embracing a high range of subject. But let the reader make the effort, and consider seriously what he would give at any moment to have the power of arresting the fairest scenes, those which so often rise before him only to vanish; to stay the cloud in its fading, the leaf in its trembling, and the shadows in their changing; to bid the fitful foam be fixed upon the river, and the ripples be everlasting upon the lake; and then to bear away with him no darkened or feeble sun-stain (though even that is beautiful), but a counterfeit which should seem no counterfeit-the true and perfect image of life indeed. Or rather (for the full majesty of such a power is not thus sufficiently expressed) let him consider that it would be in effect nothing else than a capacity of transporting himself at any moment into any scene—a gift as great as can be possessed by a disembodied spirit: and suppose, also, this necromancy embracing not only the present but the past, and enabling us seemingly to enter into the very bodily presence of men long since gathered to the dust; to behold them in act as they lived, but—with greater privilege than ever was granted to the companions of those transient acts of life—to see them fastened at our will in the gesture and expression of an instant, and stayed, on the eve of some great deed, in immortality of burning purpose. Conceive, so far as it is possible, such power as this, and then say whether the art which conferred it is to be spoken lightly of, or whether we should not rather reverence, as half divine, a gift which would go so far as to raise us into the rank, and invest us with the felicities, of angels?
It’s not easy for us to answer this question correctly because it’s hard to imagine any art that could achieve the assumed perfection. Our actual ability to imitate is so limited that whenever we try to create an illusion, we have to choose a subject that is fairly simple or narrow. I’m not going to delve into how far our imitation skills go right now, but it's clear that until now, they have been so restricted that it's almost impossible for us to picture an art form that could convincingly cover a wide range of subjects. However, I urge the reader to make an effort and seriously think about how much he would give to have the ability to capture the most beautiful scenes, those that often appear before him only to disappear; to freeze the cloud as it fades, the leaf as it quivers, and the shadows as they shift; to fix the frothy waves on the river and make the ripples on the lake everlasting; and to take away not just a dark or faint sun-stain (though that too is lovely), but a replica that doesn’t look like a replica—the true and perfect image of life itself. Or rather (since the full greatness of such power isn't adequately conveyed this way), let him consider that it would essentially be the ability to transport himself to any scene at any moment—a gift as great as any spirit could possess: and also imagine this extraordinary power encompassing not just the present but the past, allowing us seemingly to step into the actual presence of people long since returned to dust; to see them as they lived, but—with a privilege greater than that ever granted to those who witnessed those fleeting moments—to capture them at our will in the pose and expression of a specific instant, and freeze them, on the eve of some monumental act, in an immortal state of burning intent. Imagine, as much as you can, such power and then say whether the art that could give us this is something to be dismissed lightly or if we should instead regard it, as something almost divine, a gift that would elevate us to the level and grant us the joys of angels?
Yet such would imitative art be in its perfection. Not by any means an easy thing, as Reynolds supposes it. Far from being easy, it is so utterly beyond all human power that we have difficulty even in conceiving its nature or results—the best art we as yet possess comes so far short of it.
Yet that's how perfect imitative art would be. It's by no means as easy as Reynolds thinks. In fact, it's so far beyond our abilities that we struggle to even imagine what it would be like or what it would achieve—the best art we have so far falls really short of it.
But we must not rashly come to the conclusion that such art would, indeed, be the highest possible. There is much to be considered hereafter on the other side; the only conclusion we are as yet warranted in forming is, that Reynolds had no right to speak lightly or contemptuously of imitative art; that in fact, when he did so, he had not conceived its entire nature, but was thinking of some vulgar conditions of it, which were the only ones known to him, and that, therefore, his whole endeavour to explain the difference between great and mean art has been disappointed; that he has involved himself in a crowd of theories, whose issue he had not foreseen, and committed himself to conclusions which, he never intended. There is an instinctive consciousness in his own mind of the difference between high and low art; but he is utterly incapable of explaining it, and every effort which he makes to do so involves him in unexpected fallacy and absurdity. It is not true that Poetry does not concern herself with minute details. It is not true that high art seeks only the Invariable. It is not true that imitative art is an easy thing. It is not true that the faithful rendering of nature is an employment in which "the slowest intellect is likely to succeed best." All these successive assertions are utterly false and untenable, while the plain truth, a truth lying at the very door, has all the while escaped him,—that which was incidentally stated in the preceding chapter,—namely, that the difference between great and mean art lies, not in definable methods of handling, or styles of representation, or choices of subjects, but wholly in the nobleness of the end to which the effort of the painter is addressed. We cannot say that a painter is great because he paints boldly, or paints delicately; because he generalizes or particularizes; because he loves detail, or because he disdains it. He is great if, by any of these means, he has laid open noble truths, or aroused noble emotions. It does not matter whether he paint the petal of a rose, or the chasms of a precipice, so that Love and Admiration attend him as he labours, and wait for ever upon his work. It does not matter whether he toil for months upon a few inches of his canvas, or cover a palace front with colour in a day, so only that it be with a solemn purpose that he has filled his heart with patience, or urged his hand to haste. And it does not matter whether he seek for his subjects among peasants or nobles, among the heroic or the simple, in courts or in fields, so only that he behold all things with a thirst for beauty, and a hatred of meanness and vice. There are, indeed, certain methods of representation which are usually adopted by the most active minds, and certain characters of subject usually delighted in by the noblest hearts; but it is quite possible, quite easy, to adopt the manner of painting without sharing the activity of mind, and to imitate the choice of subject without possessing the nobility of spirit; while, on the other hand, it is altogether impossible to foretell on what strange objects the strength of a great man will sometimes be concentrated, or by what strange means he will sometimes express himself. So that true criticism of art never can consist in the mere application of rules; it can be just only when it is founded on quick sympathy with the innumerable instincts and changeful efforts of human nature, chastened and guided by unchanging love of all things that God has created to be beautiful, and pronounced to be good.
But we shouldn't hastily conclude that this kind of art would be the best possible. There's a lot more to consider on the other side; the only conclusion we can currently draw is that Reynolds had no right to dismiss or look down on imitative art. In fact, when he did, he hadn’t grasped its full nature and was only thinking about some crude aspects of it, which were the only ones he knew. Therefore, his whole attempt to explain the difference between great and mediocre art has fallen short. He got caught up in a jumble of theories, the outcomes of which he hadn't anticipated, and committed to conclusions he never intended. He has an instinctive understanding of the distinction between high and low art in his own mind, but he’s completely incapable of explaining it. Every attempt he makes to do so leads him into unexpected mistakes and absurdities. It is not true that poetry disregards small details. It is not true that high art only seeks the unchanging. It is not true that imitative art is easy. It is not true that accurately duplicating nature is a task where "the slowest intellect is likely to succeed best." All these assertions are absolutely false and indefensible, while the simple truth, which was mentioned in the previous chapter, has entirely eluded him—namely, that the difference between great and mediocre art lies not in specific techniques, styles of representation, or choices of subject, but entirely in the nobleness of the goal the painter is striving for. We can't say a painter is great just because he paints boldly or delicately, because he generalizes or focuses on details, because he loves intricacies or dismisses them. He is great if, by any of these means, he reveals noble truths or inspires noble feelings. It doesn’t matter whether he paints the petal of a rose or the depths of a cliff, as long as Love and Admiration accompany him as he works and always follow his creations. It doesn’t matter if he spends months on just a few inches of his canvas or covers an entire palace front with color in a day, as long as he fills his heart with purpose and balances patience with urgency. And it doesn’t matter whether he finds his subjects among peasants or nobles, the heroic or the simple, in courts or in fields, as long as he views everything with a desire for beauty and a disdain for meanness and vice. There are indeed certain styles of representation often chosen by the most active minds and certain subjects typically favored by the noblest hearts; however, it’s entirely possible—and quite common—to adopt a painting style without sharing the mindset behind it, and to mimic a subject choice without having the nobility of spirit. On the other hand, it’s entirely unpredictable what unusual subjects a great artist may focus on, or what unconventional means he will use to express himself. Therefore, true art criticism can never simply consist of following rules; it can only be valid when it comes from a deep empathy for the countless instincts and ever-changing efforts of human nature, tempered and guided by a constant love for all that God created to be beautiful and called good.
OF THE NOVELTY OF LANDSCAPE
VOLUME III, CHAPTER II
Having now obtained, I trust, clear ideas, up to a certain point, of what is generally right and wrong in all art, both in conception and in workmanship, we have to apply these laws of right to the particular branch of art which is the subject of our present inquiry, namely, landscape-painting. Respecting which, after the various meditations into which we have been led on the high duties and ideals of art, it may not improbably occur to us first to ask,—whether it be worth inquiring about at all.
Having now gained, I hope, a clear understanding, to some extent, of what is generally considered right and wrong in all art, both in ideas and execution, we need to apply these principles to the specific area of art we're currently looking at, which is landscape painting. Regarding this, after the different reflections we've had on the important responsibilities and ideals of art, it might first occur to us to ask—whether it’s even worth exploring at all.
That question, perhaps the reader thinks, should have been asked and answered before I had written, or he read, two volumes and a half about it. So I had answered it, in my own mind; but it seems time now to give the grounds for this answer. If, indeed, the reader has never suspected that landscape-painting was anything but good, right, and healthy work, I should be sorry to put any doubt of its being so into his mind; but if, as seems to me more likely, he, living in this busy and perhaps somewhat calamitous age, has some suspicion that landscape-painting is but an idle and empty business, not worth all our long talk about it, then, perhaps, he will be pleased to have such suspicion done away, before troubling himself farther with these disquisitions.
That question, the reader might think, should have been asked and answered before I wrote, or he read, two and a half volumes about it. So I had answered it in my own mind; but it seems like it’s time now to explain the reasons for this answer. If the reader has never doubted that landscape painting is anything but good, right, and healthy work, I wouldn’t want to put any doubt in his mind; but if, as I think is more likely, he, living in this busy and possibly chaotic age, suspects that landscape painting is just a pointless and empty task not worth all our lengthy discussions, then maybe he’ll appreciate having that suspicion cleared up before he continues to engage with these topics.
I should rather be glad, than otherwise, that he had formed some suspicion on this matter. If he has at all admitted the truth of anything hitherto said respecting great art, and its choices of subject, it seems to me he ought, by this time, to be questioning with himself whether road-side weeds, old cottages, broken stones, and such other materials, be worthy matters for grave men to busy themselves in the imitation of. And I should like him to probe this doubt to the deep of it, and bring all his misgivings out to the broad light, that we may see how we are to deal with them, or ascertain if indeed they are too well founded to be dealt with.
I should rather be glad than otherwise that he had formed some suspicions about this. If he has ever accepted the truth of anything we've discussed regarding great art and its choice of subjects, it seems to me he should be questioning whether roadside weeds, old cottages, broken stones, and similar things are worthy subjects for serious artists to focus on. I really want him to examine this doubt thoroughly and bring all his concerns into the open so we can figure out how to address them, or determine if they are indeed too valid to handle.
And to this end I would ask him now to imagine himself entering, for the first time in his life, the room of the Old Water-Colour Society:[51] and to suppose that he has entered it, not for the sake of a quiet examination of the paintings one by one, but in order to seize such ideas as it may generally suggest respecting the state and meaning of modern, as compared with elder, art. I suppose him, of course, that he may be capable of such a comparison, to be in some degree familiar with the different forms in which art has developed itself within the periods historically known to us; but never, till that moment, to have seen any completely modern work. So prepared, and so unprepared, he would, as his ideas began to arrange themselves, be first struck by the number of paintings representing blue mountains, clear lakes, and ruined castles or cathedrals, and he would say to himself: "There is something strange in the mind of these modern people! Nobody ever cared about blue mountains before, or tried to paint the broken stones of old walls." And the more he considered the subject, the more he would feel the peculiarity; and, as he thought over the art of Greeks and Romans, he would still repeat, with increasing certainty of conviction: "Mountains! I remember none. The Greeks did not seem, as artists, to know that such things were in the world. They carved, or variously represented, men, and horses, and beasts, and birds, and all kinds of living creatures,—yes, even down to cuttle-fish; and trees, in a sort of way; but not so much as the outline of a mountain; and as for lakes, they merely showed they knew the difference between salt and fresh water by the fish they put into each." Then he would pass on to mediæval art; and still he would be obliged to repeat: "Mountains! I remember none. Some careless and jagged arrangements of blue spires or spikes on the horizon, and, here and there, an attempt at representing an overhanging rock with a hole through it; but merely in order to divide the light behind some human figure. Lakes! No, nothing of the kind,—only blue bays of sea put in to fill up the background when the painter could not think of anything else. Broken-down buildings! No; for the most part very complete and well-appointed buildings, if any; and never buildings at all, but to give place or explanation to some circumstance of human conduct." And then he would look up again to the modern pictures, observing, with an increasing astonishment, that here the human interest had, in many cases, altogether disappeared. That mountains, instead of being used only as a blue ground for the relief of the heads of saints, were themselves the exclusive subjects of reverent contemplation; that their ravines, and peaks, and forests, were all painted with an appearance of as much enthusiasm as had formerly been devoted to the dimple of beauty, or the frowns of asceticism; and that all the living interest which was still supposed necessary to the scene, might be supplied by a traveller in a slouched hat, a beggar in a scarlet cloak, or, in default of these, even by a heron or a wild duck.
And to this end I would ask him now to imagine himself entering, for the first time in his life, the room of the Old Water-Colour Society:[51] and to suppose that he has entered it, not for the sake of a quiet examination of the paintings one by one, but in order to seize such ideas as it may generally suggest respecting the state and meaning of modern, as compared with elder, art. I suppose him, of course, that he may be capable of such a comparison, to be in some degree familiar with the different forms in which art has developed itself within the periods historically known to us; but never, till that moment, to have seen any completely modern work. So prepared, and so unprepared, he would, as his ideas began to arrange themselves, be first struck by the number of paintings representing blue mountains, clear lakes, and ruined castles or cathedrals, and he would say to himself: "There is something strange in the mind of these modern people! Nobody ever cared about blue mountains before, or tried to paint the broken stones of old walls." And the more he considered the subject, the more he would feel the peculiarity; and, as he thought over the art of Greeks and Romans, he would still repeat, with increasing certainty of conviction: "Mountains! I remember none. The Greeks did not seem, as artists, to know that such things were in the world. They carved, or variously represented, men, and horses, and beasts, and birds, and all kinds of living creatures,—yes, even down to cuttle-fish; and trees, in a sort of way; but not so much as the outline of a mountain; and as for lakes, they merely showed they knew the difference between salt and fresh water by the fish they put into each." Then he would pass on to mediæval art; and still he would be obliged to repeat: "Mountains! I remember none. Some careless and jagged arrangements of blue spires or spikes on the horizon, and, here and there, an attempt at representing an overhanging rock with a hole through it; but merely in order to divide the light behind some human figure. Lakes! No, nothing of the kind,—only blue bays of sea put in to fill up the background when the painter could not think of anything else. Broken-down buildings! No; for the most part very complete and well-appointed buildings, if any; and never buildings at all, but to give place or explanation to some circumstance of human conduct." And then he would look up again to the modern pictures, observing, with an increasing astonishment, that here the human interest had, in many cases, altogether disappeared. That mountains, instead of being used only as a blue ground for the relief of the heads of saints, were themselves the exclusive subjects of reverent contemplation; that their ravines, and peaks, and forests, were all painted with an appearance of as much enthusiasm as had formerly been devoted to the dimple of beauty, or the frowns of asceticism; and that all the living interest which was still supposed necessary to the scene, might be supplied by a traveller in a slouched hat, a beggar in a scarlet cloak, or, in default of these, even by a heron or a wild duck.
And if he could entirely divest himself of his own modern habits of thought, and regard the subjects in question with the feelings of a knight or monk of the Middle Ages, it might be a question whether those feelings would not rapidly verge towards contempt. "What!" he might perhaps mutter to himself, "here are human beings spending the whole of their lives in making pictures of bits of stone and runlets of water, withered sticks and flying fogs, and actually not a picture of the gods or the heroes! none of the saints or the martyrs! none of the angels and demons! none of councils or battles, or any other single thing worth the thought of a man! Trees and clouds indeed! as if I should not see as many trees as I cared to see, and more, in the first half of my day's journey to-morrow, or as if it mattered to any man whether the sky were clear or cloudy, so long as his armour did not get too hot in the sun!"
And if he could completely rid himself of his modern way of thinking and look at the subjects in question with the mindset of a knight or monk from the Middle Ages, he might wonder if those feelings would quickly turn to contempt. "What!" he might mumble to himself, "here are people spending their entire lives creating pictures of chunks of stone and streams of water, dead branches and drifting fogs, and not a single painting of gods or heroes! None of the saints or martyrs! None of the angels or demons! No councils or battles, or anything else worth a man's thought! Trees and clouds, really! As if I wouldn’t see as many trees as I wanted to tomorrow on the first part of my journey, or as if it mattered to anyone whether the sky was clear or overcast, as long as his armor didn’t get too hot in the sun!"
There can be no question that this would have been somewhat the tone of thought with which either a Lacedæmonian, a soldier of Rome in her strength, or a knight of the thirteenth century, would have been apt to regard these particular forms of our present art. Nor can there be any question that, in many respects, their judgment would have been just. It is true that the indignation of the Spartan or Roman would have been equally excited against any appearance of luxurious industry; but the mediæval knight would, to the full, have admitted the nobleness of art; only he would have had it employed in decorating his church or his prayer-book, not in imitating moors and clouds. And the feelings of all the three would have agreed in this,—that their main ground of offence must have been the want of seriousness and purpose in what they saw. They would all have admitted the nobleness of whatever conduced to the honour of the gods, or the power of the nation; but they would not have understood how the skill of human life could be wisely spent in that which did no honour either to Jupiter or to the Virgin; and which in no wise tended, apparently, either to the accumulation of wealth, the excitement of patriotism, or the advancement of morality.
There’s no doubt that this would have been the attitude a Spartan, a strong Roman soldier, or a knight from the thirteenth century would have toward these particular forms of our current art. And it's clear that, in many ways, their opinions would have been justified. It's true that a Spartan or Roman would have felt outraged by any sign of excessive luxury; however, the medieval knight would have fully recognized the nobility of art, but he would have wanted it used to decorate his church or prayer book, not to replicate moors and clouds. All three of them would have agreed on this—what would have offended them most would be the lack of seriousness and purpose in what they observed. They would have acknowledged the value of anything that honored the gods or empowered the nation, but they wouldn’t have grasped how the skills of human life could be wisely dedicated to things that brought no honor to Jupiter or the Virgin, and that apparently did not contribute to the accumulation of wealth, the stirring of patriotism, or the enhancement of morality.
And exactly so far forth their judgment would be just, as the landscape-painting could indeed be shown, for others as well as for them, to be art of this nugatory kind; and so far forth unjust, as that painting could be shown to depend upon, or cultivate, certain sensibilities which neither the Greek nor mediæval knight possessed, and which have resulted from some extraordinary change in human nature since their time. We have no right to assume, without very accurate examination of it, that this change has been an ennobling one. The simple fact, that we are, in some strange way, different from all the great races that have existed before us, cannot at once be received as the proof of our own greatness; nor can it be granted, without any question, that we have a legitimate subject of complacency in being under the influence of feelings, with which neither Miltiades nor the Black Prince, neither Homer nor Dante, neither Socrates nor St. Francis, could for an instant have sympathized.
And so far, their judgment would be fair, as landscape painting could indeed be shown, for both them and others, to be a form of art of this trivial kind; and so far unfair, as that painting could be shown to rely on or promote certain sensibilities that neither the Greeks nor medieval knights had, and which have emerged from a remarkable change in human nature since their era. We have no right to assume, without thorough examination, that this change has been an uplifting one. The simple fact that we are, in some strange way, different from all the great races that came before us cannot automatically be taken as proof of our own greatness; nor can it be accepted, without question, that we have a valid reason to feel proud of being influenced by emotions with which neither Miltiades nor the Black Prince, neither Homer nor Dante, nor Socrates nor St. Francis could have sympathized for even a moment.
Whether, however, this fact be one to excite our pride or not, it is assuredly one to excite our deepest interest. The fact itself is certain. For nearly six thousand years the energies of man have pursued certain beaten paths, manifesting some constancy of feeling throughout all that period, and involving some fellowship at heart, among the various nations who by turns succeeded or surpassed each other in the several aims of art or policy. So that, for these thousands of years, the whole human race might be to some extent described in general terms. Man was a creature separated from all others by his instinctive sense of an Existence superior to his own, invariably manifesting this sense of the being of a God more strongly in proportion to his own perfectness of mind and body; and making enormous and self-denying efforts, in order to obtain some persuasion of the immediate presence or approval of the Divinity. So that, on the whole, the best things he did were done as in the presence, or for the honour, of his gods; and, whether in statues, to help him to imagine them, or temples raised to their honour, or acts of self-sacrifice done in the hope of their love, he brought whatever was best and skilfullest in him into their service, and lived in a perpetual subjection to their unseen power. Also, he was always anxious to know something definite about them; and his chief books, songs, and pictures were filled with legends about them, or specially devoted to illustration of their lives and nature.
Whether or not this fact makes us feel proud, it definitely captures our deepest interest. The fact itself is clear. For nearly six thousand years, human efforts have followed certain established paths, showing a consistent feeling throughout that time and creating a sense of community among various nations that have alternated in excelling at different goals in art or politics. Thus, for all these thousands of years, humanity can be described in broad terms. Humans are unique creatures, distinguished from all others by an instinctive awareness of a higher existence, which becomes more pronounced as their mental and physical capabilities improve. They make significant and often selfless efforts to seek some assurance of the divine presence or approval. Overall, the greatest things they accomplished were done in acknowledgment or reverence for their gods. Whether through statues to help them visualize these deities, temples built in their honor, or acts of self-sacrifice in hopes of their affection, they dedicated their finest abilities to divine service and lived under the influence of an unseen power. Additionally, they were always eager to learn specific details about these gods, with their main books, songs, and artworks filled with legends about them or focused on depicting their lives and nature.
Next to these gods, he was always anxious to know something about his human ancestors; fond of exalting the memory, and telling or painting the history of old rulers and benefactors; yet full of an enthusiastic confidence in himself, as having in many ways advanced beyond the best efforts of past time; and eager to record his own doings for future fame. He was a creature eminently warlike, placing his principal pride in dominion; eminently beautiful, and having great delight in his own beauty; setting forth this beauty by every species of invention in dress, and rendering his arms and accoutrements superbly decorative of his form. He took, however, very little interest in anything but what belonged to humanity; caring in no wise for the external world, except as it influenced his own destiny; honouring the lightning because it could strike him, the sea because it could drown him, the fountains because they gave him drink, and the grass because it yielded him seed; but utterly incapable of feeling any special happiness in the love of such things, or any earnest emotion about them, considered as separate from man; therefore giving no time to the study of them;—knowing little of herbs, except only which were hurtful and which healing; of stones, only which would glitter brightest in a crown, or last the longest in a wall: of the wild beasts, which were best for food, and which the stoutest quarry for the hunter;—thus spending only on the lower creatures and inanimate things his waste energy, his dullest thoughts, his most languid emotions, and reserving all his acuter intellect for researches into his own nature and that of the gods; all his strength of will for the acquirement of political or moral power; all his sense of beauty for things immediately connected with his own person and life; and all his deep affections for domestic or divine companionship.
Next to these gods, he was always eager to learn about his human ancestors; he loved to honor their memory and share or depict the stories of past leaders and benefactors. Yet he was filled with a confident enthusiasm in himself, believing he had surpassed the greatest achievements of earlier times; and he was eager to document his own actions for future recognition. He was a distinctly warlike figure, taking his main pride in ruling; notably attractive, and enjoying his own beauty; showcasing this beauty through various styles of clothing, and making his weapons and gear impressively decorative to highlight his physique. However, he cared very little about anything beyond humanity; he was only interested in the external world as it affected his own fate; revering lightning because it could strike him, the sea because it could drown him, the fountains because they provided him with water, and the grass because it yielded him seeds; but he was completely unable to feel any real joy or strong emotion for these things, viewed separately from human existence; thus he devoted no time to studying them—knowing little about plants, only which were harmful and which were healing; about stones, only which would shine the brightest in a crown or last the longest in a wall; about wild animals, only which were best for food and which made the toughest prey for hunters; thus he wasted his energy, his dull thoughts, and his most lethargic emotions on lower creatures and inanimate things, while reserving all his sharper intellect for exploring his own nature and that of the gods; all his willpower for gaining political or moral authority; all his sense of beauty for things directly connected to his own person and life; and all his deep affections for companionship, either human or divine.
Such, in broad light and brief terms, was man for five thousand years. Such he is no longer. Let us consider what he is now, comparing the descriptions clause by clause.
Such, in broad light and brief terms, was man for five thousand years. Such he is no longer. Let us consider what he is now, comparing the descriptions clause by clause.
I. He was invariably sensible of the existence of gods, and went about all his speculations or works holding this as an acknowledged fact, making his best efforts in their service. Now he is capable of going through life with hardly any positive idea on this subject,—doubting, fearing, suspecting, analyzing,—doing everything, in fact, but believing; hardly ever getting quite up to that point which hitherto was wont to be the starting-point for all generations. And human work has accordingly hardly any reference to spiritual beings, but is done either from a patriotic or personal interest,—either to benefit mankind, or reach some selfish end, not (I speak of human work in the broad sense) to please the gods.
I. He was always aware of the existence of gods and approached all his thoughts and actions with this as a given, putting in his best efforts for their sake. Now he can go through life with barely any clear ideas on the matter—doubting, fearing, suspecting, analyzing—doing everything, in fact, but believing; rarely reaching that point which used to be the starting point for all generations. Consequently, human work seldom relates to spiritual beings and is driven either by patriotic or personal interests—either to help humanity or achieve some selfish goal, not (I’m talking about human work in general) to please the gods.
II. He was a beautiful creature, setting forth this beauty by all means in his power, and depending upon it for much of his authority over his fellows. So that the ruddy cheek of David, and the ivory skin of Atrides, and the towering presence of Saul, and the blue eyes of Coeur de Lion, were among chief reasons why they should be kings; and it was one of the aims of all education, and of all dress, to make the presence of the human form stately and lovely. Now it has become the task of grave philosophy partly to depreciate or conceal this bodily beauty; and even by those who esteem it in their hearts, it is not made one of the great ends of education; man has become, upon the whole, an ugly animal, and is not ashamed of his ugliness.
II. He was a beautiful being, showcasing this beauty in every way he could and relying on it for much of his influence over others. The rosy cheeks of David, the ivory skin of Atrides, the tall stature of Saul, and the blue eyes of Coeur de Lion were some of the main reasons they deserved to be kings; and one of the goals of all education and fashion was to make the human form appear majestic and attractive. Now, it's become the responsibility of serious philosophy to somewhat downplay or hide this physical beauty; and even among those who appreciate it inwardly, it's not prioritized as a major goal of education. Overall, humanity has become an unappealing species and isn't embarrassed by its lack of beauty.
III. He was eminently warlike. He is now gradually becoming more and more ashamed of all the arts and aims of battle. So that the desire of dominion, which was once frankly confessed or boasted of as a heroic passion, is now sternly reprobated or cunningly disclaimed.
III. He was extremely aggressive. He is now slowly becoming more and more ashamed of all the skills and goals of war. So the desire for power, which was once openly admitted or bragged about as a noble passion, is now harshly criticized or slyly denied.
IV. He used to take no interest in anything but what immediately concerned himself. Now, he has deep interest in the abstract nature of things, inquires as eagerly into the laws which regulate the economy of the material world, as into those of his own being, and manifests a passionate admiration of inanimate objects, closely resembling, in its elevation and tenderness, the affection which he bears to those living souls with which he is brought into the nearest fellowship.
IV. He used to care about nothing except what directly affected him. Now, he has a genuine interest in the fundamental nature of things, asking just as eagerly about the laws that govern the material world as he does about his own existence, and he shows a deep appreciation for inanimate objects, which closely resembles the love he has for the living beings he is closest to.
It is this last change only which is to be the subject of our present inquiry; but it cannot be doubted that it is closely connected with all the others, and that we can only thoroughly understand its nature by considering il in this connection. For, regarded by itself, we might perhaps, too rashly assume it to be a natural consequence of the progress of the race. There appears to be a diminution of selfishness in it, and a more extended and heartfelt desire of understanding the manner of God's working; and this the more, because one of the permanent characters of this change is a greater accuracy in the statement of external facts. When the eyes of men were fixed first upon themselves, and upon nature solely and secondarily as bearing upon their interests, it was of less consequence to them what the ultimate laws of nature were, than what their immediate effects were upon human beings. Hence they could rest satisfied with phenomena instead of principles, and accepted without scrutiny every fable which seemed sufficiently or gracefully to account for those phenomena. But so far as the eyes of men are now withdrawn from themselves, and turned upon the inanimate things about them, the results cease to be of importance, and the laws become essential.
It is this last change alone that will be the focus of our current inquiry; however, it’s clear that it’s closely linked with all the others, and we can only fully grasp its nature by looking at it in this context. If considered in isolation, we might too quickly assume it’s simply a natural outcome of the race's progress. There seems to be a reduction in selfishness within it and a broader, more genuine desire to understand how God works; this is especially true because one of the lasting features of this change is a greater accuracy in stating external facts. When people primarily focused on themselves and only secondarily on nature as it related to their interests, they cared less about the ultimate laws of nature than about the immediate effects on human beings. Consequently, they were satisfied with phenomena instead of principles and accepted without questioning any tale that appeared to explain those phenomena adequately or gracefully. But as people now shift their attention away from themselves and toward the inanimate things around them, the immediate outcomes lose significance, and the laws become crucial.
In these respects, it might easily appear to us that this change was assuredly one of steady and natural advance. But when we contemplate the others above noted, of which it is clearly one of the branches or consequences, we may suspect ourselves of over-rashness in our self-congratulation, and admit the necessity of a scrupulous analysis both of the feeling itself and of its tendencies.
In these ways, it might seem to us that this change was definitely a steady and natural progression. But when we think about the other aspects mentioned above, which are clearly one of the branches or results, we may start to doubt our own eagerness to celebrate and recognize the need for a careful examination of both the feeling itself and its implications.
Of course a complete analysis, or anything like it, would involve a treatise on the whole history of the world. I shall merely endeavour to note some of the leading and more interesting circumstances bearing on the subject, and to show sufficient practical ground for the conclusion, that landscape-painting is indeed a noble and useful art, though one not long known by man. I shall therefore examine, as best I can, the effect of landscape, 1st, on the Classical mind; 2dly, on the Mediæval mind; and lastly, on the Modern mind. But there is one point of some interest respecting the effect of it on any mind, which must be settled first; and this I will endeavour to do in the next chapter.
Of course, a complete analysis, or anything close to it, would require a detailed examination of the entire history of the world. I will simply try to highlight some of the key and more interesting aspects related to the topic and provide enough practical reasons to conclude that landscape painting is indeed a noble and useful art, even though it hasn't been known to humanity for very long. I will therefore look at the impact of landscape on, first, the Classical mind; second, the Medieval mind; and finally, the Modern mind. However, there is one point of particular interest regarding its effect on any mind that needs to be addressed first, and I will attempt to do so in the next chapter.
OF THE PATHETIC FALLACY
VOLUME III, CHAPTER 12
Now, therefore, putting these tiresome and absurd words[52] quite out of our way, we may go on at our ease to examine the point in question,—namely, the difference between the ordinary, proper, and true appearances of things to us; and the extraordinary, or false appearances, when we are under the influence of emotion, or contemplative fancy; false appearances, I say, as being entirely unconnected with any real power or character in the object, and only imputed to it by us.
Now, therefore, putting these tiresome and absurd words[52] quite out of our way, we may go on at our ease to examine the point in question,—namely, the difference between the ordinary, proper, and true appearances of things to us; and the extraordinary, or false appearances, when we are under the influence of emotion, or contemplative fancy; false appearances, I say, as being entirely unconnected with any real power or character in the object, and only imputed to it by us.
For instance—
For example—
This is very beautiful, and yet very untrue. The crocus is not a spendthrift, but a hardy plant; its yellow is not gold, but saffron. How is it that we enjoy so much the having it put into our heads that it is anything else than a plain crocus?
This is really beautiful, but it's not accurate. The crocus isn't extravagant; it's a tough plant. Its yellow isn't gold; it's saffron. Why do we love to convince ourselves that it's anything more than just a regular crocus?
It is an important question. For, throughout our past reasonings about art, we have always found that nothing could be good or useful, or ultimately pleasurable, which was untrue. But here is something pleasurable in written poetry which is nevertheless untrue. And what is more, if we think over our favourite poetry, we shall find it full of this kind of fallacy, and that we like it all the more for being so.
It’s an important question. Throughout our discussions about art, we've always discovered that nothing can be good, useful, or ultimately enjoyable if it's untrue. But there’s something pleasurable in written poetry that is still untrue. Moreover, if we reflect on our favorite poems, we’ll find them full of this kind of falsehood, and we actually appreciate them even more because of it.
It will appear also, on consideration of the matter, that this fallacy is of two principal kinds. Either, as in this case of the crocus, it is the fallacy of wilful fancy, which involves no real expectation that it will be believed; or else it is a fallacy caused by an excited state of the feelings, making us, for the time, more or less irrational. Of the cheating of the fancy we shall have to speak presently; but, in this chapter, I want to examine the nature of the other error, that which the mind admits when affected strongly by emotion. Thus, for instance, in Alton Locke,—
It will also become clear, upon reflection, that this fallacy has two main types. Either, like in the case of the crocus, it’s a fallacy of deliberate imagination, which doesn't really expect to be taken seriously; or it’s a fallacy brought on by heightened emotions, making us more or less irrational temporarily. We will discuss the deception of imagination shortly; but in this chapter, I want to explore the nature of the other mistake, the one that the mind accepts when strongly influenced by emotion. For example, in Alton Locke,—
They rowed her in across the rolling foam—
They rowed her in through the choppy waves—
The cruel, crawling foam.[54]
The harsh, creeping foam.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
The foam is not cruel, neither does it crawl. The state of mind which attributes to it these characters of a living creature is one in which the reason is unhinged by grief. All violent feelings have the same effect. They produce in us a falseness in all our impressions of external things, which I would generally characterize as the "pathetic fallacy."
The foam isn’t cruel, nor does it creep. The mindset that assigns these traits of a living thing to it is one where reason is shaken by sorrow. All intense emotions have the same impact. They create a distortion in how we perceive everything around us, which I would typically call the "pathetic fallacy."
Now we are in the habit of considering this fallacy as eminently a character of poetical description, and the temper of mind in which we allow it, as one eminently poetical, because passionate. But I believe, if we look well into the matter, that we shall find the greatest poets do not often admit this kind of falseness,—that it is only the second order of poets who much delight in it.[55]
Now we are in the habit of considering this fallacy as eminently a character of poetical description, and the temper of mind in which we allow it, as one eminently poetical, because passionate. But I believe, if we look well into the matter, that we shall find the greatest poets do not often admit this kind of falseness,—that it is only the second order of poets who much delight in it.[55]
Thus, when Dante describes the spirits falling from the bank of Acheron "as dead leaves flutter from a bough,"[56] he gives the most perfect image possible of their utter lightness, feebleness, passiveness, and scattering agony of despair, without, however, for an instant losing his own clear perception that these are souls, and those are leaves; he makes no confusion of one with the other. But when Coleridge speaks of
Thus, when Dante describes the spirits falling from the bank of Acheron "as dead leaves flutter from a bough,"[56] he gives the most perfect image possible of their utter lightness, feebleness, passiveness, and scattering agony of despair, without, however, for an instant losing his own clear perception that these are souls, and those are leaves; he makes no confusion of one with the other. But when Coleridge speaks of
he has a morbid, that is to say, a so far false, idea about the leaf; he fancies a life in it, and will, which there are not; confuses its powerlessness with choice, its fading death with merriment, and the wind that shakes it with music. Here, however, there is some beauty, even in the morbid passage; but take an instance in Homer and Pope. Without the knowledge of Ulysses, Elpenor, his youngest follower, has fallen from an upper chamber in the Circean palace, and has been left dead, unmissed by his leader or companions, in the haste of their departure. They cross the sea to the Cimmerian land; and Ulysses summons the shades from Tartarus. The first which appears is that of the lost Elpenor. Ulysses, amazed, and in exactly the spirit of bitter and terrified lightness which is seen in Hamlet,[58] addresses the spirit with the simple, startled words:—
he has a morbid, that is to say, a so far false, idea about the leaf; he fancies a life in it, and will, which there are not; confuses its powerlessness with choice, its fading death with merriment, and the wind that shakes it with music. Here, however, there is some beauty, even in the morbid passage; but take an instance in Homer and Pope. Without the knowledge of Ulysses, Elpenor, his youngest follower, has fallen from an upper chamber in the Circean palace, and has been left dead, unmissed by his leader or companions, in the haste of their departure. They cross the sea to the Cimmerian land; and Ulysses summons the shades from Tartarus. The first which appears is that of the lost Elpenor. Ulysses, amazed, and in exactly the spirit of bitter and terrified lightness which is seen in Hamlet,[58] addresses the spirit with the simple, startled words:—
"Elpenor! How camest thou under the shadowy darkness? Hast thou come faster on foot than I in my black ship?"[59]
"Elpenor! How camest thou under the shadowy darkness? Hast thou come faster on foot than I in my black ship?"[59]
Which Pope renders thus:—
Which Pope says:—
O, say, what angry power Elpenor led
O, say, what furious force Elpenor guided
To glide in shades, and wander with the dead?
To drift in the shadows and roam with the deceased?
How could thy soul, by realms and seas disjoined,
How could your soul, separated by lands and oceans,
Outfly the nimble sail, and leave the lagging wind?
Outrace the quick sail, and leave the slow wind behind?
I sincerely hope the reader finds no pleasure here, either in the nimbleness of the sail, or the laziness of the wind! And yet how is it that these conceits are so painful now, when they have been pleasant to us in the other instances?
I truly hope the reader takes no joy in either the swift movement of the sail or the sluggishness of the wind! And yet, how is it that these thoughts are so distressing now when they used to bring us pleasure in other situations?
For a very simple reason. They are not a pathetic fallacy at all, for they are put into the mouth of the wrong passion—a passion which never could possibly have spoken them—agonized curiosity. Ulysses wants to know the facts of the matter; and the very last thing his mind could do at the moment would be to pause, or suggest in anywise what was not a fact. The delay in the first three lines, and conceit in the last, jar upon us instantly like the most frightful discord in music. No poet of true imaginative power could possibly have written the passage.[60]
For a very simple reason. They are not a pathetic fallacy at all, for they are put into the mouth of the wrong passion—a passion which never could possibly have spoken them—agonized curiosity. Ulysses wants to know the facts of the matter; and the very last thing his mind could do at the moment would be to pause, or suggest in anywise what was not a fact. The delay in the first three lines, and conceit in the last, jar upon us instantly like the most frightful discord in music. No poet of true imaginative power could possibly have written the passage.[60]
Therefore we see that the spirit of truth must guide us in some sort, even in our enjoyment of fallacy. Coleridge's fallacy has no discord in it, but Pope's has set our teeth on edge. Without farther questioning, I will endeavour to state the main bearings of this matter.
Therefore, we can see that the spirit of truth must guide us in some way, even when we enjoy falsehoods. Coleridge's falsehood has no jarring elements, but Pope's makes us uncomfortable. Without further questioning, I will try to outline the main points of this issue.
The temperament which admits the pathetic fallacy, is, as I said above, that of a mind and body in some sort too weak to deal fully with what is before them or upon them; borne away, or over-clouded, or over-dazzled by emotion; and it is a more or less noble state, according to the force of the emotion which has induced it. For it is no credit to a man that he is not morbid or inaccurate in his perceptions, when he has no strength of feeling to warp them; and it is in general a sign of higher capacity and stand in the ranks of being, that the emotions should be strong enough to vanquish, partly, the intellect, and make it believe what they choose. But it is still a grander condition when the intellect also rises, till it is strong enough to assert its rule against, or together with, the utmost efforts of the passions; and the whole man stands in an iron glow, white hot, perhaps, but still strong, and in no wise evaporating; even if he melts, losing none of his weight.
The mindset that accepts the pathetic fallacy is, as I said before, one of a mind and body somewhat too weak to fully engage with what’s in front of them or what’s affecting them; they are swept away, clouded, or dazzled by emotion. This is a more or less noble state, depending on the intensity of the emotion that causes it. It doesn’t reflect well on a person if they are not morbid or inaccurate in their perceptions when they lack the strength of feeling to distort them. Generally, it indicates a higher capacity and a greater place in the hierarchy of existence when emotions are strong enough to partially overpower the intellect, leading it to believe what they want. However, it’s an even greater condition when the intellect also elevates itself, becoming strong enough to assert its authority against or alongside the strongest passions; and the whole person stands in a fierce glow, possibly white hot, yet still strong and not dissipating; even if they melt, they don’t lose any of their weight.
So, then, we have the three ranks: the man who perceives rightly, because he does not feel, and to whom the primrose is very accurately the primrose,[61] because he does not love it. Then, secondly, the man who perceives wrongly, because he feels, and to whom the primrose is anything else than a primrose: a star, or a sun, or a fairy's shield, or a forsaken maiden. And then, lastly, there is the man who perceives rightly in spite of his feelings, and to whom the primrose is for ever nothing else than itself—a little flower apprehended in the very plain and leafy fact of it, whatever and how many soever the associations and passions may be that crowd around it. And, in general, these three classes may be rated in comparative order, as the men who are not poets at all, and the poets of the second order, and the poets of the first; only however great a man may be, there are always some subjects which ought to throw him off his balance; some, by which his poor human capacity of thought should be conquered, and brought into the inaccurate and vague state of perception, so that the language of the highest inspiration becomes broken, obscure, and wild in metaphor, resembling that of the weaker man, overborne by weaker things.
So, then, we have the three ranks: the man who perceives rightly, because he does not feel, and to whom the primrose is very accurately the primrose,[61] because he does not love it. Then, secondly, the man who perceives wrongly, because he feels, and to whom the primrose is anything else than a primrose: a star, or a sun, or a fairy's shield, or a forsaken maiden. And then, lastly, there is the man who perceives rightly in spite of his feelings, and to whom the primrose is for ever nothing else than itself—a little flower apprehended in the very plain and leafy fact of it, whatever and how many soever the associations and passions may be that crowd around it. And, in general, these three classes may be rated in comparative order, as the men who are not poets at all, and the poets of the second order, and the poets of the first; only however great a man may be, there are always some subjects which ought to throw him off his balance; some, by which his poor human capacity of thought should be conquered, and brought into the inaccurate and vague state of perception, so that the language of the highest inspiration becomes broken, obscure, and wild in metaphor, resembling that of the weaker man, overborne by weaker things.
And thus, in full, there are four classes: the men who feel nothing, and therefore see truly; the men who feel strongly, think weakly, and see untruly (second order of poets); the men who feel strongly, think strongly, and see truly (first order of poets); and the men who, strong as human creatures can be, are yet submitted to influences stronger than they, and see in a sort untruly, because what they see is inconceivably above them. This last is the usual condition of prophetic inspiration.
And so, in summary, there are four groups: the people who feel nothing, and therefore see clearly; the people who feel strongly, think weakly, and see inaccurately (the second tier of poets); the people who feel strongly, think strongly, and see clearly (the first tier of poets); and the people who, despite being as strong as humans can be, are still influenced by forces greater than themselves and see somewhat inaccurately because what they observe is far beyond their comprehension. This last group represents the typical state of prophetic inspiration.
I separate these classes, in order that their character may be clearly understood; but of course they are united each to the other by imperceptible transitions, and the same mind, according to the influences to which it is subjected, passes at different times into the various states. Still, the difference between the great and less man is, on the whole, chiefly in this point of alterability. That is to say, the one knows too much, and perceives and feels too much of the past and future, and of all things beside and around that which immediately affects him, to be in any wise shaken by it. His mind is made up; his thoughts have an accustomed current; his ways are stedfast; it is not this or that new sight which will at once unbalance him. He is tender to impression at the surface, like a rock with deep moss upon it; but there is too much mass of him to be moved. The smaller man, with the same degree of sensibility, is at once carried off his feet; he wants to do something he did not want to do before; he views all the universe in a new light through his tears; he is gay or enthusiastic, melancholy or passionate, as things come and go to him. Therefore the high creative poet might even be thought, to a great extent, impassive (as shallow people think Dante stern), receiving indeed all feelings to the full, but having a great centre of reflection and knowledge in which he stands serene, and watches the feeling, as it were, from far off.
I separate these classes so that their nature can be clearly understood; however, they are all connected to each other through subtle transitions, and the same person, depending on the influences at play, can shift between these various states at different times. Still, the main difference between a great person and a lesser one lies mainly in their level of alterability. This means that one knows too much, and perceives and feels too much about the past and future, and everything around him that isn’t just affecting him directly, to be easily shaken by it. His mind is set; his thoughts follow a familiar path; his behaviors are consistent; it takes more than just a new sight to disturb his balance. He is sensitive on the surface, like a rock covered in thick moss; but there’s too much substance to him to be easily moved. The lesser person, with the same level of sensitivity, can be easily swept off his feet; he suddenly wants to do things he didn’t want to do before; he sees the entire universe in a new light through his tears; he feels cheerful or passionate, depressed or intense, as circumstances change around him. Thus, the highly creative poet might even be seen as somewhat impassive (as shallow people view Dante as stern), fully experiencing feelings but having a strong core of reflection and knowledge from which he remains calm and observes the feelings from a distance.
Dante, in his most intense moods, has entire command of himself, and can look around calmly, at all moments, for the image or the word that will best tell what he sees to the upper or lower world. But Keats and Tennyson, and the poets of the second order, are generally themselves subdued by the feelings under which they write, or, at least, write as choosing to be so; and therefore admit certain expressions and modes of thought which are in some sort diseased or false.
Dante, in his most intense moods, has complete control over himself and can calmly look around at all times for the image or word that will best convey what he sees to the upper or lower world. However, Keats and Tennyson, along with poets of the second tier, often find themselves overwhelmed by the emotions they’re writing under, or at least write in a way that chooses to reflect that. As a result, they incorporate certain expressions and thought patterns that are somewhat misguided or artificial.
Now so long as we see that the feeling is true, we pardon, or are even pleased by, the confessed fallacy of sight which it induces: we are pleased, for instance, with those lines of Kingsley's above quoted, not because they fallaciously describe foam, but because they faithfully describe sorrow. But the moment the mind of the speaker becomes cold, that moment every such expression becomes untrue, as being for ever untrue in the external facts. And there is no greater baseness in literature than the habit of using these metaphorical expressions in cool blood. An inspired writer, in full impetuosity of passion, may speak wisely and truly of "raging waves of the sea foaming out their own shame";[62] but it is only the basest writer who cannot speak of the sea without talking of "raging waves," "remorseless floods," "ravenous billows," etc.; and it is one of the signs of the highest power in a writer to check all such habits of thought, and to keep his eyes fixed firmly on the pure fact, out of which if any feeling conies to him or his reader, he knows it must be a true one.
Now so long as we see that the feeling is true, we pardon, or are even pleased by, the confessed fallacy of sight which it induces: we are pleased, for instance, with those lines of Kingsley's above quoted, not because they fallaciously describe foam, but because they faithfully describe sorrow. But the moment the mind of the speaker becomes cold, that moment every such expression becomes untrue, as being for ever untrue in the external facts. And there is no greater baseness in literature than the habit of using these metaphorical expressions in cool blood. An inspired writer, in full impetuosity of passion, may speak wisely and truly of "raging waves of the sea foaming out their own shame";[62] but it is only the basest writer who cannot speak of the sea without talking of "raging waves," "remorseless floods," "ravenous billows," etc.; and it is one of the signs of the highest power in a writer to check all such habits of thought, and to keep his eyes fixed firmly on the pure fact, out of which if any feeling conies to him or his reader, he knows it must be a true one.
To keep to the waves, I forget who it is who represents a man in despair desiring that his body may be cast into the sea,
To stay on topic, I can’t remember who depicts a man in despair wishing for his body to be thrown into the sea,
Whose changing mound, and foam that passed away,
Whose shifting mound, and foam that faded away,
Might mock the eye that questioned where I lay.
Might tease the eye that wondered where I was lying.
Observe, there is not a single false, or even overcharged, expression. "Mound" of the sea wave is perfectly simple and true; "changing" is as familiar as may be; "foam that passed away," strictly literal; and the whole line descriptive of the reality with a degree of accuracy which I know not any other verse, in the range of poetry, that altogether equals. For most people have not a distinct idea of the clumsiness and massiveness of a large wave. The word "wave" is used too generally of ripples and breakers, and bendings in light drapery or grass: it does not by itself convey a perfect image. But the word "mound" is heavy, large, dark, definite; there is no mistaking the kind of wave meant, nor missing the sight of it. Then the term "changing" has a peculiar force also. Most people think of waves as rising and falling. But if they look at the sea carefully, they will perceive that the waves do not rise and fall. They change. Change both place and form, but they do not fall; one wave goes on, and on, and still on; now lower, now higher, now tossing its mane like a horse, now building itself together like a wall, now shaking, now steady, but still the same wave, till at last it seems struck by something, and changes, one knows not how,—becomes another wave.
Notice that there isn’t a single false or even exaggerated expression. "Mound" of the sea wave is straightforward and accurate; "changing" is as familiar as it gets; "foam that passed away" is literally true; and the entire line describes reality with a degree of precision that I don’t know any other verse in poetry can match. Most people don’t have a clear idea of the awkwardness and bulkiness of a large wave. The word "wave" is used too broadly to describe ripples and breakers, as well as bends in light fabric or grass: it doesn’t, on its own, create a perfect image. But the word "mound" feels heavy, large, dark, and clear; there’s no confusion about what kind of wave is being referred to, and the visual is unmistakable. The term "changing" also carries a unique weight. Most people think of waves as simply rising and falling. However, if they observe the sea closely, they’ll realize that the waves don’t just rise and fall. They change. They shift in both position and shape, but they don’t fall; one wave continues on and on, sometimes lower, sometimes higher, sometimes tossing its foam like a horse’s mane, sometimes assembling itself like a wall, sometimes shaking, sometimes steady, but always the same wave, until eventually, it seems to be hit by something and transforms, one can’t explain how — becoming another wave.
The close of the line insists on this image, and paints it still more perfectly,—"foam that passed away." Not merely melting, disappearing, but passing on, out of sight, on the career of the wave. Then, having put the absolute ocean fact as far as he may before our eyes, the poet leaves us to feel about it as we may, and to trace for ourselves the opposite fact,—the image of the green mounds that do not change, and the white and written stones that do not pass away; and thence to follow out also the associated images of the calm life with the quiet grave, and the despairing life with the fading foam—
The end of the line emphasizes this image and makes it even clearer—“foam that passed away.” Not just melting and disappearing,
Let no man move his bones.
Let no one move his bones.
As for Samaria, her king is cut off like the foam upon the water.[63]
As for Samaria, her king is cut off like the foam upon the water.[63]
But nothing of this is actually told or pointed out, and the expressions, as they stand, are perfectly severe and accurate, utterly uninfluenced by the firmly governed emotion of the writer. Even the word "mock" is hardly an exception, as it may stand merely for "deceive" or "defeat," without implying any impersonation of the waves.
But none of this is actually explained or highlighted, and the expressions, as they are, are completely straightforward and precise, totally unaffected by the strongly controlled emotions of the writer. Even the word "mock" is barely an exception, as it can simply mean "deceive" or "defeat," without suggesting any imitation of the waves.
It may be well, perhaps, to give one or two more instances to show the peculiar dignity possessed by all passages, which thus limit their expression to the pure fact, and leave the hearer to gather what he can from it. Here is a notable one from the Iliad. Helen, looking from the Scæan gate of Troy over the Grecian host, and telling Priam the names of its captains, says at last:—
It might be a good idea to provide one or two more examples to highlight the unique dignity of passages that focus solely on the pure facts, allowing the listener to interpret them as they wish. Here’s a striking example from the Iliad. Helen, looking out from the Scæan gate of Troy at the Greek army and naming its leaders, eventually says:—
"I see all the other dark-eyed Greeks; but two I cannot see,—Castor and Pollux,—whom one mother bore with me. Have they not followed from fair Lacedæmon, or have they indeed come in their sea-wandering ships, but now will not enter into the battle of men, fearing the shame and the scorn that is in Me?"
"I see all the other dark-eyed Greeks, but I can’t see two—Castor and Pollux—who were born from the same mother as me. Did they not come from beautiful Lacedæmon, or have they actually arrived in their sea-faring ships, but now refuse to join the battle, afraid of the shame and scorn associated with me?"
Then Homer:—
Then Homer:—
"So she spoke. But them, already, the life-giving earth possessed, there in Lacedæmon, in the dear fatherland."[64]
"So she spoke. But them, already, the life-giving earth possessed, there in Lacedæmon, in the dear fatherland."[64]
Note, here, the high poetical truth carried to the extreme. The poet has to speak of the earth in sadness, but he will not let that sadness affect or change his thoughts of it. No; though Castor and Pollux be dead, yet the earth is our mother still, fruitful, life-giving. These are the facts of the thing. I see nothing else than these. Make what you will of them.
Note, here, the profound poetic truth taken to the limit. The poet has to talk about the earth with sadness, but he won’t let that sadness influence or alter his thoughts about it. No; even though Castor and Pollux are gone, the earth is still our mother, nurturing and full of life. These are the realities of the situation. I see nothing beyond these. Do with them what you will.
Take another very notable instance from Casimir de la Vigne's terrible ballad, "La Toilette de Constance." I must quote a few lines out of it here and there, to enable the reader who has not the book by him, to understand its close.
Take another well-known example from Casimir de la Vigne's striking ballad, "La Toilette de Constance." I should quote a few lines from it here and there, to help the reader who doesn't have the book handy understand its conclusion.
"Vite, Anna! vite; au miroir!
"Quick, Anna! Quick; to the mirror!"
Plus vite, Anna. L'heure s'avance,
Hurry up, Anna. Time's passing.
Et je vais au bal ce soir
Et je vais au bal ce soir
Chez l'ambassadeur de France.
At the French ambassador's.
"Y pensez-vous? ils sont fanés, ces noeuds;
"Do you think so? Those bows are wilted;"
Ils sont d'hier; mon Dieu, comme tout passe!
Ils sont d'hier; mon Dieu, comme tout passe!
Que du réseau qui retient mes cheveux
Que du réseau qui retient mes cheveux
Les glands d'azur retombent avec grâce.
The azure acorns fall gracefully.
Plus haut! Plus bas! Vous ne comprenez rien!
Plus haut! Plus bas! You don't understand anything!
Que sur mon front ce saphir étincelle:
Que sur mon front ce saphir étincelle:
Vous me piquez, maladroite. Ah, c'est bien,
Vous me piquez, maladroite. Ah, c'est bien,
Bien,—chère Anna! Je t'aime, je suis belle."
Bien,—chère Anna! I love you, I am beautiful.
"Celui qu'en vain je voudrais oublier ...
"Celui qu'en vain je voudrais oublier ..."
(Anna, ma robe) il y sera, j'espère.
(Anna, my dress) I hope he will be there.
(Ah, fi! profane, est-ce là mon collier?
(Ah, no! Seriously, is that my necklace?)
Quoi! ces grains d'or bénits par le Saint-Père!)
Quoi! these golden grains blessed by the Holy Father!)
II y sera; Dieu, s'il pressait ma main,
II y sera; Dieu, s'il pressait ma main,
En y pensant à peine je respire:
En y pensant à peine je respire:
Frère Anselmo doit m'entendre demain,
Brother Anselmo needs to hear me tomorrow,
Comment ferai-je, Anna, pour tout lui dire?...
Comment ferai-je, Anna, pour tout lui dire?...
"Vite! un coup d'oeil au miroir,
"Quick! Take a look in the mirror,
Le dernier.—J'ai l'assurance
The last one.—I'm confident
Qu'on va m'adorer ce soir
They're going to adore me tonight.
Chez l'ambassadeur de France."
At the French ambassador's.
Pres du foyer, Constance s'admirait.
By the fireplace, Constance admired herself.
Dieu! sur sa robe il vole une étincelle!
Dieu! There's a spark flying off her dress!
Au feu! Courez! Quand l'espoir l'enivrait,
Au feu! Courez! When hope intoxicated him,
Tout perdre ainsi! Quoi! Mourir,—et si belle!
Tout perdre ainsi! Quoi! Mourir,—et si belle!
L'horrible feu ronge avec volupté
The horrible fire devours eagerly.
Ses bras, son sein, et l'entoure, et s'élève,
Ses bras, son sein, et l'entoure, et s'élève,
Et sans pitié dévore sa beauté,
Et sans pitié dévore sa beauté,
Ses dix-huit ans, hélas, et son doux rêve!
Ses dix-huit ans, hélas, et son doux rêve!
Adieu, bal, plaisir, amour!
Goodbye, ball, pleasure, love!
On disait, Pauvre Constance!
They said, Poor Constance!
Et l'on dansa, jusqu'au jour,
And we danced, until dawn,
Chez l'ambassadeur de France.[65]
At the French ambassador's. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Yes, that is the fact of it. Right or wrong, the poet does not say. What you may think about it, he does not know. He has nothing to do with that. There lie the ashes of the dead girl in her chamber. There they danced, till the morning, at the Ambassador's of France. Make what you will of it.
Yes, that’s the reality of it. Whether it’s right or wrong, the poet doesn’t say. He doesn’t know what you might think about it. That’s not his concern. Here lie the ashes of the dead girl in her room. There, they danced until morning, at the Ambassador’s of France. Do with it what you will.
If the reader will look through the ballad, of which I have quoted only about the third part, he will find that there is not, from beginning to end of it, a single poetical (so called) expression, except in one stanza. The girl speaks as simple prose as may be; there is not a word she would not have actually used as she was dressing. The poet stands by, impassive as a statue, recording her words just as they come. At last the doom seizes her, and in the very presence of death, for an instant, his own emotions conquer him. He records no longer the facts only, but the facts as they seem to him. The fire gnaws with voluptuousness—without pity. It is soon past. The fate is fixed for ever; and he retires into his pale and crystalline atmosphere of truth. He closes all with the calm veracity,
If the reader looks through the ballad, of which I’ve quoted only about a third, they'll find that from beginning to end, there isn’t a single poetic expression, except in one stanza. The girl speaks as plainly as possible; there isn’t a word she wouldn’t have actually used while getting dressed. The poet stands by, as impassive as a statue, recording her words just as they come. Finally, doom catches up with her, and in the presence of death, for a moment, his own emotions take over. He no longer records just the facts, but how the facts appear to him. The fire gnaws with pleasure—without mercy. It’s over quickly. The fate is sealed forever; and he retreats into his pale and clear atmosphere of truth. He concludes everything with calm honesty,
They said, "Poor Constance!"
They said, "Poor Constance!"
Now in this there is the exact type of the consummate poetical temperament. For, be it clearly and constantly remembered, that the greatness of a poet depends upon the two faculties, acuteness of feeling, and command of it. A poet is great, first in proportion to the strength of his passion, and then, that strength being granted, in proportion to his government of it; there being, however, always a point beyond which it would be inhuman and monstrous if he pushed this government, and, therefore, a point at which all feverish and wild fancy becomes just and true. Thus the destruction of the kingdom of Assyria cannot be contemplated firmly by a prophet of Israel. The fact is too great, too wonderful. It overthrows him, dashes him into a confused element of dreams. All the world is, to his stunned thought, full of strange voices. "Yea, the fir-trees rejoice at thee, and the cedars of Lebanon, saying. 'Since thou art gone down to the grave, no feller is come up against us.'"[66] So, still more, the thought of the presence of Deity cannot be borne without this great astonishment. "The mountains and the hills shall break forth before you into singing, and all the trees of the field shall clap their hands."[67]
Now in this there is the exact type of the consummate poetical temperament. For, be it clearly and constantly remembered, that the greatness of a poet depends upon the two faculties, acuteness of feeling, and command of it. A poet is great, first in proportion to the strength of his passion, and then, that strength being granted, in proportion to his government of it; there being, however, always a point beyond which it would be inhuman and monstrous if he pushed this government, and, therefore, a point at which all feverish and wild fancy becomes just and true. Thus the destruction of the kingdom of Assyria cannot be contemplated firmly by a prophet of Israel. The fact is too great, too wonderful. It overthrows him, dashes him into a confused element of dreams. All the world is, to his stunned thought, full of strange voices. "Yea, the fir-trees rejoice at thee, and the cedars of Lebanon, saying. 'Since thou art gone down to the grave, no feller is come up against us.'"[66] So, still more, the thought of the presence of Deity cannot be borne without this great astonishment. "The mountains and the hills shall break forth before you into singing, and all the trees of the field shall clap their hands."[67]
But by how much this feeling is noble when it is justified by the strength of its cause, by so much it is ignoble when there is not cause enough for it; and beyond all other ignobleness is the mere affectation of it, in hardness of heart. Simply bad writing may almost always, as above noticed, be known by its adoption of these fanciful metaphorical expressions as a sort of current coin; yet there is even a worse, at least a more harmful condition of writing than this, in which such expressions are not ignorantly and feelinglessly caught up, but, by some master, skilful in handling, yet insincere, deliberately wrought out with chill and studied fancy; as if we should try to make an old lava-stream look red-hot again, by covering it with dead leaves, or white-hot, with hoar-frost.
But this feeling is so much more admirable when it’s supported by a strong reason, and so much less admirable when there’s not enough reason behind it; and the worst of all is when it’s simply pretended, stemming from a cold heart. Bad writing can often be identified, as mentioned earlier, by its use of fanciful metaphorical expressions as if they were currency; yet there’s an even worse, or at least more damaging, form of writing, where these expressions are not just thoughtlessly and emotionlessly used, but are intentionally crafted by a skilled but insincere hand with a cold and calculated creativity; as if we were trying to make an old lava flow look red-hot again by covering it with dead leaves, or white-hot with frost.
When Young is lost in veneration, as he dwells on the character of a truly good and holy man, he permits himself for a moment to be overborne by the feeling so far as to exclaim—
When Young is immersed in admiration, reflecting on the qualities of a genuinely good and holy man, he allows himself for a moment to be overwhelmed by the emotion to the point of exclaiming—
Where shall I find him? angels, tell me where.
Where can I find him? Angels, tell me where.
You know him; he is near you; point him out.
You know him; he's close by; show him to me.
Shall I see glories beaming from his brow,
Shall I see glories shining from his forehead,
This emotion has a worthy cause, and is thus true and right. But now hear the cold-hearted Pope say to a shepherd girl—
This feeling has a good reason behind it, making it genuine and just. But now listen to the unfeeling Pope speaking to a shepherd girl—
Where'er you walk, cool gales shall fan the glade;
Wherever you walk, cool breezes will refresh the clearing;
Trees, where you sit, shall crowd into a shade;
Trees, where you sit, will gather to provide shade;
Your praise the birds shall chant in every grove,
Your praise will be sung by the birds in every grove,
And winds shall waft it to the powers above.
And the winds will carry it to the powers above.
But would you sing, and rival Orpheus' strain,
But would you sing and compete with Orpheus' melody,
The wondering forests soon should dance again;
The curious forests will soon dance again;
The moving mountains hear the powerful call,
The moving mountains hear the strong call,
This is not, nor could it for a moment be mistaken for, the language of passion. It is simple falsehood, uttered by hypocrisy; definite absurdity, rooted in affectation, and coldly asserted in the teeth of nature and fact. Passion will indeed go far in deceiving itself; but it must be a strong passion, not the simple wish of a lover to tempt his mistress to sing. Compare a very closely parallel passage in Wordsworth, in which the lover has lost his mistress:—
This isn't, nor could it ever be mistaken for, passionate language. It's just plain falsehood, spoken by someone being hypocritical; it's sheer absurdity, based on pretension, and stated coldly despite nature and reality. Passion can certainly lead to self-deception, but it has to be a strong passion—not just the mere desire of a lover to entice his partner to sing. Compare this to a very similar passage in Wordsworth, where the lover has lost his partner:—
Three years had Barbara in her grave been laid,
Three years had Barbara been laid in her grave,
When thus his moan he made:—
When he filed his complaint:—
"Oh, move, thou cottage, from behind yon oak,
"Oh, move, you cottage, from behind that oak,
Or let the ancient tree uprooted lie,
Or let the ancient tree lie uprooted,
That in some other way yon smoke
That in some other way you smoke
May mount into the sky.
May ascend into the sky.
If still behind yon pine-tree's ragged bough,
If still hidden behind that pine tree's rough branch,
Headlong, the waterfall must come,
The waterfall must come rushing,
Oh, let it, then, be dumb—
Oh, let it be quiet then—
Here is a cottage to be moved, if not a mountain, and a water-fall to be silent, if it is not to hang listening: but with what different relation to the mind that contemplates them! Here, in the extremity of its agony, the soul cries out wildly for relief, which at the same moment it partly knows to be impossible, but partly believes possible, in a vague impression that a miracle might be wrought to give relief even to a less sore distress,—that nature is kind, and God is kind, and that grief is strong; it knows not well what is possible to such grief. To silence a stream, to move a cottage wall,—one might think it could do as much as that!
Here’s a cottage that could be moved, if not a whole mountain, and a waterfall that could go quiet, if it doesn’t stay still to listen: but the way they relate to the mind that considers them is so different! Here, in the depths of its suffering, the soul cries out desperately for relief, knowing all at once that it’s partly impossible, but also believing it’s possible, in a vague feeling that a miracle might happen to ease even a less intense pain—that nature is kind, and God is kind, and that grief is powerful; it doesn’t really understand what is possible for such grief. To silence a stream, to move a cottage wall—one might think it could achieve as much as that!
I believe these instances are enough to illustrate the main point I insist upon respecting the pathetic fallacy,—that so far as it is a fallacy, it is always the sign of a morbid state of mind, and comparatively of a weak one. Even in the most inspired prophet it is a sign of the incapacity of his human sight or thought to bear what has been revealed to it. In ordinary poetry, if it is found in the thoughts of the poet himself, it is at once a sign of his belonging to the inferior school; if in the thoughts of the characters imagined by him, it is right or wrong according to the genuineness of the emotion from which it springs; always, however, implying necessarily some degree of weakness in the character.
I think these examples are enough to make my main point about the pathetic fallacy clear—namely, that when it is a fallacy, it always indicates a troubled state of mind and a relatively weak one. Even in the most inspired prophet, it shows their human ability to understand or comprehend what has been revealed is limited. In regular poetry, if it's present in the poet's own thoughts, it immediately indicates that he belongs to a lesser style; if it’s in the thoughts of the characters he creates, it can be right or wrong depending on the authenticity of the emotion it comes from; however, it always suggests some level of weakness in the character.
Take two most exquisite instances from master hands. The Jessy of Shenstone, and the Ellen of Wordsworth, have both been betrayed and deserted. Jessy, in the course of her most touching complaint says:—
Take two of the most exquisite examples from the masters. The Jessy of Shenstone and the Ellen of Wordsworth have both been betrayed and abandoned. Jessy, in the midst of her most heartfelt complaint, says:—
If through the garden's flowery tribes I stray,
If I wander through the garden's blooming flowers,
Where bloom the jasmines that could once allure,
Where the jasmines bloom that used to entice,
"Hope not to find delight in us," they say,
"Don't expect to find joy in us," they say,
Compare with this some of the words of Ellen:—
Compare this with some of Ellen's words:—
"Ah, why," said Ellen, sighing to herself,
"Ah, why," said Ellen, sighing to herself,
"Why do not words, and kiss, and solemn pledge,
"Why don’t words, kisses, and serious promises,
And nature, that is kind in woman's breast,
And nature, that is gentle in a woman's heart,
And reason, that in man is wise and good,
And reason, which is wise and good in humans,
And fear of Him who is a righteous Judge,—
And fear of Him who is a fair Judge,—
Why do not these prevail for human life,
Why don't these work for human life,
To keep two hearts together, that began
To keep two hearts together that started
Their springtime with one love, and that have need
Their springtime with one love, and that have need
Of mutual pity and forgiveness sweet
Of shared compassion and gentle forgiveness
To grant, or be received; while that poor bird—
To give or to be accepted; while that poor bird—
O, come and hear him! Thou who hast to me
O, come and hear him! You who have to me
Been faithless, hear him;—though a lowly creature,
Been faithless, hear him;—even though he's a humble being,
One of God's simple children that yet know not
One of God's simple children who still do not know
The Universal Parent, how he sings!
The Universal Parent, how he sings!
As if he wished the firmament of heaven
As if he desired the sky above
Should listen, and give back to him the voice
Should listen, and give him back his voice
Of his triumphant constancy and love;
Of his unwavering strength and love;
The proclamation that he makes, how far
The proclamation he makes, how far
The perfection of both these passages, as far as regards truth and tenderness of imagination in the two poets, is quite insuperable. But of the two characters imagined, Jessy is weaker than Ellen, exactly in so far as something appears to her to be in nature which is not. The flowers do not really reproach her. God meant them to comfort her, not to taunt her; they would do so if she saw them rightly.
The perfection of both these passages, in terms of truth and the tenderness of imagination in the two poets, is completely unmatched. However, among the two characters created, Jessy is weaker than Ellen, precisely because Jessy sees something in nature that isn't actually there. The flowers don't truly blame her. God intended them to comfort her, not to mock her; they would do so if she saw them the right way.
Ellen, on the other hand, is quite above the slightest erring emotion. There is not the barest film of fallacy in all her thoughts. She reasons as calmly as if she did not feel. And, although the singing of the bird suggests to her the idea of its desiring to be heard in heaven, she does not for an instant admit any veracity in the thought. "As if," she says,—"I know he means nothing of the kind; but it does verily seem as if." The reader will find, by examining the rest of the poem, that Ellen's character is throughout consistent in this clear though passionate strength.[73]
Ellen, on the other hand, is quite above the slightest erring emotion. There is not the barest film of fallacy in all her thoughts. She reasons as calmly as if she did not feel. And, although the singing of the bird suggests to her the idea of its desiring to be heard in heaven, she does not for an instant admit any veracity in the thought. "As if," she says,—"I know he means nothing of the kind; but it does verily seem as if." The reader will find, by examining the rest of the poem, that Ellen's character is throughout consistent in this clear though passionate strength.[73]
It then being, I hope, now made clear to the reader in all respects that the pathetic fallacy is powerful only so far as it is pathetic, feeble so far as it is fallacious, and, therefore, that the dominion of Truth is entire, over this, as over every other natural and just state of the human mind, we may go on to the subject for the dealing with which this prefatory inquiry became necessary; and why necessary, we shall see forthwith.
It should now be clear to the reader in every way that the pathetic fallacy is strong only to the extent that it is emotional, weak when it is misleading, and that the rule of Truth completely governs this, as it does every other natural and rightful state of the human mind. With that established, we can move on to the topic that made this introductory discussion necessary, and we will soon understand why it was necessary.
OF CLASSICAL LANDSCAPE
VOLUME III, CHAPTER 13
My reason for asking the reader to give so much of his time to the examination of the pathetic fallacy was, that, whether in literature or in art, he will find it eminently characteristic of the modern mind; and in the landscape, whether of literature or art, he will also find the modern painter endeavouring to express something which he, as a living creature imagines in the lifeless object, while the classical and mediæval painters were content with expressing the unimaginary and actual qualities of the object itself. It will be observed that, according to the principle stated long ago, I use the words painter and poet quite indifferently, including in our inquiry the landscape of literature, as well as that of painting; and this the more because the spirit of classical landscape has hardly been expressed in any other way than by words.
My reason for asking the reader to spend so much time examining the pathetic fallacy is that, whether in literature or art, it is a key feature of the modern mindset. In both literature and visual art, today's artists strive to express something that they, as living beings, project onto lifeless objects, whereas classical and medieval artists were satisfied with showcasing the actual, unembellished qualities of the objects themselves. It should be noted that, as stated long ago, I use the terms painter and poet interchangeably, considering both literature and painting in our discussion; this is even more relevant because the essence of classical landscape has rarely been captured in any form other than words.
Taking, therefore, this wide field, it is surely a very notable circumstance, to begin with, that this pathetic fallacy is eminently characteristic of modern painting. For instance, Keats, describing a wave breaking out at sea, says of it:—
Taking, therefore, this wide field, it is surely a very notable circumstance, to begin with, that this pathetic fallacy is clearly a defining feature of modern painting. For instance, Keats, describing a wave breaking at sea, says of it:—
That is quite perfect, as an example of the modern manner. The idea of the peculiar action with which foam rolls down a long, large wave could not have been given by any other words so well as by this "wayward indolence." But Homer would never have written, never thought of, such words. He could not by any possibility have lost sight of the great fact that the wave, from the beginning to the end of it, do what it might, was still nothing else than salt water; and that salt water could not be either wayward or indolent. He will call the waves "over-roofed," "full-charged," "monstrous," "compact-black," "dark-clear," "violet-coloured," "wine-coloured," and so on. But every one of these epithets is descriptive of pure physical nature. "Over-roofed" is the term he invariably uses of anything—rock, house, or wave—that nods over at the brow; the other terms need no explanation; they are as accurate and intense in truth as words can be, but they never show the slightest feeling of anything animated in the ocean. Black or clear, monstrous or violet-coloured, cold salt water it is always, and nothing but that.
That’s a perfect example of modern style. The concept of how foam rolls down a big wave couldn’t be better described than with the phrase "wayward indolence." However, Homer would never have used or thought of such words. He couldn't possibly ignore the fact that the wave, no matter what it did, was ultimately just salt water; and salt water can’t be either wayward or lazy. He would describe waves as "over-roofed," "full-charged," "monstrous," "compact-black," "dark-clear," "violet-colored," "wine-colored," and so on. Every one of these terms describes pure physical nature. "Over-roofed" is his go-to term for anything—rock, house, or wave—that leans over at the top; the other terms need no further explanation; they are as precise and intense in truth as words can get, but they never convey any sense of animation in the ocean. It’s always just cold salt water, nothing more.
"Well, but the modern writer, by his admission of the tinge of fallacy, has given an idea of something in the action of the wave which Homer could not, and surely, therefore, has made a step in advance? Also there appears to be a degree of sympathy and feeling in the one writer, which there is not in the other; and as it has been received for a first principle that writers are great in, proportion to the intensity of their feelings, and Homer seems to have no feelings about the sea but that it is black and deep, surely in this respect also the modern writer is the greater?"
"Well, the modern writer, by acknowledging the hint of fallacy, has conveyed something about the wave's action that Homer couldn't, and thus has made progress, right? Besides, there seems to be a sense of empathy and emotion in the modern writer that isn't present in Homer. Since it's generally accepted that writers are considered great based on the depth of their emotions, and Homer only sees the sea as black and deep, then in this respect, the modern writer must be greater too."
Stay a moment. Homer had some feeling about the sea; a faith in the animation of it much stronger than Keats's. But all this sense of something living in it, he separates in his mind into a great abstract image of a Sea Power. He never says the waves rage, or the waves are idle. But he says there is somewhat in, and greater than, the waves, which rages, and is idle, and that he calls a god.
Stay a moment. Homer had some feeling about the sea; a faith in its vitality that was much stronger than Keats's. But all this sense of something alive in it, he divides in his mind into a big abstract idea of a Sea Power. He never says the waves rage, or the waves are calm. Instead, he suggests there is something within, and greater than, the waves that rages and rests, and that he calls a god.
I do not think we ever enough endeavour to enter into what a Greek's real notion of a god was. We are so accustomed to the modern mockeries of the classical religion, so accustomed to hear and see the Greek gods introduced as living personages, or invoked for help, by men who believe neither in them nor in any other gods, that we seem to have infected the Greek ages themselves with the breath, and dimmed them with the shade, of our hypocrisy; and are apt to think that Homer, as we know that Pope, was merely an ingenious fabulist; nay, more than this, that all the nations of past time were ingenious fabulists also, to whom the universe was a lyrical drama, and by whom whatsoever was said about it was merely a witty allegory, or a graceful lie, of which the entire upshot and consummation was a pretty statue in the middle of the court, or at the end of the garden.
I don’t think we really try hard enough to understand what a Greek truly believed about their gods. We are so used to the modern mockery of classical religion, to hearing the Greek gods portrayed as actual characters or called upon for assistance by people who don’t believe in them or any other gods, that we seem to have influenced the Greek eras themselves with our insincerity and have clouded them with our hypocrisy. We tend to think that Homer, like Pope, was just a clever storyteller; or worse, that all the ancient peoples were just clever storytellers as well, who viewed the universe as a musical and whatever they said about it was just a witty metaphor or a nice fabrication, culminating in a beautiful statue in the center of the courtyard or at the end of the garden.
This, at least, is one of our forms of opinion about Greek faith; not, indeed, possible altogether to any man of honesty or ordinary powers of thought; but still so venomously inherent in the modern philosophy that all the pure lightning of Carlyle cannot as yet quite burn it out of any of us. And then, side by side with this mere infidel folly, stands the bitter short-sightedness of Puritanism, holding the classical god to be either simply an idol,—a block of stone ignorantly, though sincerely, worshipped—or else an actual diabolic or betraying power, usurping the place of God.
This is one view we have about Greek faith; it’s not really something that a person of integrity or normal thinking can fully accept. However, it’s so deeply embedded in modern philosophy that even the brilliant insights of Carlyle can’t completely eliminate it from us. Next to this misguided disbelief lies the narrow-mindedness of Puritanism, which sees the classical god as either just an idol—a stone block worshipped in ignorance, though sincerely—or as a real evil force that takes God’s place.
Both these Puritanical estimates of Greek deity are of course to some extent true. The corruption of classical worship is barren idolatry; and that corruption was deepened, and variously directed to their own purposes, by the evil angels. But this was neither the whole, nor the principal part, of Pagan worship. Pallas was not, in the pure Greek mind, merely a powerful piece of ivory in a temple at Athens; neither was the choice of Leonidas between the alternatives granted him by the oracle, of personal death, or ruin to his country, altogether a work of the Devil's prompting.
Both of these Puritanical views of Greek gods are, to some extent, true. The corruption of classical worship is empty idolatry; this corruption was intensified and misdirected by evil spirits to serve their own purposes. However, this was neither the whole story nor the main aspect of Pagan worship. In the pure Greek mindset, Pallas was not just a powerful statue made of ivory in a temple in Athens; likewise, Leonidas's choice between the options presented by the oracle—personal death or the downfall of his country—was not entirely influenced by the Devil's urging.
What, then, was actually the Greek god? In what way were these two ideas of human form, and divine power, credibly associated in the ancient heart, so as to become a subject of true faith irrespective equally of fable, allegory, superstitious trust in stone, and demoniacal influence?
What, then, was the Greek god really like? How were these two concepts of human appearance and divine power convincingly connected in the minds of ancient people, to the point that they could genuinely believe in them, regardless of myths, allegories, blind faith in statues, or evil forces?
It seems to me that the Greek had exactly the same instinctive feeling about the elements that we have ourselves; that to Homer, as much as to Casimir de la Vigne,[75] fire seemed ravenous and pitiless; to Homer, as much as to Keats, the sea-wave appeared wayward or idle, or whatever else it may be to the poetical passion. But then the Greek reasoned upon this sensation, saying to himself: "I can light the fire, and put it out; I can dry this water up, or drink it. It cannot be the fire or the water that rages, or that is wayward. But it must be something in this fire and in the water, which I cannot destroy by extinguishing the one, or evaporating the other, any more than I destroy myself by cutting off my finger; I was in my finger,—something of me at least was; I had a power over it and felt pain in it, though I am still as much myself when it is gone. So there may be a power in the water which is not water, but to which the water is as a body;—which can strike with it, move in it, suffer in it, yet not be destroyed with it. This something, this Great Water Spirit, I must not confuse with the waves, which are only its body. They may flow hither and thither, increase or diminish. That must be invisible—imperishable—a god. So of fire also; those rays which I can stop, and in the midst of which I cast a shadow, cannot be divine, nor greater than I. They cannot feel, but there may be something in them that feels,—a glorious intelligence, as much nobler and more swift than mine, as these rays, which are its body, are nobler and swifter than my flesh;—the spirit of all light, and truth, and melody, and revolving hours."
It seems to me that the Greek had exactly the same instinctive feeling about the elements that we have ourselves; that to Homer, as much as to Casimir de la Vigne,[75] fire seemed ravenous and pitiless; to Homer, as much as to Keats, the sea-wave appeared wayward or idle, or whatever else it may be to the poetical passion. But then the Greek reasoned upon this sensation, saying to himself: "I can light the fire, and put it out; I can dry this water up, or drink it. It cannot be the fire or the water that rages, or that is wayward. But it must be something in this fire and in the water, which I cannot destroy by extinguishing the one, or evaporating the other, any more than I destroy myself by cutting off my finger; I was in my finger,—something of me at least was; I had a power over it and felt pain in it, though I am still as much myself when it is gone. So there may be a power in the water which is not water, but to which the water is as a body;—which can strike with it, move in it, suffer in it, yet not be destroyed with it. This something, this Great Water Spirit, I must not confuse with the waves, which are only its body. They may flow hither and thither, increase or diminish. That must be invisible—imperishable—a god. So of fire also; those rays which I can stop, and in the midst of which I cast a shadow, cannot be divine, nor greater than I. They cannot feel, but there may be something in them that feels,—a glorious intelligence, as much nobler and more swift than mine, as these rays, which are its body, are nobler and swifter than my flesh;—the spirit of all light, and truth, and melody, and revolving hours."
It was easy to conceive, farther, that such spirits should be able to assume at will a human form, in order to hold intercourse with men, or to perform any act for which their proper body, whether of fire, earth, or air, was unfitted. And it would have been to place them beneath, instead of above, humanity, if, assuming the form of man, they could not also have tasted his pleasures. Hence the easy step to the more or less material ideas of deities, which are apt at first to shock us, but which are indeed only dishonourable so far as they represent the gods as false and unholy. It is not the materialism, but the vice, which degrades the conception; for the materialism itself is never positive or complete. There is always some sense of exaltation in the spiritual and immortal body; and of a power proceeding from the visible form through all the infinity of the element ruled by the particular god. The precise nature of the idea is well seen in the passage of the Iliad which describes the river Scamander defending the Trojans against Achilles.[76] In order to remonstrate with the hero, the god assumes a human form, which nevertheless is in some way or other instantly recognized by Achilles as that of the river-god: it is addressed at once as a river, not as a man; and its voice is the voice of a river "out of the deep whirlpools."[77] Achilles refuses to obey its commands; and from the human form it returns instantly into its natural or divine one, and endeavours to overwhelm him with waves. Vulcan defends Achilles, and sends fire against the river, which suffers in its water-body, till it is able to bear no more. At last even the "nerve of the river," or "strength of the river" (note the expression), feels the fire, and this "strength of the river" addresses Vulcan in supplications for respite. There is in this precisely the idea of a vital part of the river-body, which acted and felt, and which, if the fire reached, it was death, just as would be the case if it touched a vital part of the human body. Throughout the passage the manner of conception is perfectly clear and consistent; and if, in other places, the exact connection between the ruling spirit and the thing ruled is not so manifest, it is only because it is almost impossible for the human mind to dwell long upon such subjects without falling into inconsistencies, and gradually slackening its effort to grasp the entire truth; until the more spiritual part of it slips from its hold, and only the human form of the god is left, to be conceived and described as subject to all the errors of humanity. But I do not believe that the idea ever weakens itself down to mere allegory. When Pallas is said to attack and strike down Mars, it does not mean merely that Wisdom at that moment prevailed against Wrath. It means that there are, indeed, two great spirits, one entrusted to guide the human soul to wisdom and chastity, the other to kindle wrath and prompt to battle. It means that these two spirits, on the spot where, and at the moment when, a great contest was to be decided between all that they each governed in man, then and there (assumed) human form, and human weapons, and did verily and materially strike at each other, until the Spirit of Wrath was crushed. And when Diana is said to hunt with her nymphs in the woods, it does not mean merely, as Wordsworth puts it,[78] that the poet or shepherd saw the moon and stars glancing between the branches of the trees, and wished to say so figuratively. It means that there is a living spirit, to which the light of the moon is a body; which takes delight in glancing between the clouds and following the wild beasts as they wander through the night; and that this spirit sometimes assumes a perfect human form, and in this form, with real arrows, pursues and slays the wild beasts, which with its mere arrows of moonlight it could not slay; retaining, nevertheless, all the while, its power and being in the moonlight, and in all else that it rules.
It was easy to conceive, farther, that such spirits should be able to assume at will a human form, in order to hold intercourse with men, or to perform any act for which their proper body, whether of fire, earth, or air, was unfitted. And it would have been to place them beneath, instead of above, humanity, if, assuming the form of man, they could not also have tasted his pleasures. Hence the easy step to the more or less material ideas of deities, which are apt at first to shock us, but which are indeed only dishonourable so far as they represent the gods as false and unholy. It is not the materialism, but the vice, which degrades the conception; for the materialism itself is never positive or complete. There is always some sense of exaltation in the spiritual and immortal body; and of a power proceeding from the visible form through all the infinity of the element ruled by the particular god. The precise nature of the idea is well seen in the passage of the Iliad which describes the river Scamander defending the Trojans against Achilles.[76] In order to remonstrate with the hero, the god assumes a human form, which nevertheless is in some way or other instantly recognized by Achilles as that of the river-god: it is addressed at once as a river, not as a man; and its voice is the voice of a river "out of the deep whirlpools."[77] Achilles refuses to obey its commands; and from the human form it returns instantly into its natural or divine one, and endeavours to overwhelm him with waves. Vulcan defends Achilles, and sends fire against the river, which suffers in its water-body, till it is able to bear no more. At last even the "nerve of the river," or "strength of the river" (note the expression), feels the fire, and this "strength of the river" addresses Vulcan in supplications for respite. There is in this precisely the idea of a vital part of the river-body, which acted and felt, and which, if the fire reached, it was death, just as would be the case if it touched a vital part of the human body. Throughout the passage the manner of conception is perfectly clear and consistent; and if, in other places, the exact connection between the ruling spirit and the thing ruled is not so manifest, it is only because it is almost impossible for the human mind to dwell long upon such subjects without falling into inconsistencies, and gradually slackening its effort to grasp the entire truth; until the more spiritual part of it slips from its hold, and only the human form of the god is left, to be conceived and described as subject to all the errors of humanity. But I do not believe that the idea ever weakens itself down to mere allegory. When Pallas is said to attack and strike down Mars, it does not mean merely that Wisdom at that moment prevailed against Wrath. It means that there are, indeed, two great spirits, one entrusted to guide the human soul to wisdom and chastity, the other to kindle wrath and prompt to battle. It means that these two spirits, on the spot where, and at the moment when, a great contest was to be decided between all that they each governed in man, then and there (assumed) human form, and human weapons, and did verily and materially strike at each other, until the Spirit of Wrath was crushed. And when Diana is said to hunt with her nymphs in the woods, it does not mean merely, as Wordsworth puts it,[78] that the poet or shepherd saw the moon and stars glancing between the branches of the trees, and wished to say so figuratively. It means that there is a living spirit, to which the light of the moon is a body; which takes delight in glancing between the clouds and following the wild beasts as they wander through the night; and that this spirit sometimes assumes a perfect human form, and in this form, with real arrows, pursues and slays the wild beasts, which with its mere arrows of moonlight it could not slay; retaining, nevertheless, all the while, its power and being in the moonlight, and in all else that it rules.
There is not the smallest inconsistency or unspirituality in this conception. If there were, it would attach equally to the appearance of the angels to Jacob, Abraham, Joshua, or Manoah.[79] In all those instances the highest authority which governs our own faith requires us to conceive divine power clothed with a human form (a form so real that it is recognized for superhuman only by its "doing wondrously"), and retaining, nevertheless, sovereignty and omnipresence in all the world. This is precisely, as I understand it, the heathen idea of a God; and it is impossible to comprehend any single part of the Greek mind until we grasp this faithfully, not endeavouring to explain it away in any wise, but accepting, with frank decision and definition, the tangible existence of its deities;—blue-eyed—white-fleshed— human-hearted,—capable at their choice of meeting man absolutely in his own nature—feasting with him—talking with him—fighting with him, eye to eye, or breast to breast, as Mars with Diomed;[80] or else, dealing with him in a more retired spirituality, as Apollo sending the plague upon the Greeks,[81] when his quiver rattles at his shoulders as he moves, and yet the darts sent forth of it strike not as arrows, but as plague; or, finally, retiring completely into the material universe which they properly inhabit, and dealing with man through that, as Scamander with Achilles, through his waves.
There is not the smallest inconsistency or unspirituality in this conception. If there were, it would attach equally to the appearance of the angels to Jacob, Abraham, Joshua, or Manoah.[79] In all those instances the highest authority which governs our own faith requires us to conceive divine power clothed with a human form (a form so real that it is recognized for superhuman only by its "doing wondrously"), and retaining, nevertheless, sovereignty and omnipresence in all the world. This is precisely, as I understand it, the heathen idea of a God; and it is impossible to comprehend any single part of the Greek mind until we grasp this faithfully, not endeavouring to explain it away in any wise, but accepting, with frank decision and definition, the tangible existence of its deities;—blue-eyed—white-fleshed— human-hearted,—capable at their choice of meeting man absolutely in his own nature—feasting with him—talking with him—fighting with him, eye to eye, or breast to breast, as Mars with Diomed;[80] or else, dealing with him in a more retired spirituality, as Apollo sending the plague upon the Greeks,[81] when his quiver rattles at his shoulders as he moves, and yet the darts sent forth of it strike not as arrows, but as plague; or, finally, retiring completely into the material universe which they properly inhabit, and dealing with man through that, as Scamander with Achilles, through his waves.
Nor is there anything whatever in the various actions recorded of the gods, however apparently ignoble, to indicate weakness of belief in them. Very frequently things which appear to us ignoble are merely the simplicities of a pure and truthful age. When Juno beats Diana about the ears with her own quiver,[82] for instance, we start at first, as if Homer could not have believed that they were both real goddesses. But what should Juno have done? Killed Diana with a look? Nay, she neither wished to do so, nor could she have done so, by the very faith of Diana's goddess-ship. Diana is as immortal as herself. Frowned Diana into submission? But Diana has come expressly to try conclusions with her, and will by no means be frowned into submission. Wounded her with a celestial lance? That sounds more poetical, but it is in reality partly more savage and partly more absurd, than Homer. More savage, for it makes Juno more cruel, therefore less divine; and more absurd, for it only seems elevated in tone, because we use the word "celestial," which means nothing. What sort of a thing is a "celestial" lance? Not a wooden one. Of what then? Of moonbeams, or clouds, or mist. Well, therefore, Diana's arrows were of mist too; and her quiver, and herself, and Juno, with her lance, and all, vanish into mist. Why not have said at once, if that is all you mean, that two mists met, and one drove the other back? That would have been rational and intelligible, but not to talk of celestial lances. Homer had no such misty fancy; he believed the two goddesses were there in true bodies, with true weapons, on the true earth; and still I ask, what should Juno have done? Not beaten Diana? No; for it is unlady-like. Un-English-lady-like, yes; but by no means un-Greek-lady-like, nor even un-natural-lady-like. If a modern lady does not beat her servant or her rival about the ears, it is oftener because she is too weak, or too proud, than because she is of purer mind than Homer's Juno. She will not strike them; but she will overwork the one or slander the other without pity; and Homer would not have thought that one whit more goddess-like than striking them with her open hand.
Nor is there anything whatever in the various actions recorded of the gods, however apparently ignoble, to indicate weakness of belief in them. Very frequently things which appear to us ignoble are merely the simplicities of a pure and truthful age. When Juno beats Diana about the ears with her own quiver,[82] for instance, we start at first, as if Homer could not have believed that they were both real goddesses. But what should Juno have done? Killed Diana with a look? Nay, she neither wished to do so, nor could she have done so, by the very faith of Diana's goddess-ship. Diana is as immortal as herself. Frowned Diana into submission? But Diana has come expressly to try conclusions with her, and will by no means be frowned into submission. Wounded her with a celestial lance? That sounds more poetical, but it is in reality partly more savage and partly more absurd, than Homer. More savage, for it makes Juno more cruel, therefore less divine; and more absurd, for it only seems elevated in tone, because we use the word "celestial," which means nothing. What sort of a thing is a "celestial" lance? Not a wooden one. Of what then? Of moonbeams, or clouds, or mist. Well, therefore, Diana's arrows were of mist too; and her quiver, and herself, and Juno, with her lance, and all, vanish into mist. Why not have said at once, if that is all you mean, that two mists met, and one drove the other back? That would have been rational and intelligible, but not to talk of celestial lances. Homer had no such misty fancy; he believed the two goddesses were there in true bodies, with true weapons, on the true earth; and still I ask, what should Juno have done? Not beaten Diana? No; for it is unlady-like. Un-English-lady-like, yes; but by no means un-Greek-lady-like, nor even un-natural-lady-like. If a modern lady does not beat her servant or her rival about the ears, it is oftener because she is too weak, or too proud, than because she is of purer mind than Homer's Juno. She will not strike them; but she will overwork the one or slander the other without pity; and Homer would not have thought that one whit more goddess-like than striking them with her open hand.
If, however, the reader likes to suppose that while the two goddesses in personal presence thus fought with arrow and quiver, there was also a broader and vaster contest supposed by Homer between the elements they ruled; and that the goddess of the heavens, as she struck the goddess of the moon on the flushing cheek, was at the same instant exercising omnipresent power in the heavens themselves, and gathering clouds, with which, filled with the moon's own arrows or beams, she was encumbering and concealing the moon; he is welcome to this out carrying of the idea, provided that he does not pretend to make it an interpretation instead of a mere extension, nor think to explain away my real, running, beautiful beaten Diana, into a moon behind clouds.[83]
If, however, the reader likes to suppose that while the two goddesses in personal presence thus fought with arrow and quiver, there was also a broader and vaster contest supposed by Homer between the elements they ruled; and that the goddess of the heavens, as she struck the goddess of the moon on the flushing cheek, was at the same instant exercising omnipresent power in the heavens themselves, and gathering clouds, with which, filled with the moon's own arrows or beams, she was encumbering and concealing the moon; he is welcome to this out carrying of the idea, provided that he does not pretend to make it an interpretation instead of a mere extension, nor think to explain away my real, running, beautiful beaten Diana, into a moon behind clouds.[83]
It is only farther to be noted, that the Greek conception of Godhead, as it was much more real than we usually suppose, so it was much more bold and familiar than to a modern mind would be possible. I shall have something more to observe, in a little while, of the danger of our modern habit of endeavouring to raise ourselves to something like comprehension of the truth of divinity, instead of simply believing the words in which the Deity reveals Himself to us. The Greek erred rather on the other side, making hardly any effort to conceive divine mind as above the human; and no more shrinking from frank intercourse with a divine being, or dreading its immediate presence, than that of the simplest of mortals. Thus Atrides, enraged at his sword's breaking in his hand upon the helmet of Paris, after he had expressly invoked the assistance of Jupiter, exclaims aloud, as he would to a king who had betrayed him, "Jove, Father, there is not another god more evil-minded than thou!"[84] and Helen, provoked at Paris's defeat, and oppressed with pouting shame both for him and for herself, when Venus appears at her side, and would lead her back to the delivered Paris, impatiently tells the goddess to "go and take care of Paris herself."[85]
It is only farther to be noted, that the Greek conception of Godhead, as it was much more real than we usually suppose, so it was much more bold and familiar than to a modern mind would be possible. I shall have something more to observe, in a little while, of the danger of our modern habit of endeavouring to raise ourselves to something like comprehension of the truth of divinity, instead of simply believing the words in which the Deity reveals Himself to us. The Greek erred rather on the other side, making hardly any effort to conceive divine mind as above the human; and no more shrinking from frank intercourse with a divine being, or dreading its immediate presence, than that of the simplest of mortals. Thus Atrides, enraged at his sword's breaking in his hand upon the helmet of Paris, after he had expressly invoked the assistance of Jupiter, exclaims aloud, as he would to a king who had betrayed him, "Jove, Father, there is not another god more evil-minded than thou!"[84] and Helen, provoked at Paris's defeat, and oppressed with pouting shame both for him and for herself, when Venus appears at her side, and would lead her back to the delivered Paris, impatiently tells the goddess to "go and take care of Paris herself."[85]
The modern mind is naturally, but vulgarly and unjustly, shocked by this kind of familiarity. Rightly understood, it is not so much a sign of misunderstanding of the divine nature as of good understanding of the human. The Greek lived, in all things, a healthy, and, in a certain degree, a perfect life. He had no morbid or sickly feeling of any kind. He was accustomed to face death without the slightest shrinking, to undergo all kinds of bodily hardship without complaint, and to do what he supposed right and honourable, in most cases, as a matter of course. Confident of his own immortality, and of the power of abstract justice, he expected to be dealt with in the next world as was right, and left the matter much in his god's hands; but being thus immortal, and finding in his own soul something which it seemed quite as difficult to master, as to rule the elements, he did not feel that it was an appalling superiority in those gods to have bodies of water, or fire, instead of flesh, and to have various work to do among the clouds and waves, out of his human way; or sometimes, even in a sort of service to himself. Was not the nourishment of herbs and flowers a kind of ministering to his wants; were not the gods in some sort his husbandmen, and spirit-servants? Their mere strength or omnipresence did not seem to him a distinction absolutely terrific. It might be the nature of one being to be in two places at once, and of another to be only in one; but that did not seem of itself to infer any absolute lordliness of one nature above the other, any more than an insect must be a nobler creature than a man, because it can see on four sides of its head, and the man only in front. They could kill him or torture him, it was true; but even that not unjustly, or not for ever. There was a fate, and a Divine Justice, greater than they; so that if they did wrong, and he right, he might fight it out with them, and have the better of them at last. In a general way, they were wiser, stronger, and better than he; and to ask counsel of them, to obey them, to sacrifice to them, to thank them for all good, this was well: but to be utterly downcast before them, or not to tell them his mind in plain Greek if they seemed to him to be conducting themselves in an ungodly manner—this would not be well.
The modern mindset is often, but unfairly, shocked by this kind of familiarity. When understood correctly, it reflects not so much a misunderstanding of the divine nature but rather a clear understanding of the human. The Greeks lived healthy, and to some extent, ideal lives. They didn't have any morbid or sickly feelings. They faced death boldly, endured physical hardships without complaint, and did what they believed to be right and honorable as a matter of routine. Confident in their own immortality and the power of justice, they expected to be treated fairly in the next life and mostly left those matters in their god's hands. However, being immortal, and finding something within themselves that seemed just as challenging to control as the elements, they didn't see the gods' physical forms of water or fire as an overwhelming superiority. Nor did they view the gods’ tasks among clouds and waves as being beyond their human realm; sometimes, these tasks even seemed to serve human needs. Wasn't the growth of herbs and flowers a way of meeting their own needs? Weren't the gods somewhat like caretakers and spiritual servants? The mere fact that the gods were strong or omnipresent didn’t strike them as a terrifying distinction. It could be one being's nature to exist in multiple places while another’s could exist in just one; that didn’t imply that one nature was inherently superior to the other—just as an insect wasn’t a nobler creature than a human simply because it could see in multiple directions while the human could only see straight ahead. Yes, the gods could kill or torture them, but that wouldn’t necessarily be unjust or permanent. There was a fate and a Divine Justice larger than them; so, if the gods did wrong while the Greeks did right, they could confront them and ultimately prevail. Generally speaking, the gods were wiser, stronger, and better; seeking their counsel, obeying them, making sacrifices, and expressing gratitude for all good was appropriate. But being completely subservient or failing to express their thoughts in clear and straightforward terms if they believed the gods were acting unjustly— that wouldn’t be right.
Such being their general idea of the gods, we can now easily understand the habitual tone of their feelings towards what was beautiful in nature. With us, observe, the idea of the Divinity is apt to get separated from the life of nature; and imagining our God upon a cloudy throne, far above the earth, and not in the flowers or waters, we approach those visible things with a theory that they are dead; governed by physical laws, and so forth. But coming to them, we find the theory fail; that they are not dead; that, say what we choose about them, the instinctive sense of their being alive is too strong for us; and in scorn of all physical law, the wilful fountain sings, and the kindly flowers rejoice. And then, puzzled, and yet happy; pleased, and yet ashamed of being so; accepting sympathy from nature which we do not believe it gives, and giving sympathy to nature, which we do not believe it receives,—mixing, besides, all manner of purposeful play and conceit with these involuntary fellowships,—we fall necessarily into the curious web of hesitating sentiment, pathetic fallacy, and wandering fancy, which form a great part of our modern view of nature. But the Greek never removed his god out of nature at all; never attempted for a moment to contradict his instinctive sense that God was everywhere. "The tree is glad," said he, "I know it is; I can cut it down: no matter, there was a nymph in it. The water does sing," said he; "I can dry it up; but no matter, there was a naiad in it." But in thus clearly defining his belief, observe, he threw it entirely into a human form, and gave his faith to nothing but the image of his own humanity. What sympathy and fellowship he had, were always for the spirit in the stream, not for the stream; always for the dryad in the wood, not for the wood. Content with this human sympathy, he approached the actual waves and woody fibres with no sympathy at all. The spirit that ruled them, he received as a plain fact. Them, also, ruled and material, he received as plain facts; they, without their spirit, were dead enough. A rose was good for scent, and a stream for sound and coolness; for the rest, one was no more than leaves, the other no more than water; he could not make anything else of them; and the divine power, which was involved in their existence, having been all distilled away by him into an independent Flora or Thetis, the poor leaves or waves were left, in mere cold corporealness, to make the most of their being discernibly red and soft, clear and wet, and unacknowledged in any other power whatsoever.
Given their overall view of the gods, we can now easily grasp their usual feelings towards the beauty found in nature. For us, the idea of divinity often separates from the life of nature; we visualize our God sitting on a cloudy throne far above the earth, not in the flowers or waters. We approach these visible aspects with the belief that they are lifeless, governed purely by physical laws and so on. However, when we encounter them, we realize this belief doesn't hold; they are very much alive, and regardless of what we say about them, we can't shake the instinctive sense that they have life. Defying all physical laws, the playful fountain flows, and the cheerful flowers bloom. In this confusion, we feel both puzzled and happy, pleased yet ashamed of our joy. We accept affection from nature, which we don’t truly believe it offers, while we give love to nature that we think it doesn't receive—mixing all kinds of intentional playfulness and fancies with these involuntary connections. This leads us into a strange tangle of uncertain feelings, misguided assumptions, and wandering thoughts, which shape a large part of our modern view of nature. But the Greeks never removed their gods from nature; they never tried to deny their deep-rooted belief that God was everywhere. "The tree is happy," they would say, "I know it is; even if I cut it down, there was a nymph in it. The water does sing," they said; "I can drain it, but it doesn’t matter, there was a naiad in it." In clarifying their beliefs, they gave everything a human form, placing their faith only in the image of humanity. The connection and fellowship they felt were always for the spirit in the stream, not just the stream itself; always for the dryad in the woods, not for the woods themselves. Satisfied with this human connection, they engaged with the actual waves and tree fibers with no empathy whatsoever. The spirit that governed them was accepted as a straightforward fact. And these materials, ruled and tangible, were also accepted as facts; they, without their spirit, felt lifeless enough. A rose was valuable for its fragrance, and a stream for its sound and coolness; apart from that, one was merely leaves, and the other just water; they couldn’t see anything else in them. The divine essence tied to their existence had been distilled into an independent Flora or Thetis, leaving the poor leaves or waves in mere cold materiality to showcase their visible qualities—red and soft, clear and wet—without recognition of any other power at all.
Then, observe farther, the Greeks lived in the midst of the most beautiful nature, and were as familiar with blue sea, clear air, and sweet outlines of mountain, as we are with brick walls, black smoke, and level fields. This perfect familiarity rendered all such scenes of natural beauty unexciting, if not indifferent to them, by lulling and overwearying the imagination as far as it was concerned with such things; but there was another kind of beauty which they found it required effort to obtain, and which, when thoroughly obtained, seemed more glorious than any of this wild loveliness—the beauty of the human countenance and form. This, they perceived, could only be reached by continual exercise of virtue; and it was in Heaven's sight, and theirs, all the more beautiful because it needed this self-denial to obtain it. So they set themselves to reach this, and having gained it, gave it their principal thoughts, and set it off with beautiful dress as best they might. But making this their object, they were obliged to pass their lives in simple exercise and disciplined employments. Living wholesomely, giving themselves no fever fits, either by fasting or over-eating, constantly in the open air, and full of animal spirit and physical power, they became incapable of every morbid condition of mental emotion. Unhappy love, disappointed ambition, spiritual despondency, or any other disturbing sensation, had little power over the well-braced nerves, and healthy flow of the blood; and what bitterness might yet fasten on them was soon boxed or raced out of a boy, and spun or woven out of a girl, or danced out of both. They had indeed their sorrows, true and deep, but still, more like children's sorrows than ours, whether bursting into open cry of pain, or hid with shuddering under the veil, still passing over the soul as clouds do over heaven, not sullying it, not mingling with it;—darkening it perhaps long or utterly, but still not becoming one with it, and for the most part passing away in dashing rain of tears, and leaving the man unchanged; in no wise affecting, as our sorrow does, the whole tone of his thought and imagination thenceforward.
Then, look further: the Greeks lived surrounded by the most beautiful nature, completely comfortable with the blue sea, clear sky, and lovely mountain shapes, just like we are with brick buildings, black smoke, and flat fields. This complete familiarity made all these stunning natural scenes feel less exciting, if not entirely uninteresting, by lulling and tiring out their imagination regarding such things. However, there was another type of beauty that they found required effort to achieve, and when truly won, seemed more magnificent than all this wild beauty—the beauty of the human face and body. They realized this could only be reached through constant practice of virtue; and it was in Heaven's eyes, and theirs, even more beautiful because it required this self-control to attain it. So, they dedicated themselves to achieving it, and once they did, they focused their main thoughts on it, dressing it up as beautifully as they could. But making this their goal meant they had to live their lives in simple exercise and disciplined activities. By living healthily, avoiding extremes of fasting or binge eating, spending lots of time outdoors, and being full of energy and physical strength, they became immune to any unhealthy mental states. Unrequited love, failed ambitions, spiritual despair, or any other troubling feelings had little effect on their strong nerves and healthy blood flow; and whatever negativity they experienced could quickly be run out of a boy, spun out of a girl, or danced out of both. They did indeed experience true and deep sorrows, but these were more like children's sorrows than ours, whether bursting into open cries of pain or being suppressed with a shudder behind a veil, still passing over the soul like clouds passing over the sky, not tarnishing it, not blending with it;—perhaps darkening it for a long time or even completely, but still not becoming one with it, and for the most part, fading away in a pouring rain of tears, leaving the person unchanged; not affecting, as our sorrows do, the overall tone of their thoughts and imagination afterward.
How far our melancholy may be deeper and wider than theirs in its roots and view, and therefore nobler, we shall consider presently; but at all events, they had the advantage of us in being entirely free from all those dim and feverish sensations which result from unhealthy state of the body. I believe that a large amount of the dreamy and sentimental sadness, tendency to reverie, and general patheticalness of modern life results merely from derangement of stomach; holding to the Greek life the same relation that the feverish night of an adult does to a child's sleep.
How much deeper and broader our sadness might be compared to theirs in its roots and perspective, which makes it nobler, we will discuss shortly; but in any case, they had the upper hand by being completely free from those vague and restless feelings that come from being physically unwell. I think that a lot of the dreamy and sentimental sadness, the tendency to daydream, and the overall emotional nature of modern life comes simply from stomach problems, similar to how an adult's restless night relates to a child's peaceful sleep.
Farther. The human beauty, which, whether in its bodily being or in imagined divinity, had become, for the reasons we have seen, the principal object of culture and sympathy to these Greeks, was, in its perfection, eminently orderly, symmetrical, and tender. Hence, contemplating it constantly in this state, they could not but feel a proportionate fear of all that was disorderly, unbalanced, and rugged. Having trained their stoutest soldiers into a strength so delicate and lovely, that their white flesh, with their blood upon it, should look like ivory stained with purple;[86] and having always around them, in the motion and majesty of this beauty, enough for the full employment of their imagination, they shrank with dread or hatred from all the ruggedness of lower nature,—from the wrinkled forest bark, the jagged hill-crest, and irregular, inorganic storm of sky; looking to these for the most part as adverse powers, and taking pleasure only in such portions of the lower world as were at once conducive to the rest and health of the human frame, and in harmony with the laws of its gentler beauty.
Farther. The human beauty, which, whether in its bodily being or in imagined divinity, had become, for the reasons we have seen, the principal object of culture and sympathy to these Greeks, was, in its perfection, eminently orderly, symmetrical, and tender. Hence, contemplating it constantly in this state, they could not but feel a proportionate fear of all that was disorderly, unbalanced, and rugged. Having trained their stoutest soldiers into a strength so delicate and lovely, that their white flesh, with their blood upon it, should look like ivory stained with purple;[86] and having always around them, in the motion and majesty of this beauty, enough for the full employment of their imagination, they shrank with dread or hatred from all the ruggedness of lower nature,—from the wrinkled forest bark, the jagged hill-crest, and irregular, inorganic storm of sky; looking to these for the most part as adverse powers, and taking pleasure only in such portions of the lower world as were at once conducive to the rest and health of the human frame, and in harmony with the laws of its gentler beauty.
Thus, as far as I recollect, without a single exception, every Homeric landscape, intended to be beautiful, is composed of a fountain, a meadow, and a shady grove. This ideal is very interestingly marked, as intended for a perfect one, in the fifth book of the Odyssey; when Mercury himself stops for a moment, though on a message, to look at a landscape "which even an immortal might be gladdened to behold."[87] This landscape consists of a cave covered with a running vine, all blooming into grapes, and surrounded by a grove of alder, poplar, and sweet-smelling cypress. Four fountains of white (foaming) water, springing in succession (mark the orderliness), and close to one another, flow away in different directions, through a meadow full of violets and parsley (parsley, to mark its moisture, being elsewhere called "marsh-nourished," and associated with the lotus[88]); the air is perfumed not only by these violets, and by the sweet cypress, but by Calypso's fire of finely chopped cedar-wood, which sends a smoke, as of incense, through the island; Calypso herself is singing; and finally, upon the trees are resting, or roosting, owls, hawks, and "long-tongued sea-crows." Whether these last are considered as a part of the ideal landscape, as marine singing birds, I know not; but the approval of Mercury appears to be elicited chiefly by the fountains and violet meadow.
Thus, as far as I recollect, without a single exception, every Homeric landscape, intended to be beautiful, is composed of a fountain, a meadow, and a shady grove. This ideal is very interestingly marked, as intended for a perfect one, in the fifth book of the Odyssey; when Mercury himself stops for a moment, though on a message, to look at a landscape "which even an immortal might be gladdened to behold."[87] This landscape consists of a cave covered with a running vine, all blooming into grapes, and surrounded by a grove of alder, poplar, and sweet-smelling cypress. Four fountains of white (foaming) water, springing in succession (mark the orderliness), and close to one another, flow away in different directions, through a meadow full of violets and parsley (parsley, to mark its moisture, being elsewhere called "marsh-nourished," and associated with the lotus[88]); the air is perfumed not only by these violets, and by the sweet cypress, but by Calypso's fire of finely chopped cedar-wood, which sends a smoke, as of incense, through the island; Calypso herself is singing; and finally, upon the trees are resting, or roosting, owls, hawks, and "long-tongued sea-crows." Whether these last are considered as a part of the ideal landscape, as marine singing birds, I know not; but the approval of Mercury appears to be elicited chiefly by the fountains and violet meadow.
Now the notable things in this description are, first, the evident subservience of the whole landscape to human comfort, to the foot, the taste, or the smell; and, secondly, that throughout the passage there is not a single figurative word expressive of the things being in any wise other than plain grass, fruit, or flower. I have used the term "spring" of the fountains, because, without doubt, Homer means that they sprang forth brightly, having their source at the foot of the rocks (as copious fountains nearly always have); but Homer does not say "spring," he says simply flow, and uses only one word for "growing softly," or "richly," of the tall trees, the vine, and the violets. There is, however, some expression of sympathy with the sea-birds; he speaks of them in precisely the same terms, as in other places of naval nations, saying they "have care of the works of the sea."
Now the notable things in this description are, first, the obvious way the entire landscape serves human comfort, with consideration for walking, taste, or smell; and, secondly, that throughout the passage there isn't a single figurative word suggesting that things are anything other than simple grass, fruit, or flowers. I’ve used the term "spring" for the fountains because, without a doubt, Homer means that they burst forth brightly from the base of the rocks (as abundant fountains typically do); but Homer doesn't say "spring," he simply says flow, and he uses only one word for "growing softly" or "richly" when referring to the tall trees, the vine, and the violets. However, there is some expression of connection with the sea-birds; he describes them in exactly the same way, as he does in other passages concerning naval nations, saying they "look after the works of the sea."
If we glance through the references to pleasant landscape which occur in other parts of the Odyssey, we shall always be struck by this quiet subjection of their every feature to human service, and by the excessive similarity in the scenes. Perhaps the spot intended, after this, to be most perfect, may be the garden of Alcinous, where the principal ideas are, still more definitely, order, symmetry and fruitfulness;[89] the beds being duly ranged between rows of vines, which, as well as the pear, apple, and fig trees, bear fruit continually, some grapes being yet sour, while others are getting black; there are plenty of "orderly square beds of herbs," chiefly leeks, and two fountains, one running through the garden, and one under the pavement of the palace to a reservoir for the citizens. Ulysses, pausing to contemplate this scene, is described nearly in the same terms as Mercury pausing to contemplate the wilder meadow; and it is interesting to observe, that, in spite of all Homer's love of symmetry, the god's admiration is excited by the free fountains, wild violets, and wandering vine; but the mortal's, by the vines in rows, the leeks in beds, and the fountains in pipes.
If we glance through the references to pleasant landscape which occur in other parts of the Odyssey, we shall always be struck by this quiet subjection of their every feature to human service, and by the excessive similarity in the scenes. Perhaps the spot intended, after this, to be most perfect, may be the garden of Alcinous, where the principal ideas are, still more definitely, order, symmetry and fruitfulness;[89] the beds being duly ranged between rows of vines, which, as well as the pear, apple, and fig trees, bear fruit continually, some grapes being yet sour, while others are getting black; there are plenty of "orderly square beds of herbs," chiefly leeks, and two fountains, one running through the garden, and one under the pavement of the palace to a reservoir for the citizens. Ulysses, pausing to contemplate this scene, is described nearly in the same terms as Mercury pausing to contemplate the wilder meadow; and it is interesting to observe, that, in spite of all Homer's love of symmetry, the god's admiration is excited by the free fountains, wild violets, and wandering vine; but the mortal's, by the vines in rows, the leeks in beds, and the fountains in pipes.
Ulysses has, however, one touching reason for loving vines in rows. His father had given him fifty rows for himself, when he was a boy, with corn between them (just as it now grows in Italy). Proving his identity afterwards to his father, whom he finds at work in his garden, "with thick gloves on, to keep his hands from the thorns," he reminds him of these fifty rows of vines, and of the "thirteen pear-trees and ten apple-trees" which he had given him: and Laertes faints upon his neck.[90]
Ulysses has, however, one touching reason for loving vines in rows. His father had given him fifty rows for himself, when he was a boy, with corn between them (just as it now grows in Italy). Proving his identity afterwards to his father, whom he finds at work in his garden, "with thick gloves on, to keep his hands from the thorns," he reminds him of these fifty rows of vines, and of the "thirteen pear-trees and ten apple-trees" which he had given him: and Laertes faints upon his neck.[90]
If Ulysses had not been so much of a gardener, it might have been received as a sign of considerable feeling for landscape beauty, that, intending to pay the very highest possible compliment to the Princess Nausicaa (and having, indeed, the moment before gravely asked her whether she was a goddess or not), he says that he feels, at seeing her, exactly as he did when he saw the young palm tree growing at Apollo's shrine at Delos.[91] But I think the taste for trim hedges and upright trunks has its usual influence over him here also, and that he merely means to tell the princess that she is delightfully tall and straight.
If Ulysses had not been so much of a gardener, it might have been received as a sign of considerable feeling for landscape beauty, that, intending to pay the very highest possible compliment to the Princess Nausicaa (and having, indeed, the moment before gravely asked her whether she was a goddess or not), he says that he feels, at seeing her, exactly as he did when he saw the young palm tree growing at Apollo's shrine at Delos.[91] But I think the taste for trim hedges and upright trunks has its usual influence over him here also, and that he merely means to tell the princess that she is delightfully tall and straight.
The princess is, however, pleased by his address, and tells him to wait outside the town, till she can speak to her father about him. The spot to which she directs him is another ideal piece of landscape, composed of a "beautiful grove of aspen poplars, a fountain, and a meadow,"[92] near the road-side: in fact, as nearly as possible such a scene as meets the eye of the traveller every instant on the much-despised lines of road through lowland France; for instance, on the railway between Arras and Amiens;—scenes, to my mind, quite exquisite in the various grouping and grace of their innumerable poplar avenues, casting sweet, tremulous shadows over their level meadows and labyrinthine streams. We know that the princess means aspen poplars, because soon afterwards we find her fifty maid-servants at the palace, all spinning and in perpetual motion, compared to the "leaves of the tall poplar"; and it is with exquisite feeling that it is made afterwards[93] the chief tree in the groves of Proserpine; its light and quivering leafage having exactly the melancholy expression of fragility, faintness, and inconstancy which the ancients attributed to the disembodied spirit.[94] The likeness to the poplars by the streams of Amiens is more marked still in the Iliad, where the young Simois, struck by Ajax, falls to the earth "like an aspen that has grown in an irrigated meadow, smooth-trunked, the soft shoots springing from its top, which some coach-making man has cut down with his keen iron, that he may fit a wheel of it to a fair chariot, and it lies parching by the side of the stream."[95] It is sufficiently notable that Homer, living in mountainous and rocky countries, dwells thus delightedly on all the flat bits; and so I think invariably the inhabitants of mountain countries do, but the inhabitants of the plains do not, in any similar way, dwell delightedly on mountains. The Dutch painters are perfectly contented with their flat fields and pollards;[96] Rubens, though he had seen the Alps, usually composes his landscapes of a hayfield or two, plenty of pollards and willows, a distant spire, a Dutch house with a moat about it, a windmill, and a ditch. The Flemish sacred painters are the only ones who introduce mountains in the distance, as we shall see presently; but rather in a formal way than with any appearance of enjoyment. So Shakspere never speaks of mountains with the slightest joy, but only of lowland flowers, flat fields, and Warwickshire streams. And if we talk to the mountaineer, he will usually characterize his own country to us as a "pays affreux," or in some equivalent, perhaps even more violent, German term: but the lowland peasant does not think his country frightful; he either will have no ideas beyond it, or about it; or will think it a very perfect country, and be apt to regard any deviation from its general principle of flatness with extreme disfavour; as the Lincolnshire farmer in Alton Locke: "I'll shaw 'ee some'at like a field o' beans, I wool—none o' this here darned ups and downs o' hills, to shake a body's victuals out of his inwards—all so vlat as a barn's vloor, for vorty mile on end—there's the country to live in!"[97]
The princess is, however, pleased by his address, and tells him to wait outside the town, till she can speak to her father about him. The spot to which she directs him is another ideal piece of landscape, composed of a "beautiful grove of aspen poplars, a fountain, and a meadow,"[92] near the road-side: in fact, as nearly as possible such a scene as meets the eye of the traveller every instant on the much-despised lines of road through lowland France; for instance, on the railway between Arras and Amiens;—scenes, to my mind, quite exquisite in the various grouping and grace of their innumerable poplar avenues, casting sweet, tremulous shadows over their level meadows and labyrinthine streams. We know that the princess means aspen poplars, because soon afterwards we find her fifty maid-servants at the palace, all spinning and in perpetual motion, compared to the "leaves of the tall poplar"; and it is with exquisite feeling that it is made afterwards[93] the chief tree in the groves of Proserpine; its light and quivering leafage having exactly the melancholy expression of fragility, faintness, and inconstancy which the ancients attributed to the disembodied spirit.[94] The likeness to the poplars by the streams of Amiens is more marked still in the Iliad, where the young Simois, struck by Ajax, falls to the earth "like an aspen that has grown in an irrigated meadow, smooth-trunked, the soft shoots springing from its top, which some coach-making man has cut down with his keen iron, that he may fit a wheel of it to a fair chariot, and it lies parching by the side of the stream."[95] It is sufficiently notable that Homer, living in mountainous and rocky countries, dwells thus delightedly on all the flat bits; and so I think invariably the inhabitants of mountain countries do, but the inhabitants of the plains do not, in any similar way, dwell delightedly on mountains. The Dutch painters are perfectly contented with their flat fields and pollards;[96] Rubens, though he had seen the Alps, usually composes his landscapes of a hayfield or two, plenty of pollards and willows, a distant spire, a Dutch house with a moat about it, a windmill, and a ditch. The Flemish sacred painters are the only ones who introduce mountains in the distance, as we shall see presently; but rather in a formal way than with any appearance of enjoyment. So Shakspere never speaks of mountains with the slightest joy, but only of lowland flowers, flat fields, and Warwickshire streams. And if we talk to the mountaineer, he will usually characterize his own country to us as a "pays affreux," or in some equivalent, perhaps even more violent, German term: but the lowland peasant does not think his country frightful; he either will have no ideas beyond it, or about it; or will think it a very perfect country, and be apt to regard any deviation from its general principle of flatness with extreme disfavour; as the Lincolnshire farmer in Alton Locke: "I'll shaw 'ee some'at like a field o' beans, I wool—none o' this here darned ups and downs o' hills, to shake a body's victuals out of his inwards—all so vlat as a barn's vloor, for vorty mile on end—there's the country to live in!"[97]
I do not say whether this be altogether right (though certainly not wholly wrong), but it seems to me that there must be in the simple freshness and fruitfulness of level land, in its pale upright trees, and gentle lapse of silent streams, enough for the satisfaction of the human mind in general; and I so far agree with Homer, that, if I had to educate an artist to the full perception of the meaning of the word "gracefulness" in landscape, I should send him neither to Italy nor to Greece, but simply to those poplar groves between Arras and Amiens.
I’m not saying whether this is completely right (though it’s definitely not entirely wrong), but I believe there’s something in the simple freshness and productivity of flat land, with its tall, slender trees and the gentle flow of quiet streams, that can satisfy the human mind overall. I agree with Homer to some extent; if I had to teach an artist the true meaning of "gracefulness" in a landscape, I wouldn’t send them to Italy or Greece, but rather to the poplar groves between Arras and Amiens.
But to return more definitely to our Homeric landscape. When it is perfect, we have, as in the above instances, the foliage and meadows together; when imperfect, it is always either the foliage or the meadow; pre-eminently the meadow, or arable field. Thus, meadows of asphodel are prepared for the happier dead; and even Orion, a hunter among the mountains in his lifetime, pursues the ghosts of beasts in these asphodel meadows after death.[98] So the sirens sing in a meadow; [99] and throughout the Odyssey there is a general tendency to the depreciation of poor Ithaca, because it is rocky, and only fit for goats, and has "no meadows";[100] for which reason Telemachus refuses Atrides's present of horses, congratulating the Spartan king at the same time on ruling over a plain which has "plenty of lotus in it, and rushes," with corn and barley. Note this constant dwelling on the marsh plants, or, at least, those which grow in flat and well-irrigated land, or beside streams: when Scamander, for instance, is restrained by Vulcan, Homer says, very sorrowfully, that "all his lotus, and reeds, and rushes were burnt";[101] and thus Ulysses, after being shipwrecked and nearly drowned, and beaten about the sea for many days and nights, on raft and mast, at last getting ashore at the mouth of a large river, casts himself down first upon its rushes, and then, in thankfulness, kisses the "corn-giving land," as most opposed, in his heart, to the fruitless and devouring sea.[102]
But to return more definitely to our Homeric landscape. When it is perfect, we have, as in the above instances, the foliage and meadows together; when imperfect, it is always either the foliage or the meadow; pre-eminently the meadow, or arable field. Thus, meadows of asphodel are prepared for the happier dead; and even Orion, a hunter among the mountains in his lifetime, pursues the ghosts of beasts in these asphodel meadows after death.[98] So the sirens sing in a meadow; [99] and throughout the Odyssey there is a general tendency to the depreciation of poor Ithaca, because it is rocky, and only fit for goats, and has "no meadows";[100] for which reason Telemachus refuses Atrides's present of horses, congratulating the Spartan king at the same time on ruling over a plain which has "plenty of lotus in it, and rushes," with corn and barley. Note this constant dwelling on the marsh plants, or, at least, those which grow in flat and well-irrigated land, or beside streams: when Scamander, for instance, is restrained by Vulcan, Homer says, very sorrowfully, that "all his lotus, and reeds, and rushes were burnt";[101] and thus Ulysses, after being shipwrecked and nearly drowned, and beaten about the sea for many days and nights, on raft and mast, at last getting ashore at the mouth of a large river, casts himself down first upon its rushes, and then, in thankfulness, kisses the "corn-giving land," as most opposed, in his heart, to the fruitless and devouring sea.[102]
In this same passage, also, we find some peculiar expressions of the delight which the Greeks had in trees; for, when Ulysses first comes in sight of land, which gladdens him "as the reviving of a father from his sickness gladdens his children," it is not merely the sight of the land itself which gives him such pleasure, but of the "land and wood." Homer never throws away any words, at least in such a place as this; and what in another poet would have been merely the filling up of the deficient line with an otherwise useless word, is in him the expression of the general Greek sense, that land of any kind was in no wise grateful or acceptable till there was wood upon it (or corn; but the corn, in the flats, could not be seen so far as the black masses of forest on the hill sides), and that, as in being rushy and corn-giving, the low land, so in being woody, the high land was most grateful to the mind of the man who for days and nights had been wearied on the engulphing sea. And this general idea of wood and corn, as the types of the fatness of the whole earth, is beautifully marked in another place of the Odyssey,[103] where the sailors in a desert island, having no flour of corn to offer as a meat offering with their sacrifices, take the leaves of the trees, and scatter them over the burnt offering instead.
In this same passage, also, we find some peculiar expressions of the delight which the Greeks had in trees; for, when Ulysses first comes in sight of land, which gladdens him "as the reviving of a father from his sickness gladdens his children," it is not merely the sight of the land itself which gives him such pleasure, but of the "land and wood." Homer never throws away any words, at least in such a place as this; and what in another poet would have been merely the filling up of the deficient line with an otherwise useless word, is in him the expression of the general Greek sense, that land of any kind was in no wise grateful or acceptable till there was wood upon it (or corn; but the corn, in the flats, could not be seen so far as the black masses of forest on the hill sides), and that, as in being rushy and corn-giving, the low land, so in being woody, the high land was most grateful to the mind of the man who for days and nights had been wearied on the engulphing sea. And this general idea of wood and corn, as the types of the fatness of the whole earth, is beautifully marked in another place of the Odyssey,[103] where the sailors in a desert island, having no flour of corn to offer as a meat offering with their sacrifices, take the leaves of the trees, and scatter them over the burnt offering instead.
But still, every expression of the pleasure which Ulysses has in this landing and resting, contains uninterruptedly the reference to the utility and sensible pleasantness of all things, not to their beauty. After his first grateful kiss given to the corn-growing land, he considers immediately how he is to pass the night; for some minutes hesitating whether it will be best to expose himself to the misty chill from the river, or run the risk of wild beasts in the wood. He decides for the wood, and finds in it a bower formed by a sweet and a wild olive tree, interlacing their branches, or—perhaps more accurately translating Homer's intensely graphic expression—"changing their branches with each other" (it is very curious how often, in an entanglement of wood, one supposes the branches to belong to the wrong trees) and forming a roof penetrated by neither rain, sun, nor wind. Under this bower Ulysses collects the "vain (or frustrate) outpouring of the dead leaves"—another exquisite expression, used elsewhere of useless grief or shedding of tears;—and, having got enough together, makes his bed of them, and goes to sleep, having covered himself up with them, "as embers are covered up with ashes."[104]
But still, every expression of the pleasure which Ulysses has in this landing and resting, contains uninterruptedly the reference to the utility and sensible pleasantness of all things, not to their beauty. After his first grateful kiss given to the corn-growing land, he considers immediately how he is to pass the night; for some minutes hesitating whether it will be best to expose himself to the misty chill from the river, or run the risk of wild beasts in the wood. He decides for the wood, and finds in it a bower formed by a sweet and a wild olive tree, interlacing their branches, or—perhaps more accurately translating Homer's intensely graphic expression—"changing their branches with each other" (it is very curious how often, in an entanglement of wood, one supposes the branches to belong to the wrong trees) and forming a roof penetrated by neither rain, sun, nor wind. Under this bower Ulysses collects the "vain (or frustrate) outpouring of the dead leaves"—another exquisite expression, used elsewhere of useless grief or shedding of tears;—and, having got enough together, makes his bed of them, and goes to sleep, having covered himself up with them, "as embers are covered up with ashes."[104]
Nothing can possibly be more intensely possessive of the facts than this whole passage: the sense of utter deadness and emptiness, and frustrate fall in the leaves; of dormant life in the human body,—the fire, and heroism, and strength of it, lulled under the dead brown heap, as embers under ashes, and the knitting of interchanged and close strength of living boughs above. But there is not the smallest apparent sense of there being beauty elsewhere than in the human being. The wreathed wood is admired simply as being a perfect roof for it; the fallen leaves only as being a perfect bed for it; and there is literally no more excitement of emotion in Homer, as he describes them, nor does he expect us to be more excited or touched by hearing about them, than if he had been telling us how the chambermaid at the Bull aired the four-poster, and put on two extra blankets.
Nothing can be more intensely possessive of the facts than this whole passage: the feeling of complete deadness and emptiness, and frustrating fall of the leaves; of dormant life in the human body—its fire, heroism, and strength are lulled beneath the dead brown heap, like embers under ashes, while above, the intertwined and strong living branches knit together. Yet, there’s no real sense of beauty existing anywhere outside of the human being. The twisted wood is admired just for being a perfect cover for it; the fallen leaves only as a perfect resting place for it; and there’s literally no emotional thrill in Homer’s descriptions, nor does he expect us to feel any more excitement or connection to them than we would if he were simply telling us how the chambermaid at the Bull aired the four-poster and added two extra blankets.
Now, exactly this same contemplation of subservience to human use makes the Greek take some pleasure in rocks, when they assume one particular form, but one only—that of a cave. They are evidently quite frightful things to him under any other condition, and most of all if they are rough and jagged; but if smooth, looking "sculptured," like the sides of a ship, and forming a cave or shelter for him, he begins to think them endurable. Hence, associating the ideas of rich and sheltering wood, sea, becalmed and made useful as a port by protecting promontories of rock, and smoothed caves or grottoes in the rocks themselves, we get the pleasantest idea which the Greek could form of a landscape, next to a marsh with poplars in it; not, indeed, if possible, ever to be without these last; thus, in commending the Cyclops' country as one possessed of every perfection, Homer erst says: "They have soft marshy meadows near the sea, and good, rich, crumbling, ploughing-land, giving fine deep crops, and vines always giving fruit"; then, "a port so quiet, that they have no need of cables in it; and at the head of the port, a beautiful clear spring just under a cave, and aspen poplars all round it."[105]
Now, exactly this same contemplation of subservience to human use makes the Greek take some pleasure in rocks, when they assume one particular form, but one only—that of a cave. They are evidently quite frightful things to him under any other condition, and most of all if they are rough and jagged; but if smooth, looking "sculptured," like the sides of a ship, and forming a cave or shelter for him, he begins to think them endurable. Hence, associating the ideas of rich and sheltering wood, sea, becalmed and made useful as a port by protecting promontories of rock, and smoothed caves or grottoes in the rocks themselves, we get the pleasantest idea which the Greek could form of a landscape, next to a marsh with poplars in it; not, indeed, if possible, ever to be without these last; thus, in commending the Cyclops' country as one possessed of every perfection, Homer erst says: "They have soft marshy meadows near the sea, and good, rich, crumbling, ploughing-land, giving fine deep crops, and vines always giving fruit"; then, "a port so quiet, that they have no need of cables in it; and at the head of the port, a beautiful clear spring just under a cave, and aspen poplars all round it."[105]
This, it will be seen, is very nearly Homer's usual "ideal"; but, going into the middle of the island, Ulysses comes on a rougher and less agreeable bit, though still fulfilling certain required conditions of endurableness; a "cave shaded with laurels,"[106] which, having no poplars about it, is, however, meant to be somewhat frightful, and only fit to be inhabited by a Cyclops. So in the country of the Læstrygons, Homer, preparing his reader gradually for something very disagreeable, represents the rocks as bare and "exposed to the sun";[107] only with some smooth and slippery roads over them, by which the trucks bring down wood from the higher hills. Any one familiar with Swiss slopes of hills must remember how often he has descended, sometimes faster than was altogether intentional, by these same slippery woodman's truck roads.
This, it will be seen, is very nearly Homer's usual "ideal"; but, going into the middle of the island, Ulysses comes on a rougher and less agreeable bit, though still fulfilling certain required conditions of endurableness; a "cave shaded with laurels,"[106] which, having no poplars about it, is, however, meant to be somewhat frightful, and only fit to be inhabited by a Cyclops. So in the country of the Læstrygons, Homer, preparing his reader gradually for something very disagreeable, represents the rocks as bare and "exposed to the sun";[107] only with some smooth and slippery roads over them, by which the trucks bring down wood from the higher hills. Any one familiar with Swiss slopes of hills must remember how often he has descended, sometimes faster than was altogether intentional, by these same slippery woodman's truck roads.
And thus, in general, whenever the landscape is intended to be lovely, it verges towards the ploughed lands and poplars; or, at worst, to woody rocks; but, if intended to be painful, the rocks are bare and "sharp." This last epithet, constantly used by Homer for mountains, does not altogether correspond, in Greek, to the English term, nor is it intended merely to characterize the sharp mountain summits; for it never would be applied simply to the edge or point of a sword, but signifies rather "harsh," "bitter," or "painful," being applied habitually to fate, death, and in Odyssey xi. 333, to a halter; and, as expressive of general objectionableness and unpleasantness, to all high, dangerous, or peaked mountains, as the Maleian promontory (a much-dreaded one), the crest of Parnassus, the Tereian mountain, and a grim or untoward, though, by keeping off the force of the sea, protective, rock at the mouth of the Jardanus; as well as habitually to inaccessible or impregnable fortresses built on heights.
And so, generally speaking, whenever a landscape is meant to be beautiful, it leans towards cultivated fields and poplar trees; or, at worst, to woody rocks. But if the intention is to evoke discomfort, the rocks are bare and "sharp." This last term, frequently used by Homer for mountains, doesn't completely match the English word, nor is it only meant to describe the sharp peaks of mountains. It wouldn't be used just for the edge or point of a sword; instead, it conveys more the meanings of "harsh," "bitter," or "painful," and is often associated with fate, death, and in Odyssey xi. 333, with a halter. It also expresses general unpleasantness and is applied to all high, dangerous, or jagged mountains, such as the much-dreaded Maleian promontory, the peak of Parnassus, the Tereian mountain, and a foreboding, yet protective rock at the entrance of the Jardanus that keeps the sea at bay. Additionally, it regularly refers to inaccessible or impregnable fortresses built on high ground.
In all this I cannot too strongly mark the utter absence of any trace of the feeling for what we call the picturesque, and the constant dwelling of the writer's mind on what was available, pleasant, or useful: his ideas respecting all landscape being not uncharacteristially summed, finally, by Pallas herself; when, meeting Ulysses, who after his long wandering does not recognize his own country, and meaning to describe it as politely and soothingly as possible, she says:[108]—"This Ithaca of ours is, indeed, a rough country enough, and not good for driving in; but, still, things might be worse: it has plenty of corn, and good wine, and always rain, and soft nourishing dew; and it has good feeding for goats and oxen, and all manner of wood, and springs fit to drink at all the year round."
In all this I cannot too strongly mark the utter absence of any trace of the feeling for what we call the picturesque, and the constant dwelling of the writer's mind on what was available, pleasant, or useful: his ideas respecting all landscape being not uncharacteristially summed, finally, by Pallas herself; when, meeting Ulysses, who after his long wandering does not recognize his own country, and meaning to describe it as politely and soothingly as possible, she says:[108]—"This Ithaca of ours is, indeed, a rough country enough, and not good for driving in; but, still, things might be worse: it has plenty of corn, and good wine, and always rain, and soft nourishing dew; and it has good feeding for goats and oxen, and all manner of wood, and springs fit to drink at all the year round."
We shall see presently how the blundering, pseudo-picturesque, pseudo-classical minds of Claude and the Renaissance landscape-painters, wholly missing Homer's practical common sense, and equally incapable of feeling the quiet natural grace and sweetness of his asphodel meadows, tender aspen poplars, or running vines,—fastened on his ports and caves, as the only available features of his scenery; and appointed the type of "classical landscape" thenceforward to consist in a bay of insipid sea, and a rock with a hole through it.[109]
We shall see presently how the blundering, pseudo-picturesque, pseudo-classical minds of Claude and the Renaissance landscape-painters, wholly missing Homer's practical common sense, and equally incapable of feeling the quiet natural grace and sweetness of his asphodel meadows, tender aspen poplars, or running vines,—fastened on his ports and caves, as the only available features of his scenery; and appointed the type of "classical landscape" thenceforward to consist in a bay of insipid sea, and a rock with a hole through it.[109]
It may indeed be thought that I am assuming too hastily that this was the general view of the Greeks respecting landscape, because it was Homer's. But I believe the true mind of a nation, at any period, is always best ascertainable by examining that of its greatest men; and that simpler and truer results will be attainable for us by simply comparing Homer, Dante, and Walter Scott, than by attempting (what my limits must have rendered absurdly inadequate, and in which, also, both my time and knowledge must have failed me) an analysis of the landscape in the range of contemporary literature. All that I can do, is to state the general impression, which has been made upon me by my desultory reading, and to mark accurately the grounds for this impression in the works of the greatest men. Now it is quite true that in others of the Greeks, especially in Æschylus and Aristophanes, there is infinitely more of modern feeling, of pathetic fallacy, love of picturesque or beautiful form, and other such elements, than there is in Homer; but then these appear to me just the parts of them which were not Greek, the elements of their minds by which (as one division of the human race always must be with subsequent ones) they are connected with the mediævals and moderns. And without doubt, in his influence over future mankind, Homer is eminently the Greek of Greeks: if I were to associate any one with him it would be Herodotus, and I believe all I have said of the Homeric landscape will be found equally true of the Herodotean, as assuredly it will be of the Platonic;—the contempt, which Plato sometimes expresses by the mouth of Socrates, for the country in general, except so far as it is shady, and has cicadas and running streams to make pleasant noises in it, being almost ludicrous. But Homer is the great type, and the more notable one because of his influence on Virgil, and, through him, on Dante, and all the after ages: and, in like manner, if we can get the abstract of mediæval landscape out of Dante, it will serve us as well as if we had read all the songs of the troubadours, and help us to the farther changes in derivative temper, down to all modern time.
It might seem that I'm jumping to conclusions about the Greeks' views on landscape simply because it was Homer's perspective. However, I believe the true mindset of a nation, at any time, is best understood by looking at its most influential figures. It's easier and more accurate for us to compare Homer, Dante, and Walter Scott than to attempt an analysis of landscape in modern literature, which my limited time and knowledge would make inadequate. All I can do is share the general impression I’ve gained from my varied reading and identify the reasons for this impression based on the works of these great writers. It's true that other Greek writers, especially Aeschylus and Aristophanes, show much more modern sentiment, emotional depth, and appreciation for picturesque beauty than Homer does. But these aspects seem to me to be the parts of their work that weren’t distinctly Greek—elements that connect them, as one group of humanity inevitably does with another, to the medieval and modern eras. Clearly, Homer stands out as the quintessential Greek among Greeks. If I were to link anyone to him, it would be Herodotus, and I believe everything I've stated about Homer's landscape applies equally to Herodotus' work, and certainly to Plato's as well. The disdain that Plato sometimes expresses through Socrates for the countryside, except when it’s shady and filled with cicadas and babbling brooks, is almost comical. But Homer is the great archetype, particularly because of his influence on Virgil, and through him, on Dante and all the subsequent ages. Similarly, if we glean the essence of medieval landscape from Dante, it's just as valuable as if we had read all the troubadour songs, helping us understand the further changes in temperament up to modern times.
I think, therefore, the reader may safely accept the conclusions about Greek landscape which I have got for him out of Homer; and in these he will certainly perceive something very different from the usual imaginations we form of Greek feelings. We think of the Greeks as poetical, ideal, imaginative, in the way that a modern poet or novelist is; supposing that their thoughts about their mythology and world were as visionary and artificial as ours are: but I think the passages I have quoted show that it was not so, although it may be difficult for us to apprehend the strange minglings in them of the elements of faith, which, in our days, have been blended with other parts of human nature in a totally different guise. Perhaps the Greek mind may be best imagined by taking, as its groundwork, that of a good, conscientious, but illiterate Scotch Presbyterian Border farmer of a century or two back, having perfect faith in the bodily appearances of Satan and his imps; and in all kelpies, brownies, and fairies. Substitute for the indignant terrors in this man's mind, a general persuasion of the Divinity, more or less beneficent, yet faultful, of all these beings; that is to say, take away his belief in the demoniacal malignity of the fallen spiritual world, and lower, in the same degree, his conceptions of the angelical, retaining for him the same firm faith in both; keep his ideas about flowers and beautiful scenery much as they are,—his delight in regular ploughed land and meadows, and a neat garden (only with rows of gooseberry bushes instead of vines), being, in all probability, about accurately representative of the feelings of Ulysses; then, let the military spirit that is in him, glowing against the Border forager, or the foe of old Flodden and Chevy-Chase,[110] be made more principal, with a higher sense of nobleness in soldiership, not as a careless excitement, but a knightly duty; and increased by high cultivation of every personal quality, not of mere shaggy strength, but graceful strength, aided by a softer climate, and educated in all proper harmony of sight and sound: finally, instead of an informed Christian, suppose him to have only the patriarchal Jewish knowledge of the Deity, and even this obscured by tradition, but still thoroughly solemn and faithful, requiring his continual service as a priest of burnt sacrifice and meat offering; and I think we shall get a pretty close approximation to the vital being of a true old Greek; some slight difference still existing in a feeling which the Scotch farmer would have of a pleasantness in blue hills and running streams, wholly wanting in the Greek mind; and perhaps also some difference of views on the subjects of truth and honesty. But the main points, the easy, athletic, strongly logical and argumentative, yet fanciful and credulous, characters of mind, would be very similar in both; and the most serious change in the substance of the stuff among the modifications above suggested as necessary to turn the Scot into the Greek, is that effect of softer climate and surrounding luxury, inducing the practice of various forms of polished art,—the more polished, because the practical and realistic tendency of the Hellenic mind (if my interpretation of it be right) would quite prevent it from taking pleasure in any irregularities of form, or imitations of the weeds and wildnesses of that mountain nature with which it thought itself born to contend. In its utmost refinement of work, it sought eminently for orderliness; carried the principle of the leeks in squares, and fountains in pipes, perfectly out in its streets and temples; formalized whatever decoration it put into its minor architectural mouldings, and reserved its whole heart and power to represent the action of living men, or gods, though not unconscious, meanwhile, of
I think, therefore, the reader may safely accept the conclusions about Greek landscape which I have got for him out of Homer; and in these he will certainly perceive something very different from the usual imaginations we form of Greek feelings. We think of the Greeks as poetical, ideal, imaginative, in the way that a modern poet or novelist is; supposing that their thoughts about their mythology and world were as visionary and artificial as ours are: but I think the passages I have quoted show that it was not so, although it may be difficult for us to apprehend the strange minglings in them of the elements of faith, which, in our days, have been blended with other parts of human nature in a totally different guise. Perhaps the Greek mind may be best imagined by taking, as its groundwork, that of a good, conscientious, but illiterate Scotch Presbyterian Border farmer of a century or two back, having perfect faith in the bodily appearances of Satan and his imps; and in all kelpies, brownies, and fairies. Substitute for the indignant terrors in this man's mind, a general persuasion of the Divinity, more or less beneficent, yet faultful, of all these beings; that is to say, take away his belief in the demoniacal malignity of the fallen spiritual world, and lower, in the same degree, his conceptions of the angelical, retaining for him the same firm faith in both; keep his ideas about flowers and beautiful scenery much as they are,—his delight in regular ploughed land and meadows, and a neat garden (only with rows of gooseberry bushes instead of vines), being, in all probability, about accurately representative of the feelings of Ulysses; then, let the military spirit that is in him, glowing against the Border forager, or the foe of old Flodden and Chevy-Chase,[110] be made more principal, with a higher sense of nobleness in soldiership, not as a careless excitement, but a knightly duty; and increased by high cultivation of every personal quality, not of mere shaggy strength, but graceful strength, aided by a softer climate, and educated in all proper harmony of sight and sound: finally, instead of an informed Christian, suppose him to have only the patriarchal Jewish knowledge of the Deity, and even this obscured by tradition, but still thoroughly solemn and faithful, requiring his continual service as a priest of burnt sacrifice and meat offering; and I think we shall get a pretty close approximation to the vital being of a true old Greek; some slight difference still existing in a feeling which the Scotch farmer would have of a pleasantness in blue hills and running streams, wholly wanting in the Greek mind; and perhaps also some difference of views on the subjects of truth and honesty. But the main points, the easy, athletic, strongly logical and argumentative, yet fanciful and credulous, characters of mind, would be very similar in both; and the most serious change in the substance of the stuff among the modifications above suggested as necessary to turn the Scot into the Greek, is that effect of softer climate and surrounding luxury, inducing the practice of various forms of polished art,—the more polished, because the practical and realistic tendency of the Hellenic mind (if my interpretation of it be right) would quite prevent it from taking pleasure in any irregularities of form, or imitations of the weeds and wildnesses of that mountain nature with which it thought itself born to contend. In its utmost refinement of work, it sought eminently for orderliness; carried the principle of the leeks in squares, and fountains in pipes, perfectly out in its streets and temples; formalized whatever decoration it put into its minor architectural mouldings, and reserved its whole heart and power to represent the action of living men, or gods, though not unconscious, meanwhile, of
The simple, the sincere delight;
The straightforward, genuine joy;
The habitual scene of hill and dale;
The usual view of rolling hills and valleys;
The rural herds, the vernal gale;
The country herds, the spring breeze;
The tangled vetches' purple bloom;
The tangled vetch's purple bloom;
The fragrance of the bean's perfume,—
The scent of the bean's aroma,—
Theirs, theirs alone, who cultivate the soil,
Theirs, theirs alone, who work the land,
OF MODERN LANDSCAPE
VOLUME III, CHAPTER 16
We turn our eyes, therefore, as boldly and as quickly as may be, from these serene fields and skies of mediæval art, to the most characteristic examples of modern landscape. And, I believe, the first thing that will strike us, or that ought to strike us, is their cloudiness.
We boldly and quickly shift our focus from these peaceful fields and skies of medieval art to the most distinctive examples of modern landscape. And I believe the first thing that will catch our attention, or that should catch our attention, is their cloudiness.
Out of perfect light and motionless air, we find ourselves on a sudden brought under sombre skies, and into drifting wind; and, with fickle sunbeams flashing in our face, or utterly drenched with sweep of rain, we are reduced to track the changes of the shadows on the grass, or watch the rents of twilight through angry cloud. And we find that whereas all the pleasure of the mediæval was in stability, definiteness, and luminousness, we are expected to rejoice in darkness, and triumph in mutability; to lay the foundation of happiness in things which momentarily change or fade; and to expect the utmost satisfaction and instruction from what it is impossible to arrest, and difficult to comprehend.
Out of perfect light and still air, we suddenly find ourselves under dark skies and in swirling winds; with unpredictable sunbeams flashing in our faces or completely soaked by heavy rain, we're left to follow the changes of the shadows on the grass or observe the breaks of twilight through stormy clouds. We've realized that while all the enjoyment of the medieval era was in stability, definiteness, and luminousness, we are now expected to find joy in darkness and celebrate change; to build our happiness on things that shift or fade in an instant; and to seek the highest satisfaction and understanding from what we cannot grasp and find hard to comprehend.
We find, however, together with this general delight in breeze and darkness, much attention to the real form of clouds, and careful drawing of effects of mist; so that the appearance of objects, as seen through it, becomes a subject of science with us; and the faithful representation of that appearance is made of primal importance, under the name of aërial perspective. The aspects of sunset and sunrise, with all their attendant phenomena of cloud and mist, are watchfully delineated; and in ordinary daylight landscape, the sky is considered of so much importance, that a principal mass of foliage, or a whole foreground, is unhesitatingly thrown into shade merely to bring out the form of a white cloud. So that, if a general and characteristic name were needed for modern landscape art, none better could be invented than "the service of clouds."
We notice, alongside this general enjoyment of the breeze and darkness, a strong focus on the actual shape of clouds and a careful depiction of mist effects. As a result, the way we see objects through it becomes a subject of study for us, and accurately representing that appearance is of utmost importance, referred to as aerial perspective. The colors and phenomena of sunset and sunrise, along with their clouds and mist, are closely observed. In regular daylight landscapes, the sky is so significant that a main group of trees or an entire foreground can be put into shadow just to highlight the shape of a white cloud. Therefore, if we needed a fitting name for modern landscape art, "the service of clouds" would be the perfect choice.
And this name would, unfortunately, be characteristic of our art in more ways than one. In the last chapter, I said that all the Greeks spoke kindly about the clouds, except Aristophanes; and he, I am sorry to say (since his report is so unfavourable), is the only Greek who had studied them attentively. He tells us, first, that they are "great goddesses to idle men"; then, that they are "mistresses of disputings, and logic, and monstrosities, and noisy chattering"; declares that whoso believes in their divinity must first disbelieve in Jupiter, and place supreme power in the hands of an unknown god "Whirlwind"; and, finally, he displays their influence over the mind of one of their disciples, in his sudden desire "to speak ingeniously concerning smoke."[112]
And this name would, unfortunately, be characteristic of our art in more ways than one. In the last chapter, I said that all the Greeks spoke kindly about the clouds, except Aristophanes; and he, I am sorry to say (since his report is so unfavourable), is the only Greek who had studied them attentively. He tells us, first, that they are "great goddesses to idle men"; then, that they are "mistresses of disputings, and logic, and monstrosities, and noisy chattering"; declares that whoso believes in their divinity must first disbelieve in Jupiter, and place supreme power in the hands of an unknown god "Whirlwind"; and, finally, he displays their influence over the mind of one of their disciples, in his sudden desire "to speak ingeniously concerning smoke."[112]
There is, I fear, an infinite truth in this Aristophanic judgment applied to our modern cloud-worship. Assuredly, much of the love of mystery in our romances, our poetry, our art, and, above all, in our metaphysics, must come under that definition so long ago given by the great Greek, "speaking ingeniously concerning smoke." And much of the instinct, which, partially developed in painting, may be now seen throughout every mode of exertion of mind,—the easily encouraged doubt, easily excited curiosity, habitual agitation, and delight in the changing and the marvellous, as opposed to the old quiet serenity of social custom and religious faith,—is again deeply defined in those few words, the "dethroning of Jupiter," the "coronation of the whirlwind."
There is, I fear, an infinite truth in this Aristophanic judgment applied to our modern cloud-worship. Undoubtedly, a lot of the fascination with mystery in our stories, poetry, art, and especially in our philosophy, can be linked to that definition given long ago by the great Greek, "speaking ingeniously concerning smoke." And much of the instinct that has developed in painting can now be seen in every mental endeavor—the easily sparked doubt, readily awakened curiosity, constant agitation, and enjoyment of the changing and the amazing, as opposed to the old calmness of social customs and religious beliefs—is again deeply captured in those few words, the "dethroning of Jupiter," the "coronation of the whirlwind."
Nor of whirlwind merely, but also of darkness or ignorance respecting all stable facts. That darkening of the foreground to bring out the white cloud, is, in one aspect of it, a type of the subjection of all plain and positive fact, to what is uncertain and unintelligible. And, as we examine farther into the matter, we shall be struck by another great difference between the old and modern landscape, namely, that in the old no one ever thought of drawing anything but as well as he could. That might not be well, as we have seen in the case of rocks; but it was as well as he could, and always distinctly. Leaf, or stone, or animal, or man, it was equally drawn with care and clearness, and its essential characters shown. If it was an oak tree, the acorns were drawn; if a flint pebble, its veins were drawn; if an arm of the sea, its fish were drawn; if a group of figures, their faces and dresses were drawn—to the very last subtlety of expression and end of thread that could be got into the space, far off or near. But now our ingenuity is all "concerning smoke." Nothing is truly drawn but that; all else is vague, slight, imperfect; got with as little pains as possible. You examine your closest foreground, and find no leaves; your largest oak, and find no acorns; your human figure, and find a spot of red paint instead of a face; and in all this, again and again, the Aristophanic words come true, and the clouds seem to be "great goddesses to idle men."
Not just a whirlwind, but also darkness or ignorance about all solid facts. That darkening of the background to highlight the white cloud is, in one way, a sign of how all clear and definite facts are overshadowed by what is uncertain and confusing. As we delve further into this topic, we’ll notice another significant difference between old and modern landscapes: in the past, no one ever tried to draw anything other than as well as they could. It might not have been well done, as we saw with rocks, but it was done as well as they could, and always clearly. Whether it was a leaf, stone, animal, or person, it was consistently drawn with care and clarity, showing its essential features. If it was an oak tree, the acorns were depicted; if it was a flint pebble, its veins were shown; if it was a section of the sea, its fish were illustrated; if it was a group of figures, their faces and outfits were detailed to the very last nuance and thread fit into the space, whether far away or close up. But now our creativity is all "about smoke." Nothing else is truly depicted; everything else is vague, minimal, and incomplete, achieved with as little effort as possible. You look closely at the foreground and see no leaves; at your biggest oak, you find no acorns; at your human figure, you see a patch of red paint instead of a face; and again and again in all this, the words of Aristophanes ring true, as the clouds seem to be "great goddesses to idle men."
The next thing that will strike us, after this love of clouds, is the love of liberty. Whereas the mediæval was always shutting himself into castles, and behind fosses, and drawing brickwork neatly, and beds of flowers primly, our painters delight in getting to the open fields and moors; abhor all hedges and moats; never paint anything but free-growing trees, and rivers gliding "at their own sweet will"; eschew formality down to the smallest detail; break and displace the brickwork which the mediæval would have carefully cemented; leave unpruned the thickets he would have delicately trimmed; and, carrying the love of liberty even to license, and the love of wildness even to ruin, take pleasure at last in every aspect of age and desolation which emancipates the objects of nature from the government of men;—on the castle wall displacing its tapestry with ivy, and spreading, through the garden, the bramble for the rose.
The next thing that will stand out to us, after this love of clouds, is the love of freedom. While medieval people were always shutting themselves into castles, behind moats, neatly arranging bricks, and meticulously tending to flower beds, our painters enjoy getting out into the open fields and moors; they despise all hedges and moats; they never paint anything but wild-growing trees and rivers flowing "at their own sweet will"; they avoid formality in every detail; they disrupt the brickwork that the medieval would have carefully cemented; they leave the thickets unpruned that he would have delicately trimmed; and, taking their love of freedom even to excess, and their love of wildness even to decay, they ultimately find beauty in every aspect of aging and desolation that frees elements of nature from human control;—on the castle wall replacing its tapestry with ivy, and letting brambles spread through the garden instead of roses.
Connected with this love of liberty we find a singular manifestation of love of mountains, and see our painters traversing the wildest places of the globe in order to obtain subjects with craggy foregrounds and purple distances. Some few of them remain content with pollards and flat land; but these are always men of third-rate order; and the leading masters, while they do not reject the beauty of the low grounds, reserve their highest powers to paint Alpine peaks or Italian promontories. And it is eminently noticeable, also, that this pleasure in the mountains is never mingled with fear, or tempered by a spirit of meditation, as with the mediæval; but it is always free and fearless, brightly exhilarating, and wholly unreflective; so that the painter feels that his mountain foreground may be more consistently animated by a sportsman than a hermit; and our modern society in general goes to the mountains, not to fast, but to feast, and leaves their glaciers covered with chicken-bones and egg-shells.
Connected to this love of freedom, we find a unique expression of our love for mountains, as we see our artists exploring the most remote places on Earth to find subjects with jagged landscapes and distant purple hills. A few are satisfied with flatlands and pollards, but these are typically lesser talents; the top artists, while they appreciate the beauty of lowlands, dedicate their best efforts to painting Alpine peaks or Italian cliffs. It's also striking that this enjoyment of mountains is never mixed with fear or deep contemplation, as it was in medieval times; instead, it's always free and fearless, invigorating and completely unreflective. Thus, the painter feels that a mountain scene is more perfectly alive when depicted with a sportsman rather than a hermit; our modern society heads to the mountains not to fast but to indulge, leaving their glaciers littered with chicken bones and eggshells.
Connected with this want of any sense of solemnity in mountain scenery, is a general profanity of temper in regarding all the rest of nature; that is to say, a total absence of faith in the presence of any deity therein. Whereas the mediæval never painted a cloud, but with the purpose of placing an angel in it; and a Greek never entered a wood without expecting to meet a god in it; we should think the appearance of an angel in the cloud wholly unnatural, and should be seriously surprised by meeting a god anywhere. Our chief ideas about the wood are connected with poaching. We have no belief that the clouds contain more than so many inches of rain or hail, and from our ponds and ditches expect nothing more divine than ducks and watercresses.
Connected to this lack of any sense of seriousness in mountain landscapes is a general irreverence towards the rest of nature. In other words, there’s a complete absence of belief in any divine presence within it. While medieval people never painted a cloud without intending to include an angel, and Greeks never entered a forest without anticipating a god would be there, we would find the appearance of an angel in a cloud completely unnatural and would be genuinely astonished to encounter a god anywhere. Our main thoughts about the forest revolve around hunting illegally. We don’t believe that clouds hold anything more than a certain amount of rain or hail, and from our ponds and ditches, we expect nothing more divine than ducks and watercress.
Finally: connected with this profanity of temper is a strong tendency to deny the sacred element of colour, and make our boast in blackness. For though occasionally glaring or violent, modern colour is on the whole eminently sombre, tending continually to grey or brown, and by many of our best painters consistently falsified, with a confessed pride in what they call chaste or subdued tints; so that, whereas a mediæval paints his sky bright blue and his foreground bright green, gilds the towers of his castles, and clothes his figures with purple and white, we paint our sky grey, our foreground black, and our foliage brown, and think that enough is sacrificed to the sun in admitting the dangerous brightness of a scarlet cloak or a blue jacket.
Finally: connected to this bad attitude is a strong tendency to ignore the sacred element of color, instead bragging about our darkness. Even though modern colors can sometimes be vivid or intense, they are generally quite dull, constantly leaning towards grey or brown, and many of our best artists deliberately misrepresent colors, taking pride in what they consider elegant or muted hues. So, while a medieval artist paints his sky bright blue and his foreground bright green, gilds the towers of his castles, and dresses his figures in purple and white, we paint our sky grey, our foreground black, and our foliage brown, believing that allowing even a little bit of the sun's brightness in a scarlet cloak or a blue jacket is a significant sacrifice.
These, I believe, are the principal points which would strike us instantly, if we were to be brought suddenly into an exhibition of modern landscapes out of a room filled with mediæval work. It is evident that there are both evil and good in this change; but how much evil, or how much good, we can only estimate by considering, as in the former divisions of our inquiry, what are the real roots of the habits of mind which have caused them.
These are, I think, the key points that would stand out to us immediately if we were suddenly taken from a room filled with medieval art into an exhibition of modern landscapes. It's clear that this change has both positive and negative aspects, but we can only gauge how much of each by looking at what lies at the core of the mindsets that have led to these differences, as we did in earlier parts of our discussion.
And first, it is evident that the title "Dark Ages," given to the mediæval centuries, is, respecting art, wholly inapplicable. They were, on the contrary, the bright ages; ours are the dark ones. I do not mean metaphysically, but literally. They were the ages of gold; ours are the ages of umber.
And first, it’s clear that the title "Dark Ages" given to the medieval centuries is, in terms of art, completely inappropriate. They were, in fact, the bright ages; ours are the dark ones. I don’t mean that in a metaphysical way, but literally. They were the ages of gold; ours are the ages of brown.
This is partly mere mistake in us; we build brown brick walls, and wear brown coats, because we have been blunderingly taught to do so, and go on doing so mechanically. There is, however, also some cause for the change in our own tempers. On the whole, these are much sadder ages than the early ones; not sadder in a noble and deep way, but in a dim wearied way,—the way of ennui, and jaded intellect, and uncomfortableness of soul and body. The Middle Ages had their wars and agonies, but also intense delights. Their gold was dashed with blood; but ours is sprinkled with dust. Their life was inwoven with white and purple: ours is one seamless stuff of brown. Not that we are without apparent festivity, but festivity more or less forced, mistaken, embittered, incomplete—not of the heart. How wonderfully, since Shakspere's time, have we lost the power of laughing at bad jests! The very finish of our wit belies our gaiety.
This is partly a mistake on our part; we build brown brick walls and wear brown coats because we've been misguidedly taught to do so, and we keep doing it without thinking. However, there’s also a reason for the changes in our own attitudes. Overall, these times are much sadder than earlier ones; not sadder in a noble and profound way, but in a dim, exhausted way—characterized by boredom, weary minds, and discomfort of both soul and body. The Middle Ages had their wars and suffering, but also intense joys. Their gold was mixed with blood, while ours is covered in dust. Their lives were intertwined with bright colors; ours is just a dull shade of brown. It's not that we lack celebration, but it's a kind of celebration that feels forced, misguided, bitter, and incomplete—not heartfelt. How incredibly we've lost the ability to laugh at bad jokes since Shakespeare's time! The very sharpness of our wit contradicts our joy.
The profoundest reason of this darkness of heart is, I believe, our want of faith. There never yet was a generation of men (savage or civilized) who, taken as a body, so wofully fulfilled the words "having no hope, and without God in the world,"[113] as the present civilized European race. A Red Indian or Otaheitan savage has more sense of a Divine existence round him, or government over him, than the plurality of refined Londoners and Parisians: and those among us who may in some sense be said to believe, are divided almost without exception into two broad classes, Romanist and Puritan; who, but for the interference of the unbelieving portions of society, would, either of them, reduce the other sect as speedily as possible to ashes; the Romanist having always done so whenever he could, from the beginning of their separation, and the Puritan at this time holding himself in complacent expectation of the destruction of Rome by volcanic fire. Such division as this between persons nominally of one religion, that is to say, believing in the same God, and the same Revelation, cannot but become a stumbling-block of the gravest kind to all thoughtful and far-sighted men,—a stumbling-block which they can only surmount under the most favourable circumstances of early education. Hence, nearly all our powerful men in this age of the world are unbelievers; the best of them in doubt and misery; the worst in reckless defiance; the plurality, in plodding hesitation, doing, as well as they can, what practical work lies ready to their hands. Most of our scientific men are in this last class; our popular authors either set themselves definitely against all religious form, pleading for simple truth and benevolence (Thackeray, Dickens), or give themselves up to bitter and fruitless statement of facts (De Balzac), or surface-painting (Scott), or careless blasphemy, sad or smiling (Byron, Béranger). Our earnest poets and deepest thinkers are doubtful and indignant (Tennyson, Carlyle); one or two, anchored, indeed, but anxious or weeping (Wordsworth, Mrs. Browning); and of these two, the first is not so sure of his anchor, but that now and then it drags with him, even to make him cry out,—
The profoundest reason of this darkness of heart is, I believe, our want of faith. There never yet was a generation of men (savage or civilized) who, taken as a body, so wofully fulfilled the words "having no hope, and without God in the world,"[113] as the present civilized European race. A Red Indian or Otaheitan savage has more sense of a Divine existence round him, or government over him, than the plurality of refined Londoners and Parisians: and those among us who may in some sense be said to believe, are divided almost without exception into two broad classes, Romanist and Puritan; who, but for the interference of the unbelieving portions of society, would, either of them, reduce the other sect as speedily as possible to ashes; the Romanist having always done so whenever he could, from the beginning of their separation, and the Puritan at this time holding himself in complacent expectation of the destruction of Rome by volcanic fire. Such division as this between persons nominally of one religion, that is to say, believing in the same God, and the same Revelation, cannot but become a stumbling-block of the gravest kind to all thoughtful and far-sighted men,—a stumbling-block which they can only surmount under the most favourable circumstances of early education. Hence, nearly all our powerful men in this age of the world are unbelievers; the best of them in doubt and misery; the worst in reckless defiance; the plurality, in plodding hesitation, doing, as well as they can, what practical work lies ready to their hands. Most of our scientific men are in this last class; our popular authors either set themselves definitely against all religious form, pleading for simple truth and benevolence (Thackeray, Dickens), or give themselves up to bitter and fruitless statement of facts (De Balzac), or surface-painting (Scott), or careless blasphemy, sad or smiling (Byron, Béranger). Our earnest poets and deepest thinkers are doubtful and indignant (Tennyson, Carlyle); one or two, anchored, indeed, but anxious or weeping (Wordsworth, Mrs. Browning); and of these two, the first is not so sure of his anchor, but that now and then it drags with him, even to make him cry out,—
Great God, I had rather be
Great God, I would rather be
A Pagan suckled in some creed outworn;
A pagan raised in some outdated belief;
So might I, standing on this pleasant lea,
So could I, standing on this nice meadow,
In politics, religion is now a name; in art, a hypocrisy or affectation. Over German religious pictures the inscription, "See how Pious I am," can be read at a glance by any clear-sighted person. Over French and English religious pictures the inscription, "See how Impious I am," is equally legible. All sincere and modest art is, among us, profane.[115]
In politics, religion is now a name; in art, a hypocrisy or affectation. Over German religious pictures the inscription, "See how Pious I am," can be read at a glance by any clear-sighted person. Over French and English religious pictures the inscription, "See how Impious I am," is equally legible. All sincere and modest art is, among us, profane.[115]
This faithlessness operates among us according to our tempers, producing either sadness or levity, and being the ultimate root alike of our discontents and of our wantonnesses. It is marvellous how full of contradiction it makes us: we are first dull, and seek for wild and lonely places because we have no heart for the garden; presently we recover our spirits, and build an assembly room among the mountains, because we have no reverence for the desert. I do not know if there be game on Sinai, but I am always expecting to hear of some one's shooting over it.
This lack of faith affects us based on our moods, causing either sadness or lightheartedness, and is the root of both our frustrations and our recklessness. It's amazing how contradictory it makes us: first, we feel dull and look for wild, isolated places because we have no desire for the garden; then, we regain our spirits and create a gathering space in the mountains because we have no respect for the desert. I’m not sure if there’s game on Sinai, but I always expect to hear about someone hunting there.
There is, however, another, and a more innocent root of our delight in wild scenery.
There is, however, another and more innocent reason for our enjoyment of wild scenery.
All the Renaissance principles of art tended, as I have before often explained, to the setting Beauty above Truth, and seeking for it always at the expense of truth. And the proper punishment of such pursuit—the punishment which all the laws of the universe rendered inevitable—was, that those who thus pursued beauty should wholly lose sight of beauty. All the thinkers of the age, as we saw previously, declared that it did not exist. The age seconded their efforts, and banished beauty, so far as human effort could succeed in doing so, from the face of the earth, and the form of man. To powder the hair, to patch the cheek, to hoop the body, to buckle the foot, were all part and parcel of the same system which reduced streets to brick walls, and pictures to brown stains. One desert of Ugliness was extended before the eyes of mankind; and their pursuit of the beautiful, so recklessly continued, received unexpected consummation in high-heeled shoes and periwigs,—Gower Street, and Gaspar Poussin.[116]
All the Renaissance principles of art tended, as I have before often explained, to the setting Beauty above Truth, and seeking for it always at the expense of truth. And the proper punishment of such pursuit—the punishment which all the laws of the universe rendered inevitable—was, that those who thus pursued beauty should wholly lose sight of beauty. All the thinkers of the age, as we saw previously, declared that it did not exist. The age seconded their efforts, and banished beauty, so far as human effort could succeed in doing so, from the face of the earth, and the form of man. To powder the hair, to patch the cheek, to hoop the body, to buckle the foot, were all part and parcel of the same system which reduced streets to brick walls, and pictures to brown stains. One desert of Ugliness was extended before the eyes of mankind; and their pursuit of the beautiful, so recklessly continued, received unexpected consummation in high-heeled shoes and periwigs,—Gower Street, and Gaspar Poussin.[116]
Reaction from this state was inevitable, if any true life was left in the races of mankind; and, accordingly, though still forced, by rule and fashion, to the producing and wearing all that is ugly, men steal out, half-ashamed of themselves for doing so, to the fields and mountains; and, finding among these the colour, and liberty, and variety, and power, which are for ever grateful to them, delight in these to an extent never before known; rejoice in all the wildest shattering of the mountain side, as an opposition to Gower Street, gaze in a rapt manner at sunsets and sunrises, to see there the blue, and gold, and purple, which glow for them no longer on knight's armour or temple porch; and gather with care out of the fields, into their blotted herbaria, the flowers which the five orders of architecture have banished from their doors and casements.
Reaction from this state was inevitable, if there was any real life left in humanity; and so, though still forced, by rules and trends, to create and wear everything that looks ugly, people sneak out, half-ashamed of themselves for doing it, to the fields and mountains; and, finding among these the color, freedom, variety, and power that always bring them joy, they delight in these like never before; they celebrate all the wild destruction of the mountains as a contrast to Gower Street, gaze in awe at sunsets and sunrises, to see the blue, gold, and purple that no longer glow on knight's armor or temple porches; and carefully gather flowers from the fields into their scrappy herbaria, the ones that the five orders of architecture have banished from their doors and windows.
The absence of care for personal beauty, which is another great characteristic of the age, adds to this feeling in a twofold way: first, by turning all reverent thoughts away from human nature; and making us think of men as ridiculous or ugly creatures, getting through the world as well as they can, and spoiling it in doing so; not ruling it in a kingly way and crowning all its loveliness. In the Middle Ages hardly anything but vice could be caricatured, because virtue was always visibly and personally noble: now virtue itself is apt to inhabit such poor human bodies, that no aspect of it is invulnerable to jest; and for all fairness we have to seek to the flowers, for all sublimity, to the hills.
The lack of care for personal appearance, which is a significant trait of this era, contributes to this feeling in two main ways: first, it distracts us from appreciating human nature; and second, it leads us to see people as ridiculous or unattractive beings, just trying to get by and ruining the world in the process; not ruling it gracefully and enhancing its beauty. In the Middle Ages, vice was the only thing that could be mocked because virtue was always clearly noble and admirable: now, virtue often resides in such ordinary human forms that it's hard to find any aspect of it that escapes ridicule; and for all beauty, we have to look to flowers, and for all greatness, to the hills.
The same want of care operates, in another way, by lowering the standard of health, increasing the susceptibility to nervous or sentimental impressions, and thus adding to the other powers of nature over us whatever charm may be felt in her fostering the melancholy fancies of brooding idleness.
The same lack of care affects us in another way by lowering our health standards, making us more sensitive to nervous or emotional influences, and thus adding to nature's other effects on us with whatever appeal might be felt in her nurturing the sad thoughts of idleness.
It is not, however, only to existing inanimate nature that our want of beauty in person and dress has driven us. The imagination of it, as it was seen in our ancestors, haunts us continually; and while we yield to the present fashions, or act in accordance with the dullest modern principles of economy and utility, we look fondly back to the manners of the ages of chivalry, and delight in painting, to the fancy, the fashions we pretend to despise, and the splendours we think it wise to abandon. The furniture and personages of our romance are sought, when the writer desires to please most easily, in the centuries which we profess to have surpassed in everything; the art which takes us into the present times is considered as both daring and degraded; and while the weakest words please us, and are regarded as poetry, which recall the manners of our forefathers, or of strangers, it is only as familiar and vulgar that we accept the description of our own.
It’s not just the lack of beauty in our looks and clothing that has affected us; it’s also the ideal we see in our ancestors that constantly lingers in our minds. While we follow current trends or stick to the most boring modern ideas of practicality and utility, we still happily recall the ways of the chivalric ages. We enjoy imagining the styles we claim to dislike and the grandeur we think we should let go of. When writers want to please us easily, they often turn to characters and settings from centuries we say we’ve outgrown in every way. Contemporary art is viewed as both bold and lowbrow; meanwhile, the weakest words that remind us of our predecessors or others are celebrated as poetry, but our own experiences are seen as common and ordinary.
In this we are wholly different from all the races that preceded us. All other nations have regarded their ancestors with reverence as saints or heroes; but have nevertheless thought their own deeds and ways of life the fitting subjects for their arts of painting or of verse. We, on the contrary, regard our ancestors as foolish and wicked, but yet find our chief artistic pleasures in descriptions of their ways of life.
In this, we are completely different from all the races that came before us. Other nations have looked up to their ancestors as saints or heroes, but still thought their own actions and lifestyles were the right subjects for their art, whether in painting or poetry. We, on the other hand, see our ancestors as foolish and wicked, yet we find our main artistic enjoyment in portraying their ways of life.
The Greeks and mediævals honoured, but did not imitate their forefathers; we imitate, but do not honour.
The Greeks and medieval people respected their ancestors but didn’t copy them; we copy, but we don’t respect.
With this romantic love of beauty, forced to seek in history, and in external nature, the satisfaction it cannot find in ordinary life, we mingle a more rational passion, the due and just result of newly awakened powers of attention. Whatever may first lead us to the scrutiny of natural objects, that scrutiny never fails of its reward. Unquestionably they are intended to be regarded by us with both reverence and delight; and every hour we give to them renders their beauty more apparent, and their interest more engrossing. Natural science—which can hardly be considered to have existed before modern times—rendering our knowledge fruitful in accumulation, and exquisite in accuracy, has acted for good or evil, according to the temper of the mind which received it; and though it has hardened the faithlessness of the dull and proud, has shown new grounds for reverence to hearts which were thoughtful and humble. The neglect of the art of war, while it has somewhat weakened and deformed the body,[117] has given us leisure and opportunity for studies to which, before, time and space were equally wanting; lives which once were early wasted on the battle-field are now passed usefully in the study; nations which exhausted themselves in annual warfare now dispute with each other the discovery of new planets; and the serene philosopher dissects the plants, and analyzes the dust, of lands which were of old only traversed by the knight in hasty march, or by the borderer in heedless rapine.
With this romantic love of beauty, forced to seek in history, and in external nature, the satisfaction it cannot find in ordinary life, we mingle a more rational passion, the due and just result of newly awakened powers of attention. Whatever may first lead us to the scrutiny of natural objects, that scrutiny never fails of its reward. Unquestionably they are intended to be regarded by us with both reverence and delight; and every hour we give to them renders their beauty more apparent, and their interest more engrossing. Natural science—which can hardly be considered to have existed before modern times—rendering our knowledge fruitful in accumulation, and exquisite in accuracy, has acted for good or evil, according to the temper of the mind which received it; and though it has hardened the faithlessness of the dull and proud, has shown new grounds for reverence to hearts which were thoughtful and humble. The neglect of the art of war, while it has somewhat weakened and deformed the body,[117] has given us leisure and opportunity for studies to which, before, time and space were equally wanting; lives which once were early wasted on the battle-field are now passed usefully in the study; nations which exhausted themselves in annual warfare now dispute with each other the discovery of new planets; and the serene philosopher dissects the plants, and analyzes the dust, of lands which were of old only traversed by the knight in hasty march, or by the borderer in heedless rapine.
The elements of progress and decline being thus strangely mingled in the modern mind, we might beforehand anticipate that one of the notable characters of our art would be its inconsistency; that efforts would be made in every direction, and arrested by every conceivable cause and manner of failure; that in all we did, it would become next to impossible to distinguish accurately the grounds for praise or for regret; that all previous canons of practice and methods of thought would be gradually overthrown, and criticism continually defied by successes which no one had expected, and sentiments which no one could define.
The elements of progress and decline are strangely mixed in the modern mindset, so we can expect that one of the defining traits of our art will be its inconsistency. Efforts will be made in every direction, only to be halted by all sorts of reasons and types of failure. In everything we do, it will be nearly impossible to clearly identify the reasons for praise or regret. All previous standards of practice and ways of thinking will gradually be overturned, and criticism will constantly be challenged by successes that surprise everyone and feelings that no one can articulate.
Accordingly, while, in our inquiries into Greek and mediæval art, I was able to describe, in general terms, what all men did or felt, I find now many characters in many men; some, it seems to me, founded on the inferior and evanescent principles of modernism, on its recklessness, impatience, or faithlessness; others founded on its science, its new affection for nature, its love of openness and liberty. And among all these characters, good or evil, I see that some, remaining to us from old or transitional periods, do not properly belong to us, and will soon fade away, and others, though not yet distinctly developed, are yet properly our own, and likely to grow forward into greater strength.
As a result, while in my studies of Greek and medieval art, I could generally describe what everyone experienced or felt, I now see many different traits in many people; some seem to be based on the lesser and fleeting aspects of modernism, like its recklessness, impatience, or lack of faith; others are rooted in its science, its newfound appreciation for nature, and its love of openness and freedom. Among all these traits, whether good or bad, I notice that some, which we inherited from older or transitional times, don’t truly belong to us and will soon disappear, while others, even if not fully formed yet, are genuinely ours and have the potential to grow stronger.
For instance: our reprobation of bright colour is, I think, for the most part, mere affectation, and must soon be done away with. Vulgarity, dulness, or impiety, will indeed always express themselves through art in brown and grey, as in Rembrandt, Caravaggio, and Salvator; but we are not wholly vulgar, dull, or impious; nor, as moderns, are we necessarily obliged to continue so in any wise. Our greatest men, whether sad or gay, still delight, like the great men of all ages, in brilliant hues. The colouring of Scott and Byron is full and pure; that of Keats and Tennyson rich even to excess. Our practical failures in colouring are merely the necessary consequences of our prolonged want of practice during the periods of Renaissance affectation and ignorance; and the only durable difference between old and modern colouring, is the acceptance of certain hues, by the modern, which please him by expressing that melancholy peculiar to his more reflective or sentimental character, and the greater variety of them necessary to express his greater science.
For example, our rejection of bright colors is, I believe, mostly just pretentiousness, and it should be eliminated soon. Vulgarity, dullness, or a lack of piety will always come through in art in shades of brown and gray, as seen in Rembrandt, Caravaggio, and Salvator; but we aren't completely vulgar, dull, or impious; nor are we as modern individuals required to remain that way. Our greatest artists, whether they are serious or cheerful, still enjoy, like the great artists of all times, vibrant colors. The writing of Scott and Byron is full and clear; that of Keats and Tennyson is rich almost to a fault. Our practical shortcomings in color are simply the results of the long periods of neglect during the times of Renaissance pretense and ignorance; and the only lasting difference between old and modern color use is the acceptance of certain shades by modern artists, which appeal to them by conveying the melancholy unique to their more introspective or sentimental nature, along with the greater variety required to express their advanced understanding.
Again: if we ever become wise enough to dress consistently and gracefully, to make health a principal object in education, and to render our streets beautiful with art, the external charm of past history will in great measure disappear. There is no essential reason, because we live after the fatal seventeenth century, that we should never again be able to confess interest in sculpture, or see brightness in embroidery; nor, because now we choose to make the night deadly with our pleasures, and the day with our labours, prolonging the dance till dawn, and the toil to twilight, that we should never again learn how rightly to employ the sacred trusts of strength, beauty, and time. Whatever external charm attaches itself to the past, would then be seen in proper subordination to the brightness of present life; and the elements of romance would exist, in the earlier ages, only in the attraction which must generally belong to whatever is unfamiliar; in the reverence which a noble nation always pays to its ancestors; and in the enchanted light which races, like individuals, must perceive in looking back to the days of their childhood.
Again: if we ever get wise enough to dress consistently and elegantly, to prioritize health in education, and to beautify our streets with art, the external appeal of historical charm will largely fade away. Just because we live after the unfortunate seventeenth century doesn’t mean we can’t appreciate sculpture or see beauty in embroidery again. Nor does our choice to fill the night with reckless fun and the day with hard work, extending our parties until dawn and our labor until dusk, mean we can’t learn how to properly use the precious gifts of strength, beauty, and time. Any external charm tied to the past would then be viewed as secondary to the vibrancy of our current lives; and the elements of romance from earlier times would exist mainly in the allure of the unfamiliar, the respect a great nation shows to its ancestors, and the magical light that cultures, like individuals, see when they look back at their childhood days.
Again: the peculiar levity with which natural scenery Is regarded by a large number of modern minds cannot be considered as entirely characteristic of the age, inasmuch as it never can belong to its greatest intellects. Men of any high mental power must be serious, whether in ancient or modern days: a certain degree of reverence for fair scenery is found in all our great writers without exception,—even the one who has made us laugh oftenest, taking us to the valley of Chamouni, and to the sea beach, there to give peace after suffering, and change revenge into pity.[118] It is only the dull, the uneducated, or the worldly, whom it is painful to meet on the hillsides; and levity, as a ruling character, cannot be ascribed to the whole nation, but only to its holiday-making apprentices, and its House of Commons.
Again: the peculiar levity with which natural scenery Is regarded by a large number of modern minds cannot be considered as entirely characteristic of the age, inasmuch as it never can belong to its greatest intellects. Men of any high mental power must be serious, whether in ancient or modern days: a certain degree of reverence for fair scenery is found in all our great writers without exception,—even the one who has made us laugh oftenest, taking us to the valley of Chamouni, and to the sea beach, there to give peace after suffering, and change revenge into pity.[118] It is only the dull, the uneducated, or the worldly, whom it is painful to meet on the hillsides; and levity, as a ruling character, cannot be ascribed to the whole nation, but only to its holiday-making apprentices, and its House of Commons.
We need not, therefore, expect to find any single poet or painter representing the entire group of powers, weaknesses, and inconsistent instincts which govern or confuse our modern life. But we may expect that in the man who seems to be given by Providence as the type of the age (as Homer and Dante were given, as the types of classical and mediæval mind), we shall find whatever is fruitful and substantial to be completely present, together with those of our weaknesses, which are indeed nationally characteristic, and compatible with general greatness of mind, just as the weak love of fences, and dislike of mountains, were found compatible with Dante's greatness in other respects.
We shouldn't expect to find a single poet or painter who captures the whole range of strengths, weaknesses, and conflicting instincts that shape or confuse modern life. However, we can expect that in the person who seems to be provided by fate as the representative of our time (similar to how Homer and Dante represented the classical and medieval intellect), we'll find everything that is valuable and meaningful, along with our weaknesses that are indeed characteristic of our nation and compatible with overall greatness of mind, just as Dante's lesser appreciation for boundaries and his aversion to mountains coexisted with his greatness in other areas.
Farther: as the admiration of mankind is found, in our times, to have in great part passed from men to mountains, and from human emotion to natural phenomena, we may anticipate that the great strength of art will also be warped in this direction; with this notable result for us, that whereas the greatest painters or painter of classical and mediæval periods, being wholly devoted to the representation of humanity, furnished us with but little to examine in landscape, the greatest painters or painter of modern times will in all probability be devoted to landscape principally: and farther, because in representing human emotion words surpass painting, but in representing natural scenery painting surpasses words, we may anticipate also that the painter and poet (for convenience' sake I here use the words in opposition) will somewhat change their relations of rank in illustrating the mind of the age; that the painter will become of more importance, the poet of less; and that the relations between the men who are the types and firstfruits of the age in word and work,—namely, Scott and Turner,—will be, in many curious respects, different from those between Homer and Phidias, or Dante and Giotto.[119]
Farther: as the admiration of mankind is found, in our times, to have in great part passed from men to mountains, and from human emotion to natural phenomena, we may anticipate that the great strength of art will also be warped in this direction; with this notable result for us, that whereas the greatest painters or painter of classical and mediæval periods, being wholly devoted to the representation of humanity, furnished us with but little to examine in landscape, the greatest painters or painter of modern times will in all probability be devoted to landscape principally: and farther, because in representing human emotion words surpass painting, but in representing natural scenery painting surpasses words, we may anticipate also that the painter and poet (for convenience' sake I here use the words in opposition) will somewhat change their relations of rank in illustrating the mind of the age; that the painter will become of more importance, the poet of less; and that the relations between the men who are the types and firstfruits of the age in word and work,—namely, Scott and Turner,—will be, in many curious respects, different from those between Homer and Phidias, or Dante and Giotto.[119]
THE TWO BOYHOODS
VOLUME V, PART 9, CHAPTER 9
Born half-way between the mountains and the sea—that young George of Castelfranco—of the Brave Castle:—Stout George they called him, George of Georges, so goodly a boy he was—Giorgione.[120]
Born half-way between the mountains and the sea—that young George of Castelfranco—of the Brave Castle:—Stout George they called him, George of Georges, so goodly a boy he was—Giorgione.[120]
Have you ever thought what a world his eyes opened on—fair, searching eyes of youth? What a world of mighty life, from those mountain roots to the shore;—of loveliest life, when he went down, yet so young, to the marble city—and became himself as a fiery heart to it?
Have you ever considered the world that unfolded before his fair, keen youthful eyes? What a world of incredible life, from the mountains to the shore;—of beautiful life, when he descended, so young, to the marble city—and became like a burning heart to it?
A city of marble, did I say? nay, rather a golden city, paved with emerald. For truly, every pinnacle and turret glanced or glowed, overlaid with gold, or bossed with jasper. Beneath, the unsullied sea drew in deep breathing, to and fro, its eddies of green wave. Deep-hearted, majestic, terrible as the sea,—the men of Venice moved in sway of power and war; pure as her pillars of alabaster, stood her mothers and maidens; from foot to brow, all noble, walked her knights; the low bronzed gleaming of sea-rusted armour shot angrily under their blood-red mantle-folds. Fearless, faithful, patient, impenetrable, implacable,—every word a fate—sate her senate. In hope and honour, lulled by flowing of wave around their isles of sacred sand, each with his name written and the cross graved at his side, lay her dead. A wonderful piece of world. Rather, itself a world. It lay along the face of the waters, no larger, as its captains saw it from their masts at evening, than a bar of sunset that could not pass away; but for its power, it must have seemed to them as if they were sailing in the expanse of heaven, and this a great planet, whose orient edge widened through ether. A world from which all ignoble care and petty thoughts were banished, with all the common and poor elements of life. No foulness, nor tumult, in those tremulous streets, that filled, or fell, beneath the moon; but rippled music of majestic change, or thrilling silence. No weak walls could rise above them; no low-roofed cottage, nor straw-built shed. Only the strength as of rock, and the finished setting of stones most precious. And around them, far as the eye could reach, still the soft moving of stainless waters, proudly pure; as not the flower, so neither the thorn nor the thistle, could grow in the glancing fields. Ethereal strength of Alps, dreamlike, vanishing in high procession beyond the Torcellan shore; blue islands of Paduan hills, poised in the golden west. Above, free winds and fiery clouds ranging at their will;—brightness out of the north, and balm from the south, and the stars of the evening and morning clear in the limitless light of arched heaven and circling sea.
A city of marble, did I say? No, it’s more like a golden city, paved with emerald. Every peak and turret sparkled or shone, covered in gold or decorated with jasper. Below, the clear sea breathed deeply, its green waves rolling in and out. Deep-hearted, majestic, and as fierce as the sea, the people of Venice moved with power and in wartime; pure as her alabaster pillars, her mothers and daughters stood; noble in stature, her knights walked with pride; the dull shine of sea-rusted armor flashed angrily beneath their blood-red cloaks. Fearless, loyal, patient, unyielding—each word a destiny—sat her senate. In hope and honor, lulled by the gentle waves around their sacred sandy islands, each with his name engraved and the cross etched by his side, lay her dead. A remarkable place in the world. More like, it was a world in itself. It lay along the water’s edge, as small as it appeared to its captains from their masts at sunset; but because of its power, it must have felt to them like they were sailing in the vastness of heaven, and this was a great planet, whose glowing edge spread through the sky. A world where all unworthy worries and trivial thoughts were cast away, free from the common and mundane aspects of life. No dirt or chaos in those trembling streets, whether they were filled or empty under the moon; just the sound of majestic change or a thrilling silence. No weak walls could rise above them; no low-roofed cottages or straw shacks. Only the strength of rock and the exquisite arrangement of the most precious stones. And around them, as far as the eye could see, the soft movement of pristine waters, proudly pure; neither flower nor thorn nor thistle could grow in those shimmering fields. The ethereal strength of the Alps, dreamlike, disappearing in a high procession beyond the Torcellan shore; blue islands of Paduan hills, balanced in the golden west. Above, free winds and fiery clouds roamed as they pleased; brightness from the north and warmth from the south, with stars of evening and morning clear in the endless light of the arching sky and surrounding sea.
Such was Giorgione's school—such Titian's home.
Such was Giorgione's school—such was Titian's home.
Near the south-west corner of Covent Garden, a square brick pit or well is formed by a close-set block of houses, to the back windows of which it admits a few rays of light. Access to the bottom of it is obtained out of Maiden Lane, through a low archway and an iron gate; and if you stand long enough under the archway to accustom your eyes to the darkness you may see on the left hand a narrow door, which formerly gave quiet access to a respectable barber's shop, of which the front window, looking into Maiden Lane, is still extant, filled, in this year (1860), with a row of bottles, connected, in some defunct manner, with a brewer's business. A more fashionable neighbourhood, it is said, eighty years ago than now—never certainly a cheerful one—wherein a boy being born on St. George's day, 1775, began soon after to take interest in the world of Covent Garden, and put to service such spectacles of life as it afforded.
At the southwest corner of Covent Garden, there's a square brick pit or well created by a tightly packed row of houses, which lets a few beams of light into the back windows. You can get to the bottom from Maiden Lane, through a low archway and an iron gate; and if you stand under the archway long enough for your eyes to adjust to the darkness, you might notice a narrow door on the left. This door used to lead to a nice barber shop, and the front window, still facing Maiden Lane, remains there filled, in this year (1860), with a lineup of bottles that are somehow related to a brewery. It’s said that this area was more fashionable eighty years ago than it is now—though it was never really a cheerful place—where a boy born on St. George's Day, 1775, began to take an interest in the world of Covent Garden and made use of the spectacles of life it offered.
No knights to be seen there, nor, I imagine, many beautiful ladies; their costume at least disadvantageous, depending much on incumbency of hat and feather, and short waists; the majesty of men founded similarly on shoebuckles and wigs;—impressive enough when Reynolds will do his best for it; but not suggestive of much ideal delight to a boy.
No knights to be seen there, nor, I guess, many beautiful ladies; their outfits are definitely a drawback, relying heavily on hats and feathers, and short waists; the grandeur of men similarly based on shoe buckles and wigs;—pretty impressive when Reynolds gives it his all; but not really suggesting much ideal joy to a boy.
"Bello ovile dov' io dormii agnello";[121] of things beautiful, besides men and women, dusty sunbeams up or down the street on summer mornings; deep furrowed cabbage-leaves at the greengrocer's; magnificence of oranges in wheelbarrows round the corner; and Thames' shore within three minutes' race.
"Bello ovile dov' io dormii agnello";[121] of things beautiful, besides men and women, dusty sunbeams up or down the street on summer mornings; deep furrowed cabbage-leaves at the greengrocer's; magnificence of oranges in wheelbarrows round the corner; and Thames' shore within three minutes' race.
None of these things very glorious; the best, however, that England, it seems, was then able to provide for a boy of gift: who, such as they are, loves them—never, indeed, forgets them. The short waists modify to the last his visions of Greek ideal. His foregrounds had always a succulent cluster or two of greengrocery at the corners. Enchanted oranges gleam in Covent Gardens of the Hesperides; and great ships go to pieces in order to scatter chests of them on the waves.[122] That mist of early sunbeams in the London dawn crosses, many and many a time, the clearness of Italian air; and by Thames' shore, with its stranded barges and glidings of red sail, dearer to us than Lucerne lake or Venetian lagoon,—by Thames' shore we will die.
None of these things very glorious; the best, however, that England, it seems, was then able to provide for a boy of gift: who, such as they are, loves them—never, indeed, forgets them. The short waists modify to the last his visions of Greek ideal. His foregrounds had always a succulent cluster or two of greengrocery at the corners. Enchanted oranges gleam in Covent Gardens of the Hesperides; and great ships go to pieces in order to scatter chests of them on the waves.[122] That mist of early sunbeams in the London dawn crosses, many and many a time, the clearness of Italian air; and by Thames' shore, with its stranded barges and glidings of red sail, dearer to us than Lucerne lake or Venetian lagoon,—by Thames' shore we will die.
With such circumstance round him in youth, let us note what necessary effects followed upon the boy. I assume him to have had Giorgione's sensibility (and more than Giorgione's, if that be possible) to colour and form. I tell you farther, and this fact you may receive trustfully, that his sensibility to human affection and distress was no less keen than even his sense for natural beauty—heart-sight deep as eyesight.
With such circumstances surrounding him in his youth, let's note the necessary effects that followed on the boy. I assume he had Giorgione's sensitivity (and perhaps even more than Giorgione, if that's possible) to color and shape. I can also tell you, and you can trust this fact, that his sensitivity to human affection and suffering was just as sharp as his appreciation for natural beauty—his heart's insight as deep as his eyesight.
Consequently, he attaches himself with the faithfullest child-love to everything that bears an image of the place he was born in. No matter how ugly it is,—has it anything about it like Maiden Lane, or like Thames' shore? If so, it shall be painted for their sake. Hence, to the very close of life, Turner could endure ugliness which no one else, of the same sensibility, would have borne with for an instant. Dead brick walls, blank square windows, old clothes, market-womanly types of humanity—anything fishy and muddy, like Billingsgate or Hungerford Market, had great attraction for him; black barges, patched sails, and every possible condition of fog.
As a result, he clings to everything that resembles the place where he was born with a child-like affection. No matter how unattractive it is—if it reminds him of Maiden Lane or the Thames shore, then it will be painted for their sake. Therefore, even into old age, Turner could tolerate ugliness that no one else with similar sensibilities would have put up with for even a moment. Dull brick walls, plain square windows, worn clothes, and the rough types of people you see at markets—anything gritty and muddy, like Billingsgate or Hungerford Market, captured his interest; black barges, tattered sails, and every kind of foggy condition.
You will find these tolerations and affections guiding or sustaining him to the last hour of his life; the notablest of all such endurances being that of dirt. No Venetian ever draws anything foul; but Turner devoted picture after picture to the illustration of effects of dinginess, smoke, soot, dust, and dusty texture; old sides of boats, weedy roadside vegetation, dunghills, straw-yards, and all the soilings and stains of every common labour.
You’ll see these tolerances and feelings supporting him until the very end of his life; the most remarkable of all these endurance examples is his fascination with dirt. No Venetian ever portrays anything dirty, but Turner dedicated painting after painting to show the effects of grime, smoke, soot, dust, and dusty textures; old sides of boats, weedy roadside plants, garbage heaps, straw yards, and all the messes and stains from everyday work.
And more than this, he not only could endure, but enjoyed and looked for litter, like Covent Garden wreck after the market. His pictures are often full of it, from side to side; their foregrounds differ from all others in the natural way that things have of lying about in them. Even his richest vegetation, in ideal work, is confused; and he delights in shingle, debris, and heaps of fallen stones. The last words he ever spoke to me about a picture were in gentle exultation about his St. Gothard: "that litter of stones which I endeavoured to represent."
And even more than that, he not only could handle it, but actually enjoyed it and looked for litter, like the mess left after the market at Covent Garden. His paintings are often filled with it, from one side to the other; their foregrounds are different from all others in the natural way things are just left there. Even his most vibrant vegetation, in his ideal works, is a bit chaotic; and he takes joy in pebbles, debris, and piles of fallen stones. The last thing he ever said to me about a painting was with gentle excitement about his St. Gothard: "that litter of stones which I tried to depict."
The second great result of this Covent Garden training was understanding of and regard for the poor, whom the Venetians, we saw, despised; whom, contrarily, Turner loved, and more than loved—understood. He got no romantic sight of them, but an infallible one, as he prowled about the end of his lane, watching night effects in the wintry streets; nor sight of the poor alone, but of the poor in direct relations with the rich. He knew, in good and evil, what both classes thought of, and how they dwelt with, each other.
The second major outcome of this Covent Garden training was an understanding of and respect for the poor, whom the Venetians, as we observed, looked down on; whom, on the other hand, Turner loved, and loved deeply—he understood them. He didn’t have a romanticized view of them, but a clear and accurate one, as he wandered around the end of his lane, observing the night scenes in the chilly streets; and not just witnessing the poor, but also the interactions between the poor and the rich. He was aware, in both good and bad ways, of what each class thought of one another and how they lived alongside each other.
Reynolds and Gainsborough, bred in country villages, learned there the country boy's reverential theory of "the squire," and kept it. They painted the squire and the squire's lady as centres of the movements of the universe, to the end of their lives. But Turner perceived the younger squire in other aspects about his lane, occurring prominently in its night scenery, as a dark figure, or one of two, against the moonlight. He saw also the working of city commerce, from endless warehouse, towering over Thames, to the back shop in the lane, with its stale herrings—highly interesting these last; one of his father's best friends, whom he often afterwards visited affectionately at Bristol, being a fishmonger and glue-boiler; which gives us a friendly turn of mind towards herring-fishing, whaling, Calais poissardes, and many other of our choicest subjects in after life; all this being connected with that mysterious forest below London Bridge on one side;—and, on the other, with these masses of human power and national wealth which weigh upon us, at Covent Garden here, with strange compression, and crush us into narrow Hand Court.
Reynolds and Gainsborough, raised in rural villages, absorbed the country boy's respectful view of "the squire" and maintained it throughout their lives. They depicted the squire and his lady as the focal points of the universe's activities until the end of their days. However, Turner viewed the younger squire through a different lens, often finding him in the night scenes of his lane, appearing as a dark figure or one of two against the moonlight. He also recognized the hustle of city commerce, from the towering warehouses overlooking the Thames to the back shop in the lane with its old herring—especially interesting since one of his father's closest friends, whom he later visited affectionately in Bristol, was a fishmonger and glue-boiler. This gave him an enduring fondness for herring fishing, whaling, Calais fishwomen, and many other favorite subjects later in life. All this was tied to that mysterious forest below London Bridge on one side, and on the other, to the immense human energy and national wealth that weighs upon us here in Covent Garden, compressing us strangely and pressing us into the narrow Hand Court.
"That mysterious forest below London Bridge"—better for the boy than wood of pine, or grove of myrtle. How he must have tormented the watermen, beseeching them to let him crouch anywhere in the bows, quiet as a log, so only that he might get floated down there among the ships, and round and round the ships, and with the ships, and by the ships, and under the ships, staring, and clambering;—these the only quite beautiful things he can see in all the world, except the sky; but these, when the sun is on their sails, filling or falling, endlessly disordered by sway of tide and stress of anchorage, beautiful unspeakably; which ships also are inhabited by glorious creatures—red-faced sailors, with pipes, appearing over the gunwales, true knights, over their castle parapets—the most angelic beings in the whole compass of London world. And Trafalgar happening long before we can draw ships, we, nevertheless, coax all current stories out of the wounded sailors, do our best at present to show Nelson's funeral streaming up the Thames; and vow that Trafalgar shall have its tribute of memory some day. Which, accordingly, is accomplished—once, with all our might, for its death; twice, with all our might, for its victory; thrice, in pensive farewell to the old Téméraire, and, with it, to that order of things.[123]
"That mysterious forest below London Bridge"—better for the boy than wood of pine, or grove of myrtle. How he must have tormented the watermen, beseeching them to let him crouch anywhere in the bows, quiet as a log, so only that he might get floated down there among the ships, and round and round the ships, and with the ships, and by the ships, and under the ships, staring, and clambering;—these the only quite beautiful things he can see in all the world, except the sky; but these, when the sun is on their sails, filling or falling, endlessly disordered by sway of tide and stress of anchorage, beautiful unspeakably; which ships also are inhabited by glorious creatures—red-faced sailors, with pipes, appearing over the gunwales, true knights, over their castle parapets—the most angelic beings in the whole compass of London world. And Trafalgar happening long before we can draw ships, we, nevertheless, coax all current stories out of the wounded sailors, do our best at present to show Nelson's funeral streaming up the Thames; and vow that Trafalgar shall have its tribute of memory some day. Which, accordingly, is accomplished—once, with all our might, for its death; twice, with all our might, for its victory; thrice, in pensive farewell to the old Téméraire, and, with it, to that order of things.[123]
Now this fond companying with sailors must have divided his time, it appears to me, pretty equally between Covent Garden and Wapping (allowing for incidental excursions to Chelsea on one side, and Greenwich on the other), which time he would spend pleasantly, but not magnificently, being limited in pocket-money, and leading a kind of "Poor-Jack" life on the river.
Now, it seems that his time spent hanging out with sailors was pretty much split between Covent Garden and Wapping (with occasional trips to Chelsea on one side and Greenwich on the other). He enjoyed his time, but it wasn’t extravagant, as he had limited spending money and lived a sort of "Poor-Jack" life on the river.
In some respects, no life could be better for a lad. But it was not calculated to make his ear fine to the niceties of language, nor form his moralities on an entirely regular standard. Picking up his first scraps of vigorous English chiefly at Deptford and in the markets, and his first ideas of female tenderness and beauty among nymphs of the barge and the barrow,—another boy might, perhaps, have become what people usually term "vulgar." But the original make and frame of Turner's mind being not vulgar, but as nearly as possible a combination of the minds of Keats and Dante, joining capricious waywardness, and intense openness to every fine pleasure of sense, and hot defiance of formal precedent, with a quite infinite tenderness, generosity, and desire of justice and truth—this kind of mind did not become vulgar, but very tolerant of vulgarity, even fond of it in some forms; and on the outside, visibly infected by it, deeply enough; the curious result, in its combination of elements, being to most people wholly incomprehensible. It was as if a cable had been woven of blood-crimson silk, and then tarred on the outside. People handled it, and the tar came off on their hands; red gleams were seen through the black, underneath, at the places where it had been strained. Was it ochre?—said the world—or red lead?
In some ways, life couldn't be better for a boy. But it didn’t really help him develop a refined ear for language or establish a consistent sense of morality. He picked up his first bits of strong English mainly at Deptford and in the markets, along with his initial ideas of female warmth and beauty from the women at the barge and the market—another boy might have turned out what people usually call "vulgar." However, Turner's mind was not vulgar; it was more like a blend of Keats and Dante, combining whimsical unpredictability, a deep appreciation for sensory pleasures, and a fierce rejection of traditional norms, with boundless tenderness, generosity, and a quest for justice and truth. This kind of mind didn’t become vulgar but was very accepting of it, even fond of certain aspects; and on the outside, it was visibly marked by it, quite significantly. The curious result of all these elements left most people baffled. It was as if a cable was made from red silk and then coated in tar. People would touch it, and the tar would come off on their hands; red glimmers could be seen through the black at the points where it had been strained. Was it ochre?—the world wondered—or red lead?
Schooled thus in manners, literature, and general moral principles at Chelsea and Wapping, we have finally to inquire concerning the most important point of all. We have seen the principal differences between this boy and Giorgione, as respects sight of the beautiful, understanding of poverty, of commerce, and of order of battle; then follows another cause of difference in our training—not slight,—the aspect of religion, namely, in the neighbourhood of Covent Garden. I say the aspect; for that was all the lad could judge by. Disposed, for the most part, to learn chiefly by his eyes, in this special matter he finds there is really no other way of learning. His father had taught him "to lay one penny upon another." Of mother's teaching, we hear of none; of parish pastoral teaching, the reader may guess how much.
Trained in manners, literature, and general moral principles at Chelsea and Wapping, we must now consider the most crucial point. We've observed the main differences between this boy and Giorgione regarding their appreciation of beauty, understanding of poverty, commerce, and battlefield strategy. Another significant aspect of our differing upbringing is the role of religion, specifically in the Covent Garden area. I refer to the role of religion because that’s all the boy could assess. Primarily inclined to learn through observation, he realizes that there’s really no other way to learn about this. His father taught him "to stack one penny on top of another." We hear nothing about his mother's teachings, and as for pastoral guidance from the parish, readers can imagine how much that amounted to.
I chose Giorgione rather than Veronese to help me in carrying out this parallel; because I do not find in Giorgione's work any of the early Venetian monarchist element. He seems to me to have belonged more to an abstract contemplative school. I may be wrong in this; it is no matter;—suppose it were so, and that he came down to Venice somewhat recusant, or insentient, concerning the usual priestly doctrines of his day,—how would the Venetian religion, from an outer intellectual standing-point, have looked to him?
I chose Giorgione over Veronese to help me with this comparison because I don’t see any of the early Venetian monarchist themes in Giorgione's work. To me, he seems more aligned with an abstract, contemplative style. I could be mistaken about this; it doesn't really matter. Let's say that's the case, and that he arrived in Venice somewhat resistant or indifferent to the typical priestly teachings of his time—how would the Venetian religion have appeared to him from an outside intellectual perspective?
He would have seen it to be a religion indisputably powerful in human affairs; often very harmfully so; sometimes devouring widows' houses,[124] and consuming the strongest and fairest from among the young; freezing into merciless bigotry the policy of the old: also, on the other hand, animating national courage, and raising souls, otherwise sordid, into heroism: on the whole, always a real and great power; served with daily sacrifice of gold, time, and thought; putting forth its claims, if hypocritically, at least in bold hypocrisy, not waiving any atom of them in doubt or fear; and, assuredly, in large measure, sincere, believing in itself, and believed: a goodly system, moreover, in aspect; gorgeous, harmonious, mysterious;—a thing which had either to be obeyed or combated, but could not be scorned. A religion towering over all the city—many-buttressed—luminous in marble stateliness, as the dome of our Lady of Safety[125] shines over the sea; many-voiced also, giving, over all the eastern seas, to the sentinel his watchword, to the soldier his war-cry; and, on the lips of all who died for Venice, shaping the whisper of death.
He would have seen it to be a religion indisputably powerful in human affairs; often very harmfully so; sometimes devouring widows' houses,[124] and consuming the strongest and fairest from among the young; freezing into merciless bigotry the policy of the old: also, on the other hand, animating national courage, and raising souls, otherwise sordid, into heroism: on the whole, always a real and great power; served with daily sacrifice of gold, time, and thought; putting forth its claims, if hypocritically, at least in bold hypocrisy, not waiving any atom of them in doubt or fear; and, assuredly, in large measure, sincere, believing in itself, and believed: a goodly system, moreover, in aspect; gorgeous, harmonious, mysterious;—a thing which had either to be obeyed or combated, but could not be scorned. A religion towering over all the city—many-buttressed—luminous in marble stateliness, as the dome of our Lady of Safety[125] shines over the sea; many-voiced also, giving, over all the eastern seas, to the sentinel his watchword, to the soldier his war-cry; and, on the lips of all who died for Venice, shaping the whisper of death.
I suppose the boy Turner to have regarded the religion of his city also from an external intellectual standing-point.
I think the boy Turner saw the religion of his city as something to be analyzed from an outside, intellectual perspective.
What did he see in Maiden Lane?
What did he see on Maiden Lane?
Let not the reader be offended with me; I am willing to let him describe, at his own pleasure, what Turner saw there; but to me, it seems to have been this. A religion maintained occasionally, even the whole length of the lane, at point of constable's staff; but, at other times, placed under the custody of the beadle, within certain black and unstately iron railings of St. Paul's, Covent Garden. Among the wheelbarrows and over the vegetables, no perceptible dominance of religion; in the narrow, disquieted streets, none; in the tongues, deeds, daily ways of Maiden Lane, little. Some honesty, indeed, and English industry, and kindness of heart, and general idea of justice; but faith, of any national kind, shut up from one Sunday to the next, not artistically beautiful even in those Sabbatical exhibitions; its paraphernalia being chiefly of high pews, heavy elocution, and cold grimness of behaviour.
Let the reader not be upset with me; I’m open to letting him express, however he likes, what Turner observed there; but to me, it seems to be this. A religion that is occasionally upheld, even along the entire length of the lane, by the threat of a constable's staff; but at other times, it is placed under the watch of the beadle, confined within certain black and unimpressive iron railings of St. Paul's, Covent Garden. Among the wheelbarrows and over the vegetables, there’s no noticeable presence of religion; in the narrow, troubled streets, none; in the conversations, actions, daily habits of Maiden Lane, very little. Some honesty, indeed, and English hard work, and kindness, and a general sense of justice; but faith, of any national sort, is locked away from one Sunday to the next, not artistically beautiful even in those Sunday demonstrations; its trappings mainly consist of tall pews, heavy oratory, and cold, stern behavior.
What chiaroscuro belongs to it—(dependent mostly on candlelight),—we will, however, draw considerately; no goodliness of escutcheon, nor other respectability being omitted, and the best of their results confessed, a meek old woman and a child being let into a pew, for whom the reading by candlelight will be beneficial.[126]
What chiaroscuro belongs to it—(dependent mostly on candlelight),—we will, however, draw considerately; no goodliness of escutcheon, nor other respectability being omitted, and the best of their results confessed, a meek old woman and a child being let into a pew, for whom the reading by candlelight will be beneficial.[126]
For the rest, this religion seems to him discreditable—discredited—not believing in itself; putting forth its authority in a cowardly way, watching how far it might be tolerated, continually shrinking, disclaiming, fencing, finessing; divided against itself, not by stormy rents, but by thin fissures, and splittings of plaster from the walls. Not to be either obeyed, or combated, by an ignorant, yet clear-sighted youth: only to be scorned. And scorned not one whit the less, though also the dome dedicated to it looms high over distant winding of the Thames; as St. Mark's campanile rose, for goodly landmark, over mirage of lagoon. For St. Mark ruled over life; the Saint of London over death; St. Mark over St. Mark's Place, but St. Paul over St. Paul's Churchyard.
For the rest, this religion seems discreditable to him—it's been discredited, not believing in itself; it asserts its authority in a cowardly way, testing how much it can be tolerated, constantly retreating, denying, dodging, and evading; divided within itself, not by major conflicts, but by thin cracks and splits in the walls. It’s neither something to obey nor fight against for an ignorant yet clear-sighted youth: it’s just something to be scorned. And it’s scorned all the more, even though the dome dedicated to it looms high over the winding Thames, much like St. Mark's campanile stood tall as a good landmark over the mirage of the lagoon. St. Mark had dominance over life; the Saint of London had dominion over death; St. Mark ruled over St. Mark's Place, while St. Paul ruled over St. Paul's Churchyard.
Under these influences pass away the first reflective hours of life, with such conclusion as they can reach. In consequence of a fit of illness, he was taken—I cannot ascertain in what year[127]—to live with an aunt, at Brentford; and here, I believe, received some schooling, which he seems to have snatched vigorously; getting knowledge, at least by translation, of the more picturesque classical authors, which he turned presently to use, as we shall see. Hence also, walks about Putney and Twickenham in the summer time acquainted him with the look of English meadow-ground in its restricted states of paddock and park; and with some round-headed appearances of trees, and stately entrances to houses of mark: the avenue at Bushy, and the iron gates and carved pillars of Hampton,[128] impressing him apparently with great awe and admiration; so that in after life his little country house is,—of all places in the world,—at Twickenham! Of swans and reedy shores he now learns the soft motion and the green mystery, in a way not to be forgotten.
Under these influences pass away the first reflective hours of life, with such conclusion as they can reach. In consequence of a fit of illness, he was taken—I cannot ascertain in what year[127]—to live with an aunt, at Brentford; and here, I believe, received some schooling, which he seems to have snatched vigorously; getting knowledge, at least by translation, of the more picturesque classical authors, which he turned presently to use, as we shall see. Hence also, walks about Putney and Twickenham in the summer time acquainted him with the look of English meadow-ground in its restricted states of paddock and park; and with some round-headed appearances of trees, and stately entrances to houses of mark: the avenue at Bushy, and the iron gates and carved pillars of Hampton,[128] impressing him apparently with great awe and admiration; so that in after life his little country house is,—of all places in the world,—at Twickenham! Of swans and reedy shores he now learns the soft motion and the green mystery, in a way not to be forgotten.
And at last fortune wills that the lad's true life shall begin; and one summer's evening, after various wonderful stage-coach experiences on the north road, which gave him a love of stage-coaches ever after, he finds himself sitting alone among the Yorkshire hills.[129] For the first time, the silence of Nature round him, her freedom sealed to him, her glory opened to him. Peace at last; no roll of cart-wheel, nor mutter of sullen voices in the back shop; but curlew-cry in space of heaven, and welling of bell-toned streamlet by its shadowy rock. Freedom at last. Dead-wall, dark railing, fenced field, gated garden, all passed away like the dream, of a prisoner; and behold, far as foot or eye can race or range, the moor, and cloud. Loveliness at last. It is here, then, among these deserted vales! Not among men. Those pale, poverty-struck, or cruel faces;—that multitudinous, marred humanity—are not the only things that God has made. Here is something He has made which no one has marred. Pride of purple rocks, and river pools of blue, and tender wilderness of glittering trees, and misty lights of evening on immeasurable hills.
And at last fortune wills that the lad's true life shall begin; and one summer's evening, after various wonderful stage-coach experiences on the north road, which gave him a love of stage-coaches ever after, he finds himself sitting alone among the Yorkshire hills.[129] For the first time, the silence of Nature round him, her freedom sealed to him, her glory opened to him. Peace at last; no roll of cart-wheel, nor mutter of sullen voices in the back shop; but curlew-cry in space of heaven, and welling of bell-toned streamlet by its shadowy rock. Freedom at last. Dead-wall, dark railing, fenced field, gated garden, all passed away like the dream, of a prisoner; and behold, far as foot or eye can race or range, the moor, and cloud. Loveliness at last. It is here, then, among these deserted vales! Not among men. Those pale, poverty-struck, or cruel faces;—that multitudinous, marred humanity—are not the only things that God has made. Here is something He has made which no one has marred. Pride of purple rocks, and river pools of blue, and tender wilderness of glittering trees, and misty lights of evening on immeasurable hills.
Beauty, and freedom, and peace; and yet another teacher, graver than these. Sound preaching at last here, in Kirkstall crypt, concerning fate and life. Here, where the dark pool reflects the chancel pillars, and the cattle lie in unhindered rest, the soft sunshine on their dappled bodies, instead of priests' vestments; their white furry hair ruffled a little, fitfully, by the evening wind deep-scented from the meadow thyme.
Beauty, freedom, and peace; and yet another teacher, more serious than these. There’s powerful preaching happening here, in the Kirkstall crypt, about fate and life. Here, where the dark pool reflects the chancel pillars, and the cattle rest peacefully, their dappled bodies warmed by the soft sunlight instead of being dressed in priests' garments; their white, furry hair gently ruffled now and then by the evening wind, rich with the scent of meadow thyme.
Consider deeply the import to him of this, his first sight of ruin, and compare it with the effect of the architecture that was around Giorgione. There were indeed aged buildings, at Venice, in his time, but none in decay. All ruin was removed, and its place filled as quickly as in our London; but filled always by architecture loftier and more wonderful than that whose place it took, the boy himself happy to work upon the walls of it; so that the idea of the passing away of the strength of men and beauty of their works never could occur to him sternly. Brighter and brighter the cities of Italy had been rising and broadening on hill and plain, for three hundred years. He saw only strength and immortality, could not but paint both; conceived the form of man as deathless, calm with power, and fiery with life.
Consider deeply what this moment meant for him, seeing ruin for the first time, and compare it to the effect of the architecture surrounding Giorgione. There were indeed old buildings in Venice during his time, but none in decay. All signs of ruin were quickly removed, and their places were filled as quickly as in our London; but they were always replaced by architecture that was taller and more amazing than what came before, with the boy himself happy to work on its walls. So, the idea that the strength of people and the beauty of their creations could fade away never occurred to him in a serious way. For three hundred years, the cities of Italy had been growing brighter and more expansive on hills and plains. He saw only strength and immortality, and he couldn't help but paint both; he imagined the human form as eternal, calm with power, and vibrant with life.
Turner saw the exact reverse of this. In the present work of men, meanness, aimlessness, unsightliness: thin-walled, lath-divided, narrow-garreted houses of clay; booths of a darksome Vanity Fair, busily base.
Turner saw the complete opposite of this. In the work of men today, there's pettiness, lack of purpose, and ugliness: flimsy, partitioned, cramped houses made of clay; stalls from a gloomy Vanity Fair, bustling with lowly activities.
But on Whitby Hill, and by Bolton Brook,[130] remained traces of other handiwork. Men who could build had been there; and who also had wrought, not merely for their own days. But to what purpose? Strong faith, and steady hands, and patient souls—can this, then, be all you have left! this the sum of your doing on the earth!—a nest whence the night-owl may whimper to the brook, and a ribbed skeleton of consumed arches, looming above the bleak banks of mist, from its cliff to the sea?
But on Whitby Hill, and by Bolton Brook,[130] remained traces of other handiwork. Men who could build had been there; and who also had wrought, not merely for their own days. But to what purpose? Strong faith, and steady hands, and patient souls—can this, then, be all you have left! this the sum of your doing on the earth!—a nest whence the night-owl may whimper to the brook, and a ribbed skeleton of consumed arches, looming above the bleak banks of mist, from its cliff to the sea?
As the strength of men to Giorgione, to Turner their weakness and vileness, were alone visible. They themselves, unworthy or ephemeral; their work, despicable, or decayed. In the Venetian's eyes, all beauty depended on man's presence and pride; in Turner's, on the solitude he had left, and the humiliation he had suffered.
As Giorgione highlighted the strength of men, Turner showcased their weaknesses and flaws. The men themselves were insignificant or fleeting; their work was contemptible or worn out. To the Venetian, all beauty relied on man's presence and confidence; to Turner, it rested on the solitude he had departed from and the humiliation he had endured.
And thus the fate and issue of all his work were determined at once. He must be a painter of the strength of nature, there was no beauty elsewhere than in that; he must paint also the labour and sorrow and passing away of men: this was the great human truth visible to him.
And so, the outcome of all his work was decided in an instant. He had to be a painter capturing the power of nature; there was no beauty to be found anywhere else. He also needed to portray the struggles, pain, and mortality of people: this was the profound human truth he saw.
Their labour, their sorrow, and their death. Mark the three. Labour; by sea and land, in field and city, at forge and furnace, helm and plough. No pastoral indolence nor classic pride shall stand between him and the troubling of the world; still less between him and the toil of his country,—blind, tormented, unwearied, marvellous England.
Their work, their pain, and their deaths. Note the three. Work; by sea and land, in fields and cities, at the forge and furnace, with helm and plow. No idle luxury or classical pride will stand between him and the challenges of the world; even less will it stand between him and the hard work of his country—blind, tormented, tireless, incredible England.
Also their Sorrow; Ruin of all their glorious work, passing away of their thoughts and their honour, mirage of pleasure, FALLACY OF HOPE; gathering of weed on temple step; gaining of wave on deserted strand; weeping of the mother for the children, desolate by her breathless first-born in the streets of the city,[131] desolate by her last sons slain, among the beasts of the field.[132]
Also their Sorrow; Ruin of all their glorious work, passing away of their thoughts and their honour, mirage of pleasure, FALLACY OF HOPE; gathering of weed on temple step; gaining of wave on deserted strand; weeping of the mother for the children, desolate by her breathless first-born in the streets of the city,[131] desolate by her last sons slain, among the beasts of the field.[132]
And their Death. That old Greek question again;—yet unanswered. The unconquerable spectre still flitting among the forest trees at twilight; rising ribbed out of the sea-sand;—white, a strange Aphrodite,—out of the sea-foam; stretching its grey, cloven wings among the clouds; turning the light of their sunsets into blood. This has to be looked upon, and in a more terrible shape than ever Salvator or Dürer saw it.[133] The wreck of one guilty country does not infer the ruin of all countries, and need not cause general terror respecting the laws of the universe. Neither did the orderly and narrow succession of domestic joy and sorrow in a small German community bring the question in its breadth, or in any unresolvable shape, before the mind of Dürer. But the English death—the European death of the nineteenth century—was of another range and power; more terrible a thousandfold in its merely physical grasp and grief; more terrible, incalculably, in its mystery and shame. What were the robber's casual pang, or the range of the flying skirmish, compared to the work of the axe, and the sword, and the famine, which was done during this man's youth on all the hills and plains of the Christian earth, from Moscow to Gibraltar? He was eighteen years old when Napoleon came down on Arcola. Look on the map of Europe and count the blood-stains on it, between Arcola and Waterloo.[134]
And their Death. That old Greek question again;—yet unanswered. The unconquerable spectre still flitting among the forest trees at twilight; rising ribbed out of the sea-sand;—white, a strange Aphrodite,—out of the sea-foam; stretching its grey, cloven wings among the clouds; turning the light of their sunsets into blood. This has to be looked upon, and in a more terrible shape than ever Salvator or Dürer saw it.[133] The wreck of one guilty country does not infer the ruin of all countries, and need not cause general terror respecting the laws of the universe. Neither did the orderly and narrow succession of domestic joy and sorrow in a small German community bring the question in its breadth, or in any unresolvable shape, before the mind of Dürer. But the English death—the European death of the nineteenth century—was of another range and power; more terrible a thousandfold in its merely physical grasp and grief; more terrible, incalculably, in its mystery and shame. What were the robber's casual pang, or the range of the flying skirmish, compared to the work of the axe, and the sword, and the famine, which was done during this man's youth on all the hills and plains of the Christian earth, from Moscow to Gibraltar? He was eighteen years old when Napoleon came down on Arcola. Look on the map of Europe and count the blood-stains on it, between Arcola and Waterloo.[134]
Not alone those blood-stains on the Alpine snow, and the blue of the Lombard plain. The English death was before his eyes also. No decent, calculable, consoled dying; no passing to rest like that of the aged burghers of Nuremberg town. No gentle processions to churchyards among the fields, the bronze crests bossed deep on the memorial tablets, and the skylark singing above them from among the corn. But the life trampled out in the slime of the street, crushed to dust amidst the roaring of the wheel, tossed countlessly away into howling winter wind along five hundred leagues of rock-fanged shore. Or, worst of all, rotted down to forgotten graves through years of ignorant patience, and vain seeking for help from man, for hope in God—infirm, imperfect yearning, as of motherless infants starving at the dawn; oppressed royalties of captive thought, vague ague-fits of bleak, amazed despair.
Not just those bloodstains on the Alpine snow and the blue of the Lombard plain. The English death was also right in front of him. It wasn't a decent, predictable, comforting death; it wasn't a peaceful end like that of the aged townsfolk of Nuremberg. There were no gentle processions to the graveyards among the fields, no bronze crests deeply embossed on the memorial tablets, and no skylarks singing above them amid the corn. Instead, it was a life stomped out in the muck of the street, crushed to dust amid the noise of wheels, endlessly tossed away into the howling winter wind along five hundred leagues of jagged shores. Or, even worse, lost to forgotten graves through years of ignorant patience, and futile searching for help from humans, for hope in God—weak, imperfect longing, like motherless infants starving at dawn; oppressed royalties of trapped thoughts, vague fits of bleak, stunned despair.
A goodly landscape this, for the lad to paint, and under a goodly light. Wide enough the light was, and clear; no more Salvator's lurid chasm on jagged horizon, nor Dürer's spotted rest of sunny gleam on hedgerow and field; but light over all the world. Full shone now its awful globe, one pallid charnel-house,—a ball strewn bright with human ashes, glaring in poised sway beneath the sun, all blinding-white with death from pole to pole,—death, not of myriads of poor bodies only, but of will, and mercy, and conscience; death, not once inflicted on the flesh, but daily, fastening on the spirit; death, not silent or patient, waiting his appointed hour, but voiceful, venomous; death with the taunting word, and burning grasp, and infixed sting.
This is a great landscape for the young man to paint, and the light is just right. The light was wide and clear; no more of Salvator's eerie chasms on a jagged horizon, nor Dürer's speckled patches of sunny brightness on hedgerows and fields; instead, light spread over the entire world. Its powerful globe now shone brightly, like a pale charnel-house—a ball scattered with human ashes, glaring in a suspended sway beneath the sun, all blinding-white with death from pole to pole—death, not just of countless bodies, but of will, mercy, and conscience; death, not inflicted just once on the flesh, but every day, gripping the spirit; death, not silent or patient, waiting for its time, but loud and venomous; death with a taunting word, a burning grip, and a deep sting.
"Put ye in the sickle, for the harvest is ripe."[135] The word is spoken in our ears continually to other reapers than the angels,—to the busy skeletons that never tire for stooping. When the measure of iniquity is full, and it seems that another day might bring repentance and redemption,—"Put ye in the sickle." When the young life has been wasted all away, and the eyes are just opening upon the tracks of ruin, and faint resolution rising in the heart for nobler things,—"Put ye in the sickle." When the roughest blows of fortune have been borne long and bravely, and the hand is just stretched to grasp its goal,—"Put ye in the sickle." And when there are but a few in the midst of a nation, to save it, or to teach, or to cherish; and all its life is bound up in those few golden ears,—"Put ye in the sickle, pale reapers, and pour hemlock for your feast of harvest home."
"Put ye in the sickle, for the harvest is ripe."[135] The word is spoken in our ears continually to other reapers than the angels,—to the busy skeletons that never tire for stooping. When the measure of iniquity is full, and it seems that another day might bring repentance and redemption,—"Put ye in the sickle." When the young life has been wasted all away, and the eyes are just opening upon the tracks of ruin, and faint resolution rising in the heart for nobler things,—"Put ye in the sickle." When the roughest blows of fortune have been borne long and bravely, and the hand is just stretched to grasp its goal,—"Put ye in the sickle." And when there are but a few in the midst of a nation, to save it, or to teach, or to cherish; and all its life is bound up in those few golden ears,—"Put ye in the sickle, pale reapers, and pour hemlock for your feast of harvest home."
This was the sight which opened on the young eyes, this the watchword sounding within the heart of Turner in his youth.
This was the scene that unfolded before the young eyes, this the mantra echoing in Turner's heart during his youth.
So taught, and prepared for his life's labour, sate the boy at last alone among his fair English hills; and began to paint, with cautious toil, the rocks, and fields, and trickling brooks, and soft white clouds of heaven.
So taught and ready for his life's work, the boy finally sat alone among his beautiful English hills; and started to paint, with careful effort, the rocks, fields, trickling brooks, and soft white clouds in the sky.
The first volume of The Stones of Venice appeared in March, 1851; the first day of May of the same year we find the following entry in Ruskin's diary: "About to enter on the true beginning of the second part of my Venetian work. May God help me to finish it—to His glory, and man's good." The main part of the volume was composed at Venice in the winter of 1851-52, though it did not appear until the end of July, 1853. His work on architecture, including The Seven Lamps, it will be noted, intervenes between the composition of the second and third volumes of Modern Painters; and Ruskin himself always looked upon the work as an interlude, almost as an interruption. But he also came to believe that this digression had really led back to the heart of the truth for all art. Its main theme, as in The Seven Lamps of Architecture, is its illustration of the principle that architecture expresses certain states in the moral temper of the people by and for whom it is produced. It may surprise us to-day to know that when Ruskin wrote of the glories of Venetian architecture, the common "professional opinion was that St. Mark's and the Ducal Palace were as ugly and repulsive as they were contrary to rule and order." In a private letter Gibbon writes of the Square of St. Mark's as "a large square decorated with the worst architecture I ever saw." The architects of his own time regarded Ruskin's opinions as dictated by wild caprice, and almost evincing an unbalanced mind. Probably the core of all this architectural work is to be found in his chapter "On the Nature of Gothic," in the main reproduced in this volume. And we find here again a point of fundamental significance—that his artistic analysis led him inevitably on to social inquiries. He proved to himself that the main virtue of Gothic lay in the unrestricted play of the individual imagination; that the best results were produced when every artist was a workman and every workman an artist. Twenty years after the publication of this book, he wrote in a private letter that his main purpose "was to show the dependence of (architectural) beauty on the happiness and fancy of the workman, and to show also that no architect could claim the title to authority of Magister unless he himself wrought at the head of his men, captain of manual skill, as the best knight is captain of armies." He himself called the chapter "precisely and accurately the most important in the whole book." Mr. Frederic Harrison says that in it is "the creed, if it be not the origin, of a new industrial school of thought."
The first volume of The Stones of Venice came out in March 1851. On May 1 of that same year, Ruskin wrote in his diary: "About to start on the real beginning of the second part of my Venetian work. May God help me finish it—for His glory and the good of mankind." The main portion of this volume was written in Venice during the winter of 1851-52, but it didn't get published until the end of July 1853. His work on architecture, including The Seven Lamps, occurs between the writing of the second and third volumes of Modern Painters, and Ruskin always viewed this work as an interlude, almost an interruption. However, he eventually believed that this detour had genuinely led him back to the core truth about all art. Its main theme, similar to The Seven Lamps of Architecture, illustrates the idea that architecture reflects certain states of the people's moral character for whom it is created. It's surprising to learn that when Ruskin praised the beauty of Venetian architecture, the common view among professionals was that St. Mark's and the Ducal Palace were as ugly and unappealing as they were unconventional. In a private letter, Gibbon referred to St. Mark's Square as "a large square adorned with the worst architecture I've ever seen." Architects of his time considered Ruskin's views to be driven by wild whim and an almost unstable mind. The essence of his architectural work is likely found in his chapter "On the Nature of Gothic," which is largely reproduced in this volume. Here again, we see a critical point—the way his artistic analysis naturally led to social questions. He demonstrated to himself that Gothic's primary virtue was in the free expression of individual imagination; the best outcomes happened when every artist was a craftsman, and every craftsman was an artist. Two decades after this book was published, he wrote in a private letter that his main goal "was to show how (architectural) beauty depends on the happiness and creativity of the worker, and also to indicate that no architect could claim the title of Magister unless he worked alongside his crew, leading skilled labor, just as the best knight leads armies." He called this chapter "precisely and accurately the most important in the whole book." Mr. Frederic Harrison states that in it lies "the creed, if not the origin, of a new industrial school of thought."
THE THRONE
VOLUME II, CHAPTER I
In the olden days of travelling, now to return no more, in which distance could not be vanquished without toil, but in which that toil was rewarded, partly by the power of deliberate survey of the countries through which the journey lay, and partly by the happiness of the evening hours, when from the top of the last hill he had surmounted, the traveller beheld the quiet village where he was to rest, scattered among the meadows beside its valley stream; or, from the long hoped for turn in the dusty perspective of the causeway, saw, for the first time, the towers of some famed city, faint in the rays of sunset—hours of peaceful and thoughtful pleasure, for which the rush of the arrival in the railway station is perhaps not always, or to all men, an equivalent,—in those days, I say, when there was something more to be anticipated and remembered in the first aspect of each successive halting-place, than a new arrangement of glass roofing and iron girder, there were few moments of which the recollection was more fondly cherished by the traveller, than that which, as I endeavoured to describe in the close of the last chapter, brought him within sight of Venice, as his gondola shot into the open lagoon from the canal of Mestre. Not but that the aspect of the city itself was generally the source of some slight disappointment, for, seen in this direction, its buildings are far less characteristic than those of the other great towns of Italy; but this inferiority was partly disguised by distance, and more than atoned for by the strange rising of its walls and towers out of the midst, as it seemed, of the deep sea, for it was impossible that the mind or the eye could at once comprehend the shallowness of the vast sheet of water which stretched away in leagues of rippling lustre to the north and south, or trace the narrow line of islets bounding it to the east. The salt breeze, the white moaning sea-birds, the masses of black weed separating and disappearing gradually, in knots of heaving shoal, under the advance of the steady tide, all proclaimed it to be indeed the ocean on whose bosom the great city rested so calmly; not such blue, soft, lake-like ocean as bathes the Neapolitan promontories, or sleeps beneath the marble rocks of Genoa, but a sea with the bleak power of our own northern waves, yet subdued into a strange spacious rest, and changed from its angry pallor into a field of burnished gold, as the sun declined behind the belfry tower of the lonely island church, fitly named "St. George of the Seaweed." As the boat drew nearer to the city, the coast which the traveller had just left sank behind him into one long, low, sad-coloured line, tufted irregularly with brushwood and willows: but, at what seemed its northern extremity, the hills of Arqua rose in a dark cluster of purple pyramids, balanced on the bright mirage of the lagoon; two or three smooth surges of inferior hill extended themselves about their roots, and beyond these, beginning with the craggy peaks above Vicenza, the chain of the Alps girded the whole horizon to the north—a wall of jagged blue, here and there showing through its clefts a wilderness of misty precipices, fading far back into the recesses of Cadore, and itself rising and breaking away eastward, where the sun struck opposite upon its snow, into mighty fragments of peaked light, standing up behind the barred clouds of evening, one after another, countless, the crown of the Adrian Sea, until the eye turned back from pursuing them, to rest upon the nearer burning of the campaniles of Murano, and on the great city, where it magnified itself along the waves, as the quick silent pacing of the gondola drew nearer and nearer. And at last, when its walls were reached, and the outmost of its untrodden streets was entered, not through towered gate or guarded rampart, but as a deep inlet between two rocks of coral in the Indian sea; when first upon the traveller's sight opened the long ranges of columned palaces,—each with its black boat moored at the portal,—each with its image cast down, beneath its feet, upon that green pavement which every breeze broke into new fantasies of rich tessellation; when first, at the extremity of the bright vista, the shadowy Rialto threw its colossal curve slowly forth from behind the palace of the Camerlenghi;[136] that strange curve, so delicate, so adamantine, strong as a mountain cavern, graceful as a bow just bent; when first, before its moonlike circumference was all risen, the gondolier's cry, "Ah! Stalì,"[137] struck sharp upon the ear, and the prow turned aside under the mighty cornices that half met over the narrow canal, where the splash of the water followed close and loud, ringing along the marble by the boat's side; and when at last that boat darted forth upon the breadth of silver sea, across which the front of the Ducal Palace, flushed with its sanguine veins, looks to the snowy dome of Our Lady of Salvation,[138] it was no marvel that the mind should be so deeply entranced by the visionary charm of a scene so beautiful and so strange, as to forget the darker truths of its history and its being. Well might it seem that such a city had owed her existence rather to the rod of the enchanter, than the fear of the fugitive; that the waters which encircled her had been chosen for the mirror of her state, rather than the shelter of her nakedness; and that all which in nature was wild or merciless,—Time and Decay, as well as the waves and tempests,—had been won to adorn her instead of to destroy, and might still spare, for ages to come, that beauty which seemed to have fixed for its throne the sands of the hour-glass as well as of the sea.
In the olden days of travelling, now to return no more, in which distance could not be vanquished without toil, but in which that toil was rewarded, partly by the power of deliberate survey of the countries through which the journey lay, and partly by the happiness of the evening hours, when from the top of the last hill he had surmounted, the traveller beheld the quiet village where he was to rest, scattered among the meadows beside its valley stream; or, from the long hoped for turn in the dusty perspective of the causeway, saw, for the first time, the towers of some famed city, faint in the rays of sunset—hours of peaceful and thoughtful pleasure, for which the rush of the arrival in the railway station is perhaps not always, or to all men, an equivalent,—in those days, I say, when there was something more to be anticipated and remembered in the first aspect of each successive halting-place, than a new arrangement of glass roofing and iron girder, there were few moments of which the recollection was more fondly cherished by the traveller, than that which, as I endeavoured to describe in the close of the last chapter, brought him within sight of Venice, as his gondola shot into the open lagoon from the canal of Mestre. Not but that the aspect of the city itself was generally the source of some slight disappointment, for, seen in this direction, its buildings are far less characteristic than those of the other great towns of Italy; but this inferiority was partly disguised by distance, and more than atoned for by the strange rising of its walls and towers out of the midst, as it seemed, of the deep sea, for it was impossible that the mind or the eye could at once comprehend the shallowness of the vast sheet of water which stretched away in leagues of rippling lustre to the north and south, or trace the narrow line of islets bounding it to the east. The salt breeze, the white moaning sea-birds, the masses of black weed separating and disappearing gradually, in knots of heaving shoal, under the advance of the steady tide, all proclaimed it to be indeed the ocean on whose bosom the great city rested so calmly; not such blue, soft, lake-like ocean as bathes the Neapolitan promontories, or sleeps beneath the marble rocks of Genoa, but a sea with the bleak power of our own northern waves, yet subdued into a strange spacious rest, and changed from its angry pallor into a field of burnished gold, as the sun declined behind the belfry tower of the lonely island church, fitly named "St. George of the Seaweed." As the boat drew nearer to the city, the coast which the traveller had just left sank behind him into one long, low, sad-coloured line, tufted irregularly with brushwood and willows: but, at what seemed its northern extremity, the hills of Arqua rose in a dark cluster of purple pyramids, balanced on the bright mirage of the lagoon; two or three smooth surges of inferior hill extended themselves about their roots, and beyond these, beginning with the craggy peaks above Vicenza, the chain of the Alps girded the whole horizon to the north—a wall of jagged blue, here and there showing through its clefts a wilderness of misty precipices, fading far back into the recesses of Cadore, and itself rising and breaking away eastward, where the sun struck opposite upon its snow, into mighty fragments of peaked light, standing up behind the barred clouds of evening, one after another, countless, the crown of the Adrian Sea, until the eye turned back from pursuing them, to rest upon the nearer burning of the campaniles of Murano, and on the great city, where it magnified itself along the waves, as the quick silent pacing of the gondola drew nearer and nearer. And at last, when its walls were reached, and the outmost of its untrodden streets was entered, not through towered gate or guarded rampart, but as a deep inlet between two rocks of coral in the Indian sea; when first upon the traveller's sight opened the long ranges of columned palaces,—each with its black boat moored at the portal,—each with its image cast down, beneath its feet, upon that green pavement which every breeze broke into new fantasies of rich tessellation; when first, at the extremity of the bright vista, the shadowy Rialto threw its colossal curve slowly forth from behind the palace of the Camerlenghi;[136] that strange curve, so delicate, so adamantine, strong as a mountain cavern, graceful as a bow just bent; when first, before its moonlike circumference was all risen, the gondolier's cry, "Ah! Stalì,"[137] struck sharp upon the ear, and the prow turned aside under the mighty cornices that half met over the narrow canal, where the splash of the water followed close and loud, ringing along the marble by the boat's side; and when at last that boat darted forth upon the breadth of silver sea, across which the front of the Ducal Palace, flushed with its sanguine veins, looks to the snowy dome of Our Lady of Salvation,[138] it was no marvel that the mind should be so deeply entranced by the visionary charm of a scene so beautiful and so strange, as to forget the darker truths of its history and its being. Well might it seem that such a city had owed her existence rather to the rod of the enchanter, than the fear of the fugitive; that the waters which encircled her had been chosen for the mirror of her state, rather than the shelter of her nakedness; and that all which in nature was wild or merciless,—Time and Decay, as well as the waves and tempests,—had been won to adorn her instead of to destroy, and might still spare, for ages to come, that beauty which seemed to have fixed for its throne the sands of the hour-glass as well as of the sea.
And although the last few eventful years, fraught with change to the face of the whole earth, have been more fatal in their influence on Venice than the five hundred that preceded them; though the noble landscape of approach to her can now be seen no more, or seen only by a glance, as the engine slackens its rushing on the iron line; and though many of her palaces are for ever defaced, and many in desecrated ruins, there is still so much of magic in her aspect, that the hurried traveller, who must leave her before the wonder of that first aspect has been worn away, may still be led to forget the humility of her origin, and to shut his eyes to the depth of her desolation. They, at least, are little to be envied, in whose hearts the great charities of the imagination lie dead, and for whom the fancy has no power to repress the importunity of painful impressions, or to raise what is ignoble, and disguise what is discordant, in a scene so rich in its remembrances, so surpassing in its beauty. But for this work of the imagination there must be no permission during the task which is before us. The impotent feelings of romance, so singularly characteristic of this century, may indeed gild, but never save, the remains of those mightier ages to which they are attached like climbing flowers; and they must be torn away from the magnificent fragments, if we would see them as they stood in their own strength. Those feelings, always as fruitless as they are fond, are in Venice not only incapable of protecting, but even of discerning, the objects to which they ought to have been attached. The Venice of modern fiction and drama is a thing of yesterday, a mere efflorescence of decay, a stage dream which the first ray of daylight must dissipate into dust. No prisoner, whose name is worth remembering, or whose sorrow deserved sympathy, ever crossed that "Bridge of Sighs," which is the centre of the Byronic ideal of Venice;[139] no great merchant of Venice ever saw that Rialto under which the traveller now passes with breathless interest: the statue which Byron makes Faliero address as of one of his great ancestors was erected to a soldier of fortune a hundred and fifty years after Faliero's death;[140] and the most conspicuous parts of the city have been so entirely altered in the course of the last three centuries, that if Henry Dandolo or Francis Foscari[141] could be summoned from their tombs, and stood each on the deck of his galley at the entrance of the Grand Canal, that renowned entrance, the painter's favourite subject, the novelist's favourite scene, where the water first narrows by the steps of the Church of La Salute,—the mighty Doges would not know in what part of the world they stood, would literally not recognize one stone of the great city, for whose sake, and by whose ingratitude, their grey hairs had been brought down with bitterness to the grave. The remains of their Venice lie hidden behind the cumbrous masses which were the delight of the nation in its dotage; hidden in many a grass-grown court, and silent pathway, and lightless canal, where the slow waves have sapped their foundations for five hundred years, and must soon prevail over them for ever. It must be our task to glean and gather them forth, and restore out of them some faint image of the lost city; more gorgeous a thousandfold than that which now exists, yet not created in the day-dream of the prince, nor by the ostentation of the noble, but built by iron hands and patient hearts, contending against the adversity of nature and the fury of man, so that its wonderfulness cannot be grasped by the indolence of imagination, but only after frank inquiry into the true nature of that wild and solitary scene, whose restless tides and trembling sands did indeed shelter the birth of the city, but long denied her dominion.
And although the last few eventful years, fraught with change to the face of the whole earth, have been more fatal in their influence on Venice than the five hundred that preceded them; though the noble landscape of approach to her can now be seen no more, or seen only by a glance, as the engine slackens its rushing on the iron line; and though many of her palaces are for ever defaced, and many in desecrated ruins, there is still so much of magic in her aspect, that the hurried traveller, who must leave her before the wonder of that first aspect has been worn away, may still be led to forget the humility of her origin, and to shut his eyes to the depth of her desolation. They, at least, are little to be envied, in whose hearts the great charities of the imagination lie dead, and for whom the fancy has no power to repress the importunity of painful impressions, or to raise what is ignoble, and disguise what is discordant, in a scene so rich in its remembrances, so surpassing in its beauty. But for this work of the imagination there must be no permission during the task which is before us. The impotent feelings of romance, so singularly characteristic of this century, may indeed gild, but never save, the remains of those mightier ages to which they are attached like climbing flowers; and they must be torn away from the magnificent fragments, if we would see them as they stood in their own strength. Those feelings, always as fruitless as they are fond, are in Venice not only incapable of protecting, but even of discerning, the objects to which they ought to have been attached. The Venice of modern fiction and drama is a thing of yesterday, a mere efflorescence of decay, a stage dream which the first ray of daylight must dissipate into dust. No prisoner, whose name is worth remembering, or whose sorrow deserved sympathy, ever crossed that "Bridge of Sighs," which is the centre of the Byronic ideal of Venice;[139] no great merchant of Venice ever saw that Rialto under which the traveller now passes with breathless interest: the statue which Byron makes Faliero address as of one of his great ancestors was erected to a soldier of fortune a hundred and fifty years after Faliero's death;[140] and the most conspicuous parts of the city have been so entirely altered in the course of the last three centuries, that if Henry Dandolo or Francis Foscari[141] could be summoned from their tombs, and stood each on the deck of his galley at the entrance of the Grand Canal, that renowned entrance, the painter's favourite subject, the novelist's favourite scene, where the water first narrows by the steps of the Church of La Salute,—the mighty Doges would not know in what part of the world they stood, would literally not recognize one stone of the great city, for whose sake, and by whose ingratitude, their grey hairs had been brought down with bitterness to the grave. The remains of their Venice lie hidden behind the cumbrous masses which were the delight of the nation in its dotage; hidden in many a grass-grown court, and silent pathway, and lightless canal, where the slow waves have sapped their foundations for five hundred years, and must soon prevail over them for ever. It must be our task to glean and gather them forth, and restore out of them some faint image of the lost city; more gorgeous a thousandfold than that which now exists, yet not created in the day-dream of the prince, nor by the ostentation of the noble, but built by iron hands and patient hearts, contending against the adversity of nature and the fury of man, so that its wonderfulness cannot be grasped by the indolence of imagination, but only after frank inquiry into the true nature of that wild and solitary scene, whose restless tides and trembling sands did indeed shelter the birth of the city, but long denied her dominion.
When the eye falls casually on a map of Europe, there is no feature by which it is more likely to be arrested than the strange sweeping loop formed by the junction of the Alps and Apennines, and enclosing the great basin of Lombardy. This return of the mountain chain upon itself causes a vast difference in the character of the distribution of its debris on its opposite sides. The rock fragments and sediment which the torrents on the other side of the Alps bear into the plains are distributed over a vast extent of country, and, though here and there lodged in beds of enormous thickness, soon permit the firm substrata to appear from underneath them; but all the torrents which descend from the southern side of the High Alps, and from the northern slope of the Apennines, meet concentrically in the recess or mountain bay which the two ridges enclose; every fragment which thunder breaks out of their battlements, and every grain of dust which the summer rain washes from their pastures, is at last laid at rest in the blue sweep of the Lombardic plain; and that plain must have risen within its rocky barriers as a cup fills with wine, but for two contrary influences which continually depress, or disperse from its surface, the accumulation of the ruins of ages.
When you casually glance at a map of Europe, one feature that stands out is the strange sweeping loop formed by the junction of the Alps and Apennines, which surrounds the great basin of Lombardy. This bend in the mountain range leads to a significant difference in how its debris is spread on either side. The rock fragments and sediment carried by the torrents from the Alps are spread across a wide area, and even though some parts settle in thick layers, the solid ground eventually shows through. In contrast, all the torrents flowing down from the southern side of the High Alps and the northern slope of the Apennines converge in the recess or mountain bay created by the two ridges; every fragment blasted off their cliffs and every grain of dust washed away by summer rain ends up settling in the vast expanse of the Lombard plain. That plain must have risen within its rocky boundaries like a cup filling with wine, were it not for two opposing forces that continually press down or disperse the accumulation of ancient debris from its surface.
I will not tax the reader's faith in modern science by insisting on the singular depression of the surface of Lombardy, which appears for many centuries to have taken place steadily and continually; the main fact with which we have to do is the gradual transport, by the Po and its great collateral rivers, of vast masses of the finer sediment to the sea. The character of the Lombardic plains is most strikingly expressed by the ancient walls of its cities, composed for the most part of large rounded Alpine pebbles alternating with narrow courses of brick; and was curiously illustrated in 1848, by the ramparts of these same pebbles thrown up four or five feet high round every field, to check the Austrian cavalry in the battle under the walls of Verona.[142] The finer dust among which these pebbles are dispersed is taken up by the rivers, fed into continual strength by the Alpine snow, so that, however pure their waters may be when they issue from the lakes at the foot of the great chain, they become of the colour and opacity of clay before they reach the Adriatic; the sediment which they bear is at once thrown down as they enter the sea, forming a vast belt of low land along the eastern coast of Italy. The powerful stream of the Po of course builds forward the fastest; on each side of it, north and south, there is a tract of marsh, fed by more feeble streams, and less liable to rapid change than the delta of the central river. In one of these tracts is built RAVENNA, and in the other VENICE.
I will not tax the reader's faith in modern science by insisting on the singular depression of the surface of Lombardy, which appears for many centuries to have taken place steadily and continually; the main fact with which we have to do is the gradual transport, by the Po and its great collateral rivers, of vast masses of the finer sediment to the sea. The character of the Lombardic plains is most strikingly expressed by the ancient walls of its cities, composed for the most part of large rounded Alpine pebbles alternating with narrow courses of brick; and was curiously illustrated in 1848, by the ramparts of these same pebbles thrown up four or five feet high round every field, to check the Austrian cavalry in the battle under the walls of Verona.[142] The finer dust among which these pebbles are dispersed is taken up by the rivers, fed into continual strength by the Alpine snow, so that, however pure their waters may be when they issue from the lakes at the foot of the great chain, they become of the colour and opacity of clay before they reach the Adriatic; the sediment which they bear is at once thrown down as they enter the sea, forming a vast belt of low land along the eastern coast of Italy. The powerful stream of the Po of course builds forward the fastest; on each side of it, north and south, there is a tract of marsh, fed by more feeble streams, and less liable to rapid change than the delta of the central river. In one of these tracts is built RAVENNA, and in the other VENICE.
What circumstances directed the peculiar arrangement of this great belt of sediment in the earliest times, it is not here the place to inquire. It is enough for us to know that from the mouths of the Adige to those of the Piave there stretches, at a variable distance of from three to five miles from the actual shore, a bank of sand, divided into long islands by narrow channels of sea. The space between this bank and the true shore consists of the sedimentary deposits from these and other rivers, a great plain of calcareous mud, covered, in the neighbourhood of Venice, by the sea at high water, to the depth in most places of a foot or a foot and a half, and nearly everywhere exposed at low tide, but divided by an intricate network of narrow and winding channels, from which the sea never retires. In some places, according to the run of the currents, the land has risen into marshy islets, consolidated, some by art, and some by time, into ground firm enough to be built upon, or fruitful enough to be cultivated: in others, on the contrary, it has not reached the sea level; so that, at the average low water, shallow lakelets glitter among its irregularly exposed fields of seaweed. In the midst of the largest of these, increased in importance by the confluence of several large river channels towards one of the openings in the sea bank, the city of Venice itself is built, on a crowded cluster of islands; the various plots of higher ground which appear to the north and south of this central cluster, have at different periods been also thickly inhabited, and now bear, according to their size, the remains of cities, villages, or isolated convents and churches, scattered among spaces of open ground, partly waste and encumbered by ruins, partly under cultivation for the supply of the metropolis.
What circumstances led to the unique formation of this vast belt of sediment in ancient times is not our focus here. It's enough to know that from the mouths of the Adige to those of the Piave, a sandbank stretches, varying from three to five miles from the actual shore, divided into long islands by narrow sea channels. The area between this bank and the true shore contains sediment deposits from these and other rivers, creating a large plain of muddy limestone, which is covered by the sea at high tide, usually to a depth of about one to one and a half feet in most places, but is nearly always exposed at low tide. However, it is crisscrossed by a complex network of narrow, winding channels where the sea never retreats. In some areas, depending on the current flow, the land has formed marshy islets, some shaped by human intervention and others by natural processes, that are solid enough for construction or fertile enough for farming. In contrast, some areas haven’t reached sea level, so at low tide, shallow ponds sparkle amid the irregularly exposed fields of seaweed. In the middle of the largest of these, which is enhanced by the convergence of several major river channels leading to an opening in the sandbank, the city of Venice itself is built on a dense cluster of islands. The various patches of higher ground to the north and south of this central hub have also been densely populated at different times, and now show, depending on their size, the remnants of cities, villages, or solitary convents and churches scattered among areas of open land, some of which are neglected and filled with ruins, while others are farmed to support the metropolis.
The average rise and fall of the tide is about three feet (varying considerably with the seasons); but this fall, on so flat a shore, is enough to cause continual movement in the waters, and in the main canals to produce a reflux which frequently runs like a mill stream. At high water no land is visible for many miles to the north or south of Venice, except in the form of small islands crowned with towers or gleaming with villages: there is a channel, some three miles wide, between the city and the mainland, and some mile and a half wide between it and the sandy breakwater called the Lido, which divides the lagoon from the Adriatic, but which is so low as hardly to disturb the impression of the city's having been built in the midst of the ocean, although the secret of its true position is partly, yet not painfully, betrayed by the clusters of piles set to mark the deepwater channels, which undulate far away in spotty chains like the studded backs of huge sea-snakes, and by the quick glittering of the crisped and crowded waves that flicker and dance before the strong winds upon the uplifted level of the shallow sea. But the scene is widely different at low tide. A fall of eighteen or twenty inches is enough to show ground over the greater part of the lagoon; and at the complete ebb the city is seen standing in the midst of a dark plain of sea-weed, of gloomy green, except only where the larger branches of the Brenta and its associated streams converge towards the port of the Lido. Through this salt and sombre plain the gondola and the fishing-boat advance by tortuous channels, seldom more than four or five feet deep, and often so choked with slime that the heavier keels furrow the bottom till their crossing tracks are seen through the clear sea water like the ruts upon a wintry road, and the oar leaves blue gashes upon the ground at every stroke, or is entangled among the thick weed that fringes the banks with the weight of its sullen waves, leaning to and fro upon the uncertain sway of the exhausted tide. The scene is often profoundly oppressive, even at this day, when every plot of higher ground bears some fragment of fair building: but, in order to know what it was once, let the traveller follow in his boat at evening the windings of some unfrequented channel far into the midst of the melancholy plain; let him remove, in his imagination, the brightness of the great city that still extends itself in the distance, and the walls and towers from the islands that are near; and so wait, until the bright investiture and sweet warmth of the sunset are withdrawn from the waters, and the black desert of their shore lies in its nakedness beneath the night, pathless, comfortless, infirm, lost in dark languor and fearful silence, except where the salt runlets plash into the tideless pools, or the sea-birds flit from their margins with a questioning cry; and he will be enabled to enter in some sort into the horror of heart with which this solitude was anciently chosen by man for his habitation. They little thought, who first drove the stakes into the sand, and strewed the ocean reeds for their rest, that their children were to be the princes of that ocean, and their palaces its pride; and yet, in the great natural laws that rule that sorrowful wilderness, let it be remembered what strange preparation had been made for the things which no human imagination could have foretold, and how the whole existence and fortune of the Venetian nation were anticipated or compelled, by the setting of those bars and doors to the rivers and the sea. Had deeper currents divided their islands, hostile navies would again and again have reduced the rising city into servitude; had stronger surges beaten their shores, all the richness and refinement of the Venetian architecture must have been exchanged for the walls and bulwarks of an ordinary sea-port. Had there been no tide, as in other parts of the Mediterranean, the narrow canals of the city would have become noisome, and the marsh in which it was built pestiferous. Had the tide been only a foot or eighteen inches higher in its rise, the water-access to the doors of the palaces would have been impossible: even as it is, there is sometimes a little difficulty, at the ebb, in landing without setting foot upon the lower and slippery steps; and the highest tides sometimes enter the courtyards, and overflow the entrance halls. Eighteen inches more of difference between the level of the flood and ebb would have rendered the doorsteps of every palace, at low water, a treacherous mass of weeds and limpets, and the entire system of water-carriage for the higher classes, in their easy and daily intercourse, must have been done away with. The streets of the city would have been widened, its network of canals filled up, and all the peculiar character of the place and the people destroyed.
The average rise and fall of the tide is about three feet (varying a lot with the seasons); but on such a flat shoreline, this drop is enough to cause constant movement in the waters, and in the main canals to create a current that often flows like a mill stream. At high tide, no land is visible for miles north or south of Venice, except for small islands topped with towers or filled with villages: there is a channel about three miles wide between the city and the mainland, and about a mile and a half wide between it and the sandy breakwater known as the Lido, which separates the lagoon from the Adriatic. The Lido is so low that it hardly disrupts the impression that the city is built in the middle of the ocean, although the truth of its position is somewhat revealed by the clusters of piles marking the deepwater channels, which undulate in a spotted pattern like the backs of giant sea snakes, and by the quick glinting of the choppy waves that flicker and dance before the strong winds on the surface of the shallow sea. But the scene changes dramatically at low tide. A drop of eighteen or twenty inches is enough to reveal ground over most of the lagoon; and at complete ebb, the city appears to be standing in the midst of a dark expanse of seaweed, a gloomy green, except where the larger branches of the Brenta and its tributaries come together toward the port of the Lido. Through this salty and somber plain, gondolas and fishing boats navigate winding channels, often no more than four or five feet deep, and often so filled with sludge that the heavier keels leave furrows in the bottom, which can be seen through the clear sea water like ruts on a winter road, and the oars leave blue marks on the ground with every stroke, or get tangled in the thick weeds that cling to the banks under the weight of their sluggish waves, swaying back and forth on the uncertain movements of the depleted tide. The scene can feel profoundly oppressive, even today, where every bit of higher ground has some remnant of a beautiful building: but to understand what it once was, let the traveler take a boat in the evening along some rarely used channel deep into the melancholy plain; let him imagine removing the brightness of the grand city that still stretches in the distance, along with the walls and towers of the nearby islands; and wait until the bright glow and warm comfort of the sunset vanish from the waters, leaving the dark wilderness of its shore bare beneath the night, pathless, comfortless, weak, lost in dark sluggishness and eerie silence, except for the splashing of saltwater into the motionless pools, or the cries of seabirds flitting from their edges; and he will start to feel something of the horror that once filled human hearts in choosing this solitude for habitation. Those who first drove the stakes into the sand and laid ocean reeds for their rest could hardly have imagined that their descendants would become the rulers of that ocean, with their palaces as its pride; yet, in the great natural laws that govern that sorrowful wilderness, it's worth noting the strange preparations made for things that no human foresight could have predicted, and how the entire existence and fortune of the Venetian people were shaped or dictated by those barriers and entrances to the rivers and the sea. If stronger currents had divided their islands, hostile navies would have repeatedly conquered the growing city; if bigger waves had battered their shores, all the richness and elegance of Venetian architecture would have been replaced by the walls and defenses of an ordinary seaport. If there had been no tide, like in other parts of the Mediterranean, the city’s narrow canals would have become foul, and the marsh it was built on would have become unhealthy. If the tide had been only a foot or eighteen inches higher, getting to the doors of the palaces would have been impossible: even as it stands, there is sometimes a little trouble at low tide in landing without stepping on the lower and slippery steps; during the highest tides, water even enters the courtyards and floods the entrance halls. An additional eighteen inches of difference between the flood and ebb levels would have turned the doorsteps of every palace, at low tide, into a hazardous tangle of weeds and limpets, and the whole system of water transport for the upper classes in their easy and regular dealings would have vanished. The city streets would have been widened, its intricate network of canals filled in, and all the unique character of the place and its people erased.
The reader may perhaps have felt some pain in the contrast between this faithful view of the site of the Venetian Throne, and the romantic conception of it which we ordinarily form; but this pain, if he have felt it, ought to be more than counterbalanced by the value of the instance thus afforded to us at once of the inscrutableness and the wisdom of the ways of God. If, two thousand years ago, we had been permitted to watch the slow settling of the slime of those turbid rivers into the polluted sea, and the gaining upon its deep and fresh waters of the lifeless, impassable, unvoyageable plain, how little could we have understood the purpose with which those islands were shaped out of the void, and the torpid waters enclosed with their desolate walls of sand! How little could we have known, any more than of what now seems to us most distressful, dark, and objectless, the glorious aim which was then in the mind of Him in whose hand are all the corners of the earth! how little imagined that in the laws which were stretching forth the gloomy margins of those fruitless banks, and feeding the bitter grass among their shallows, there was indeed a preparation, and the only preparation possible, for the founding of a city which was to be set like a golden clasp on the girdle of the earth, to write her history on the white scrolls of the sea-surges, and to word it in their thunder, and to gather and give forth, in world-wide pulsation, the glory of the West and of the East, from the burning heart of her Fortitude and Splendour.
The reader may have felt some discomfort in the contrast between this accurate depiction of the site of the Venetian Throne and the romantic image we usually create; but if that discomfort is felt, it should be more than overshadowed by the lesson this example offers us about the mystery and wisdom of God's ways. If, two thousand years ago, we could have observed the slow accumulation of the murky sediments from those polluted rivers into the tainted sea, and the takeover of its deep, fresh waters by the barren, unreachable plain, we would have understood so little of the purpose behind the islands formed from the void, and the stagnant waters contained by their desolate sandy barriers! We would have known so little, just as we often fail to see the glorious intentions at work amid what currently seems most troubling, dark, and pointless, in the plans of the One who holds all the corners of the earth in His hand! We could hardly have imagined that within the laws that were shaping the bleak edges of those unproductive banks and nurturing the bitter grass in their shallows, there was indeed a preparation, and the only preparation possible, for establishing a city that was to be like a golden clasp on the earth's belt, to inscribe her history on the white pages of the sea surges, to express it in their thunder, and to gather and share, in a worldwide rhythm, the glory of the West and the East from the burning heart of her Strength and Grandeur.
ST. MARK'S
VOLUME II, CHAPTER 4
"And so Barnabas took Mark, and sailed unto Cyprus." If as the shores of Asia lessened upon his sight, the spirit of prophecy had entered into the heart of the weak disciple who had turned back when his hand was on the plough, and who had been judged, by the chiefest of Christ's captains, unworthy thenceforward to go forth with him to the work,[143] how wonderful would he have thought it, that by the lion symbol in future ages he was to be represented among men! how woful, that the war-cry of his name should so often reanimate the rage of the soldier, on those very plains where he himself had failed in the courage of the Christian, and so often dye with fruitless blood that very Cypriot Sea, over whose waves, in repentance and shame, he was following the Son of Consolation!
"And so Barnabas took Mark, and sailed unto Cyprus." If as the shores of Asia lessened upon his sight, the spirit of prophecy had entered into the heart of the weak disciple who had turned back when his hand was on the plough, and who had been judged, by the chiefest of Christ's captains, unworthy thenceforward to go forth with him to the work,[143] how wonderful would he have thought it, that by the lion symbol in future ages he was to be represented among men! how woful, that the war-cry of his name should so often reanimate the rage of the soldier, on those very plains where he himself had failed in the courage of the Christian, and so often dye with fruitless blood that very Cypriot Sea, over whose waves, in repentance and shame, he was following the Son of Consolation!
That the Venetians possessed themselves of his body in the ninth century, there appears no sufficient reason to doubt, nor that it was principally in consequence of their having done so, that they chose him for their patron saint. There exists, however, a tradition that before he went into Egypt he had founded the church at Aquileia, and was thus in some sort the first bishop of the Venetian isles and people. I believe that this tradition stands on nearly as good grounds as that of St. Peter having been the first bishop of Rome[144]; but, as usual, it is enriched by various later additions and embellishments, much resembling the stories told respecting the church of Murano. Thus we find it recorded by the Santo Padre who compiled the Vife de' Santi spettanti alle Chiese di Venezia,[145] that "St. Mark having seen the people of Aquileia well grounded in religion, and being called to Rome by St. Peter, before setting off took with him the holy bishop Hermagoras, and went in a small boat to the marshes of Venice. There were at that period some houses built upon a certain high bank called Rialto, and the boat being driven by the wind was anchored in a marshy place, when St. Mark, snatched into ecstasy, heard the voice of an angel saying to him: 'Peace be to thee, Mark; here shall thy body rest.'" The angel goes on to foretell the building of "una stupenda, ne più veduta Città"[146]; but the fable is hardly ingenious enough to deserve farther relation.
That the Venetians possessed themselves of his body in the ninth century, there appears no sufficient reason to doubt, nor that it was principally in consequence of their having done so, that they chose him for their patron saint. There exists, however, a tradition that before he went into Egypt he had founded the church at Aquileia, and was thus in some sort the first bishop of the Venetian isles and people. I believe that this tradition stands on nearly as good grounds as that of St. Peter having been the first bishop of Rome[144]; but, as usual, it is enriched by various later additions and embellishments, much resembling the stories told respecting the church of Murano. Thus we find it recorded by the Santo Padre who compiled the Vife de' Santi spettanti alle Chiese di Venezia,[145] that "St. Mark having seen the people of Aquileia well grounded in religion, and being called to Rome by St. Peter, before setting off took with him the holy bishop Hermagoras, and went in a small boat to the marshes of Venice. There were at that period some houses built upon a certain high bank called Rialto, and the boat being driven by the wind was anchored in a marshy place, when St. Mark, snatched into ecstasy, heard the voice of an angel saying to him: 'Peace be to thee, Mark; here shall thy body rest.'" The angel goes on to foretell the building of "una stupenda, ne più veduta Città"[146]; but the fable is hardly ingenious enough to deserve farther relation.
But whether St. Mark was first bishop of Aquileia or not, St. Theodore was the first patron of the city; nor can he yet be considered as having entirely abdicated his early right, as his statue, standing on a crocodile, still companions the winged lion on the opposing pillar of the piazzetta. A church erected to this Saint is said to have occupied, before the ninth century, the site of St. Mark's; and the traveller, dazzled by the brilliancy of the great square, ought not to leave it without endeavouring to imagine its aspect in that early time, when it was a green field cloister-like and quiet,[147] divided by a small canal, with a line of trees on each side; and extending between the two churches of St. Theodore and St. Gemanium, as the little piazza of Torcello lies between its "palazzo" and cathedral.
But whether St. Mark was first bishop of Aquileia or not, St. Theodore was the first patron of the city; nor can he yet be considered as having entirely abdicated his early right, as his statue, standing on a crocodile, still companions the winged lion on the opposing pillar of the piazzetta. A church erected to this Saint is said to have occupied, before the ninth century, the site of St. Mark's; and the traveller, dazzled by the brilliancy of the great square, ought not to leave it without endeavouring to imagine its aspect in that early time, when it was a green field cloister-like and quiet,[147] divided by a small canal, with a line of trees on each side; and extending between the two churches of St. Theodore and St. Gemanium, as the little piazza of Torcello lies between its "palazzo" and cathedral.
But in the year 813, when the seat of government was finally removed to the Rialto, a Ducal Palace, built on the spot where the present one stands, with a Ducal Chapel beside it,[148] gave a very different character to the Square of St. Mark; and fifteen years later, the acquisition of the body of the Saint, and its deposition in the Ducal Chapel, perhaps not yet completed, occasioned the investiture of that chapel with all possible splendour. St. Theodore was deposed from his patronship, and his church destroyed, to make room for the aggrandizement of the one attached to the Ducal Palace, and thenceforward known as "St. Mark's."[149]
But in the year 813, when the seat of government was finally removed to the Rialto, a Ducal Palace, built on the spot where the present one stands, with a Ducal Chapel beside it,[148] gave a very different character to the Square of St. Mark; and fifteen years later, the acquisition of the body of the Saint, and its deposition in the Ducal Chapel, perhaps not yet completed, occasioned the investiture of that chapel with all possible splendour. St. Theodore was deposed from his patronship, and his church destroyed, to make room for the aggrandizement of the one attached to the Ducal Palace, and thenceforward known as "St. Mark's."[149]
This first church was however destroyed by fire, when the Ducal Palace was burned in the revolt against Candiano, in 976. It was partly rebuilt by his successor, Pietro Orseolo, on a larger scale; and, with the assistance of Byzantine architects, the fabric was carried on under successive Doges for nearly a hundred years; the main building being completed in 1071, but its incrustation with marble not till considerably later. It was consecrated on the 8th of October, 1085,[150] according to Sansovino and the author of the Chiesa Ducale di S. Marco, in 1094 according to Lazari, but certainly between 1084 and 1096, those years being the limits of the reign of Vital Falier; I incline to the supposition that it was soon after his accession to the throne in 1085, though Sansovino writes, by mistake, Ordelafo instead of Vital Falier. But, at all events, before the close of the eleventh century the great consecration of the church took place. It was again injured by fire in 1106, but repaired; and from that time to the fall of Venice there was probably no Doge who did not in some slight degree embellish or alter the fabric, so that few parts of it can be pronounced boldly to be of any given date. Two periods of interference are, however, notable above the rest: the first, that in which the Gothic school had superseded the Byzantine towards the close of the fourteenth century, when the pinnacles, upper archivolts, and window traceries were added to the exterior, and the great screen with various chapels and tabernacle-work, to the interior; the second, when the Renaissance school superseded the Gothic, and the pupils of Titian and Tintoret substituted, over one half of the church, their own compositions for the Greek mosaics with which it was originally decorated;[151] happily, though with no good will, having left enough to enable us to imagine and lament what they destroyed. Of this irreparable loss we shall have more to say hereafter; meantime, I wish only to fix in the reader's mind the succession of periods of alterations as firmly and simply as possible.
This first church was however destroyed by fire, when the Ducal Palace was burned in the revolt against Candiano, in 976. It was partly rebuilt by his successor, Pietro Orseolo, on a larger scale; and, with the assistance of Byzantine architects, the fabric was carried on under successive Doges for nearly a hundred years; the main building being completed in 1071, but its incrustation with marble not till considerably later. It was consecrated on the 8th of October, 1085,[150] according to Sansovino and the author of the Chiesa Ducale di S. Marco, in 1094 according to Lazari, but certainly between 1084 and 1096, those years being the limits of the reign of Vital Falier; I incline to the supposition that it was soon after his accession to the throne in 1085, though Sansovino writes, by mistake, Ordelafo instead of Vital Falier. But, at all events, before the close of the eleventh century the great consecration of the church took place. It was again injured by fire in 1106, but repaired; and from that time to the fall of Venice there was probably no Doge who did not in some slight degree embellish or alter the fabric, so that few parts of it can be pronounced boldly to be of any given date. Two periods of interference are, however, notable above the rest: the first, that in which the Gothic school had superseded the Byzantine towards the close of the fourteenth century, when the pinnacles, upper archivolts, and window traceries were added to the exterior, and the great screen with various chapels and tabernacle-work, to the interior; the second, when the Renaissance school superseded the Gothic, and the pupils of Titian and Tintoret substituted, over one half of the church, their own compositions for the Greek mosaics with which it was originally decorated;[151] happily, though with no good will, having left enough to enable us to imagine and lament what they destroyed. Of this irreparable loss we shall have more to say hereafter; meantime, I wish only to fix in the reader's mind the succession of periods of alterations as firmly and simply as possible.
We have seen that the main body of the church may be broadly stated to be of the eleventh century, the Gothic additions of the fourteenth, and the restored mosaics of the seventeenth. There is no difficulty in distinguishing at a glance the Gothic portions from the Byzantine; but there is considerable difficulty in ascertaining how long, during the course of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, additions were made to the Byzantine church, which cannot be easily distinguished from the work of the eleventh century, being purposely executed in the same manner. Two of the most important pieces of evidence on this point are, a mosaic in the south transept, and another over the northern door of the façade; the first representing the interior, the second the exterior, of the ancient church.
We can say that the main part of the church is mainly from the eleventh century, with Gothic additions from the fourteenth century and restored mosaics from the seventeenth century. It's easy to tell the Gothic parts apart from the Byzantine ones at a glance, but it's quite challenging to figure out how long, during the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, additions were made to the Byzantine church. These additions can be hard to distinguish from the eleventh-century work because they were intentionally done in the same style. Two key pieces of evidence for this are a mosaic in the south transept and another one over the northern door of the façade; the first shows the interior, while the second shows the exterior of the ancient church.
It has just been stated that the existing building was consecrated by the Doge Vital Falier. A peculiar solemnity was given to that act of consecration, in the minds of the Venetian people, by what appears to have been one of the best arranged and most successful impostures ever attempted by the clergy of the Romish church. The body of St. Mark had, without doubt, perished in the conflagration of 976; but the revenues of the church depended too much upon the devotion excited by these relics to permit the confession of their loss. The following is the account given by Corner, and believed to this day by the Venetians, of the pretended miracle by which it was concealed.
It has just been mentioned that the existing building was consecrated by Doge Vital Falier. The people of Venice attached a special solemnity to that act of consecration, influenced by what seems to have been one of the best orchestrated and most successful deceptions ever attempted by the clergy of the Roman church. The body of St. Mark had undoubtedly been destroyed in the fire of 976; however, the church's income relied heavily on the devotion these relics inspired, so they couldn't admit to their loss. Below is the account provided by Corner, which the Venetians still believe to this day, of the supposed miracle that was used to cover it up.
"After the repairs undertaken by the Doge Orseolo, the place in which the body of the holy Evangelist rested had been altogether forgotten; so that the Doge Vital Falier was entirely ignorant of the place of the venerable deposit. This was no light affliction, not only to the pious Doge, but to all the citizens and people; so that at last, moved by confidence in the Divine mercy, they determined to implore, with prayer and fasting, the manifestation of so great a treasure, which did not now depend upon any human effort. A general fast being therefore proclaimed, and a solemn procession appointed for the 25th day of June, while the people assembled in the church interceded with God in fervent prayers for the desired boon, they beheld, with as much amazement as joy, a slight shaking in the marbles of a pillar (near the place where the altar of the Cross is now), which, presently falling to the earth, exposed to the view of the rejoicing people the chest of bronze in which the body of the Evangelist was laid."
"After the repairs made by Doge Orseolo, the location of the holy Evangelist's body had been completely forgotten; Doge Vital Falier was completely unaware of where the revered remains were. This was a heavy burden, not just for the devout Doge, but for all the citizens and people. Eventually, encouraged by faith in Divine mercy, they decided to earnestly pray and fast, hoping to reveal such a significant treasure, which now relied on no human effort. A general fast was proclaimed, and a solemn procession was scheduled for June 25th. As the people gathered in the church, fervently praying to God for this desired blessing, they saw, with a mix of astonishment and joy, a slight tremor in the marble of a pillar (near where the altar of the Cross is now). This then fell to the ground, revealing to the delighted crowd the bronze chest that contained the body of the Evangelist."
Of the main facts of this tale there is no doubt. They were embellished afterwards, as usual, by many fanciful traditions; as, for instance, that, when the sarcophagus was discovered, St. Mark extended his hand out of it, with a gold ring on one of the fingers, which he permitted a noble of the Dolfin family to remove; and a quaint and delightful story was further invented of this ring, which I shall not repeat here, as it is now as well known as any tale of the Arabian Nights. But the fast and the discovery of the coffin, by whatever means effected, are facts; and they are recorded in one of the best-preserved mosaics of the north[152] transept, executed very certainly not long after the event had taken place, closely resembling in its treatment that of the Bayeux tapestry, and showing, in a conventional manner, the interior of the church, as it then was, filled by the people, first in prayer, then in thanksgiving, the pillar standing open before them, and the Doge, in the midst of them, distinguished by his crimson bonnet embroidered with gold, but more unmistakably by the inscription "Dux" over his head, as uniformly is the case in the Bayeux tapestry, and most other pictorial works of the period. The church is, of course, rudely represented, and the two upper stories of it reduced to a small scale in order to form a background to the figures; one of those bold pieces of picture history which we in our pride of perspective, and a thousand things besides, never dare attempt. We should have put in a column or two, of the real or perspective size, and subdued it into a vague background: the old workman crushed the church together that he might get it all in, up to the cupolas; and has, therefore, left us some useful notes of its ancient form, though any one who is familiar with the method of drawing employed at the period will not push the evidence too far. The two pulpits are there, however, as they are at this day, and the fringe of mosaic flowerwork which then encompassed the whole church, but which modern restorers have destroyed, all but one fragment still left in the south aisle. There is no attempt to represent the other mosaics on the roof, the scale being too small to admit of their being represented with any success; but some at least of those mosaics had been executed at that period, and their absence in the representation of the entire church is especially to be observed, in order to show that we must not trust to any negative evidence in such works. M. Lazari has rashly concluded that the central archivolt of St. Mark's must be posterior to the year 1205, because it does not appear in the representation of the exterior of the church over the northern door;[153] but he justly observes that this mosaic (which is the other piece of evidence we possess respecting the ancient form of the building) cannot itself be earlier than 1205, since it represents the bronze horses which were brought from Constantinople in that year. And this one fact renders it very difficult to speak with confidence respecting the date of any part of the exterior of St. Mark's; for we have above seen that it was consecrated in the eleventh century, and yet here is one of its most important exterior decorations assuredly retouched, if not entirely added, in the thirteenth, although its style would have led us to suppose it had been an original part of the fabric. However, for all our purposes, it will be enough for the reader to remember that the earliest parts of the building belong to the eleventh, twelfth, and first part of the thirteenth century; the Gothic portions to the fourteenth; some of the altars and embellishments to the fifteenth and sixteenth; and the modern portion of the mosaics to the seventeenth.
Of the main facts of this tale there is no doubt. They were embellished afterwards, as usual, by many fanciful traditions; as, for instance, that, when the sarcophagus was discovered, St. Mark extended his hand out of it, with a gold ring on one of the fingers, which he permitted a noble of the Dolfin family to remove; and a quaint and delightful story was further invented of this ring, which I shall not repeat here, as it is now as well known as any tale of the Arabian Nights. But the fast and the discovery of the coffin, by whatever means effected, are facts; and they are recorded in one of the best-preserved mosaics of the north[152] transept, executed very certainly not long after the event had taken place, closely resembling in its treatment that of the Bayeux tapestry, and showing, in a conventional manner, the interior of the church, as it then was, filled by the people, first in prayer, then in thanksgiving, the pillar standing open before them, and the Doge, in the midst of them, distinguished by his crimson bonnet embroidered with gold, but more unmistakably by the inscription "Dux" over his head, as uniformly is the case in the Bayeux tapestry, and most other pictorial works of the period. The church is, of course, rudely represented, and the two upper stories of it reduced to a small scale in order to form a background to the figures; one of those bold pieces of picture history which we in our pride of perspective, and a thousand things besides, never dare attempt. We should have put in a column or two, of the real or perspective size, and subdued it into a vague background: the old workman crushed the church together that he might get it all in, up to the cupolas; and has, therefore, left us some useful notes of its ancient form, though any one who is familiar with the method of drawing employed at the period will not push the evidence too far. The two pulpits are there, however, as they are at this day, and the fringe of mosaic flowerwork which then encompassed the whole church, but which modern restorers have destroyed, all but one fragment still left in the south aisle. There is no attempt to represent the other mosaics on the roof, the scale being too small to admit of their being represented with any success; but some at least of those mosaics had been executed at that period, and their absence in the representation of the entire church is especially to be observed, in order to show that we must not trust to any negative evidence in such works. M. Lazari has rashly concluded that the central archivolt of St. Mark's must be posterior to the year 1205, because it does not appear in the representation of the exterior of the church over the northern door;[153] but he justly observes that this mosaic (which is the other piece of evidence we possess respecting the ancient form of the building) cannot itself be earlier than 1205, since it represents the bronze horses which were brought from Constantinople in that year. And this one fact renders it very difficult to speak with confidence respecting the date of any part of the exterior of St. Mark's; for we have above seen that it was consecrated in the eleventh century, and yet here is one of its most important exterior decorations assuredly retouched, if not entirely added, in the thirteenth, although its style would have led us to suppose it had been an original part of the fabric. However, for all our purposes, it will be enough for the reader to remember that the earliest parts of the building belong to the eleventh, twelfth, and first part of the thirteenth century; the Gothic portions to the fourteenth; some of the altars and embellishments to the fifteenth and sixteenth; and the modern portion of the mosaics to the seventeenth.
This, however, I only wish him to recollect in order that I may speak generally of the Byzantine architecture of St. Mark's, without leading him to suppose the whole church to have been built and decorated by Greek artists. Its later portions, with the single exception of the seventeenth-century mosaics, have been so dexterously accommodated to the original fabric that the general effect is still that of a Byzantine building; and I shall not, except when it is absolutely necessary, direct attention to the discordant points, or weary the reader with anatomical criticism. Whatever in St. Mark's arrests the eye, or affects the feelings, is either Byzantine, or has been modified by Byzantine influence; and our inquiry into its architectural merits need not therefore be disturbed by the anxieties of antiquarianism, or arrested by the obscurities of chronology.
This, however, I just want him to remember so I can talk generally about the Byzantine architecture of St. Mark's, without making him think that Greek artists built and decorated the entire church. Its later parts, with the one exception of the seventeenth-century mosaics, have been so skillfully blended with the original structure that the overall impression still feels like a Byzantine building; and I will only draw attention to the mismatched elements when absolutely necessary, so I don't tire the reader with detailed critiques. Everything in St. Mark's that catches the eye or stirs emotions is either Byzantine or has been influenced by Byzantine styles; and our exploration of its architectural qualities doesn’t need to be interrupted by concerns about antiquity or complicated timelines.
And now I wish that the reader, before I bring him into St. Mark's Place, would imagine himself for a little time in a quiet English cathedral town, and walk with me to the west front of its cathedral. Let us go together up the more retired street, at the end of which we can see the pinnacles of one of the towers, and then through the low grey gateway, with its battlemented top and small latticed window in the centre, into the inner private-looking road or close, where nothing goes in but the carts of the tradesmen who supply the bishop and the chapter, and where there are little shaven grass-plots, fenced in by neat rails, before old-fashioned groups of somewhat diminutive and excessively trim houses, with little oriel and bay windows jutting out here and there, and deep wooden cornices and eaves painted cream colour and white, and small porches to their doors in the shape of cockle-shells, or little, crooked, thick, indescribable wooden gables warped a little on one side; and so forward till we come to larger houses, also old-fashioned, but of red brick, and with gardens behind them, and fruit walls, which show here and there, among the nectarines, the vestiges of an old cloister arch or shaft, and looking in front on the cathedral square itself, laid out in rigid divisions of smooth grass and gravel walk, yet not uncheerful, especially on the sunny side, where the canons' children are walking with their nursery-maids. And so, taking care not to tread on the grass, we will go along the straight walk to the west front, and there stand for a time, looking up at its deep-pointed porches and the dark places between their pillars where there were statues once, and where the fragments, here and there, of a stately figure are still left, which has in it the likeness of a king, perhaps indeed a king on earth, perhaps a saintly king long ago in heaven; and so higher and higher up to the great mouldering wall of rugged sculpture and confused arcades, shattered, and grey, and grisly with heads of dragons and mocking fiends, worn by the rain and swirling winds into yet unseemlier shape, and coloured on their stony scales by the deep russet-orange lichen, melancholy gold; and so, higher still, to the bleak towers, so far above that the eye loses itself among the bosses of their traceries, though they are rude and strong, and only sees like a drift of eddying black points, now closing, now scattering, and now settling suddenly into invisible places among the bosses and flowers, the crowd of restless birds that fill the whole square with that strange clangour of theirs, so harsh and yet so soothing, like the cries of birds on a solitary coast between the cliffs and sea.
And now I would like the reader, before I take him to St. Mark's Place, to picture himself for a moment in a quiet English cathedral town and walk with me to the west front of its cathedral. Let’s stroll together up the quieter street, at the end of which we can see the tops of one of the towers, and then through the low grey gate with its battlemented top and small window in the center, into the private-looking road or close, where only the carts of the tradespeople who supply the bishop and the chapter come in, and where there are little neatly trimmed grass plots fenced in by tidy rails, in front of old-fashioned groups of rather small and extremely neat houses, with little oriel and bay windows sticking out here and there, and deep wooden cornices and eaves painted cream and white, along with small porches to their doors shaped like cockle-shells, or little, crooked, thick wooden gables warped a bit to one side; and so we move forward until we reach larger houses, also old-fashioned but made of red brick, with gardens behind them, and fruit walls, which display, here and there, among the nectarines, remnants of an old cloister arch or shaft, looking directly onto the cathedral square itself, arranged in strict divisions of smooth grass and gravel paths, yet not gloomy, especially on the sunny side where the canons' children are strolling with their nannies. Taking care not to step on the grass, we will walk along the straight path to the west front and stand there for a while, looking up at its pointed porches and the dark spaces between their pillars where statues once stood, and where fragments of a grand figure still remain, which resembles a king, perhaps a king from the past on earth, or maybe a saintly king long ago in heaven; and then higher and higher up to the great crumbling wall of rough sculptures and confused archways, battered, grey, and grimy with dragon heads and mocking fiends, worn by rain and swirling winds into even stranger shapes, and colored on their stony scales by deep russet-orange lichen, like sad gold; and even higher still, to the stark towers, so far above that the eye gets lost among the intricacies of their designs, though they are crude and strong, and only sees a swirl of drifting black dots, now gathering, now scattering, and now suddenly settling into hidden places among the intricate designs and flowers, the mass of restless birds that fill the whole square with their strange noise, harsh yet soothing, like the calls of birds on a lonely coast between cliffs and sea.
Think for a little while of that scene, and the meaning of all its small formalisms, mixed with its serene sublimity. Estimate its secluded, continuous, drowsy felicities, and its evidence of the sense and steady performance of such kind of duties as can be regulated by the cathedral clock; and weigh the influence of those dark towers on all who have passed through the lonely square at their feet for centuries, and on all who have seen them rising far away over the wooded plain, or catching on their square masses the last rays of the sunset, when the city at their feet was indicated only by the mist at the bend of the river. And then let us quickly recollect that we are in Venice, and land at the extremity of the Calla Lunga San Moisè, which may be considered as there answering to the secluded street that led us to our English cathedral gateway.
Think for a moment about that scene, and the meaning behind all its little formalities, mixed with its calm grandeur. Consider its quiet, constant, dreamy joys, and its reflection of the sensible and steady performance of duties that can be timed by the cathedral clock; and think about the impact of those dark towers on everyone who has walked through the lonely square at their base for centuries, and on everyone who has seen them rising far away over the wooded landscape, or catching the last rays of sunset on their solid forms, when the city below was only marked by the mist at the river’s bend. And then let's quickly remember that we are in Venice, standing at the end of the Calla Lunga San Moisè, which can be seen as the equivalent of the secluded street that led us to our English cathedral entrance.
We find ourselves in a paved alley, some seven feet wide where it is widest, full of people, and resonant with cries of itinerant salesmen,—a shriek in their beginning, and dying away into a kind of brazen ringing, all the worse for its confinement between the high houses of the passage along which we have to make our way. Over-head, an inextricable confusion of rugged shutters, and iron balconies and chimney flues, pushed out on brackets to save room, and arched windows with projecting sills of Istrian stone, and gleams of green leaves here and there where a fig-tree branch escapes over a lower wall from some inner cortile, leading the eye up to the narrow stream of blue sky high over all. On each side, a row of shops, as densely set as may be, occupying, in fact, intervals between the square stone shafts, about eight feet high, which carry the first floors: intervals of which one is narrow and serves as a door; the other is, in the more respectable shops, wainscotted to the height of the counter and glazed above, but in those of the poorer tradesmen left open to the ground, and the wares laid on benches and tables in the open air, the light in all cases entering at the front only, and fading away in a few feet from the threshold into a gloom which the eye from without cannot penetrate, but which is generally broken by a ray or two from a feeble lamp at the back of the shop, suspended before a print of the Virgin. The less pious shopkeeper sometimes leaves his lamp unlighted, and is contented with a penny print; the more religious one has his print coloured and set in a little shrine with a gilded or figured fringe, with perhaps a faded flower or two on each side, and his lamp burning brilliantly. Here, at the fruiterer's, where the dark-green water-melons are heaped upon the counter like cannon balls, the Madonna has a tabernacle of fresh laurel leaves; but the pewterer next door has let his lamp out, and there is nothing to be seen in his shop but the dull gleam of the studded patterns on the copper pans, hanging from his roof in the darkness. Next comes a "Vendita Frittole e Liquori,"[154] where the Virgin, enthroned in a very humble manner beside a tallow candle on a back shelf, presides over certain ambrosial morsels of a nature too ambiguous to be defined or enumerated. But a few steps farther on, at the regular wine-shop of the calle, where we are offered "Vino Nostrani a Soldi 28-32," the Madonna is in great glory, enthroned above ten or a dozen large red casks of three-year-old vintage, and flanked by goodly ranks of bottles of Maraschino, and two crimson lamps; and for the evening, when the gondoliers will come to drink out, under her auspices, the money they have gained during the day, she will have a whole chandelier.
We find ourselves in a paved alley, some seven feet wide where it is widest, full of people, and resonant with cries of itinerant salesmen,—a shriek in their beginning, and dying away into a kind of brazen ringing, all the worse for its confinement between the high houses of the passage along which we have to make our way. Over-head, an inextricable confusion of rugged shutters, and iron balconies and chimney flues, pushed out on brackets to save room, and arched windows with projecting sills of Istrian stone, and gleams of green leaves here and there where a fig-tree branch escapes over a lower wall from some inner cortile, leading the eye up to the narrow stream of blue sky high over all. On each side, a row of shops, as densely set as may be, occupying, in fact, intervals between the square stone shafts, about eight feet high, which carry the first floors: intervals of which one is narrow and serves as a door; the other is, in the more respectable shops, wainscotted to the height of the counter and glazed above, but in those of the poorer tradesmen left open to the ground, and the wares laid on benches and tables in the open air, the light in all cases entering at the front only, and fading away in a few feet from the threshold into a gloom which the eye from without cannot penetrate, but which is generally broken by a ray or two from a feeble lamp at the back of the shop, suspended before a print of the Virgin. The less pious shopkeeper sometimes leaves his lamp unlighted, and is contented with a penny print; the more religious one has his print coloured and set in a little shrine with a gilded or figured fringe, with perhaps a faded flower or two on each side, and his lamp burning brilliantly. Here, at the fruiterer's, where the dark-green water-melons are heaped upon the counter like cannon balls, the Madonna has a tabernacle of fresh laurel leaves; but the pewterer next door has let his lamp out, and there is nothing to be seen in his shop but the dull gleam of the studded patterns on the copper pans, hanging from his roof in the darkness. Next comes a "Vendita Frittole e Liquori,"[154] where the Virgin, enthroned in a very humble manner beside a tallow candle on a back shelf, presides over certain ambrosial morsels of a nature too ambiguous to be defined or enumerated. But a few steps farther on, at the regular wine-shop of the calle, where we are offered "Vino Nostrani a Soldi 28-32," the Madonna is in great glory, enthroned above ten or a dozen large red casks of three-year-old vintage, and flanked by goodly ranks of bottles of Maraschino, and two crimson lamps; and for the evening, when the gondoliers will come to drink out, under her auspices, the money they have gained during the day, she will have a whole chandelier.
A yard or two farther, we pass the hostelry of the Black Eagle, and, glancing as we pass through the square door of marble, deeply moulded, in the outer wall, we see the shadows of its pergola of vines resting on an ancient well, with a pointed shield carved on its side; and so presently emerge on the bridge and Campo San Moisè, whence to the entrance into St. Mark's Place, called the Bocca di Piazza (mouth of the square), the Venetian character is nearly destroyed, first by the frightful facade of San Moisè, which we will pause at another time to examine, and then by the modernizing of the shops as they near the piazza, and the mingling with the lower Venetian populace of lounging groups of English and Austrians. We will push fast through them into the shadow of the pillars at the end of the "Bocca di Piazza," and then we forget them all; for between those pillars there opens a great light, and, in the midst of it, as we advance slowly, the vast tower of St. Mark seems to lift itself visibly forth from the level field of chequered stones; and, on each side, the countless arches prolong themselves into ranged symmetry, as if the rugged and irregular houses that pressed together above us in the dark alley had been struck back into sudden obedience and lovely order, and all their rude casements and broken walls had been transformed into arches charged with goodly sculpture, and fluted shafts of delicate stone.
A yard or two further, we pass the inn of the Black Eagle, and, glancing as we go through the square, deeply carved marble door in the outer wall, we see the shadows of its vine-covered pergola resting on an ancient well, with a pointed shield carved on its side; and soon we emerge onto the bridge and Campo San Moisè, where the entrance to St. Mark's Place, called the Bocca di Piazza (mouth of the square), starts to lose its Venetian character, first because of the hideous facade of San Moisè, which we’ll take a closer look at another time, and then because of the modernization of the shops as they approach the piazza, mixed with groups of English and Austrians lounging among the local Venetian crowds. We’ll quickly push through them into the shadows of the pillars at the end of the "Bocca di Piazza," and then we forget them all; for between those pillars, a great light opens up, and, as we move forward slowly, the towering St. Mark's bell tower seems to rise visibly from the patterned stones below; and on either side, the countless arches extend into neat symmetry, as if the rough and irregular houses that crowded above us in the dark alley had been pushed back into sudden order and beauty, transforming all their shabby windows and crumbling walls into arches adorned with beautiful sculptures and slender stone columns.
And well may they fall back, for beyond those troops of ordered arches there rises a vision out of the earth, and all the great square seems to have opened from it in a kind of awe, that we may see it far away;—a multitude of pillars and white domes, clustered into a long low pyramid of coloured light; a treasure-heap, it seems, partly of gold, and partly of opal and mother-of-pearl, hollowed beneath into five great vaulted porches, ceiled with fair mosaic, and beset with sculpture of alabaster, clear as amber and delicate as ivory,—sculpture fantastic and involved, of palm leaves and lilies, and grapes and pomegranates, and birds clinging and fluttering among the branches, all twined together into an endless network of buds and plumes; and, in the midst of it, the solemn forms of angels, sceptred, and robed to the feet, and leaning to each other across the gates, their figures indistinct among the gleaming of the golden ground through the leaves beside them, interrupted and dim, like the morning light as it faded back among the branches of Eden, when first its gates were angel-guarded long ago. And round the walls of the porches there are set pillars of variegated stones, jasper and porphyry, and deep-green serpentine spotted with flakes of snow, and marbles, that half refuse and half yield to the sunshine, Cleopatra-like, "their bluest veins to kiss"[155]—the shadow, as it steals back from them, revealing line after line of azure undulation, as a receding tide leaves the waved sand; their capitals rich with interwoven tracery, rooted knots of herbage, and drifting leaves of acanthus and vine, and mystical signs, all beginning and ending in the Cross; and above them, in the broad archivolts, a continuous chain of language and of life—angels, and the signs of heaven, and the labours of men, each in its appointed season upon the earth; and above these, another range of glittering pinnacles, mixed with white arches edged with scarlet flowers,—a confusion of delight, amidst which the breasts of the Greek horses are seen blazing in their breadth of golden strength, and the St. Mark's Lion, lifted on a blue field covered with stars, until at last, as if in ecstasy, the crests of the arches break into a marble foam, and toss themselves far into the blue sky in flashes and wreaths of sculptured spray, as if the breakers on the Lido shore had been frost-bound before they fell, and the sea-nymphs had inlaid them with coral and amethyst.
And well may they fall back, for beyond those troops of ordered arches there rises a vision out of the earth, and all the great square seems to have opened from it in a kind of awe, that we may see it far away;—a multitude of pillars and white domes, clustered into a long low pyramid of coloured light; a treasure-heap, it seems, partly of gold, and partly of opal and mother-of-pearl, hollowed beneath into five great vaulted porches, ceiled with fair mosaic, and beset with sculpture of alabaster, clear as amber and delicate as ivory,—sculpture fantastic and involved, of palm leaves and lilies, and grapes and pomegranates, and birds clinging and fluttering among the branches, all twined together into an endless network of buds and plumes; and, in the midst of it, the solemn forms of angels, sceptred, and robed to the feet, and leaning to each other across the gates, their figures indistinct among the gleaming of the golden ground through the leaves beside them, interrupted and dim, like the morning light as it faded back among the branches of Eden, when first its gates were angel-guarded long ago. And round the walls of the porches there are set pillars of variegated stones, jasper and porphyry, and deep-green serpentine spotted with flakes of snow, and marbles, that half refuse and half yield to the sunshine, Cleopatra-like, "their bluest veins to kiss"[155]—the shadow, as it steals back from them, revealing line after line of azure undulation, as a receding tide leaves the waved sand; their capitals rich with interwoven tracery, rooted knots of herbage, and drifting leaves of acanthus and vine, and mystical signs, all beginning and ending in the Cross; and above them, in the broad archivolts, a continuous chain of language and of life—angels, and the signs of heaven, and the labours of men, each in its appointed season upon the earth; and above these, another range of glittering pinnacles, mixed with white arches edged with scarlet flowers,—a confusion of delight, amidst which the breasts of the Greek horses are seen blazing in their breadth of golden strength, and the St. Mark's Lion, lifted on a blue field covered with stars, until at last, as if in ecstasy, the crests of the arches break into a marble foam, and toss themselves far into the blue sky in flashes and wreaths of sculptured spray, as if the breakers on the Lido shore had been frost-bound before they fell, and the sea-nymphs had inlaid them with coral and amethyst.
Between that grim cathedral of England and this, what an interval! There is a type of it in the very birds that haunt them; for, instead of the restless crowd, hoarse-voiced and sable-winged, drifting on the bleak upper air, the St. Mark's porches are full of doves, that nestle among the marble foliage, and mingle the soft iridescence of their living plumes, changing at every motion, with the tints, hardly less lovely, that have stood unchanged for seven hundred years.
Between that stark cathedral in England and this one, what a contrast! You can even see it in the birds that hang around; instead of the restless crowd, loud and dark-winged, moving in the cold sky, the porches of St. Mark's are filled with doves that snuggle among the marble leaves. Their soft, shimmering feathers change with every movement, blending with the colors, which are almost as beautiful, that have remained the same for seven hundred years.
And what effect has this splendour on those who pass beneath it? You may walk from sunrise to sunset, to and fro, before the gateway of St. Mark's, and you will not see an eye lifted to it, nor a countenance brightened by it. Priest and layman, soldier and civilian, rich and poor, pass by it alike regardlessly. Up to the very recesses of the porches, the meanest tradesmen of the city push their counters; nay, the foundations of its pillars are themselves the seats—not "of them that sell doves"[156] for sacrifice, but of the vendors of toys and caricatures. Round the whole square in front of the church there is almost a continuous line of cafés, where the idle Venetians of the middle classes lounge, and read empty journals; in its centre the Austrian bands play during the time of vespers, their martial music jarring with the organ notes,—the march drowning the miserere, and the sullen crowd thickening round them,—a crowd, which, if it had its will, would stiletto every soldier that pipes to it. And in the recesses of the porches, all day long, knots of men of the lowest classes, unemployed and listless, lie basking in the sun like lizards; and unregarded children,—every heavy glance of their young eyes full of desperation and stony depravity, and their throats hoarse with cursing,—gamble, and fight, and snarl, and sleep, hour after hour, clashing their bruised centesimi upon the marble ledges of the church porch. And the images of Christ and His angels look down upon it continually.
And what effect has this splendour on those who pass beneath it? You may walk from sunrise to sunset, to and fro, before the gateway of St. Mark's, and you will not see an eye lifted to it, nor a countenance brightened by it. Priest and layman, soldier and civilian, rich and poor, pass by it alike regardlessly. Up to the very recesses of the porches, the meanest tradesmen of the city push their counters; nay, the foundations of its pillars are themselves the seats—not "of them that sell doves"[156] for sacrifice, but of the vendors of toys and caricatures. Round the whole square in front of the church there is almost a continuous line of cafés, where the idle Venetians of the middle classes lounge, and read empty journals; in its centre the Austrian bands play during the time of vespers, their martial music jarring with the organ notes,—the march drowning the miserere, and the sullen crowd thickening round them,—a crowd, which, if it had its will, would stiletto every soldier that pipes to it. And in the recesses of the porches, all day long, knots of men of the lowest classes, unemployed and listless, lie basking in the sun like lizards; and unregarded children,—every heavy glance of their young eyes full of desperation and stony depravity, and their throats hoarse with cursing,—gamble, and fight, and snarl, and sleep, hour after hour, clashing their bruised centesimi upon the marble ledges of the church porch. And the images of Christ and His angels look down upon it continually.
CHARACTERISTICS OF GOTHIC ARCHITECTURE
VOLUME II, CHAPTER 6
I believe, then, that the characteristic or moral elements of Gothic are the following, placed in the order of their importance:
I believe that the key moral elements of Gothic literature are as follows, listed in order of importance:
- 1. Savageness.
- 2. Changefulness.
- 3. Naturalism.
- 4. Grotesqueness.
- 5. Rigidity.
- 6. Redundance.
These characters are here expressed as belonging to the building; as belonging to the builder, they would be expressed thus:—1. Savageness, or Rudeness. 2. Love of Change. 3. Love of Nature. 4. Disturbed Imagination. 5. Obstinacy. 6. Generosity. And I repeat, that the withdrawal of any one, or any two, will not at once destroy the Gothic character of a building, but the removal of a majority of them will. I shall proceed to examine them in their order.
These traits are shown to be part of the building; if they were associated with the builder, they would be described as follows: 1. Savageness, or Rudeness. 2. Love of Change. 3. Love of Nature. 4. Disturbed Imagination. 5. Obstinacy. 6. Generosity. And I emphasize that removing any one or two of these traits won’t immediately eliminate the Gothic character of a building, but getting rid of most of them will. I will now discuss them in order.
1. SAVAGENESS. I am not sure when the word "Gothic" was first generically applied to the architecture of the North; but I presume that, whatever the date of its original usage, it was intended to imply reproach, and express the barbaric character of the nations among whom that architecture arose. It never implied that they were literally of Gothic lineage, far less that their architecture had been originally invented by the Goths themselves; but it did imply that they and their buildings together exhibited a degree of sternness and rudeness, which, in contradistinction to the character of Southern and Eastern nations, appeared like a perpetual reflection of the contrast between the Goth and the Roman in their first encounter. And when that fallen Roman, in the utmost impotence of his luxury, and insolence of his guilt, became the model for the imitation of civilized Europe, at the close of the so-called Dark Ages, the word Gothic became a term of unmitigated contempt, not unmixed with aversion. From that contempt, by the exertion of the antiquaries and architects of this century, Gothic architecture has been sufficiently vindicated; and perhaps some among us, in our admiration of the magnificent science of its structure, and sacredness of its expression, might desire that the term of ancient reproach should be withdrawn, and some other, of more apparent honourableness, adopted in its place. There is no chance, as there is no need, of such a substitution. As far as the epithet was used scornfully, it was used falsely; but there is no reproach in the word, rightly understood; on the contrary, there is a profound truth, which the instinct of mankind almost unconsciously recognizes. It is true, greatly and deeply true, that the architecture of the North is rude and wild; but it is not true, that, for this reason, we are to condemn it, or despise. Far otherwise: I believe it is in this very character that it deserves our profoundest reverence.
1. SAVAGENESS. I’m not sure when the term "Gothic" was first used to describe the architecture of the North, but I think that, regardless of when it was first used, it was meant to imply criticism and reflect the savage nature of the people where that architecture developed. It didn’t mean that they were literally of Gothic descent, let alone that the Goths invented this style of architecture themselves; instead, it suggested that they and their buildings shared a certain severity and roughness, which starkly contrasted with the cultures of the South and East. This contrast seemed like a lasting reminder of the clash between the Goths and the Romans when they first met. When the weakened Roman, in the peak of his luxury and the arrogance of his guilt, became the model for civilized Europe at the end of the so-called Dark Ages, "Gothic" became a term of complete disdain, mixed with some repulsion. Thanks to the efforts of scholars and architects of this century, Gothic architecture has been well defended; and perhaps some of us, in our admiration for the stunning complexity of its design and the sacredness of its function, might wish the old term of criticism to be replaced with something more dignified. However, there’s no possibility, nor necessity, for such a change. While it was used mockingly, that usage was incorrect; but the term carries no shame when understood correctly. Rather, there is a deep truth that people instinctively recognize. It is indeed true, profoundly true, that Northern architecture is rough and untamed; but that doesn’t mean we should reject or look down on it. On the contrary, I believe it is precisely this quality that earns it our deepest respect.
The charts of the world which have been drawn up by modern science have thrown into a narrow space the expression of a vast amount of knowledge, but I have never yet seen any one pictorial enough to enable the spectator to imagine the kind of contrast in physical character which exists between Northern and Southern countries. We know the differences in detail, but we have not that broad glance and grasp which would enable us to feel them in their fulness. We know that gentians grow on the Alps, and olives on the Apennines; but we do not enough conceive for ourselves that variegated mosaic of the world's surface which a bird sees in its migration, that difference between the district of the gentian and of the olive which the stork and the swallow see far off, as they lean upon the sirocco wind. Let us, for a moment, try to raise ourselves even above the level of their flight, and imagine the Mediterranean lying beneath us like an irregular lake, and all its ancient promontories sleeping in the sun: here and there an angry spot of thunder, a grey stain of storm, moving upon the burning field; and here and there a fixed wreath of white volcano smoke, surrounded by its circle of ashes; but for the most part a great peacefulness of light, Syria and Greece, Italy and Spain, laid like pieces of a golden pavement into the sea-blue, chased, as we stoop nearer to them, with bossy beaten work of mountain chains, and glowing softly with terraced gardens, and flowers heavy with frankincense, mixed among masses of laurel, and orange, and plumy palm, that abate with their grey-green shadows the burning of the marble rocks, and of the ledges of porphyry sloping under lucent sand. Then let us pass farther towards the north, until we see the orient colours change gradually into a vast belt of rainy green, where the pastures of Switzerland, and poplar valleys of France, and dark forests of the Danube and Carpathians stretch from the mouths of the Loire to those of the Volga, seen through clefts in grey swirls of rain-cloud and flaky veils of the mist of the brooks, spreading low along the pasture lands: and then, farther north still, to see the earth heave into mighty masses of leaden rock and heathy moor, bordering with a broad waste of gloomy purple that belt of field and wood, and splintering into irregular and grisly islands amidst the northern seas, beaten by storm, and chilled by ice-drift, and tormented by furious pulses of contending tide, until the roots of the last forests fail from among the hill ravines, and the hunger of the north wind bites their peaks into barrenness; and, at last, the wall of ice, durable like iron, sets, deathlike, its white teeth against us out of the polar twilight. And, having once traversed in thought this gradation of the zoned iris of the earth in all its material vastness, let us go down nearer to it, and watch the parallel change in the belt of animal life; the multitudes of swift and brilliant creatures that glance in the air and sea, or tread the sands of the southern zone; striped zebras and spotted leopards, glistening serpents, and birds arrayed in purple and scarlet. Let us contrast their delicacy and brilliancy of colour, and swiftness of motion, with the frost-cramped strength, and shaggy covering, and dusky plumage of the northern tribes; contrast the Arabian horse with the Shetland, the tiger and leopard with the wolf and bear, the antelope with the elk, the bird of paradise with the osprey: and then, submissively acknowledging the great laws by which the earth and all that it bears are ruled throughout their being. Let us not condemn, but rejoice in the expression by man of his own rest in the statutes of the lands that gave him birth. Let us watch him with reverence as he sets side by side the burning gems, and smooths with soft sculpture the jasper pillars, that are to reflect a ceaseless sunshine, and rise into a cloudless sky: but not with less reverence let us stand by him, when, with rough strength and hurried stroke, he smites an uncouth animation out of the rocks which he has torn from among the moss of the moorland, and heaves into the darkened air the pile of iron buttress and rugged wall, instinct with work of an imagination as wild and wayward as the northern sea; creations of ungainly shape and rigid limb, but full of wolfish life; fierce as the winds that beat, and changeful as the clouds that shade them.
The maps of the world created by modern science have compacted an immense amount of knowledge into a small space, but I've yet to see any representation vivid enough to help viewers grasp the stark contrast in physical characteristics between Northern and Southern countries. We’re aware of the specific differences, but we lack that broader perspective that would allow us to fully experience them. We know that gentians flourish in the Alps and olives thrive in the Apennines, but we don’t fully visualize that vibrant mosaic of the Earth's surface that a bird observes during migration, the distinction between the gentian's region and the olive's, which storks and swallows perceive from afar as they ride the sirocco wind. Let’s take a moment to imagine ourselves soaring above their flight, viewing the Mediterranean as an uneven lake, with its ancient promontories basking in sunlight: occasionally, a dark storm cloud looms, and patches of grey indicate a brewing tempest on the sunlit landscape; sporadically, a fixed, white plume of volcanic smoke rises among its circle of ashes. Yet mostly, there’s a stunning tranquility of light, with Syria, Greece, Italy, and Spain appearing as pieces of a golden mosaic cast into the sea-blue, intricately patterned as we draw nearer, with rugged mountain ranges glowing softly, terraced gardens adorned with fragrant flowers, and masses of laurel, orange trees, and feathery palms that temper the heat of the marble rocks and the slopes of porphyry beneath the clear sands. Then, let’s venture further north to witness the transition of colors into a vast expanse of rainy green, where the pastoral landscapes of Switzerland, the poplar valleys of France, and the dark forests of the Danube and Carpathians stretch from the Loire’s mouth to those of the Volga, seen through gaps in grey rain clouds and thin streams of mist floating over meadows. Continuing farther north, we’ll see the land rise into massive, leaden rock formations and heathy moors, bordered by a broad swath of gloomy purple that fringes fields and woods, fracturing into jagged, grim islands in the northern seas, battered by storms, chilled by ice, and twisted by the furious eddies of competing tides until the last trees vanish from the hill ravines, and the harsh north wind strips their peaks bare. Eventually, we encounter an ice barrier, as unyielding as iron, jutting out like a white-toothed grimace from the dim polar twilight. After traversing in thought this gradient of the Earth’s colorful zones in all their material grandeur, let’s draw closer and observe the parallel shifts in the realm of animal life; the flocks of swift, bright creatures that flit through the air and sea or tread the sands of the southern zone—striped zebras and spotted leopards, shimmering snakes, and birds dressed in purple and scarlet. Let’s compare their delicate brilliance and swift movements against the frost-hardened strength, shaggy coats, and dark feathers of the northern inhabitants; juxtapose the Arabian horse with the Shetland, the tiger and leopard with the wolf and bear, the antelope with the elk, the bird of paradise with the osprey: and then, with humility, accept the great laws that govern the Earth and all it harbors. Let’s not condemn but celebrate humanity’s expression of its own comfort in the customs of the lands that nurtured it. Let’s watch with reverence as humans juxtapose radiant gems, refining the jasper pillars meant to reflect enduring sunshine and rise toward an unclouded sky; but with equal reverence, let’s stand by as they passionately carve rough shapes from rocks pulled from the moorland moss, lifting into the shadowy air heavy iron structures and sturdy walls, infused with a creativity as wild and unpredictable as the northern sea; creations with awkward forms and stiff limbs, yet brimming with fierce vitality; as wild as the winds that ravage them and ever-changing like the clouds that cast their shadows.
There is, I repeat, no degradation, no reproach in this, but all dignity and honourableness: and we should err grievously in refusing either to recognize as an essential character of the existing architecture of the North, or to admit as a desirable character in that which it yet may be, this wildness of thought, and roughness of work; this look of mountain brotherhood between the cathedral and the Alp; this magnificence of sturdy power, put forth only the more energetically because the fine finger-touch was chilled away by the frosty wind, and the eye dimmed by the moor-mist, or blinded by the hail; this outspeaking of the strong spirit of men who may not gather redundant fruitage from the earth, nor bask in dreamy benignity of sunshine, but must break the rock for bread, and cleave the forest for fire, and show, even in what they did for their delight, some of the hard habits of the arm and heart that grew on them as they swung the axe or pressed the plough.
There is, I repeat, no shame or blame in this, but all dignity and honor: and we would be making a serious mistake in refusing to acknowledge, as an essential trait of the current architecture of the North, or to accept as a desirable quality in what it could still become, this wildness of thought and roughness of work; this connection of mountain camaraderie between the cathedral and the Alps; this grandeur of robust strength, made even more impressive because the delicate touch was lost to the chilling wind, and the vision obscured by the moor mist, or blinded by the hail; this expression of the resilient spirit of people who may not harvest abundant fruits from the land, nor enjoy the soothing warmth of sunshine, but must break the rock for bread, and clear the forest for fire, and show, even in what they did for pleasure, some of the tough habits of the body and heart that developed as they swung the axe or worked the plow.
If, however, the savageness of Gothic architecture, merely as an expression of its origin among Northern nations, may be considered, in some sort, a noble character, it possesses a higher nobility still, when considered as an index, not of climate, but of religious principle.
If we think about the roughness of Gothic architecture, which reflects its roots in Northern cultures, it can be seen as having a certain nobility. However, it has an even greater nobility when seen as a reflection of religious values rather than just climate.
In the 13th and 14th paragraphs of Chapter XXL of the first volume of this work, it was noticed that the systems of architectural ornament, properly so called, might be divided into three:—1. Servile ornament, in which the execution or power of the inferior workman is entirely subjected to the intellect of the higher;—2. Constitutional ornament, in which the executive inferior power is, to a certain point, emancipated and independent, having a will of its own, yet confessing its inferiority and rendering obedience to higher powers;—and 3. Revolutionary ornament, in which no executive inferiority is admitted at all. I must here explain the nature of these divisions at somewhat greater length.
In the 13th and 14th paragraphs of Chapter XXL of the first volume of this work, it was noted that the systems of architectural ornament can be divided into three types: 1. Servile ornament, where the skills of the lower worker are completely controlled by the intellect of the higher one; 2. Constitutional ornament, where the lower worker has some degree of independence and a will of its own, while still acknowledging its inferiority and obeying the higher powers; and 3. Revolutionary ornament, which allows for no acknowledgment of inferior execution at all. I need to explain these categories in a bit more detail.
Of Servile ornament, the principal schools are the Greek, Ninevite, and Egyptian; but their servility is of different kinds. The Greek master-workman was far advanced in knowledge and power above the Assyrian or Egyptian. Neither he nor those for whom he worked could endure the appearance of imperfection in anything; and, therefore, what ornament he appointed to be done by those beneath him was composed of mere geometrical forms,—balls, ridges, and perfectly symmetrical foliage,—which could be executed with absolute precision by line and rule, and were as perfect in their way, when completed, as his own figure sculpture. The Assyrian and Egyptian, on the contrary, less cognizant of accurate form in anything, were content to allow their figure sculpture to be executed by inferior workmen, but lowered the method of its treatment to a standard which every workman could reach, and then trained him by discipline so rigid, that there was no chance of his falling beneath the standard appointed. The Greek gave to the lower workman no subject which he could not perfectly execute. The Assyrian gave him subjects which he could only execute imperfectly, but fixed a legal standard for his imperfection. The workman was, in both systems, a slave.[157]
Of Servile ornament, the principal schools are the Greek, Ninevite, and Egyptian; but their servility is of different kinds. The Greek master-workman was far advanced in knowledge and power above the Assyrian or Egyptian. Neither he nor those for whom he worked could endure the appearance of imperfection in anything; and, therefore, what ornament he appointed to be done by those beneath him was composed of mere geometrical forms,—balls, ridges, and perfectly symmetrical foliage,—which could be executed with absolute precision by line and rule, and were as perfect in their way, when completed, as his own figure sculpture. The Assyrian and Egyptian, on the contrary, less cognizant of accurate form in anything, were content to allow their figure sculpture to be executed by inferior workmen, but lowered the method of its treatment to a standard which every workman could reach, and then trained him by discipline so rigid, that there was no chance of his falling beneath the standard appointed. The Greek gave to the lower workman no subject which he could not perfectly execute. The Assyrian gave him subjects which he could only execute imperfectly, but fixed a legal standard for his imperfection. The workman was, in both systems, a slave.[157]
But in the mediæval, or especially Christian, system of ornament, this slavery is done away with altogether; Christianity having recognized, in small things as well as great, the individual value of every soul. But it not only recognizes its value; it confesses its imperfection, in only bestowing dignity upon the acknowledgment of unworthiness. That admission of lost power and fallen nature, which the Greek or Ninevite felt to be intensely painful, and, as far as might be, altogether refused, the Christian makes daily and hourly contemplating the fact of it without fear, as tending, in the end, to God's greater glory. Therefore, to every spirit which Christianity summons to her service, her exhortation is: Do what you can, and confess frankly what you are unable to do; neither let your effort be shortened for fear of failure, nor your confession silenced for fear of shame. And it is, perhaps, the principal admirableness of the Gothic schools of architecture, that they thus receive the results of the labour of inferior minds; and out of fragments full of imperfection, and betraying that imperfection in every touch, indulgently raise up a stately and unaccusable whole.
But in the medieval, or especially Christian, approach to decoration, this bondage is completely eliminated; Christianity has recognized, in both small and large matters, the individual value of every soul. It not only acknowledges this value; it admits imperfection by granting dignity to the acknowledgment of unworthiness. The recognition of lost power and fallen nature, which the Greeks or Ninevites found to be intensely painful and, as much as possible, denied, is something the Christian faces daily and hourly without fear, seeing it as ultimately leading to God's greater glory. Therefore, to every spirit that Christianity calls to serve, its message is: Do what you can, and honestly admit what you can't do; let your efforts not be limited by the fear of failure, nor your admissions silenced by the fear of shame. Perhaps the most admirable aspect of Gothic architecture is that it embraces the results of the work of lesser minds, and with fragments full of imperfection, openly displaying that imperfection in every detail, it gracefully elevates them into a magnificent and faultless whole.
But the modern English mind has this much in common with that of the Greek, that it intensely desires, in all things, the utmost completion or perfection compatible with their nature. This is a noble character in the abstract, but becomes ignoble when it causes us to forget the relative dignities of that nature itself, and to prefer the perfectness of the lower nature to the imperfection of the higher; not considering that as, judged by such a rule, all the brute animals would be preferable to man, because more perfect in their functions and kind, and yet are always held inferior to him, so also in the works of man, those which are more perfect in their kind are always inferior to those which are, in their nature, liable to more faults and shortcomings. For the finer the nature, the more flaws it will show through the clearness of it; and it is a law of this universe, that the best things shall be seldomest seen in their best form. The wild grass grows well and strongly, one year with another; but the wheat is, according to the greater nobleness of its nature, liable to the bitterer blight. And therefore, while in all things that we see or do, we are to desire perfection, and strive for it, we are nevertheless not to set the meaner thing, in its narrow accomplishment, above the nobler thing, in its mighty progress; not to esteem smooth minuteness above shattered majesty; not to prefer mean victory to honourable defeat; not to lower the level of our aim, that we may the more surely enjoy the complacency of success. But, above all, in our dealings with the souls of other men, we are to take care how we check, by severe requirement or narrow caution, efforts which might otherwise lead to a noble issue; and, still more, how we withhold our admiration from great excellencies, because they are mingled with rough faults. Now, in the make and nature of every man, however rude or simple, whom we employ in manual labour, there are some powers for better things: some tardy imagination, torpid capacity of emotion, tottering steps of thought, there are, even at the worst; and in most cases it is all our own fault that they are tardy or torpid. But they cannot be strengthened, unless we are content to take them in their feebleness, and unless we prize and honour them in their imperfection above the best and most perfect manual skill. And this is what we have to do with all our labourers; to look for the thoughtful part of them, and get that out of them, whatever we lose for it, whatever faults and errors we are obliged to take with it. For the best that is in them cannot manifest itself, but in company with much error. Understand this clearly; You can teach a man to draw a straight line, and to cut one; to strike a curved line, and to carve it; and to copy and carve any number of given lines or forms, with admirable speed and perfect precision; and you find his work perfect of its kind: but if you ask him to think about any of those forms, to consider if he cannot find any better in his own head, he stops; his execution becomes hesitating; he thinks, and ten to one he thinks wrong; ten to one he makes a mistake in the first touch he gives to his work as a thinking being. But you have made a man of him for all that. He was only a machine before, an animated tool.
But the modern English mind shares this with the Greek mind: it intensely seeks perfection or completion in everything, as much as their nature allows. This is a noble trait in theory, but it becomes less admirable when it makes us forget the relative values of that nature itself, leading us to favor the perfection of a lower nature over the imperfections of a higher one. We overlook that, based on this reasoning, all animals would be deemed superior to humans because they perform their functions more perfectly; yet they are consistently viewed as inferior. Similarly, in human creations, those that are more perfect in their specific kind often fall short compared to those that, by their nature, are prone to more faults and limitations. The finer the nature, the more flaws will show through its clarity; it's a law of the universe that the best things are rarely seen in their best form. Wild grass grows robustly every year, but wheat, due to its higher nature, is more susceptible to harsher blights. Therefore, while we should seek and strive for perfection in all we see and do, we should not regard the lesser thing, with its limited achievements, as superior to the greater thing, with its significant progress; we shouldn't value smooth triviality over shattered greatness, or prefer a minor victory to an honorable defeat; we shouldn’t lower our ambitions just to feel the ease of success. Above all, in our interactions with others' souls, we must be cautious how we hinder, through strict demands or narrow caution, efforts that could lead to something truly noble; and, even more importantly, we should not withhold our admiration from great qualities simply because they are mixed with rough flaws. Within every person, no matter how crude or simple, whom we engage for manual work, there are some capabilities for greater things: some slow imagination, dormant emotions, hesitating thoughts, even at their worst; and in most instances, it’s our fault that they are slow or dormant. But these qualities can’t be nurtured unless we accept them in their weakness and value them in their imperfections more than the best manual skills. This is what we must do with all our workers: seek out their thoughtful aspects and draw those out of them, no matter what we lose in the process, accepting whatever faults and mistakes come along with it. The best in them can only show itself alongside many errors. Understand this clearly: You can teach a person to draw a straight line, to cut one; to create a curved line, and to carve it; to replicate and carve any number of lines or shapes with impressive speed and precision, producing perfect work within its category. But if you ask them to think about those forms, to consider if they can come up with anything better from their own imagination, they hesitate; their execution wavers; they think, and it’s likely they think incorrectly; chances are they make a mistake in that very first touch of their work as a thinking individual. But despite that, you’ve helped make them into a person. Before, they were just a machine, an animated tool.
And observe, you are put to stern choice in this matter. You must either make a tool of the creature, or a man of him. You cannot make both. Men were not intended to work with the accuracy of tools, to be precise and perfect in all their actions. If you will have that precision out of them, and make their fingers measure degrees like cog-wheels, and their arms strike curves like compasses, you must unhumanize them. All the energy of their spirits must be given to make cogs and compasses of themselves. All their attention and strength must go to the accomplishment of the mean act. The eye of the soul must be bent upon the finger-point, and the soul's force must fill all the invisible nerves that guide it, ten hours a day, that it may not err from its steely precision, and so soul and sight be worn away, and the whole human being be lost at last—a heap of sawdust, so far as its intellectual work in this world is concerned; saved only by its Heart, which cannot go into the form of cogs and compasses, but expands, after the ten hours are over, into fireside humanity. On the other hand, if you will make a man of the working creature, you cannot make a tool. Let him but begin to imagine, to think, to try to do anything worth doing; and the engine-turned precision is lost at once. Out come all his roughness, all his dulness, all his incapability; shame upon shame, failure upon failure, pause after pause: but out comes the whole majesty of him also; and we know the height of it only when we see the clouds settling upon him. And, whether the clouds be bright or dark, there will be transfiguration behind and within them.
And look, you have a tough choice to make here. You can either treat the creature as a tool or as a man. You can’t do both. People weren’t meant to work with tool-like precision, to be exact and flawless in everything they do. If you want that level of precision and want their fingers to measure degrees like gears, and their arms to create curves like compasses, you have to strip away their humanity. All their spirit’s energy will go into turning themselves into cogs and compasses. Their attention and strength will solely focus on completing simple tasks. The eye of the soul will fixate on the fingertip, and the soul’s energy will fill all the invisible nerves that direct it, ten hours a day, just to maintain that exactness, causing the soul and sight to fade away, ultimately reducing the whole person to nothing but sawdust in terms of their intellectual contributions in this world—only their heart remains, which can’t be turned into cogs or compasses but instead grows into a human warmth once the workday ends. On the flip side, if you choose to nurture the human side of the working creature, you can’t treat them like a tool. As soon as they start to imagine, think, or attempt something meaningful, all that mechanical precision is lost immediately. Their rough edges, dullness, and shortcomings will surface; there will be embarrassment and numerous failures, along with moments of hesitation. But alongside all that comes their full potential, and we only recognize its greatness when we see the clouds gathering around them. Whether those clouds are bright or dark, transformation is happening both outside and within.
And now, reader, look round this English room of yours, about which you have been proud so often, because the work of it was so good and strong, and the ornaments of it so finished. Examine again all those accurate mouldings, and perfect polishings, and unerring adjustments of the seasoned wood and tempered steel. Many a time you have exulted over them, and thought how great England was, because her slightest work was done so thoroughly. Alas! if read rightly, these perfectnesses are signs of a slavery in our England a thousand times more bitter and more degrading than that of the scourged African, or helot Greek. Men may be beaten, chained, tormented, yoked like cattle, slaughtered like summer flies, and yet remain in one sense, and the best sense, free. But to smother their souls within them, to blight and hew into rotting pollards the suckling branches of their human intelligence, to make the flesh and skin which, after the worm's work on it, is to see God,[158] into leathern thongs to yoke machinery with,—this it is to be slave-masters indeed; and there might be more freedom in England, though her feudal lords' lightest words were worth men's lives, and though the blood of the vexed husbandman dropped in the furrows of her fields, than there is while the animation of her multitudes is sent like fuel to feed the factory smoke, and the strength of them is given daily to be wasted into the fineness of a web, or racked into the exactness of a line.
And now, reader, look round this English room of yours, about which you have been proud so often, because the work of it was so good and strong, and the ornaments of it so finished. Examine again all those accurate mouldings, and perfect polishings, and unerring adjustments of the seasoned wood and tempered steel. Many a time you have exulted over them, and thought how great England was, because her slightest work was done so thoroughly. Alas! if read rightly, these perfectnesses are signs of a slavery in our England a thousand times more bitter and more degrading than that of the scourged African, or helot Greek. Men may be beaten, chained, tormented, yoked like cattle, slaughtered like summer flies, and yet remain in one sense, and the best sense, free. But to smother their souls within them, to blight and hew into rotting pollards the suckling branches of their human intelligence, to make the flesh and skin which, after the worm's work on it, is to see God,[158] into leathern thongs to yoke machinery with,—this it is to be slave-masters indeed; and there might be more freedom in England, though her feudal lords' lightest words were worth men's lives, and though the blood of the vexed husbandman dropped in the furrows of her fields, than there is while the animation of her multitudes is sent like fuel to feed the factory smoke, and the strength of them is given daily to be wasted into the fineness of a web, or racked into the exactness of a line.
And, on the other hand, go forth again to gaze upon the old cathedral front, where you have smiled so often at the fantastic ignorance of the old sculptors: examine once more those ugly goblins, and formless monsters, and stern statues, anatomiless and rigid; but do not mock at them, for they are signs of the life and liberty of every workman who struck the stone; a freedom of thought, and rank in scale of being, such as no laws, no charters, no charities can secure; but which it must be the first aim of all Europe at this day to regain for her children.
And, on the other hand, go back and look at the old cathedral front, where you've smiled many times at the odd ignorance of the old sculptors: take another look at those ugly goblins, shapeless monsters, and stern statues, without bodies and stiff; but don't make fun of them, because they represent the life and freedom of every worker who shaped the stone; a freedom of thought and level of existence that no laws, charters, or charities can guarantee; but which should be the primary goal of all of Europe today to reclaim for its people.
Let me not be thought to speak wildly or extravagantly. It is verily this degradation of the operative into a machine, which, more than any other evil of the times, is leading the mass of the nations everywhere into vain, incoherent, destructive struggling for a freedom of which they cannot explain the nature to themselves. Their universal outcry against wealth, and against nobility, is not forced from them either by the pressure of famine, or the sting of mortified pride. These do much, and have done much in all ages; but the foundations of society were never yet shaken as they are at this day. It is not that men are ill fed, but that they have no pleasure in the work by which they make their bread, and therefore look to wealth as the only means of pleasure. It is not that men are pained by the scorn of the upper classes, but they cannot endure their own; for they feel that the kind of labour to which they are condemned is verily a degrading one, and makes them less than men. Never had the upper classes so much sympathy with the lower, or charity for them, as they have at this day, and yet never were they so much hated by them: for, of old, the separation between the noble and the poor was merely a wall built by law; now it is a veritable difference in level of standing, a precipice between upper and lower grounds in the field of humanity, and there is pestilential air at the bottom of it. I know not if a day is ever to come when the nature of right freedom will be understood, and when men will see that to obey another man, to labour for him, yield reverence to him or to his place, is not slavery. It is often the best kind of liberty,—liberty from care. The man who says to one, Go, and he goeth, and to another, Come, and he cometh,[159] has, in most cases, more sense of restraint and difficulty than the man who obeys him. The movements of the one are hindered by the burden on his shoulder; of the other, by the bridle on his lips: there is no way by which the burden may be lightened; but we need not suffer from the bridle if we do not champ at it. To yield reverence to another, to hold ourselves and our lives at his disposal, is not slavery; often it is the noblest state in which a man can live in this world. There is, indeed, a reverence which is servile, that is to say irrational or selfish: but there is also noble reverence, that is to say, reasonable and loving; and a man is never so noble as when he is reverent in this kind; nay, even if the feeling pass the bounds of mere reason, so that it be loving, a man is raised by it. Which had, in reality, most of the serf nature in him,—the Irish peasant who was lying in wait yesterday for his landlord, with his musket muzzle thrust through the ragged hedge; or that old mountain servant, who 200 years ago, at Inverkeithing, gave up his own life and the lives of his seven sons for his chief?—as each fell, calling forth his brother to the death, "Another for Hector!"[160] And therefore, in all ages and all countries, reverence has been paid and sacrifice made by men to each other, not only without complaint, but rejoicingly; and famine, and peril, and sword, and all evil, and all shame, have been borne willingly in the causes of masters and kings; for all these gifts of the heart ennobled the men who gave not less than the men who received them, and nature prompted, and God rewarded the sacrifice. But to feel their souls withering within them, unthanked, to find their whole being sunk into an unrecognized abyss, to be counted off into a heap of mechanism, numbered with its wheels, and weighed with its hammer strokes;—this nature bade not,—this God blesses not,—this humanity for no long time is able to endure.
Let me not be thought to speak wildly or extravagantly. It is verily this degradation of the operative into a machine, which, more than any other evil of the times, is leading the mass of the nations everywhere into vain, incoherent, destructive struggling for a freedom of which they cannot explain the nature to themselves. Their universal outcry against wealth, and against nobility, is not forced from them either by the pressure of famine, or the sting of mortified pride. These do much, and have done much in all ages; but the foundations of society were never yet shaken as they are at this day. It is not that men are ill fed, but that they have no pleasure in the work by which they make their bread, and therefore look to wealth as the only means of pleasure. It is not that men are pained by the scorn of the upper classes, but they cannot endure their own; for they feel that the kind of labour to which they are condemned is verily a degrading one, and makes them less than men. Never had the upper classes so much sympathy with the lower, or charity for them, as they have at this day, and yet never were they so much hated by them: for, of old, the separation between the noble and the poor was merely a wall built by law; now it is a veritable difference in level of standing, a precipice between upper and lower grounds in the field of humanity, and there is pestilential air at the bottom of it. I know not if a day is ever to come when the nature of right freedom will be understood, and when men will see that to obey another man, to labour for him, yield reverence to him or to his place, is not slavery. It is often the best kind of liberty,—liberty from care. The man who says to one, Go, and he goeth, and to another, Come, and he cometh,[159] has, in most cases, more sense of restraint and difficulty than the man who obeys him. The movements of the one are hindered by the burden on his shoulder; of the other, by the bridle on his lips: there is no way by which the burden may be lightened; but we need not suffer from the bridle if we do not champ at it. To yield reverence to another, to hold ourselves and our lives at his disposal, is not slavery; often it is the noblest state in which a man can live in this world. There is, indeed, a reverence which is servile, that is to say irrational or selfish: but there is also noble reverence, that is to say, reasonable and loving; and a man is never so noble as when he is reverent in this kind; nay, even if the feeling pass the bounds of mere reason, so that it be loving, a man is raised by it. Which had, in reality, most of the serf nature in him,—the Irish peasant who was lying in wait yesterday for his landlord, with his musket muzzle thrust through the ragged hedge; or that old mountain servant, who 200 years ago, at Inverkeithing, gave up his own life and the lives of his seven sons for his chief?—as each fell, calling forth his brother to the death, "Another for Hector!"[160] And therefore, in all ages and all countries, reverence has been paid and sacrifice made by men to each other, not only without complaint, but rejoicingly; and famine, and peril, and sword, and all evil, and all shame, have been borne willingly in the causes of masters and kings; for all these gifts of the heart ennobled the men who gave not less than the men who received them, and nature prompted, and God rewarded the sacrifice. But to feel their souls withering within them, unthanked, to find their whole being sunk into an unrecognized abyss, to be counted off into a heap of mechanism, numbered with its wheels, and weighed with its hammer strokes;—this nature bade not,—this God blesses not,—this humanity for no long time is able to endure.
We have much studied and much perfected, of late, the great civilized invention of the division of labour; only we give it a false name. It is not, truly speaking; the labour that is divided; but the men:—Divided into mere segments of men—broken into small fragments and crumbs of life; so that all the little piece of intelligence that is left in a man is not enough to make a pin, or a nail, but exhausts itself in making the point of a pin or the head of a nail. Now it is a good and desirable thing, truly, to make many pins in a day; but if we could only see with what crystal sand their points were polished,—sand of human soul, much to be magnified before it can be discerned for what it is,—we should think there might be some loss in it also. And the great cry that rises from all our manufacturing cities, louder than their furnace blast, is all in very deed for this,—that we manufacture everything there except men; we blanch cotton, and strengthen steel, and refine sugar, and shape pottery; but to brighten, to strengthen, to refine, or to form a single living spirit, never enters into our estimate of advantages. And all the evil to which that cry is urging our myriads can be met only in one way: not by teaching nor preaching, for to teach them is but to show them their misery, and to preach to them, if we do nothing more than preach, is to mock at it. It can be met only by a right understanding, on the part of all classes, of what kinds of labour are good for men, raising them, and making them happy; by a determined sacrifice of such convenience, or beauty, or cheapness as is to be got only by the degradation of the workman; and by equally determined demand for the products and results of healthy and ennobling labour.
We have studied and refined the great civilized invention of the division of labor a lot lately; we just call it the wrong thing. It isn't really the labor that's divided; it's the people: divided into mere fragments—broken into small pieces of life; so that all the little bit of intelligence left in a person isn’t enough to make a pin or a nail, but is exhausted making just the point of a pin or the head of a nail. It’s a good and desirable thing, truly, to make many pins in a day; but if we could see the fine sand with which their points are polished—sand of human soul, which needs magnification to discern its true nature—we might think there’s some loss in it as well. And the loud cry that rises from all our manufacturing cities, even louder than their furnace blast, is really for this: that we manufacture everything there except for people; we bleach cotton, strengthen steel, refine sugar, and shape pottery; but to brighten, strengthen, refine, or form a single living spirit never enters into our calculation of benefits. All the harm that cry is urging upon our countless numbers can only be addressed in one way: not by teaching or preaching, because teaching them only reveals their misery, and preaching, without taking further action, just mocks it. It can only be addressed by a proper understanding among all classes of what types of labor are good for people, uplifting them and making them happy; by a committed sacrifice of convenience, beauty, or affordability that only comes at the cost of degrading the worker; and by an equally determined demand for the products and outcomes of healthy and meaningful labor.
And how, it will be asked, are these products to be recognized, and this demand to be regulated? Easily: by the observance of three broad and simple rules:
And how, you might wonder, can we identify these products and manage this demand? It’s simple: by following three straightforward rules:
1. Never encourage the manufacture of any article not absolutely necessary, in the production of which Invention has no share.
1. Never promote the creation of any item that isn't absolutely necessary, where Invention plays no role in its production.
2. Never demand an exact finish for its own sake, but only for some practical or noble end.
2. Never insist on a perfect finish just for the sake of it; do so only if it serves a practical or meaningful purpose.
3. Never encourage imitation or copying of any kind, except for the sake of preserving record of great works.
3. Never promote imitation or copying in any form, except when it’s necessary to preserve the record of significant works.
The second of these principles is the only one which directly rises out of the consideration of our immediate subject; but I shall briefly explain the meaning and extent of the first also, reserving the enforcement of the third for another place.
The second of these principles is the only one that directly comes from the consideration of our immediate topic; however, I will briefly explain the meaning and scope of the first as well, saving the discussion of the third for another time.
1. Never encourage the manufacture of anything not necessary, in the production of which invention has no share.
1. Never support the creation of anything unnecessary if invention isn’t involved in its production.
For instance. Glass beads are utterly unnecessary, and there is no design or thought employed in their manufacture. They are formed by first drawing out the glass into rods; these rods are chopped up into fragments of the size of beads by the human hand, and the fragments are then rounded in the furnace. The men who chop up the rods sit at their work all day, their hands vibrating with a perpetual and exquisitely timed palsy, and the beads dropping beneath their vibration like hail. Neither they, nor the men who draw out the rods or fuse the fragments, have the smallest occasion for the use of any single human faculty; and every young lady, therefore, who buys glass beads is engaged in the slave-trade, and in a much more cruel one than that which we have so long been endeavouring to put down.
For example, glass beads are completely unnecessary, and there's no design or thought put into making them. They're created by first pulling the glass into rods; then, these rods are chopped into bead-sized pieces by hand, and the pieces are rounded in a furnace. The workers who chop the rods sit at their stations all day, their hands shaking with a constant and perfectly timed tremor, and the beads fall from their hands like hail. Neither they, nor the workers who pull the rods or melt the pieces, have any real need for any human skills; therefore, any young woman who buys glass beads is participating in a form of slave trade, one that's even more brutal than the one we've been trying to eliminate for so long.
But glass cups and vessels may become the subjects of exquisite invention; and if in buying these we pay for the invention, that is to say for the beautiful form, or colour, or engraving, and not for mere finish of execution, we are doing good to humanity.
But glass cups and containers can inspire amazing creativity; and if when we buy these we are paying for the creativity, meaning the beautiful shape, color, or engraving, and not just for the quality of the finish, we are benefiting humanity.
So, again, the cutting of precious stones, in all ordinary cases, requires little exertion of any mental faculty; some tact and judgment in avoiding flaws, and so on, but nothing to bring out the whole mind. Every person who wears cut jewels merely for the sake of their value is, therefore, a slave-driver.
So, once again, cutting precious stones, in most cases, doesn’t take much mental effort; just some skill and judgment to avoid flaws and similar issues, but nothing that engages the whole mind. Anyone who wears cut jewels just for their value is, therefore, a slave driver.
But the working of the goldsmith, and the various designing of grouped jewellery and enamel-work, may become the subject of the most noble human intelligence. Therefore, money spent in the purchase of well-designed plate, of precious engraved vases, cameos, or enamels, does good to humanity; and, in work of this kind, jewels may be employed to heighten its splendour; and their cutting is then a price paid for the attainment of a noble end, and thus perfectly allowable.
But the work of the goldsmith, along with the various designs of grouped jewelry and enamel art, can be a subject for the greatest human intelligence. Therefore, money spent on beautifully designed plates, precious engraved vases, cameos, or enamels does good for humanity; and in this type of work, jewels can be used to enhance its beauty; their cutting is then a cost for achieving a noble purpose, and is totally justifiable.
I shall perhaps press this law farther elsewhere, but our immediate concern is chiefly with the second, namely, never to demand an exact finish, when it does not lead to a noble end. For observe, I have only dwelt upon the rudeness of Gothic, or any other kind of imperfectness, as admirable, where it was impossible to get design or thought without it. If you are to have the thought of a rough and untaught man, you must have it in a rough and untaught way; but from an educated man, who can without effort express his thoughts in an educated way, take the graceful expression, and be thankful. Only get the thought, and do not silence the peasant because he cannot speak good grammar, or until you have taught him his grammar. Grammar and refinement are good things, both, only be sure of the better thing first. And thus in art, delicate finish is desirable from the greatest masters, and is always given by them. In some places Michael Angelo, Leonardo, Phidias, Perugino, Turner, all finished with the most exquisite care; and the finish they give always leads to the fuller accomplishment of their noble purpose. But lower men than these cannot finish, for it requires consummate knowledge to finish consummately, and then we must take their thoughts as they are able to give them. So the rule is simple: Always look for invention first, and after that, for such execution as will help the invention, and as the inventor is capable of without painful effort, and no more. Above all, demand no refinement of execution where there is no thought, for that is slaves' work, unredeemed. Rather choose rough work than smooth work, so only that the practical purpose be answered, and never imagine there is reason to be proud of anything that may be accomplished by patience and sand-paper.
I might explore this rule further elsewhere, but right now, our main focus is on the second point: never demand perfection when it doesn’t lead to something meaningful. Note that I’ve only highlighted the beauty in the roughness of Gothic or any other type of imperfection where genuine design or thought emerges from it. If you want the raw thoughts of an unrefined person, you have to accept them in an unrefined manner. However, when it comes to an educated person who can easily express their ideas eloquently, appreciate that graceful expression without hesitation. Just make sure to capture the thought and don’t dismiss the unpolished speaker just because they don't use proper grammar, or until you’ve taught them how. Grammar and refinement are both valuable, but always prioritize the deeper meaning first. In art, a delicate finish is desirable from the greatest masters, and they consistently deliver it. For instance, Michelangelo, Leonardo, Phidias, Perugino, and Turner all finished their work with remarkable care; their finishing touches enhance the achievement of their grand purpose. Lesser artists may not achieve the same level of finish, as it demands profound knowledge. So, we must accept their ideas as they present them. The guideline is straightforward: always prioritize originality first, and then seek execution that supports that originality, done as effortlessly as the creator can manage, and not beyond that. Most importantly, don’t ask for execution refinement when there’s no substantial thought behind it, as that’s merely work of the unskilled and unremarkable. It’s better to choose rough work over smooth work, as long as the practical goal is met, and never think there’s reason to be proud of anything achieved through mere patience and sanding.
I shall only give one example, which however will show the reader what I mean, from the manufacture already alluded to, that of glass. Our modern glass is exquisitely clear in its substance, true in its form, accurate in its cutting. We are proud of this. We ought to be ashamed of it. The old Venice glass was muddy, inaccurate in all its forms, and clumsily cut, if at all. And the old Venetian was justly proud of it. For there is this difference between the English and Venetian workman, that the former thinks only of accurately matching his patterns, and getting his curves perfectly true and his edges perfectly sharp, and becomes a mere machine for rounding curves and sharpening edges; while the old Venetian cared not a whit whether his edges were sharp or not, but he invented a new design for every glass that he made, and never moulded a handle or a lip without a new fancy in it. And therefore, though some Venetian glass is ugly and clumsy enough when made by clumsy and uninventive workmen, other Venetian glass is so lovely in its forms that no price is too great for it; and we never see the same form in it twice. Now you cannot have the finish and the varied form too. If the workman is thinking about his edges, he cannot be thinking of his design; if of his design, he cannot think of his edges. Choose whether you will pay for the lovely form or the perfect finish, and choose at the same moment whether you will make the worker a man or a grindstone.
I’ll give just one example that will show you what I mean, from the manufacturing process mentioned earlier, which is glass. Our modern glass is incredibly clear, precise in its shape, and expertly cut. We take pride in this. But we should feel ashamed of it. The old Venetian glass was murky, imprecise in its shapes, and not cut well at all, if it was cut at all. Yet the old Venetians took pride in their work. The difference between the English and Venetian craftsmen is that the former focuses solely on matching patterns accurately, getting the curves just right, and making the edges perfectly sharp, turning into machines for rounding curves and sharpening edges. In contrast, the old Venetians didn’t care whether their edges were sharp; they created a new design for every piece of glass they made and never shaped a handle or lip without a fresh idea. Therefore, while some Venetian glass can be ugly and awkward when made by uninspired and clumsy workers, other Venetian pieces are so beautiful in design that no price is too high for them, and you never see the same shape twice. You can’t have both the perfect finish and the variety in design. If a craftsman is focused on his edges, he can't focus on his design; if he’s focused on his design, he can't think about his edges. Decide whether you want to pay for the beautiful design or the perfect finish, and at the same time, decide whether you want to treat the worker as a person or as a grindstone.
Nay, but the reader interrupts me,—"If the workman can design beautifully, I would not have him kept at the furnace. Let him be taken away and made a gentleman, and have a studio, and design his glass there, and I will have it blown and cut for him by common workmen, and so I will have my design and my finish too."
No, but the reader interrupts me, “If the craftsman can create beautiful designs, I wouldn’t want him stuck at the furnace. Let him be taken away, become a gentleman, have his own studio, and design his glass there. I’ll have it blown and cut for him by regular workers, and that way I’ll get both my design and my finish.”
All ideas of this kind are founded upon two mistaken suppositions: the first, that one man's thoughts can be, or ought to be, executed by another man's hands; the second, that manual labour is a degradation, when it is governed by intellect.
All ideas like this are based on two incorrect assumptions: the first is that one person's thoughts can or should be carried out by someone else's hands; the second is that manual labor is degrading when it is guided by intellect.
On a large scale, and in work determinable by line and rule, it is indeed both possible and necessary that the thoughts of one man should be carried out by the labour of others; in this sense I have already defined the best architecture to be the expression of the mind of manhood by the hands of childhood. But on a smaller scale, and in a design which cannot be mathematically defined, one man's thoughts can never be expressed by another: and the difference between the spirit of touch of the man who is inventing, and of the man who is obeying directions, is often all the difference between a great and a common work of art. How wide the separation is between original and second-hand execution, I shall endeavour to show elsewhere; it is not so much to our purpose here as to mark the other and more fatal error of despising manual labour when governed by intellect; for it is no less fatal an error to despise it when thus regulated by intellect, than to value it for its own sake. We are always in these days endeavouring to separate the two; we want one man to be always thinking, and another to be always working, and we call one a gentleman, and the other an operative; whereas the workman ought often to be thinking, and the thinker often to be working, and both should be gentlemen, in the best sense. As it is, we make both ungentle, the one envying, the other despising, his brother; and the mass of society is made up of morbid thinkers, and miserable workers. Now it is only by labour that thought can be made healthy, and only by thought that labour can be made happy, and the two cannot be separated with impunity. It would be well if all of us were good handicraftsmen in some kind, and the dishonour of manual labour done away with altogether; so that though there should still be a trenchant distinction of race between nobles and commoners, there should not, among the latter, be a trenchant distinction of employment, as between idle and working men, or between men of liberal and illiberal professions. All professions should be liberal, and there should be less pride felt in peculiarity of employment, and more in excellence of achievement. And yet more, in each several profession, no master should be too proud to do its hardest work. The painter should grind his own colours; the architect work in the mason's yard with his men; the master-manufacturer be himself a more skilful operative than any man in his mills; and the distinction between one man and another be only in experience and skill, and the authority and wealth which these must naturally and justly obtain.
On a large scale, and in work that can be measured and organized, it’s both possible and necessary for one person's thoughts to be executed by the labor of others; in this way, I’ve already described the best architecture as the expression of a man’s mind through the hands of youth. However, on a smaller scale, where the design isn’t precisely defined, one person's ideas can never be truly expressed by someone else: the difference between the creator's touch and the person following instructions often marks the difference between great art and mediocre work. I’ll try to illustrate how vast the gap is between original and imitative execution elsewhere; however, the more critical error to highlight here is the disdain for manual labor that is governed by intellect. It’s just as damaging to undervalue it when guided by intellect as it is to value it for its own sake. Nowadays, we tend to separate the two: we expect one person to always be thinking while another is always working, labeling one as a gentleman and the other as a laborer; when in reality, the worker should often be thinking, and the thinker should often be working, and both should be gentlemen in the best sense. Instead, we make both undignified, with one envying the other and the workforce made up of unhappy thinkers and miserable laborers. Only through labor can thoughts be healthy, and only through thought can labor be fulfilling, and the two cannot be easily divided. It would be beneficial for all of us to be skilled craftsmen of some sort, eliminating the stigma around manual labor; so that even if a clear distinction remains between nobles and commoners, there shouldn’t be a sharp divide among the latter in terms of employment, whether between idle and working men or between those in prestigious versus less respected professions. All professions should be considered dignified, with less pride in unique jobs, and more in achieving excellence. Furthermore, within each profession, no leader should be too proud to do the hardest tasks. The painter should mix his own paints; the architect should work alongside his team at the construction site; the master manufacturer should be a more skilled worker than anyone in his mills; and distinctions among individuals should be based only on experience, skill, and the authority and wealth that come naturally and fairly from these attributes.
I should be led far from the matter in hand, if I were to pursue this interesting subject. Enough, I trust, has been said to show the reader that the rudeness or imperfection which at first rendered the term "Gothic" one of reproach is indeed, when rightly understood, one of the most noble characters of Christian architecture, and not only a noble but an essential one. It seems a fantastic paradox, but it is nevertheless a most important truth, that no architecture can be truly noble which is not imperfect. And this is easily demonstrable. For since the architect, whom we will suppose capable of doing all in perfection, cannot execute the whole with his own hands, he must either make slaves of his workmen in the old Greek, and present English fashion, and level his work to a slave's capacities, which is to degrade it; or else he must take his workmen as he finds them, and let them show their weaknesses together with their strength, which will involve the Gothic imperfection, but render the whole work as noble as the intellect of the age can make it.
I would go off-topic if I continued with this fascinating subject. I hope I've said enough to show the reader that the roughness or flaws that initially made the term "Gothic" a criticism are actually, when understood correctly, one of the most admirable aspects of Christian architecture—and not just admirable but an essential part of it. It seems like a weird contradiction, but it’s a crucial truth that no architecture can be truly great if it’s not imperfect. This is easy to prove. Since an architect, whom we can assume is capable of perfect execution, cannot do everything by himself, he has to either treat his workers like slaves, as was common in ancient Greece and is still seen in some modern practices, thus lowering the quality of the work, or he can accept his workers as they are and allow their flaws to show alongside their strengths. This will introduce the Gothic imperfections but will also make the entire project as impressive as the intellect of the age can achieve.
But the principle may be stated more broadly still. I have confined the illustration of it to architecture, but I must not leave it as if true of architecture only. Hitherto I have used the words imperfect and perfect merely to distinguish between work grossly unskilful, and work executed with average precision and science; and I have been pleading that any degree of unskilfulness should be admitted, so only that the labourer's mind had room for expression. But, accurately speaking, no good work whatever can be perfect, and the demand for perfection is always a sign of a misunderstanding of the ends of art.
But the principle can be stated even more broadly. I've focused on architecture as an example, but I don't want to limit it to just that. Until now, I've used the terms imperfect and perfect simply to differentiate between work that is poorly executed and work that is done with average skill and knowledge. I've argued that any level of lack of skill should be accepted, as long as the worker has space for expression. However, to be precise, no good work can ever be perfect, and the demand for perfection is always a sign of misunderstanding the purposes of art.
This for two reasons, both based on everlasting laws. The first, that no great man ever stops working till he has reached his point of failure: that is to say, his mind is always far in advance of his powers of execution, and the latter will now and then give way in trying to follow it; besides that he will always give to the inferior portions of his work only such inferior attention as they require; and according to his greatness he becomes so accustomed to the feeling of dissatisfaction with the best he can do, that in moments of lassitude or anger with himself he will not care though the beholder be dissatisfied also. I believe there has only been one man who would not acknowledge this necessity, and strove always to reach perfection, Leonardo; the end of his vain effort being merely that he would take ten years to a picture and leave it unfinished. And therefore, if we are to have great men working at all, or less men doing their best, the work will be imperfect, however beautiful. Of human work none but what is bad can be perfect, in its own bad way.[161]
This for two reasons, both based on everlasting laws. The first, that no great man ever stops working till he has reached his point of failure: that is to say, his mind is always far in advance of his powers of execution, and the latter will now and then give way in trying to follow it; besides that he will always give to the inferior portions of his work only such inferior attention as they require; and according to his greatness he becomes so accustomed to the feeling of dissatisfaction with the best he can do, that in moments of lassitude or anger with himself he will not care though the beholder be dissatisfied also. I believe there has only been one man who would not acknowledge this necessity, and strove always to reach perfection, Leonardo; the end of his vain effort being merely that he would take ten years to a picture and leave it unfinished. And therefore, if we are to have great men working at all, or less men doing their best, the work will be imperfect, however beautiful. Of human work none but what is bad can be perfect, in its own bad way.[161]
The second reason is, that imperfection is in some sort essential to all that we know of life. It is the sign of life in a mortal body, that is to say, of a state of progress and change. Nothing that lives is, or can be, rigidly perfect; part of it is decaying, part nascent. The foxglove blossom,—a third part bud, a third part past, a third part in full bloom,—is a type of the life of this world. And in all things that live there are certain irregularities and deficiencies which are not only signs of life, but sources of beauty. No human face is exactly the same in its lines on each side, no leaf perfect in its lobes, no branch in its symmetry. All admit irregularity as they imply change; and to banish imperfection is to destroy expression, to check exertion, to paralyze vitality. All things are literally better, lovelier, and more beloved for the imperfections which have been divinely appointed, that the law of human life may be Effort, and the law of human judgment, Mercy.
The second reason is that imperfection is in some way essential to everything we know about life. It symbolizes life in a mortal body, meaning a state of progress and change. Nothing that lives is, or can be, rigidly perfect; part of it is deteriorating, and part is beginning anew. The foxglove flower—a third in bud, a third past, a third in full bloom—is a representation of life in this world. In all living things, there are certain irregularities and flaws that are not only signs of life but also sources of beauty. No human face is exactly symmetrical, no leaf is perfect in its shape, and no branch has perfect symmetry. All acknowledge irregularity as they suggest change; to eliminate imperfection is to eradicate expression, stifle effort, and paralyze vitality. Everything is literally better, more beautiful, and more cherished because of the imperfections that have been divinely appointed, so that the law of human life may be Effort, and the law of human judgment, Mercy.
Accept this then for a universal law, that neither architecture nor any other noble work of man can be good unless it be imperfect; and let us be prepared for the otherwise strange fact, which we shall discern clearly as we approach the period of the Renaissance, that the first cause of the fall of the arts of Europe was a relentless requirement of perfection, incapable alike either of being silenced by veneration for greatness, or softened into forgiveness of simplicity.
Accept this as a universal rule: neither architecture nor any other great work of human creativity can be good unless it has some imperfections. And we should be ready for the somewhat surprising fact that we'll see clearly as we get closer to the Renaissance—that the main reason for the decline of the arts in Europe was a harsh demand for perfection, which could not be quieted by admiration for greatness or eased by an acceptance of simplicity.
Thus far then of the Rudeness or Savageness, which is the first mental element of Gothic architecture. It is an element in many other healthy architectures also, as in Byzantine and Romanesque; but true Gothic cannot exist without it.
Thus far, we’ve discussed the roughness or wildness, which is the first mental aspect of Gothic architecture. This aspect is also present in many other robust architectural styles, like Byzantine and Romanesque; however, true Gothic cannot exist without it.
The second mental element above named was CHANGEFULNESS, or Variety.
The second mental element mentioned above was CHANGEFULNESS, or Variety.
I have already enforced the allowing independent operation to the inferior workman, simply as a duty to him, and as ennobling the architecture by rendering it more Christian. We have now to consider what reward we obtain for the performance of this duty, namely, the perpetual variety of every feature of the building.
I have already made it a point to allow the lower-skilled worker to operate independently, simply as a responsibility to him, and as a way to elevate the architecture by making it more Christian. Now we need to think about what reward we get for fulfilling this responsibility, which is the endless variety in every aspect of the building.
Wherever the workman is utterly enslaved, the parts of the building must of course be absolutely like each other; for the perfection of his execution can only be reached by exercising him in doing one thing, and giving him nothing else to do. The degree in which the workman is degraded may be thus known at a glance, by observing whether the several parts of the building are similar or not; and if, as in Greek work, all the capitals are alike, and all the mouldings unvaried, then the degradation is complete; if, as in Egyptian or Ninevite work, though the manner of executing certain figures is always the same, the order of design is perpetually varied, the degradation is less total; if, as in Gothic work, there is perpetual change both in design and execution, the workman must have been altogether set free.
Wherever the worker is completely oppressed, the parts of the building must all look exactly the same; the only way to achieve perfection in their work is to make them focus on just one task and give them nothing else to do. You can easily tell how degraded the worker is by looking at whether the different parts of the building are similar. If, like in Greek architecture, all the capitals are the same and all the moldings are unchanging, then the degradation is total; if, like in Egyptian or Ninevite work, the method of creating certain figures is always the same but the overall design varies constantly, the degradation is less severe; if, like in Gothic work, there is constant variation in both design and execution, then the worker must have been completely liberated.
How much the beholder gains from the liberty of the labourer may perhaps be questioned in England, where one of the strongest instincts in nearly every mind is that Love of Order which makes us desire that our house windows should pair like our carriage horses, and allows us to yield our faith unhesitatingly to architectural theories which fix a form for everything, and forbid variation from it. I would not impeach love of order: it is one of the most useful elements of the English mind; it helps us in our commerce and in all purely practical matters; and it is in many cases one of the foundation stones of morality. Only do not let us suppose that love of order is love of art. It is true that order, in its highest sense, is one of the necessities of art, just as time is a necessity of music; but love of order has no more to do with our right enjoyment of architecture or painting, than love of punctuality with the appreciation of an opera. Experience, I fear, teaches us that accurate and methodical habits in daily life are seldom characteristic of those who either quickly perceive, or richly possess, the creative powers of art; there is, however, nothing inconsistent between the two instincts, and nothing to hinder us from retaining our business habits, and yet fully allowing and enjoying the noblest gifts of Invention. We already do so, in every other branch of art except architecture, and we only do not so there because we have been taught that it would be wrong. Our architects gravely inform us that, as there are four rules of arithmetic, there are five orders of architecture; we, in our simplicity, think that this sounds consistent, and believe them. They inform us also that there is one proper form for Corinthian capitals, another for Doric, and another for Ionic. We, considering that there is also a proper form for the letters A, B, and C, think that this also sounds consistent, and accept the proposition. Understanding, therefore, that one form of the said capitals is proper, and no other, and having a conscientious horror of all impropriety, we allow the architect to provide us with the said capitals, of the proper form, in such and such a quantity, and in all other points to take care that the legal forms are observed; which having done, we rest in forced confidence that we are well housed.
How much the viewer benefits from the freedom of the worker might be questioned in England, where a strong instinct in almost everyone is the Love of Order. This makes us want our house windows to match our carriage horses, and it leads us to trust architectural theories that dictate a specific form for everything, banning any variation. I wouldn’t criticize the love of order; it’s one of the most useful aspects of the English mindset. It aids us in business and all practical matters, and it serves as a foundation for morality in many cases. However, we shouldn’t assume that the love of order equals the love of art. While it's true that order, in its highest form, is essential to art—just like time is essential to music—the love of order has nothing to do with truly enjoying architecture or painting, just as punctuality has nothing to do with appreciating an opera. Unfortunately, experience suggests that precise and methodical habits in everyday life rarely characterize those who quickly understand or possess the creative powers of art. Still, there’s no conflict between the two instincts, and nothing stops us from keeping our businesslike tendencies while also fully embracing and appreciating the greatest gifts of invention. We already do this in every other art form except architecture, and we only don’t do it there because we’ve been taught that it’s wrong. Our architects tell us earnestly that, just as there are four rules of arithmetic, there are five architectural orders; we, in our naivety, assume that this sounds logical and believe them. They also tell us that there's one correct form for Corinthian capitals, a different one for Doric, and another for Ionic. We think that, just as there’s a proper form for the letters A, B, and C, this too sounds consistent and accept it. Thus, understanding that one form of these capitals is correct and no other, and having a deep-seated aversion to any impropriety, we let the architect provide us with these capitals, in the correct form, in specific amounts, and we accept that all other legal forms are followed. After this, we take a forced comfort in the belief that we have a well-built home.
But our higher instincts are not deceived. We take no pleasure in the building provided for us, resembling that which we take in a new book or a new picture. We may be proud of its size, complacent in its correctness, and happy in its convenience. We may take the same pleasure in its symmetry and workmanship as in a well-ordered room, or a skilful piece of manufacture. And this we suppose to be all the pleasure that architecture was ever intended to give us. The idea of reading a building as we would read Milton or Dante, and getting the same kind of delight out of the stones as out of the stanzas, never enters our minds for a moment. And for good reason;—There is indeed rhythm in the verses, quite as strict as the symmetries or rhythm of the architecture, and a thousand times more beautiful, but there is something else than rhythm. The verses were neither made to order, nor to match, as the capitals were; and we have therefore a kind of pleasure in them other than a sense of propriety. But it requires a strong effort of common sense to shake ourselves quit of all that we have been taught for the last two centuries, and wake to the perception of a truth just as simple and certain as it is new: that great art, whether expressing itself in words, colours, or stones, does not say the same thing over and over again; that the merit of architectural, as of every other art, consists in its saying new and different things; that to repeat itself is no more a characteristic of genius in marble than it is of genius in print; and that we may, without offending any laws of good taste, require of an architect, as we do of a novelist, that he should be not only correct, but entertaining.
But our higher instincts aren't fooled. We don’t find joy in the buildings provided for us the same way we do with a new book or a new painting. We might feel proud of its size, content with how accurate it is, and pleased with its convenience. We might appreciate its symmetry and craftsmanship like we would a well-organized room or a skillfully made product. And we think this is the only enjoyment architecture was ever meant to give us. The thought of experiencing a building like we would read Milton or Dante, and finding the same delight in the stones as in the lines of poetry, never crosses our minds. And for good reason; there is indeed a rhythm in the verses, just as strict as the symmetries or rhythm of the architecture, and a thousand times more beautiful, but there’s more than just rhythm. The verses weren't created on command, nor to fit together like the capitals were; and so, we gain a type of pleasure from them that goes beyond a simple sense of propriety. But it takes a strong dose of common sense to break free from everything we've learned over the last two centuries and awaken to a truth that’s as straightforward and certain as it is new: that great art, whether expressed in words, colors, or stones, does not repeat itself; that the value of architecture, like every other art, lies in its ability to convey new and varied messages; that redundancy is not a trait of genius in marble any more than it is in print; and that we can, without breaking any rules of good taste, expect an architect to be not only accurate but also engaging, just like we do with a novelist.
Yet all this is true, and self-evident; only hidden from us, as many other self-evident things are, by false teaching. Nothing is a great work of art, for the production of which either rules or models can be given. Exactly so far as architecture works on known rules, and from given models, it is not an art, but a manufacture; and it is, of the two procedures, rather less rational (because more easy) to copy capitals or mouldings from Phidias, and call ourselves architects, than to copy heads and hands from Titian, and call ourselves painters.
Yet all this is true and obvious; it's just hidden from us, like many other obvious things, by misleading teachings. Nothing is a great work of art that can be produced by following rules or models. To the extent that architecture relies on known rules and given models, it’s not an art but a craft. It's actually a bit less rational (because it's easier) to replicate capitals or moldings from Phidias and call ourselves architects than to replicate heads and hands from Titian and call ourselves painters.
Let us then understand at once that change or variety is as much a necessity to the human heart and brain in buildings as in books; that there is no merit, though there is some occasional use, in monotony; and that we must no more expect to derive either pleasure or profit from an architecture whose ornaments are of one pattern, and whose pillars are of one proportion, than we should out of a universe in which the clouds were all of one shape, and the trees all of one size.
Let’s recognize right away that change or variety is just as essential for our hearts and minds in buildings as it is in books. There’s no real value, though it can be sometimes useful, in monotony. We shouldn't expect to find pleasure or benefit from architecture that has decorations of one style and columns of one size any more than we would from a universe where all the clouds have the same shape and all the trees are the same height.
And this we confess in deeds, though not in words. All the pleasure which the people of the nineteenth century take in art, is in pictures, sculpture, minor objects of virtù, or mediæval architecture, which we enjoy under the term picturesque: no pleasure is taken anywhere in modern buildings, and we find all men of true feeling delighting to escape out of modern cities into natural scenery: hence, as I shall hereafter show, that peculiar love of landscape, which is characteristic of the age. It would be well, if, in all other matters, we were as ready to put up with what we dislike, for the sake of compliance with established law, as we are in architecture.
And this we show through our actions, even if not through our words. All the enjoyment that people in the nineteenth century find in art comes from paintings, sculptures, small collectibles, or medieval architecture, which we appreciate under the term picturesque; no one finds any pleasure in modern buildings, and we see that all people with genuine feelings prefer to escape from modern cities to natural landscapes. Therefore, as I will later explain, this unique love of landscapes is a defining feature of the age. It would be good if, in all other matters, we were as willing to tolerate what we dislike for the sake of following established rules, as we are in architecture.
How so debased a law ever came to be established, we shall see when we come to describe the Renaissance schools; here we have only to note, as the second most essential element of the Gothic spirit, that it broke through that law wherever it found it in existence; it not only dared, but delighted in, the infringement of every servile principle; and invented a series of forms of which the merit was, not merely that they were new, but that they were capable of perpetual novelty. The pointed arch was not merely a bold variation from the round, but it admitted of millions of variations in itself; for the proportions of a pointed arch are changeable to infinity, while a circular arch is always the same. The grouped shaft was not merely a bold variation from the single one, but it admitted of millions of variations in its grouping, and in the proportions resultant from its grouping. The introduction of tracery was not only a startling change in the treatment of window lights, but admitted endless changes in the interlacement of the tracery bars themselves. So that, while in all living Christian architecture the love of variety exists, the Gothic schools exhibited that love in culminating energy; and their influence, wherever it extended itself, may be sooner and farther traced by this character than by any other; the tendency to the adoption of Gothic types being always first shown by greater irregularity, and richer variation in the forms of the architecture it is about to supersede, long before the appearance of the pointed arch or of any other recognizable outward sign of the Gothic mind.
How such a flawed law came to be established will become clear when we discuss the Renaissance schools; for now, we just need to note, as the second most important element of the Gothic spirit, that it broke through that law wherever it existed. It not only dared but also took pleasure in violating every restrictive principle and created a variety of forms that were not only new but also capable of endless innovation. The pointed arch was not just a bold change from the round arch; it allowed for countless variations because the proportions of a pointed arch can be adjusted infinitely, while a circular arch remains constant. The grouped shaft wasn't merely a daring variation from a single shaft; it allowed for numerous variations in its arrangement and in the proportions that resulted from that arrangement. The introduction of tracery was not just a surprising change in how window lights were treated; it permitted endless variations in how the tracery bars intertwined. Therefore, while all living Christian architecture shows a love for variety, the Gothic schools demonstrated that love with extraordinary energy; their influence, wherever it spread, can be traced more quickly and further by this characteristic than by any other. The shift toward adopting Gothic styles was always initially indicated by greater irregularity and richer variation in the forms of the architecture it was set to replace, long before the pointed arch or any other recognizable external sign of the Gothic mindset appeared.
We must, however, herein note carefully what distinction there is between a healthy and a diseased love of change; for as it was in healthy love of change that the Gothic architecture rose, it was partly in consequence of diseased love of change that it was destroyed. In order to understand this clearly, it will be necessary to consider the different ways in which change and monotony are presented to us in nature; both having their use, like darkness and light, and the one incapable of being enjoyed without the other: change being most delightful after some prolongation of monotony, as light appears most brilliant after the eyes have been for some time closed.
We need to carefully consider the difference between a healthy and an unhealthy love of change. Just as the healthy love of change led to the rise of Gothic architecture, it was the unhealthy love of change that contributed to its downfall. To understand this clearly, we should look at how change and monotony are presented to us in nature; both have their purpose, much like darkness and light, and one cannot be fully appreciated without the other. Change is most enjoyable after experiencing a prolonged period of monotony, just as light seems brightest after our eyes have been closed for a while.
I believe that the true relations of monotony and change may be most simply understood by observing them in music. We may therein notice first, that there is a sublimity and majesty in monotony, which there is not in rapid or frequent variation. This is true throughout all nature. The greater part of the sublimity of the sea depends on its monotony; so also that of desolate moor and mountain scenery; and especially the sublimity of motion, as in the quiet, unchanged fall and rise of an engine beam. So also there is sublimity in darkness which there is not in light.
I think the true relationship between monotony and change can be best understood by looking at music. First, we can see that monotony has a certain grandeur and majesty that rapid or frequent changes lack. This holds true across all of nature. Much of the awe we feel from the sea comes from its monotony; the same goes for the emptiness of moors and mountains; and especially the majestic motion found in the steady rise and fall of an engine beam. There’s also a sense of grandeur in darkness that isn’t present in light.
Again, monotony after a certain time, or beyond a certain degree, becomes either uninteresting or intolerable, and the musician is obliged to break it in one or two ways: either while the air or passage is perpetually repeated, its notes are variously enriched and harmonized; or else, after a certain number of repeated passages, an entirely new passage is introduced, which is more or less delightful according to the length of the previous monotony. Nature, of course, uses both these kinds of variation perpetually. The sea-waves, resembling each other in general mass, but none like its brother in minor divisions and curves, are a monotony of the first kind; the great plain, broken by an emergent rock or clump of trees, is a monotony of the second.
Once again, after a while, monotony becomes either boring or unbearable, and the musician has to change things up in one of two ways: either by adding different variations and harmonies while the melody or passage keeps repeating, or by introducing a completely new passage after a certain number of repetitions, which could be more or less enjoyable depending on how long the previous monotony lasted. Nature, of course, constantly employs both types of variation. The sea waves, which are similar in overall shape but different in their smaller details and curves, represent the first type of monotony; meanwhile, a vast plain interrupted by a rising rock or a cluster of trees is an example of the second type.
Farther: in order to the enjoyment of the change in either case, a certain degree of patience is required from the hearer or observer. In the first case, he must be satisfied to endure with patience the recurrence of the great masses of sound or form, and to seek for entertainment in a careful watchfulness of the minor details. In the second case, he must bear patiently the infliction of the monotony for some moments, in order to feel the full refreshment of the change. This is true even of the shortest musical passage in which the element of monotony is employed. In cases of more majestic monotony, the patience required is so considerable that it becomes a kind of pain,—a price paid for the future pleasure.
Further: to enjoy the change in either case, the listener or observer needs a certain level of patience. In the first instance, they must be willing to patiently endure the repetition of the large masses of sound or shape and find entertainment in carefully observing the small details. In the second case, they must endure the monotony for a few moments to fully appreciate the refreshing change. This holds true even for the briefest musical passage that uses monotony. In instances of more grand monotony, the patience required can be so great that it feels almost painful—a price paid for future enjoyment.
Again: the talent of the composer is not in the monotony, but in the changes: he may show feeling and taste by his use of monotony in certain places or degrees; that is to say, by his various employment of it; but it is always in the new arrangement or invention that his intellect is shown, and not in the monotony which relieves it.
Again: the composer's talent isn't in the monotony, but in the changes. He can express feeling and taste through his use of monotony in certain places or levels; that is to say, through his various use of it. However, it's always in the new arrangement or invention that his intellect shines, and not in the monotony that provides relief.
Lastly: if the pleasure of change be too often repeated, it ceases to be delightful, for then change itself becomes monotonous, and we are driven to seek delight in extreme and fantastic degrees of it. This is the diseased love of change of which we have above spoken.
Lastly: if the pleasure of change happens too frequently, it stops being enjoyable, because then change itself becomes boring, and we are forced to find excitement in extreme and outrageous forms of it. This is the unhealthy obsession with change we mentioned earlier.
From these facts we may gather generally that monotony is, and ought to be, in itself painful to us, just as darkness is; that an architecture which is altogether monotonous is a dark or dead architecture; and of those who love it, it may be truly said, "they love darkness rather than light." But monotony in certain measure, used in order to give value to change, and above all, that transparent monotony, which, like the shadows of a great painter, suffers all manner of dimly suggested form to be seen through the body of it, is an essential in architectural as in all other composition; and the endurance of monotony has about the same place in a healthy mind that the endurance of darkness has: that is to say, as a strong intellect will have pleasure in the solemnities of storm and twilight, and in the broken and mysterious lights that gleam among them, rather than in mere brilliancy and glare, while a frivolous mind will dread the shadow and the storm; and as a great man will be ready to endure much darkness of fortune in order to reach greater eminence of power or felicity, while an inferior man will not pay the price; exactly in like manner a great mind will accept, or even delight in, monotony which would be wearisome to an inferior intellect, because it has more patience and power of expectation, and is ready to pay the full price for the great future pleasure of change. But in all cases it is not that the noble nature loves monotony, anymore than it loves darkness or pain. But it can bear with it, and receives a high pleasure in the endurance or patience, a pleasure necessary to the well-being of this world; while those who will not submit to the temporary sameness, but rush from one change to another, gradually dull the edge of change itself, and bring a shadow and weariness over the whole world from which there is no more escape.
From these facts, we can generally conclude that monotony is, and should be, painful to us, just like darkness; that architecture which is completely monotonous is dark or lifeless; and for those who love it, it can honestly be said, "they love darkness more than light." However, some degree of monotony, used to highlight change, and especially that transparent monotony, which, like the shadows of a great painter, allows all sorts of faintly suggested forms to be seen through it, is essential in architecture as in all other forms of composition. The ability to endure monotony has a similar role in a healthy mind as enduring darkness does: just as a strong intellect finds pleasure in the solemnity of storms and twilight, and in the complex and mysterious lights that shine amid them, rather than in mere brightness and glare, while a superficial mind fears shadows and storms; and as a great person is willing to endure significant misfortune to achieve greater power or happiness, while a lesser person won't pay that price; similarly, a great mind will accept, or even enjoy, monotony that would wear down a lesser intellect, because it has more patience and the ability to anticipate, being ready to pay the full price for the greater future pleasure of change. But in all cases, it's not that noble beings love monotony any more than they love darkness or pain. They can tolerate it and find great joy in that endurance or patience, a pleasure that's necessary for the well-being of this world; while those who refuse to submit to temporary sameness and constantly jump from one change to another gradually dull the essence of change itself, casting a shadow of weariness over everything from which there's no escape.
From these general uses of variety in the economy of the world, we may at once understand its use and abuse in architecture. The variety of the Gothic schools is the more healthy and beautiful, because in many cases it is entirely unstudied, and results, not from the mere love of change, but from practical necessities. For in one point of view Gothic is not only the best, but the only rational architecture, as being that which can fit itself most easily to all services, vulgar or noble. Undefined in its slope of roof, height of shaft, breadth of arch, or disposition of ground plan, it can shrink into a turret, expand into a hall, coil into a staircase, or spring into a spire, with undegraded grace and unexhausted energy; and whenever it finds occasion for change in its form or purpose, it submits to it without the slightest sense of loss either to its unity or majesty,—subtle and flexible like a fiery serpent, but ever attentive to the voice of the charmer. And it is one of the chief virtues of the Gothic builders, that they never suffered ideas of outside symmetries and consistencies to interfere with the real use and value of what they did. If they wanted a window, they opened one; a room, they added one; a buttress, they built one; utterly regardless of any established conventionalities of external appearance, knowing (as indeed it always happened) that such daring interruptions of the formal plan would rather give additional interest to its symmetry than injure it. So that, in the best times of Gothic, a useless window would rather have been opened in an unexpected place for the sake of the surprise, than a useful one forbidden for the sake of symmetry. Every successive architect, employed upon a great work, built the pieces he added in his own way, utterly regardless of the style adopted by his predecessors; and if two towers were raised in nominal correspondence at the sides of a cathedral front, one was nearly sure to be different from the other, and in each the style at the top to be different from the style at the bottom.
From these general uses of variety in the world's economy, we can immediately grasp its application and misuse in architecture. The variety found in Gothic styles is healthier and more beautiful because, in many instances, it is completely unplanned and stems not from a simple desire for change, but from practical needs. In one sense, Gothic architecture is not just the best but the only rational form of architecture, as it can adapt easily to all functions, whether ordinary or grand. With no fixed rules for roof slope, shaft height, arch width, or ground plan layout, it can transform into a turret, expand into a hall, spiral into a staircase, or rise into a spire, all with graceful ease and boundless energy. Whenever it needs to adapt its form or purpose, it does so without losing its unity or majesty—it's as subtle and flexible as a fiery serpent, always responsive to its master’s call. One of the greatest strengths of Gothic builders was that they never allowed ideas of external symmetry and consistency to interfere with the genuine use and value of their work. If they needed a window, they created one; if they required a room, they added it; if a buttress was necessary, they built it; completely unconcerned with any established standards of appearance, knowing that such bold deviations from the formal plan would usually enhance its symmetry rather than harm it. Thus, during the peak of Gothic architecture, a useless window would more likely be placed in an unexpected location for the element of surprise than a useful one be omitted for the sake of symmetry. Each architect tasked with a major project constructed their additions in their own style, completely unbothered by the designs of their predecessors; and if two towers were built symmetrically flanking a cathedral's facade, one was almost always sure to differ from the other, with the style at the top being different from the style at the bottom in each case.
These marked variations were, however, only permitted as part of the great system of perpetual change which ran through every member of Gothic design, and rendered it as endless a field for the beholder's inquiry as for the builder's imagination: change, which in the best schools is subtle and delicate, and rendered more delightful by intermingling of a noble monotony; in the more barbaric schools is somewhat fantastic and redundant; but, in all, a necessary and constant condition of the life of the school. Sometimes the variety is in one feature, sometimes in another; it may be in the capitals or crockets, in the niches or the traceries, or in all together, but in some one or other of the features it will be found always. If the mouldings are constant, the surface sculpture will change; if the capitals are of a fixed design, the traceries will change; if the traceries are monotonous, the capitals will change; and if even, as in some fine schools, the early English for example, there is the slightest approximation to an unvarying type of mouldings, capitals, and floral decoration, the variety is found in the disposition of the masses, and in the figure sculpture.
These noticeable differences were only allowed as part of the ongoing change that flowed through every aspect of Gothic design, making it a never-ending source of exploration for the viewer and imagination for the builder: change, which in the best styles is subtle and refined, and made more enjoyable by a blend of a noble consistency; in the more primitive styles, it can be somewhat whimsical and excessive; but in all cases, it’s a necessary and constant aspect of the school’s life. Sometimes the variety shows up in one element, sometimes in another; it can be in the capitals or crockets, in the niches or tracery, or in all of them combined, but it will always be present in some feature. If the moldings remain the same, the surface sculptures will vary; if the capitals stick to a specific design, the tracery will change; if the tracery is constant, the capitals will change; and even if, in some excellent schools, like early English for instance, there’s a slight approach to a uniform type of moldings, capitals, and floral decoration, the variety is found in the arrangement of the masses, and in the figure sculpture.
I must now refer for a moment, before we quit the consideration of this, the second mental element of Gothic, to the opening of the third chapter of the Seven Lamps of Architecture, in which the distinction was drawn (§ 2) between man gathering and man governing; between his acceptance of the sources of delight from nature, and his development of authoritative or imaginative power in their arrangement: for the two mental elements, not only of Gothic, but of all good architecture, which we have just been examining, belong to it, and are admirable in it, chiefly as it is, more than any other subject of art, the work of man, and the expression of the average power of man. A picture or poem is often little more than a feeble utterance of man's admiration of something out of himself; but architecture approaches more to a creation of his own, born of his necessities, and expressive of his nature. It is also, in some sort, the work of the whole race, while the picture or statue are the work of one only, in most cases more highly gifted than his fellows. And therefore we may expect that the first two elements of good architecture should be expressive of some great truths commonly belonging to the whole race, and necessary to be understood or felt by them in all their work that they do under the sun. And observe what they are: the confession of Imperfection, and the confession of Desire of Change. The building of the bird and the bee needs not express anything like this. It is perfect and unchanging. But just because we are something better than birds or bees, our building must confess that we have not reached the perfection we can imagine, and cannot rest in the condition we have attained. If we pretend to have reached either perfection or satisfaction, we have degraded ourselves and our work. God's work only may express that; but ours may never have that sentence written upon it,—"And behold, it was very good." And, observe again, it is not merely as it renders the edifice a book of various knowledge, or a mine of precious thought, that variety is essential to its nobleness. The vital principle is not the love of Knowledge, but the love of Change. It is that strange disquietude of the Gothic spirit that is its greatness; that restlessness of the dreaming mind, that wanders hither and thither among the niches, and flickers feverishly around the pinnacles, and frets and fades in labyrinthine knots and shadows along wall and roof, and yet is not satisfied, nor shall be satisfied. The Greek could stay in his triglyph furrow, and be at peace; but the work of the Gothic heart is fretwork still, and it can neither rest in, nor from, its labour, but must pass on, sleeplessly, until its love of change shall be pacified for ever in the change that must come alike on them that wake and them that sleep....
I need to briefly refer back to the second mental element of Gothic style before we move on. In the third chapter of the Seven Lamps of Architecture, a distinction is made (§ 2) between humans gathering inspiration from nature and humans taking charge of that inspiration through creative organization. These two mental elements, essential to both Gothic architecture and all great architecture we’ve just explored, stand out because this form of art, more than others, is a product of human effort and a reflection of our collective capabilities. A painting or poem often feels like a weak expression of admiration for something beyond us, while architecture feels more like a creation born from our needs and reflective of our identity. It represents not just an individual’s work, as most paintings or sculptures do, but the work of our entire species. Thus, we can expect that the first two elements of great architecture should reveal significant truths universally acknowledged, which are necessary for everyone to grasp or feel in their endeavors under the sky. And what are these truths? The acknowledgment of Imperfection and the acknowledgment of the Desire for Change. The construction of nests by birds and bees doesn’t need to express these ideas. Their creations are flawless and unchanged. But because we are more advanced than birds or bees, our structures must reveal that we haven't achieved the perfection we can envision and we cannot rest content with what we've accomplished. Claiming to have achieved perfection or satisfaction only diminishes both ourselves and our work. Only God's work can express that ideal; our work should never carry the statement, “And behold, it was very good.” Moreover, it’s not just about how the architecture serves as a wealth of knowledge or valuable ideas; variety is crucial to its greatness. The essential driving force is not the love of Knowledge, but rather the love of Change. It’s that unique restlessness of the Gothic spirit that defines its greatness; a restless mind flitting among niches, flickering excitedly around spires, and becoming entangled in intricate patterns and shadows along walls and ceilings, yet never finds satisfaction. The Greek could find peace in his triglyph designs, but the Gothic heart is always in motion, never at rest from its labor, endlessly moving on until its desire for change is finally quieted by the change that ultimately affects both the awake and the asleep.
Last, because the least essential, of the constituent elements of this noble school, was placed that of REDUNDANCE,—the uncalculating bestowal of the wealth of its labour. There is, indeed, much Gothic, and that of the best period, in which this element is hardly traceable, and which depends for its effect almost exclusively on loveliness of simple design and grace of uninvolved proportion; still, in the most characteristic buildings, a certain portion of their effect depends upon accumulation of ornament; and many of those which have most influence on the minds of men, have attained it by means of this attribute alone. And although, by careful study of the school, it is possible to arrive at a condition of taste which shall be better contented by a few perfect lines than by a whole façade covered with fretwork, the building which only satisfies such a taste is not to be considered the best. For the very first requirement of Gothic architecture being, as we saw above, that it shall both admit the aid, and appeal to the admiration, of the rudest as well as the most refined minds, the richness of the work is, paradoxical as the statement may appear, a part of its humility. No architecture is so haughty as that which is simple; which refuses to address the eye, except in a few clear and forceful lines; which implies, in offering so little to our regards, that all it has offered is perfect; and disdains, either by the complexity of the attractiveness of its features, to embarrass our investigation, or betray us into delight. That humility, which is the very life of the Gothic school, is shown not only in the imperfection, but in the accumulation, of ornament. The inferior rank of the workman is often shown as much in the richness, as the roughness, of his work; and if the co-operation of every hand, and the sympathy of every heart, are to be received, we must be content to allow the redundance which disguises the failure of the feeble, and wins the regard of the inattentive. There are, however, far nobler interests mingling, in the Gothic heart, with the rude love of decorative accumulation: a magnificent enthusiasm, which feels as if it never could do enough to reach the fulness of its ideal; an unselfishness of sacrifice, which would rather cast fruitless labour before the altar than stand idle in the market; and, finally, a profound sympathy with the fulness and wealth of the material universe, rising out of that Naturalism whose operation we have already endeavoured to define. The sculptor who sought for his models among the forest leaves, could not but quickly and deeply feel that complexity need not involve the loss of grace, nor richness that of repose; and every hour which he spent in the study of the minute and various work of Nature, made him feel more forcibly the barrenness of what was best in that of man: nor is it to be wondered at, that, seeing her perfect and exquisite creations poured forth in a profusion which conception could not grasp nor calculation sum, he should think that it ill became him to be niggardly of his own rude craftsmanship; and where he saw throughout the universe a faultless beauty lavished on measureless spaces of broidered field and blooming mountain, to grudge his poor and imperfect labour to the few stones that he had raised one upon another, for habitation or memorial. The years of his life passed away before his task was accomplished; but generation succeeded generation with unwearied enthusiasm, and the cathedral front was at last lost in the tapestry of its traceries, like a rock among the thickets and herbage of spring.
Last, because it is the least essential part of this noble school, is the element of REDUNDANCE—the uncalculated sharing of its labor's wealth. There is indeed a lot of Gothic architecture, particularly from the best period, where this element is hardly noticeable, relying almost entirely on the beauty of simple design and the grace of straightforward proportions. Still, in the most characteristic buildings, a significant part of their impact comes from the accumulation of ornamentation; many that have the greatest influence on people have achieved it through this quality alone. Although a careful study of the school can lead to a taste that prefers a few perfect lines over an entire façade adorned with intricate details, a building that solely satisfies such a taste should not be seen as the best. The primary requirement of Gothic architecture, as we noted before, is that it must appeal to and engage both the simplest and the most discerning minds. Paradoxically, the richness of the work is part of its humility. No architecture is as arrogant as that which is simple, offering only a few clear and bold lines, implying that everything it presents is flawless, and refusing to overwhelm our attention with complexity or lead us into joy. That humility, which is the very essence of the Gothic school, is evident not only in its imperfections but also in its abundance of decorations. A skilled worker often shows their lesser rank as much in the richness as in the roughness of their work; and if we are to seek the cooperation of every hand and the sympathy of every heart, we must accept the redundancy that masks the failures of the weak and captures the attention of the indifferent. However, there are far greater interests intertwined in the Gothic spirit alongside the simple love of decorative excess: a magnificent enthusiasm that feels it can never do enough to achieve its ideals; a selflessness that prefers to offer fruitless labor to the altar rather than remain idle in the market; and, finally, a deep sympathy with the richness and abundance of the material universe, arising from that Naturalism we have previously attempted to define. The sculptor who searches for their models among the forest leaves cannot help but quickly and profoundly realize that complexity does not have to sacrifice grace, nor does richness need to undermine tranquility; and each hour spent studying the intricate and varied work of Nature made him acutely aware of the barrenness of the best in human craftsmanship. It is no wonder that, witnessing Nature's perfect and exquisite creations overflowing in a profusion beyond comprehension or calculation, he would feel it inappropriate to be stingy with his own crude artistry; and where he saw a flawless beauty in the unlimited expanses of embroidered fields and blooming mountains, he would hesitate to begrudge his meager and imperfect work to the few stones he had piled up for habitation or remembrance. Years of his life passed before his task was finished; yet generation after generation continued with tireless enthusiasm, and the cathedral façade was ultimately lost within its tapestry of intricate designs, like a rock hidden among the thickets and greenery of spring.
This book began to assume shape in Ruskin's mind as early as 1846; he actually wrote it in the six months between November, 1848, and April, 1849. It is the first of five illustrated volumes embodying the results of seven years devoted to the study of the principles and ideals of Gothic Architecture, the other volumes being The Stones of Venice and Examples of the Architecture of Venice (1851). In the first edition of The Seven Lamps the plates were not only all drawn but also etched by his own hand. Ruskin at a later time wrote that the purpose of The Seven Lamps was "to show that certain right states of temper and moral feeling were the magic powers by which all good architecture had been produced." He is really applying here the same tests of truth and sincerity that he employed in Modern Painters. Chronologically, this volume and the others treating of architecture come between the composition of Volumes II and III of Modern Painters. Professor Charles Eliot Norton writes that the Seven Lamps is "the first treatise in English to teach the real significance of architecture as the most trustworthy record of the life and faith of nations." The following selections form the closing chapters of the volume, and have a peculiar interest as anticipating the social and political ideas which came to colour all his later work.
This book started taking shape in Ruskin's mind as early as 1846; he actually wrote it in the six months between November 1848 and April 1849. It's the first of five illustrated volumes that embody the results of seven years spent studying the principles and ideals of Gothic Architecture, with the other volumes being The Stones of Venice and Examples of the Architecture of Venice (1851). In the first edition of The Seven Lamps, the plates were not only all drawn but also etched by him personally. Ruskin later stated that the aim of The Seven Lamps was "to show that certain right states of temper and moral feeling were the magic powers by which all good architecture had been produced." He is essentially applying the same standards of truth and sincerity that he used in Modern Painters. Chronologically, this volume and the others about architecture come between the writing of Volumes II and III of Modern Painters. Professor Charles Eliot Norton notes that The Seven Lamps is "the first treatise in English to teach the real significance of architecture as the most trustworthy record of the life and faith of nations." The selections that follow form the closing chapters of the volume and are particularly interesting as they anticipate the social and political ideas that influenced all his later work.
THE LAMP OF MEMORY
Among the hours of his life to which the writer looks back with peculiar gratitude, as having been marked by more than ordinary fulness of joy or clearness of teaching, is one passed, now some years ago, near time of sunset, among the broken masses of pine forest which skirt the course of the Ain, above the village of Champagnole, in the Jura. It is a spot which has all the solemnity, with none of the savageness, of the Alps; where there is a sense of a great power beginning to be manifested in the earth, and of a deep and majestic concord in the rise of the long low lines of piny hills; the first utterance of those mighty mountain symphonies, soon to be more loudly lifted and wildly broken along the battlements of the Alps. But their strength is as yet restrained; and the far reaching ridges of pastoral mountain succeed each other, like the long and sighing swell which moves over quiet waters from some far off stormy sea. And there is a deep tenderness pervading that vast monotony. The destructive forces and the stern expression of the central ranges are alike withdrawn. No frost-ploughed, dust-encumbered paths of ancient glacier fret the soft Jura pastures; no splintered heaps of ruin break the fair ranks of her forest; no pale, defiled, or furious rivers rend their rude and changeful ways among her rocks. Patiently, eddy by eddy, the clear green streams wind along their well-known beds; and under the dark quietness of the undisturbed pines, there spring up, year by year, such company of joyful flowers as I know not the like of among all the blessings of the earth. It was spring time, too; and all were coming forth in clusters crowded for very love; there was room enough for all, but they crushed their leaves into all manner of strange shapes only to be nearer each other. There was the wood anemone, star after star, closing every now and then into nebulae; and there was the oxalis, troop by troop, like virginal processions of the Mois de Marie,[162] the dark vertical clefts in the limestone choked up with them as with heavy snow, and touched with ivy on the edges—ivy as light and lovely as the vine; and, ever and anon, a blue gush of violets, and cowslip bells in sunny places; and in the more open ground, the vetch, and comfrey, and mezereon, and the small sapphire buds of the Polygala Alpina, and the wild strawberry, just a blossom or two all showered amidst the golden softness of deep, warm, amber-coloured moss. I came out presently on the edge of the ravine: the solemn murmur of its waters rose suddenly from beneath, mixed with the singing of the thrushes among the pine boughs; and, on the opposite side of the valley, walled all along as it was by grey cliffs of limestone, there was a hawk sailing slowly off their brow, touching them nearly with his wings, and with the shadows of the pines flickering upon his plumage from above; but with the fall of a hundred fathoms under his breast, and the curling pools of the green river gliding and glittering dizzily beneath him, their foam globes moving with him as he flew. It would be difficult to conceive a scene less dependent upon any other interest than that of its own secluded and serious beauty; but the writer well remembers the sudden blankness and chill which were cast upon it when he endeavoured, in order more strictly to arrive at the sources of its impressiveness, to imagine it, for a moment, a scene in some aboriginal forest of the New Continent. The flowers in an instant lost their light, the river its music; the hills became oppressively desolate; a heaviness in the boughs of the darkened forest showed how much of their former power had been dependent upon a life which was not theirs, how much of the glory of the imperishable, or continually renewed, creation is reflected from things more precious in their memories than it, in its renewing. Those ever springing flowers and ever flowing streams had been dyed by the deep colours of human endurance, valour, and virtue; and the crests of the sable hills that rose against the evening sky received a deeper worship, because their far shadows fell eastward over the iron wall of Joux, and the four-square keep of Granson.
Among the hours of his life to which the writer looks back with peculiar gratitude, as having been marked by more than ordinary fulness of joy or clearness of teaching, is one passed, now some years ago, near time of sunset, among the broken masses of pine forest which skirt the course of the Ain, above the village of Champagnole, in the Jura. It is a spot which has all the solemnity, with none of the savageness, of the Alps; where there is a sense of a great power beginning to be manifested in the earth, and of a deep and majestic concord in the rise of the long low lines of piny hills; the first utterance of those mighty mountain symphonies, soon to be more loudly lifted and wildly broken along the battlements of the Alps. But their strength is as yet restrained; and the far reaching ridges of pastoral mountain succeed each other, like the long and sighing swell which moves over quiet waters from some far off stormy sea. And there is a deep tenderness pervading that vast monotony. The destructive forces and the stern expression of the central ranges are alike withdrawn. No frost-ploughed, dust-encumbered paths of ancient glacier fret the soft Jura pastures; no splintered heaps of ruin break the fair ranks of her forest; no pale, defiled, or furious rivers rend their rude and changeful ways among her rocks. Patiently, eddy by eddy, the clear green streams wind along their well-known beds; and under the dark quietness of the undisturbed pines, there spring up, year by year, such company of joyful flowers as I know not the like of among all the blessings of the earth. It was spring time, too; and all were coming forth in clusters crowded for very love; there was room enough for all, but they crushed their leaves into all manner of strange shapes only to be nearer each other. There was the wood anemone, star after star, closing every now and then into nebulae; and there was the oxalis, troop by troop, like virginal processions of the Mois de Marie,[162] the dark vertical clefts in the limestone choked up with them as with heavy snow, and touched with ivy on the edges—ivy as light and lovely as the vine; and, ever and anon, a blue gush of violets, and cowslip bells in sunny places; and in the more open ground, the vetch, and comfrey, and mezereon, and the small sapphire buds of the Polygala Alpina, and the wild strawberry, just a blossom or two all showered amidst the golden softness of deep, warm, amber-coloured moss. I came out presently on the edge of the ravine: the solemn murmur of its waters rose suddenly from beneath, mixed with the singing of the thrushes among the pine boughs; and, on the opposite side of the valley, walled all along as it was by grey cliffs of limestone, there was a hawk sailing slowly off their brow, touching them nearly with his wings, and with the shadows of the pines flickering upon his plumage from above; but with the fall of a hundred fathoms under his breast, and the curling pools of the green river gliding and glittering dizzily beneath him, their foam globes moving with him as he flew. It would be difficult to conceive a scene less dependent upon any other interest than that of its own secluded and serious beauty; but the writer well remembers the sudden blankness and chill which were cast upon it when he endeavoured, in order more strictly to arrive at the sources of its impressiveness, to imagine it, for a moment, a scene in some aboriginal forest of the New Continent. The flowers in an instant lost their light, the river its music; the hills became oppressively desolate; a heaviness in the boughs of the darkened forest showed how much of their former power had been dependent upon a life which was not theirs, how much of the glory of the imperishable, or continually renewed, creation is reflected from things more precious in their memories than it, in its renewing. Those ever springing flowers and ever flowing streams had been dyed by the deep colours of human endurance, valour, and virtue; and the crests of the sable hills that rose against the evening sky received a deeper worship, because their far shadows fell eastward over the iron wall of Joux, and the four-square keep of Granson.
It is as the centralization and protectress of this sacred influence, that Architecture is to be regarded by us with the most serious thought. We may live without her, and worship without her, but we cannot remember without her. How cold is all history, how lifeless all imagery, compared to that which the living nation writes, and the uncorrupted marble bears!—how many pages of doubtful record might we not often spare, for a few stones left one upon another! The ambition of the old Babel builders was well directed for this world:[163] there are but two strong conquerors of the forgetfulness of men, Poetry and Architecture; and the latter in some sort includes the former, and is mightier in its reality: it is well to have, not only what men have thought and felt, but what their hands have handled, and their strength wrought, and their eyes beheld, all the days of their life. The age of Homer is surrounded with darkness, his very personality with doubt. Not so that of Pericles: and the day is coming when we shall confess, that we have learned more of Greece out of the crumbled fragments of her sculpture than even from her sweet singers or soldier historians. And if indeed there be any profit in our knowledge of the past, or any joy in the thought of being remembered hereafter, which can give strength to present exertion, or patience to present endurance, there are two duties respecting national architecture whose importance it is impossible to overrate: the first, to render the architecture of the day, historical; and, the second, to preserve, as the most precious of inheritances, that of past ages.
It is as the centralization and protectress of this sacred influence, that Architecture is to be regarded by us with the most serious thought. We may live without her, and worship without her, but we cannot remember without her. How cold is all history, how lifeless all imagery, compared to that which the living nation writes, and the uncorrupted marble bears!—how many pages of doubtful record might we not often spare, for a few stones left one upon another! The ambition of the old Babel builders was well directed for this world:[163] there are but two strong conquerors of the forgetfulness of men, Poetry and Architecture; and the latter in some sort includes the former, and is mightier in its reality: it is well to have, not only what men have thought and felt, but what their hands have handled, and their strength wrought, and their eyes beheld, all the days of their life. The age of Homer is surrounded with darkness, his very personality with doubt. Not so that of Pericles: and the day is coming when we shall confess, that we have learned more of Greece out of the crumbled fragments of her sculpture than even from her sweet singers or soldier historians. And if indeed there be any profit in our knowledge of the past, or any joy in the thought of being remembered hereafter, which can give strength to present exertion, or patience to present endurance, there are two duties respecting national architecture whose importance it is impossible to overrate: the first, to render the architecture of the day, historical; and, the second, to preserve, as the most precious of inheritances, that of past ages.
It is in the first of these two directions that Memory may truly be said to be the Sixth Lamp of Architecture; for it is in becoming memorial or monumental that a true perfection is attained by civil and domestic buildings; and this partly as they are, with such a view, built in a more stable manner, and partly as their decorations are consequently animated by a metaphorical or historical meaning.
It is in the first of these two directions that Memory can really be called the Sixth Lamp of Architecture; because it's through becoming memorial or monumental that real perfection is achieved by public and private buildings. This is partly because they are built more sturdily with this in mind, and partly because their decorations are then brought to life by metaphorical or historical significance.
As regards domestic buildings, there must always be a certain limitation to views of this kind in the power, as well as in the hearts, of men; still I cannot but think it an evil sign of a people when their houses are built to last for one generation only. There is a sanctity in a good man's house which cannot be renewed in every tenement that rises on its ruins: and I believe that good men would generally feel this; and that having spent their lives happily and honourably, they would be grieved, at the close of them, to think that the place of their earthly abode, which had seen, and seemed almost to sympathize in, all their honour, their gladness, or their suffering,—that this, with all the record it bare of them, and of all material things that they had loved and ruled over, and set the stamp of themselves upon—was to be swept away, as soon as there was room made for them in the grave; that no respect was to be shown to it, no affection felt for it, no good to be drawn from it by their children; that though there was a monument in the church, there was no warm monument in the hearth and house to them; that all that they ever treasured was despised, and the places that had sheltered and comforted them were dragged down to the dust. I say that a good man would fear this; and that, far more, a good son, a noble descendant, would fear doing it to his father's house. I say that if men lived like men indeed, their houses would be temples—temples which we should hardly dare to injure, and in which it would make us holy to be permitted to live; and there must be a strange dissolution of natural affection, a strange unthankfulness for all that homes have given and parents taught, a strange consciousness that we have been unfaithful to our fathers' honour, or that our own lives are not such as would make our dwellings sacred to our children, when each man would fain build to himself, and build for the little revolution of his own life only. And I look upon those pitiful concretions of lime and clay which spring up, in mildewed forwardness, out of the kneaded fields about our capital—upon those thin, tottering, foundationless shells of splintered wood and imitated stone—upon those gloomy rows of formalized minuteness, alike without difference and without fellowship, as solitary as similar—not merely with the careless disgust of an offended eye, not merely with sorrow for a desecrated landscape, but with a painful foreboding that the roots of our national greatness must be deeply cankered when they are thus loosely struck in their native ground; that those comfortless and unhonoured dwellings are the signs of a great and spreading spirit of popular discontent; that they mark the time when every man's aim is to be in some more elevated sphere than his natural one, and every man's past life is his habitual scorn; when men build in the hope of leaving the places they have built, and live in the hope of forgetting the years that they have lived; when the comfort, the peace, the religion of home have ceased to be felt; and the crowded tenements of a struggling and restless population differ only from the tents of the Arab or the Gipsy by their less healthy openness to the air of heaven, and less happy choice of their spot of earth; by their sacrifice of liberty without the gain of rest, and of stability without the luxury of change.
As for homes, there should always be some limitations on how people view them, both in their power and in their hearts. Still, I can’t help but see it as a troubling sign when houses are built to last only a single generation. There’s a sanctity in a good person's home that can’t be replicated in every building that comes up on its ruins. I believe that decent individuals would feel this deeply; after living their lives joyfully and honorably, they would be saddened at the end to think that the place they lived, which witnessed and almost empathized with all their honor, joy, or suffering—where all the memories of what they cherished and ruled over were stored—would be wiped away as soon as there was space for them in the grave. They would feel that no respect is given to it, no affection felt, and no benefit drawn from it by their children; that even though there might be a monument in the church, there would be no warm monument in the hearth and home for them; that everything they ever valued would be neglected, and the places that had offered them shelter and comfort would be reduced to dust. I say that a good person would dread this, and even more so, a good son or noble descendant would fear doing this to their father’s home. If people lived authentically, their homes would be temples—sacred places that we’d hesitate to harm, and where it would be a privilege to live. There must be a strange breakdown of natural affection, a peculiar ungratefulness for what homes have provided and what parents have taught, a strange awareness of our failure to honor our fathers, or that our own lives aren’t worthy of making our homes sacred to our children when each person is focused only on building for themselves and for the fleeting moments of their own lives. I look at those sad clusters of cement and clay that pop up, carelessly, in the damp fields around our capital—those flimsy, wobbly, foundationless shells of broken wood and faux stone—those dreary rows of standardized little houses, identical and disconnected, solitary as they are similar—not just with a weary disgust of an offended eye, not just with sadness for a spoiled landscape, but with a painful sense that the roots of our national greatness must be severely damaged when they’re so loosely planted in their natural soil; that these uncomfortable, unvalued homes are signs of a widespread spirit of public discontent; that they reflect a time when each person’s goal is to be in a higher place than where they naturally belong, and every man’s past life is something to be scorned; when people build hoping to leave the places they’ve built, and live hoping to forget the years they’ve lived; when the comfort, peace, and sense of belonging of home have faded away; and the cramped residences of a struggling and restless populace differ only from the tents of the Arab or the Gypsy by their less healthy exposure to the air of heaven, and their less fortunate choice of land; by their surrender of freedom without gaining rest, and of stability without enjoying change.
This is no slight, no consequenceless evil; it is ominous, infectious, and fecund of other fault and misfortune. When men do not love their hearths, nor reverence their thresholds, it is a sign that they have dishonoured both, and that they have never acknowledged the true universality of that Christian worship which was indeed to supersede the idolatry, but not the piety, of the pagan. Our God is a household God, as well as a heavenly one; He has an altar in every man's dwelling; let men look to it when they rend it lightly and pour out its ashes. It is not a question of mere ocular delight, it is no question of intellectual pride, or of cultivated and critical fancy, how, and with what aspect of durability and of completeness, the domestic buildings of a nation shall be raised. It is one of those moral duties, not with more impunity to be neglected because the perception of them depends on a finely toned and balanced conscientiousness, to build our dwellings with care, and patience, and fondness, and diligent completion, and with a view to their duration at least for such a period as, in the ordinary course of national revolutions, might be supposed likely to extend to the entire alteration of the direction of local interests. This at the least; but it would be better if, in every possible instance, men built their own houses on a scale commensurate rather with their condition at the commencement, than their attainments at the termination, of their worldly career; and built them to stand as long as human work at its strongest can be hoped to stand; recording to their children what they had been, and from what, if so it had been permitted them, they had risen. And when houses are thus built, we may have that true domestic architecture, the beginning of all other, which does not disdain to treat with respect and thoughtfulness the small habitation as well as the large, and which invests with the dignity of contented manhood the narrowness of worldly circumstance.
This isn’t just a minor issue; it’s a serious problem that has far-reaching effects. When people don’t cherish their homes or respect their doorsteps, it shows they’ve disrespected both and haven’t recognized the true universal nature of the Christian faith that was meant to replace pagan idolatry, but not the devotion behind it. Our God is both a God of the home and of the heavens; He has an altar in every person’s home, and people should be mindful when they disregard it and scatter its ashes. This isn’t just about superficial beauty or intellectual pride, nor is it merely a matter of refined taste when it comes to how and with what level of durability and completeness we construct our homes as a nation. It’s one of those moral responsibilities that can’t be ignored just because recognizing them requires a well-tuned sense of conscience. We must build our homes with care, patience, affection, and thoroughness, aiming for their lasting presence, at least during a time frame that would typically encompass significant changes in local interests. Ideally, people should build their houses according to their initial circumstances rather than their final achievements, constructing them to endure as long as human effort can reasonably expect. This way, they’ll remind their children of who they were and how far they’ve come, if given the chance. When homes are built in this manner, we can create a true domestic architecture—the foundation of all others—that respects and thoughtfully acknowledges both small and large dwellings, giving dignity to modest means and the contentment of mature adulthood.
I look to this spirit of honourable, proud, peaceful self-possession, this abiding wisdom of contented life, as probably one of the chief sources of great intellectual power in all ages, and beyond dispute as the very primal source of the great architecture of old Italy and France. To this day, the interest of their fairest cities depends, not on the isolated richness of palaces, but on the cherished and exquisite decoration of even the smallest tenements of their proud periods. The most elaborate piece of architecture in Venice is a small house at the head of the Grand Canal, consisting of a ground floor with two storeys above, three windows in the first, and two in the second. Many of the most exquisite buildings are on the narrower canals, and of no larger dimensions. One of the most interesting pieces of fifteenth-century architecture in North Italy, is a small house in a back street, behind the market-place of Vicenza; it bears date 1481, and the motto, Il. n'est. rose. sans. épine; it has also only a ground floor and two storeys, with three windows in each, separated by rich flower-work, and with balconies, supported, the central one by an eagle with open wings, the lateral ones by winged griffins standing on cornucopiæ. The idea that a house must be large in order to be well built, is altogether of modern growth, and is parallel with the idea, that no picture can be historical, except of a size admitting figures larger than life.
I admire the spirit of honorable, proud, and peaceful self-possession, this lasting wisdom of a contented life, as one of the main sources of great intellectual power throughout history, and undeniably the foundational source of the magnificent architecture of old Italy and France. Even today, the beauty of their finest cities relies not on the isolated wealth of palaces, but on the beloved and exquisite detailing of even the smallest homes from their proud eras. The most elaborate piece of architecture in Venice is a small house at the head of the Grand Canal, which has a ground floor with two stories above, three windows on the first floor, and two on the second. Many of the most stunning buildings are along the narrower canals and are no larger. One of the most interesting examples of fifteenth-century architecture in Northern Italy is a small house in a back street behind the market square of Vicenza; it dates back to 1481 and has the motto, Il. n'est. rose. sans. épine; it also features just a ground floor and two stories, with three windows on each floor, separated by intricate floral designs, and balconies supported— the central one by an eagle with open wings, the side ones by winged griffins perched on cornucopia. The notion that a house must be large to be well built is entirely a modern concept, just like the belief that a painting can’t be historical unless it features figures larger than life.
I would have, then, our ordinary dwelling-houses built to last, and built to be lovely; as rich and full of pleasantness as may be, within and without; with what degree of likeness to each other in style and manner, I will say presently, under another head;[164] but, at all events, with such differences as might suit and express each man's character and occupation, and partly his history. This right over the house, I conceive, belongs to its first builder, and is to be respected by his children; and it would be well that blank stones should be left in places, to be inscribed with a summary of his life and of its experience, raising thus the habitation into a kind of monument, and developing, into more systematic instructiveness, that good custom which was of old universal, and which still remains among some of the Swiss and Germans, of acknowledging the grace of God's permission to build and possess a quiet resting-place, in such sweet words as may well close our speaking of these things. I have taken them from the front of a cottage lately built among the green pastures which descend from the village of Grindelwald to the lower glacier:—
I would have, then, our ordinary dwelling-houses built to last, and built to be lovely; as rich and full of pleasantness as may be, within and without; with what degree of likeness to each other in style and manner, I will say presently, under another head;[164] but, at all events, with such differences as might suit and express each man's character and occupation, and partly his history. This right over the house, I conceive, belongs to its first builder, and is to be respected by his children; and it would be well that blank stones should be left in places, to be inscribed with a summary of his life and of its experience, raising thus the habitation into a kind of monument, and developing, into more systematic instructiveness, that good custom which was of old universal, and which still remains among some of the Swiss and Germans, of acknowledging the grace of God's permission to build and possess a quiet resting-place, in such sweet words as may well close our speaking of these things. I have taken them from the front of a cottage lately built among the green pastures which descend from the village of Grindelwald to the lower glacier:—
Mit herzlichem Vertrauen
With heartfelt trust
Hat Johannes Mooter und Maria Rubi
Hat Johannes Mooter und Maria Rubi
Dieses Haus bauen lassen.
Build this house.
Der liebe Gott woll uns bewahren
Der liebe Gott woll uns bewahren
Vor allem Unglück und Gefahren,
Especially misfortune and dangers,
Und es in Segen lassen stehn
Und es in Segen lassen stehn
Auf der Reise durch diese Jammerzeit
Auf der Reise durch diese schwere Zeit
Nach dem himmlischen Paradiese,
After the heavenly paradise,
Wo alle Frommen wohnen,
Where all the faithful live,
Da wird Gott sie belohnen
There God will reward them.
Mil der Friedenskrone
Mil of the Peace Crown
Zu alle Ewigkeit.[165]
For all eternity.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
In public buildings the historical purpose should be still more definite. It is one of the advantages of Gothic architecture,—I use the word Gothic in the most extended sense as broadly opposed to classical,—that it admits of a richness of record altogether unlimited. Its minute and multitudinous sculptural decorations afford means of expressing, either symbolically or literally, all that need be known of national feeling or achievement. More decoration will, indeed, be usually required than can take so elevated a character; and much, even in the most thoughtful periods, has been left to the freedom of fancy, or suffered to consist of mere repetitions of some national bearing or symbol. It is, however, generally unwise, even in mere surface ornament, to surrender the power and privilege of variety which the spirit of Gothic architecture admits; much more in important features—capitals of columns or bosses, and string-courses, as of course in all confessed has-reliefs. Better the rudest work that tells a story or records a fact, than the richest without meaning. There should not be a single ornament put upon great civic buildings, without some intellectual intention. Actual representation of history has in modern times been checked by a difficulty, mean indeed, but steadfast; that of unmanageable costume: nevertheless, by a sufficiently bold imaginative treatment, and frank use of symbols, all such obstacles may be vanquished; not perhaps in the degree necessary to produce sculpture in itself satisfactory, but at all events so as to enable it to become a grand and expressive element of architectural composition. Take, for example, the management of the capitals of the ducal palace at Venice. History, as such, was indeed entrusted to the painters of its interior, but every capital of its arcades was filled with meaning. The large one, the corner stone of the whole, next the entrance, was devoted to the symbolization of Abstract Justice; above it is a sculpture of the Judgment of Solomon, remarkable for a beautiful subjection in its treatment to its decorative purpose. The figures, if the subject had been entirely composed of them, would have awkwardly interrupted the line of the angle, and diminished its apparent strength; and therefore in the midst of them, entirely without relation to them, and indeed actually between the executioner and interceding mother, there rises the ribbed trunk of a massy tree, which supports and continues the shaft of the angle, and whose leaves above overshadow and enrich the whole. The capital below bears among its leafage a throned figure of Justice, Trajan doing justice to the widow, Aristotle "che die legge," and one or two other subjects now unintelligible from decay. The capitals next in order represent the virtues and vices in succession, as preservative or destructive of national peace and power, concluding with Faith, with the inscription "Fides optima in Deo est." A figure is seen on the opposite side of the capital, worshipping the sun. After these, one or two capitals are fancifully decorated with birds, and then come a series representing, first the various fruits, then the national costumes, and then the animals of the various countries subject to Venetian rule.
In public buildings, the historical purpose should be even clearer. One of the advantages of Gothic architecture—I use the term Gothic in a broad sense, contrasting it with classical architecture—is that it allows for an unlimited richness of expression. Its detailed and numerous decorative sculptures provide a way to convey, either symbolically or literally, everything that needs to be known about national pride or achievements. More decoration is usually required than can convey such elevated concepts, and even during the most thoughtful periods, a lot has been left to imagination or has ended up being just repetitive national symbols. However, it is generally unwise, even in mere surface decoration, to surrender the ability to incorporate variety that the spirit of Gothic architecture encourages; this is even truer for key features—like column capitals or decorative bosses, and of course in all prominent reliefs. It’s better to have the simplest work that tells a story or records a fact than to have the richest decoration that lacks meaning. No ornament should be added to significant civic buildings without some intellectual purpose behind it. The actual representation of history in modern times has faced a persistent challenge, albeit a minor one: unmanageable costumes. Nonetheless, with bold imaginative approaches and straightforward use of symbols, all such challenges can be overcome; perhaps not to the extent needed for sculpture to be fully satisfactory on its own, but certainly enough to enable it to become a grand and expressive part of architectural design. For example, look at how the capitals of the ducal palace in Venice are handled. History, in a sense, was left to the painters of the interior, but each capital of its arcades was packed with meaning. The prominent one, the cornerstone of the whole structure, located by the entrance, symbolizes Abstract Justice; above it is a sculpture of the Judgment of Solomon, notable for how beautifully it fits its decorative purpose. The figures, if the subject relied solely on them, would awkwardly disrupt the angle's line and lessen its visual strength; thus, amidst them, completely unrelated and indeed positioned between the executioner and the interceding mother, rises the ribbed trunk of a sturdy tree that supports and extends the angle’s shaft, with its leaves above casting shade and enriching the whole design. The capital below has among its foliage a throned figure of Justice, Trajan delivering justice to a widow, Aristotle "che die legge," and a few other subjects now obscured by time. The next capitals in line depict virtues and vices in succession, either preserving or threatening national peace and strength, ending with Faith, which has the inscription "Fides optima in Deo est." A figure can be seen on the opposite side of the capital, worshipping the sun. Following these, one or two capitals are whimsically decorated with birds, and then comes a series representing first various fruits, then national costumes, and finally the animals from the different countries under Venetian rule.
Now, not to speak of any more important public building, let us imagine our own India House adorned in this way, by historical or symbolical sculpture: massively built in the first place; then chased with has-reliefs of our Indian battles, and fretted with carvings of Oriental foliage, or inlaid with Oriental stones; and the more important members of its decoration composed of groups of Indian life and landscape, and prominently expressing the phantasms of Hindoo worship in their subjection to the Cross. Would not one such work be better than a thousand histories? If, however, we have not the invention necessary for such efforts, or if, which is probably one of the most noble excuses we can offer for our deficiency in such matters, we have less pleasure in talking about ourselves, even in marble, than the Continental nations, at least we have no excuse for any want of care in the points which insure the building's endurance. And as this question is one of great interest in its relations to the choice of various modes of decoration, it will be necessary to enter into it at some length.
Now, without discussing any other important public building, let’s picture our own India House decorated like this, with historical or symbolic sculptures: solidly constructed to begin with; then embellished with reliefs of our Indian battles, and intricately carved with floral designs typical of the East, or inlaid with stones from the region; and the key parts of its decor featuring groups representing Indian life and landscapes, clearly showcasing aspects of Hindu worship in relation to the Cross. Wouldn’t one such piece be more valuable than a thousand histories? However, if we lack the creativity for such ventures, or if, which is perhaps one of the best excuses we can offer for our shortcomings in these areas, we care less about celebrating ourselves, even in stone, than the nations of Europe do, we at least shouldn't be careless about ensuring the building's durability. Since this topic is of significant interest regarding the choice of different decoration styles, it’s important to explore it in depth.
The benevolent regards and purposes of men in masses seldom can be supposed to extend beyond their own generation. They may look to posterity as an audience, may hope for its attention, and labour for its praise: they may trust to its recognition of unacknowledged merit, and demand its justice for contemporary wrong. But all this is mere selfishness, and does not involve the slightest regard to, or consideration of, the interest of those by whose numbers we would fain swell the circle of our flatterers, and by whose authority we would gladly support our presently disputed claims. The idea of self-denial for the sake of posterity, of practising present economy for the sake of debtors yet unborn, of planting forests that our descendants may live under their shade, or of raising cities for future nations to inhabit, never, I suppose, efficiently takes place among publicly recognized motives of exertion. Yet these are not the less our duties; nor is our part fitly sustained upon the earth, unless the range of our intended and deliberate usefulness include, not only the companions but the successors, of our pilgrimage. God has lent us the earth for our life; it is a great entail. It belongs as much to those who are to come after us, and whose names are already written in the book of creation, as to us; and we have no right, by anything that we do or neglect, to involve them in unnecessary penalties, or deprive them of benefits which it was in our power to bequeath. And this the more, because it is one of the appointed conditions of the labour of men that, in proportion to the time between the seed-sowing and the harvest, is the fulness of the fruit; and that generally, therefore, the farther off we place our aim, and the less we desire to be ourselves the witnesses of what we have laboured for, the more wide and rich will be the measure of our success. Men cannot benefit those that are with them as they can benefit those who come after them; and of all the pulpits from which human voice is ever sent forth, there is none from which it reaches so far as from the grave.
The good intentions and goals of people in groups rarely seem to go beyond their own generation. They might see future generations as an audience, hoping for their attention and working for their praise. They might rely on future recognition of unrecognized efforts and expect justice for injustices faced in their own time. But all of this is just selfishness and doesn’t truly consider the interests of those whose numbers we wish to increase in our circle of admirers, or whose authority we would like to back our currently contested claims. The idea of sacrificing for future generations, practicing frugality for those still to come, planting trees so that our descendants can live in their shade, or building cities for future populations to inhabit, doesn’t usually come up as a public motivation for effort. Still, these are our responsibilities; our role on this earth isn't fulfilled unless our intended and conscious contributions consider not just our contemporaries but also those who will follow us. God has given us this earth for our lives; it's a great inheritance. It belongs just as much to those who will come after us and who are already part of creation, as it does to us; we have no right, through our actions or inactions, to impose unnecessary hardships on them or deprive them of benefits we could have left behind. This is especially true because one of the conditions of human labor is that, the longer the time between planting and harvesting, the greater the yield. Generally, the more distant our goals are and the less we desire to witness the results of our efforts, the greater and richer our success will be. People can help those who are currently around them, but they can benefit those who come after them even more; and among all the platforms from which the human voice is heard, none travels further than from the grave.
Nor is there, indeed, any present loss, in such respect for futurity. Every human action gains in honour, in grace, in all true magnificence, by its regard to things that are to come. It is the far sight, the quiet and confident patience, that, above all other attributes, separate man from man, and near him to his Maker; and there is no action nor art, whose majesty we may not measure by this test. Therefore, when we build, let us think that we build for ever. Let it not be for present delight, nor for present use alone; let it be such work as our descendants will thank us for, and let us think, as we lay stone on stone, that a time is to come when those stones will be held sacred because our hands have touched them, and that men will say as they look upon the labour and wrought substance of them, "See! this our fathers did for us." For, indeed, the greatest glory of a building is not in its stones, nor in its gold. Its glory is in its Age, and in that deep sense of voicefulness, of stern watching, of mysterious sympathy, nay, even of approval or condemnation, which we feel in walls that have long been washed by the passing waves of humanity. It is in their lasting witness against men, in their quiet contrast with the transitional character of all things, in the strength which, through the lapse of seasons and times, and the decline and birth of dynasties, and the changing of the face of the earth, and of the limits of the sea, maintains its sculptured shapeliness for a time insuperable, connects forgotten and following ages with each other, and half constitutes the identity, as it concentrates the sympathy, of nations: it is in that golden stain of time, that we are to look for the real light, and colour, and preciousness of architecture; and it is not until a building has assumed this character, till it has been entrusted with the fame, and hallowed by the deeds of men, till its walls have been witnesses of suffering, and its pillars rise out of the shadows of death, that its existence, more lasting as it is than that of the natural objects of the world around it, can be gifted with even so much as these possess, of language and of life.
Nor is there, in fact, any current loss when it comes to future considerations. Every human action gains in honor, grace, and true magnificence by looking ahead. It’s the long-term vision, the calm and confident patience, that sets one person apart from another and draws them closer to their Creator; and there's no action or art whose greatness we can't measure by this standard. So, when we build, let's remember that we’re building for eternity. It shouldn't just be for present enjoyment or immediate use; let's create something our descendants will appreciate. As we lay stone upon stone, let’s think of a time to come when those stones will be revered because we have touched them, and people will say as they view the labor and craftsmanship, "Look! This is what our ancestors did for us." Because, in truth, the greatest glory of a building isn’t in its materials or its gold. It lies in its age, and in that profound sense of character, of steadfast observation, of mysterious connection, even of approval or disapproval, that we perceive in walls that have long been shaped by the flows of humanity. It's in their enduring testimony against mankind, in their quiet contrast with the fleeting nature of all things, in the strength that, through the passing of seasons and eras, and the rise and fall of dynasties, and the alteration of landscapes and sea boundaries, preserves their sculpted beauty for an unbeatable time, linking forgotten and future eras with one another, and partly forming the identity as it draws together the spirit of nations: it’s in that golden patina of time where we should seek the true light, color, and value of architecture; and it’s not until a building has acquired this essence, until it bears the weight of fame and is sanctified by human actions, until its walls have witnessed suffering and its pillars rise from the shadows of death, that its existence, lasting even longer than the natural elements around it, can possess even a fraction of the language and life that they do.
For that period, then, we must build; not, indeed, refusing to ourselves the delight of present completion, nor hesitating to follow such portions of character as may depend upon delicacy of execution to the highest perfection of which they are capable, even although we may know that in the course of years such details must perish; but taking care that for work of this kind we sacrifice no enduring quality, and that the building shall not depend for its impressiveness upon anything that is perishable. This would, indeed, be the law of good composition under any circumstances, the arrangement of the larger masses being always a matter of greater importance than the treatment of the smaller; but in architecture there is much in that very treatment which is skilful or otherwise in proportion to its just regard to the probable effects of time: and (which is still more to be considered) there is a beauty in those effects themselves, which nothing else can replace, and which it is our wisdom to consult and to desire. For though, hitherto, we have been speaking of the sentiment of age only, there is an actual beauty in the marks of it, such and so great as to have become not unfrequently the subject of especial choice among certain schools of art, and to have impressed upon those schools the character usually and loosely expressed by the term "picturesque."....
For that time, we need to build; not by denying ourselves the joy of completing things in the moment, nor by hesitating to pursue those aspects of character that rely on fine details crafted to their highest potential, even if we know that over the years, those details will fade away; but we must ensure that this type of work does not sacrifice any lasting quality and that the building's impact does not rely on anything temporary. This would be the principle of good design in any situation, as organizing the larger structures is always more important than how we handle the smaller elements; but in architecture, there is a lot that depends on how those smaller elements are treated, skillfully or not, in relation to how time will affect them: and (which is even more important) there is a beauty in those time-related effects that nothing else can replicate, and it is wise for us to recognize and appreciate. Because even though we've been discussing the sentiment of age alone, there is a genuine beauty in its signs, so significant that it has often become a key focus for certain art movements and has given those movements a character that is commonly and loosely described as "picturesque."
Now, to return to our immediate subject, it so happens that, in architecture, the superinduced and accidental beauty is most commonly inconsistent with the preservation of original character, and the picturesque is therefore sought in ruin, and supposed to consist in decay. Whereas, even when so sought, it consists in the mere sublimity of the rents, or fractures, or stains, or vegetation, which assimilate the architecture with the work of Nature, and bestow upon it those circumstances of colour and form which are universally beloved by the eye of man. So far as this is done, to the extinction of the true characters of the architecture, it is picturesque, and the artist who looks to the stem of the ivy instead of the shaft of the pillar, is carrying out in more daring freedom the debased sculptor's choice of the hair instead of the countenance. But so far as it can be rendered consistent with the inherent character, the picturesque or extraneous sublimity of architecture has just this of nobler function in it than that of any other object whatsoever, that it is an exponent of age, of that in which, as has been said, the greatest glory of the building consists; and, therefore, the external signs of this glory, having power and purpose greater than any belonging to their mere sensible beauty, may be considered as taking rank among pure and essential characters; so essential to my mind, that I think a building cannot be considered as in its prime until four or five centuries have passed over it; and that the entire choice and arrangement of its details should have reference to their appearance after that period, so that none should be admitted which would suffer material injury either by the weather-staining, or the mechanical degradation which the lapse of such a period would necessitate.
Now, to get back to our main topic, it turns out that in architecture, added beauty often clashes with the preservation of the original character, which is why people often find beauty in ruins and associate it with decay. Even when beauty is found in this way, it really comes from the striking nature of cracks, stains, or overgrown plants, which connect the architecture to the natural world and give it those colors and shapes that everyone appreciates. When this process erases the true characteristics of the architecture, it becomes picturesque, and the artist who focuses on the ivy instead of the pillar is making a bolder choice, akin to a poor sculptor emphasizing hair over the face. However, when this beauty aligns with the inherent character of the structure, the picturesque or external grandeur of architecture has a nobler role than that of any other object, as it represents age, which, as mentioned, is the ultimate glory of a building. Thus, the signs of this glory, having more power and purpose than mere visual appeal, can be considered fundamental characteristics; so fundamental, in fact, that I believe a building can't be seen as being at its best until four or five centuries have passed. The choice and arrangement of its details should account for how they will look after that time, ensuring that nothing is included that would suffer significant wear from weathering or the inevitable decay that comes with such an age.
It is not my purpose to enter into any of the questions which the application of this principle involves. They are of too great interest and complexity to be even touched upon within my present limits, but this is broadly to be noticed, that those styles of architecture which are picturesque in the sense above explained with respect to sculpture, that is to say, whose decoration depends on the arrangement of points of shade rather than on purity of outline, do not suffer, but commonly gain in richness of effect when their details are partly worn away; hence such styles, pre-eminently that of French Gothic, should always be adopted when the materials to be employed are liable to degradation, as brick, sandstone, or soft limestone; and styles in any degree dependent on purity of line, as the Italian Gothic, must be practised altogether in hard and undecomposing materials, granite, serpentine, or crystalline marbles. There can be no doubt that the nature of the accessible materials influenced the formation of both styles; and it should still more authoritatively determine our choice of either.
I don't intend to dive into the questions that applying this principle brings up. They are too interesting and complex to even scratch the surface within my current limits, but it’s important to note that architectural styles considered picturesque, as explained with respect to sculpture—meaning those whose decoration is based on how light and shadow are arranged rather than on clean lines—actually benefit in richness when details are somewhat worn away. Therefore, styles like French Gothic should always be used when materials that are prone to wear, like brick, sandstone, or soft limestone, are involved. On the other hand, styles that rely heavily on clean lines, such as Italian Gothic, should only be built using hard and durable materials like granite, serpentine, or crystalline marble. There’s no doubt that the types of materials available shaped the development of both styles, and this should guide our choice between them even more strongly.
It does not belong to my present plan to consider at length the second head of duty of which I have above spoken; the preservation of the architecture we possess: but a few words may be forgiven, as especially necessary in modern times. Neither by the public, nor by those who have the care of public monuments, is the true meaning of the word restoration understood. It means the most total destruction which a building can suffer: a destruction out of which no remnants can be gathered: a destruction accompanied with false description of the thing destroyed. Do not let us deceive ourselves in this important matter; it is impossible, as impossible as to raise the dead, to restore anything that has ever been great or beautiful in architecture. That which I have above insisted upon as the life of the whole, that spirit which is given only by the hand and eye of the workman, never can be recalled. Another spirit may be given by another time, and it is then a new building; but the spirit of the dead workman cannot be summoned up, and commanded to direct other hands, and other thoughts. And as for direct and simple copying, it is palpably impossible. What copying can there be of surfaces that have been worn half an inch down? The whole finish of the work was in the half inch that is gone; if you attempt to restore that finish, you do it conjecturally; if you copy what is left, granting fidelity to be possible (and what care, or watchfulness, or cost can secure it,) how is the new work better than the old? There was yet in the old some life, some mysterious suggestion of what it had been, and of what it had lost; some sweetness in the gentle lines which rain and sun had wrought. There can be none in the brute hardness of the new carving. Look at the animals which I have given in Plate XIV., as an instance of living work, and suppose the markings of the scales and hair once worn away, or the wrinkles of the brows, and who shall ever restore them? The first step to restoration, (I have seen it, and that again and again—seen it on the Baptistery of Pisa, seen it on the Casa d'Oro at Venice, seen it on the Cathedral of Lisieux,) is to dash the old work to pieces; the second is usually to put up the cheapest and basest imitation which can escape detection, but in all cases, however careful, and however laboured, an imitation still, a cold model of such parts as can be modelled, with conjectural supplements; and my experience has as yet furnished me with only one instance, that of the Palais de Justice at Rouen, in which even this, the utmost degree of fidelity which is possible, has been attained, or even attempted.[166]
It does not belong to my present plan to consider at length the second head of duty of which I have above spoken; the preservation of the architecture we possess: but a few words may be forgiven, as especially necessary in modern times. Neither by the public, nor by those who have the care of public monuments, is the true meaning of the word restoration understood. It means the most total destruction which a building can suffer: a destruction out of which no remnants can be gathered: a destruction accompanied with false description of the thing destroyed. Do not let us deceive ourselves in this important matter; it is impossible, as impossible as to raise the dead, to restore anything that has ever been great or beautiful in architecture. That which I have above insisted upon as the life of the whole, that spirit which is given only by the hand and eye of the workman, never can be recalled. Another spirit may be given by another time, and it is then a new building; but the spirit of the dead workman cannot be summoned up, and commanded to direct other hands, and other thoughts. And as for direct and simple copying, it is palpably impossible. What copying can there be of surfaces that have been worn half an inch down? The whole finish of the work was in the half inch that is gone; if you attempt to restore that finish, you do it conjecturally; if you copy what is left, granting fidelity to be possible (and what care, or watchfulness, or cost can secure it,) how is the new work better than the old? There was yet in the old some life, some mysterious suggestion of what it had been, and of what it had lost; some sweetness in the gentle lines which rain and sun had wrought. There can be none in the brute hardness of the new carving. Look at the animals which I have given in Plate XIV., as an instance of living work, and suppose the markings of the scales and hair once worn away, or the wrinkles of the brows, and who shall ever restore them? The first step to restoration, (I have seen it, and that again and again—seen it on the Baptistery of Pisa, seen it on the Casa d'Oro at Venice, seen it on the Cathedral of Lisieux,) is to dash the old work to pieces; the second is usually to put up the cheapest and basest imitation which can escape detection, but in all cases, however careful, and however laboured, an imitation still, a cold model of such parts as can be modelled, with conjectural supplements; and my experience has as yet furnished me with only one instance, that of the Palais de Justice at Rouen, in which even this, the utmost degree of fidelity which is possible, has been attained, or even attempted.[166]
Do not let us talk then of restoration. The thing is a Lie from beginning to end. You may make a model of a building as you may of a corpse, and your model may have the shell of the old walls within it as your cast might have the skeleton, with what advantage I neither see nor care: but the old building is destroyed, and that more totally and mercilessly than if it had sunk into a heap of dust, or melted into a mass of clay: more has been gleaned out of desolated Nineveh than ever will be out of re-built Milan. But, it is said, there may come a necessity for restoration! Granted. Look the necessity full in the face, and understand it on its own terms. It is a necessity for destruction. Accept it as such, pull the building down, throw its stones into neglected corners, make ballast of them, or mortar, if you will; but do it honestly, and do not set up a Lie in their place. And look that necessity in the face before it comes, and you may prevent it. The principle of modern times, (a principle which, I believe, at least in France, to be systematically acted on by the masons, in order to find themselves work, as the abbey of St. Ouen was pulled down by the magistrates of the town by way of giving work to some vagrants,) is to neglect buildings first, and restore them afterwards. Take proper care of your monuments, and you will not need to restore them. A few sheets of lead put in time upon the roof, a few dead leaves and sticks swept in time out of a water-course, will save both roof and walls from ruin. Watch an old building with an anxious care; guard it as best you may, and at any cost, from every influence of dilapidation. Count its stones as you would jewels of a crown; set watches about it as if at the gates of a besieged city; bind it together with iron where it loosens; stay it with timber where it declines; do not care about the unsightliness of the aid: better a crutch than a lost limb; and do this tenderly, and reverently, and continually, and many a generation will still be born and pass away beneath its shadow. Its evil day must come at last; but let it come declaredly and openly, and let no dishonouring and false substitute deprive it of the funeral offices of memory.
Don't let’s talk about restoration. It's a complete Lie from start to finish. You can create a model of a building just like you can from a corpse, and your model might have the old walls inside it, just like a cast might show a skeleton, but I don’t see any benefit in that: the old building is gone, entirely and mercilessly, more so than if it had turned to dust or clay. More has been learned from the ruins of Nineveh than will ever come from rebuilt Milan. They say there might come a need for restoration! Fine. Face that need honestly and understand it for what it is. It’s a need for destruction. Accept it, tear the building down, toss the stones into neglected corners, use them as ballast or mortar if you want; just be honest about it and don’t replace it with a Lie. Look that need in the eye before it arises, and you might be able to prevent it. The principle of modern times, (a principle I believe is systematically followed by the masons in France to find work, as when the abbey of St. Ouen was demolished by the town magistrates to give jobs to some vagrants,) is to neglect buildings first and restore them later. Take care of your monuments, and you won't need to restore them. A few sheets of lead placed on the roof in time, a few dead leaves and sticks cleared from a waterway, will save both roof and walls from destruction. Monitor an old building with dedicated care; protect it as best you can from every element that causes decay. Count its stones as if they were crown jewels; station guards around it like at the gates of a besieged city; reinforce it with iron where it weakens; support it with timber where it tilts; don’t worry about how it looks: better a crutch than a lost limb; and do all this thoughtfully, reverently, and consistently, and many generations will still live and die under its shadow. Its downfall will come eventually; but let it come clearly and openly, and don't let an unworthy substitute rob it of the respectful memory it deserves.
Of more wanton or ignorant ravage it is vain to speak; my words will not reach those who commit them, and yet, be it heard or not, I must not leave the truth unstated, that it is again no question of expediency or feeling whether we shall preserve the buildings of past times or not. We have no right whatever to touch them. They are not ours. They belong partly to those who built them, and partly to all the generations of mankind who are to follow us. The dead have still their right in them: that which they laboured for, the praise of achievement or the expression of religious feeling, or whatsoever else it might be which in those buildings they intended to be permanent, we have no right to obliterate. What we have ourselves built, we are at liberty to throw down; but what other men gave their strength and wealth and life to accomplish, their right over does not pass away with their death; still less is the right to the use of what they have left vested in us only. It belongs to all their successors. It may hereafter be a subject of sorrow, or a cause of injury, to millions, that we have consulted our present convenience by casting down such buildings as we choose to dispense with. That sorrow, that loss, we have no right to inflict. Did the cathedral of Avranches[167] belong to the mob who destroyed it, any more than it did to us, who walk in sorrow to and fro over its foundation? Neither does any building whatever belong to those mobs who do violence to it. For a mob it is, and must be always; it matters not whether enraged, or in deliberate folly; whether countless, or sitting in committees; the people who destroy anything causelessly are a mob, and Architecture is always destroyed causelessly. A fair building is necessarily worth the ground it stands upon, and will be so until Central Africa and America shall have become as populous as Middlesex: nor is any cause whatever valid as a ground for its destruction. If ever valid, certainly not now, when the place both of the past and future is too much usurped in our minds by the restless and discontented present. The very quietness of nature is gradually withdrawn from us; thousands who once in their necessarily prolonged travel were subjected to an influence, from the silent sky and slumbering fields, more effectual than known or confessed, now bear with them even there the ceaseless fever of their life; and along the iron veins that traverse the frame of our country, beat and flow the fiery pulses of its exertion, hotter and faster every hour. All vitality is concentrated through those throbbing arteries into the central cities; the country is passed over like a green sea by narrow bridges, and we are thrown back in continually closer crowds upon the city gates. The only influence which can in any wise there take the place of that of the woods and fields, is the power of ancient Architecture. Do not part with it for the sake of the formal square, or of the fenced and planted walk, nor of the goodly street nor opened quay. The pride of a city is not in these. Leave them to the crowd; but remember that there will surely be some within the circuit of the disquieted walls who would ask for some other spots than these wherein to walk; for some other forms to meet their sight familiarly: like him[168] who sat so often where the sun struck from the west to watch the lines of the dome of Florence drawn on the deep sky, or like those, his Hosts, who could bear daily to behold, from their palace chambers, the places where their fathers lay at rest, at the meeting of the dark streets of Verona.
Of more wanton or ignorant ravage it is vain to speak; my words will not reach those who commit them, and yet, be it heard or not, I must not leave the truth unstated, that it is again no question of expediency or feeling whether we shall preserve the buildings of past times or not. We have no right whatever to touch them. They are not ours. They belong partly to those who built them, and partly to all the generations of mankind who are to follow us. The dead have still their right in them: that which they laboured for, the praise of achievement or the expression of religious feeling, or whatsoever else it might be which in those buildings they intended to be permanent, we have no right to obliterate. What we have ourselves built, we are at liberty to throw down; but what other men gave their strength and wealth and life to accomplish, their right over does not pass away with their death; still less is the right to the use of what they have left vested in us only. It belongs to all their successors. It may hereafter be a subject of sorrow, or a cause of injury, to millions, that we have consulted our present convenience by casting down such buildings as we choose to dispense with. That sorrow, that loss, we have no right to inflict. Did the cathedral of Avranches[167] belong to the mob who destroyed it, any more than it did to us, who walk in sorrow to and fro over its foundation? Neither does any building whatever belong to those mobs who do violence to it. For a mob it is, and must be always; it matters not whether enraged, or in deliberate folly; whether countless, or sitting in committees; the people who destroy anything causelessly are a mob, and Architecture is always destroyed causelessly. A fair building is necessarily worth the ground it stands upon, and will be so until Central Africa and America shall have become as populous as Middlesex: nor is any cause whatever valid as a ground for its destruction. If ever valid, certainly not now, when the place both of the past and future is too much usurped in our minds by the restless and discontented present. The very quietness of nature is gradually withdrawn from us; thousands who once in their necessarily prolonged travel were subjected to an influence, from the silent sky and slumbering fields, more effectual than known or confessed, now bear with them even there the ceaseless fever of their life; and along the iron veins that traverse the frame of our country, beat and flow the fiery pulses of its exertion, hotter and faster every hour. All vitality is concentrated through those throbbing arteries into the central cities; the country is passed over like a green sea by narrow bridges, and we are thrown back in continually closer crowds upon the city gates. The only influence which can in any wise there take the place of that of the woods and fields, is the power of ancient Architecture. Do not part with it for the sake of the formal square, or of the fenced and planted walk, nor of the goodly street nor opened quay. The pride of a city is not in these. Leave them to the crowd; but remember that there will surely be some within the circuit of the disquieted walls who would ask for some other spots than these wherein to walk; for some other forms to meet their sight familiarly: like him[168] who sat so often where the sun struck from the west to watch the lines of the dome of Florence drawn on the deep sky, or like those, his Hosts, who could bear daily to behold, from their palace chambers, the places where their fathers lay at rest, at the meeting of the dark streets of Verona.
THE LAMP OF OBEDIENCE
It has been my endeavour to show in the preceding pages how every form of noble architecture is in some sort the embodiment of the Polity, Life, History, and Religious Faith of nations. Once or twice in doing this, I have named a principle to which I would now assign a definite place among those which direct that embodiment; the last place, not only as that to which its own humility would incline, but rather as belonging to it in the aspect of the crowning grace of all the rest; that principle, I mean, to which Polity owes its stability, Life its happiness, Faith its acceptance, Creation its continuance,—Obedience.
It has been my goal to show in the previous pages how every type of noble architecture reflects the governance, life, history, and religious beliefs of nations. Once or twice while doing this, I mentioned a principle that I would now like to clearly define among those that guide this embodiment; it holds the last position, not just because of its own modesty, but also because it represents the crowning quality of all the others. That principle is what gives governance its stability, life its happiness, faith its acceptance, and creation its continuity—Obedience.
Nor is it the least among the sources of more serious satisfaction which I have found in the pursuit of a subject that at first appeared to bear but slightly on the grave interests of mankind, that the conditions of material perfection which it leads me in conclusion to consider, furnish a strange proof how false is the conception, how frantic the pursuit, of that treacherous phantom which men call Liberty: most treacherous, indeed, of all phantoms; for the feeblest ray of reason might surely show us, that not only its attainment, but its being, was impossible. There is no such thing in the universe. There can never be. The stars have it not; the earth has it not; the sea has it not; and we men have the mockery and semblance of it only for our heaviest punishment.
Nor is it the least among the sources of deeper satisfaction that I’ve discovered in pursuing a subject that initially seemed only slightly related to the serious interests of humanity. The conditions of material perfection that I ultimately end up considering provide a strange proof of how misguided the idea is, and how frantic the chase, for that deceptive illusion called Liberty. It is, indeed, the most deceptive of all illusions, for even the faintest glimmer of reason should make it clear that not only is its achievement impossible, but its very existence is as well. There is no such thing in the universe. There never will be. The stars don’t possess it; the earth doesn’t possess it; the sea doesn’t possess it; and we humans only have its mockery and semblance as our greatest punishment.
In one of the noblest poems[169] for its imagery and its music belonging to the recent school of our literature, the writer has sought in the aspect of inanimate nature the expression of that Liberty which, having once loved, he had seen among men in its true dyes of darkness. But with what strange fallacy of interpretation! since in one noble line of his invocation he has contradicted the assumptions of the rest, and acknowledged the presence of a subjection, surely not less severe because eternal. How could he otherwise? since if there be any one principle more widely than another confessed by every utterance, or more sternly than another imprinted on every atom, of the visible creation, that principle is not Liberty, but Law.
In one of the noblest poems[169] for its imagery and its music belonging to the recent school of our literature, the writer has sought in the aspect of inanimate nature the expression of that Liberty which, having once loved, he had seen among men in its true dyes of darkness. But with what strange fallacy of interpretation! since in one noble line of his invocation he has contradicted the assumptions of the rest, and acknowledged the presence of a subjection, surely not less severe because eternal. How could he otherwise? since if there be any one principle more widely than another confessed by every utterance, or more sternly than another imprinted on every atom, of the visible creation, that principle is not Liberty, but Law.
The enthusiast would reply that by Liberty he meant the Law of Liberty. Then why use the single and misunderstood word? If by liberty you mean chastisement of the passions, discipline of the intellect, subjection of the will; if you mean the fear of inflicting, the shame of committing, a wrong; if you mean respect for all who are in authority, and consideration for all who are in dependence; veneration for the good, mercy to the evil, sympathy with the weak; if you mean watchfulness over all thoughts, temperance in all pleasures, and perseverance in all toils; if you mean, in a word, that Service which is defined in the liturgy of the English church to be perfect Freedom, why do you name this by the same word by which the luxurious mean license, and the reckless mean change; by which the rogue means rapine, and the fool, equality; by which the proud mean anarchy, and the malignant mean violence? Call it by any name rather than this, but its best and truest, is Obedience. Obedience is, indeed, founded on a kind of freedom, else it would become mere subjugation, but that freedom is only granted that obedience may be more perfect; and thus, while a measure of license is necessary to exhibit the individual energies of things, the fairness and pleasantness and perfection of them all consist in their Restraint. Compare a river that has burst its banks with one that is bound by them, and the clouds that are scattered over the face of the whole heaven with those that are marshalled into ranks and orders by its winds. So that though restraint, utter and unrelaxing, can never be comely, this is not because it is in itself an evil, but only because, when too great, it overpowers the nature of the thing restrained, and so counteracts the other laws of which that nature is itself composed. And the balance wherein consists the fairness of creation is between the laws of life and being in the things governed, and the laws of general sway to which they are subjected; and the suspension or infringement of either, kind of law, or, literally, disorder, is equivalent to, and synonymous with, disease; while the increase of both honour and beauty is habitually on the side of restraint (or the action of superior law) rather than of character (or the action of inherent law). The noblest word in the catalogue of social virtue is "Loyalty," and the sweetest which men have learned in the pastures of the wilderness is "Fold."
The enthusiast would respond that by Liberty, he meant the Law of Liberty. Then why use a single, misunderstood word? If by liberty you mean controlling the passions, training the intellect, submitting the will; if you mean the fear of causing harm, the shame of doing wrong; if you mean respect for all in authority, and consideration for those who are dependent; reverence for the good, mercy for the evil, empathy for the weak; if you mean being vigilant over all thoughts, moderation in all pleasures, and perseverance in all efforts; if you mean, in short, that Service which is defined in the liturgy of the English church as perfect Freedom, why do you use the same word that the indulgent equate with license, and the reckless equate with change; that the rogue associates with theft, and the fool, with equality; that the arrogant call anarchy, and the malicious call violence? Call it by any name but this one, yet its truest and best is Obedience. Obedience is indeed based on a kind of freedom, or it would just be domination, but that freedom exists solely so that obedience can be more complete; thus, while some measure of freedom is necessary to show the individual strengths of things, the fairness, joy, and perfection of them all come from their Restraint. Compare a river that has overflowed its banks with one that is contained by them, and the clouds scattered across the sky with those organized into formations by the winds. Therefore, while restraint that is absolute and unyielding can never be beautiful, this is not because it is wrong in itself, but rather because, when excessive, it overwhelms the nature of the thing being restrained, counteracting the other laws that comprise that nature. The balance that creates the beauty of existence lies between the laws of life and being in the governed things, and the laws of general control to which they are subjected; the suspension or breach of either type of law, or, literally, disorder, is equivalent to and synonymous with disease; while the growth of both honor and beauty is typically on the side of restraint (or the action of a higher law) rather than character (or the action of inherent law). The noblest word in the list of social virtues is “Loyalty,” and the sweetest one that people have learned in the wilderness is “Fold.”
Nor is this all; but we may observe, that exactly in proportion to the majesty of things in the scale of being, is the completeness of their obedience to the laws that are set over them. Gravitation is less quietly, less instantly obeyed by a grain of dust than it is by the sun and moon; and the ocean falls and flows under influences which the lake and river do not recognize. So also in estimating the dignity of any action or occupation of men, there is perhaps no better test than the question "are its laws strait?" For their severity will probably be commensurate with the greatness of the numbers whose labour it concentrates or whose interest it concerns.
Nor is this all; we can see that the greater the majesty of things in the hierarchy of existence, the more completely they follow the laws that govern them. A grain of dust doesn’t respond to gravity as instantly or quietly as the sun and moon do; the ocean rises and falls under influences that lakes and rivers don’t even recognize. Similarly, when judging the dignity of any action or occupation of people, there’s perhaps no better measure than asking, "Are its laws strict?" Because their harshness will likely be proportional to the number of people whose labor is focused by them or whose interests are affected.
This severity must be singular, therefore, in the case of that art, above all others, whose productions are the most vast and the most common; which requires for its practice the co-operation of bodies of men, and for its perfection the perseverance of successive generations. And, taking into account also what we have before so often observed of Architecture, her continual influence over the emotions of daily life, and her realism, as opposed to the two sister arts which are in comparison but the picturing of stories and of dreams, we might beforehand expect that we should find her healthy state and action dependent on far more severe laws than theirs: that the license which they extend to the workings of individual mind would be withdrawn by her; and that, in assertion of the relations which she holds with all that is universally important to man, she would set forth, by her own majestic subjection, some likeness of that on which man's social happiness and power depend. We might, therefore, without the light of experience, conclude, that Architecture never could flourish except when it was subjected to a national law as strict and as minutely authoritative as the laws which regulate religion, policy, and social relations; nay, even more authoritative than these, because both capable of more enforcement, as over more passive matter; and needing more enforcement, as the purest type not of one law nor of another, but of the common authority of all. But in this matter experience speaks more loudly than reason. If there be any one condition which, in watching the progress of architecture, we see distinct and general; if, amidst the counter-evidence of success attending opposite accidents of character and circumstance, any one conclusion may be constantly and indisputably drawn, it is this; that the architecture of a nation is great only when it is as universal and as established as its language; and when provincial differences of style are nothing more than so many dialects. Other necessities are matters of doubt: nations have been alike successful in their architecture in times of poverty and of wealth; in times of war and of peace; in times of barbarism and of refinement; under governments the most liberal or the most arbitrary; but this one condition has been constant, this one requirement clear in all places and at all times, that the work shall be that of a school, that no individual caprice shall dispense with, or materially vary, accepted types and customary decorations; and that from the cottage to the palace, and from the chapel to the basilica, and from the garden fence to the fortress wall, every member and feature of the architecture of the nation shall be as commonly current, as frankly accepted, as its language or its coin.
This severity must be unique, then, in the case of that art, above all others, whose works are the most extensive and the most widespread; which needs the collaboration of groups of people for its practice, and the dedication of successive generations for its perfection. And considering what we have often noted about Architecture, its constant influence on the emotions of daily life, and its realism—unlike the two sister arts that merely depict stories and dreams—we might expect that its healthy state and function depend on much stricter rules than theirs: that the freedom they allow for individual creativity would be restricted by it; and that, in asserting the connections it has with everything that is universally important to humanity, it would present, through its own majestic authority, a reflection of what human social happiness and power rely on. Thus, we could conclude, even without the experience to back it up, that Architecture could never thrive unless it was governed by a national law as strict and detailed as the laws that regulate religion, politics, and social relations; indeed, even more authoritative than these because it can be enforced more effectively, as it deals with more passive material; and requiring more enforcement, as it represents not just one law or another, but the collective authority of all. However, in this matter, experience speaks louder than reason. If there is any condition that stands out and is universal as we observe the progress of architecture; if, despite the conflicting evidence of success depending on varying circumstances and characteristics, one conclusion can be consistently and unmistakably drawn, it is this: that a nation’s architecture is truly remarkable only when it is as universal and established as its language; and when regional variations in style are merely dialects. Other necessities are debatable: nations have achieved architectural success in times of both poverty and wealth; in periods of war and peace; during times of barbarism and refinement; under the most liberal or the most oppressive governments; but this one condition has remained constant, this one requirement clear in all situations and at all times, that the work must represent a school, that no individual whims can replace or significantly alter accepted styles and traditional decorations; and that from the cottage to the palace, from the chapel to the basilica, and from the garden fence to the fortress wall, every element and feature of a nation’s architecture must be as widely accepted and typically recognized as its language or its currency.
A day never passes without our hearing our English architects called upon to be original, and to invent a new style: about as sensible and necessary an exhortation as to ask of a man who has never had rags enough on his back to keep out cold, to invent a new mode of cutting a coat. Give him a whole coat first, and let him concern himself about the fashion of it afterwards. We want no new style of architecture. Who wants a new style of painting or sculpture? But we want some style. It is of marvellously little importance, if we have a code of laws and they be good laws, whether they be new or old, foreign or native, Roman or Saxon, or Norman, or English laws. But it is of considerable importance that we should have a code of laws of one kind or another, and that code accepted and enforced from one side of the island to another, and not one law made ground of judgment at York and another in Exeter. And in like manner it does not matter one marble splinter whether we have an old or new architecture, but it matters everything whether we have an architecture truly so called or not; that is, whether an architecture whose laws might be taught at our schools from Cornwall to Northumberland, as we teach English spelling and English grammar, or an architecture which is to be invented fresh every time we build a workhouse or a parish school. There seems to me to be a wonderful misunderstanding among the majority of architects at the present day as to the very nature and meaning of Originality, and of all wherein it consists. Originality in expression does not depend on invention of new words; nor originality in poetry on invention of new measures; nor, in painting, on invention of new colours, or new modes of using them. The chords of music, the harmonies of colour, the general principles of the arrangement of sculptural masses, have been determined long ago, and, in all probability, cannot be added to any more than they can be altered. Granting that they may be, such additions or alterations are much more the work of time and of multitudes than of individual inventors. We may have one Van Eyck,[170] who will be known as the introducer of a new style once in ten centuries, but he himself will trace his invention to some accidental by-play or pursuit; and the use of that invention will depend altogether on the popular necessities or instincts of the period. Originality depends on nothing of the kind. A man who has the gift, will take up any style that is going, the style of his day, and will work in that, and be great in that, and make everything that he does in it look as fresh as if every thought of it had just come down from heaven. I do not say that he will not take liberties with his materials, or with his rules: I do not say that strange changes will not sometimes be wrought by his efforts, or his fancies, in both. But those changes will be instructive, natural, facile, though sometimes marvellous; they will never be sought after as things necessary to his dignity or to his independence; and those liberties will be like the liberties that a great speaker takes with the language, not a defiance of its rules for the sake of singularity; but inevitable, uncalculated, and brilliant consequences of an effort to express what the language, without such infraction, could not. There may be times when, as I have above described, the life of an art is manifested in its changes, and in its refusal of ancient limitations: so there are in the life of an insect; and there is great interest in the state of both the art and the insect at those periods when, by their natural progress and constitutional power, such changes are about to be wrought. But as that would be both an Uncomfortable and foolish caterpillar which, instead of being contented with a caterpillar's life and feeding on caterpillar's food, was always striving to turn itself into a chrysalis; and as that would be an unhappy chrysalis which should lie awake at night and roll restlessly in its cocoon, in efforts to turn itself prematurely into a moth; so will that art be unhappy and unprosperous which, instead of supporting itself on the food, and contenting itself with the customs, which have been enough for the support and guidance of other arts before it and like it, is struggling and fretting under the natural limitations of its existence, and striving to become something other than it is. And though it is the nobility of the highest creatures to look forward to, and partly to understand the changes which are appointed for them, preparing for them beforehand; and if, as is usual with appointed changes, they be into a higher state, even desiring them, and rejoicing in the hope of them, yet it is the strength of every creature, be it changeful or not, to rest for the time being, contented with the conditions of its existence, and striving only to bring about the changes which it desires, by fulfilling to the uttermost the duties for which its present state is appointed and continued.
A day never passes without our hearing our English architects called upon to be original, and to invent a new style: about as sensible and necessary an exhortation as to ask of a man who has never had rags enough on his back to keep out cold, to invent a new mode of cutting a coat. Give him a whole coat first, and let him concern himself about the fashion of it afterwards. We want no new style of architecture. Who wants a new style of painting or sculpture? But we want some style. It is of marvellously little importance, if we have a code of laws and they be good laws, whether they be new or old, foreign or native, Roman or Saxon, or Norman, or English laws. But it is of considerable importance that we should have a code of laws of one kind or another, and that code accepted and enforced from one side of the island to another, and not one law made ground of judgment at York and another in Exeter. And in like manner it does not matter one marble splinter whether we have an old or new architecture, but it matters everything whether we have an architecture truly so called or not; that is, whether an architecture whose laws might be taught at our schools from Cornwall to Northumberland, as we teach English spelling and English grammar, or an architecture which is to be invented fresh every time we build a workhouse or a parish school. There seems to me to be a wonderful misunderstanding among the majority of architects at the present day as to the very nature and meaning of Originality, and of all wherein it consists. Originality in expression does not depend on invention of new words; nor originality in poetry on invention of new measures; nor, in painting, on invention of new colours, or new modes of using them. The chords of music, the harmonies of colour, the general principles of the arrangement of sculptural masses, have been determined long ago, and, in all probability, cannot be added to any more than they can be altered. Granting that they may be, such additions or alterations are much more the work of time and of multitudes than of individual inventors. We may have one Van Eyck,[170] who will be known as the introducer of a new style once in ten centuries, but he himself will trace his invention to some accidental by-play or pursuit; and the use of that invention will depend altogether on the popular necessities or instincts of the period. Originality depends on nothing of the kind. A man who has the gift, will take up any style that is going, the style of his day, and will work in that, and be great in that, and make everything that he does in it look as fresh as if every thought of it had just come down from heaven. I do not say that he will not take liberties with his materials, or with his rules: I do not say that strange changes will not sometimes be wrought by his efforts, or his fancies, in both. But those changes will be instructive, natural, facile, though sometimes marvellous; they will never be sought after as things necessary to his dignity or to his independence; and those liberties will be like the liberties that a great speaker takes with the language, not a defiance of its rules for the sake of singularity; but inevitable, uncalculated, and brilliant consequences of an effort to express what the language, without such infraction, could not. There may be times when, as I have above described, the life of an art is manifested in its changes, and in its refusal of ancient limitations: so there are in the life of an insect; and there is great interest in the state of both the art and the insect at those periods when, by their natural progress and constitutional power, such changes are about to be wrought. But as that would be both an Uncomfortable and foolish caterpillar which, instead of being contented with a caterpillar's life and feeding on caterpillar's food, was always striving to turn itself into a chrysalis; and as that would be an unhappy chrysalis which should lie awake at night and roll restlessly in its cocoon, in efforts to turn itself prematurely into a moth; so will that art be unhappy and unprosperous which, instead of supporting itself on the food, and contenting itself with the customs, which have been enough for the support and guidance of other arts before it and like it, is struggling and fretting under the natural limitations of its existence, and striving to become something other than it is. And though it is the nobility of the highest creatures to look forward to, and partly to understand the changes which are appointed for them, preparing for them beforehand; and if, as is usual with appointed changes, they be into a higher state, even desiring them, and rejoicing in the hope of them, yet it is the strength of every creature, be it changeful or not, to rest for the time being, contented with the conditions of its existence, and striving only to bring about the changes which it desires, by fulfilling to the uttermost the duties for which its present state is appointed and continued.
Neither originality, therefore, nor change, good though both may be, and this is commonly a most merciful and enthusiastic supposition with respect to either, is ever to be sought in itself, or can ever be healthily obtained by any struggle or rebellion against common laws. We want neither the one nor the other. The forms of architecture already known are good enough for us, and for far better than any of us: and it will be time enough to think of changing them for better when we can use them as they are. But there are some things which we not only want, but cannot do without; and which all the struggling and raving in the world, nay more, which all the real talent and resolution in England, will never enable us to do without: and these are Obedience, Unity, Fellowship, and Order. And all our schools of design, and committees of taste; all our academies and lectures, and journalisms, and essays; all the sacrifices which we are beginning to make, all the truth which there is in our English nature, all the power of our English will, and the life of our English intellect, will in this matter be as useless as efforts and emotions in a dream, unless we are contented to submit architecture and all art, like other things, to English law.
Neither originality nor change, as beneficial as they may be, should be pursued for their own sake, nor can they be achieved healthily through defiance of established norms. We don’t need either one. The architectural styles we already have are sufficient for us, and far superior to what any of us could create; it will be time to consider changing them for better options once we can fully utilize what we have. However, there are some essentials that we not only desire but cannot live without, which all the struggle and passion in the world, or even the true talent and determination in England, cannot provide us: Obedience, Unity, Fellowship, and Order. All our design schools, taste committees, academies, lectures, journalism, and essays; all the sacrifices we’re starting to make, all the truths within our English nature, all the strength of our English will, and the vigor of our English intellect will be as pointless as dreams, unless we are willing to align architecture and all art with the laws of England.
I say architecture and all art; for I believe architecture must be the beginning of arts, and that the others must follow her in their time and order; and I think the prosperity of our schools of painting and sculpture, in which no one will deny the life, though many the health, depends upon that of our architecture. I think that all will languish until that takes the lead, and (this I do not think, but I proclaim, as confidently as I would assert the necessity, for the safety of society, of an understood and strongly administered legal government) our architecture will languish, and that in the very dust, until the first principle of common sense be manfully obeyed, and an universal system of form and workmanship be everywhere adopted and enforced. It may be said that this is impossible. It may be so—I fear it is so: I have nothing to do with the possibility or impossibility of it; I simply know and assert the necessity of it. If it be impossible, English art is impossible. Give it up at once. You are wasting time, and money, and energy upon it, and though you exhaust centuries and treasures, and break hearts for it, you will never raise it above the merest dilettanteism. Think not of it. It is a dangerous vanity, a mere gulph in which genius after genius will be swallowed up, and it will not close. And so it will continue to be, unless the one bold and broad step be taken at the beginning. We shall not manufacture art out of pottery and printed stuffs; we shall not reason out art by our philosophy; we shall not stumble upon art by our experiments, nor create it by our fancies: I do not say that we can even build it out of brick and stone; but there is a chance for us in these, and there is none else; and that chance rests on the bare possibility of obtaining the consent, both of architects and of the public, to choose a style, and to use it universally.
I talk about architecture and all forms of art because I believe architecture should be the starting point for all arts, and the others should follow in their own time and order. I think the success of our schools of painting and sculpture, which no one can deny has life, though many might question its health, relies on our architecture. Everything will struggle until architecture takes the lead, and (this isn’t just my opinion, I state it as confidently as I would claim the need for a well-understood and strongly enforced legal government for societal safety) our architecture will suffer, remaining stagnant, until we truly embrace and enforce a universal system of form and craftsmanship. Some might say this is impossible. It may be; I fear it is: my concern isn’t about what’s possible or not; I simply recognize and stress its necessity. If it is impossible, then English art is impossible. You should abandon it right away. You are wasting time, money, and energy on it, and even if you invest centuries and treasures, breaking hearts in the process, you’ll never elevate it beyond mere amateurism. Don’t dwell on it. It’s a risky vanity, a pit where talent after talent will be lost, and it won’t close. It will stay that way unless we take one bold and sweeping step from the start. We won’t create art from pottery and printed fabrics; we can’t reason out art through philosophy; we won’t stumble upon art through experiments, nor will we bring it to life through our imaginations. I’m not saying we can even build it from brick and stone, but we have a chance with those materials, and no other options; that chance lies in getting both architects and the public to agree on a style and use it uniformly.
How surely its principles ought at first to be limited, we may easily determine by the consideration of the necessary modes of teaching any other branch of general knowledge. When we begin to teach children writing, we force them to absolute copyism, and require absolute accuracy in the formation of the letters; as they obtain command of the received modes of literal expression, we cannot prevent their falling into such variations as are consistent with their feeling, their circumstances, or their characters. So, when a boy is first taught to write Latin, an authority is required of him for every expression he uses; as he becomes master of the language he may take a license, and feel his right to do so without any authority, and yet write better Latin than when he borrowed every separate expression. In the same way our architects would have to be taught to write the accepted style. We must first determine what buildings are to be considered Augustan in their authority; their modes of construction and laws of proportion are to be studied with the most penetrating care; then the different forms and uses of their decorations are to be classed and catalogued, as a German grammarian classes the powers of prepositions; and under this absolute, irrefragable authority, we are to begin to work; admitting not so much as an alteration in the depth of a cavetto,[171] or the breadth of a fillet. Then, when our sight is once accustomed to the grammatical forms and arrangements, and our thoughts familiar with the expression of them all; when we can speak this dead language naturally, and apply it to whatever ideas we have to render, that is to say, to every practical purpose of life; then, and not till then, a license might be permitted, and individual authority allowed to change or to add to the received forms, always within certain limits; the decorations, especially, might be made subjects of variable fancy, and enriched with ideas either original or taken from other schools. And thus, in process of time and by a great national movement, it might come to pass that a new style should arise, as language itself changes; we might perhaps come to speak Italian instead of Latin, or to speak modern instead of old English; but this would be a matter of entire indifference, and a matter, besides, which no determination or desire could either hasten or prevent. That alone which it is in our power to obtain, and which it is our duty to desire, is an unanimous style of some kind, and such comprehension and practice of it as would enable us to adapt its features to the peculiar character of every several building, large or small, domestic, civil or ecclesiastical.
How surely its principles ought at first to be limited, we may easily determine by the consideration of the necessary modes of teaching any other branch of general knowledge. When we begin to teach children writing, we force them to absolute copyism, and require absolute accuracy in the formation of the letters; as they obtain command of the received modes of literal expression, we cannot prevent their falling into such variations as are consistent with their feeling, their circumstances, or their characters. So, when a boy is first taught to write Latin, an authority is required of him for every expression he uses; as he becomes master of the language he may take a license, and feel his right to do so without any authority, and yet write better Latin than when he borrowed every separate expression. In the same way our architects would have to be taught to write the accepted style. We must first determine what buildings are to be considered Augustan in their authority; their modes of construction and laws of proportion are to be studied with the most penetrating care; then the different forms and uses of their decorations are to be classed and catalogued, as a German grammarian classes the powers of prepositions; and under this absolute, irrefragable authority, we are to begin to work; admitting not so much as an alteration in the depth of a cavetto,[171] or the breadth of a fillet. Then, when our sight is once accustomed to the grammatical forms and arrangements, and our thoughts familiar with the expression of them all; when we can speak this dead language naturally, and apply it to whatever ideas we have to render, that is to say, to every practical purpose of life; then, and not till then, a license might be permitted, and individual authority allowed to change or to add to the received forms, always within certain limits; the decorations, especially, might be made subjects of variable fancy, and enriched with ideas either original or taken from other schools. And thus, in process of time and by a great national movement, it might come to pass that a new style should arise, as language itself changes; we might perhaps come to speak Italian instead of Latin, or to speak modern instead of old English; but this would be a matter of entire indifference, and a matter, besides, which no determination or desire could either hasten or prevent. That alone which it is in our power to obtain, and which it is our duty to desire, is an unanimous style of some kind, and such comprehension and practice of it as would enable us to adapt its features to the peculiar character of every several building, large or small, domestic, civil or ecclesiastical.
Ruskin was first elected to the Slade Professorship of Fine Art in Oxford in 1869, and held the chair continuously until 1878, when he resigned because of ill-health, and again from 1883 to 1885. The Lectures on Art were announced in the Oxford University Gazette of January 28, 1870, the general subject of the course being "The Limits and Elementary Practice of Art," with Leonardo's Trattato della Pittura as the text-book. The lectures were delivered between February 8 and March 23, 1870. They appeared in book form in July of the same year. These lectures contain much of his best and most mature thought, of his most painstaking research and keenest analysis. Talking with a friend in later years, he said: "I have taken more pains with the Oxford Lectures than with anything else I have ever done": and in the preface to the edition of 1887 he began: "The following lectures were the most important piece of my literary work, done with unabated power, best motive, and happiest concurrence of circumstance." Ruskin took his professorship very seriously. He spent almost infinite labour in composing his more formal lectures, and during the eight years in which he held the chair he published six volumes of them, not to mention three Italian guide-books, which came under his interpretation of his professional duties;—"the real duty involved in my Oxford Professorship cannot be completely done by giving lectures in Oxford only, but ... I ought also to give what guidance I may to travellers in Italy." Not only by lecturing and writing did he fill the chair, but he taught individuals, founded and endowed a Drawing mastership, and presented elaborately catalogued collections to illustrate his subject. His lecture classes were always large, and his work had a marked influence in the University.
Ruskin was first elected to the Slade Professorship of Fine Art at Oxford in 1869 and held the position continuously until 1878, when he resigned due to ill health. He returned to the role from 1883 to 1885. The Lectures on Art were announced in the Oxford University Gazette on January 28, 1870, with the general topic of the course being "The Limits and Elementary Practice of Art," using Leonardo's Trattato della Pittura as the textbook. The lectures took place between February 8 and March 23, 1870, and were published as a book in July of the same year. These lectures include much of his best and most developed ideas, featuring his most meticulous research and sharpest analysis. Reflecting on his experience years later, he mentioned to a friend, "I put more effort into the Oxford Lectures than anything else I've ever done." In the preface to the 1887 edition, he stated, "The following lectures were the most significant piece of my literary work, done with unwavering energy, the best intentions, and the most favorable circumstances." Ruskin took his professorship very seriously. He invested countless hours crafting his more formal lectures, and during the eight years he held the position, he published six volumes of them, along with three Italian guidebooks, which he saw as part of his professional responsibilities: "The real duty involved in my Oxford Professorship cannot be fully completed by just giving lectures in Oxford; I also should provide any guidance I can to travelers in Italy." He filled the role not only through lecturing and writing but also by teaching individuals, establishing and funding a drawing mastership, and donating well-organized collections to illustrate his subject. His lecture classes were always large, and his work had a significant impact on the University.
INAUGURAL
We see lately a most powerful impulse given to the production of costly works of art by the various causes which promote the sudden accumulation of wealth in the hands of private persons. We have thus a vast and new patronage, which, in its present agency, is injurious to our schools; but which is nevertheless in a great degree earnest and conscientious, and far from being influenced chiefly by motives of ostentation. Most of our rich men would be glad to promote the true interests of art in this country; and even those who buy for vanity, found their vanity on the possession of what they suppose to be best.
We’re seeing a powerful boost in the production of expensive artwork driven by various factors that lead to the sudden accumulation of wealth among individuals. This has created a vast and new group of patrons that, while currently detrimental to our schools, is largely sincere and committed, and not just motivated by the desire to show off. Most of our wealthy individuals would be eager to support the genuine interests of art in this country; even those who purchase for vanity base their pride on owning what they believe to be the best.
It is therefore in a great measure the fault of artists themselves if they suffer from this partly unintelligent, but thoroughly well-intended patronage. If they seek to attract it by eccentricity, to deceive it by superficial qualities, or take advantage of it by thoughtless and facile production, they necessarily degrade themselves and it together, and have no right to complain afterwards that it will not acknowledge better-grounded claims. But if every painter of real power would do only what he knew to be worthy of himself, and refuse to be involved in the contention for undeserved or accidental success, there is indeed, whatever may have been thought or said to the contrary, true instinct enough in the public mind to follow such firm guidance. It is one of the facts which the experience of thirty years enables me to assert without qualification, that a really good picture is ultimately always approved and bought, unless it is wilfully rendered offensive to the public by faults which the artist has been either too proud to abandon or too weak to correct.
It's largely the artists' own fault if they struggle with this somewhat clueless, but genuinely well-meaning support. If they try to attract it through weirdness, mislead it with shallow traits, or exploit it through careless and easy production, they end up degrading both themselves and the support they seek, and they don’t have the right to complain later that it won’t acknowledge more legitimate claims. However, if every genuinely talented painter would only do what they know is worthy of themselves and refuse to compete for unearned or random success, there is indeed, despite what has been thought or said otherwise, plenty of true instinct in the public mind to follow such strong guidance. It’s one of the facts that my thirty years of experience allow me to assert without reservation: a truly great painting is eventually always recognized and purchased unless it is intentionally made unappealing to the public by flaws that the artist has either been too proud to fix or too weak to address.
The development of whatever is healthful and serviceable in the two modes of impulse which we have been considering, depends however, ultimately, on the direction taken by the true interest in art which has lately been aroused by the great and active genius of many of our living, or but lately lost, painters, sculptors, and architects. It may perhaps surprise, but I think it will please you to hear me, or (if you will forgive me, in my own Oxford, the presumption of fancying that some may recognize me by an old name) to hear the author of Modern Painters say, that his chief error in earlier days was not in over-estimating, but in too slightly acknowledging the merit of living men. The great painter whose power, while he was yet among us, I was able to perceive,[172] was the first to reprove me for my disregard of the skill of his fellow-artists; and, with this inauguration of the study of the art of all time,—a study which can only by true modesty end in wise admiration,—it is surely well that I connect the record of these words of his, spoken then too truly to myself, and true always more or less for all who are untrained in that toil,—"You don't know how difficult it is."
The development of whatever is healthful and serviceable in the two modes of impulse which we have been considering, depends however, ultimately, on the direction taken by the true interest in art which has lately been aroused by the great and active genius of many of our living, or but lately lost, painters, sculptors, and architects. It may perhaps surprise, but I think it will please you to hear me, or (if you will forgive me, in my own Oxford, the presumption of fancying that some may recognize me by an old name) to hear the author of Modern Painters say, that his chief error in earlier days was not in over-estimating, but in too slightly acknowledging the merit of living men. The great painter whose power, while he was yet among us, I was able to perceive,[172] was the first to reprove me for my disregard of the skill of his fellow-artists; and, with this inauguration of the study of the art of all time,—a study which can only by true modesty end in wise admiration,—it is surely well that I connect the record of these words of his, spoken then too truly to myself, and true always more or less for all who are untrained in that toil,—"You don't know how difficult it is."
You will not expect me, within the compass of this lecture, to give you any analysis of the many kinds of excellent art (in all the three great divisions) which the complex demands of modern life, and yet more varied instincts of modern genius, have developed for pleasure or service. It must be my endeavour, in conjunction with my colleagues in other Universities, hereafter to enable you to appreciate these worthily; in the hope that also the members of the Royal Academy, and those of the Institute of British Architects, may be induced to assist, and guide, the efforts of the Universities, by organizing such a system of art education for their own students, as shall in future prevent the waste of genius in any mistaken endeavours; especially removing doubt as to the proper substance and use of materials; and requiring compliance with certain elementary principles of right, in every picture and design exhibited with their sanction. It is not indeed possible for talent so varied as that of English artists to be compelled into the formalities of a determined school; but it must certainly be the function of every academical body to see that their younger students are guarded from what must in every school be error; and that they are practised in the best methods of work hitherto known, before their ingenuity is directed to the invention of others.
You wouldn’t expect me, in this lecture, to analyze the various types of outstanding art (across all three major categories) that modern life’s complex demands and the diverse instincts of contemporary genius have created for enjoyment or utility. My goal, along with my colleagues at other universities, is to help you genuinely appreciate these works; I hope that members of the Royal Academy and the Institute of British Architects will also be encouraged to support and guide universities by creating a system of art education for their students that will prevent the misdirection of talent in the future—especially by clarifying the proper use of materials and ensuring adherence to essential principles of integrity in every artwork and design they approve. It's not really feasible for the diverse talent of English artists to be forced into the strictures of a specific school; however, it surely is the responsibility of every academic institution to make sure their younger students are protected from common mistakes that can occur in any school, and that they are trained in the best-known methods of practice before they start inventing new ones.
I need scarcely refer, except for the sake of completeness in my statement, to one form of demand for art which is wholly unenlightened, and powerful only for evil;—namely, the demand of the classes occupied solely in the pursuit of pleasure, for objects and modes of art that can amuse indolence or excite passion. There is no need for any discussion of these requirements, or of their forms of influence, though they are very deadly at present in their operation on sculpture, and on jewellers' work. They cannot be checked by blame, nor guided by instruction; they are merely the necessary results of whatever defects exist in the temper and principles of a luxurious society; and it is only by moral changes, not by art-criticism, that their action can be modified.
I hardly need to mention, just for the sake of thoroughness in my statement, one type of demand for art that is completely ignorant and only serves to cause harm; that is, the demand from people who are solely focused on pleasure, for art forms and objects that can entertain laziness or stir up passion. There's no need for any discussion about these demands or how they affect things, although they are currently very harmful to sculpture and jewelry. They can't be stopped by criticism, nor directed by teaching; they are simply the unavoidable outcomes of the flaws in the attitudes and values of a luxurious society. The only way to change their impact is through moral shifts, not art critiques.
Lastly, there is a continually increasing demand for popular art, multipliable by the printing-press, illustrative of daily events, of general literature, and of natural science. Admirable skill, and some of the best talent of modern times, are occupied in supplying this want; and there is no limit to the good which may be effected by rightly taking advantage of the powers we now possess of placing good and lovely art within the reach of the poorest classes. Much has been already accomplished; but great harm has been done also,—first, by forms of art definitely addressed to depraved tastes; and, secondly, in a more subtle way, by really beautiful and useful engravings which are yet not good enough to retain their influence on the public mind;—which weary it by redundant quantity of monotonous average excellence, and diminish or destroy its power of accurate attention to work of a higher order.
Lastly, there’s a constantly growing demand for popular art, easily produced through the printing press, that reflects daily events, general literature, and natural science. Amazing skill and some of the best talent of our time are dedicated to meeting this need; and there’s no limit to the good that can come from effectively using our current ability to make quality and beautiful art accessible to even the poorest communities. A lot has already been achieved; however, significant harm has also been done—first, by creating art that caters to poor tastes; and secondly, in a more subtle way, by producing truly beautiful and useful engravings that aren’t high enough quality to have a lasting impact on the public’s mind—which exhausts it with an abundance of monotonous average excellence and weakens or even destroys its ability to focus on higher-quality works.
Especially this is to be regretted in the effect produced on the schools of line engraving, which had reached in England an executive skill of a kind before unexampled, and which of late have lost much of their more sterling and legitimate methods. Still, I have seen plates produced quite recently, more beautiful, I think, in some qualities than anything ever before attained by the burin:[173] and I have not the slightest fear that photography, or any other adverse or competitive operation, will in the least ultimately diminish,—I believe they will, on the contrary, stimulate and exalt—the grand old powers of the wood and the steel.
Especially this is to be regretted in the effect produced on the schools of line engraving, which had reached in England an executive skill of a kind before unexampled, and which of late have lost much of their more sterling and legitimate methods. Still, I have seen plates produced quite recently, more beautiful, I think, in some qualities than anything ever before attained by the burin:[173] and I have not the slightest fear that photography, or any other adverse or competitive operation, will in the least ultimately diminish,—I believe they will, on the contrary, stimulate and exalt—the grand old powers of the wood and the steel.
Such are, I think, briefly the present conditions of art with which we have to deal; and I conceive it to be the function of this Professorship, with respect to them, to establish both a practical and critical school of fine art for English gentlemen: practical, so that, if they draw at all, they may draw rightly; and critical, so that, being first directed to such works of existing art as will best reward their study, they may afterwards make their patronage of living artists delightful to themselves in their consciousness of its justice, and, to the utmost, beneficial to their country, by being given only to the men who deserve it; in the early period of their lives, when they both need it most and can be influenced by it to the best advantage.
I believe these are, in short, the current conditions of art that we need to address. I see the role of this Professorship as establishing both a practical and critical school of fine art for English gentlemen. Practical, so that if they draw at all, they draw accurately; and critical, so that, after being guided towards the works of existing art that will best benefit their study, they can make their support of living artists genuinely rewarding for themselves in recognizing its fairness, and ultimately beneficial for their country by ensuring it goes to those who truly deserve it, especially early in their careers when they need it most and can be influenced effectively.
And especially with reference to this function of patronage, I believe myself justified in taking into account future probabilities as to the character and range of art in England; and I shall endeavour at once to organize with you a system of study calculated to develope chiefly the knowledge of those branches in which the English schools have shown, and are likely to show, peculiar excellence.
And especially regarding this role of support, I feel justified in considering future possibilities about the nature and scope of art in England. I will work with you to create a study system designed to primarily develop knowledge in those areas where English schools have demonstrated—and are likely to demonstrate—specific excellence.
Now, in asking your sanction both for the nature of the general plans I wish to adopt, and for what I conceive to be necessary limitations of them, I wish you to be fully aware of my reasons for both: and I will therefore risk the burdening of your patience while I state the directions of effort in which I think English artists are liable to failure, and those also in which past experience has shown they are secure of success.
Now, as I ask for your approval on the general plans I want to implement, as well as what I believe are necessary limitations on them, I want you to fully understand my reasons for both: so I will take the risk of testing your patience while I outline the areas where I think English artists might struggle and those where past experience has shown they are likely to succeed.
I referred, but now, to the effort we are making to improve the designs of our manufactures. Within certain limits I believe this improvement may indeed take effect: so that we may no more humour momentary fashions by ugly results of chance instead of design; and may produce both good tissues, of harmonious colours, and good forms and substance of pottery and glass. But we shall never excel in decorative design. Such design is usually produced by people of great natural powers of mind, who have no variety of subjects to employ themselves on, no oppressive anxieties, and are in circumstances either of natural scenery or of daily life, which cause pleasurable excitement. We cannot design because we have too much to think of, and we think of it too anxiously. It has long been observed how little real anxiety exists in the minds of the partly savage races which excel in decorative art; and we must not suppose that the temper of the middle ages was a troubled one, because every day brought its dangers or its changes. The very eventfulness of the life rendered it careless, as generally is still the case with soldiers and sailors. Now, when there are great powers of thought, and little to think of, all the waste energy and fancy are thrown into the manual work, and you have as much intellect as would direct the affairs of a large mercantile concern for a day, spent all at once, quite unconsciously, in drawing an ingenious spiral.
I’m referring now to the effort we're making to improve the designs of our products. Within certain limits, I believe this improvement can actually happen, so we won't have to cater to fleeting trends with unattractive results driven by chance rather than design; instead, we can create both beautiful fabrics in harmonious colors and well-shaped, quality pottery and glass. However, we'll never truly excel in decorative design. Such design is typically created by people with great natural talent, who have no variety of subjects to work on, no overwhelming worries, and find themselves in surroundings—either natural landscapes or everyday life—that evoke joy. We can’t design because we have too much on our minds, and we think about it too anxiously. It’s long been noted how little real anxiety exists in the minds of the somewhat primitive cultures that excel in decorative art; and we shouldn't assume that the mindset of the Middle Ages was troubled simply because each day brought its own risks and changes. The very unpredictability of life made it more carefree, as is still often the case with soldiers and sailors. Now, when there’s great mental capacity but little to contemplate, all that excess energy and imagination is poured into manual labor, resulting in as much intellect as would manage the affairs of a large business for a day, spent all at once, quite unconsciously, in drawing an intricate spiral.
Also, powers of doing fine ornamental work are only to be reached by a perpetual discipline of the hand as well as of the fancy; discipline as attentive and painful as that which a juggler has to put himself through, to overcome the more palpable difficulties of his profession. The execution of the best artists is always a splendid tour-de-force, and much that in painting is supposed to be dependent on material is indeed only a lovely and quite inimitable legerdemain. Now, when powers of fancy, stimulated by this triumphant precision of manual dexterity, descend uninterruptedly from generation to generation, you have at last, what is not so much a trained artist as a new species of animal, with whose instinctive gifts you have no chance of contending. And thus all our imitations of other peoples' work are futile. We must learn first to make honest English wares, and afterward to decorate them as may please the then approving Graces.
Also, the skill to create fine decorative work can only be achieved through constant practice of both the hands and the imagination; a discipline that is just as careful and challenging as what a juggler endures to master the obvious challenges of their craft. The work of the best artists is always an impressive display of skill, and much of what is believed to rely on materials in painting is really just beautiful and completely unique sleight of hand. When the imaginative skills, inspired by this outstanding precision in manual skill, are passed down continuously from generation to generation, you end up with not just a trained artist but a completely new kind of being, equipped with instinctive talents that you can't compete with. As a result, all our attempts to replicate others' work are pointless. We need to first learn to create genuine English products, and then decorate them in a way that pleases the contemporary audience.
Secondly—and this is an incapacity of a graver kind, yet having its own good in it also—we shall never be successful in the highest fields of ideal or theological art.
Secondly—and this is a more serious limitation, yet it has its own benefits as well—we will never excel in the highest realms of ideal or theological art.
For there is one strange, but quite essential, character in us—ever since the Conquest, if not earlier:—a delight in the forms of burlesque which are connected in some degree with the foulness in evil. I think the most perfect type of a true English mind in its best possible temper, is that of Chaucer; and you will find that, while it is for the most part full of thoughts of beauty, pure and wild like that of an April morning, there are, even in the midst of this, sometimes momentarily jesting passages which stoop to play with evil—while the power of listening to and enjoying the jesting of entirely gross persons, whatever the feeling may be which permits it, afterwards degenerates into forms of humour which render some of quite the greatest, wisest, and most moral of English writers now almost useless for our youth. And yet you will find that whenever Englishmen are wholly without this instinct, their genius is comparatively weak and restricted.
For there is one strange but essential aspect of us—ever since the Conquest, if not earlier—a fascination with the forms of burlesque that are somewhat linked to the ugliness in evil. I believe the perfect example of a true English mind at its best is Chaucer; and you will see that, while it is mostly filled with thoughts of beauty, pure and wild like an April morning, there are moments where it playfully engages with evil. The ability to listen to and enjoy the jokes of completely crude individuals, whatever the sentiment that allows it, eventually leads to forms of humor that make some of the greatest, wisest, and most moral English writers almost irrelevant for our youth. Yet, you will find that whenever English people are entirely devoid of this instinct, their creativity tends to be relatively weak and limited.
Now, the first necessity for the doing of any great work in ideal art, is the looking upon all foulness with horror, as a contemptible though dreadful enemy. You may easily understand what I mean, by comparing the feelings with which Dante regards any form of obscenity or of base jest, with the temper in which the same things are regarded by Shakspere. And this strange earthly instinct of ours, coupled as it is, in our good men, with great simplicity and common sense, renders them shrewd and perfect observers and delineators of actual nature, low or high; but precludes them from that speciality of art which is properly called sublime. If ever we try anything in the manner of Michael Angelo or of Dante, we catch a fall, even in literature, as Milton in the battle of the angels, spoiled from Hesiod:[174] while in art, every attempt in this style has hitherto been the sign either of the presumptuous egotism of persons who had never really learned to be workmen, or it has been connected with very tragic forms of the contemplation of death,—it has always been partly insane, and never once wholly successful.
Now, the first necessity for the doing of any great work in ideal art, is the looking upon all foulness with horror, as a contemptible though dreadful enemy. You may easily understand what I mean, by comparing the feelings with which Dante regards any form of obscenity or of base jest, with the temper in which the same things are regarded by Shakspere. And this strange earthly instinct of ours, coupled as it is, in our good men, with great simplicity and common sense, renders them shrewd and perfect observers and delineators of actual nature, low or high; but precludes them from that speciality of art which is properly called sublime. If ever we try anything in the manner of Michael Angelo or of Dante, we catch a fall, even in literature, as Milton in the battle of the angels, spoiled from Hesiod:[174] while in art, every attempt in this style has hitherto been the sign either of the presumptuous egotism of persons who had never really learned to be workmen, or it has been connected with very tragic forms of the contemplation of death,—it has always been partly insane, and never once wholly successful.
But we need not feel any discomfort in these limitations of our capacity. We can do much that others cannot, and more than we have ever yet ourselves completely done. Our first great gift is in the portraiture of living people—a power already so accomplished in both Reynolds and Gainsborough, that nothing is left for future masters but to add the calm of perfect workmanship to their vigour and felicity of perception. And of what value a true school of portraiture may become in the future, when worthy men will desire only to be known, and others will not fear to know them, for what they truly were, we cannot from any past records of art influence yet conceive. But in my next address it will be partly my endeavour to show you how much more useful, because more humble, the labour of great masters might have been, had they been content to bear record of the souls that were dwelling with them on earth, instead of striving to give a deceptive glory to those they dreamed of in heaven.
But we shouldn't feel uncomfortable about these limits to our ability. We can achieve a lot that others can’t, and even more than we’ve fully accomplished ourselves. Our greatest gift lies in depicting living people—a skill that both Reynolds and Gainsborough have mastered so well that future artists only need to add the calm of perfect craftsmanship to their energy and insight. The value of a true school of portraiture in the future, where deserving individuals will want to be recognized and others won't hesitate to see them for who they really were, is something we can't fully imagine based on past records of art. But in my next speech, I’ll try to show you how much more beneficial, and humbler, the work of great masters could have been if they had focused on capturing the souls of those around them instead of trying to create a false glory for those they envisioned in heaven.
Secondly, we have an intense power of invention and expression in domestic drama; (King Lear and Hamlet being essentially domestic in their strongest motives of interest). There is a tendency at this moment towards a noble development of our art in this direction, checked by many adverse conditions, which may be summed in one,—the insufficiency of generous civic or patriotic passion in the heart of the English people; a fault which makes its domestic affections selfish, contracted, and, therefore, frivolous.
Secondly, we have a strong ability to create and express ourselves in domestic drama; (King Lear and Hamlet are fundamentally domestic in their key themes). Right now, there's a tendency towards a meaningful advancement of our art in this area, but it's hindered by many challenges, which can be boiled down to one issue—the lack of genuine civic or patriotic passion in the hearts of the English people; this flaw makes their domestic relationships selfish, limited, and, as a result, shallow.
Thirdly, in connection with our simplicity and good-humour, and partly with that very love of the grotesque which debases our ideal, we have a sympathy with the lower animals which is peculiarly our own; and which, though it has already found some exquisite expression in the works of Bewick and Landseer, is yet quite undeveloped. This sympathy, with the aid of our now authoritative science of physiology, and in association with our British love of adventure, will, I hope, enable us to give to the future inhabitants of the globe an almost perfect record of the present forms of animal life upon it, of which many are on the point of being extinguished....
Thirdly, along with our simplicity and good nature, and partly because of our quirky love for the bizarre that lowers our ideals, we have a unique connection with lower animals. This bond, while it has already been beautifully captured in the works of Bewick and Landseer, remains quite underexplored. I hope that this sympathy, combined with our now established science of physiology and our British spirit of adventure, will allow us to provide future generations with an almost complete account of the current forms of animal life on our planet, many of which are about to disappear...
While I myself hold this professorship, I shall direct you in these exercises very definitely to natural history, and to landscape; not only because in these two branches I am probably able to show you truths which might be despised by my successors; but because I think the vital and joyful study of natural history quite the principal element requiring introduction, not only into University, but into national, education, from highest to lowest; and I even will risk incurring your ridicule by confessing one of my fondest dreams, that I may succeed in making some of you English youths like better to look at a bird than to shoot it; and even desire to make wild creatures tame, instead of tame creatures wild. And for the study of landscape, it is, I think, now calculated to be of use in deeper, if not more important modes, than that of natural science, for reasons which I will ask you to let me state at some length.
While I'm holding this professorship, I will guide you in these exercises specifically towards natural history and landscape. This isn't just because I might be able to show you important truths that my successors may overlook, but because I believe that the essential and joyful study of natural history is a key component that should be introduced into education at all levels, from university to national programs. I’m even willing to risk your ridicule by sharing one of my biggest dreams: to inspire some of you young English men to prefer observing a bird over shooting it, and to want to tame wild creatures instead of turning domestic animals wild. As for studying landscape, I believe it has the potential to be incredibly useful in ways that are deeper, if not more significant, than those of natural science, for reasons I would like to explain in more detail.
Observe first;—no race of men which is entirety bred in wild country, far from cities, ever enjoys landscape. They may enjoy the beauty of animals, but scarcely even that: a true peasant cannot see the beauty of cattle; but only the qualities expressive of their serviceableness. I waive discussion of this to-day; permit my assertion of it, under my confident guarantee of future proof. Landscape can only be enjoyed by cultivated persons; and it is only by music, literature, and painting, that cultivation can be given. Also, the faculties which are thus received are hereditary; so that the child of an educated race has an innate instinct for beauty, derived from arts practised hundreds of years before its birth. Now farther note this, one of the loveliest things in human nature. In the children of noble races, trained by surrounding art, and at the same time in the practice of great deeds, there is an intense delight in the landscape of their country as memorial; a sense not taught to them, nor teachable to any others; but, in them, innate; and the seal and reward of persistence in great national life;—the obedience and the peace of ages having extended gradually the glory of the revered ancestors also to the ancestral land; until the Motherhood of the dust, the mystery of the Demeter from whose bosom we came, and to whose bosom we return, surrounds and inspires, everywhere, the local awe of field and fountain; the sacredness of landmark that none may remove, and of wave that none may pollute; while records of proud days, and of dear persons, make every rock monumental with ghostly inscription, and every path lovely with noble desolateness.
Observe this first: no group of people raised entirely in the wild, away from cities, ever truly appreciates a landscape. They may admire the beauty of animals, but not even that fully; a true peasant can't see the beauty in cattle, only the traits that show how useful they are. I'm not going to discuss this today; just allow me to assert it, confidently promising future proof. Only educated people can enjoy landscapes, and it's through music, literature, and painting that this education comes. The skills gained in this way are inherited, so the child of an educated lineage has an instinctive appreciation for beauty from the arts practiced centuries before their birth. Now consider this further, one of the most beautiful aspects of human nature. In the children of noble lineages, shaped by surrounding art and engaged in great deeds, there is a deep joy in their country's landscape as a memorial; a feeling not taught to them, nor teachable to anyone else; but innate in them; a mark and reward for enduring great national life;—the obedience and peace of ages have gradually extended the glory of honored ancestors to the ancestral land as well; until the Motherhood of the earth, the mystery of Demeter from whose embrace we came, and to whose embrace we return, surrounds and inspires us with a local reverence for fields and fountains; the sacredness of landmarks that cannot be removed, and of waves that cannot be polluted; while memories of proud days and beloved people make every rock a monument inscribed with ghostly writing, and every path beautiful with noble solitude.
Now, however checked by lightness of temperament, the instinctive love of landscape in us has this deep root, which, in your minds, I will pray you to disencumber from whatever may oppress or mortify it, and to strive to feel with all the strength of your youth that a nation is only worthy of the soil and the scenes that it has inherited, when, by all its acts and arts, it is making them more lovely for its children....
Now, however, tempered by a light-hearted attitude, our natural love for landscapes has this deep foundation, which, in your minds, I ask you to free from anything that may weigh it down or embarrass it. Strive to feel with all the energy of your youth that a nation is truly deserving of the land and the sights it has inherited only when, through all its actions and creations, it is making them more beautiful for its future generations...
But if either our work, or our inquiries, are to be indeed successful in their own field, they must be connected with others of a sterner character. Now listen to me, if I have in these past details lost or burdened your attention; for this is what I have chiefly to say to you. The art of any country is the exponent of its social and political virtues. I will show you that it is so in some detail, in the second of my subsequent course of lectures; meantime accept this as one of the things, and the most important of all things, I can positively declare to you. The art, or general productive and formative energy, of any country, is an exact exponent of its ethical life. You can have noble art only from noble persons, associated under laws fitted to their time and circumstances. And the best skill that any teacher of art could spend here in your help, would not end in enabling you even so much as rightly to draw the water-lilies in the Cherwell (and though it did, the work when done would not be worth the lilies themselves) unless both he and you were seeking, as I trust we shall together seek, in the laws which regulate the finest industries, the clue to the laws which regulate all industries, and in better obedience to which we shall actually have henceforward to live: not merely in compliance with our own sense of what is right, but under the weight of quite literal necessity. For the trades by which the British people has believed it to be the highest of destinies to maintain itself, cannot now long remain undisputed in its hands; its unemployed poor are daily becoming more violently criminal; and a certain distress in the middle classes, arising, partly from their vanity in living always up to their incomes, and partly from, their folly in imagining that they can subsist in idleness upon usury, will at last compel the sons and daughters of English families to acquaint themselves with the principles of providential economy; and to learn that food can only be got out of the ground, and competence only secured by frugality; and that although it is not possible for all to be occupied in the highest arts, nor for any, guiltlessly, to pass their days in a succession of pleasures, the most perfect mental culture possible to men is founded on their useful energies, and their best arts and brightest happiness are consistent, and consistent only, with their virtue.
But if our work or our inquiries are going to be truly successful in their own fields, they must connect with others that are more serious. Now, listen to me; if I've lost or burdened your attention with these past details, here’s the main point I want to make. The art of any country reflects its social and political values. I'll show you this in detail in the second part of my upcoming lectures; for now, accept this as one of the most important things I can definitively tell you. The art, or the general creative energy, of any country is a true representation of its ethical life. You can have great art only from admirable people who are working together under rules suited to their time and situation. And the best guidance any art teacher could provide you wouldn’t help you even to accurately draw the water-lilies in the Cherwell (and even if you did, the finished work wouldn’t be worth the lilies themselves) unless both you and your teacher are striving, as I hope we will together, to understand the laws that govern the finest industries, as clues to the laws that regulate all industries, and by better following them, we will have to live from now on: not just by our own sense of what is right, but under the heavy weight of real necessity. The trades that the British people have believed to be their highest destiny to maintain cannot remain uncontested for long; the number of unemployed people is increasingly becoming more violent and criminal; and a certain strain in the middle classes, arising, partly from their vanity in always living up to their incomes, and partly from their foolishness in thinking they can live in idleness on interest, will eventually force the sons and daughters of English families to understand the principles of careful economic planning; to learn that food can only be taken from the ground, and a comfortable life can only be secured by being frugal; and that although it is not possible for everyone to be engaged in the highest arts, nor is it right for anyone to spend their days indulging in pleasures, the deepest mental development achievable by people is based on their productive energies, and their best arts and truest happiness are aligned, and only aligned, with their virtue.
This, I repeat, gentlemen, will soon become manifest to those among us, and there are yet many, who are honest-hearted. And the future fate of England depends upon the position they then take, and on their courage in maintaining it.
This, I say again, gentlemen, will soon be clear to those of us, and there are still many, who have good intentions. The future of England relies on the stance they take at that time and their bravery in upholding it.
There is a destiny now possible to us—the highest ever set before a nation to be accepted or refused. We are still undegenerate in race; a race mingled of the best northern blood. We are not yet dissolute in temper, but still have the firmness to govern, and the grace to obey. We have been taught a religion of pure mercy, which we must either now betray, or learn to defend by fulfilling. And we are rich in an inheritance of honour, bequeathed to us through a thousand years of noble history, which it should be our daily thirst to increase with splendid avarice, so that Englishmen, if it be a sin to covet honour, should be the most offending souls alive.[175] Within the last few years we have had the laws of natural science opened to us with a rapidity which has been blinding by its brightness; and means of transit and communication given to us, which have made but one kingdom of the habitable globe. One kingdom;—but who is to be its king? Is there to be no king in it, think you, and every man to do that which is right in his own eyes? Or only kings of terror, and the obscene empires of Mammon and Belial? Or will you, youths of England, make your country again a royal throne of kings; a sceptred isle, for all the world a source of light, a centre of peace; mistress of Learning and of the Arts;—faithful guardian of great memories in the midst of irreverent and ephemeral visions;—faithful servant of time-tried principles, under temptation from fond experiments and licentious desires; and amidst the cruel and clamorous jealousies of the nations, worshipped in her strange valour of goodwill toward men?[176]
There is a destiny now possible to us—the highest ever set before a nation to be accepted or refused. We are still undegenerate in race; a race mingled of the best northern blood. We are not yet dissolute in temper, but still have the firmness to govern, and the grace to obey. We have been taught a religion of pure mercy, which we must either now betray, or learn to defend by fulfilling. And we are rich in an inheritance of honour, bequeathed to us through a thousand years of noble history, which it should be our daily thirst to increase with splendid avarice, so that Englishmen, if it be a sin to covet honour, should be the most offending souls alive.[175] Within the last few years we have had the laws of natural science opened to us with a rapidity which has been blinding by its brightness; and means of transit and communication given to us, which have made but one kingdom of the habitable globe. One kingdom;—but who is to be its king? Is there to be no king in it, think you, and every man to do that which is right in his own eyes? Or only kings of terror, and the obscene empires of Mammon and Belial? Or will you, youths of England, make your country again a royal throne of kings; a sceptred isle, for all the world a source of light, a centre of peace; mistress of Learning and of the Arts;—faithful guardian of great memories in the midst of irreverent and ephemeral visions;—faithful servant of time-tried principles, under temptation from fond experiments and licentious desires; and amidst the cruel and clamorous jealousies of the nations, worshipped in her strange valour of goodwill toward men?[176]
"Vexilla regis prodeunt."[177] Yes, but of which king? There are the two oriflammes; which shall we plant on the farthest islands—the one that floats in heavenly fire, or that hangs heavy with foul tissue of terrestrial gold? There is indeed a course of beneficent glory open to us, such as never was yet offered to any poor group of mortal souls. But it must be—it is with us, now. "Reign or Die." And if it shall be said of this country, "Fece per viltate, il gran rifiuto,"[178] that refusal of the crown will be, of all yet recorded in history, the shamefullest and most untimely.
"Vexilla regis prodeunt."[177] Yes, but of which king? There are the two oriflammes; which shall we plant on the farthest islands—the one that floats in heavenly fire, or that hangs heavy with foul tissue of terrestrial gold? There is indeed a course of beneficent glory open to us, such as never was yet offered to any poor group of mortal souls. But it must be—it is with us, now. "Reign or Die." And if it shall be said of this country, "Fece per viltate, il gran rifiuto,"[178] that refusal of the crown will be, of all yet recorded in history, the shamefullest and most untimely.
And this is what she must either do, or perish: she must found colonies as fast and as far as she is able, formed of her most energetic and worthiest men;—seizing every piece of fruitful waste ground she can set her foot on, and there teaching these her colonists that their chief virtue is to be fidelity to their country, and that their first aim is to be to advance the power of England by land and sea: and that, though they live on a distant plot of ground, they are no more to consider themselves therefore disfranchised from their native land, than the sailors of her fleets do, because they float on distant waves. So that literally, these colonies must be fastened fleets; and every man of them must be under authority of captains and officers, whose better command is to be over fields and streets instead of ships of the line; and England, in these her motionless navies (or, in the true and mightiest sense, motionless churches, ruled by pilots on the Galilean lake[179] of all the world), is to "expect every man to do his duty";[180] recognizing that duty is indeed possible no less in peace than war; and that if we can get men, for little pay, to cast themselves against cannon-mouths for love of England, we may find men also who will plough and sow for her, who will behave kindly and righteously for her, who will bring up their children to love her, and who will gladden themselves in the brightness of her glory, more than in all the light of tropic skies.
And this is what she must either do, or perish: she must found colonies as fast and as far as she is able, formed of her most energetic and worthiest men;—seizing every piece of fruitful waste ground she can set her foot on, and there teaching these her colonists that their chief virtue is to be fidelity to their country, and that their first aim is to be to advance the power of England by land and sea: and that, though they live on a distant plot of ground, they are no more to consider themselves therefore disfranchised from their native land, than the sailors of her fleets do, because they float on distant waves. So that literally, these colonies must be fastened fleets; and every man of them must be under authority of captains and officers, whose better command is to be over fields and streets instead of ships of the line; and England, in these her motionless navies (or, in the true and mightiest sense, motionless churches, ruled by pilots on the Galilean lake[179] of all the world), is to "expect every man to do his duty";[180] recognizing that duty is indeed possible no less in peace than war; and that if we can get men, for little pay, to cast themselves against cannon-mouths for love of England, we may find men also who will plough and sow for her, who will behave kindly and righteously for her, who will bring up their children to love her, and who will gladden themselves in the brightness of her glory, more than in all the light of tropic skies.
But that they may be able to do this, she must make her own majesty stainless; she must give them thoughts of their home of which they can be proud. The England who is to be mistress of half the earth, cannot remain herself a heap of cinders, trampled by contending and miserable crowds; she must yet again become the England she was once, and in all beautiful ways,—more: so happy, so secluded, and so pure, that in her sky—polluted by no unholy clouds—she may be able to spell rightly of every star that heaven doth show; and in her fields, ordered and wide and fair, of every herb that sips the dew;[181] and under the green avenues of her enchanted garden, a sacred Circe, true Daughter of the Sun, she must guide the human arts, and gather the divine knowledge, of distant nations, transformed from savageness to manhood, and redeemed from despairing into Peace.
But that they may be able to do this, she must make her own majesty stainless; she must give them thoughts of their home of which they can be proud. The England who is to be mistress of half the earth, cannot remain herself a heap of cinders, trampled by contending and miserable crowds; she must yet again become the England she was once, and in all beautiful ways,—more: so happy, so secluded, and so pure, that in her sky—polluted by no unholy clouds—she may be able to spell rightly of every star that heaven doth show; and in her fields, ordered and wide and fair, of every herb that sips the dew;[181] and under the green avenues of her enchanted garden, a sacred Circe, true Daughter of the Sun, she must guide the human arts, and gather the divine knowledge, of distant nations, transformed from savageness to manhood, and redeemed from despairing into Peace.
You think that an impossible ideal. Be it so; refuse to accept it if you will; but see that you form your own in its stead. All that I ask of you is to have a fixed purpose of some kind for your country and yourselves; no matter how restricted, so that it be fixed and unselfish. I know what stout hearts are in you, to answer acknowledged need; but it is the fatallest form of error in English youth to hide their hardihood till it fades for lack of sunshine, and to act in disdain of purpose, till all purpose is vain. It is not by deliberate, but by careless selfishness; not by compromise with evil, but by dull following of good, that the weight of national evil increases upon us daily. Break through at least this pretence of existence; determine what you will be, and what you would win. You will not decide wrongly if you resolve to decide at all. Were even the choice between lawless pleasure and loyal suffering, you would not, I believe, choose basely. But your trial is not so sharp. It is between drifting in confused wreck among the castaways of Fortune, who condemns to assured ruin those who know not either how to resist her, or obey; between this, I say, and the taking of your appointed part in the heroism of Rest; the resolving to share in the victory which is to the weak rather than the strong; and the binding yourselves by that law, which, thought on through lingering night and labouring day, makes a man's life to be as a tree planted by the water-side, that bringeth forth his fruit in his season;—
You think that's an impossible ideal. Fine; if you want to reject it, go ahead, but make sure you create your own in its place. All I ask is for you to have a clear purpose of some kind for your country and yourselves, no matter how small, as long as it’s consistent and selfless. I know you have strong hearts to respond to acknowledged needs, but it’s a serious mistake for young people in England to hide their courage until it fades away without sunlight, and to act without a clear purpose until all purpose becomes pointless. It’s not through deliberate choices, but through careless selfishness; not by compromising with evil, but by mindlessly following what's good, that the burden of national troubles grows heavier on us every day. Break through this pretense of existence; decide what you will be and what you want to achieve. You won’t make the wrong choice if you just choose to make one. Even if it’s a choice between reckless pleasure and loyal suffering, I believe you wouldn’t choose poorly. But your choice isn’t as harsh. It’s between drifting aimlessly among the shipwrecked of Fortune, who condemns those who don’t know how to either resist or obey her, and taking your rightful place in the heroism of Rest; deciding to join in the victory that comes to the weak rather than the strong; binding yourselves to that law, which, when considered through long nights and hard days, makes a man's life like a tree planted by the water that bears its fruit in season;—
"ET FOLIUM EJUS NON DEFLUET,
ET OMNIA, QUÆCUNQUE FACIET, PROSPERABUNTUR."[182]
"ET FOLIUM EJUS NON DEFLUET,
ET OMNIA, QUÆCUNQUE FACIET, PROSPERABUNTUR."[182]
THE RELATION OF ART TO MORALS
And now I pass to the arts with which I have special concern, in which, though the facts are exactly the same, I shall have more difficulty in proving my assertion, because very few of us are as cognizant of the merit of painting as we are of that of language; and I can only show you whence that merit springs, after having thoroughly shown you in what it consists. But, in the meantime, I have simply to tell you, that the manual arts are as accurate exponents of ethical state, as other modes of expression; first, with absolute precision, of that of the workman; and then with precision, disguised by many distorting influences, of that of the nation to which it belongs.
And now I’ll move on to the arts that I’m particularly passionate about, where, even though the facts are the same, I’ll find it more challenging to support my point. This is because not many of us appreciate the value of painting as much as we do with language. I can only show you where that value comes from after I’ve clearly explained what it consists of. But for now, I just want to say that the manual arts are as clear representations of the ethical state as other forms of expression; first, with complete accuracy, reflecting the workman’s perspective; and then, with accuracy that’s obscured by various distorting influences, reflecting the nation it comes from.
And, first, they are a perfect exponent of the mind of the workman: but, being so, remember, if the mind be great or complex, the art is not an easy book to read; for we must ourselves possess all the mental characters of which we are to read the signs. No man can read the evidence of labour who is not himself laborious, for he does not know what the work cost: nor can he read the evidence of true passion if he is not passionate; nor of gentleness if he is not gentle: and the most subtle signs of fault and weakness of character he can only judge by having had the same faults to fight with. I myself, for instance, know impatient work, and tired work, better than most critics, because I am myself always impatient, and often tired:—so also, the patient and indefatigable touch of a mighty master becomes more wonderful to me than to others. Yet, wonderful in no mean measure it will be to you all, when I make it manifest;—and as soon as we begin our real work, and you have learned what it is to draw a true line, I shall be able to make manifest to you,—and undisputably so,—that the day's work of a man like Mantegna or Paul Veronese consists of an unfaltering, uninterrupted, succession of movements of the hand more precise than those of the finest fencer: the pencil leaving one point and arriving at another, not only with unerring precision at the extremity of the line, but with an unerring and yet varied course—sometimes over spaces a foot or more in extent—yet a course so determined everywhere that either of these men could, and Veronese often does, draw a finished profile, or any other portion of the contour of the face, with one line, not afterwards changed. Try, first, to realize to yourselves the muscular precision of that action, and the intellectual strain of it; for the movement of a fencer is perfect in practised monotony; but the movement of the hand of a great painter is at every instant governed by direct and new intention. Then imagine that muscular firmness and subtlety, and the instantaneously selective and ordinant energy of the brain, sustained all day long, not only without fatigue, but with a visible joy in the exertion, like that which an eagle seems to take in the wave of his wings; and this all life long, and through long life, not only without failure of power, but with visible increase of it, until the actually organic changes of old age. And then consider, so far as you know anything of physiology, what sort of an ethical state of body and mind that means!—ethic through ages past! what fineness of race there must be to get it, what exquisite balance and symmetry of the vital powers! And then, finally, determine for yourselves whether a manhood like that is consistent with any viciousness of soul, with any mean anxiety, any gnawing lust, any wretchedness of spite or remorse, any consciousness of rebellion against law of God or man, or any actual, though unconscious violation of even the least law to which obedience is essential for the glory of life, and the pleasing of its Giver.
And first, they perfectly represent the mindset of the worker: however, remember, if the mind is great or complex, the artwork isn't easy to understand; because we must share the same mental traits to interpret the signs. No one can understand the proof of labor unless they are hardworking themselves, as they won't know the effort required; nor can someone grasp true passion if they're not passionate; nor gentleness if they lack gentleness; the most subtle signs of flaws and weaknesses can only be judged by having faced similar shortcomings themselves. For example, I understand impatient and exhausting work better than most critics because I am usually impatient and often tired: likewise, the patient and tireless touch of a great master is more impressive to me than to others. Yet it will still be remarkable to all of you when I show it; as soon as we start our real work and you discover what it means to draw a true line, I will be able to demonstrate to you, without a doubt, that the daily efforts of a man like Mantegna or Paul Veronese involve a continuous, uninterrupted sequence of hand movements that are more precise than those of the finest fencer: the pencil moving from one point to another, not only with perfect accuracy at the end of the line, but also with an unwavering and varied path—sometimes over distances of a foot or more—yet so determined that either of these men could, and Veronese often does, draw a complete profile or any part of a face's outline with a single stroke that isn't altered afterwards. First, try to comprehend the muscular precision of that action, and the mental effort involved; for a fencer's movement is perfect in its practiced monotony; but a great painter's hand movement is continuously guided by fresh, direct intention. Now imagine that muscular strength and finesse, alongside the instantaneously selecting and organizing energy of the brain, sustained all day long, not only without weariness, but with a visible joy in the effort, similar to that which an eagle seems to take in the movement of its wings; and this throughout their entire life, well into old age, not just without losing strength, but with a noticeable increase of it, even through the genuine organic changes of aging. Then consider, as much as you know about physiology, what kind of ethical state of body and mind that entails!—ethics from ages past! What a fine lineage must be needed to achieve it, what exquisite balance and symmetry of life forces! Finally, determine for yourselves whether such a manhood can be compatible with any soul's wickedness, any petty anxiety, any gnawing desires, any misery of spite or guilt, any awareness of defying the laws of God or man, or any actual, although unconscious violation of even the smallest laws essential for the glory of life and pleasing its Creator.
It is, of course, true that many of the strong masters had deep faults of character, but their faults always show in their work. It is true that some could not govern their passions; if so, they died young, or they painted ill when old. But the greater part of our misapprehension in the whole matter is from our not having well known who the great painters were, and taking delight in the petty skill that was bred in the fumes of the taverns of the North, instead of theirs who breathed empyreal air, sons of the morning, under the woods of Assisi and the crags of Cadore.
It’s certainly true that many talented masters had significant flaws in their character, but these flaws are always evident in their work. It’s also true that some couldn’t control their passions; if that’s the case, they died young or painted poorly in their later years. However, much of our misunderstanding about this matter comes from not clearly knowing who the great painters were and instead finding pleasure in the minor skills developed in the smoky taverns of the North, rather than appreciating those who breathed the heavenly air, the bright stars, beneath the trees of Assisi and the cliffs of Cadore.
It is true however also, as I have pointed out long ago, that the strong masters fall into two great divisions, one leading simple and natural lives, the other restrained in a Puritanism of the worship of beauty; and these two manners of life you may recognize in a moment by their work. Generally the naturalists are the strongest; but there are two of the Puritans, whose work if I can succeed in making clearly understandable to you during my three years[183] here, it is all I need care to do. But of these two Puritans one I cannot name to you, and the other I at present will not. One I cannot, for no one knows his name, except the baptismal one, Bernard, or "dear little Bernard"—Bernardino, called from his birthplace, (Luino, on the Lago Maggiore,) Bernard of Luino. The other is a Venetian, of whom many of you probably have never heard, and of whom, through me, you shall not hear, until I have tried to get some picture by him over to England.
It is true however also, as I have pointed out long ago, that the strong masters fall into two great divisions, one leading simple and natural lives, the other restrained in a Puritanism of the worship of beauty; and these two manners of life you may recognize in a moment by their work. Generally the naturalists are the strongest; but there are two of the Puritans, whose work if I can succeed in making clearly understandable to you during my three years[183] here, it is all I need care to do. But of these two Puritans one I cannot name to you, and the other I at present will not. One I cannot, for no one knows his name, except the baptismal one, Bernard, or "dear little Bernard"—Bernardino, called from his birthplace, (Luino, on the Lago Maggiore,) Bernard of Luino. The other is a Venetian, of whom many of you probably have never heard, and of whom, through me, you shall not hear, until I have tried to get some picture by him over to England.
Observe then, this Puritanism in the worship of beauty, though sometimes weak, is always honourable and amiable, and the exact reverse of the false Puritanism, which consists in the dread or disdain of beauty. And in order to treat my subject rightly, I ought to proceed from the skill of art to the choice of its subject, and show you how the moral temper of the workman is shown by his seeking lovely forms and thoughts to express, as well as by the force of his hand in expression. But I need not now urge this part of the proof on you, because you are already, I believe, sufficiently conscious of the truth in this matter, and also I have already said enough of it in my writings; whereas I have not at all said enough of the infallibleness of fine technical work as a proof of every other good power. And indeed it was long before I myself understood the true meaning of the pride of the greatest men in their mere execution, shown for a permanent lesson to us, in the stories which, whether true or not, indicate with absolute accuracy the general conviction of great artists;—the stories of the contest of Apelles and Protogenes[184] in a line only, (of which I can promise you, you shall know the meaning to some purpose in a little while),—the story of the circle of Giotto,[185] and especially, which you may perhaps not have observed, the expression of Dürer in his inscription on the drawings sent him by Raphael. These figures, he says, "Raphael drew and sent to Albert Dürer in Nurnberg, to show him"—What? Not his invention, nor his beauty of expression, but "sein Hand zu weisen," "to show him his hand." And you will find, as you examine farther, that all inferior artists are continually trying to escape from the necessity of sound work, and either indulging themselves in their delights in subject, or pluming themselves on their noble motives for attempting what they cannot perform; (and observe, by the way, that a great deal of what is mistaken for conscientious motive is nothing but a very pestilent, because very subtle, condition of vanity); whereas the great men always understand at once that the first morality of a painter, as of everybody else, is to know his business; and so earnest are they in this, that many, whose lives you would think, by the results of their work, had been passed in strong emotion, have in reality subdued themselves, though capable of the very strongest passions, into a calm as absolute as that of a deeply sheltered mountain lake, which reflects every agitation of the clouds in the sky, and every change of the shadows on the hills, but AS itself motionless.
Observe then, this Puritanism in the worship of beauty, though sometimes weak, is always honourable and amiable, and the exact reverse of the false Puritanism, which consists in the dread or disdain of beauty. And in order to treat my subject rightly, I ought to proceed from the skill of art to the choice of its subject, and show you how the moral temper of the workman is shown by his seeking lovely forms and thoughts to express, as well as by the force of his hand in expression. But I need not now urge this part of the proof on you, because you are already, I believe, sufficiently conscious of the truth in this matter, and also I have already said enough of it in my writings; whereas I have not at all said enough of the infallibleness of fine technical work as a proof of every other good power. And indeed it was long before I myself understood the true meaning of the pride of the greatest men in their mere execution, shown for a permanent lesson to us, in the stories which, whether true or not, indicate with absolute accuracy the general conviction of great artists;—the stories of the contest of Apelles and Protogenes[184] in a line only, (of which I can promise you, you shall know the meaning to some purpose in a little while),—the story of the circle of Giotto,[185] and especially, which you may perhaps not have observed, the expression of Dürer in his inscription on the drawings sent him by Raphael. These figures, he says, "Raphael drew and sent to Albert Dürer in Nurnberg, to show him"—What? Not his invention, nor his beauty of expression, but "sein Hand zu weisen," "to show him his hand." And you will find, as you examine farther, that all inferior artists are continually trying to escape from the necessity of sound work, and either indulging themselves in their delights in subject, or pluming themselves on their noble motives for attempting what they cannot perform; (and observe, by the way, that a great deal of what is mistaken for conscientious motive is nothing but a very pestilent, because very subtle, condition of vanity); whereas the great men always understand at once that the first morality of a painter, as of everybody else, is to know his business; and so earnest are they in this, that many, whose lives you would think, by the results of their work, had been passed in strong emotion, have in reality subdued themselves, though capable of the very strongest passions, into a calm as absolute as that of a deeply sheltered mountain lake, which reflects every agitation of the clouds in the sky, and every change of the shadows on the hills, but AS itself motionless.
Finally, you must remember that great obscurity has been brought upon the truth in this matter by the want of integrity and simplicity in our modern life. I mean integrity in the Latin sense, wholeness. Everything is broken up, and mingled in confusion, both in our habits and thoughts; besides being in great part imitative: so that you not only cannot tell what a man is, but sometimes you cannot tell whether he is, at all!—whether you have indeed to do with a spirit, or only with an echo. And thus the same inconsistencies appear now, between the work of artists of merit and their personal characters, as those which you find continually disappointing expectation in the lives of men of modern literary power;—the same conditions of society having obscured or misdirected the best qualities of the imagination, both in our literature and art. Thus there is no serious question with any of us as to the personal character of Dante and Giotto, of Shakespeare and Holbein; but we pause timidly in the attempt to analyze the moral laws of the art skill in recent poets, novelists, and painters.
Finally, you need to remember that great confusion has clouded the truth in this matter due to the lack of integrity and simplicity in our modern lives. I’m talking about integrity in the sense of being whole. Everything is fragmented and tangled in chaos, both in our habits and thoughts; and it's largely imitative, making it hard to understand what a person truly is—sometimes you can’t even tell if they really exist or if you’re just dealing with a reflection. As a result, we see the same inconsistencies today between the works of talented artists and their personal characters, similar to the disappointments we frequently encounter in the lives of contemporary literary figures; the same societal conditions have obscured or misdirected the best qualities of imagination in our literature and art. Therefore, we have no serious doubts about the personal character of Dante and Giotto, or Shakespeare and Holbein; but we hesitate when it comes to analyzing the moral principles behind the artistic skills of recent poets, novelists, and painters.
Let me assure you once for all, that as you grow older, if you enable yourselves to distinguish by the truth of your own lives, what is true in those of other men, you will gradually perceive that all good has its origin in good, never in evil; that the fact of either literature or painting being truly fine of their kind, whatever their mistaken aim, or partial error, is proof of their noble origin: and that, if there is indeed sterling value in the thing done, it has come of a sterling worth in the soul that did it, however alloyed or defiled by conditions of sin which are sometimes more appalling or more strange than those which all may detect in their own hearts, because they are part of a personality altogether larger than ours, and as far beyond our judgment in its darkness as beyond our following in its light. And it is sufficient warning against what some might dread as the probable effect of such a conviction on your own minds, namely, that you might permit yourselves in the weaknesses which you imagined to be allied to genius, when they took the form of personal temptations;—it is surely, I say, sufficient warning against so mean a folly, to discern, as you may with little pains, that, of all human existences, the lives of men of that distorted and tainted nobility of intellect are probably the most miserable.
Let me assure you once and for all that as you get older, if you allow yourselves to recognize the truth in your own lives, you'll start to see that all good comes from good, never from evil. The fact that literature or painting can be truly excellent in their own way, despite their misguided purposes or flaws, is proof of their noble origins. If something has real value, it comes from a genuinely good soul, even if it’s mixed or tainted by sinful circumstances that can sometimes be more shocking or unusual than what we see in ourselves because they are part of a personality much larger than ours, and as far beyond our understanding in its darkness as it is in its light. It's a strong warning against what some might fear as the potential impact of this belief on your own minds—that you might excuse your weaknesses, which you think are related to genius, when they manifest as personal temptations. It’s definitely a good warning against such a cheap mistake to realize, with minimal effort, that among all human lives, those of people with distorted and corrupted intellectual nobility are probably the most unhappy.
I pass to the second, and for us the more practically important question, What is the effect of noble art upon other men; what has it done for national morality in time past: and what effect is the extended knowledge or possession of it likely to have upon us now? And here we are at once met by the facts, which are as gloomy as indisputable, that, while many peasant populations, among whom scarcely the rudest practice of art has ever been attempted, have lived in comparative innocence, honour, and happiness, the worst foulness and cruelty of savage tribes have been frequently associated with fine ingenuities of decorative design; also, that no people has ever attained the higher stages of art skill, except at a period of its civilization which was sullied by frequent, violent, and even monstrous crime; and, lastly, that the attaining of perfection in art power, has been hitherto, in every nation, the accurate signal of the beginning of its ruin.
I move on to the second question, which is more practically important for us: What impact does noble art have on others? What has it contributed to national morality in the past, and what effect is the broader understanding or possession of it likely to have on us now? Here, we are immediately confronted with the gloomy yet undeniable facts that, while many peasant populations, among whom barely any form of art has ever been attempted, have lived relatively innocent, honorable, and happy lives, the deepest depravity and cruelty of savage tribes have often been linked to intricate decorative designs. Moreover, no society has ever reached higher levels of artistic skill without going through a period of civilization that was tainted by frequent, violent, and even monstrous crimes. Lastly, in every nation, achieving perfection in artistic power has consistently marked the beginning of its downfall.
Respecting which phenomena, observe first, that although good never springs out of evil, it is developed to its highest by contention with evil. There are some groups of peasantry, in far-away nooks of Christian countries, who are nearly as innocent as lambs; but the morality which gives power to art is the morality of men, not of cattle.
Respecting which phenomena, observe first, that even though good never comes from evil, it reaches its peak through the struggle against evil. There are some rural communities in remote areas of Christian countries, who are almost as innocent as lambs; but the morality that empowers art is the morality of humans, not of animals.
Secondly, the virtues of the inhabitants of many country districts are apparent, not real; their lives are indeed artless, but not innocent; and it is only the monotony of circumstances, and the absence of temptation, which prevent the exhibition of evil passions not less real because often dormant, nor less foul because shown only in petty faults, or inactive malignities.
Secondly, the virtues of people in many rural areas seem obvious but aren’t truly genuine; their lives may be simple, but they are not innocent. It’s just the routine nature of their lives and the lack of temptation that keeps selfish desires hidden—desires that are still very much present, even if they’re often suppressed, and they’re no less ugly just because they only appear in small faults or unexpressed grudges.
But you will observe also that absolute artlessness, to men in any kind of moral health, is impossible; they have always, at least, the art by which they live—agriculture or seamanship; and in these industries, skilfully practised, you will find the law of their moral training; while, whatever the adversity of circumstances, every rightly-minded peasantry, such as that of Sweden, Denmark, Bavaria, or Switzerland, has associated with its needful industry a quite studied school of pleasurable art in dress; and generally also in song, and simple domestic architecture.
But you'll also notice that absolute innocence is impossible for anyone in decent moral health; they always possess at least the skills they use to survive—like farming or sailing. In these professions, practiced skillfully, you can see the foundation of their moral education. Moreover, regardless of tough situations, any well-intentioned farming community, such as those in Sweden, Denmark, Bavaria, or Switzerland, has tied its necessary work to a thoughtfully developed sense of enjoyable art in clothing, as well as in music and basic home design.
Again, I need not repeat to you here what I endeavoured to explain in the first lecture in the book I called The Two Paths, respecting the arts of savage races: but I may now note briefly that such arts are the result of an intellectual activity which has found no room to expand, and which the tyranny of nature or of man has condemned to disease through arrested growth. And where neither Christianity, nor any other religion conveying some moral help, has reached, the animal energy of such races necessarily flames into ghastly conditions of evil, and the grotesque or frightful forms assumed by their art are precisely indicative of their distorted moral nature.
Again, I don't need to repeat what I tried to explain in the first lecture of the book I called The Two Paths, regarding the arts of primitive cultures: but I can briefly point out that such arts come from an intellectual drive that has been stifled and has resulted in a kind of stagnation caused by the harshness of nature or humanity. In places where neither Christianity nor any other religion offering moral guidance has reached, the raw energy of these cultures often devolves into severe conditions of wrongdoing, and the bizarre or terrifying forms their art takes clearly reflect their troubled moral state.
But the truly great nations nearly always begin from a race possessing this imaginative power; and for some time their progress is very slow, and their state not one of innocence, but of feverish and faultful animal energy. This is gradually subdued and exalted into bright human life; the art instinct purifying itself with the rest of the nature, until social perfectness is nearly reached; and then comes the period when conscience and intellect are so highly developed, that new forms of error begin in the inability to fulfil the demands of the one, or to answer the doubts of the other. Then the wholeness of the people is lost; all kinds of hypocrisies and oppositions of science develope themselves; their faith is questioned on one side, and compromised with on the other; wealth commonly increases at the same period to a destructive extent; luxury follows; and the ruin of the nation is then certain: while the arts, all this time, are simply, as I said at first, the exponents of each phase of its moral state, and no more control it in its political career than the gleam of the firefly guides its oscillation. It is true that their most splendid results are usually obtained in the swiftness of the power which is hurrying to the precipice; but to lay the charge of the catastrophe to the art by which it is illumined, is to find a cause for the cataract in the hues of its iris. It is true that the colossal vices belonging to periods of great national wealth (for wealth, you will find, is the real root of all evil)[186] can turn every good gift and skill of nature or of man to evil purpose. If, in such times, fair pictures have been misused, how much more fair realities? And if Miranda is immoral to Caliban is that Miranda's fault?
But the truly great nations nearly always begin from a race possessing this imaginative power; and for some time their progress is very slow, and their state not one of innocence, but of feverish and faultful animal energy. This is gradually subdued and exalted into bright human life; the art instinct purifying itself with the rest of the nature, until social perfectness is nearly reached; and then comes the period when conscience and intellect are so highly developed, that new forms of error begin in the inability to fulfil the demands of the one, or to answer the doubts of the other. Then the wholeness of the people is lost; all kinds of hypocrisies and oppositions of science develope themselves; their faith is questioned on one side, and compromised with on the other; wealth commonly increases at the same period to a destructive extent; luxury follows; and the ruin of the nation is then certain: while the arts, all this time, are simply, as I said at first, the exponents of each phase of its moral state, and no more control it in its political career than the gleam of the firefly guides its oscillation. It is true that their most splendid results are usually obtained in the swiftness of the power which is hurrying to the precipice; but to lay the charge of the catastrophe to the art by which it is illumined, is to find a cause for the cataract in the hues of its iris. It is true that the colossal vices belonging to periods of great national wealth (for wealth, you will find, is the real root of all evil)[186] can turn every good gift and skill of nature or of man to evil purpose. If, in such times, fair pictures have been misused, how much more fair realities? And if Miranda is immoral to Caliban is that Miranda's fault?
THE RELATION OF ART TO USE
Our subject of inquiry to-day, you will remember, is the mode in which fine art is founded upon, or may contribute to, the practical requirements of human life.
Our topic of discussion today, as you will recall, is how fine art is based on, or can help with, the practical needs of human life.
Its offices in this respect are mainly twofold: it gives Form to knowledge, and Grace to utility; that is to say, it makes permanently visible to us things which otherwise could neither be described by our science, nor retained by our memory; and it gives delightfulness and worth to the implements of daily use, and materials of dress, furniture and lodging. In the first of these offices it gives precision and charm to truth; in the second it gives precision and charm to service. For, the moment we make anything useful thoroughly, it is a law of nature that we shall be pleased with ourselves, and with the thing we have made; and become desirous therefore to adorn or complete it, in some dainty way, with finer art expressive of our pleasure.
Its functions in this regard are mainly twofold: it gives form to knowledge and grace to utility. In other words, it makes things visible to us that we couldn't describe through science or remember otherwise. It adds beauty and value to the tools we use daily, as well as to the materials for clothing, furniture, and housing. In the first role, it adds precision and charm to truth, and in the second, it does the same for utility. The moment we perfect anything useful, it's a natural law that we feel pleased with ourselves and with what we've created; this desire then leads us to embellish or enhance it in a refined way, using art that expresses our enjoyment.
And the point I wish chiefly to bring before you today is this close and healthy connection of the fine arts with material use; but I must first try briefly to put in clear light the function of art in giving Form to truth.
And the main point I want to highlight today is the strong and beneficial connection between the fine arts and practical use; but first, I need to briefly clarify the role of art in shaping truth.
Much that I have hitherto tried to teach has been disputed on the ground that I have attached too much importance to art as representing natural facts, and too little to it as a source of pleasure. And I wish, in the close of these four prefatory lectures, strongly to assert to you, and, so far as I can in the time, convince you, that the entire vitality of art depends upon its being either full of truth, or full of use; and that, however pleasant, wonderful, or impressive it may be in itself, it must yet be of inferior kind, and tend to deeper inferiority, unless it has clearly one of these main objects,—either to state a true thing, or to adorn a serviceable one. It must never exist alone,—never for itself; it exists rightly only when it is the means of knowledge, or the grace of agency for life.
Much of what I have tried to teach so far has been challenged because some believe I focus too much on art as a representation of natural facts and not enough on its role as a source of pleasure. As I conclude these four introductory lectures, I want to strongly emphasize, and as much as I can in this time, convince you that the real essence of art relies on it being either full of truth or full of utility. No matter how enjoyable, amazing, or impressive it may be on its own, it will always be of lesser quality and likely become even less significant unless it clearly serves one of these main purposes—either to express a true idea or to enhance something practical. Art should never exist in isolation—never just for its own sake; it is truly valuable only when it serves as a means of knowledge or adds grace to our actions in life.
Now, I pray you to observe—for though I have said this often before, I have never yet said it clearly enough—every good piece of art, to whichever of these ends it may be directed, involves first essentially the evidence of human skill, and the formation of an actually beautiful thing by it.
Now, I urge you to pay attention—because even though I’ve said this many times before, I’ve never said it clearly enough—every great piece of art, no matter what purpose it serves, fundamentally involves the demonstration of human skill and the creation of something truly beautiful.
Skill and beauty, always, then; and, beyond these, the formative arts have always one or other of the two objects which I have just defined to you—truth, or serviceableness; and without these aims neither the skill nor their beauty will avail; only by these can either legitimately reign. All the graphic arts begin in keeping the outline of shadow that we have loved, and they end in giving to it the aspect of life; and all the architectural arts begin in the shaping of the cup and the platter, and they end in a glorified roof.
Skill and beauty are essential; and beyond these, the creative arts always aim for one of two goals I've just described—truth or usefulness. Without these goals, neither skill nor beauty will matter; only through these can either truly thrive. All graphic arts start by maintaining the outline of the shadows we cherish, and they conclude by bringing that outline to life. Similarly, all architectural arts begin with shaping everyday items like cups and plates, and they culminate in a stunning roof.
Therefore, you see, in the graphic arts you have Skill, Beauty, and Likeness; and in the architectural arts Skill, Beauty, and Use: and you must have the three in each group, balanced and co-ordinate; and all the chief errors of art consist in losing or exaggerating one of these elements.
Therefore, you see, in the graphic arts, you have skill, beauty, and likeness; and in the architectural arts, you have skill, beauty, and functionality. You must have all three in each group, balanced and coordinated; and all the major mistakes in art come from losing or overemphasizing one of these elements.
For instance, almost the whole system and hope of modern life are founded on the notion that you may substitute mechanism for skill, photograph for picture, cast-iron for sculpture. That is your main nineteenth-century faith, or infidelity. You think you can get everything by grinding—music, literature, and painting. You will find it grievously not so; you can get nothing but dust by mere grinding. Even to have the barley-meal out of it, you must have the barley first; and that comes by growth, not grinding. But essentially, we have lost our delight in Skill; in that majesty of it which I was trying to make clear to you in my last address, and which long ago[187] I tried to express, under the head of ideas of power. The entire sense of that, we have lost, because we ourselves do not take pains enough to do right, and have no conception of what the right costs; so that all the joy and reverence we ought to feel in looking at a strong man's work have ceased in us. We keep them yet a little in looking at a honeycomb or a bird's-nest; we understand that these differ, by divinity of skill, from a lump of wax or a cluster of sticks. But a picture, which is a much more wonderful thing than a honeycomb or a bird's-nest,—have we not known people, and sensible people too, who expected to be taught to produce that, in six lessons?
For instance, almost the whole system and hope of modern life are founded on the notion that you may substitute mechanism for skill, photograph for picture, cast-iron for sculpture. That is your main nineteenth-century faith, or infidelity. You think you can get everything by grinding—music, literature, and painting. You will find it grievously not so; you can get nothing but dust by mere grinding. Even to have the barley-meal out of it, you must have the barley first; and that comes by growth, not grinding. But essentially, we have lost our delight in Skill; in that majesty of it which I was trying to make clear to you in my last address, and which long ago[187] I tried to express, under the head of ideas of power. The entire sense of that, we have lost, because we ourselves do not take pains enough to do right, and have no conception of what the right costs; so that all the joy and reverence we ought to feel in looking at a strong man's work have ceased in us. We keep them yet a little in looking at a honeycomb or a bird's-nest; we understand that these differ, by divinity of skill, from a lump of wax or a cluster of sticks. But a picture, which is a much more wonderful thing than a honeycomb or a bird's-nest,—have we not known people, and sensible people too, who expected to be taught to produce that, in six lessons?
Well, you must have the skill, you must have the beauty, which is the highest moral element; and then, lastly, you must have the verity or utility, which is not the moral, but the vital element; and this desire for verity and use is the one aim of the three that always leads in great schools, and in the minds of great masters, without any exception. They will permit themselves in awkwardness, they will permit themselves in ugliness;—but they will never permit themselves in uselessness or in unveracity.
Well, you need to have skill and beauty, which is the highest moral quality; and finally, you need to have truth or usefulness, which isn't moral, but vital. This desire for truth and utility is the one goal among these three that always guides great schools and the minds of great masters, without exception. They may allow for awkwardness or lack of beauty, but they will never accept uselessness or dishonesty.
And farther, as their skill increases, and as their grace, so much more their desire for truth. It is impossible to find the three motives in fairer balance and harmony than in our own Reynolds. He rejoices in showing you his skill; and those of you who succeed in learning what painters' work really is, will one day rejoice also, even to laughter—that highest laughter which springs of pure delight, in watching the fortitude and the fire of a hand which strikes forth its will upon the canvas as easily as the wind strikes it on the sea. He rejoices in all abstract beauty and rhythm and melody of design; he will never give you a colour that is not lovely, nor a shade that is unnecessary, nor a line that is ungraceful. But all his power and all his invention are held by him subordinate,—and the more obediently because of their nobleness,-to his true leading purpose of setting before you such likeness of the living presence of an English gentleman or an English lady, as shall be worthy of being looked upon for ever.
And as their skills and grace improve, so does their desire for truth. It's hard to find a better balance of these three motivations than in our own Reynolds. He loves to showcase his skill; and those of you who understand what a painter’s work truly is will one day find joy—even to the point of laughter—that pure kind of laughter that comes from sheer delight, as you watch the strength and passion of his hand bringing its vision to life on the canvas as effortlessly as the wind blows across the sea. He delights in all forms of abstract beauty, rhythm, and design; he will never give you a color that isn’t beautiful, a shade that isn’t needed, or a line that lacks grace. However, all of his power and creativity are held in check—more obediently due to their nobility—by his true goal of presenting a likeness of the living presence of an English gentleman or lady that is worthy of eternal admiration.
But farther, you remember, I hope—for I said it in a way that I thought would shock you a little, that you might remember it—my statement, that art had never done more than this, never more than given the likeness of a noble human being. Not only so, but it very seldom does so much as this, and the best pictures that exist of the great schools are all portraits, or groups of portraits, often of very simple and nowise noble persons. You may have much more brilliant and impressive qualities in imaginative pictures; you may have figures scattered like clouds, or garlanded like flowers; you may have light and shade as of a tempest, and colour, as of the rainbow; but all that is child's play to the great men, though it is astonishment to us. Their real strength is tried to the utmost, and as far as I know, it is never elsewhere brought out so thoroughly, as in painting one man or woman, and the soul that was in them; nor that always the highest soul, but often only a thwarted one that was capable of height; or perhaps not even that, but faultful and poor, yet seen through, to the poor best of it, by the masterful sight. So that in order to put before you in your Standard series the best art possible, I am obliged, even from the very strongest men, to take the portraits, before I take the idealism. Nay, whatever is best in the great compositions themselves has depended on portraiture; and the study necessary to enable you to understand invention will also convince you that the mind of man never invented a greater thing than the form of man, animated by faithful life. Every attempt to refine or exalt such healthy humanity has weakened or caricatured it; or else consists only in giving it, to please our fancy, the wings of birds, or the eyes of antelopes. Whatever is truly great in either Greek or Christian art, is also restrictedly human; and even the raptures of the redeemed souls who enter "celestemente ballando,"[188] the gate of Angelico's Paradise, were seen first in the terrestrial, yet most pure, mirth of Florentine maidens.
But farther, you remember, I hope—for I said it in a way that I thought would shock you a little, that you might remember it—my statement, that art had never done more than this, never more than given the likeness of a noble human being. Not only so, but it very seldom does so much as this, and the best pictures that exist of the great schools are all portraits, or groups of portraits, often of very simple and nowise noble persons. You may have much more brilliant and impressive qualities in imaginative pictures; you may have figures scattered like clouds, or garlanded like flowers; you may have light and shade as of a tempest, and colour, as of the rainbow; but all that is child's play to the great men, though it is astonishment to us. Their real strength is tried to the utmost, and as far as I know, it is never elsewhere brought out so thoroughly, as in painting one man or woman, and the soul that was in them; nor that always the highest soul, but often only a thwarted one that was capable of height; or perhaps not even that, but faultful and poor, yet seen through, to the poor best of it, by the masterful sight. So that in order to put before you in your Standard series the best art possible, I am obliged, even from the very strongest men, to take the portraits, before I take the idealism. Nay, whatever is best in the great compositions themselves has depended on portraiture; and the study necessary to enable you to understand invention will also convince you that the mind of man never invented a greater thing than the form of man, animated by faithful life. Every attempt to refine or exalt such healthy humanity has weakened or caricatured it; or else consists only in giving it, to please our fancy, the wings of birds, or the eyes of antelopes. Whatever is truly great in either Greek or Christian art, is also restrictedly human; and even the raptures of the redeemed souls who enter "celestemente ballando,"[188] the gate of Angelico's Paradise, were seen first in the terrestrial, yet most pure, mirth of Florentine maidens.
I am aware that this cannot but at present appear gravely questionable to those of my audience who are strictly cognizant of the phases of Greek art; for they know that the moment of its decline is accurately marked, by its turning from abstract form to portraiture. But the reason of this is simple. The progressive course of Greek art was in subduing monstrous conceptions to natural ones; it did this by general laws; it reached absolute truth of generic human form, and if its ethical force had remained, would have advanced into healthy portraiture. But at the moment of change the national life ended in Greece; and portraiture, there, meant insult to her religion, and flattery to her tyrants. And her skill perished, not because she became true in sight, but because she became vile in heart....
I understand that this may seem highly questionable to those in my audience who are well-versed in the stages of Greek art; they recognize that its decline is clearly marked by a shift from abstract forms to portraiture. But the reason for this is straightforward. The development of Greek art involved transforming monstrous ideas into natural ones; it achieved this through universal principles and reached absolute truth in the generic human form. If its ethical strength had persisted, it would have evolved into genuine portraiture. However, at the time of this shift, national life in Greece came to an end; there, portraiture became an offense to its religion and a way to flatter its oppressors. Its skill faded not because it became realistic in appearance, but because it became corrupt in spirit...
But I have told you enough, it seems to me, at least to-day, of this function of art in recording fact; let me now finally, and with all distinctness possible to me, state to you its main business of all;—its service in the actual uses of daily life.
But I think I've shared enough with you today about how art serves to record facts. Now, let me clearly state its primary purpose—its role in the everyday aspects of life.
You are surprised, perhaps, to hear me call this its main business. That is indeed so, however. The giving brightness to picture is much, but the giving brightness to life more. And remember, were it as patterns only, you cannot, without the realities, have the pictures. You cannot have a landscape by Turner without a country for him to paint; you cannot have a portrait by Titian, without a man to be pourtrayed. I need not prove that to you, I suppose, in these short terms; but in the outcome I can get no soul to believe that the beginning of art is in getting our country clean, and our people beautiful. I have been ten years trying to get this very plain certainty—I do not say believed—but even thought of, as anything but a monstrous proposition. To get your country clean, and your people lovely;—I assure you that is a necessary work of art to begin with! There has indeed been art in countries where people lived in dirt to serve God, but never in countries where they lived in dirt to serve the devil. There has indeed been art where the people were not all lovely,—where even their lips were thick—and their skins black, because the sun had looked upon them;[189] but never in a country where the people were pale with miserable toil and deadly shade, and where the lips of youth, instead of being full with blood, were pinched by famine, or warped with poison. And now, therefore, note this well, the gist of all these long prefatory talks. I said that the two great moral instincts were those of Order and Kindness. Now, all the arts are founded on agriculture by the hand, and on the graces and kindness of feeding, and dressing, and lodging your people. Greek art begins in the gardens of Alcinous—perfect order, leeks in beds, and fountains in pipes.[190] And Christian art, as it arose out of chivalry, was only possible so far as chivalry compelled both kings and knights to care for the right personal training of their people; it perished utterly when those kings and knights became δημοβσροι, devourers of the people. And it will become possible again only, when, literally, the sword is beaten into the ploughshare,[191] when your St. George of England shall justify his name,[192] and Christian art shall be known as its Master was, in breaking of bread.[193]
You are surprised, perhaps, to hear me call this its main business. That is indeed so, however. The giving brightness to picture is much, but the giving brightness to life more. And remember, were it as patterns only, you cannot, without the realities, have the pictures. You cannot have a landscape by Turner without a country for him to paint; you cannot have a portrait by Titian, without a man to be pourtrayed. I need not prove that to you, I suppose, in these short terms; but in the outcome I can get no soul to believe that the beginning of art is in getting our country clean, and our people beautiful. I have been ten years trying to get this very plain certainty—I do not say believed—but even thought of, as anything but a monstrous proposition. To get your country clean, and your people lovely;—I assure you that is a necessary work of art to begin with! There has indeed been art in countries where people lived in dirt to serve God, but never in countries where they lived in dirt to serve the devil. There has indeed been art where the people were not all lovely,—where even their lips were thick—and their skins black, because the sun had looked upon them;[189] but never in a country where the people were pale with miserable toil and deadly shade, and where the lips of youth, instead of being full with blood, were pinched by famine, or warped with poison. And now, therefore, note this well, the gist of all these long prefatory talks. I said that the two great moral instincts were those of Order and Kindness. Now, all the arts are founded on agriculture by the hand, and on the graces and kindness of feeding, and dressing, and lodging your people. Greek art begins in the gardens of Alcinous—perfect order, leeks in beds, and fountains in pipes.[190] And Christian art, as it arose out of chivalry, was only possible so far as chivalry compelled both kings and knights to care for the right personal training of their people; it perished utterly when those kings and knights became δημοβσροι, devourers of the people. And it will become possible again only, when, literally, the sword is beaten into the ploughshare,[191] when your St. George of England shall justify his name,[192] and Christian art shall be known as its Master was, in breaking of bread.[193]
Now look at the working out of this broad principle in minor detail; observe how, from highest to lowest, health of art has first depended on reference to industrial use. There is first the need of cup and platter, especially of cup; for you can put your meat on the Harpies',[194] or any other, tables; but you must have your cup to drink from. And to hold it conveniently, you must put a handle to it; and to fill it when it is empty you must have a large pitcher of some sort; and to carry the pitcher you may most advisably have two handles. Modify the forms of these needful possessions according to the various requirements of drinking largely and drinking delicately; of pouring easily out, or of keeping for years the perfume in; of storing in cellars, or bearing from fountains; of sacrificial libation, of Pan-athenaic treasure of oil, and sepulchral treasure of ashes,—and you have a resultant series of beautiful form and decoration, from the rude amphora of red earth up to Cellini's vases of gems and crystal, in which series, but especially in the more simple conditions of it, are developed the most beautiful lines and most perfect types of severe composition which have yet been attained by art.
Now look at the working out of this broad principle in minor detail; observe how, from highest to lowest, health of art has first depended on reference to industrial use. There is first the need of cup and platter, especially of cup; for you can put your meat on the Harpies',[194] or any other, tables; but you must have your cup to drink from. And to hold it conveniently, you must put a handle to it; and to fill it when it is empty you must have a large pitcher of some sort; and to carry the pitcher you may most advisably have two handles. Modify the forms of these needful possessions according to the various requirements of drinking largely and drinking delicately; of pouring easily out, or of keeping for years the perfume in; of storing in cellars, or bearing from fountains; of sacrificial libation, of Pan-athenaic treasure of oil, and sepulchral treasure of ashes,—and you have a resultant series of beautiful form and decoration, from the rude amphora of red earth up to Cellini's vases of gems and crystal, in which series, but especially in the more simple conditions of it, are developed the most beautiful lines and most perfect types of severe composition which have yet been attained by art.
But again, that you may fill your cup with pure water, you must go to the well or spring; you need a fence round the well; you need some tube or trough, or other means of confining the stream at the spring. For the conveyance of the current to any distance you must build either enclosed or open aqueduct; and in the hot square of the city where you set it free, you find it good for health and pleasantness to let it leap into a fountain. On these several needs you have a school of sculpture founded; in the decoration of the walls of wells in level countries, and of the sources of springs in mountainous ones, and chiefly of all, where the women of household or market meet at the city fountain.
But again, to fill your cup with clean water, you have to go to the well or spring; you need a fence around the well; you need some sort of tube or trough, or other means to direct the water at the spring. To move the water any distance, you must build either an enclosed or open aqueduct; and in the hot square of the city where you let it flow, it’s beneficial for health and enjoyable to let it splash into a fountain. These various needs have inspired a school of sculpture, seen in the decoration of well walls in flat areas, and of spring sources in mountainous regions, and especially where women gather at the city fountain for household or market needs.
There is, however, a farther reason for the use of art here than in any other material service, so far as we may, by art, express our reverence or thankfulness. Whenever a nation is in its right mind, it always has a deep sense of divinity in the gift of rain from heaven, filling its heart with food and gladness;[195] and all the more when that gift becomes gentle and perennial in the flowing of springs. It literally is not possible that any fruitful power of the Muses should be put forth upon a people which disdains their Helicon; still less is it possible that any Christian nation should grow up "tanquam lignum quod plantatum est secus decursus aquarum,"[196] which cannot recognize the lesson meant in their being told of the places where Rebekah was met;—where Rachel,—where Zipporah,—and she who was asked for water under Mount Gerizim by a Stranger, weary, who had nothing to draw with.[197]
There is, however, a farther reason for the use of art here than in any other material service, so far as we may, by art, express our reverence or thankfulness. Whenever a nation is in its right mind, it always has a deep sense of divinity in the gift of rain from heaven, filling its heart with food and gladness;[195] and all the more when that gift becomes gentle and perennial in the flowing of springs. It literally is not possible that any fruitful power of the Muses should be put forth upon a people which disdains their Helicon; still less is it possible that any Christian nation should grow up "tanquam lignum quod plantatum est secus decursus aquarum,"[196] which cannot recognize the lesson meant in their being told of the places where Rebekah was met;—where Rachel,—where Zipporah,—and she who was asked for water under Mount Gerizim by a Stranger, weary, who had nothing to draw with.[197]
And truly, when our mountain springs are set apart in vale or craggy glen, or glade of wood green through the drought of summer, far from cities, then, it is best let them stay in their own happy peace; but if near towns, and liable therefore to be defiled by common usage, we could not use the loveliest art more worthily than by sheltering the spring and its first pools with precious marbles: nor ought anything to be esteemed more important, as a means of healthy education, than the care to keep the streams of it afterwards, to as great a distance as possible, pure, full of fish, and easily accessible to children. There used to be, thirty years ago, a little rivulet of the Wandel, about an inch deep, which ran over the carriage-road and under a footbridge just under the last chalk hill near Croydon. Alas! men came and went; and it—did not go on for ever. It has long since been bricked over by the parish authorities; but there was more education in that stream with its minnows than you could get out of a thousand pounds spent yearly in the parish schools, even though you were to spend every farthing of it in teaching the nature of oxygen and hydrogen, and the names, and rate per minute, of all the rivers in Asia and America.
And honestly, when our mountain springs are located in a valley or a rocky glen, or a green glade in the woods that remains vibrant through the summer drought, far from cities, it’s best to let them stay in their peaceful state. But if they are close to towns and likely to be polluted by everyday use, we couldn't find a more worthy way to celebrate their beauty than by surrounding the spring and its initial pools with precious marble. Nothing should be considered more important for health education than making sure to keep the waters downstream, as clean as possible, abundant with fish, and easily accessible for children. Thirty years ago, there was a small stream called the Wandel, about an inch deep, which flowed over the road and beneath a footbridge at the last chalk hill near Croydon. Unfortunately, people came and went, and it—did not last forever. It has long since been covered over by the local authorities, but that little stream, with its minnows, provided more education than you could gain from spending a thousand pounds each year in local schools, even if you used every penny to teach about oxygen and hydrogen and the names and flow rates of all the rivers in Asia and America.
Well, the gist of this matter lies here then. Suppose we want a school of pottery again in England, all we poor artists are ready to do the best we can, to show you how pretty a line may be that is twisted first to one side, and then to the other; and how a plain household-blue will make a pattern on white; and how ideal art may be got out of the spaniel's colours of black and tan. But I tell you beforehand, all that we can do will be utterly useless, unless you teach your peasant to say grace, not only before meat, but before drink; and having provided him with Greek cups and platters, provide him also with something that is not poisoned to put into them.
Well, the main point here is this. If we want a pottery school in England again, all of us artists are ready to do our best to show you how beautiful a line can be when it's twisted one way and then the other; how a simple household blue can create a pattern on white; and how ideal art can come from the spaniel's colors of black and tan. But I’ll tell you upfront, everything we do will be completely pointless unless you teach your peasant to say grace, not just before meals, but also before drinks; and after giving him Greek cups and plates, make sure he has something safe to put in them.
There cannot be any need that I should trace for you the conditions of art that are directly founded on serviceableness of dress, and of armour; but it is my duty to affirm to you, in the most positive manner, that after recovering, for the poor, wholesomeness of food, your next step toward founding schools of art in England must be in recovering, for the poor, decency and wholesomeness of dress; thoroughly good in substance, fitted for their daily work, becoming to their rank in life, and worn with order and dignity. And this order and dignity must be taught them by the women of the upper and middle classes, whose minds can be in nothing right, as long as they are so wrong in this matter us to endure the squalor of the poor, while they themselves dress gaily. And on the proper pride and comfort of both poor and rich in dress, must be founded the true arts of dress; carried on by masters of manufacture no less careful of the perfectness and beauty of their tissues, and of all that in substance and in design can be bestowed upon them, than ever the armourers of Milan and Damascus were careful of their steel.
There’s no need for me to explain the impact of functional clothing and armor on art. However, I must strongly state that after ensuring nutritious food for the poor, your next priority in establishing art schools in England should be to provide the poor with decent and functional clothing. This clothing should be of good quality, suitable for their daily tasks, appropriate for their social status, and worn with dignity and order. Women from upper and middle classes need to teach this sense of order and dignity, as their perspective on things can’t be right if they tolerate the poverty of the less fortunate while dressing extravagantly themselves. The true art of dressing should be based on the proper pride and comfort of both the wealthy and the impoverished. This should be pursued by manufacturers who care as much about the quality and beauty of their fabrics as the armorers of Milan and Damascus cared about their steel.
Then, in the third place, having recovered some wholesome habits of life as to food and dress, we must recover them as to lodging. I said just now that the best architecture was but a glorified roof. Think of it. The dome of the Vatican, the porches of Rheims or Chartres, the vaults and arches of their aisles, the canopy of the tomb, and the spire of the belfry, are all forms resulting from the mere requirement that a certain space shall be strongly covered from heat and rain. More than that—as I have tried all through The Stones of Venice to show—the lovely forms of these were every one of them developed in civil and domestic building, and only after their invention employed ecclesiastically on the grandest scale. I think you cannot but have noticed here in Oxford, as elsewhere, that our modern architects never seem to know what to do with their roofs. Be assured, until the roofs are right, nothing else will be; and there are just two ways of keeping them right. Never build them of iron, but only of wood or stone; and secondly, take care that in every town the little roofs are built before the large ones, and that everybody who wants one has got one. And we must try also to make everybody want one. That is to say, at some not very advanced period of life, men should desire to have a home, which they do not wish to quit any more, suited to their habits of life, and likely to be more and more suitable to them until their death. And men must desire to have these their dwelling-places built as strongly as possible, and furnished and decorated daintily, and set in pleasant places, in bright light, and good air, being able to choose for themselves that at least as well as swallows. And when the houses are grouped together in cities, men must have so much civic fellowship as to subject their architecture to a common law, and so much civic pride as to desire that the whole gathered group of human dwellings should be a lovely thing, not a frightful one, on the face of the earth. Not many weeks ago an English clergyman,[198] a master of this University, a man not given to sentiment, but of middle age, and great practical sense, told me, by accident, and wholly without reference to the subject now before us, that he never could enter London from his country parsonage but with closed eyes, lest the sight of the blocks of houses which the railroad intersected in the suburbs should unfit him, by the horror of it, for his day's work.
Then, in the third place, having recovered some wholesome habits of life as to food and dress, we must recover them as to lodging. I said just now that the best architecture was but a glorified roof. Think of it. The dome of the Vatican, the porches of Rheims or Chartres, the vaults and arches of their aisles, the canopy of the tomb, and the spire of the belfry, are all forms resulting from the mere requirement that a certain space shall be strongly covered from heat and rain. More than that—as I have tried all through The Stones of Venice to show—the lovely forms of these were every one of them developed in civil and domestic building, and only after their invention employed ecclesiastically on the grandest scale. I think you cannot but have noticed here in Oxford, as elsewhere, that our modern architects never seem to know what to do with their roofs. Be assured, until the roofs are right, nothing else will be; and there are just two ways of keeping them right. Never build them of iron, but only of wood or stone; and secondly, take care that in every town the little roofs are built before the large ones, and that everybody who wants one has got one. And we must try also to make everybody want one. That is to say, at some not very advanced period of life, men should desire to have a home, which they do not wish to quit any more, suited to their habits of life, and likely to be more and more suitable to them until their death. And men must desire to have these their dwelling-places built as strongly as possible, and furnished and decorated daintily, and set in pleasant places, in bright light, and good air, being able to choose for themselves that at least as well as swallows. And when the houses are grouped together in cities, men must have so much civic fellowship as to subject their architecture to a common law, and so much civic pride as to desire that the whole gathered group of human dwellings should be a lovely thing, not a frightful one, on the face of the earth. Not many weeks ago an English clergyman,[198] a master of this University, a man not given to sentiment, but of middle age, and great practical sense, told me, by accident, and wholly without reference to the subject now before us, that he never could enter London from his country parsonage but with closed eyes, lest the sight of the blocks of houses which the railroad intersected in the suburbs should unfit him, by the horror of it, for his day's work.
Now, it is not possible—and I repeat to you, only in more deliberate assertion, what I wrote just twenty-two years ago in the last chapter of the Seven Lamps of Architecture—it is not possible to have any right morality, happiness, or art, in any country where the cities are thus built, or thus, let me rather say, clotted and coagulated; spots of a dreadful mildew, spreading by patches and blotches over the country they consume. You must have lovely cities, crystallized, not coagulated, into form; limited in size, and not casting out the scum and scurf of them into an encircling eruption of shame, but girded each with its sacred pomoerium, and with garlands of gardens full of blossoming trees and softly guided streams.
Now, it’s not possible—and I’ll say this again more deliberately, echoing what I wrote just twenty-two years ago in the last chapter of the Seven Lamps of Architecture—it’s not possible to have any genuine morality, happiness, or art in any country where the cities are built like this, or rather, let me say, clotted and stuck together; spots of a terrible mildew, spreading in patches all over the land they take over. You need beautiful cities, crystallized, not clotted, into shape; limited in size, not expelling the waste of them into a surrounding eruption of shame, but each surrounded by its sacred boundary, with garlands of gardens filled with blooming trees and gently flowing streams.
ATHENA ERGANE
This short selection is taken from the volume entitled The Queen of the Air, in which Ruskin, fascinated by the deep significance of the Greek myths and realizing the religious sincerity underlying them, attempts to interpret those that cluster about Athena. The book was published June 22, 1869. It is divided into three "Lectures," parts of which actually were delivered as lectures on different occasions, entitled respectively "Athena Chalinitis" (Athena in the Heavens), "Athena Keramitis" (Athena in the Earth), "Athena Ergane" (Athena in the Heart). The first lecture is the only one which keeps to the title of the book; in the others the legend is used merely as a starting-point for the expression of various pregnant ideas on social and historical problems. The book as a whole abounds in flashes of inspiration and insight, and is a favourite with many readers of Ruskin. Carlyle, in a letter to Froude, wrote: "Passages of that last book, Queen of the Air, went into my heart like arrows."
This short selection is taken from the volume titled The Queen of the Air, where Ruskin, captivated by the profound meaning of Greek myths and recognizing the genuine spirituality behind them, seeks to interpret those associated with Athena. The book was published on June 22, 1869. It's divided into three "Lectures," some of which were actually delivered as talks on various occasions, titled respectively "Athena Chalinitis" (Athena in the Heavens), "Athena Keramitis" (Athena in the Earth), and "Athena Ergane" (Athena in the Heart). The first lecture aligns with the title of the book; in the others, the legend serves merely as a starting point for exploring different significant ideas regarding social and historical issues. Overall, the book is filled with moments of inspiration and insight, making it a favorite among many of Ruskin's readers. Carlyle, in a letter to Froude, wrote: "Passages of that last book, Queen of the Air, went into my heart like arrows."
In different places of my writings, and through many years of endeavour to define the laws of art, I have insisted on this Tightness in work, and on its connection with virtue of character, in so many partial ways, that the impression left on the reader's mind—if, indeed, it was ever impressed at all—has been confused and uncertain. In beginning the series of my corrected works, I wish this principle (in my own mind the foundation of every other) to be made plain, if nothing else is: and will try, therefore, to make it so, so far as, by any effort, I can put it into unmistakable words. And, first, here is a very simple statement of it, given lately in a lecture on the Architecture of the Valley of the Somme,[199] which will be better read in this place than in its incidental connection with my account of the porches of Abbeville.
In different places of my writings, and through many years of endeavour to define the laws of art, I have insisted on this Tightness in work, and on its connection with virtue of character, in so many partial ways, that the impression left on the reader's mind—if, indeed, it was ever impressed at all—has been confused and uncertain. In beginning the series of my corrected works, I wish this principle (in my own mind the foundation of every other) to be made plain, if nothing else is: and will try, therefore, to make it so, so far as, by any effort, I can put it into unmistakable words. And, first, here is a very simple statement of it, given lately in a lecture on the Architecture of the Valley of the Somme,[199] which will be better read in this place than in its incidental connection with my account of the porches of Abbeville.
I had used, in a preceding part of the lecture, the expression, "by what faults" this Gothic architecture fell. We continually speak thus of works of art. We talk of their faults and merits, as of virtues and vices. What do we mean by talking of the faults of a picture, or the merits of a piece of stone?
I had used, earlier in the lecture, the phrase, "by what faults" this Gothic architecture had fallen. We often discuss art in this way. We mention their faults and merits, like we do with virtues and vices. What do we mean when we talk about the faults of a picture or the merits of a block of stone?
The faults of a work of art are the faults of its workman, and its virtues his virtues.
The flaws in a piece of art reflect the flaws of its creator, and its strengths reflect his strengths.
Great art is the expression of the mind of a great man, and mean art, that of the want of mind of a weak man. A foolish person builds foolishly, and a wise one, sensibly; a virtuous one, beautifully; and a vicious one, basely. If stone work is well put together, it means that a thoughtful man planned it, and a careful man cut it, and an honest man cemented it. If it has too much ornament, it means that its carver was too greedy of pleasure; if too little, that he was rude, or insensitive, or stupid, and the like. So that when once you have learned how to spell these most precious of all legends,—pictures and buildings,—you may read the characters of men, and of nations, in their art, as in a mirror;—nay, as in a microscope, and magnified a hundredfold; for the character becomes passionate in the art, and intensifies itself in all its noblest or meanest delights. Nay, not only as in a microscope, but as under a scalpel, and in dissection; for a man may hide himself from you, or misrepresent himself to you, every other way; but he cannot in his work: there, be sure, you have him to the inmost. All that he likes, all that he sees,—all that he can do,—his imagination, his affections, his perseverance, his impatience, his clumsiness, cleverness, everything is there. If the work is a cobweb, you know it was made by a spider; if a honeycomb, by a bee; a worm-cast is thrown up by a worm, and a nest wreathed by a bird; and a house built by a man, worthily, if he is worthy, and ignobly, if he is ignoble.
Great art expresses the thoughts of a great person, while poor art reflects the lack of thought in a weaker person. A foolish person constructs foolishly, a wise one does so sensibly; a virtuous one creates beautifully, and a vicious one acts poorly. If stonework is well done, it shows that a thoughtful person designed it, a careful person shaped it, and an honest person joined it together. If there's too much decoration, it indicates that the carver was too focused on pleasure; if there's too little, it suggests he was rude, insensitive, or simply dull. Once you learn how to interpret these invaluable messages—through pictures and buildings—you can read the character of people and nations in their art, like looking in a mirror; in fact, it's like using a microscope, magnifying it a hundred times; because the character is expressed passionately in art, revealing both its highest and lowest pleasures. Not only like a microscope but also like a scalpel, exposing everything; a person might hide or misrepresent themselves in many ways, but not in their work: there, you truly see them at their core. Everything they enjoy, everything they perceive—every ability, imagination, emotion, persistence, impatience, awkwardness, talent—it's all there. If the work is a cobweb, you know it was created by a spider; if it's a honeycomb, it came from a bee; worm castings come from worms, and nests are built by birds; and a house is built by a person, done honorably if they are worthy, and shamefully if they are not.
And always, from the least to the greatest, as the made thing is good or bad, so is the maker of it.
And always, from the smallest to the largest, the quality of the created thing reflects the quality of its creator.
You all use this faculty of judgment more or less, whether you theoretically admit the principle or not. Take that floral gable;[200] you don't suppose the man who built Stonehenge could have built that, or that the man who built that, would have built Stonehenge? Do you think an old Roman would have liked such a piece of filigree work? or that Michael Angelo would have spent his time in twisting these stems of roses in and out? Or, of modern handicraftsmen, do you think a burglar, or a brute, or a pickpocket could have carved it? Could Bill Sykes have done it? or the Dodger, dexterous with finger and tool? You will find in the end, that no man could have done it but exactly the man who did it; and by looking close at it, you may, if you know your letters, read precisely the manner of man he was.
You all use this faculty of judgment more or less, whether you theoretically admit the principle or not. Take that floral gable;[200] you don't suppose the man who built Stonehenge could have built that, or that the man who built that, would have built Stonehenge? Do you think an old Roman would have liked such a piece of filigree work? or that Michael Angelo would have spent his time in twisting these stems of roses in and out? Or, of modern handicraftsmen, do you think a burglar, or a brute, or a pickpocket could have carved it? Could Bill Sykes have done it? or the Dodger, dexterous with finger and tool? You will find in the end, that no man could have done it but exactly the man who did it; and by looking close at it, you may, if you know your letters, read precisely the manner of man he was.
Now I must insist on this matter, for a grave reason. Of all facts concerning art, this is the one most necessary to be known, that, while manufacture is the work of hands only, art is the work of the whole spirit of man; and as that spirit is, so is the deed of it: and by whatever power of vice or virtue any art is produced, the same vice or virtue it reproduces and teaches. That which is born of evil begets evil; and that which is born of valour and honour, teaches valour and honour. Al art is either infection or education. It must be one or other of these.
Now I need to stress this point because it's really important. Of all things to know about art, this is the most crucial: while manufacturing is just a process done by hands, art comes from the entire spirit of a person; and how that spirit is will shape the outcome. The vices or virtues that influence the creation of art will also influence what it teaches. What comes from evil produces more evil, while what comes from bravery and integrity teaches bravery and integrity. All art is either a contagion or a form of education. It has to be one or the other.
This, I repeat, of all truths respecting art, is the one of which understanding is the most precious, and denial the most deadly. And I assert it the more, because it has of late been repeatedly, expressly, and with contumely denied; and that by high authority: and I hold it one of the most sorrowful facts connected with the decline of the arts among us, that English gentlemen, of high standing as scholars and artists, should have been blinded into the acceptance, and betrayed into the assertion of a fallacy which only authority such as theirs could have rendered for an instant credible. For the contrary of it is written in the history of all great nations; it is the one sentence always inscribed on the steps of their thrones; the one concordant voice in which they speak to us out of their dust.
This, I say again, is the most important truth about art, where understanding is invaluable and denial is extremely harmful. I emphasize this even more because it has recently been denied repeatedly and disrespectfully by people in high positions. I find it incredibly sad that respected English gentlemen—both scholars and artists—have been misled into believing and promoting a falsehood that only their authority could have made seem credible, even for a moment. The opposite of this idea is recorded in the history of all great nations; it's the one phrase always found on the steps of their thrones; the one unified message that they communicate to us from their past.
All such nations first manifest themselves as a pure and beautiful animal race, with intense energy and imagination. They live lives of hardship by choice, and by grand instinct of manly discipline: they become fierce and irresistible soldiers; the nation is always its own army, and their king, or chief head of government, is always their first soldier. Pharaoh, or David, or Leonidas, or Valerius, or Barbarossa, or Coeur de Lion, or St. Louis, or Dandolo, or Frederick the Great:—Egyptian, Jew, Greek, Roman, German, English, French, Venetian,—that is inviolable law for them all; their king must be their first soldier, or they cannot be in progressive power. Then, after their great military period, comes the domestic period; in which, without betraying the discipline of war, they add to their great soldiership the delights and possessions of a delicate and tender home-life: and then, for all nations, is the time of their perfect art, which is the fruit, the evidence, the reward of their national ideal of character, developed by the finished care of the occupations of peace. That is the history of all true art that ever was, or can be: palpably the history of it,—unmistakably,—written on the forehead of it in letters of light,—in tongues of fire, by which the seal of virtue is branded as deep as ever iron burnt into a convict's flesh the seal of crime. But always, hitherto, after the great period, has followed the day of luxury, and pursuit of the arts for pleasure only. And all has so ended.
All such nations first show themselves as a pure and beautiful race of strong creatures, filled with energy and creativity. They willingly endure hardships and exhibit a great sense of discipline: they become fierce and unstoppable soldiers; the nation is always its own army, and their king, or main leader, is always their top soldier. Pharaoh, David, Leonidas, Valerius, Barbarossa, Coeur de Lion, St. Louis, Dandolo, Frederick the Great—Egyptian, Jew, Greek, Roman, German, English, French, Venetian—this is an unbreakable rule for them all; their king must be their leading soldier, or they cannot maintain their strength. After their significant period of military power, they enter a domestic phase; in this time, without losing their war discipline, they enhance their military prowess with the joys and comforts of a gentle home life: then comes the period of perfect art for all nations, which is the outcome, the proof, and the reward of their national character ideals, nurtured through the diligent work of peace. This is the story of all true art that has ever existed or will exist: undeniably clear in its history—written brightly on its surface—in fiery letters, by which the mark of virtue is impressed as deeply as the brand of crime has scarred a convict's flesh. But always, until now, following the great period has been an era of luxury, and the pursuit of the arts for mere pleasure. And it all ends there.
Thus far of Abbeville building. Now I have here asserted two things,—first, the foundation of art in moral character; next, the foundation of moral character in war. I must make both these assertions clearer, and prove them.
Thus far of Abbeville building. Now, I have stated two things—first, that the foundation of art is in moral character; next, that the foundation of moral character is in war. I need to clarify both of these statements and provide evidence for them.
First, of the foundation of art in moral character. Of course art-gift and amiability of disposition are two different things. A good man is not necessarily a painter, nor does an eye for colour necessarily imply an honest mind. But great art implies the union of both powers: it is the expression, by an art-gift, of a pure soul. If the gift is not there, we can have no art at all; and if the soul—and a right soul too—is not there, the art is bad, however dexterous.
First, consider the foundation of art in moral character. Obviously, having an artistic talent and being a good person are two different things. A good person isn’t automatically an artist, and having a good eye for color doesn’t mean one has an honest mind. However, great art combines both of these qualities: it expresses, through artistic ability, a pure soul. Without the talent, there can be no art at all; and if the soul—and the right kind of soul—is missing, the art will be flawed, no matter how skillful.
But also, remember, that the art-gift itself is only the result of the moral character of generations. A bad woman may have a sweet voice; but that sweetness of voice comes of the past morality of her race. That she can sing with it at all, she owes to the determination of laws of music by the morality of the past. Every act, every impulse, of virtue and vice, affects in any creature, face, voice, nervous power, and vigour and harmony of invention, at once. Perseverance in rightness of human conduct, renders, after a certain number of generations, human art possible; every sin clouds it, be it ever so little a one; and persistent vicious living and following of pleasure render, after a certain number of generations, all art impossible. Men are deceived by the long-suffering of the laws of nature; and mistake, in a nation, the reward of the virtue of its sires for the issue of its own sins. The time of their visitation will come, and that inevitably; for, it is always true, that if the fathers have eaten sour grapes, the children's teeth are set on edge.[201] And for the individual, as soon as you have learned to read, you may, as I have said, know him to the heart's core, through his art. Let his art-gift be never so great, and cultivated to the height by the schools of a great race of men; and it is still but a tapestry thrown over his own being and inner soul; and the bearing of it will show, infallibly, whether it hangs on a man, or on a skeleton. If you are dim-eyed, you may not see the difference in the fall of the folds at first, but learn how to look, and the folds themselves will become transparent, and you shall see through them the death's shape, or the divine one, making the tissue above it as a cloud of light, or as a winding-sheet.
But also, remember, that the art-gift itself is only the result of the moral character of generations. A bad woman may have a sweet voice; but that sweetness of voice comes of the past morality of her race. That she can sing with it at all, she owes to the determination of laws of music by the morality of the past. Every act, every impulse, of virtue and vice, affects in any creature, face, voice, nervous power, and vigour and harmony of invention, at once. Perseverance in rightness of human conduct, renders, after a certain number of generations, human art possible; every sin clouds it, be it ever so little a one; and persistent vicious living and following of pleasure render, after a certain number of generations, all art impossible. Men are deceived by the long-suffering of the laws of nature; and mistake, in a nation, the reward of the virtue of its sires for the issue of its own sins. The time of their visitation will come, and that inevitably; for, it is always true, that if the fathers have eaten sour grapes, the children's teeth are set on edge.[201] And for the individual, as soon as you have learned to read, you may, as I have said, know him to the heart's core, through his art. Let his art-gift be never so great, and cultivated to the height by the schools of a great race of men; and it is still but a tapestry thrown over his own being and inner soul; and the bearing of it will show, infallibly, whether it hangs on a man, or on a skeleton. If you are dim-eyed, you may not see the difference in the fall of the folds at first, but learn how to look, and the folds themselves will become transparent, and you shall see through them the death's shape, or the divine one, making the tissue above it as a cloud of light, or as a winding-sheet.
Then farther, observe, I have said (and you will find it true, and that to the uttermost) that, as all lovely art is rooted in virtue, so it bears fruit of virtue, and is didactic in its own nature. It is often didactic also in actually expressed thought, as Giotto's, Michael Angelo's, Dürer's, and hundreds more; but that is not its special function,—it is didactic chiefly by being beautiful; but beautiful with haunting thought, no less than with form, and full of myths that can be read only with the heart.
Then further, notice, I have said (and you will find it true, completely) that, as all beautiful art is grounded in virtue, it also produces virtue and is educational by its very nature. It can also be educational in its actual expressed ideas, like Giotto’s, Michelangelo’s, Dürer’s, and many more; but that's not its main purpose—its primary educational role comes from being beautiful; beautiful not only in form but also in deep thoughts, filled with myths that can only be understood with the heart.
For instance, at this moment there is open beside me as I write, a page of Persian manuscript, wrought with wreathed azure and geld, and soft green, and violet, and ruby and scarlet, into one field of pure resplendence. It is wrought to delight the eyes only; and does delight them; and the man who did it assuredly had eyes in his head; but not much more. It is not didactic art, but its author was happy: and it will do the good, and the harm, that mere pleasure can do. But, opposite me, is an early Turner drawing of the lake of Geneva, taken about two miles from Geneva, on the Lausanne road, with Mont Blanc in the distance. The old city is seen lying beyond the waveless waters, veiled with a sweet misty veil of Athena's weaving: a faint light of morning, peaceful exceedingly, and almost colourless, shed from behind the Voirons, increases into soft amber along the slope of the Salève, and is just seen, and no more, on the fair warm fields of its summit, between the folds of a white cloud that rests upon the grass, but rises, high and towerlike, into the zenith of dawn above.
For example, right now as I write, there’s a page of a Persian manuscript beside me, adorned with swirling patterns in blue, gold, soft green, violet, ruby, and scarlet, creating a vibrant display. It's meant purely for visual enjoyment, and it certainly achieves that; the artist who created it clearly had a good eye, but not much else. It's not educational art, but its creator was happy, and it will have the effects—both good and bad—that simple pleasure can bring. Meanwhile, in front of me is an early Turner drawing of Lake Geneva, created about two miles from Geneva on the road to Lausanne, with Mont Blanc visible in the background. The old city is seen lying beyond the calm waters, cloaked in a gentle mist woven by Athena: a subtle morning light, extremely peaceful and almost colorless, shines from behind the Voirons, intensifying into soft amber along the slope of the Salève, barely visible on the warm fields at its peak, nestled between the layers of a white cloud resting on the grass, but soaring high and tower-like into the dawn sky above.
There is not as much colour in that low amber light upon the hill-side as there is in the palest dead leaf. The lake is not blue, but grey in mist, passing into deep shadow beneath the Voirons' pines; a few dark clusters of leaves, a single white flower—scarcely seen—are all the gladness given to the rocks of the shore. One of the ruby spots of the eastern manuscript would give colour enough for all the red that is in Turner's entire drawing. For the mere pleasure of the eye, there is not so much in all those lines of his, throughout the entire landscape, as in half an inch square of the Persian's page. What made him take pleasure in the low colour that is only like the brown of a dead leaf? in the cold grey of dawn—in the one white flower among the rocks—in these—and no more than these?
There isn’t as much color in that low amber light on the hillside as there is in the palest dead leaf. The lake isn’t blue, but rather grey in the mist, fading into deep shadow beneath the Voirons' pines; a few dark clusters of leaves and a single barely noticeable white flower are all the cheer brought to the rocks of the shore. One of the ruby spots from the eastern manuscript would provide enough color for all the red in Turner’s entire drawing. For sheer visual pleasure, there’s less in all those lines of his throughout the landscape than in just half an inch square of the Persian's page. What made him find joy in the muted colors that resemble the brown of a dead leaf? In the cold grey of dawn? In the single white flower among the rocks? In these—and just these?
He took pleasure in them because he had been bred among English fields and hills; because the gentleness of a great race was in his heart, and its power of thought in his brain; because he knew the stories of the Alps, and of the cities at their feet; because he had read the Homeric legends of the clouds, and beheld the gods of dawn, and the givers of dew to the fields; because he knew the faces of the crags, and the imagery of the passionate mountains, as a man knows the face of his friend; because he had in him the wonder and sorrow concerning life and death, which are the inheritance of the Gothic soul from the days of its first sea kings; and also the compassion and the joy that are woven into the innermost fabric of every great imaginative spirit, born now in countries that have lived by the Christian faith with any courage or truth. And the picture contains also, for us, just this which its maker had in him to give; and can convey it to us, just so far as we are of the temper in which it must be received. It is didactic if we are worthy to be taught, no otherwise. The pure heart, it will make more pure; the thoughtful, more thoughtful. It has in it no words for the reckless or the base.
He found joy in them because he had grown up among English fields and hills; because the gentleness of a great culture was in his heart and its depth of thought in his mind; because he knew the stories of the Alps and the cities around them; because he had read the epic tales of the skies and seen the dawn's deities and the ones who bless the fields with dew; because he recognized the faces of the cliffs and the imagery of the passionate mountains, like a person knows the face of a friend; because he carried the wonder and sorrow about life and death, which are the legacy of the Gothic spirit since the times of its first sea kings; and also the compassion and joy that are woven into the very essence of every great imaginative soul, born in lands that have embraced the Christian faith with any courage or truth. And the art conveys to us exactly what its creator had to offer, and it can reach us just as much as we are open to receive it. It is instructive if we are ready to learn, otherwise not. It will purify the pure heart more; it will make the thoughtful even more thoughtful. It contains no words for the reckless or the unworthy.
"Traffic" is the second of the three lectures published May, 1866, in the volume entitled The Crown of Wild Olive. All these lectures were delivered in the years 1864 and 1865, but the one here printed was earliest. The occasion on which Ruskin addressed the people of Bradford is made sufficiently clear from the opening sentences. The lecture is important as emphasizing in a popular way some of his most characteristic economic theories.
"Traffic" is the second of the three lectures published in May 1866, in the volume titled The Crown of Wild Olive. All these lectures were delivered in 1864 and 1865, but the one printed here was the first. The context in which Ruskin spoke to the people of Bradford is made clear from the opening sentences. The lecture is significant for highlighting some of his most distinctive economic theories in an accessible manner.
TRAFFIC[202]
My good Yorkshire friends, you asked me down here among your hills that I might talk to you about this Exchange you are going to build: but, earnestly and seriously asking you to pardon me, I am going to do nothing of the kind. I cannot talk, or at least can say very little, about this same Exchange. I must talk of quite other things, though not willingly;—I could not deserve your pardon, if, when you invited me to speak on one subject, I wilfully spoke on another. But I cannot speak, to purpose, of anything about which I do not care; and most simply and sorrowfully I have to tell you, in the outset, that I do not care about this Exchange of yours.
My good friends from Yorkshire, you invited me to come here to your hills so I could talk to you about the Exchange you’re planning to build. However, I sincerely ask for your forgiveness because that's not what I’m going to do. I can’t discuss this Exchange, or at least I can say very little about it. I need to talk about other matters, though I don’t want to; I wouldn’t deserve your forgiveness if I deliberately spoke about something else when you asked me to focus on one topic. But I can't engage meaningfully in a conversation about something I don’t care about, and I regret to tell you right at the start that I do not care about this Exchange of yours.
If, however, when you sent me your invitation, I had answered, "I won't come, I don't care about the Exchange of Bradford," you would have been justly offended with me, not knowing the reasons of so blunt a carelessness. So I have come down, hoping that you will patiently let me tell you why, on this, and many other such occasions, I now remain silent, when formerly I should have caught at the opportunity of speaking to a gracious audience.
If, when you sent me your invitation, I had responded, "I’m not coming, I don't care about the Exchange of Bradford," you would have been justly upset with me, unaware of the reasons behind such a blunt disregard. So I came, hoping that you'll patiently allow me to explain why, on this and many other similar occasions, I now stay quiet when in the past I would have eagerly taken the chance to speak to a kind audience.
In a word, then, I do not care about this Exchange—because you don't; and because you know perfectly well I cannot make you. Look at the essential conditions of the case, which you, as business men, know perfectly well, though perhaps you think I forget them. You are going to spend £30,000, which to you, collectively, is nothing; the buying a new coat is, as to the cost of it, a much more important matter of consideration to me, than building a new Exchange is to you. But you think you may as well have the right thing for your money. You know there are a great many odd styles of architecture about; you don't want to do anything ridiculous; you hear of me, among others, as a respectable architectural man-milliner; and you send for me, that I may tell you the leading fashion; and what is, in our shops, for the moment, the newest and sweetest thing in pinnacles.
In short, I really don’t care about this Exchange—because you don’t; and because you know very well that I can’t make you care. Look at the key points of this situation, which you, as business people, understand perfectly, even if you think I might forget them. You’re about to spend £30,000, which is nothing for you all together; buying a new coat is, for me, a much more significant consideration in terms of cost than building a new Exchange is for you. But you think you should get the right thing for your money. You know there are many different architectural styles out there; you don’t want to do anything absurd; you hear of me, among others, as a reputable architectural consultant; and you reach out to me so I can tell you what’s currently in style and what’s the hottest new trend in designs.
Now, pardon me for telling you frankly, you cannot have good architecture merely by asking people's advice on occasion. All good architecture is the expression of national life and character, and it is produced by a prevalent and eager national taste, or desire for beauty. And I want you to think a little of the deep significance of this word "taste"; for no statement of mine has been more earnestly or oftener controverted than that good taste is essentially a moral quality. "No," say many of my antagonists, "taste is one thing, morality is another. Tell us what is pretty: we shall be glad to know that; but we need no sermons—even were you able to preach them, which may be doubted."
Now, let me be straightforward with you: you can’t achieve great architecture just by occasionally asking for people's opinions. Great architecture reflects the essence of national life and character, and it arises from a strong and passionate national taste or desire for beauty. I want you to consider the deep meaning of the word "taste"; because no statement of mine has been more strongly challenged than the idea that good taste is fundamentally a moral quality. "No," many of my critics argue, "taste is one thing, and morality is another. Tell us what looks good; we’d love to know that. But we don’t need lectures—even if you could deliver them, which is debatable."
Permit me, therefore, to fortify this old dogma of mine somewhat. Taste is not only a part and an index of morality;—it is the ONLY morality. The first, and last, and closest trial question to any living creature is, "What do you like?" Tell me what you like, and I'll tell you what you are. Go out into the street, and ask the first man or woman you meet, what their "taste" is; and if they answer candidly, you know them, body and soul. "You, my friend in the rags, with the unsteady gait, what do you like?" "A pipe and a quartern of gin." I know you. "You, good woman, with the quick step and tidy bonnet, what do you like?" "A swept hearth, and a clean tea-table; and my husband opposite me, and a baby at my breast." Good, I know you also. "You, little girl with the golden hair and the soft eyes, what do you like?" "My canary, and a run among the wood hyacinths." "You, little boy with the dirty hands, and the low forehead, what do you like?" "A shy at the sparrows, and a game at pitch farthing." Good; we know them all now. What more need we ask?
So let me expand on this old belief of mine a bit. Taste is not just a part of morality; it is the ONLY morality. The first, last, and closest question every living being faces is, "What do you like?" Tell me what you like, and I'll tell you who you are. Go out into the street and ask the first person you see what their "taste" is; if they answer honestly, you'll understand them completely. "You, my friend in rags with an unsteady walk, what do you like?" "A pipe and a shot of gin." I know you. "You, ma'am with the brisk pace and neat bonnet, what do you like?" "A clean hearth, a tidy tea table, my husband across from me, and a baby in my arms." Great, I know you too. "You, little girl with golden hair and gentle eyes, what do you like?" "My canary and running through the wood hyacinths." "You, little boy with dirty hands and a low forehead, what do you like?" "A shot at the sparrows and a game of pitch farthing." Good; now we know them all. What else do we need to ask?
"Nay," perhaps you answer; "we need rather to ask what these people and children do, than what they like. If they do right, it is no matter that they like what is wrong; and if they do wrong, it is no matter that they like what is right. Doing is the great thing; and it does not matter that the man likes drinking, so that he does not drink; nor that the little girl likes to be kind to her canary, if she will not learn her lessons; nor that the little boy likes throwing stones at the sparrows, if he goes to the Sunday school." Indeed, for a short time, and in a provisional sense, this is true. For if, resolutely, people do what is right, in time they come to like doing it. But they only are in a right moral state when they have come to like doing it; and as long as they don't like it, they are still in a vicious state. The man is not in health of body who is always thinking of the bottle in the cupboard, though he bravely bears his thirst; but the man who heartily enjoys water in the morning, and wine in the evening, each in its proper quantity and time. And the entire object of true education is to make people not merely do the right things, but enjoy the right things:—not merely industrious, but to love industry—not merely learned, but to love knowledge—not merely pure, but to love purity—not merely just, but to hunger and thirst after justice.[203]
"Nay," perhaps you answer; "we need rather to ask what these people and children do, than what they like. If they do right, it is no matter that they like what is wrong; and if they do wrong, it is no matter that they like what is right. Doing is the great thing; and it does not matter that the man likes drinking, so that he does not drink; nor that the little girl likes to be kind to her canary, if she will not learn her lessons; nor that the little boy likes throwing stones at the sparrows, if he goes to the Sunday school." Indeed, for a short time, and in a provisional sense, this is true. For if, resolutely, people do what is right, in time they come to like doing it. But they only are in a right moral state when they have come to like doing it; and as long as they don't like it, they are still in a vicious state. The man is not in health of body who is always thinking of the bottle in the cupboard, though he bravely bears his thirst; but the man who heartily enjoys water in the morning, and wine in the evening, each in its proper quantity and time. And the entire object of true education is to make people not merely do the right things, but enjoy the right things:—not merely industrious, but to love industry—not merely learned, but to love knowledge—not merely pure, but to love purity—not merely just, but to hunger and thirst after justice.[203]
But you may answer or think, "Is the liking for outside ornaments,—for pictures, or statues, or furniture, or architecture,—a moral quality?" Yes, most surely, if a rightly set liking. Taste for any pictures or statues is not a moral quality, but taste for good ones is. Only here again we have to define the word "good." I don't mean by "good," clever—or learned—or difficult in the doing. Take a picture by Teniers, of sots quarrelling over their dice; it is an entirely clever picture; so clever that nothing in its kind has ever been done equal to it; but it is also an entirely base and evil picture. It is an expression of delight in the prolonged contemplation of a vile thing, and delight in that is an "unmannered," or "immoral" quality. It is "bad taste" in the profoundest sense—it is the taste of the devils. On the other hand, a picture of Titian's, or a Greek statue, or a Greek coin, or a Turner landscape, expresses delight in the perpetual contemplation of a good and perfect thing. That is an entirely moral quality—it is the taste of the angels And all delight in art, and all love of it, resolve themselves into simple love of that which deserves love. That deserving is the quality which we call "loveliness"—(we ought to have an opposite word, hateliness, to be said of the things which deserve to be hated); and it is not an indifferent nor optional thing whether we love this or that; but it is just the vital function of all our being. What we like determines what we are, and is the sign of what we are; and to teach taste is inevitably to form character.
But you might ask or think, "Is the appreciation for external decorations—like paintings, sculptures, furniture, or architecture—a moral quality?" Yes, definitely, if it's a properly aligned appreciation. Liking any pictures or statues isn’t a moral quality, but liking good ones is. However, we need to clarify what we mean by "good." I don’t mean "good" as in clever, knowledgeable, or difficult to create. Consider a painting by Teniers showing drunks arguing over their dice; it's a very clever painting—so clever that nothing of its kind has ever matched it—but it’s also utterly base and wrong. It reflects a pleasure in staring at something vile, and enjoying that is an "unrefined" or "immoral" quality. It represents "bad taste" in the deepest sense—it’s the taste of devils. On the flip side, a painting by Titian, a Greek statue, a Greek coin, or a Turner landscape reflects a joy in continually contemplating something good and perfect. That is a completely moral quality—it’s the taste of angels. All appreciation of art and all love for it boil down to a simple love for what deserves love. That deserving is the quality we call "loveliness"—(we should have an opposite term, "hateliness," for things that deserve to be hated); and it’s not neutral or optional whether we love one thing or another; it’s a fundamental aspect of our existence. What we like shapes who we are and signifies what we are, and teaching taste inevitably shapes character.
As I was thinking over this, in walking up Fleet Street the other day, my eye caught the title of a book standing open in a bookseller's window. It was—"On the necessity of the diffusion of taste among all classes." "Ah," I thought to myself, "my classifying friend, when you have diffused your taste, where will your classes be? The man who likes what you like, belongs to the same class with you, I think. Inevitably so. You may put him to other work if you choose; but, by the condition you have brought him into, he will dislike the other work as much as you would yourself. You get hold of a scavenger or a costermonger, who enjoyed the Newgate Calendar for literature, and 'Pop goes the Weasel' for music. You think you can make him like Dante and Beethoven? I wish you joy of your lessons; but if you do, you have made a gentleman of him:—he won't like to go back to his coster-mongering."
As I was pondering this while walking up Fleet Street the other day, I noticed the title of a book displayed in a bookseller's window. It was—"On the necessity of spreading taste among all classes." "Ah," I thought to myself, "my classifying friend, when you've spread your taste, where will your classes be? The person who enjoys what you enjoy is, in my opinion, in the same class as you. Inevitably so. You might assign him to different work if you want; but given the situation you've put him in, he'll dislike the other work just as much as you would. You find a scavenger or a costermonger who appreciates the Newgate Calendar for literature and 'Pop goes the Weasel' for music. You think you can make him appreciate Dante and Beethoven? Good luck with your lessons; but if you do, you've turned him into a gentleman:—he won't want to go back to his costermongering."
And so completely and unexceptionally is this so, that, if I had time to-night, I could show you that a nation cannot be affected by any vice, or weakness, without expressing it, legibly, and for ever, either in bad art, or by want of art; and that there is no national virtue, small or great, which is not manifestly expressed in all the art which circumstances enable the people possessing that virtue to produce. Take, for instance, your great English virtue of enduring and patient courage. You have at present in England only one art of any consequence—that is, iron-working. You know thoroughly well how to cast and hammer iron. Now, do you think, in those masses of lava which you build volcanic cones to melt, and which you forge at the mouths of the Infernos you have created; do you think, on those iron plates, your courage and endurance are not written for ever,—not merely with an iron pen, but on iron parchment? And take also your great English vice—European vice—vice of all the world—vice of all other worlds that roll or shine in heaven, bearing with them yet the atmosphere of hell—the vice of jealousy, which brings competition into your commerce, treachery into your councils, and dishonour into your wars—that vice which has rendered for you, and for your next neighbouring nation, the daily occupations of existence no longer possible, but with the mail upon your breasts and the sword loose in its sheath; so that at last, you have realized for all the multitudes of the two great peoples who lead the so-called civilization of the earth,—you have realized for them all, I say, in person and in policy, what was once true only of the rough Border riders of your Cheviot hills—
And so completely and obviously this is true, that if I had time tonight, I could show you that a nation can't be impacted by any vice or weakness without making it clear, permanently, either through bad art or a lack of art; and that there’s no national virtue, big or small, that isn’t clearly reflected in all the art that circumstances allow the people with that virtue to create. For example, consider your great English quality of enduring and patient courage. Currently, England really only has one significant art form—that is, iron-working. You know very well how to cast and shape iron. Now, do you think, in those massive pieces of iron you melt down and forge at the mouths of the hellish forges you've created; do you think, on those iron plates, your courage and endurance aren't etched forever—not just with an iron pen, but on iron parchment? And consider too your great English vice—the European vice—the vice shared by every nation and every other world that orbits or shines in the heavens, still carrying the essence of hell—the vice of jealousy, which brings competition into your trade, deceit into your decisions, and dishonor into your conflicts—that vice which has made the daily necessities of life for you and your neighboring nation only possible while wearing armor and with swords drawn; ultimately, you have demonstrated for all the multitudes of the two great peoples who lead what we call civilization on earth—you’ve made it clear for them all, I say, in their actions and decisions, what was once true only of the rough Border riders of your Cheviot hills—
They carved at the meal
With gloves of steel,
They dug into the meal
With steel gloves,
And they drank the red wine through the helmet barr'd;[204] do you think that this national shame and dastardliness of heart are not written as legibly on every rivet of your iron armour as the strength of the right hands that forged it?
And they drank the red wine through the helmet barr'd;[204] do you think that this national shame and dastardliness of heart are not written as legibly on every rivet of your iron armour as the strength of the right hands that forged it?
Friends, I know not whether this thing be the more ludicrous or the more melancholy. It is quite unspeakably both. Suppose, instead of being now sent for by you, I had been sent for by some private gentleman, living in a suburban house, with his garden separated only by a fruit wall from his next door neighbour's; and he had called me to consult with him on the furnishing of his drawing-room. I begin looking about me, and find the walls rather bare; I think such and such a paper might be desirable—perhaps a little fresco here and there on the ceiling—a damask curtain or so at the windows. "Ah," says my employer, "damask curtains, indeed! That's all very fine, but you know I can't afford that kind of thing just now!" "Yet the world credits you with a splendid income!" "Ah, yes," says my friend, "but do you know, at present I am obliged to spend it nearly all in steel-traps?" "Steel-traps! for whom?" "Why, for that fellow on the other side the wall, you know: we're very good friends, capital friends; but we are obliged to keep our traps set on both sides of the wall; we could not possibly keep on friendly terms without them, and our spring guns. The worst of it is, we are both clever fellows enough; and there's never a day passes that we don't find out a new trap, or a new gun-barrel, or something; we spend about fifteen millions a year each in our traps, take it altogether; and I don't see how we're to do with less." A highly comic state of life for two private gentlemen! but for two nations, it seems to me, not wholly comic. Bedlam would be comic, perhaps, if there were only one madman in it; and your Christmas pantomime is comic, when there is only one clown in it; but when the whole world turns clown, and paints itself red with its own heart's blood instead of vermilion, it is something else than comic, I think.
Friends, I’m not sure if this situation is more ridiculous or more sad. It’s both in a way that’s hard to describe. Imagine, instead of being called to meet you, I was called by some guy living in a suburban house, where his garden is only separated by a fruit wall from his neighbor’s. He asked me to help him furnish his living room. I start looking around and notice the walls are pretty bare; I think maybe a certain type of wallpaper would be nice—perhaps a little fresco on the ceiling here and there—a few damask curtains at the windows. "Oh," my client says, "damask curtains! That sounds great, but you know I can’t afford that right now!" "But everyone thinks you have a great income!" "Well, yes," my friend replies, "but right now I have to spend almost all of it on steel traps." "Steel traps? For who?" "For that guy on the other side of the wall, you know: we're good friends, great friends; but we have to keep our traps set on both sides of the wall; we couldn’t possibly stay on friendly terms without them, and our spring guns. The worst part is, we’re both pretty smart, and every day we come up with a new trap, or a new gun barrel, or something; all together, we spend about fifteen million a year each on our traps, and I don’t see how we can manage with less." It’s a pretty funny situation for two private guys! But for two nations, it seems to me, it’s not entirely funny. A lunatic asylum might be funny if there was only one madman in it; and your Christmas pantomime is funny when there’s just one clown; but when the whole world turns into a clown and paints itself red with its own blood instead of red paint, it’s something else entirely, I think.
Mind, I know a great deal of this is play, and willingly allow for that. You don't know what to do with yourselves for a sensation: fox-hunting and cricketing will not carry you through the whole of this unendurably long mortal life: you liked pop-guns when you were schoolboys, and rifles and Armstrongs are only the same things better made: but then the worst of it is, that what was play to you when boys, was not play to the sparrows; and what is play to you now, is not play to the small birds of State neither; and for the black eagles, you are somewhat shy of taking shots at them, if I mistake not.[205]
Mind, I know a great deal of this is play, and willingly allow for that. You don't know what to do with yourselves for a sensation: fox-hunting and cricketing will not carry you through the whole of this unendurably long mortal life: you liked pop-guns when you were schoolboys, and rifles and Armstrongs are only the same things better made: but then the worst of it is, that what was play to you when boys, was not play to the sparrows; and what is play to you now, is not play to the small birds of State neither; and for the black eagles, you are somewhat shy of taking shots at them, if I mistake not.[205]
I must get back to the matter in hand, however. Believe me, without further instance, I could show you, in all time, that every nation's vice, or virtue, was written in its art: the soldiership of early Greece; the sensuality of late Italy; the visionary religion of Tuscany; the splendid human energy and beauty of Venice. I have no time to do this to-night (I have done it elsewhere before now);[206] but I proceed to apply the principle to ourselves in a more searching manner.
I must get back to the matter in hand, however. Believe me, without further instance, I could show you, in all time, that every nation's vice, or virtue, was written in its art: the soldiership of early Greece; the sensuality of late Italy; the visionary religion of Tuscany; the splendid human energy and beauty of Venice. I have no time to do this to-night (I have done it elsewhere before now);[206] but I proceed to apply the principle to ourselves in a more searching manner.
I notice that among all the new buildings that cover your once wild hills, churches and schools are mixed in due, that is to say, in large proportion, with your mills and mansions; and I notice also that the churches and schools are almost always Gothic, and the mansions and mills are never Gothic. Will you allow me to ask precisely the meaning of this? For, remember, it is peculiarly a modern phenomenon. When Gothic was invented, houses were Gothic as well as churches; and when the Italian style superseded the Gothic, churches were Italian as well as houses. If there is a Gothic spire to the cathedral of Antwerp, there is a Gothic belfry to the Hotel de Ville at Brussels; if Inigo Jones builds an Italian Whitehall, Sir Christopher Wren builds an Italian St. Paul's.[207] But now you live under one school of architecture, and worship under another. What do you mean by doing this? Am I to understand that you are thinking of changing your architecture back to Gothic; and that you treat your churches experimentally, because it does not matter what mistakes you make in a church? Or am I to understand that you consider Gothic a pre-eminently sacred and beautiful mode of building, which you think, like the fine frankincense, should be mixed for the tabernacle only, and reserved for your religious services? For if this be the feeling, though it may seem at first as if it were graceful and reverent, you will find that, at the root of the matter, it signifies neither more nor less than that you have separated your religion from your life.
I notice that among all the new buildings that cover your once wild hills, churches and schools are mixed in due, that is to say, in large proportion, with your mills and mansions; and I notice also that the churches and schools are almost always Gothic, and the mansions and mills are never Gothic. Will you allow me to ask precisely the meaning of this? For, remember, it is peculiarly a modern phenomenon. When Gothic was invented, houses were Gothic as well as churches; and when the Italian style superseded the Gothic, churches were Italian as well as houses. If there is a Gothic spire to the cathedral of Antwerp, there is a Gothic belfry to the Hotel de Ville at Brussels; if Inigo Jones builds an Italian Whitehall, Sir Christopher Wren builds an Italian St. Paul's.[207] But now you live under one school of architecture, and worship under another. What do you mean by doing this? Am I to understand that you are thinking of changing your architecture back to Gothic; and that you treat your churches experimentally, because it does not matter what mistakes you make in a church? Or am I to understand that you consider Gothic a pre-eminently sacred and beautiful mode of building, which you think, like the fine frankincense, should be mixed for the tabernacle only, and reserved for your religious services? For if this be the feeling, though it may seem at first as if it were graceful and reverent, you will find that, at the root of the matter, it signifies neither more nor less than that you have separated your religion from your life.
For consider what a wide significance this fact has: and remember that it is not you only, but all the people of England, who are behaving thus, just now.
For think about how significant this fact is: and remember that it’s not just you, but everyone in England, who is acting this way right now.
You have all got into the habit of calling the church "the house of God." I have seen, over the doors of many churches, the legend actually carved, "This is the house of God and this is the gate of heaven."[208] Now, note where that legend comes from, and of what place it was first spoken. A boy leaves his father's house to go on a long journey on foot, to visit his uncle: he has to cross a wild hill-desert; just as if one of your own boys had to cross the wolds to visit an uncle at Carlisle. The second or third day your boy finds himself somewhere between Hawes and Brough, in the midst of the moors, at sunset. It is stony ground, and boggy; he cannot go one foot further that night. Down he lies, to sleep, on Wharnside, where best he may, gathering a few of the stones together to put under his head;—so wild the place is, he cannot get anything but stones. And there, lying under the broad night, he has a dream; and he sees a ladder set up on the earth, and the top of it reaches to heaven, and the angels of God are ascending and descending upon it. And when he wakes out of his sleep, he says, "How dreadful is this place; surely this is none other than the house of God, and this is the gate of heaven." This PLACE, observe; not this church; not this city; not this stone, even, which he puts up for a memorial—the piece of flint on which his head has lain. But this place; this windy slope of Wharnside; this moorland hollow, torrent-bitten, snow-blighted! this any place where God lets down the ladder. And how are you to know where that will be? or how are you to determine where it may be, but by being ready for it always? Do you know where the lightning is to fall next? You do know that, partly; you can guide the lightning; but you cannot guide the going forth of the Spirit, which is that lightning when it shines from the east to the west.[209]
You have all got into the habit of calling the church "the house of God." I have seen, over the doors of many churches, the legend actually carved, "This is the house of God and this is the gate of heaven."[208] Now, note where that legend comes from, and of what place it was first spoken. A boy leaves his father's house to go on a long journey on foot, to visit his uncle: he has to cross a wild hill-desert; just as if one of your own boys had to cross the wolds to visit an uncle at Carlisle. The second or third day your boy finds himself somewhere between Hawes and Brough, in the midst of the moors, at sunset. It is stony ground, and boggy; he cannot go one foot further that night. Down he lies, to sleep, on Wharnside, where best he may, gathering a few of the stones together to put under his head;—so wild the place is, he cannot get anything but stones. And there, lying under the broad night, he has a dream; and he sees a ladder set up on the earth, and the top of it reaches to heaven, and the angels of God are ascending and descending upon it. And when he wakes out of his sleep, he says, "How dreadful is this place; surely this is none other than the house of God, and this is the gate of heaven." This PLACE, observe; not this church; not this city; not this stone, even, which he puts up for a memorial—the piece of flint on which his head has lain. But this place; this windy slope of Wharnside; this moorland hollow, torrent-bitten, snow-blighted! this any place where God lets down the ladder. And how are you to know where that will be? or how are you to determine where it may be, but by being ready for it always? Do you know where the lightning is to fall next? You do know that, partly; you can guide the lightning; but you cannot guide the going forth of the Spirit, which is that lightning when it shines from the east to the west.[209]
But the perpetual and insolent warping of that strong verse to serve a merely ecclesiastical purpose is only one of the thousand instances in which we sink back into gross Judaism. We call our churches "temples." Now, you know perfectly well they are not temples. They have never had, never can have, anything whatever to do with temples. They are "synagogues"—"gathering places"—where you gather yourselves together as an assembly; and by not calling them so, you again miss the force of another mighty text—"Thou, when thou prayest, shalt not be as the hypocrites are; for they love to pray standing in the churches" [we should translate it], "that they may be seen of men. But thou, when thou prayest, enter into thy closet, and when thou hast shut thy door, pray to thy Father"—which is, not in chancel nor in aisle, but "in secret."[210]
But the perpetual and insolent warping of that strong verse to serve a merely ecclesiastical purpose is only one of the thousand instances in which we sink back into gross Judaism. We call our churches "temples." Now, you know perfectly well they are not temples. They have never had, never can have, anything whatever to do with temples. They are "synagogues"—"gathering places"—where you gather yourselves together as an assembly; and by not calling them so, you again miss the force of another mighty text—"Thou, when thou prayest, shalt not be as the hypocrites are; for they love to pray standing in the churches" [we should translate it], "that they may be seen of men. But thou, when thou prayest, enter into thy closet, and when thou hast shut thy door, pray to thy Father"—which is, not in chancel nor in aisle, but "in secret."[210]
Now, you feel, as I say this to you—I know you feel—as if I were trying to take away the honour of your churches. Not so; I am trying to prove to you the honour of your houses and your hills; not that the Church is not sacred—but that the whole Earth is. I would have you feel, what careless, what constant, what infectious sin there is in all modes of thought, whereby, in calling your churches only "holy," you call your hearths and homes "profane"; and have separated yourselves from the heathen by casting all your household gods to the ground, instead of recognizing, in the place of their many and feeble Lares, the presence of your One and Mighty Lord and Lar.
Now, you might feel, as I say this to you—I know you feel—as if I were trying to take away the honor of your churches. That's not the case; I'm trying to show you the honor of your homes and your hills; it's not that the Church isn't sacred—it's that the whole Earth is. I want you to see how careless, how constant, how infectious sin is in all ways of thinking, where, by calling your churches only "holy," you label your hearths and homes as "profane"; and have distanced yourselves from the heathen by throwing down all your household gods, instead of recognizing, in place of their many weak Lares, the presence of your One and Mighty Lord and Lar.
"But what has all this to do with our Exchange?" you ask me, impatiently. My dear friends, it has just everything to do with it; on these inner and great questions depend all the outer and little ones; and if you have asked me down here to speak to you, because you had before been interested in anything I have written, you must know that all I have yet said about architecture was to show this. The book I called The Seven Lamps was to show that certain right states of temper and moral feeling were the magic powers by which all good architecture, without exception, had been produced. The Stones of Venice had, from beginning to end, no other aim than to show that the Gothic architecture of Venice had arisen out of, and indicated in all its features, a state of pure national faith, and of domestic virtue; and that its Renaissance architecture had arisen out of, and in all its features indicated, a state of concealed national infidelity, and of domestic corruption. And now, you ask me what style is best to build in, and how can I answer, knowing the meaning of the two styles, but by another question—do you mean to build as Christians or as Infidels? And still more—do you mean to build as honest Christians or as honest Infidels? as thoroughly and confessedly either one or the other? You don't like to be asked such rude questions. I cannot help it; they are of much more importance than this Exchange business; and if they can be at once answered, the Exchange business settles itself in a moment. But before I press them farther, I must ask leave to explain one point clearly.
"But what does all this have to do with our Exchange?" you ask me, impatiently. My dear friends, it has everything to do with it; these big inner questions influence all the smaller outer ones. If you’ve invited me here to speak because you were interested in anything I’ve written, you should know that everything I’ve said about architecture was to illustrate this point. The book I called The Seven Lamps aimed to show that certain positive states of mind and moral feelings were the magic factors that produced all good architecture, without exception. The Stones of Venice had, from start to finish, one goal: to show that the Gothic architecture of Venice arose from, and reflected in all its features, a state of pure national faith and domestic virtue; while its Renaissance architecture came from, and indicated, a state of hidden national infidelity and domestic corruption. Now, you ask me what style is best for building, and how can I answer, knowing the meanings of these two styles, other than by posing another question—do you intend to build as Christians or as Infidels? And even more—do you plan to build as honest Christians or as honest Infidels, fully and openly either one or the other? You don't appreciate being asked such blunt questions. I can't help it; they are far more important than this Exchange issue, and if they can be answered straightforwardly, the Exchange situation resolves itself immediately. But before I delve further into this, I need to clarify one point.
In all my past work, my endeavour has been to show that good architecture is essentially religious—the production of a faithful and virtuous, not of an infidel and corrupted people. But in the course of doing this, I have had also to show that good architecture is not ecclesiastical. People are so apt to look upon religion as the business of the clergy, not their own, that the moment they hear of anything depending on "religion," they think it must also have depended on the priesthood; and I have had to take what place was to be occupied between these two errors, and fight both, often with seeming contradiction. Good architecture is the work of good and believing men; therefore, you say, at least some people say, "Good architecture must essentially have been the work of the clergy, not of the laity." No—a thousand times no; good architecture[211] has always been the work of the commonalty, not of the clergy. "What," you say, "those glorious cathedrals—the pride of Europe—did their builders not form Gothic architecture?" No; they corrupted Gothic architecture. Gothic was formed in the baron's castle, and the burgher's street. It was formed by the thoughts, and hands, and powers of labouring citizens and warrior kings. By the monk it was used as an instrument for the aid of his superstition; when that superstition became a beautiful madness, and the best hearts of Europe vainly dreamed and pined in the cloister, and vainly raged and perished in the crusade,—through that fury of perverted faith and wasted war, the Gothic rose also to its loveliest, most fantastic, and, finally, most foolish dreams; and in those dreams, was lost.
In all my past work, my endeavour has been to show that good architecture is essentially religious—the production of a faithful and virtuous, not of an infidel and corrupted people. But in the course of doing this, I have had also to show that good architecture is not ecclesiastical. People are so apt to look upon religion as the business of the clergy, not their own, that the moment they hear of anything depending on "religion," they think it must also have depended on the priesthood; and I have had to take what place was to be occupied between these two errors, and fight both, often with seeming contradiction. Good architecture is the work of good and believing men; therefore, you say, at least some people say, "Good architecture must essentially have been the work of the clergy, not of the laity." No—a thousand times no; good architecture[211] has always been the work of the commonalty, not of the clergy. "What," you say, "those glorious cathedrals—the pride of Europe—did their builders not form Gothic architecture?" No; they corrupted Gothic architecture. Gothic was formed in the baron's castle, and the burgher's street. It was formed by the thoughts, and hands, and powers of labouring citizens and warrior kings. By the monk it was used as an instrument for the aid of his superstition; when that superstition became a beautiful madness, and the best hearts of Europe vainly dreamed and pined in the cloister, and vainly raged and perished in the crusade,—through that fury of perverted faith and wasted war, the Gothic rose also to its loveliest, most fantastic, and, finally, most foolish dreams; and in those dreams, was lost.
I hope, now, that there is no risk of your misunderstanding me when I come to the gist of what I want to say to-night;—when I repeat, that every great national architecture has been the result and exponent of a great national religion. You can't have bits of it here, bits there—you must have it everywhere or nowhere. It is not the monopoly of a clerical company—it is not the exponent of a theological dogma—it is not the hieroglyphic writing of an initiated priesthood; it is the manly language of a people inspired by resolute and common purpose, and rendering resolute and common fidelity to the legible laws of an undoubted God.
I hope there’s no chance of you misunderstanding me when I get to the main point of what I want to say tonight;—when I say that every remarkable national architecture has been shaped by a significant national religion. You can’t have bits of it here and there—you need it everywhere or not at all. It’s not just for a religious group—it’s not just a reflection of a theological belief—it’s not the secret writing of an exclusive priesthood; it’s the strong voice of a people driven by a shared and determined purpose, faithfully upholding the clear laws of an undeniable God.
Now, there have as yet been three distinct schools of European architecture. I say, European, because Asiatic and African architectures belong so entirely to other races and climates, that there is no question of them here; only, in passing, I will simply assure you that whatever is good or great in Egypt, and Syria, and India, is just good or great for the same reasons as the buildings on our side of the Bosphorus. We Europeans, then, have had three great religions: the Greek, which was the worship of the God of Wisdom and Power; the Mediæval, which was the worship of the God of Judgment and Consolation; the Renaissance, which was the worship of the God of Pride and Beauty: these three we have had—they are past,—and now, at last, we English have got a fourth religion, and a God of our own, about which I want to ask you. But I must explain these three old ones first.
Now, there have been three distinct schools of European architecture. I mention European because Asian and African architectures are so different, shaped by their own races and climates, that they aren't relevant here; I will just briefly assure you that whatever is considered good or great in Egypt, Syria, and India is good or great for the same reasons as the buildings on our side of the Bosphorus. We Europeans have experienced three major religions: the Greek, which focused on the worship of the God of Wisdom and Power; the Medieval, which centered on the God of Judgment and Consolation; and the Renaissance, which celebrated the God of Pride and Beauty. These three are in the past, and now, finally, we English have a fourth religion and a God of our own that I want to discuss with you. But first, I need to explain these three older ones.
I repeat, first, the Greeks essentially worshipped the God of Wisdom; so that whatever contended against their religion,—to the Jews a stumbling-block,—was, to the Greeks—Foolishness.[212]
I repeat, first, the Greeks essentially worshipped the God of Wisdom; so that whatever contended against their religion,—to the Jews a stumbling-block,—was, to the Greeks—Foolishness.[212]
The first Greek idea of deity was that expressed in the word, of which we keep the remnant in our words "Di-urnal" and "Di-vine"—the god of Day, Jupiter the revealer. Athena is his daughter, but especially daughter of the Intellect, springing armed from the head. We are only with the help of recent investigation beginning to penetrate the depth of meaning couched under the Athenaic symbols: but I may note rapidly, that her ægis, the mantle with the serpent fringes, in which she often, in the best statues, is represented as folding up her left hand, for better guard; and the Gorgon, on her shield, are both representative mainly of the chilling horror and sadness (turning men to stone, as it were), of the outmost and superficial spheres of knowledge—that knowledge which separates, in bitterness, hardness, and sorrow, the heart of the full-grown man from the heart of the child. For out of imperfect knowledge spring terror, dissension, danger, and disdain; but from perfect knowledge, given by the full-revealed Athena, strength and peace, in sign of which she is crowned with the olive spray, and bears the resistless spear.[213]
The first Greek idea of deity was that expressed in the word, of which we keep the remnant in our words "Di-urnal" and "Di-vine"—the god of Day, Jupiter the revealer. Athena is his daughter, but especially daughter of the Intellect, springing armed from the head. We are only with the help of recent investigation beginning to penetrate the depth of meaning couched under the Athenaic symbols: but I may note rapidly, that her ægis, the mantle with the serpent fringes, in which she often, in the best statues, is represented as folding up her left hand, for better guard; and the Gorgon, on her shield, are both representative mainly of the chilling horror and sadness (turning men to stone, as it were), of the outmost and superficial spheres of knowledge—that knowledge which separates, in bitterness, hardness, and sorrow, the heart of the full-grown man from the heart of the child. For out of imperfect knowledge spring terror, dissension, danger, and disdain; but from perfect knowledge, given by the full-revealed Athena, strength and peace, in sign of which she is crowned with the olive spray, and bears the resistless spear.[213]
This, then, was the Greek conception of purest Deity; and every habit of life, and every form of his art developed themselves from the seeking this bright, serene, resistless wisdom; and setting himself, as a man, to do things evermore rightly and strongly;[214] not with any ardent affection or ultimate hope; but with a resolute and continent energy of will, as knowing that for failure there was no consolation, and for sin there was no remission. And the Greek architecture rose unerring, bright, clearly defined, and self-contained.
This, then, was the Greek conception of purest Deity; and every habit of life, and every form of his art developed themselves from the seeking this bright, serene, resistless wisdom; and setting himself, as a man, to do things evermore rightly and strongly;[214] not with any ardent affection or ultimate hope; but with a resolute and continent energy of will, as knowing that for failure there was no consolation, and for sin there was no remission. And the Greek architecture rose unerring, bright, clearly defined, and self-contained.
Next followed in Europe the great Christian faith, which was essentially the religion of Comfort. Its great doctrine is the remission of sins; for which cause, it happens, too often, in certain phases of Christianity, that sin and sickness themselves are partly glorified, as if, the more you had to be healed of, the more divine was the healing. The practical result of this doctrine, in art, is a continual contemplation of sin and disease, and of imaginary states of purification from them; thus we have an architecture conceived in a mingled sentiment of melancholy and aspiration, partly severe, partly luxuriant, which will bend itself to every one of our needs, and every one of our fancies, and be strong or weak with us, as we are strong or weak ourselves. It is, of all architecture, the basest, when base people build it—of all, the noblest, when built by the noble.
Next came the great Christian faith in Europe, which was fundamentally a religion of comfort. Its main teaching is about the forgiveness of sins. Because of this, in certain aspects of Christianity, sin and sickness are often somewhat glorified, as if the more you need healing, the more divine that healing becomes. The practical outcome of this belief in art is a constant focus on sin and illness, as well as imagined states of purification from them. This leads to an architecture that reflects a blend of sadness and hope, at times strict and at times lush, which adapts to all our needs and whims, being strong or weak alongside our own strengths and weaknesses. It is, of all architecture, the least admirable when built by unworthy people—yet the most admirable when built by the worthy.
And now note that both these religions—Greek and Mediæval—perished by falsehood in their own main purpose. The Greek religion of Wisdom perished in a false philosophy—"Oppositions of science, falsely so called." The Mediæval religion of Consolation perished in false comfort; in remission of sins given lyingly. It was the selling of absolution that ended the Mediæval faith; and I can tell you more, it is the selling of absolution which, to the end of time, will mark false Christianity. Pure Christianity gives her remission of sins only by ending them; but false Christianity gets her remission of sins by compounding for them. And there are many ways of compounding for them. We English have beautiful little quiet ways of buying absolution, whether in low Church or high, far more cunning than any of Tetzel's trading.[215]
And now note that both these religions—Greek and Mediæval—perished by falsehood in their own main purpose. The Greek religion of Wisdom perished in a false philosophy—"Oppositions of science, falsely so called." The Mediæval religion of Consolation perished in false comfort; in remission of sins given lyingly. It was the selling of absolution that ended the Mediæval faith; and I can tell you more, it is the selling of absolution which, to the end of time, will mark false Christianity. Pure Christianity gives her remission of sins only by ending them; but false Christianity gets her remission of sins by compounding for them. And there are many ways of compounding for them. We English have beautiful little quiet ways of buying absolution, whether in low Church or high, far more cunning than any of Tetzel's trading.[215]
Then, thirdly, there followed the religion of Pleasure, in which all Europe gave itself to luxury, ending in death. First, bals masqués in every saloon, and then guillotines in every square. And all these three worships issue in vast temple building. Your Greek worshipped Wisdom, and built you the Parthenon—the Virgin's temple. The Mediæval worshipped Consolation, and built you Virgin temples also—but to our Lady of Salvation. Then the Revivalist worshipped beauty, of a sort, and built you Versailles and the Vatican. Now, lastly, will you tell me what we worship, and what we build?
Then, thirdly, there came the religion of Pleasure, where all of Europe indulged in luxury, leading to ruin. First, there were masquerade balls in every social hall, and then guillotines in every public square. All three of these forms of worship resulted in grand temple construction. The Greeks worshipped Wisdom and built the Parthenon—the temple of the Virgin. Medieval people revered Consolation and built Virgin temples too—but dedicated to Our Lady of Salvation. Then the Revivalists admired beauty, of a kind, and constructed Versailles and the Vatican. Now, lastly, can you tell me what we worship and what we are building?
You know we are speaking always of the real, active, continual, national worship; that by which men act, while they live; not that which they talk of, when they die. Now, we have, indeed, a nominal religion, to which we pay tithes of property and sevenths of time; but we have also a practical and earnest religion, to which we devote nine-tenths of our property and sixth-sevenths of our time. And we dispute a great deal about the nominal religion: but we are all unanimous about this practical one; of which I think you will admit that the ruling goddess may be best generally described as the "Goddess of Getting-on," or "Britannia of the Market." The Athenians had an "Athena Agoraia," or Athena of the Market; but she was a subordinate type of their goddess, while our Britannia Agoraia is the principal type of ours. And all your great architectural works are, of course, built to her. It is long since you built a great cathedral; and how you would laugh at me if I proposed building a cathedral on the top of one of these hills of yours, taking it for an Acropolis! But your railroad mounds, vaster than the walls of Babylon; your railroad stations, vaster than the temple of Ephesus, and innumerable; your chimneys, how much more mighty and costly than cathedral spires! your harbour-piers; your warehouses; your exchanges!—all these are built to your great Goddess of "Getting-on"; and she has formed, and will continue to form your architecture, as long as you worship her; and it is quite vain to ask me to tell you how to build to her; you know far better than I.
You know we are always talking about real, active, ongoing national worship; the kind that drives people in their everyday lives, not just what they think about when they’re on their deathbed. We do have a nominal religion that we contribute money and time to, but we also engage in a practical and serious religion where we dedicate most of our resources. We argue a lot about the nominal religion, but we all agree on the practical one, which I think can best be described as the "Goddess of Getting Ahead" or "Britannia of the Market." The Athenians had an "Athena Agoraia," or Athena of the Market, but she was a minor aspect of their goddess, while our Britannia Agoraia is the main focus for us. And of course, all your significant architectural projects are dedicated to her. It’s been ages since you built a grand cathedral; you’d probably laugh if I suggested putting one on top of one of your hills, thinking it was an Acropolis! But your railroad hills, bigger than the walls of Babylon; your train stations, larger than the Temple of Ephesus, and countless; your chimneys, so much mightier and more expensive than cathedral spires; your harbor piers; your warehouses; your stock exchanges!—all of these are built for your great Goddess of "Getting Ahead"; and she has shaped, and will keep shaping, your architecture as long as you worship her; and asking me how to build for her is pointless—you know far better than I.
There might, indeed, on some theories, be a conceivably good architecture for Exchanges—that is to say, if there were any heroism in the fact or deed of exchange which might be typically carved on the outside of your building. For, you know, all beautiful architecture must be adorned with sculpture or painting; and for sculpture or painting, you must have a subject. And hitherto it has been a received opinion among the nations of the world that the only right subjects for either, were heroisms of some sort. Even on his pots and his flagons, the Greek put a Hercules slaying lions, or an Apollo slaying serpents, or Bacchus slaying melancholy giants, and earthborn despondencies. On his temples, the Greek put contests of great warriors in founding states, or of gods with evil spirits. On his houses and temples alike, the Christian put carvings of angels conquering devils; or of hero-martyrs exchanging this world for another: subject inappropriate, I think, to our manner of exchange here. And the Master of Christians not only left His followers without any orders as to the sculpture of affairs of exchange on the outside of buildings, but gave some strong evidence of His dislike of affairs of exchange within them.[216] And yet there might surely be a heroism in such affairs; and all commerce become a kind of selling of doves, not impious. The wonder has always been great to me, that heroism has never been supposed to be in any wise consistent with the practice of supplying people with food, or clothes; but rather with that of quartering one's self upon them for food, and stripping them of their clothes. Spoiling of armour is an heroic deed in all ages; but the selling of clothes, old, or new, has never taken any colour of magnanimity. Yet one does not see why feeding the hungry and clothing the naked should ever become base businesses, even when engaged in on a large scale. If one could contrive to attach the notion of conquest to them anyhow! so that, supposing there were anywhere an obstinate race, who refused to be comforted, one might take some pride in giving them compulsory comfort! and, as it were, "occupying a country" with one's gifts, instead of one's armies? If one could only consider it as much a victory to get a barren field sown, as to get an eared field stripped; and contend who should build villages, instead of who should "carry" them! Are not all forms of heroism conceivable in doing these serviceable deeds? You doubt who is strongest? It might be ascertained by push of spade, as well as push of sword. Who is wisest? There are witty things to be thought of in planning other business than campaigns. Who is bravest? There are always the elements to fight with, stronger than men; and nearly as merciless.
There might, indeed, on some theories, be a conceivably good architecture for Exchanges—that is to say, if there were any heroism in the fact or deed of exchange which might be typically carved on the outside of your building. For, you know, all beautiful architecture must be adorned with sculpture or painting; and for sculpture or painting, you must have a subject. And hitherto it has been a received opinion among the nations of the world that the only right subjects for either, were heroisms of some sort. Even on his pots and his flagons, the Greek put a Hercules slaying lions, or an Apollo slaying serpents, or Bacchus slaying melancholy giants, and earthborn despondencies. On his temples, the Greek put contests of great warriors in founding states, or of gods with evil spirits. On his houses and temples alike, the Christian put carvings of angels conquering devils; or of hero-martyrs exchanging this world for another: subject inappropriate, I think, to our manner of exchange here. And the Master of Christians not only left His followers without any orders as to the sculpture of affairs of exchange on the outside of buildings, but gave some strong evidence of His dislike of affairs of exchange within them.[216] And yet there might surely be a heroism in such affairs; and all commerce become a kind of selling of doves, not impious. The wonder has always been great to me, that heroism has never been supposed to be in any wise consistent with the practice of supplying people with food, or clothes; but rather with that of quartering one's self upon them for food, and stripping them of their clothes. Spoiling of armour is an heroic deed in all ages; but the selling of clothes, old, or new, has never taken any colour of magnanimity. Yet one does not see why feeding the hungry and clothing the naked should ever become base businesses, even when engaged in on a large scale. If one could contrive to attach the notion of conquest to them anyhow! so that, supposing there were anywhere an obstinate race, who refused to be comforted, one might take some pride in giving them compulsory comfort! and, as it were, "occupying a country" with one's gifts, instead of one's armies? If one could only consider it as much a victory to get a barren field sown, as to get an eared field stripped; and contend who should build villages, instead of who should "carry" them! Are not all forms of heroism conceivable in doing these serviceable deeds? You doubt who is strongest? It might be ascertained by push of spade, as well as push of sword. Who is wisest? There are witty things to be thought of in planning other business than campaigns. Who is bravest? There are always the elements to fight with, stronger than men; and nearly as merciless.
The only absolutely and unapproachably heroic element in the soldier's work seems to be—that he is paid little for it—and regularly: while you traffickers, and exchangers, and others occupied in presumably benevolent business, like to be paid much for it—and by chance. I never can make out how it is that a knight-errant does not expect to be paid for his trouble, but a pedlar-errant always does;—that people are willing to take hard knocks for nothing, but never to sell ribands cheap; that they are ready to go on fervent crusades, to recover the tomb of a buried God, but never on any travels to fulfil the orders of a living one;—that they will go anywhere barefoot to preach their faith, but must be well bribed to practise it, and are perfectly ready to give the Gospel gratis, but never the loaves and fishes.
The only truly and undeniably heroic part of a soldier's job seems to be that he gets paid very little for it—and on a regular basis; while you merchants, traders, and others engaged in seemingly charitable work expect to be paid a lot for it—and by chance. I can never figure out why a knight-errant doesn't expect to be compensated for his efforts, but a traveling vendor always does; that people are willing to take hard hits for nothing, but won't sell ribbons cheaply; that they’re ready to embark on passionate crusades to reclaim the grave of a buried God, but never take journeys to fulfill the orders of a living one; that they’ll go anywhere barefoot to preach their beliefs but need a good bribe to practice them, and are completely willing to give away the Gospel for free, but never the bread and fish.
If you chose to take the matter up on any such soldierly principle; to do your commerce, and your feeding of nations, for fixed salaries; and to be as particular about giving people the best food, and the best cloth, as soldiers are about giving them the best gunpowder, I could carve something for you on your exchange worth looking at. But I can only at present suggest decorating its frieze with pendant purses; and making its pillars broad at the base, for the sticking of bills. And in the innermost chambers of it there might be a statue of Britannia of the Market, who may have, perhaps advisably, a partridge for her crest, typical at once of her courage in fighting for noble ideas, and of her interest in game; and round its neck, the inscription in golden letters, "Perdix fovit quæ non peperit."[217] Then, for her spear, she might have a weaver's beam; and on her shield, instead of St. George's Cross, the Milanese boar, semi-fleeced, with the town of Gennesaret proper, in the field; and the legend, "In the best market,"[218] and her corslet, of leather, folded over her heart in the shape of a purse, with thirty slits in it, for a piece of money to go in at, on each day of the month. And I doubt not but that people would come to see your exchange, and its goddess, with applause.
If you chose to take the matter up on any such soldierly principle; to do your commerce, and your feeding of nations, for fixed salaries; and to be as particular about giving people the best food, and the best cloth, as soldiers are about giving them the best gunpowder, I could carve something for you on your exchange worth looking at. But I can only at present suggest decorating its frieze with pendant purses; and making its pillars broad at the base, for the sticking of bills. And in the innermost chambers of it there might be a statue of Britannia of the Market, who may have, perhaps advisably, a partridge for her crest, typical at once of her courage in fighting for noble ideas, and of her interest in game; and round its neck, the inscription in golden letters, "Perdix fovit quæ non peperit."[217] Then, for her spear, she might have a weaver's beam; and on her shield, instead of St. George's Cross, the Milanese boar, semi-fleeced, with the town of Gennesaret proper, in the field; and the legend, "In the best market,"[218] and her corslet, of leather, folded over her heart in the shape of a purse, with thirty slits in it, for a piece of money to go in at, on each day of the month. And I doubt not but that people would come to see your exchange, and its goddess, with applause.
Nevertheless, I want to point out to you certain strange characters in this goddess of yours. She differs from the great Greek and Mediæval deities essentially in two things—first, as to the continuance of her presumed power; secondly, as to the extent of it.
Nevertheless, I want to highlight some unusual traits in this goddess of yours. She differs from the major Greek and Medieval deities in two main ways—first, regarding the lasting nature of her supposed power; second, in terms of the scope of that power.
1st, as to the Continuance.
First, regarding the Continuance.
The Greek Goddess of Wisdom gave continual increase of wisdom, as the Christian Spirit of Comfort (or Comforter) continual increase of comfort. There was no question, with these, of any limit or cessation of function. But with your Agora Goddess, that is just the most important question. Getting on—but where to? Gathering together—but how much? Do you mean to gather always—never to spend? If so, I wish you joy of your goddess, for I am just as well off as you, without the trouble of worshipping her at all. But if you do not spend, somebody else will—somebody else must. And it is because of this (among many other such errors) that I have fearlessly declared your so-called science of Political Economy to be no science; because, namely, it has omitted the study of exactly the most important branch of the business—the study of spending. For spend you must, and as much as you make, ultimately. You gather corn:—will you bury England under a heap of grain; or will you, when you have gathered, finally eat? You gather gold:—will you make your house-roofs of it, or pave your streets with it? That is still one way of spending it. But if you keep it, that you may get more, I'll give you more; I'll give you all the gold you want—all you can imagine—if you can tell me what you'll do with it. You shall have thousands of gold-pieces;—thousands of thousands—millions—mountains, of gold: where will you keep them? Will you put an Olympus of silver upon a golden Pelion—make Ossa like a wart?[219] Do you think the rain and dew would then come down to you, in the streams from such mountains, more blessedly than they will down the mountains which God has made for you, of moss and whinstone? But it is not gold that you want to gather! What is it? greenbacks? No; not those neither. What is it then—is it ciphers after a capital I? Cannot you practise writing ciphers, and write as many as you want? Write ciphers for an hour every morning, in a big book, and say every evening, I am worth all those noughts more than I was yesterday. Won't that do? Well, what in the name of Plutus is it you want? Not gold, not greenbacks, not ciphers after a capital I? You will have to answer, after all, "No; we want, somehow or other, money's worth." Well, what is that? Let your Goddess of Getting-on discover it, and let her learn to stay therein.
The Greek Goddess of Wisdom gave continual increase of wisdom, as the Christian Spirit of Comfort (or Comforter) continual increase of comfort. There was no question, with these, of any limit or cessation of function. But with your Agora Goddess, that is just the most important question. Getting on—but where to? Gathering together—but how much? Do you mean to gather always—never to spend? If so, I wish you joy of your goddess, for I am just as well off as you, without the trouble of worshipping her at all. But if you do not spend, somebody else will—somebody else must. And it is because of this (among many other such errors) that I have fearlessly declared your so-called science of Political Economy to be no science; because, namely, it has omitted the study of exactly the most important branch of the business—the study of spending. For spend you must, and as much as you make, ultimately. You gather corn:—will you bury England under a heap of grain; or will you, when you have gathered, finally eat? You gather gold:—will you make your house-roofs of it, or pave your streets with it? That is still one way of spending it. But if you keep it, that you may get more, I'll give you more; I'll give you all the gold you want—all you can imagine—if you can tell me what you'll do with it. You shall have thousands of gold-pieces;—thousands of thousands—millions—mountains, of gold: where will you keep them? Will you put an Olympus of silver upon a golden Pelion—make Ossa like a wart?[219] Do you think the rain and dew would then come down to you, in the streams from such mountains, more blessedly than they will down the mountains which God has made for you, of moss and whinstone? But it is not gold that you want to gather! What is it? greenbacks? No; not those neither. What is it then—is it ciphers after a capital I? Cannot you practise writing ciphers, and write as many as you want? Write ciphers for an hour every morning, in a big book, and say every evening, I am worth all those noughts more than I was yesterday. Won't that do? Well, what in the name of Plutus is it you want? Not gold, not greenbacks, not ciphers after a capital I? You will have to answer, after all, "No; we want, somehow or other, money's worth." Well, what is that? Let your Goddess of Getting-on discover it, and let her learn to stay therein.
2d. But there is yet another question to be asked respecting this Goddess of Getting-on. The first was of the continuance of her power; the second is of its extent.
2d. But there's one more question to ask about this Goddess of Getting-on. The first was about how long her power lasts; the second is about how far that power reaches.
Pallas and the Madonna were supposed to be all the world's Pallas, and all the world's Madonna. They could teach all men, and they could comfort all men. But, look strictly into the nature of the power of your Goddess of Getting-on; and you will find she is the Goddess—not of everybody's getting on—but only of somebody's getting on. This is a vital, or rather deathful, distinction. Examine it in your own ideal of the state of national life which this Goddess is to evoke and maintain. I asked you what it was, when I was last here;—you have never told me.[220] Now, shall I try to tell you?
Pallas and the Madonna were supposed to be all the world's Pallas, and all the world's Madonna. They could teach all men, and they could comfort all men. But, look strictly into the nature of the power of your Goddess of Getting-on; and you will find she is the Goddess—not of everybody's getting on—but only of somebody's getting on. This is a vital, or rather deathful, distinction. Examine it in your own ideal of the state of national life which this Goddess is to evoke and maintain. I asked you what it was, when I was last here;—you have never told me.[220] Now, shall I try to tell you?
Your ideal of human life then is, I think, that it should be passed in a pleasant undulating world, with iron and coal everywhere underneath it. On each pleasant bank of this world is to be a beautiful mansion, with two wings; and stables, and coach-houses; a moderately-sized park; a large garden and hot-houses; and pleasant carriage drives through the shrubberies In this mansion are to live the favoured votaries of the Goddess; the English gentleman, with his gracious wife, and his beautiful family; always able to have the boudoir and the jewels for the wife, and the beautiful ball dresses for the daughters, and hunters for the sons, and a shooting in the Highlands for himself. At the bottom of the bank, is to be the mill; not less than a quarter of a mile long, with a steam engine at each end, and two in the middle, and a chimney three hundred feet high. In this mill are to be in constant employment from eight hundred to a thousand workers, who never drink, never strike, always go to church on Sunday, and always express themselves in respectful language.
Your idea of an ideal life seems to be one spent in a pleasant, rolling landscape, with iron and coal found everywhere beneath it. Each nice area of this world should have a beautiful mansion with two wings, stables, and coach houses; a moderately sized park, a large garden with greenhouses, and enjoyable carriage drives winding through the shrubbery. The mansion would be home to the privileged followers of the Goddess: the English gentleman, his gracious wife, and their lovely family. They would always have a stylish boudoir and jewelry for the wife, elegant ball gowns for the daughters, hunters for the sons, and a shooting retreat in the Highlands for himself. At the base of the bank would be a mill, no less than a quarter of a mile long, with a steam engine at each end and two in the middle, plus a chimney rising three hundred feet. This mill would provide constant work for eight hundred to a thousand employees, who never drink, never go on strike, always attend church on Sundays, and always speak with respect.
Is not that, broadly, and in the main features, the kind of thing you propose to yourselves? It is very pretty indeed seen from above; not at all so pretty, seen from below. For, observe, while to one family this deity is indeed the Goddess of Getting-on, to a thousand families she is the Goddess of not Getting-on. "Nay," you say, "they have all their chance." Yes, so has every one in a lottery, but there must always be the same number of blanks. "Ah! but in a lottery it is not skill and intelligence which take the lead, but blind chance." What then! do you think the old practice, that "they should take who have the power, and they should keep who can,"[221] is less iniquitous, when the power has become power of brains instead of fist? and that, though we may not take advantage of a child's or a woman's weakness, we may of a man's foolishness? "Nay, but finally, work must be done, and some one must be at the top, some one at the bottom." Granted, my friends. Work must always be, and captains of work must always be; and if you in the least remember the tone of any of my writings, you must know that they are thought unfit for this age, because they are always insisting on need of government, and speaking with scorn of liberty. But I beg you to observe that there is a wide difference between being captains or governors of work, and taking the profits of it. It does not follow, because you are general of an army, that you are to take all the treasure, or land, it wins; (if it fight for treasure or land;) neither, because you are king of a nation, that you are to consume all the profits of the nation's work. Real kings, on the contrary, are known invariably by their doing quite the reverse of this,—by their taking the least possible quantity of the nation's work for themselves. There is no test of real kinghood so infallible as that. Does the crowned creature live simply, bravely, unostentatiously? probably he is a King. Does he cover his body with jewels, and his table with delicates? in all probability he is not a King. It is possible he may be, as Solomon was; but that is when the nation shares his splendour with him. Solomon made gold, not only to be in his own palace as stones, but to be in Jerusalem as stones.[222] But, even so, for the most part, these splendid kinghoods expire in ruin, and only the true king-hoods live, which are of royal labourers governing loyal labourers; who, both leading rough lives, establish the true dynasties. Conclusively you will find that because you are king of a nation, it does not follow that you are to gather for yourself all the wealth of that nation; neither, because you are king of a small part of the nation, and lord over the means of its maintenance—over field, or mill, or mine,—are you to take all the produce of that piece of the foundation of national existence for yourself.
Is not that, broadly, and in the main features, the kind of thing you propose to yourselves? It is very pretty indeed seen from above; not at all so pretty, seen from below. For, observe, while to one family this deity is indeed the Goddess of Getting-on, to a thousand families she is the Goddess of not Getting-on. "Nay," you say, "they have all their chance." Yes, so has every one in a lottery, but there must always be the same number of blanks. "Ah! but in a lottery it is not skill and intelligence which take the lead, but blind chance." What then! do you think the old practice, that "they should take who have the power, and they should keep who can,"[221] is less iniquitous, when the power has become power of brains instead of fist? and that, though we may not take advantage of a child's or a woman's weakness, we may of a man's foolishness? "Nay, but finally, work must be done, and some one must be at the top, some one at the bottom." Granted, my friends. Work must always be, and captains of work must always be; and if you in the least remember the tone of any of my writings, you must know that they are thought unfit for this age, because they are always insisting on need of government, and speaking with scorn of liberty. But I beg you to observe that there is a wide difference between being captains or governors of work, and taking the profits of it. It does not follow, because you are general of an army, that you are to take all the treasure, or land, it wins; (if it fight for treasure or land;) neither, because you are king of a nation, that you are to consume all the profits of the nation's work. Real kings, on the contrary, are known invariably by their doing quite the reverse of this,—by their taking the least possible quantity of the nation's work for themselves. There is no test of real kinghood so infallible as that. Does the crowned creature live simply, bravely, unostentatiously? probably he is a King. Does he cover his body with jewels, and his table with delicates? in all probability he is not a King. It is possible he may be, as Solomon was; but that is when the nation shares his splendour with him. Solomon made gold, not only to be in his own palace as stones, but to be in Jerusalem as stones.[222] But, even so, for the most part, these splendid kinghoods expire in ruin, and only the true king-hoods live, which are of royal labourers governing loyal labourers; who, both leading rough lives, establish the true dynasties. Conclusively you will find that because you are king of a nation, it does not follow that you are to gather for yourself all the wealth of that nation; neither, because you are king of a small part of the nation, and lord over the means of its maintenance—over field, or mill, or mine,—are you to take all the produce of that piece of the foundation of national existence for yourself.
You will tell me I need not preach against these things, for I cannot mend them. No, good friends, I cannot; but you can, and you will; or something else can and will. Even good things have no abiding power—and shall these evil things persist in victorious evil? All history shows, on the contrary, that to be the exact thing they never can do. Change must come; but it is ours to determine whether change of growth, or change of death. Shall the Parthenon be in ruins on its rock, and Bolton priory[223] in its meadow, but these mills of yours be the consummation of the buildings of the earth, and their wheels be as the wheels of eternity? Think you that "men may come, and men may go," but—mills—go on for ever?[224] Not so; out of these, better or worse shall come; and it is for you to choose which.
You will tell me I need not preach against these things, for I cannot mend them. No, good friends, I cannot; but you can, and you will; or something else can and will. Even good things have no abiding power—and shall these evil things persist in victorious evil? All history shows, on the contrary, that to be the exact thing they never can do. Change must come; but it is ours to determine whether change of growth, or change of death. Shall the Parthenon be in ruins on its rock, and Bolton priory[223] in its meadow, but these mills of yours be the consummation of the buildings of the earth, and their wheels be as the wheels of eternity? Think you that "men may come, and men may go," but—mills—go on for ever?[224] Not so; out of these, better or worse shall come; and it is for you to choose which.
I know that none of this wrong is done with deliberate purpose. I know, on the contrary, that you wish your workmen well; that you do much for them, and that you desire to do more for them, if you saw your way to such benevolence safely. I know that even all this wrong and misery are brought about by a warped sense of duty, each of you striving to do his best; but, unhappily, not knowing for whom this best should be done. And all our hearts have been betrayed by the plausible impiety of the modern economist, telling us that, "To do the best for ourselves, is finally to do the best for others." Friends, our great Master said not so; and most absolutely we shall find this world is not made so. Indeed, to do the best for others, is finally to do the best for ourselves; but it will not do to have our eyes fixed on that issue. The Pagans had got beyond that. Hear what a Pagan says of this matter; hear what were, perhaps, the last written words of Plato,—if not the last actually written (for this we cannot know), yet assuredly in fact and power his parting words—in which, endeavouring to give full crowning and harmonious close to all his thoughts, and to speak the sum of them by the imagined sentence of the Great Spirit, his strength and his heart fail him, and the words cease, broken off for ever. They are at the close of the dialogue called Critias, in which he describes, partly from real tradition, partly in ideal dream, the early state of Athens; and the genesis, and order, and religion, of the fabled isle of Atlantis; in which genesis he conceives the same first perfection and final degeneracy of man, which in our own Scriptural tradition is expressed by saying that the Sons of God inter-married with the daughters of men,[225] for he supposes the earliest race to have been indeed the children of God; and to have corrupted themselves, until "their spot was not the spot of his children."[226] And this, he says, was the end; that indeed "through many generations, so long as the God's nature in them yet was full, they were submissive to the sacred laws, and carried themselves lovingly to all that had kindred with them in divineness; for their uttermost spirit was faithful and true, and in every wise great; so that, in all meekness of wisdom, they dealt with each other, and took all the chances of life; and despising all things except virtue, they cared little what happened day by day, and bore lightly the burden of gold and of possessions; for they saw that, if only their common love and virtue increased, all these things would be increased together with them; but to set their esteem and ardent pursuit upon material possession would be to lose that first, and their virtue and affection together with it. And by such reasoning, and what of the divine nature remained in them, they gained all this greatness of which we have already told; but when the God's part of them faded and became extinct, being mixed again and again, and effaced by the prevalent mortality; and the human nature at last exceeded, they then became unable to endure the courses of fortune; and fell into shapelessness of life, and baseness in the sight of him who could see, having lost everything that was fairest of their honour; while to the blind hearts which could not discern the true life, tending to happiness, it seemed that they were then chiefly noble and happy, being filled with an iniquity of inordinate possession and power. Whereupon, the God of Gods, whose Kinghood is in laws, beholding a once just nation thus cast into misery, and desiring to lay such punishment upon them as might make them repent into restraining, gathered together all the gods into his dwelling-place, which from heaven's centre overlooks whatever has part in creation; and having assembled them, he said "—
I know that none of this wrong is done with deliberate purpose. I know, on the contrary, that you wish your workmen well; that you do much for them, and that you desire to do more for them, if you saw your way to such benevolence safely. I know that even all this wrong and misery are brought about by a warped sense of duty, each of you striving to do his best; but, unhappily, not knowing for whom this best should be done. And all our hearts have been betrayed by the plausible impiety of the modern economist, telling us that, "To do the best for ourselves, is finally to do the best for others." Friends, our great Master said not so; and most absolutely we shall find this world is not made so. Indeed, to do the best for others, is finally to do the best for ourselves; but it will not do to have our eyes fixed on that issue. The Pagans had got beyond that. Hear what a Pagan says of this matter; hear what were, perhaps, the last written words of Plato,—if not the last actually written (for this we cannot know), yet assuredly in fact and power his parting words—in which, endeavouring to give full crowning and harmonious close to all his thoughts, and to speak the sum of them by the imagined sentence of the Great Spirit, his strength and his heart fail him, and the words cease, broken off for ever. They are at the close of the dialogue called Critias, in which he describes, partly from real tradition, partly in ideal dream, the early state of Athens; and the genesis, and order, and religion, of the fabled isle of Atlantis; in which genesis he conceives the same first perfection and final degeneracy of man, which in our own Scriptural tradition is expressed by saying that the Sons of God inter-married with the daughters of men,[225] for he supposes the earliest race to have been indeed the children of God; and to have corrupted themselves, until "their spot was not the spot of his children."[226] And this, he says, was the end; that indeed "through many generations, so long as the God's nature in them yet was full, they were submissive to the sacred laws, and carried themselves lovingly to all that had kindred with them in divineness; for their uttermost spirit was faithful and true, and in every wise great; so that, in all meekness of wisdom, they dealt with each other, and took all the chances of life; and despising all things except virtue, they cared little what happened day by day, and bore lightly the burden of gold and of possessions; for they saw that, if only their common love and virtue increased, all these things would be increased together with them; but to set their esteem and ardent pursuit upon material possession would be to lose that first, and their virtue and affection together with it. And by such reasoning, and what of the divine nature remained in them, they gained all this greatness of which we have already told; but when the God's part of them faded and became extinct, being mixed again and again, and effaced by the prevalent mortality; and the human nature at last exceeded, they then became unable to endure the courses of fortune; and fell into shapelessness of life, and baseness in the sight of him who could see, having lost everything that was fairest of their honour; while to the blind hearts which could not discern the true life, tending to happiness, it seemed that they were then chiefly noble and happy, being filled with an iniquity of inordinate possession and power. Whereupon, the God of Gods, whose Kinghood is in laws, beholding a once just nation thus cast into misery, and desiring to lay such punishment upon them as might make them repent into restraining, gathered together all the gods into his dwelling-place, which from heaven's centre overlooks whatever has part in creation; and having assembled them, he said "—
The rest is silence. Last words of the chief wisdom of the heathen, spoken of this idol of riches; this idol of yours; this golden image, high by measureless cubits, set up where your green fields of England are furnace-burnt into the likeness of the plain of Dura:[227] this idol, forbidden to us, first of all idols, by our own Master and faith; forbidden to us also by every human lip that has ever, in any age or people, been accounted of as able to speak according to the purposes of God. Continue to make that forbidden deity your principal one, and soon no more art, no more science, no more pleasure will be possible. Catastrophe will come; or, worse than catastrophe, slow mouldering and withering into Hades. But if you can fix some conception of a true human state of life to be striven for—life, good for all men, as for yourselves; if you can determine some honest and simple order of existence; following those trodden ways of wisdom, which are pleasantness,[228] and seeking her quiet and withdrawn paths, which are peace;—then, and so sanctifying wealth into "commonwealth," all your art, your literature, your daily labours, your domestic affection, and citizen's duty, will join and increase into one magnificent harmony. You will know then how to build, well enough; you will build with stone well, but with flesh better; temples not made with hands,[229] but riveted of hearts; and that kind of marble, crimson-veined, is indeed eternal.
The rest is silence. Last words of the chief wisdom of the heathen, spoken of this idol of riches; this idol of yours; this golden image, high by measureless cubits, set up where your green fields of England are furnace-burnt into the likeness of the plain of Dura:[227] this idol, forbidden to us, first of all idols, by our own Master and faith; forbidden to us also by every human lip that has ever, in any age or people, been accounted of as able to speak according to the purposes of God. Continue to make that forbidden deity your principal one, and soon no more art, no more science, no more pleasure will be possible. Catastrophe will come; or, worse than catastrophe, slow mouldering and withering into Hades. But if you can fix some conception of a true human state of life to be striven for—life, good for all men, as for yourselves; if you can determine some honest and simple order of existence; following those trodden ways of wisdom, which are pleasantness,[228] and seeking her quiet and withdrawn paths, which are peace;—then, and so sanctifying wealth into "commonwealth," all your art, your literature, your daily labours, your domestic affection, and citizen's duty, will join and increase into one magnificent harmony. You will know then how to build, well enough; you will build with stone well, but with flesh better; temples not made with hands,[229] but riveted of hearts; and that kind of marble, crimson-veined, is indeed eternal.
This lecture, the full title of which is "The Mystery of Life and its Arts," was delivered in Dublin on May 13, 1868. It composed one of a series of afternoon lectures on various subjects, religion excepted, arranged by some of the foremost residents in Dublin. The latter half of the lecture is included in the present volume of selections. The first publication of the lecture was as an additional part to a revised edition of Sesame and Lilies in 1871. Ruskin took exceptional care in writing "The Mystery of Life": he once said in conversation, "I put into it all that I know," and in the preface to it when published he tells us that certain passages of it "contain the best expression I have yet been able to put in words of what, so far as is within my power, I mean henceforward both to do myself, and to plead with all over whom I have any influence to do according to their means." Sir Leslie Stephen says this "is, to my mind, the most perfect of his essays." In later editions of Sesame and Lilies this lecture was withdrawn. At the time the lecture was delivered its tone was characteristic of Ruskin's own thought and of the attitude he then took toward the public.
This lecture, titled "The Mystery of Life and its Arts," was given in Dublin on May 13, 1868. It was part of a series of afternoon lectures on various topics, excluding religion, organized by some of Dublin's leading residents. The latter half of the lecture is included in this collection of selections. The first publication of the lecture appeared as an additional section in a revised edition of Sesame and Lilies in 1871. Ruskin took great care in writing "The Mystery of Life": he once remarked in conversation, "I put into it all that I know," and in the preface, upon publication, he noted that certain passages "contain the best expression I have been able to put into words of what, as much as I can, I intend to do myself, and to encourage everyone I influence to do as they can." Sir Leslie Stephen stated that "this is, to my mind, the most perfect of his essays." In later editions of Sesame and Lilies, this lecture was removed. At the time the lecture was delivered, its tone reflected Ruskin's personal thoughts and the stance he took toward the public.
We have sat at the feet of the poets who sang of heaven, and they have told us their dreams. We have listened to the poets who sang of earth, and they have chanted to us dirges and words of despair. But there is one class of men more:—men, not capable of vision, nor sensitive to sorrow, but firm of purpose—practised in business; learned in all that can be, (by handling,) known. Men, whose hearts and hopes are wholly in this present world, from whom, therefore, we may surely learn, at least, how, at present, conveniently to live in it. What will they say to us, or show us by example? These kings—these councillors—these statesmen and builders of kingdoms—these capitalists and men of business, who weigh the earth, and the dust of it, in a balance.[230] They know the world, surely; and what is the mystery of life to us, is none to them. They can surely show us how to live, while we live, and to gather out of the present world what is best.
We have sat at the feet of the poets who sang of heaven, and they have told us their dreams. We have listened to the poets who sang of earth, and they have chanted to us dirges and words of despair. But there is one class of men more:—men, not capable of vision, nor sensitive to sorrow, but firm of purpose—practised in business; learned in all that can be, (by handling,) known. Men, whose hearts and hopes are wholly in this present world, from whom, therefore, we may surely learn, at least, how, at present, conveniently to live in it. What will they say to us, or show us by example? These kings—these councillors—these statesmen and builders of kingdoms—these capitalists and men of business, who weigh the earth, and the dust of it, in a balance.[230] They know the world, surely; and what is the mystery of life to us, is none to them. They can surely show us how to live, while we live, and to gather out of the present world what is best.
I think I can best tell you their answer, by telling you a dream I had once. For though I am no poet, I have dreams sometimes:—I dreamed I was at a child's May-day party, in which every means of entertainment had been provided for them, by a wise and kind host. It was in a stately house, with beautiful gardens attached to it; and the children had been set free in the rooms and gardens, with no care whatever but how to pass their afternoon rejoicingly. They did not, indeed, know much about what was to happen next day; and some of them, I thought, were a little frightened, because there was a chance of their being sent to a new school where there were examinations; but they kept the thoughts of that out of their heads as well as they could, and resolved to enjoy themselves. The house, I said, was in a beautiful garden, and in the garden were all kinds of flowers; sweet, grassy banks for rest; and smooth lawns for play; and pleasant streams and woods; and rocky places for climbing. And the children were happy for a little while, but presently they separated themselves into parties; and then each party declared it would have a piece of the garden for its own, and that none of the others should have anything to do with that piece. Next, they quarrelled violently which pieces they would have; and at last the boys took up the thing, as boys should do, "practically," and fought in the flower-beds till there was hardly a flower left standing; then they trampled down each other's bits of the garden out of spite; and the girls cried till they could cry no more; and so they all lay down at last breathless in the ruin, and waited for the time when they were to be taken home in the evening.[231]
I think I can best tell you their answer, by telling you a dream I had once. For though I am no poet, I have dreams sometimes:—I dreamed I was at a child's May-day party, in which every means of entertainment had been provided for them, by a wise and kind host. It was in a stately house, with beautiful gardens attached to it; and the children had been set free in the rooms and gardens, with no care whatever but how to pass their afternoon rejoicingly. They did not, indeed, know much about what was to happen next day; and some of them, I thought, were a little frightened, because there was a chance of their being sent to a new school where there were examinations; but they kept the thoughts of that out of their heads as well as they could, and resolved to enjoy themselves. The house, I said, was in a beautiful garden, and in the garden were all kinds of flowers; sweet, grassy banks for rest; and smooth lawns for play; and pleasant streams and woods; and rocky places for climbing. And the children were happy for a little while, but presently they separated themselves into parties; and then each party declared it would have a piece of the garden for its own, and that none of the others should have anything to do with that piece. Next, they quarrelled violently which pieces they would have; and at last the boys took up the thing, as boys should do, "practically," and fought in the flower-beds till there was hardly a flower left standing; then they trampled down each other's bits of the garden out of spite; and the girls cried till they could cry no more; and so they all lay down at last breathless in the ruin, and waited for the time when they were to be taken home in the evening.[231]
Meanwhile, the children in the house had been making themselves happy also in their manner. For them, there had been provided every kind of in-door pleasure: there was music for them to dance to; and the library was open, with all manner of amusing books; and there was a museum full of the most curious shells, and animals, and birds; and there was a workshop, with lathes and carpenters' tools, for the ingenious boys; and there were pretty fantastic dresses, for the girls to dress in; and there were microscopes, and kaleidoscopes; and whatever toys a child could fancy; and a table, in the dining-room, loaded with everything nice to eat.
Meanwhile, the kids in the house were keeping themselves entertained in their own way. They had access to all sorts of indoor fun: there was music for dancing, and the library was open with plenty of entertaining books; there was a museum filled with fascinating shells, animals, and birds; there was a workshop with lathes and carpentry tools for the crafty boys; there were beautiful, imaginative dresses for the girls to wear; there were microscopes and kaleidoscopes; and whatever toys a child could dream of; plus, a dining room table piled high with delicious food.
But, in the midst of all this, it struck two or three of the more "practical" children, that they would like some of the brass-headed nails that studded the chairs; and so they set to work to pull them out. Presently, the others, who were reading, or looking at shells, took a fancy to do the like; and, in a little while, all the children, nearly, were spraining their fingers, in pulling out brass-headed nails. With all that they could pull out, they were not satisfied; and then, everybody wanted some of somebody else's. And at last, the really practical and sensible ones declared, that nothing was of any real consequence, that afternoon, except to get plenty of brass-headed nails; and that the books, and the cakes, and the microscopes were of no use at all in themselves, but only, if they could be exchanged for nail-heads. And at last they began to fight for nail-heads, as the others fought for the bits of garden. Only here and there, a despised one shrank away into a corner, and tried to get a little quiet with a book, in the midst of the noise; but all the practical ones thought of nothing else but counting nail-heads all the afternoon—even though they knew they would not be allowed to carry so much as one brass knob away with them. But no—it was—"who has most nails? I have a hundred, and you have fifty; or, I have a thousand, and you have two. I must have as many as you before I leave the house, or I cannot possibly go home in peace." At last, they made so much noise that I awoke, and thought to myself, "What a false dream that is, of children!" The child is the father of the man;[232] and wiser. Children never do such foolish things. Only men do.
But, in the midst of all this, it struck two or three of the more "practical" children, that they would like some of the brass-headed nails that studded the chairs; and so they set to work to pull them out. Presently, the others, who were reading, or looking at shells, took a fancy to do the like; and, in a little while, all the children, nearly, were spraining their fingers, in pulling out brass-headed nails. With all that they could pull out, they were not satisfied; and then, everybody wanted some of somebody else's. And at last, the really practical and sensible ones declared, that nothing was of any real consequence, that afternoon, except to get plenty of brass-headed nails; and that the books, and the cakes, and the microscopes were of no use at all in themselves, but only, if they could be exchanged for nail-heads. And at last they began to fight for nail-heads, as the others fought for the bits of garden. Only here and there, a despised one shrank away into a corner, and tried to get a little quiet with a book, in the midst of the noise; but all the practical ones thought of nothing else but counting nail-heads all the afternoon—even though they knew they would not be allowed to carry so much as one brass knob away with them. But no—it was—"who has most nails? I have a hundred, and you have fifty; or, I have a thousand, and you have two. I must have as many as you before I leave the house, or I cannot possibly go home in peace." At last, they made so much noise that I awoke, and thought to myself, "What a false dream that is, of children!" The child is the father of the man;[232] and wiser. Children never do such foolish things. Only men do.
But there is yet one last class of persons to be interrogated. The wise religious men we have asked in vain; the wise contemplative men, in vain; the wise worldly men, in vain. But there is another group yet. In the midst of this vanity of empty religion—of tragic contemplation—of wrathful and wretched ambition, and dispute for dust, there is yet one great group of persons, by whom all these disputers live—the persons who have determined, or have had it by a beneficent Providence determined for them, that they will do something useful; that whatever may be prepared for them hereafter, or happen to them here, they will, at least, deserve the food that God gives them by winning it honourably: and that, however fallen from the purity, or far from the peace, of Eden, they will carry out the duty of human dominion, though they have lost its felicity; and dress and keep the wilderness,[233] though they no more can dress or keep the garden.
But there is yet one last class of persons to be interrogated. The wise religious men we have asked in vain; the wise contemplative men, in vain; the wise worldly men, in vain. But there is another group yet. In the midst of this vanity of empty religion—of tragic contemplation—of wrathful and wretched ambition, and dispute for dust, there is yet one great group of persons, by whom all these disputers live—the persons who have determined, or have had it by a beneficent Providence determined for them, that they will do something useful; that whatever may be prepared for them hereafter, or happen to them here, they will, at least, deserve the food that God gives them by winning it honourably: and that, however fallen from the purity, or far from the peace, of Eden, they will carry out the duty of human dominion, though they have lost its felicity; and dress and keep the wilderness,[233] though they no more can dress or keep the garden.
These,—hewers of wood, and drawers of water,[234]—these, bent under burdens, or torn of scourges—these, that dig and weave—that plant and build; workers in wood, and in marble, and in iron—by whom all food, clothing, habitation, furniture, and means of delight are produced, for themselves, and for all men beside; men, whose deeds are good, though their words may be few; men, whose lives are serviceable, be they never so short, and worthy of honour, be they never so humble;—from these, surely, at least, we may receive some clear message of teaching; and pierce, for an instant, into the mystery of life, and of its arts.
These,—hewers of wood, and drawers of water,[234]—these, bent under burdens, or torn of scourges—these, that dig and weave—that plant and build; workers in wood, and in marble, and in iron—by whom all food, clothing, habitation, furniture, and means of delight are produced, for themselves, and for all men beside; men, whose deeds are good, though their words may be few; men, whose lives are serviceable, be they never so short, and worthy of honour, be they never so humble;—from these, surely, at least, we may receive some clear message of teaching; and pierce, for an instant, into the mystery of life, and of its arts.
Yes; from these, at last, we do receive a lesson. But I grieve to say, or rather—for that is the deeper truth of the matter—I rejoice to say—this message of theirs can only be received by joining them—not by thinking about them.
Yes; from these, we finally get a lesson. But I'm sorry to say, or rather—because that's the deeper truth—I’m glad to say—this message of theirs can only be understood by joining them—not by just thinking about them.
You sent for me to talk to you of art; and I have obeyed you in coming. But the main thing I have to tell you is,—that art must not be talked about. The fact that there is talk about it at all, signifies that it is ill done, or cannot be done. No true painter ever speaks, or ever has spoken, much of his art. The greatest speak nothing. Even Reynolds is no exception, for he wrote of all that he could not himself do,[235] and was utterly silent respecting all that he himself did.
You sent for me to talk to you of art; and I have obeyed you in coming. But the main thing I have to tell you is,—that art must not be talked about. The fact that there is talk about it at all, signifies that it is ill done, or cannot be done. No true painter ever speaks, or ever has spoken, much of his art. The greatest speak nothing. Even Reynolds is no exception, for he wrote of all that he could not himself do,[235] and was utterly silent respecting all that he himself did.
The moment a man can really do his work he becomes speechless about it. All words become idle to him—all theories.
The moment a man can truly do his job, he becomes at a loss for words about it. All words feel pointless to him—all theories.
Does a bird need to theorize about building its nest, or boast of it when built? All good work is essentially done that way—without hesitation, without difficulty, without boasting; and in the doers of the best, there is an inner and involuntary power which approximates literally to the instinct of an animal—nay, I am certain that in the most perfect human artists, reason does not supersede instinct, but is added to an instinct as much more divine than that of the lower animals as the human body is more beautiful than theirs; that a great singer sings not with less instinct than the nightingale, but with more—only more various, applicable, and governable; that a great architect does not build with less instinct than the beaver or the bee, but with more—with an innate cunning of proportion that embraces all beauty, and a divine ingenuity of skill that improvises all construction. But be that as it may—be the instinct less or more than that of inferior animals—like or unlike theirs, still the human art is dependent on that first, and then upon an amount of practice, of science,—and of imagination disciplined by thought, which the true possessor of it knows to be incommunicable, and the true critic of it, inexplicable, except through long process of laborious years. That journey of life's conquest, in which hills over hills, and Alps on Alps arose, and sank,—do you think you can make another trace it painlessly, by talking? Why, you cannot even carry us up an Alp, by talking. You can guide us up it, step by step, no otherwise—even so, best silently. You girls, who have been among the hills, know how the bad guide chatters and gesticulates, and it is "put your foot here"; and "mind how you balance yourself there"; but the good guide walks on quietly, without a word, only with his eyes on you when need is, and his arm like an iron bar, if need be.
Does a bird need to think about building its nest or brag about it when it’s done? All good work is done that way—without hesitation, difficulty, or boasting; and among those who do the best work, there’s a natural and instinctive power that’s almost like that of an animal. In fact, I’m sure that in the most skilled human artists, reason doesn’t take the place of instinct but rather enhances it, just like the human body is more beautiful than that of lower animals. A great singer doesn’t sing with less instinct than a nightingale but with more—only it’s more varied, applicable, and controllable; a great architect doesn’t build with less instinct than a beaver or a bee, but with more—with an innate sense of proportion that captures all beauty, and divine skill that creates all structures. But regardless of whether the instinct is less or more than that of lesser animals—whether it’s similar or different—human art relies on that instinct first, and then on a mix of practice, science, and imagination shaped by thought, which the true possessor knows can’t be clearly communicated, and the true critic finds hard to explain, only through years of hard work. Do you think you can guide someone through the challenging journey of life effortlessly just by talking? You can’t even lead us up a mountain by just talking. You can only guide us step by step, and even then, it’s often best done in silence. You girls who have been in the hills know how a bad guide talks too much and gestures wildly, telling you, “Put your foot here” and “Watch your balance there”; but the good guide moves quietly, without saying a word, only looking at you when it’s necessary, and ready to help if needed.
In that slow way, also, art can be taught—if you have faith in your guide, and will let his arm be to you as an iron bar when need is. But in what teacher of art have you such faith? Certainly not in me; for, as I told you at first, I know well enough it is only because you think I can talk, not because you think I know my business, that you let me speak to you at all. If I were to tell you anything that seemed to you strange, you would not believe it, and yet it would only be in telling you strange things that I could be of use to you. I could be of great use to you—infinite use—with brief saying, if you would believe it; but you would not, just because the thing that would be of real use would displease you. You are all wild, for instance, with admiration of Gustave Doré. Well, suppose I were to tell you, in the strongest terms I could use, that Gustave Doré's art was bad—bad, not in weakness,—not in failure,—but bad with dreadful power—the power of the Furies and the Harpies mingled, enraging, and polluting; that so long as you looked at it, no perception of pure or beautiful art was possible for you. Suppose I were to tell you that! What would be the use? Would you look at Gustave Doré less? Rather, more, I fancy. On the other hand, I could soon put you into good humour with me, if I chose. I know well enough what you like, and how to praise it to your better liking. I could talk to you about moonlight, and twilight, and spring flowers, and autumn leaves, and the Madonnas of Raphael—how motherly! and the Sibyls of Michael Angelo—how majestic! and the Saints of Angelico—how pious! and the Cherubs of Correggio—how delicious! Old as I am, I could play you a tune on the harp yet, that you would dance to. But neither you nor I should be a bit the better or wiser; or, if we were, our increased wisdom could be of no practical effect. For, indeed, the arts, as regards teachableness, differ from the sciences also in this, that their power is founded not merely on facts which can be communicated, but on dispositions which require to be created. Art is neither to be achieved by effort of thinking, nor explained by accuracy of speaking. It is the instinctive and necessary result of power, which can only be developed through the mind of successive generations, and which finally burst into life under social conditions as slow of growth as the faculties they regulate. Whole æras of mighty history are summed, and the passions of dead myriads are concentrated, in the existence of a noble art; and if that noble art were among us, we should feel it and rejoice; not caring in the least to hear lectures on it; and since it is not among us, be assured we have to go back to the root of it, or, at least, to the place where the stock of it is yet alive, and the branches began to die.
In that gradual way, art can also be taught—if you trust your guide and let their support be as solid as an iron bar when needed. But in which art teacher do you have such trust? Definitely not in me; because, as I mentioned earlier, I know very well it's only because you think I can speak well, not because you believe I know what I'm talking about, that you let me talk to you at all. If I were to tell you anything that seemed strange, you wouldn't believe it, and yet the only way I could really help you would be by sharing those strange things. I could be incredibly helpful to you—limitlessly helpful—with simple words, if you would just believe me; but you wouldn't, simply because the truths that would truly help you would upset you. You are all excited, for example, by your admiration for Gustave Doré. Well, what if I were to tell you, as strongly as I could, that Gustave Doré's art is bad—bad, not out of weakness or failure, but bad with terrible power—the power of the Furies and the Harpies combined, infuriating and corrupting; that as long as you look at it, no understanding of pure or beautiful art is possible for you. What would be the use of telling you that? Would you look at Gustave Doré less? Probably more, I think. On the other hand, I could quickly make you like me if I wanted to. I know very well what you enjoy, and how to flatter it just the way you like. I could chat about moonlight, twilight, spring flowers, autumn leaves, and Raphael’s Madonnas—how motherly! and Michelangelo's Sibyls—how majestic! and Angelico's Saints—how pious! and Correggio's Cherubs—how delightful! Even though I'm old, I could still play you a tune on the harp that would make you want to dance. But neither you nor I would be any better or wiser; or, if we were, our newfound wisdom wouldn't have any practical impact. The arts are different from the sciences in terms of what can be taught, in that their value is based not just on facts that can be shared, but on qualities that need to be nurtured. Art isn't something to be achieved by mere thinking effort or explained through precise speaking. It is the instinctive and necessary result of talent, which can only develop through the minds of successive generations and finally comes to life under social conditions that grow as slowly as the faculties they inspire. Entire eras of significant history are captured, and the emotions of countless dead are concentrated, in the existence of a noble art; and if that noble art were present among us, we would feel it and celebrate it, having no desire to hear lectures about it; and since it isn't present, just know we must return to its roots, or at least to the place where it is still alive, and where its branches began to wither.
And now, may I have your pardon for pointing out, partly with reference to matters which are at this time of greater moment than the arts—that if we undertook such recession to the vital germ of national arts that have decayed, we should find a more singular arrest of their power in Ireland than in any other European country. For in the eighth century Ireland possessed a school of art in her manuscripts and sculpture, which, in many of its qualities—apparently in all essential qualities of decorative invention—was quite without rival; seeming as if it might have advanced to the highest triumphs in architecture and in painting. But there was one fatal flaw in its nature, by which it was stayed, and stayed with a conspicuousness of pause to which there is no parallel: so that, long ago, in tracing the progress of European schools from infancy to strength, I chose for the students of Kensington, in a lecture since published, two characteristic examples of early art, of equal skill; but in the one case, skill which was progressive—in the other, skill which was at pause. In the one case, it was work receptive of correction—hungry for correction; and in the other, work which inherently rejected correction. I chose for them a corrigible Eve, and an incorrigible Angel, and I grieve to say[236] that the incorrigible Angel was also an Irish angel!
And now, may I have your pardon for pointing out, partly with reference to matters which are at this time of greater moment than the arts—that if we undertook such recession to the vital germ of national arts that have decayed, we should find a more singular arrest of their power in Ireland than in any other European country. For in the eighth century Ireland possessed a school of art in her manuscripts and sculpture, which, in many of its qualities—apparently in all essential qualities of decorative invention—was quite without rival; seeming as if it might have advanced to the highest triumphs in architecture and in painting. But there was one fatal flaw in its nature, by which it was stayed, and stayed with a conspicuousness of pause to which there is no parallel: so that, long ago, in tracing the progress of European schools from infancy to strength, I chose for the students of Kensington, in a lecture since published, two characteristic examples of early art, of equal skill; but in the one case, skill which was progressive—in the other, skill which was at pause. In the one case, it was work receptive of correction—hungry for correction; and in the other, work which inherently rejected correction. I chose for them a corrigible Eve, and an incorrigible Angel, and I grieve to say[236] that the incorrigible Angel was also an Irish angel!
And the fatal difference lay wholly in this. In both pieces of art there was an equal falling short of the needs of fact; but the Lombardic Eve knew she was in the wrong, and the Irish Angel thought himself all right. The eager Lombardic sculptor, though firmly insisting on his childish idea, yet showed in the irregular broken touches of the features, and the imperfect struggle for softer lines in the form, a perception of beauty and law that he could not render; there was the strain of effort, under conscious imperfection, in every line. But the Irish missal-painter had drawn his angel with no sense of failure, in happy complacency, and put red dots into the palms of each hand, and rounded the eyes into perfect circles, and, I regret to say, left the mouth out altogether, with perfect satisfaction to himself.
And the crucial difference was completely this. In both pieces of art, there was a similar lack in meeting the demands of reality; however, the Lombardic Eve was aware of her shortcomings, while the Irish Angel believed he was perfectly fine. The eager Lombardic sculptor, although stubbornly holding onto his naïve idea, still showed in the uneven, jagged touches of the features, and the imperfect attempt at softer lines in the form, an awareness of beauty and rules that he couldn’t fully achieve; there was a sense of struggle, under conscious imperfection, in every line. But the Irish missal-painter created his angel without any sense of failure, in blissful satisfaction, adding red dots to the palms of each hand, rounding the eyes into perfect circles, and, I regret to say, entirely omitting the mouth, with complete contentment in his work.
May I without offence ask you to consider whether this mode of arrest in ancient Irish art may not be indicative of points of character which even yet, in some measure, arrest your national power? I have seen much of Irish character, and have watched it closely, for I have also much loved it. And I think the form of failure to which it is most liable is this,—that being generous-hearted, and wholly intending always to do right, it does not attend to the external laws of right, but thinks it must necessarily do right because it means to do so, and therefore does wrong without finding it out; and then, when the consequences of its wrong come upon it, or upon others connected with it, it cannot conceive that the wrong is in any wise of its causing or of its doing, but flies into wrath, and a strange agony of desire for justice, as feeling itself wholly innocent, which leads it farther astray, until there is nothing that it is not capable of doing with a good conscience.
May I kindly ask you to consider whether this way of halting in ancient Irish art might reveal aspects of character that still, to some extent, hinder your national strength? I’ve observed a lot about Irish character and have studied it closely because I’ve grown to love it deeply. I believe the most common mistake it makes is this: being kind-hearted and genuinely wanting to do the right thing, it often overlooks the actual laws of right and assumes it will automatically do right because it intends to. As a result, it does wrong without realizing it; then, when the consequences hit it or those connected to it, it can’t comprehend that the wrongdoing is in any way its fault. Instead, it reacts with anger and a deep yearning for justice, feeling entirely innocent, which leads it even further off course, until there’s nothing it wouldn’t do with a clear conscience.
But mind, I do not mean to say that, in past or present relations between Ireland and England, you have been wrong, and we right. Far from that, I believe that in all great questions of principle, and in all details of administration of law, you have been usually right, and we wrong; sometimes in misunderstanding you, sometimes in resolute iniquity to you. Nevertheless, in all disputes between states, though the strongest is nearly always mainly in the wrong, the weaker is often so in a minor degree; and I think we sometimes admit the possibility of our being in error, and you never do.[237]
But mind, I do not mean to say that, in past or present relations between Ireland and England, you have been wrong, and we right. Far from that, I believe that in all great questions of principle, and in all details of administration of law, you have been usually right, and we wrong; sometimes in misunderstanding you, sometimes in resolute iniquity to you. Nevertheless, in all disputes between states, though the strongest is nearly always mainly in the wrong, the weaker is often so in a minor degree; and I think we sometimes admit the possibility of our being in error, and you never do.[237]
And now, returning to the broader question, what these arts and labours of life have to teach us of its mystery, this is the first of their lessons—that the more beautiful the art, the more it is essentially the work of people who feel themselves wrong;—who are striving for the fulfilment of a law, and the grasp of a loveliness, which they have not yet attained, which they feel even farther and farther from attaining the more they strive for it. And yet, in still deeper sense, it is the work of people who know also that they are right. The very sense of inevitable error from their purpose marks the perfectness of that purpose, and the continued sense of failure arises from the continued opening of the eyes more clearly to all the sacredest laws of truth.
And now, going back to the bigger question of what these arts and efforts of life can teach us about its mystery, this is the first of their lessons— that the more beautiful the art, the more it comes from people who feel they’ve been wronged;— who are working towards a law and a beauty that they haven’t yet achieved, and the more they strive for it, the more distant it feels. Yet, on a deeper level, it’s also the work of people who know they are right. The very feeling of unavoidable error in their purpose highlights the perfection of that purpose, and the ongoing sense of failure comes from the growing awareness of all the deepest truths.
This is one lesson. The second is a very plain, and greatly precious one: namely,—that whenever the arts and labours of life are fulfilled in this spirit of striving against misrule, and doing whatever we have to do, honourably and perfectly, they invariably bring happiness, as much as seems possible to the nature of man. In all other paths by which that happiness is pursued there is disappointment, or destruction: for ambition and for passion there is no rest—no fruition; the fairest pleasures of youth perish in a darkness greater than their past light; and the loftiest and purest love too often does but inflame the cloud of life with endless fire of pain. But, ascending from lowest to highest, through every scale of human industry, that industry worthily followed, gives peace. Ask the labourer in the field, at the forge, or in the mine; ask the patient, delicate-fingered artisan, or the strong-armed, fiery-hearted worker in bronze, and in marble, and in the colours of light; and none of these, who are true workmen, will ever tell you, that they have found the law of heaven an unkind one—that in the sweat of their face they should eat bread, till they return to the ground;[238] nor that they ever found it an unrewarded obedience, if, indeed, it was rendered faithfully to the command—"Whatsoever thy hand findeth to do—do it with thy might."[239]
This is one lesson. The second is a very plain, and greatly precious one: namely,—that whenever the arts and labours of life are fulfilled in this spirit of striving against misrule, and doing whatever we have to do, honourably and perfectly, they invariably bring happiness, as much as seems possible to the nature of man. In all other paths by which that happiness is pursued there is disappointment, or destruction: for ambition and for passion there is no rest—no fruition; the fairest pleasures of youth perish in a darkness greater than their past light; and the loftiest and purest love too often does but inflame the cloud of life with endless fire of pain. But, ascending from lowest to highest, through every scale of human industry, that industry worthily followed, gives peace. Ask the labourer in the field, at the forge, or in the mine; ask the patient, delicate-fingered artisan, or the strong-armed, fiery-hearted worker in bronze, and in marble, and in the colours of light; and none of these, who are true workmen, will ever tell you, that they have found the law of heaven an unkind one—that in the sweat of their face they should eat bread, till they return to the ground;[238] nor that they ever found it an unrewarded obedience, if, indeed, it was rendered faithfully to the command—"Whatsoever thy hand findeth to do—do it with thy might."[239]
These are the two great and constant lessons which our labourers teach us of the mystery of life. But there is another, and a sadder one, which they cannot teach us, which we must read on their tombstones.
These are the two important and ongoing lessons that our workers show us about the mystery of life. But there is another, and a more sorrowful one, that they can't teach us; we must read it on their gravestones.
"Do it with thy might." There have been myriads upon myriads of human creatures who have obeyed this law—who have put every breath and nerve of their being into its toil—who have devoted every hour, and exhausted every faculty—who have bequeathed their unaccomplished thoughts at death—who, being dead, have yet spoken,[240] by majesty of memory, and strength of example. And, at last, what has all this "Might" of humanity accomplished, in six thousand years of labour and sorrow? What has it done? Take the three chief occupations and arts of men, one by one, and count their achievements. Begin with the first—the lord of them all—Agriculture. Six thousand years have passed since we were sent to till the ground, from which we were taken. How much of it is tilled? How much of that which is, wisely or well? In the very centre and chief garden of Europe—where the two forms of parent Christianity have had their fortresses—where the noble Catholics of the Forest Cantons, and the noble Protestants of the Vaudois valleys, have maintained, for dateless ages, their faiths and liberties—there the unchecked Alpine rivers yet run wild in devastation; and the marshes, which a few hundred men could redeem with a year's labour, still blast their helpless inhabitants into fevered idiotism. That is so, in the centre of Europe! While, on the near coast of Africa, once the Garden of the Hesperides, an Arab woman, but a few sunsets since, ate her child, for famine. And, with all the treasures of the East at our feet, we, in our own dominion, could not find a few grains of rice, for a people that asked of us no more; but stood by, and saw five hundred thousand of them perish of hunger.[241]
"Do it with thy might." There have been myriads upon myriads of human creatures who have obeyed this law—who have put every breath and nerve of their being into its toil—who have devoted every hour, and exhausted every faculty—who have bequeathed their unaccomplished thoughts at death—who, being dead, have yet spoken,[240] by majesty of memory, and strength of example. And, at last, what has all this "Might" of humanity accomplished, in six thousand years of labour and sorrow? What has it done? Take the three chief occupations and arts of men, one by one, and count their achievements. Begin with the first—the lord of them all—Agriculture. Six thousand years have passed since we were sent to till the ground, from which we were taken. How much of it is tilled? How much of that which is, wisely or well? In the very centre and chief garden of Europe—where the two forms of parent Christianity have had their fortresses—where the noble Catholics of the Forest Cantons, and the noble Protestants of the Vaudois valleys, have maintained, for dateless ages, their faiths and liberties—there the unchecked Alpine rivers yet run wild in devastation; and the marshes, which a few hundred men could redeem with a year's labour, still blast their helpless inhabitants into fevered idiotism. That is so, in the centre of Europe! While, on the near coast of Africa, once the Garden of the Hesperides, an Arab woman, but a few sunsets since, ate her child, for famine. And, with all the treasures of the East at our feet, we, in our own dominion, could not find a few grains of rice, for a people that asked of us no more; but stood by, and saw five hundred thousand of them perish of hunger.[241]
Then, after agriculture, the art of kings, take the next head of human arts—weaving; the art of queens, honoured of all noble Heathen women, in the person of their virgin goddess[242]—honoured of all Hebrew women, by the word of their wisest king—"She layeth her hands to the spindle, and her hands hold the distaff; she stretcheth out her hand to the poor. She is not afraid of the snow for her household, for all her household are clothed with scarlet. She maketh herself covering of tapestry; her clothing is silk and purple. She maketh fine linen, and selleth it, and delivereth girdles unto the merchant."[243] What have we done in all these thousands of years with this bright art of Greek maid and Christian matron? Six thousand years of weaving, and have we learned to weave? Might not every naked wall have been purple with tapestry, and every feeble breast fenced with sweet colours from the cold? What have we done? Our fingers are too few, it seems, to twist together some poor covering for our bodies. We set our streams to work for us, and choke the air with fire, to turn our pinning-wheels—and,—are we yet clothed? Are not the streets of the capitals of Europe foul with the sale of cast clouts and rotten rags?[244] Is not the beauty of your sweet children left in wretchedness of disgrace, while, with better honour, nature clothes the brood of the bird in its nest, and the suckling of the wolf in her den? And does not every winter's snow robe what you have not robed, and shroud what you have not shrouded; and every winter's wind bear up to heaven its wasted souls, to witness against you hereafter, by the voice of their Christ,—"I was naked, and ye clothed me not"?[245]
Then, after agriculture, the art of kings, take the next head of human arts—weaving; the art of queens, honoured of all noble Heathen women, in the person of their virgin goddess[242]—honoured of all Hebrew women, by the word of their wisest king—"She layeth her hands to the spindle, and her hands hold the distaff; she stretcheth out her hand to the poor. She is not afraid of the snow for her household, for all her household are clothed with scarlet. She maketh herself covering of tapestry; her clothing is silk and purple. She maketh fine linen, and selleth it, and delivereth girdles unto the merchant."[243] What have we done in all these thousands of years with this bright art of Greek maid and Christian matron? Six thousand years of weaving, and have we learned to weave? Might not every naked wall have been purple with tapestry, and every feeble breast fenced with sweet colours from the cold? What have we done? Our fingers are too few, it seems, to twist together some poor covering for our bodies. We set our streams to work for us, and choke the air with fire, to turn our pinning-wheels—and,—are we yet clothed? Are not the streets of the capitals of Europe foul with the sale of cast clouts and rotten rags?[244] Is not the beauty of your sweet children left in wretchedness of disgrace, while, with better honour, nature clothes the brood of the bird in its nest, and the suckling of the wolf in her den? And does not every winter's snow robe what you have not robed, and shroud what you have not shrouded; and every winter's wind bear up to heaven its wasted souls, to witness against you hereafter, by the voice of their Christ,—"I was naked, and ye clothed me not"?[245]
Lastly—take the Art of Building—the strongest—proudest—most orderly—most enduring of the arts of man; that of which the produce is in the surest manner accumulative, and need not perish, or be replaced; but if once well done, will stand more strongly than the unbalanced rocks—more prevalently than the crumbling hills. The art which is associated with all civic pride and sacred principle; with which men record their power—satisfy their enthusiasm—make sure their defence—define and make dear their habitation. And in six thousand years of building, what have we done? Of the greater part of all that skill and strength, no vestige is left, but fallen stones, that encumber the fields and impede the streams. But, from this waste of disorder, and of time, and of rage, what is left to us? Constructive and progressive creatures that we are, with ruling brains, and forming hands, capable of fellowship, and thirsting for fame, can we not contend, in comfort, with the insects of the forest, or, in achievement, with the worm of the sea? The white surf rages in vain against the ramparts built by poor atoms of scarcely nascent life; but only ridges of formless ruin mark the places where once dwelt our noblest multitudes. The ant and the moth have cells for each of their young, but our little ones lie in festering heaps, in homes that consume them like graves; and night by night, from the corners of our streets, rises up the cry of the homeless—"I was a stranger, and ye took me not in."[246]
Lastly—take the Art of Building—the strongest—proudest—most orderly—most enduring of the arts of man; that of which the produce is in the surest manner accumulative, and need not perish, or be replaced; but if once well done, will stand more strongly than the unbalanced rocks—more prevalently than the crumbling hills. The art which is associated with all civic pride and sacred principle; with which men record their power—satisfy their enthusiasm—make sure their defence—define and make dear their habitation. And in six thousand years of building, what have we done? Of the greater part of all that skill and strength, no vestige is left, but fallen stones, that encumber the fields and impede the streams. But, from this waste of disorder, and of time, and of rage, what is left to us? Constructive and progressive creatures that we are, with ruling brains, and forming hands, capable of fellowship, and thirsting for fame, can we not contend, in comfort, with the insects of the forest, or, in achievement, with the worm of the sea? The white surf rages in vain against the ramparts built by poor atoms of scarcely nascent life; but only ridges of formless ruin mark the places where once dwelt our noblest multitudes. The ant and the moth have cells for each of their young, but our little ones lie in festering heaps, in homes that consume them like graves; and night by night, from the corners of our streets, rises up the cry of the homeless—"I was a stranger, and ye took me not in."[246]
Must it be always thus? Is our life for ever to be without profit—without possession? Shall the strength of its generations be as barren as death; or cast away their labour, as the wild fig-tree casts her untimely figs?[247] Is it all a dream then—the desire of the eyes and the pride of life—or, if it be, might we not live in nobler dream than this? The poets and prophets, the wise men, and the scribes, though they have told us nothing about a life to come, have told us much about the life that is now. They have had—they also,—their dreams, and we have laughed at them. They have dreamed of mercy, and of justice; they have dreamed of peace and good-will; they have dreamed of labour undisappointed, and of rest undisturbed; they have dreamed of fulness in harvest, and overflowing in store; they have dreamed of wisdom in council, and of providence in law; of gladness of parents, and strength of children, and glory of grey hairs. And at these visions of theirs we have mocked, and held them for idle and vain, unreal and unaccomplishable. What have we accomplished with our realities? Is this what has come of our worldly wisdom, tried against their folly? this, our mightiest possible, against their impotent ideal? or, have we only wandered among the spectra of a baser felicity, and chased phantoms of the tombs, instead of visions of the Almighty; and walked after the imaginations of our evil hearts,[248] instead of after the counsels of Eternity, until our lives—not in the likeness of the cloud of heaven, but of the smoke of hell—have become "as a vapour, that appeareth for a little time, and then vanisheth away"?[249]
Must it be always thus? Is our life for ever to be without profit—without possession? Shall the strength of its generations be as barren as death; or cast away their labour, as the wild fig-tree casts her untimely figs?[247] Is it all a dream then—the desire of the eyes and the pride of life—or, if it be, might we not live in nobler dream than this? The poets and prophets, the wise men, and the scribes, though they have told us nothing about a life to come, have told us much about the life that is now. They have had—they also,—their dreams, and we have laughed at them. They have dreamed of mercy, and of justice; they have dreamed of peace and good-will; they have dreamed of labour undisappointed, and of rest undisturbed; they have dreamed of fulness in harvest, and overflowing in store; they have dreamed of wisdom in council, and of providence in law; of gladness of parents, and strength of children, and glory of grey hairs. And at these visions of theirs we have mocked, and held them for idle and vain, unreal and unaccomplishable. What have we accomplished with our realities? Is this what has come of our worldly wisdom, tried against their folly? this, our mightiest possible, against their impotent ideal? or, have we only wandered among the spectra of a baser felicity, and chased phantoms of the tombs, instead of visions of the Almighty; and walked after the imaginations of our evil hearts,[248] instead of after the counsels of Eternity, until our lives—not in the likeness of the cloud of heaven, but of the smoke of hell—have become "as a vapour, that appeareth for a little time, and then vanisheth away"?[249]
Does it vanish then? Are you sure of that?—sure, that the nothingness of the grave will be a rest from this troubled nothingness; and that the coiling shadow, which disquiets itself in vain, cannot change into the smoke of the torment that ascends for ever?[250] Will any answer that they are sure of it, and that there is no fear, nor hope, nor desire, nor labour, whither they go?[251] Be it so: will you not, then, make as sure of the Life that now is, as you are of the Death that is to come? Your hearts are wholly in this world—will you not give them to it wisely, as well as perfectly? And see, first of all, that you have hearts, and sound hearts, too, to give. Because you have no heaven to look for, is that any reason that you should remain ignorant of this wonderful and infinite earth, which is firmly and instantly given you in possession? Although your days are numbered, and the following darkness sure, is it necessary that you should share the degradation of the brute, because you are condemned to its mortality; or live the life of the moth, and of the worm, because you are to companion them in the dust? Not so; we may have but a few thousands of days to spend, perhaps hundreds only—perhaps tens; nay, the longest of our time and best, looked back on, will be but as a moment, as the twinkling of an eye; still we are men, not insects; we are living spirits, not passing clouds. "He maketh the winds His messengers; the momentary fire, His minister";[252] and shall we do less than these? Let us do the work of men while we bear the form of them; and, as we snatch our narrow portion of time out of Eternity, snatch also our narrow inheritance of passion out of Immortality—even though our lives be as a vapour, that appeareth for a little time, and then vanisheth away.
Does it vanish then? Are you sure of that?—sure, that the nothingness of the grave will be a rest from this troubled nothingness; and that the coiling shadow, which disquiets itself in vain, cannot change into the smoke of the torment that ascends for ever?[250] Will any answer that they are sure of it, and that there is no fear, nor hope, nor desire, nor labour, whither they go?[251] Be it so: will you not, then, make as sure of the Life that now is, as you are of the Death that is to come? Your hearts are wholly in this world—will you not give them to it wisely, as well as perfectly? And see, first of all, that you have hearts, and sound hearts, too, to give. Because you have no heaven to look for, is that any reason that you should remain ignorant of this wonderful and infinite earth, which is firmly and instantly given you in possession? Although your days are numbered, and the following darkness sure, is it necessary that you should share the degradation of the brute, because you are condemned to its mortality; or live the life of the moth, and of the worm, because you are to companion them in the dust? Not so; we may have but a few thousands of days to spend, perhaps hundreds only—perhaps tens; nay, the longest of our time and best, looked back on, will be but as a moment, as the twinkling of an eye; still we are men, not insects; we are living spirits, not passing clouds. "He maketh the winds His messengers; the momentary fire, His minister";[252] and shall we do less than these? Let us do the work of men while we bear the form of them; and, as we snatch our narrow portion of time out of Eternity, snatch also our narrow inheritance of passion out of Immortality—even though our lives be as a vapour, that appeareth for a little time, and then vanisheth away.
But there are some of you who believe not this—who think this cloud of life has no such close—that it is to float, revealed and illumined, upon the floor of heaven, in the day when He cometh with clouds, and every eye shall see Him.[253] Some day, you believe, within these five, or ten, or twenty years, for every one of us the judgment will be set, and the books opened.[254] If that be true, far more than that must be true. Is there but one day of judgment? Why, for us every day is a day of judgment—every day is a Dies Iræ,[255] and writes its irrevocable verdict in the flame of its West. Think you that judgment waits till the doors of the grave are opened? It waits at the doors of your houses—it waits at the corners of your streets; we are in the midst of judgment—the insects that we crush are our judges—the moments that we fret away are our judges—the elements that feed us, judge, as they minister—and the pleasures that deceive us, judge as they indulge. Let us, for our lives, do the work of Men while we bear the form of them, if indeed those lives are Not as a vapour, and do Not vanish away.
But there are some of you who believe not this—who think this cloud of life has no such close—that it is to float, revealed and illumined, upon the floor of heaven, in the day when He cometh with clouds, and every eye shall see Him.[253] Some day, you believe, within these five, or ten, or twenty years, for every one of us the judgment will be set, and the books opened.[254] If that be true, far more than that must be true. Is there but one day of judgment? Why, for us every day is a day of judgment—every day is a Dies Iræ,[255] and writes its irrevocable verdict in the flame of its West. Think you that judgment waits till the doors of the grave are opened? It waits at the doors of your houses—it waits at the corners of your streets; we are in the midst of judgment—the insects that we crush are our judges—the moments that we fret away are our judges—the elements that feed us, judge, as they minister—and the pleasures that deceive us, judge as they indulge. Let us, for our lives, do the work of Men while we bear the form of them, if indeed those lives are Not as a vapour, and do Not vanish away.
"The work of men"—and what is that? Well, we may any of us know very quickly, on the condition of being wholly ready to do it. But many of us are for the most part thinking, not of what we are to do, but of what we are to get; and the best of us are sunk into the sin of Ananias,[256] and it is a mortal one—we want to keep back part of the price; and we continually talk of taking up our cross, as if the only harm in a cross was the weight of it—as if it was only a thing to be carried, instead of to be—crucified upon. "They that are His have crucified the flesh, with the affections and lusts."[257] Does that mean, think you, that in time of national distress, of religious trial, of crisis for every interest and hope of humanity—none of us will cease jesting, none cease idling, none put themselves to any wholesome work, none take so much as a tag of lace off their footmen's coats, to save the world? Or does it rather mean, that they are ready to leave houses, lands, and kindreds—yes, and life, if need be? Life!—some of us are ready enough to throw that away, joyless as we have made it. But "station in Life"—how many of us are ready to quit that? Is it not always the great objection, where there is question of finding something useful to do—"We cannot leave our stations in Life"?
"The work of men"—and what is that? Well, we may any of us know very quickly, on the condition of being wholly ready to do it. But many of us are for the most part thinking, not of what we are to do, but of what we are to get; and the best of us are sunk into the sin of Ananias,[256] and it is a mortal one—we want to keep back part of the price; and we continually talk of taking up our cross, as if the only harm in a cross was the weight of it—as if it was only a thing to be carried, instead of to be—crucified upon. "They that are His have crucified the flesh, with the affections and lusts."[257] Does that mean, think you, that in time of national distress, of religious trial, of crisis for every interest and hope of humanity—none of us will cease jesting, none cease idling, none put themselves to any wholesome work, none take so much as a tag of lace off their footmen's coats, to save the world? Or does it rather mean, that they are ready to leave houses, lands, and kindreds—yes, and life, if need be? Life!—some of us are ready enough to throw that away, joyless as we have made it. But "station in Life"—how many of us are ready to quit that? Is it not always the great objection, where there is question of finding something useful to do—"We cannot leave our stations in Life"?
Those of us who really cannot—that is to say, who can only maintain themselves by continuing in some business or salaried office, have already something to do; and all that they have to see to is, that they do it honestly and with all their might. But with most people who use that apology, "remaining in the station of life to which Providence has called them" means keeping all the carriages, and all the footmen and large houses they can possibly pay for; and, once for all, I say that if ever Providence did put them into stations of that sort—which is not at all a matter of certainty—Providence is just now very distinctly calling them out again. Levi's station in life was the receipt of custom; and Peter's, the shore of Galilee; and Paul's, the antechambers of the High Priest,—which "station in life" each had to leave, with brief notice.
Those of us who really can’t—meaning those who can only support themselves by staying in some job or salaried position—have already got something to do; and all they need to focus on is doing it honestly and with all their effort. But for most people who use the excuse of "staying in the station of life that Providence has assigned them," it means keeping all the luxury cars, footmen, and big houses they can afford; and, once and for all, I’ll say that if Providence ever did place them in those kinds of positions—which is by no means certain—Providence is clearly calling them out of them now. Levi's place in life was collecting taxes; Peter's was by the shores of Galilee; and Paul's was in the halls of the High Priest—each of which they had to leave without much notice.
And, whatever our station in life may be, at this crisis, those of us who mean to fulfil our duty ought first to live on as little as we can; and, secondly, to do all the wholesome work for it we can, and to spend all we can spare in doing all the sure good we can.
And no matter where we stand in life right now, those of us who want to fulfill our responsibilities should first live on as little as possible; and second, do all the meaningful work we can, and spend whatever we can spare to do as much good as we can.
And sure good is, first in feeding people, then in dressing people, then in lodging people, and lastly in rightly pleasing people, with arts, or sciences, or any other subject of thought.
And sure, it’s great for feeding people, then dressing them, then giving them a place to stay, and finally for genuinely pleasing them with arts, sciences, or any other topic of interest.
I say first in feeding; and, once for all, do not let yourselves be deceived by any of the common talk of "indiscriminate charity." The order to us is not to feed the deserving hungry, nor the industrious hungry, nor the amiable and well-intentioned hungry, but simply to feed the hungry.[258] It is quite true, infallibly true, that if any man will not work, neither should he eat[259] —think of that, and every time you sit down to your dinner, ladies and gentlemen, say solemnly, before you ask a blessing, "How much work have I done to-day for my dinner?" But the proper way to enforce that order on those below you, as well as on yourselves, is not to leave vagabonds and honest people to starve together, but very distinctly to discern and seize your vagabond; and shut your vagabond up out of honest people's way, and very sternly then see that, until he has worked, he does not eat. But the first thing is to be sure you have the food to give; and, therefore, to enforce the organization of vast activities in agriculture and in commerce, for the production of the wholesomest food, and proper storing and distribution of it, so that no famine shall any more be possible among civilized beings There is plenty of work in this business alone, and at once, for any number of people who like to engage in it.
I say first in feeding; and, once for all, do not let yourselves be deceived by any of the common talk of "indiscriminate charity." The order to us is not to feed the deserving hungry, nor the industrious hungry, nor the amiable and well-intentioned hungry, but simply to feed the hungry.[258] It is quite true, infallibly true, that if any man will not work, neither should he eat[259] —think of that, and every time you sit down to your dinner, ladies and gentlemen, say solemnly, before you ask a blessing, "How much work have I done to-day for my dinner?" But the proper way to enforce that order on those below you, as well as on yourselves, is not to leave vagabonds and honest people to starve together, but very distinctly to discern and seize your vagabond; and shut your vagabond up out of honest people's way, and very sternly then see that, until he has worked, he does not eat. But the first thing is to be sure you have the food to give; and, therefore, to enforce the organization of vast activities in agriculture and in commerce, for the production of the wholesomest food, and proper storing and distribution of it, so that no famine shall any more be possible among civilized beings There is plenty of work in this business alone, and at once, for any number of people who like to engage in it.
Secondly, dressing people—that is to say, urging every one within reach of your influence to be always neat and clean, and giving them means of being so. In so far as they absolutely refuse, you must give up the effort with respect to them, only taking care that no children within your sphere of influence shall any more be brought up with such habits; and that every person who is willing to dress with propriety shall have encouragement to do so. And the first absolutely necessary step towards this is the gradual adoption of a consistent dress for different ranks of persons, so that their rank shall be known by their dress; and the restriction of the changes of fashion within certain limits. All which appears for the present quite impossible; but it is only so far even difficult as it is difficult to conquer our vanity, frivolity, and desire to appear what we are not. And it is not, nor ever shall be, creed of mine, that these mean and shallow vices are unconquerable by Christian women.
Secondly, helping people dress—that is, encouraging everyone you can to always look neat and clean, and providing them with the means to do so. If they completely refuse, you should drop the effort with them but make sure that no children in your influence grow up with those habits; and that anyone who wants to dress properly gets support to do so. The first essential step toward this is gradually creating a consistent way of dressing for different social ranks, so their status can be recognized by their attire; and limiting the changes in fashion to certain boundaries. All this seems completely impossible right now; however, it’s only as difficult as it is to overcome our vanity, superficiality, and the urge to appear different from who we are. And it is not, nor will it ever be, my belief that these petty and shallow flaws are unchangeable for Christian women.
And then, thirdly, lodging people, which you may think should have been put first, but I put it third, because we must feed and clothe people where we find them, and lodge them afterwards. And providing lodgment for them means a great deal of vigorous legislation, and cutting down of vested interests that stand in the way, and after that, or before that, so far as we can get it, thorough sanitary and remedial action in the houses that we have; and then the building of more, strongly, beautifully, and in groups of limited extent, kept in proportion to their streams, and walled round, so that there may be no festering and wretched suburb anywhere, but clean and busy street within, and the open country without, with a belt of beautiful garden and orchard round the walls, so that from any part of the city perfectly fresh air and grass, and the sight of far horizon, might be reachable in a few minutes' walk. This is the final aim; but in immediate action every minor and possible good to be instantly done, when, and as, we can; roofs mended that have holes in them—fences patched that have gaps in them—walls buttressed that totter—and floors propped that shake; cleanliness and order enforced with our own hands and eyes, till we are breathless, every day. And all the fine arts will healthily follow. I myself have washed a flight of stone stairs all down, with bucket and broom, in a Savoy inn, where they hadn't washed their stairs since they first went up them; and I never made a better sketch than that afternoon.
And then, thirdly, providing housing for people, which you might think should have come first, but I placed it third because we need to feed and clothe people where we find them before we find them a place to stay. Making sure they have a place to live requires a lot of strong legislation and cutting through the established interests that get in the way. After that, or even before, we need to focus on thorough sanitary and remedial actions in the housing we already have, followed by building more homes that are strong, beautiful, and grouped in limited areas, maintaining a balance with their surroundings. They should be walled off to prevent any rundown and miserable neighborhoods, leaving clean and lively streets within and open countryside outside, with a lovely garden and orchard surrounding the walls. This way, fresh air, grass, and a view of the horizon would be just a short walk away from anywhere in the city. This is the ultimate goal; however, in the meantime, we must take every possible step to do good immediately, fixing roofs with holes, patching fences with gaps, bracing walls that are unstable, and propping up shaky floors. We should enforce cleanliness and order with our own hands and eyes every day, until we are out of breath. And all the fine arts will naturally follow. I’ve personally washed a flight of stone stairs in a Savoy inn, where they hadn't been cleaned since they were first built, and I’ve never made a better sketch than that afternoon.
These, then, are the three first needs of civilized life; and the law for every Christian man and woman is, that they shall be in direct service towards one of these three needs, as far as is consistent with their own special occupation, and if they have no special business, then wholly in one of these services. And out of such exertion in plain duty all other good will come; for in this direct contention with material evil, you will find out the real nature of all evil; you will discern by the various kinds of resistance, what is really the fault and main antagonism to good; also you will find the most unexpected helps and profound lessons given, and truths will come thus down to us which the speculation of all our lives would never have raised us up to. You will find nearly every educational problem solved, as soon as you truly want to do something; everybody will become of use in their own fittest way, and will learn what is best for them to know in that use. Competitive examination will then, and not till then, be wholesome, because it will be daily, and calm, and in practice; and on these familiar arts, and minute, but certain and serviceable knowledges, will be surely edified and sustained the greater arts and splendid theoretical sciences.
These are the three basic needs of civilized life. For every Christian man and woman, the principle is that they should directly contribute to one of these needs, as long as it aligns with their specific job. If they don’t have a particular occupation, they should fully dedicate themselves to one of these services. Through this effort in fulfilling basic duties, all other good will emerge; because in tackling material challenges, you'll discover the true nature of all evils. You'll see through various forms of resistance what the real faults and main oppositions to goodness are. Additionally, you'll find unexpected support and valuable lessons coming your way, revealing truths that a lifetime of speculation would never have uncovered. As soon as you genuinely want to accomplish something, almost every educational challenge will be resolved; everyone will find their own best way to contribute and will learn what they need to know in that context. Competitions for assessment will then become beneficial, but only when they’re regular, calm, and practical; and on these familiar skills and specific useful knowledge, the greater arts and impressive theoretical sciences will surely be built and sustained.
But much more than this. On such holy and simple practice will be founded, indeed, at last, an infallible religion. The greatest of all the mysteries of life, and the most terrible, is the corruption of even the sincerest religion, which is not daily founded on rational, effective, humble, and helpful action. Helpful action, observe! for there is just one law, which obeyed, keeps all religions pure—forgotten, makes them all false. Whenever in any religious faith, dark or bright, we allow our minds to dwell upon the points in which we differ from other people, we are wrong, and in the devil's power. That is the essence of the Pharisee's thanksgiving—"Lord, I thank Thee that I am not as other men are."[260] At every moment of our lives we should be trying to find out, not in what we differ with other people, but in what we agree with them; and the moment we find we can agree as to anything that should be done, kind or good, (and who but fools couldn't?) then do it; push at it together: you can't quarrel in a side-by-side push; but the moment that even the best men stop pushing, and begin talking, they mistake their pugnacity for piety, and if's all over. I will not speak of the crimes which in past times have been committed in the name of Christ, nor of the follies which are at this hour held to be consistent with obedience to Him; but I will speak of the morbid corruption and waste of vital power in religious sentiment, by which the pure strength of that which should be the guiding soul of every nation, the splendour of its youthful manhood, and spotless light of its maidenhood, is averted or cast away. You may see continually girls who have never been taught to do a single useful thing thoroughly; who cannot sew, who cannot cook, who cannot cast an account, nor prepare a medicine, whose whole life has been passed either in play or in pride; you will find girls like these, when they are earnest-hearted, cast all their innate passion of religious spirit, which was meant by God to support them through the irksomeness of daily toil, into grievous and vain meditation over the meaning of the great Book, of which no syllable was ever yet to be understood but through a deed; all the instinctive wisdom and mercy of their womanhood made vain, and the glory of their pure consciences warped into fruitless agony concerning questions which the laws of common serviceable life would have either solved for them in an instant, or kept out of their way. Give such a girl any true work that will make her active in the dawn, and weary at night, with the consciousness that her fellow-creatures have indeed been the better for her day, and the powerless sorrow of her enthusiasm will transform itself into a majesty of radiant and beneficent peace.
But much more than this. On such holy and simple practice will be founded, indeed, at last, an infallible religion. The greatest of all the mysteries of life, and the most terrible, is the corruption of even the sincerest religion, which is not daily founded on rational, effective, humble, and helpful action. Helpful action, observe! for there is just one law, which obeyed, keeps all religions pure—forgotten, makes them all false. Whenever in any religious faith, dark or bright, we allow our minds to dwell upon the points in which we differ from other people, we are wrong, and in the devil's power. That is the essence of the Pharisee's thanksgiving—"Lord, I thank Thee that I am not as other men are."[260] At every moment of our lives we should be trying to find out, not in what we differ with other people, but in what we agree with them; and the moment we find we can agree as to anything that should be done, kind or good, (and who but fools couldn't?) then do it; push at it together: you can't quarrel in a side-by-side push; but the moment that even the best men stop pushing, and begin talking, they mistake their pugnacity for piety, and if's all over. I will not speak of the crimes which in past times have been committed in the name of Christ, nor of the follies which are at this hour held to be consistent with obedience to Him; but I will speak of the morbid corruption and waste of vital power in religious sentiment, by which the pure strength of that which should be the guiding soul of every nation, the splendour of its youthful manhood, and spotless light of its maidenhood, is averted or cast away. You may see continually girls who have never been taught to do a single useful thing thoroughly; who cannot sew, who cannot cook, who cannot cast an account, nor prepare a medicine, whose whole life has been passed either in play or in pride; you will find girls like these, when they are earnest-hearted, cast all their innate passion of religious spirit, which was meant by God to support them through the irksomeness of daily toil, into grievous and vain meditation over the meaning of the great Book, of which no syllable was ever yet to be understood but through a deed; all the instinctive wisdom and mercy of their womanhood made vain, and the glory of their pure consciences warped into fruitless agony concerning questions which the laws of common serviceable life would have either solved for them in an instant, or kept out of their way. Give such a girl any true work that will make her active in the dawn, and weary at night, with the consciousness that her fellow-creatures have indeed been the better for her day, and the powerless sorrow of her enthusiasm will transform itself into a majesty of radiant and beneficent peace.
So with our youths. We once taught them to make Latin verses, and called them educated; now we teach them to leap and to row, to hit a ball with a bat, and call them educated. Can they plough, can they sow, can they plant at the right time, or build with a steady hand? Is it the effort of their lives to be chaste, knightly, faithful, holy in thought, lovely in word and deed? Indeed it is, with some, nay with many, and the strength of England is in them, and the hope; but we have to turn their courage from the toil of war to the toil of mercy; and their intellect from dispute of words to discernment of things; and their knighthood from the errantry of adventure to the state and fidelity of a kingly power. And then, indeed, shall abide, for them, and for us, an incorruptible felicity, and an infallible religion; shall abide for us Faith, no more to be assailed by temptation, no more to be defended by wrath and by fear;—shall abide with us Hope, no more to be quenched by the years that overwhelm, or made ashamed by the shadows that betray:—shall abide for us, and with us, the greatest of these; the abiding will, the abiding name of our Father. For the greatest of these is Charity.[261]
So with our youths. We once taught them to make Latin verses, and called them educated; now we teach them to leap and to row, to hit a ball with a bat, and call them educated. Can they plough, can they sow, can they plant at the right time, or build with a steady hand? Is it the effort of their lives to be chaste, knightly, faithful, holy in thought, lovely in word and deed? Indeed it is, with some, nay with many, and the strength of England is in them, and the hope; but we have to turn their courage from the toil of war to the toil of mercy; and their intellect from dispute of words to discernment of things; and their knighthood from the errantry of adventure to the state and fidelity of a kingly power. And then, indeed, shall abide, for them, and for us, an incorruptible felicity, and an infallible religion; shall abide for us Faith, no more to be assailed by temptation, no more to be defended by wrath and by fear;—shall abide with us Hope, no more to be quenched by the years that overwhelm, or made ashamed by the shadows that betray:—shall abide for us, and with us, the greatest of these; the abiding will, the abiding name of our Father. For the greatest of these is Charity.[261]
Editions. The standard edition of Ruskin is that of Cook and Wedderburn in 34 volumes. Most of his better-known works may be had in cheap and convenient forms.
Editions. The standard edition of Ruskin is the one by Cook and Wedderburn in 34 volumes. Most of his well-known works are available in affordable and easy-to-access formats.
The best lives are:
The best lives are:
COLLINGWOOD, W.G. The Life and Work of John Ruskin Houghton Mifflin Company, 1893. (2 vols.) The standard biography.
COLLINGWOOD, W.G. The Life and Work of John Ruskin Houghton Mifflin Company, 1893. (2 vols.) The standard biography.
HARRISON, P. John Ruskin (English Men of Letters). The Macmillan Company, 1902. A short and readable biography.
HARRISON, P. John Ruskin (English Men of Letters). The Macmillan Company, 1902. A brief and engaging biography.
Footnotes
Footnotes
[2] Ruskin himself quotes a not very brilliant specimen in Modern Painters, III, in "Moral of Landscape."
[2] Ruskin himself quotes a not very impressive example in Modern Painters, III, in "Moral of Landscape."
[5] See Harrison's Life, p. 111. Cf. the opening of The Mystery of Life.
[5] See Harrison's Life, p. 111. Compare with the beginning of The Mystery of Life.
[7] See p. 159.
See p. 159.
[8] Modern Painters, vol. 1, part 2, sec. 1, chap. 7.
[8] Modern Painters, vol. 1, part 2, sec. 1, chap. 7.
[10] See p. 262.
See p. 262.
[11] See p. 162.
See p. 162.
[12] See p. 139.
See p. 139.
[14] See p. 121.
See p. 121.
[15] See p. 122.
See p. 122.
[16] See p. 149.
See p. 149.
[18] The Mystery of Life.
The Mystery of Life.
[19] Sesame and Lilies, "Kings' Treasuries," §§ 25, 31.
[19] Sesame and Lilies, "Kings' Treasuries," §§ 25, 31.
[21] "Kings' Treasuries," § 32.
"Kings' Treasuries," § 32.
[23] "In our own National Gallery. It is quaint and imperfect, but of great interest." [Ruskin.] Paolo Uccello (c. 1397-1475), a Florentine painter of the Renaissance, the first of the naturalists. His real name was Paolo di Dono, but he was called Uccello from his fondness for birds.
[23] "In our own National Gallery. It's charming and not without flaws, but definitely intriguing." [Ruskin.] Paolo Uccello (c. 1397-1475), a Florentine painter from the Renaissance, was the first of the naturalists. His actual name was Paolo di Dono, but he was nicknamed Uccello because of his love for birds.
[24] In tracing the whole of the deep enjoyment to mountain association, I of course except whatever feelings are connected with the observance of rural life, or with that of architecture. None of these feelings arise out of the landscape properly so called: the pleasure with which we see a peasant's garden fairly kept, or a ploughman doing his work well, or a group of children playing at a cottage door, being wholly separate from that which we find in the fields or commons around them; and the beauty of architecture, or the associations connected with it, in like manner often ennobling the most tame scenery;—yet not so but that we may always distinguish between the abstract character of the unassisted landscape, and the charm which it derives from the architecture. Much of the majesty of French landscape consists in its grand and grey village churches and turreted farmhouses, not to speak of its cathedrals, castles, and beautifully placed cities. [Ruskin.]
[24] In exploring the overall deep enjoyment derived from mountains, I will exclude any feelings linked to rural life or to architecture. None of these feelings come from the landscape itself: the joy we get from seeing a well-kept peasant’s garden, a ploughman working diligently, or a group of children playing at a cottage door is completely different from what we experience in the fields or commons around them; and the beauty of architecture, or the feelings it evokes, often enhances even the most mundane scenery. Still, we can always differentiate between the pure character of the untouched landscape and the appeal it gains from the presence of architecture. Much of the grandeur of French landscapes comes from their impressive gray village churches and turreted farmhouses, not to mention their cathedrals, castles, and beautifully situated cities. [Ruskin.]
[25] One of the principal reasons for the false supposition that Switzerland is not picturesque, is the error of most sketchers and painters in representing pine forest in middle distance as dark green, or grey green, whereas its true colour is always purple, at distances of even two or three miles. Let any traveller coming down the Montanvert look for an aperture, three or four inches wide, between the near pine branches, through which, standing eight or ten feet from it, he can see the opposite forests on the Breven or Flegère. Those forests are not above two or two and a half miles from him; but he will find the aperture is filled by a tint of nearly pure azure or purple, not by green. [Ruskin.]
[25] One of the main reasons people mistakenly think Switzerland isn't scenic is that most sketch artists and painters incorrectly depict the pine forests in the background as dark green or grey-green. However, their actual color is always purple when viewed from even two or three miles away. If a traveler coming down from Montanvert looks for a small opening, just three or four inches wide, between the nearby pine branches, and stands eight to ten feet from it, they can see the opposite forests on the Breven or Flegère. Those forests are only about two to two and a half miles away, but they'll see that the opening reveals a hue of nearly pure azure or purple, not green. [Ruskin.]
[26] The Savoyard's name for its flower, "Pain du Bon Dieu," is very beautiful; from, I believe, the supposed resemblance of its white and scattered blossom to the fallen manna, [Ruskin.]
[26] The Savoyard's name for its flower, "Pain du Bon Dieu," is quite lovely; I think it comes from the way its white and scattered blossoms resemble fallen manna, [Ruskin.]
[28] In "The Mountain Gloom," the chapter immediately preceding.
[28] In "The Mountain Gloom," the chapter right before this one.
[29] Ruskin refers to The Fulfilling of the Scripture, a book by Robert Fleming [1630-94].
[29] Ruskin talks about The Fulfilling of the Scripture, a book by Robert Fleming [1630-94].
[30] Some sentences of an argumentative nature have been omitted from this selection.
[30] Some argumentative sentences have been left out of this selection.
[32] I have often seen the white, thin, morning cloud, edged with the seven colours of the prism. I am not aware of the cause of this phenomenon, for it takes place not when we stand with our backs to the sun, but in clouds near the sun itself, irregularly and over indefinite spaces, sometimes taking place in the body of the cloud. The colours are distinct and vivid, but have a kind of metallic lustre upon them. [Ruskin.]
[32] I have often noticed the thin, white morning cloud, outlined with the seven colors of the rainbow. I don't know what causes this phenomenon, since it happens not when we turn our backs to the sun, but in clouds close to the sun itself, unevenly and over uncertain areas, sometimes appearing within the cloud itself. The colors are bright and clear, but they have a sort of metallic shine to them. [Ruskin.]
[33] Lake Lucerne. [Ruskin.]
Lake Lucerne. [Ruskin.]
[34] The implication is that Turner has best delivered it.
[34] The suggestion is that Turner has presented it the best.
[35] The full title of this chapter is "Of the Received Opinions touching the 'Grand Style.'"
[35] The complete title of this chapter is "Of the Accepted Views Regarding the 'Grand Style.'"
[36] I have put this sentence in a parenthesis, because it is inconsistent with the rest of the statement, and with the general teaching of the paper; since that which "attends only to the invariable" cannot certainly adopt "every ornament that will warm the imagination." [Ruskin.]
[36] I’ve put this sentence in parentheses because it doesn’t match the rest of the statement or the overall message of the paper; since what "focuses only on the unchanging" certainly cannot embrace "every ornament that will ignite the imagination." [Ruskin.]
[37] Stanza 6 of Byron's Prisoner of Chillon, quoted with a slight inaccuracy.
[37] Stanza 6 of Byron's Prisoner of Chillon, quoted with a slight inaccuracy.
[38] "Messrs. Mallet and Pictet, being on the lake, in front of the Castle of Chillon, on August 6, 1774, sunk a thermometer to the depth of 312 feet." ... —SAUSSURE, Voyages dans les Alpes, chap. ii, § 33. It appears from the next paragraph, that the thermometer was at the bottom of the lake. [Ruskin, altered.]
[38] "Mr. Mallet and Mr. Pictet were by the lake, in front of the Castle of Chillon, on August 6, 1774, when they lowered a thermometer to a depth of 312 feet." ... —SAUSSURE, Voyages dans les Alpes, chap. ii, § 33. It seems from the following paragraph that the thermometer was at the bottom of the lake. [Ruskin, altered.]
[39] Ruskin later wrote: "It leaves out rhythm, which I now consider a defect in said definition; otherwise good."
[39] Ruskin later wrote: "It misses rhythm, which I now see as a flaw in that definition; otherwise it's good."
[40] Take, for instance, the beautiful stanza in the Affliction of Margaret:
[40] Take, for example, the beautiful stanza in the Affliction of Margaret:
I look for ghosts, but none will force
I look for ghosts, but none will appear.
Their way to me. 'T is falsely said
Their way to me. It's falsely said
That ever there was intercourse
That there ever was intimacy
Between the living and the dead;
Between the living and the dead;
For, surely, then, I should have sight
For sure, then I would have sight
Of him I wait for, day and night.
Of him I wait for, day and night.
With love and longing infinite.
With endless love and longing.
This we call Poetry, because it is invented or made by the writer, entering into the mind of a supposed person. Next, take an instance of the actual feeling truly experienced and simply expressed by a real person.
This is what we refer to as Poetry because it is created or crafted by the writer, tapping into the thoughts of a fictional character. Now, consider an example of a genuine feeling that is honestly felt and straightforwardly expressed by a real person.
"Nothing surprised me more than a woman of Argentière, whose cottage I went into to ask for milk, as I came down from the glacier of Argentière, in the month of March, 1764. An epidemic dysentery had prevailed in the village, and, a few months before, had taken away from her, her father, her husband, and her brothers, so that she was left alone, with three children in the cradle. Her face had something noble in it, and its expression bore the seal of a calm and profound sorrow. After having given me milk, she asked me whence I came, and what I came there to do, so early in the year. When she knew that I was of Geneva, she said to me, 'she could not believe that all Protestants were lost souls; that there were many honest people among us, and that God was too good and too great to condemn all without distinction.' Then, after a moment of reflection, she added, in shaking her head, 'But that which is very strange is that of so many who have gone away, none have ever returned. I,' she added, with an expression of grief, 'who have so mourned my husband and my brothers, who have never ceased to think of them, who every night conjure them with beseechings to tell me where they are, and in what state they are! Ah, surely, if they lived anywhere, they would not leave me thus! But, perhaps,' she added, 'I am not worthy of this kindness, perhaps the pure and innocent spirits of these children,' and she looked at the cradle, 'may have their presence, and the joy which is denied to me.'"—SAUSSURE, Voyages dans les Alpes, chap. xxiv.
"Nothing surprised me more than a woman from Argentière, whose cottage I entered to ask for milk as I came down from the glacier of Argentière in March 1764. An epidemic of dysentery had swept through the village, and a few months earlier, it had taken her father, her husband, and her brothers, leaving her alone with three children in the crib. Her face had a noble quality, and its expression showed the mark of deep and quiet sorrow. After giving me milk, she asked where I was from and what I was doing there so early in the year. When she learned I was from Geneva, she told me she couldn’t believe that all Protestants were lost souls; she believed there were many honest people among us, and that God was too good and too great to condemn everyone without exception. Then, after a moment of thought, she added, shaking her head, 'But what’s really strange is that of all those who have gone away, none have ever come back. I,' she continued, with a look of sadness, 'who have mourned my husband and my brothers, who have never stopped thinking of them, who every night call out to them, begging to know where they are and how they are doing! Ah, surely, if they were alive anywhere, they wouldn’t leave me like this! But maybe,' she added, 'I’m not worthy of this kindness; perhaps the pure and innocent spirits of these children,' and she glanced at the crib, 'may have their presence, and the joy that is denied to me.'"—SAUSSURE, Voyages dans les Alpes, chap. xxiv.
This we do not call Poetry, merely because it is not invented, but the true utterance of a real person. [Ruskin.]
This isn't what we consider Poetry, just because it's not made up, but rather the genuine expression of a real person. [Ruskin.]
[41] The closing lines of Wordsworth's Childless Father.
[41] The closing lines of Wordsworth's Childless Father.
[42] Iliad, 1. 463 ff., 2. 425 ff.; Odyssey, 3. 455 ff., etc.
[42] Iliad, 1. 463 ff., 2. 425 ff.; Odyssey, 3. 455 ff., etc.
[43] Iliad, 6. 468 ff.
Iliad, 6. 468 ff.
[44] 1625-1713. Known also as Carlo delle Madonne.
[44] 1625-1713. Also known as Carlo delle Madonne.
[45] Claude Gelée [1600-82], usually called Claude Lorrain, a French landscape painter and etcher.
[45] Claude Gelée [1600-82], commonly known as Claude Lorrain, was a French landscape painter and etcher.
[46] Vasari, in his Lives of the Painters, tells how Giotto, when a student under Cimabue, once painted a fly on the nose of a figure on which the master was working, the fly being so realistic that Cimabue on returning to the painting attempted to brush it away.
[46] Vasari, in his Lives of the Painters, recounts how Giotto, while studying under Cimabue, once painted a fly on the nose of a figure that his master was working on. The fly looked so real that when Cimabue came back to the painting, he tried to swat it away.
[47] Guercino's Hagar in the Brera gallery in Milan.
[47] Guercino's Hagar in the Brera gallery in Milan.
[48] Gerard Dow [1613-75], a Dutch genre painter; Hobbima [1638-1709], a Dutch landscape painter; Walpole [1717-97], a famous English litterateur; Vasari [1511-74], an Italian painter, now considered full of mannerisms and without originality, mainly famous as author of The Lives of the Painters.
[48] Gerard Dow [1613-75], a Dutch genre painter; Hobbima [1638-1709], a Dutch landscape painter; Walpole [1717-97], a well-known English writer; Vasari [1511-74], an Italian painter, now seen as having many stylistic quirks and lacking originality, primarily known as the author of The Lives of the Painters.
[49] Giotto.
Giotto.
[51] The Society of Painters in Water-Colours, often referred to as the Old Water-Colour Society. Ruskin was elected an honorary member in 1873.
[51] The Society of Painters in Watercolors, commonly known as the Old Water-Color Society. Ruskin became an honorary member in 1873.
[52] Three short sections discussing the use of the terms "Objective" and "Subjective" have been omitted from the beginning of this chapter.
[52] Three brief sections about the terms "Objective" and "Subjective" have been removed from the start of this chapter.
[53] Holmes (Oliver Wendell), quoted by Miss Mitford in her Recollections of a Literary Life. [Ruskin.] From Astræa, a Poem delivered before the Phi Beta Kappa Society of Yale College. The passage in which these lines are found was later published as Spring.
[53] Holmes (Oliver Wendell), quoted by Miss Mitford in her Recollections of a Literary Life. [Ruskin.] From Astræa, a Poem delivered before the Phi Beta Kappa Society of Yale College. The passage in which these lines are found was later published as Spring.
[54] Kingsley's Alton Locke, chap. 26.
Kingsley's Alton Locke, ch. 26.
[55] I admit two orders of poets, but no third; and by these two orders I mean the creative (Shakspere, Homer, Dante), and Reflective or Perceptive (Wordsworth, Keats, Tennyson). But both of these must be first-rate in their range, though their range is different; and with poetry second-rate in quality no one ought to be allowed to trouble mankind. There is quite enough of the best,—much more than we can ever read or enjoy in the length of a life; and it is a literal wrong or sin in any person to encumber us with inferior work. I have no patience with apologies made by young pseudo-poets, "that they believe there is some good in what they have written: that they hope to do better in time," etc. Some good! If there is not all good, there is no good. If they ever hope to do better, why do they trouble us now? Let them rather courageously burn all they have done, and wait for the better days. There are few men, ordinarily educated, who in moments of strong feeling could not strike out a poetical thought, and afterwards polish it so as to be presentable. But men of sense know better than so to waste their time; and those who sincerely love poetry, know the touch of the master's hand on the chords too well to fumble among them after him. Nay, more than this, all inferior poetry is an injury to the good, inasmuch as it takes away the freshness of rhymes, blunders upon and gives a wretched commonalty to good thoughts; and, in general, adds to the weight of human weariness in a most woful and culpable manner. There are few thoughts likely to come across ordinary men, which have not already been expressed by greater men in the best possible way; and it is a wiser, more generous, more noble thing to remember and point out the perfect words, than to invent poorer ones, wherewith to encumber temporarily the world. [Ruskin.]
[55] I recognize two types of poets, but no more; these two types are the creative (Shakespeare, Homer, Dante) and the Reflective or Perceptive (Wordsworth, Keats, Tennyson). However, both must be top-notch in their scope, even though that scope is different; and no one should be allowed to bother humanity with second-rate poetry in quality. There’s already plenty of the best—much more than we can ever read or enjoy in a lifetime; it's wrong or sinful for anyone to burden us with inferior work. I have no patience for excuses from young wannabe poets, like "I believe there's some good in what I've written: I hope to do better in the future," etc. Some good? If it isn't all good, then there's no good at all. If they hope to do better, why are they bothering us now? They should bravely discard everything they’ve done and wait for better days. There are few normally educated men who, in moments of strong emotion, couldn’t come up with a poetic thought and then refine it so it's presentable. But sensible people know better than to waste their time; those who genuinely love poetry understand the master's touch on the strings too well to fumble around after him. Moreover, all inferior poetry harms the good because it dulls the freshness of rhymes, clumsily dilutes great ideas, and generally adds to the burden of human fatigue in a regrettable and irresponsible way. There are few thoughts that would likely occur to ordinary people that haven't already been expressed by greater minds in the best way possible; it's a wiser, more generous, and nobler thing to remember and highlight the perfect words than to create inferior ones that temporarily clutter the world. [Ruskin.]
[56] Inferno, 3. 112.
Inferno, 3. 112.
[58] "Well said, old mole! can'st work i' the ground so fast?"—[Ruskin.]
[58] "Well said, old mole! Can you work in the ground so fast?"—[Ruskin.]
[59] Odyssey, 11. 57-58.
Odyssey, 11. 57-58.
[60] It is worth while comparing the way a similar question is put by the exquisite sincerity of Keats:—
[60] It’s interesting to compare how a similar question is expressed through the exquisite sincerity of Keats:—
He wept, and his bright tears
He cried, and his shining tears
Went trickling down the golden bow he held.
Went trickling down the golden bow he held.
Thus, with half-shut, suffused eyes, he stood;
Thus, with half-closed, glazed eyes, he stood;
While from beneath some cumbrous boughs hard by
While from underneath some heavy branches nearby
With solemn step an awful goddess came,
With a serious walk, a terrifying goddess approached,
And there was purport in her looks for him,
And there was meaning in her gaze for him,
Which he with eager guess began to read
Which he eagerly started to read
Perplex'd, the while melodiously he said,
Confused, he said sweetly,
"How cam'st thou over the unfooted sea?"
"How did you get across the untamed sea?"
Hyperion, 3. 42.—[Ruskin.]
Hyperion, 3. 42.—[Ruskin.]
[61] See Wordsworth's Peter Bell, Part I:—
See Wordsworth's Peter Bell, Part I:—
A primrose by a river's brim
A primrose by the edge of a river
A yellow primrose was to him,
A yellow primrose was for him,
And it was nothing more.
And it was just that.
[62] Jude 13.
Jude 13.
[64] Iliad, 3. 243. In the MS. Ruskin notes, "The insurpassably tender irony in the epithet—'life-giving earth'—of the grave"; and then adds another illustration:—"Compare the hammer-stroke at the close of the [32d] chapter of Vanity Fair—'The darkness came down on the field and city, and Amelia was praying for George, who was lying on his face, dead, with a bullet through his heart. A great deal might have been said about it. The writer is very sorry for Amelia, neither does he want faith in prayer. He knows as well as any of us that prayer must be answered in some sort; but those are the facts. The man and woman sixteen miles apart—-one on her knees on the floor, the other on his face in the clay. So much love in her heart, so much lead in his. Make what you can of it." [Cook and Wedderburn.]
[64] Iliad, 3. 243. In the manuscript, Ruskin points out, "The profoundly tender irony in the phrase—'life-giving earth'—when referring to the grave"; and then adds another example:—"Think about the hammer-stroke at the end of the [32d] chapter of Vanity Fair—'The darkness descended on the field and city, and Amelia was praying for George, who was lying on his face, dead, with a bullet through his heart. A lot could be said about it. The author feels very sorry for Amelia, nor does he doubt the power of prayer. He understands, just like the rest of us, that prayer must be answered in some way; but those are the facts. The man and woman sixteen miles apart—one on her knees on the floor, the other on his face in the earth. So much love in her heart, so much lead in his. Interpret it however you like.'" [Cook and Wedderburn.]
[65] The poem may be crudely paraphrased as follows:—
[65] The poem can be roughly rephrased like this:—
"Quick, Anna, quick! to the mirror! It is late,
"Quick, Anna, hurry to the mirror! It's late,
And I'm to dance at the ambassador's ...
And I'm supposed to dance at the ambassador's ...
I'm going to the ball ...
I'm going to the party ...
"They're faded, see,
"They're worn out, see,"
These ribbons—they belong to yesterday.
These ribbons belong to the past.
Heavens, how all things pass! Now gracefully hang
Heavens, how quickly everything changes! Now they hang gracefully
The blue tassels from the net that holds my hair.
The blue tassels from the net that holds my hair.
"Higher!—no, lower!—you get nothing right!...
"Higher!—no, lower!—you got nothing right!..."
Now let this sapphire sparkle on my brow.
Now let this sapphire shine on my forehead.
You're pricking me, you careless thing! That's good!
You're poking me, you careless thing! That's good!
I love you, Anna dear. How fair I am....
I love you, dear Anna. How beautiful I am...
"I hope he'll be there, too—the one I've tried
"I hope he'll be there, too—the one I've tried"
To forget! no use! (Anna, my gown!) he too ...
To forget! No way! (Anna, my dress!) He too ...
(O fie, you wicked girl! my necklace, this?
(O no, you naughty girl! my necklace, this?
These golden beads the Holy Father blessed?)
These golden beads that the Holy Father blessed?
"He'll be there—Heavens! suppose he takes my hand—
"He'll be there—Oh my! What if he takes my hand—
I scarce can draw my breath for thinking of it!
I can barely breathe just thinking about it!
And I confess to Father Anselmo
And I confess to Father Anselmo
To-morrow—how can I ever tell him all?...
To-morrow—how can I ever tell him everything?...
One last glance at the mirror. O, I'm sure
One last look in the mirror. Oh, I'm sure
That they'll adore me at the ball to-night."
That they'll love me at the party tonight."
Before the fire she stands admiringly.
Before the fire, she stands in admiration.
O God! a spark has leapt into her gown.
O God! A spark has jumped into her dress.
Fire, fire!—O run!—Lost thus when mad with hope?
Fire, fire!—Oh, run!—Lost like this when consumed by hope?
What, die? and she so fair? The hideous flames
What, die? And she's so beautiful? The terrible flames
Rage greedily about her arms and breast,
Rage fiercely about her arms and chest,
Envelop her, and leaping ever higher,
Envelop her and keep jumping higher and higher,
Swallow up all her beauty, pitiless—
Swallow up all her beauty, merciless—
Her eighteen years, alas! and her sweet dream.
Her eighteen years, unfortunately! and her sweet dream.
Adieu to ball, to pleasure, and to love!
Goodbye to parties, to fun, and to love!
"Poor Constance!" said the dancers at the ball,
"Poor Constance!" said the dancers at the party,
"Poor Constance!"—and they danced till break of day.
"Poor Constance!"—and they danced until dawn.
[66] Isaiah xiv, 8.
Isaiah 14:8.
[67] Isaiah lv, 12.
Isaiah 55:12.
[69] Pastorals: Summer, or Alexis, 73 ff., with the omission of two couplets after the first.
[69] Pastorals: Summer, or Alexis, 73 ff., with the omission of two couplets after the first.
[70] From the poem beginning 'T is said that some have died for love, Ruskin evidently quoted from memory, for there are several verbal slips in the passage quoted.
[70] From the poem beginning 'It is said that some have died for love, Ruskin clearly quoted from memory, as there are a few verbal errors in the passage quoted.
[71] Stanza 16, of Shenstone's twenty-sixth Elegy.
[71] Stanza 16, of Shenstone's twenty-sixth Elegy.
[73] I cannot quit this subject without giving two more instances, both exquisite, of the pathetic fallacy, which I have just come upon, in Maud:—
[73] I can’t leave this topic without sharing two more examples, both beautiful, of the pathetic fallacy, which I've just found in Maud:—
For a great speculation had fail'd;
For a big gamble had failed;
And ever he mutter'd and madden'd, and ever wann'd with despair;
And he kept murmuring and getting worked up, growing more and more pale with despair;
And out he walk'd, when the wind like a broken worldling wail'd,
And out he walked, when the wind cried like a lost soul,
And the flying gold of the ruin'd woodlands drove thro' the air.
And the golden leaves from the ruined forests swept through the air.
There has fallen a splendid tear
There has fallen a beautiful tear
From the passion-flower at the gate.
From the passionflower at the gate.
The red rose cries, "She is near, she is near!"
The red rose shouts, "She's here, she's here!"
And the white rose weeps, "She is late."
And the white rose cries, "She's late."
The larkspur listens, "I hear, I hear!"
The larkspur listens, "I hear, I hear!"
And the lily whispers, "I wait." [Ruskin.]
And the lily whispers, "I’m waiting."
[76] Iliad, 21. 212-360.
Iliad, 21. 212-360.
[77] Compare Lay of the Last Minstrel, canto i. stanza 15, and canto v. stanza 2. In the first instance, the river-spirit is accurately the Homeric god, only Homer would have believed in it,—Scott did not, at least not altogether. [Ruskin.]
[77] Compare Lay of the Last Minstrel, canto i. stanza 15, and canto v. stanza 2. In the first case, the river spirit matches the Homeric god, except Homer would have believed in it—Scott, at least not entirely. [Ruskin.]
[79] Genesis xxviii, 12; xxxii, 1; xxii, 11; Joshua v, 13 ff.; Judges xiii, 3 ff.
[79] Genesis 28:12; 32:1; 22:11; Joshua 5:13 and following; Judges 13:3 and following.
[83] Compare the exquisite lines of Longfellow on the sunset in The Golden Legend:—
[83] Compare the beautiful lines of Longfellow about the sunset in The Golden Legend:—
The day is done; and slowly from the scene
The day is over; and slowly from the scene
The stooping sun up-gathers his spent shafts.
The setting sun collects its fading rays.
And puts them back into his golden quiver. [Ruskin.]
And puts them back into his golden quiver. [Ruskin.]
[86] Iliad, 4. 141. [Ruskin.]
Iliad, 4. 141. [Ruskin.]
[94] Compare the passage in Dante referred to above, p. 60. [Ruskin.]
[94] Compare the passage in Dante mentioned above, p. 60. [Ruskin.]
[96] Pollards, trees polled or cut back at some height above the ground, producing a thick growth of young branches in a rounded mass.
[96] Pollards are trees that have been trimmed or cut back at a certain height above the ground, resulting in a dense growth of young branches in a rounded shape.
[98] Odyssey, 11. 572; 24. 13. The couch of Ceres, with Homer's usual faithfulness, is made of a ploughed field, 5. 127. [Ruskin.]
[98] Odyssey, 11. 572; 24. 13. The couch of Ceres, true to Homer’s style, is created from a ploughed field, 5. 127. [Ruskin.]
[103] Odyssey, 12. 357. [Ruskin.]
Odyssey, 12. 357. [Ruskin.]
From haunted spring, and dale,
From haunted spring and valley,
Edged with poplar pale. [Ruskin.]
Framed with pale poplar. [Ruskin.]
Hymn on The Morning of Christ's Nativity, 184-185.
Hymn on The Morning of Christ's Nativity, 184-185.
[109] Educated, as we shall see hereafter, first in this school. Turner gave the hackneyed composition a strange power and freshness, in his Glaucus and Scylla. [Ruskin.]
[109] Educated, as we will see later, first in this school. Turner gave the overused theme a unique strength and newness in his Glaucus and Scylla. [Ruskin.]
[110] Flodden, Flodden Field, a plain in Northumberland, famous as the battlefield where James IV of Scotland was defeated by an English army under the Earl of Surrey, Sept. 9, 1513. The sixth canto of Scott's Marmion gives a fairly accurate description of the action.
[110] Flodden, Flodden Field, a flat area in Northumberland, known as the battlefield where James IV of Scotland was beaten by an English army led by the Earl of Surrey on September 9, 1513. The sixth canto of Scott's Marmion provides a pretty accurate account of the events.
Chevy-Chase, a famous old English ballad recounting the incidents of the battle of Otterburn [Aug. 19, 1388] in which the Scots under the Earl of Douglas defeated the English under the Percies.
Chevy-Chase, a well-known old English ballad tells the story of the battle of Otterburn [Aug. 19, 1388], where the Scots led by the Earl of Douglas defeated the English forces under the Percies.
[111] Shenstone's Rural Elegance, 201 ff., quoted with some slight inaccuracies.
[111] Shenstone's Rural Elegance, 201 ff., quoted with a few minor inaccuracies.
[114] Wordsworth's "The world is too much with us."
[114] Wordsworth's "The world is too much with us."
[115] Pre-Raphaelitism, of course, excepted, which is a new phase of art, in no wise considered in this chapter. Blake was sincere, but full of wild creeds, and somewhat diseased in brain. [Ruskin.]
[115] Pre-Raphaelitism, of course, excepted, which is a new phase of art, in no way considered in this chapter. Blake was sincere, but full of wild beliefs, and somewhat troubled in mind. [Ruskin.]
[116] Gower Street, a London street selected as typical of modern ugliness.
[116] Gower Street, a street in London that serves as an example of contemporary ugliness.
Gaspar Poussin [1613-75], a French landscape painter, of the pseudo-classical school.
Gaspar Poussin [1613-75], a French landscape painter from the pseudo-classical school.
[117] Of course this is meant only of the modern citizen or country-gentleman, as compared with a citizen of Sparta or old Florence. I leave it to others to say whether the "neglect of the art of war" may or may not, in a yet more fatal sense, be predicated of the English nation. War, without art, we seem, with God's help, able still to wage nobly. [Ruskin.]
[117] Of course, this is only about the modern citizen or country gentleman, compared to a citizen of Sparta or old Florence. I'll let others determine whether the "neglect of the art of war" could also be applied to the English nation in a more serious way. War, without art, seems to be something we can still fight nobly, with God's help. [Ruskin.]
[118] See David Copperfield, chap. 55 and 58. [Ruskin.]
[118] See David Copperfield, chap. 55 and 58. [Ruskin.]
[119] Ruskin proceeds to discuss Scott as he has discussed Homer. The chapter on Turner that follows here is an almost equally good illustration of Ruskin's ideas.
[119] Ruskin continues to talk about Scott just like he did with Homer. The chapter on Turner that comes next is also a great example of Ruskin's ideas.
[120] c. 1478-1511.
c. 1478-1511.
[121] Dante, alluding to Florence, Paradiso, 25. 5. "From the fair sheepfold, where a lamb I slumbered." Longfellow's tr.
[121] Dante, referring to Florence, Paradiso, 25. 5. "From the beautiful sheepfold, where I slept as a lamb." Longfellow's tr.
[122] Allusions to pictures by Turner, The Garden of the Hesperides, and The Meuse: Orange-Merchantman going to pieces on the Bar.
[122] Allusions to paintings by Turner, The Garden of the Hesperides, and The Meuse: Orange merchant ship breaking apart on the bar.
[123] The pictures referred to are: The Death of Nelson, The Battle of Trafalgar, and The Fighting Téméraire being towed to its Last Berth (see cut). The first and third are in the National Gallery, London.
[123] The pictures mentioned are: The Death of Nelson, The Battle of Trafalgar, and The Fighting Téméraire being towed to its Last Berth (see cut). The first and third are in the National Gallery, London.
[125] Santa Maria della Salute, a church conspicuously situated at the junction of the Grand Canal and the Giudecca.
[125] Santa Maria della Salute, a church prominently located at the intersection of the Grand Canal and the Giudecca.
[126] Liber Studiorum. "Interior of a church." It is worthy of remark that Giorgione and Titian are always delighted to have an opportunity of drawing priests. The English Church may, perhaps, accept it as matter of congratulation that this is the only instance in which Turner drew a clergyman. [Ruskin.]
[126] Liber Studiorum. "Inside a church." It’s worth noting that Giorgione and Titian always enjoy the chance to draw priests. The Church of England might consider it a point of celebration that this is the only time Turner drew a clergyman. [Ruskin.]
[127] 1785.
1785.
[128] Wolsey's famous palace, twelve miles from London.
[128] Wolsey's renowned palace, twelve miles from London.
[129] I do not mean that this is his first acquaintance with the country, but the first impressive and touching one, after his mind was formed. The earliest sketches I found in the National Collection are at Clifton and Bristol; the next, at Oxford. [Ruskin.]
[129] I don't mean that this is his first experience with the country, but it's the first one that really struck him and moved him, after he had developed his understanding. The earliest drawings I found in the National Collection are from Clifton and Bristol; the next ones are from Oxford. [Ruskin.]
[130] The reference is to the two famous ruined abbeys of Yorkshire—Whitby and Bolton.
[130] The reference is to the two well-known ruined abbeys in Yorkshire—Whitby and Bolton.
[133] Dürer [1471-1528], German painter, engraver, and designer. Salvator [1615-73], Italian painter, etcher, satirical poet, and musical composer.
[133] Dürer [1471-1528], German painter, engraver, and designer. Salvator [1615-73], Italian painter, etcher, satirical poet, and musical composer.
[134] I.e., between November 17, 1796, and June 18, 1815.
[134] That is, between November 17, 1796, and June 18, 1815.
[136] The palace of the Camerlenghi, beside the Rialto, is a graceful work of the early Renaissance (1525) passing into Roman Renaissance. [Adapted from Ruskin.]
[136] The Camerlenghi palace, next to the Rialto, is an elegant piece of early Renaissance architecture (1525) transitioning into the Roman Renaissance. [Adapted from Ruskin.]
[138] See note 1, p. 129.
See note 1, p. 129.
[141] Dandolo [c. 1108-1205] and Foscari [1372-1457] were among the most famous of Venetian Doges.
[141] Dandolo [c. 1108-1205] and Foscari [1372-1457] were some of the most well-known Doges of Venice.
[142] In the battle of Custozza, 1848, the Austrians defeated the Piedmontese.
[142] In the battle of Custozza, 1848, the Austrians defeated the Piedmontese.
[144] The reader who desires to investigate it may consult Galliciolli, Delle Memorie Venete (Venice, 1795), tom. 2, p. 332, and the authorities quoted by him. [Ruskin.]
[144] The reader who wants to explore this further can check out Galliciolli, Delle Memorie Venete (Venice, 1795), vol. 2, p. 332, and the references he cites. [Ruskin.]
[146] A wonderful City, such as was never seen before.
[146] A remarkable city, unlike anything seen before.
[147] St. Mark's Place, "partly covered by turf, and planted with a few trees; and on account of its pleasant aspect called Brollo or Broglio, that is to say, Garden." The canal passed through it, over which is built the bridge of the Malpassi. Galliciolli, lib. I, cap. viii. [Ruskin.]
[147] St. Mark's Place, "partly covered with grass and dotted with a few trees; because of its nice look, it's called Brollo or Broglio, meaning Garden." The canal flows through it, over which the Malpassi bridge is built. Galliciolli, lib. I, cap. viii. [Ruskin.]
[148] My authorities for this statement are given below, in the chapter on the Ducal Palace. [Ruskin.]
[148] My sources for this statement are listed below, in the chapter on the Ducal Palace. [Ruskin.]
[149] In the Chronicles, Sancti Marci Ducalis Cappdla. [Ruskin.]
[149] In the Chronicles, Saint Mark's Ducal Chapel. [Ruskin.]
[150] "To God the Lord, the glorious Virgin Annunciate, and the Protector St. Mark."—Corner, p. 14. It is needless to trouble the reader with the various authorities for the above statements: I have consulted the best. The previous inscription once existing on the church itself:
[150] "To God the Lord, the glorious Virgin Annunciate, and the Protector St. Mark."—Corner, p. 14. There's no need to bother the reader with the different sources for the statements above: I've checked the most reliable ones. The earlier inscription that used to be on the church itself:
Anno milleno transacto bisque trigeno Desuper undecimo fuit facta primo,
Anno milleno transacto bisque trigeno Desuper undecimo fuit facta primo,
is no longer to be seen, and is conjectured by Corner, with much probability, to have perished "in qualche ristauro." [Ruskin.]
is no longer visible and is thought by Corner, with a good chance of being right, to have been lost "during some restoration." [Ruskin.]
[151] Signed Bartolomeus Bozza, 1634, 1647, 1656, etc. [Ruskin.]
[151] Signed Bartolomeus Bozza, 1634, 1647, 1656, etc. [Ruskin.]
[152] An obvious slip. The mosaic is on the west wall of the south transept. [Cook and Wedderburn.]
[152] An obvious mistake. The mosaic is located on the west wall of the south transept. [Cook and Wedderburn.]
[154] Fritters and liquors for sale.
Fritters and drinks available.
[157] The third kind of ornament, the Renaissance, is that in which the inferior detail becomes principal, the executor of every minor portion being required to exhibit skill and possess knowledge as great as that which is possessed by the master of the design; and in the endeavour to endow him with this skill and knowledge, his own original power is overwhelmed, and the whole building becomes a wearisome exhibition of well-educated imbecility. We must fully inquire into the nature of this form of error, when we arrive at the examination of the Renaissance schools. [Ruskin.]
[157] The third type of ornamentation, the Renaissance, is when the less important details take center stage, requiring every person working on the minor elements to demonstrate skills and knowledge as significant as that of the master designer. In trying to give them this skill and expertise, their own unique abilities get stifled, and the entire building ends up being a tiring display of well-trained incompetence. We need to thoroughly investigate this kind of mistake when we look into the Renaissance schools. [Ruskin.]
[158] Job xix, 26.
Job 19:26
[160] Vide Preface to Fair Maid of Perth. [Ruskin.]
[160] Vide Preface to Fair Maid of Perth. [Ruskin.]
[161] The Elgin marbles are supposed by many persons to be "perfect". In the most important portions they indeed approach perfection, but only there. The draperies are unfinished, the hair and wool of the animals are unfinished, and the entire bas-reliefs of the frieze are roughly cut. [Ruskin.]
[161] The Elgin marbles are considered by many people to be "perfect." In the most significant parts, they really do come close to perfection, but only in those areas. The drapery isn't complete, the hair and wool of the animals are incomplete, and the entire bas-reliefs of the frieze are roughly carved. [Ruskin.]
[164] See pp. 225 ff.
See pp. 225 and following.
[165] In heartfelt trust Johannes Mooter and Maria Rubi had this house erected. May dear God shield us from all perils and misfortune; and let His blessing rest upon it during the journey through this wretched life up to heavenly Paradise where the pious dwell. There will God reward them with the Crown of Peace to all eternity.
[165] In sincere trust, Johannes Mooter and Maria Rubi had this house built. May God protect us from all dangers and misfortunes; and may His blessings be upon it as we navigate this difficult life toward the heavenly Paradise where the faithful reside. There, God will reward them with the Crown of Peace for all eternity.
[166] Baptistery of Pisa, circular, of marble, with dome two hundred feet high, embellished with numerous columns, is a notable work of the twelfth century. The pulpit is a masterpiece of Nicola Pisano. Casa d'Oro at Venice is noted for its elegance. It was built in the fourteenth century. The Cathedral of Lisieux dates chiefly from the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, and contains many works of art. The Palais de Justice is of the fifteenth century. It was built for the Parliament of the Province.
[166] The Baptistery of Pisa is a circular, marble structure with a dome that reaches two hundred feet high, adorned with numerous columns. It's a remarkable piece from the twelfth century. The pulpit inside is a masterpiece by Nicola Pisano. Casa d'Oro in Venice is known for its elegance and was constructed in the fourteenth century. The Cathedral of Lisieux primarily dates back to the twelfth and thirteenth centuries and features many works of art. The Palais de Justice was built in the fifteenth century for the Parliament of the Province.
[167] This cathedral, destroyed in 1799, was one of the most beautiful in all Normandy.
[167] This cathedral, which was destroyed in 1799, was one of the most beautiful in all of Normandy.
[168] Dante.
Dante.
[169] Coleridge's Ode to France.
Coleridge's *Ode to France*.
[170] Hubert Van Eyck [1366-1440]. The great Flemish master.
[170] Hubert Van Eyck [1366-1440]. The amazing Flemish master.
[173] The tool of the engraver on copper.
The engraver's tool for copper.
[174] See Paradise Lost, 6. 207 ff., and Hesiod's Theogony, 676 ff.
[174] See Paradise Lost, 6. 207 ff., and Hesiod's Theogony, 676 ff.
[177] "Forward go the banners of the King," or more commonly, "The royal banners forward go." One of the seven great hymns of the Church. See the Episcopal Hymnal, 94.
[177] "The king's banners move forward," or more commonly, "The royal banners move forward." One of the seven great hymns of the Church. See the Episcopal Hymnal, 94.
[178] Dante, Inferno, 3. 60. "Who made through cowardice the great refusal." Longfellow's tr.
[178] Dante, Inferno, 3. 60. "Who out of fear chose to reject the great opportunity." Longfellow's tr.
[179] Lyridas, 109.
Lyridas, 109.
[180] Nelson's famous signal at Trafalgar.
Nelson's famous message at Trafalgar.
[181] Milton's Il Penseroso, 170 ff.
Milton's Il Penseroso, line 170 ff.
[183] As Slade Professor, Ruskin held a three years' appointment at Oxford.
[183] As the Slade Professor, Ruskin had a three-year appointment at Oxford.
[184] This story comes from Pliny, Natural History, 35. 36; the two rival painters alternately showing their skill by the drawing of lines of increasing fineness.
[184] This story comes from Pliny, Natural History, 35. 36; the two competing painters taking turns to demonstrate their talent by drawing lines that get finer and finer.
[185] This story comes from Vasari's Lives of the Painters. See Blashfield and Hopkins's ed. vol. 1, p. 61. Giotto was asked by a messenger of the Pope for a specimen of his work, and sent a perfect circle, drawn free hand.
[185] This story comes from Vasari's Lives of the Painters. See Blashfield and Hopkins's ed. vol. 1, p. 61. Giotto was asked by a messenger from the Pope for a sample of his work, and he sent back a perfect circle, drawn by hand.
[187] In Modern Painters, vol. 1.
In *Modern Painters*, vol. 1.
[188] The quotation is from Vasari's account of Angelico's Last Judgment (now in the Accademia at Florence). [Cook and Wedderbum.]
[188] The quote is from Vasari's description of Angelico's Last Judgment (currently in the Accademia in Florence). [Cook and Wedderbum.]
[192] The name of St. George, the "Earthworker," or "Husbandman." [Ruskin.]
[192] The name of St. George, the "Earthworker," or "Farming Man." [Ruskin.]
[197] Genesis xxiv, 15, 16 and xxix, 10; Exodus ii, 16; John iv, 11.
[197] Genesis 24:15-16 and 29:10; Exodus 2:16; John 4:11.
[198] Osborne Gordon. [Ruskin.]
Osborne Gordon. [Ruskin.]
[199] The Flamboyant Architecture of the Valley of the Somme, a lecture delivered at the Royal Institution, January 29, 1869.
[199] The Flamboyant Architecture of the Valley of the Somme, a lecture given at the Royal Institution, January 29, 1869.
[200] The elaborate pediment above the central porch at the west end of Rouen Cathedral, pierced into a transparent web of tracery, and enriched with a border of "twisted eglantine." [Ruskin.]
[200] The intricate pediment above the main entrance at the west end of Rouen Cathedral, cut into a delicate network of tracery, and embellished with a border of "twisted wild rose." [Ruskin.]
[202] Delivered in the Town Hall, Bradford, April 21, 1864.
[202] Delivered in the Town Hall, Bradford, April 21, 1864.
[204] Scott's Lay of the Last Minstrel, canto 1, stanza 4.
[204] Scott's Lay of the Last Minstrel, canto 1, stanza 4.
[205] The reference was to the reluctance of this country to take arms in defence of Denmark against Prussia and Austria. [Cook and Wedderburn.]
[205] The reference was about this country's unwillingness to take up arms to defend Denmark against Prussia and Austria. [Cook and Wedderburn.]
[207] Inigo Jones [1573-1652] and Sir Christopher Wren [1632-1723] were the best known architects of their respective generations.
[207] Inigo Jones [1573-1652] and Sir Christopher Wren [1632-1723] were the most famous architects of their times.
[211] And all other arts, for the most part; even of incredulous and secularly-minded commonalties. [Ruskin.]
[211] And most other arts too; even among those who are skeptical and focused on the material world. [Ruskin.]
[213] For further interpretation of Greek mythology see Ruskin's Queen of the Air.
[213] For more insights into Greek mythology, check out Ruskin's Queen of the Air.
[214] It is an error to suppose that the Greek worship, or seeking, was chiefly of Beauty. It was essentially of Rightness and Strength, founded on Forethought: the principal character of Greek art is not beauty, but design: and the Dorian Apollo-worship and Athenian Virgin-worship are both expressions of adoration of divine wisdom and purity. Next to these great deities, rank, in power over the national mind, Dionysus and Ceres, the givers of human strength and life; then, for heroic example, Hercules. There is no Venus-worship among the Greeks in the great times: and the Muses are essentially teachers of Truth, and of its harmonies. [Ruskin.]
[214] It’s a mistake to think that Greek worship or pursuit was mostly about Beauty. It was fundamentally about Rightness and Strength, rooted in Forethought: the main focus of Greek art is not beauty but design. The worship of Dorian Apollo and Athenian Virgin both express admiration for divine wisdom and purity. Following these major deities, there’s Dionysus and Ceres, who represent human strength and life; and then, as a heroic example, Hercules. There’s no worship of Venus among the Greeks in the great times, and the Muses are fundamentally teachers of Truth and its harmonies. [Ruskin.]
[215] Tetzel's trading in Papal indulgences aroused Luther to the protest which ended in the Reformation.
[215] Tetzel's sale of Papal indulgences sparked Luther's protest that led to the Reformation.
[217] Jeremiah xvii, 11 (best in Septuagint and Vulgate). "As the partridge, fostering what she brought not forth, so he that getteth riches not by right shall leave them in the midst of his days, and at his end shall be a fool." [Ruskin.]
[217] Jeremiah xvii, 11 (best in Septuagint and Vulgate). "Like the partridge that hatches eggs it didn’t lay, the one who gains wealth unfairly will lose it in the prime of life and will be a fool in the end." [Ruskin.]
[218] Meaning, fully, "We have brought our pigs to it." [Ruskin.]
[218] Meaning, fully, "We have brought our pigs to it." [Ruskin.]
[220] Referring to a lecture on Modern Manufacture and Design, delivered at Bradford, March 1, 1859 published later as Lecture III in The Two Paths.
[220] Referring to a lecture on Modern Manufacture and Design, delivered at Bradford on March 1, 1859, later published as Lecture III in The Two Paths.
[223] A beautiful ruin in Yorkshire.
A gorgeous ruin in Yorkshire.
[231] I have sometimes been asked what this means. I intended it to set forth the wisdom of men in war contending for kingdoms, and what follows to set forth their wisdom in peace, contending for wealth. [Ruskin.]
[231] I’ve been asked what this means. I meant it to show the wisdom of people in war fighting for kingdoms, and what follows is meant to highlight their wisdom in peace, fighting for wealth. [Ruskin.]
[232] See Wordsworth's poem, My heart leaps up when I behold.
[232] See Wordsworth's poem, My heart leaps up when I see.
[233] See Genesis ii, 15, and the opening lines of the first selection in this volume.
[233] See Genesis 2:15, and the opening lines of the first selection in this volume.
[235] In his Discourses on Art. Cf. pp. 24 ff. above.
[235] In his Discourses on Art. See pp. 24 ff. above.
[237] References mainly to the Irish Land Question, on which Ruskin agreed with Mill and Gladstone in advocating the establishment of a peasant-proprietorship in Ireland.
[237] References mainly to the Irish Land Question, where Ruskin aligned with Mill and Gladstone in supporting the creation of a peasant-proprietorship in Ireland.
[241] During the famine in the Indian province of Orissa.
[241] During the famine in the Indian state of Odisha.
[242] Athena, goddess of weaving.
Athena, goddess of weaving.
[255] Dies Iræ, the name generally given (from the opening words) to the most famous of the mediæval hymns, usually ascribed to the Franciscan Thomas of Celano (died c. 1255). It is composed in triplets of rhyming trochaic tetrameters, and describes the Last Judgment in language of magnificent grandeur, passing into a plaintive plea for the souls of the dead.
[255] Dies Iræ is the name commonly given (from the opening words) to the most renowned medieval hymns, typically attributed to the Franciscan Thomas of Celano (who died around 1255). It is written in triplets of rhyming trochaic tetrameters and depicts the Last Judgment in a grand and magnificent way, transitioning into a heartfelt request for the souls of the deceased.
[258] Isaiah lviii, 7.
Isaiah 58:7.
[261] 1 Corinthians xiii, 13.
1 Corinthians 13:13.
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!