This is a modern-English version of The Works of the Right Honourable Edmund Burke, Vol. 03 (of 12), originally written by Burke, Edmund. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.



THE WORKS

OF

THE RIGHT HONOURABLE

EDMUND BURKE

IN TWELVE VOLUMES

VOLUME 3

London

JOHN C. NIMMO

14, KING WILLIAM STREET, STRAND, W.C.

MDCCCLXXXVII

London

JOHN C. NIMMO

14 KING WILLIAM STREET, STRAND, W.C.

1887


CONTENTS OF VOL. III.


SPEECH

ON THE

MOTION MADE FOR PAPERS

IN RELATION TO THE

INSTRUCTIONS FOR CHARGING THE NABOB OF ARCOT'S PRIVATE DEBTS TO EUROPEANS FROM THE REVENUES OF THE CARNATIC,

FEB 28, 1785.

WITH AN APPENDIX,

CONTAINS MULTIPLE DOCUMENTS.

Ἐνταῦθα τί πράττειν ἐχρῆν ἄνδρα τῶν Πλάτωνος καὶ Ἀριστοτέλους ζηλωτὴν δογμάτων; ἆρα περιορᾶν ἀνθρώπους ἀθλίους τοῖς κλέπταις ἐκδιδομένους, ἢ κατὰ δύναμιν αὐτοῖς ἀμύνειν, οἶμαι ὡς ἤδη τὸ κύκνειον; ἐξᾴδουσι διὰ τὸ θεμισές ἐργαστήριον τῶν τοιούτων; Ἐμοὶ μὲν οὖν αἰσχρὸν εἶναι δοκεῖ τοὺς μὲν χιλιάρχους, ὅταν λείπωσι τὴν τάξιν, καταδικάζειν' ... τὴν δὲ ὑπέρ ἀθλίων ἀνθρώπων ἀπολείπειν τάξιν, ὅταν δὲῃ πρὸς κλέπτας ἀγωνίζεσθαι τοιούτους, καὶ ταῦτα τοῦ θεοῦ συμμαχοῦντος ἡμῖν, ὅσπερ οὖν ἔταξεν.

What should a follower of Plato and Aristotle do? Should we restrict the unfortunate individuals who are vulnerable to thieves, or should we protect them to the best of our ability? It feels like a swan’s final song; they’re being pushed out to make room for a workshop for these people. It seems shameful to criticize the leaders when they fail in their duties... yet to abandon the order concerning the unfortunate when it’s time to stand against such thieves, especially with God supporting us, as he has planned.

JULIANI Epist. 17.

JULIANI Epist. 17.


ADVERTISEMENT.

That the least informed reader of this speech may be enabled to enter fully into the spirit of the transaction on occasion of which it was delivered, it may be proper to acquaint him, that, among the princes dependent on this nation in the southern part of India, the most considerable at present is commonly known by the title of the Nabob of Arcot.

To help even the least informed reader understand the context of this speech, it’s important to note that among the princes who rely on this nation in southern India, the most notable one currently is usually referred to as the Nabob of Arcot.

This prince owed the establishment of his government, against the claims of his elder brother, as well as those of other competitors, to the arms and influence of the British East India Company. Being thus established in a considerable part of the dominions he now possesses, he began, about the year 1765, to form, at the instigation (as he asserts) of the servants of the East India Company, a variety of designs for the further extension of his territories. Some years after, he carried his views to certain objects of interior arrangement, of a very pernicious nature. None of these designs could be compassed without the aid of the Company's arms; nor could those arms be employed consistently with an obedience to the Company's orders. He was therefore advised to form a more secret, but an equally powerful, interest among the servants of that Company, and among others both at home and abroad. By engaging them in his interests, the use of the Company's power might be obtained without their ostensible authority; the power might even be employed in defiance of the authority, if the case should require, as in truth it often did require, a proceeding of that degree of boldness.

This prince established his government, despite the claims of his older brother and other rivals, thanks to the support and influence of the British East India Company. With his rule solidified over a significant portion of his current territories, he began around 1765, under the encouragement (as he claims) of the Company's officials, to create various plans to expand his lands. Several years later, he turned his attention to certain internal arrangements that were quite harmful. None of these plans could succeed without the Company's military support, and using that military support would conflict with the Company's orders. He was therefore advised to build a more discreet but equally strong alliance with the Company's agents and others both domestically and internationally. By aligning their interests with his, he could utilize the Company's power without their explicit authority; in fact, that power could even be used against the authority when necessary, which, as it turned out, often was needed.

The Company had put him into possession of several great cities and magnificent castles. The good order of his affairs, his sense of personal dignity, his ideas of Oriental splendor, and the habits of an Asiatic life, (to which, being a native of India, and a Mahometan, he had from his infancy been inured,) would naturally have led him to fix the seat of his government within his own dominions. Instead of this, he totally sequestered himself from his country, and, abandoning all appearance of state, he took up his residence in an ordinary house, which he purchased in the suburbs of the Company's factory at Madras. In that place he has lived, without removing one day from thence, for several years past. He has there continued a constant cabal with the Company's servants, from the highest to the lowest,—creating, out of the ruins of the country, brilliant fortunes for those who will, and entirely destroying those who will not, be subservient to his purposes.

The Company had given him control over several major cities and impressive castles. His organized affairs, sense of personal pride, views on Eastern luxury, and lifestyle habits (which he had been accustomed to since childhood as a native of India and a Muslim) would normally lead him to establish his government within his own territory. Instead, he completely separated himself from his homeland and, giving up all pretenses of power, settled into a regular house he bought in the suburbs of the Company's factory in Madras. He has lived there, without leaving for even a day, for several years now. There, he has maintained a constant alliance with the Company’s employees, from the highest to the lowest, building dazzling fortunes for those who align with him and utterly ruining those who do not serve his interests.

An opinion prevailed, strongly confirmed by several passages in his own letters, as well as by a combination of circumstances forming a body of evidence which cannot be resisted, that very great sums have been by him distributed, through a long course of years, to some of the Company's servants. Besides these presumed payments in ready money, (of which, from the nature of the thing, the direct proof is very difficult,) debts have at several periods been acknowledged to those gentlemen, to an immense amount,—that is, to some millions of sterling money. There is strong reason to suspect that the body of these debts is wholly fictitious, and was never created by money bonâ fide lent. But even on a supposition that this vast sum was really advanced, it was impossible that the very reality of such an astonishing transaction should not cause some degree of alarm and incite to some sort of inquiry.

An opinion has emerged, strongly supported by several excerpts from his own letters, along with a mix of circumstances that create undeniable evidence, suggesting that he has distributed very large amounts of money over many years to some of the Company’s employees. In addition to these supposed cash payments, which are hard to prove directly due to their nature, debts have been recognized at various times by those gentlemen, amounting to an enormous sum—essentially millions of pounds. There is strong reason to suspect that these debts are entirely fake and were never created by money actually lent. However, even if we assume that this vast sum was truly given, the reality of such an astonishing transaction would undoubtedly raise concerns and prompt some investigation.

It was not at all seemly, at a moment when the Company itself was so distressed as to require a suspension, by act of Parliament, of the payment of bills drawn on them from India,—and also a direct tax upon every house in England, in order to facilitate the vent of their goods, and to avoid instant insolvency,—at that very moment, that their servants should appear in so flourishing a condition, as, besides ten millions of other demands on their masters, to be entitled to claim a debt of three or four millions more from the territorial revenue of one of their dependent princes.

It was completely inappropriate, at a time when the Company was so distressed that it required an act of Parliament to suspend payments on bills drawn from India—and also a direct tax on every house in England to help sell their goods and avoid immediate bankruptcy—that their employees should seem to be in such a prosperous situation that, on top of ten million other demands on their bosses, they could also claim a debt of three or four million more from the revenue of one of their dependent princes.

The ostensible pecuniary transactions of the Nabob of Arcot with very private persons are so enormous, that they evidently set aside every pretence of policy which might induce a prudent government in some instances to wink at ordinary loose practice in ill-managed departments. No caution could be too great in handling this matter, no scrutiny too exact. It was evidently the interest, and as evidently at least in the power, of the creditors, by admitting secret participation in this dark and undefined concern, to spread corruption to the greatest and the most alarming extent.

The apparent financial dealings of the Nabob of Arcot with private individuals are so vast that they clearly undermine any claims of policy that might lead a cautious government to overlook typical mishandling in poorly managed departments. No level of caution is too great in dealing with this issue, and no examination is too thorough. It was clearly in the interest, and just as clearly within the capability, of the creditors, by allowing hidden involvement in this shady and ambiguous matter, to spread corruption to the widest and most alarming degree.

These facts relative to the debts were so notorious, the opinion of their being a principal source of the disorders of the British government in India was so undisputed and universal, that there was no party, no description of men in Parliament, who did not think themselves bound, if not in honor and conscience, at least in common decency, to institute a vigorous inquiry into the very bottom of the business, before they admitted any part of that vast and suspicious charge to be laid upon an exhausted country. Every plan concurred in directing such an inquiry, in order that whatever was discovered to be corrupt, fraudulent, or oppressive should lead to a due animadversion on the offenders, and, if anything fair and equitable in its origin should be found, (nobody suspected that much, comparatively speaking, would be so found,) it might be provided for,—in due subordination, however, to the ease of the subject and the service of the state.

These facts about the debts were so well-known, and the belief that they were a main cause of the problems in the British government in India was so accepted and widespread, that there was no group or type of people in Parliament who didn't feel obligated, if not out of honor and conscience, then at least out of basic decency, to start a thorough investigation into the matter before they accepted any part of that huge and questionable burden being placed on a weary country. Every plan agreed on pursuing such an investigation so that any corruption, fraud, or oppression discovered would result in appropriate action against those responsible, and if anything fair and just in its origin was found (though no one expected that much would be), it could be addressed—however, it should be done with respect to the well-being of the people and the interests of the state.

These were the alleged grounds for an inquiry, settled in all the bills brought into Parliament relative to India,—and there were, I think, no less than four of them. By the bill commonly called Mr. Pitt's bill, the inquiry was specially, and by express words, committed to the Court of Directors, without any reserve for the interference of any other person or persons whatsoever. It was ordered that they should make the inquiry into the origin and justice of these debts, as far as the materials in their possession enabled them to proceed; and where they found those materials deficient, they should order the Presidency of Fort St. George (Madras) to complete the inquiry.

These were the supposed reasons for an investigation, included in all the bills presented to Parliament regarding India—and I believe there were at least four of them. According to the bill commonly known as Mr. Pitt's bill, the investigation was specifically and explicitly assigned to the Court of Directors, without allowing any other individual or individuals to interfere. It was mandated that they should look into the origins and fairness of these debts, as much as the information in their possession allowed them to proceed; and where they found that information lacking, they should instruct the Presidency of Fort St. George (Madras) to complete the investigation.

The Court of Directors applied themselves to the execution of the trust reposed in them. They first examined into the amount of the debt, which they computed, at compound interest, to be 2,945,600l. sterling. Whether their mode of computation, either of the original sums or the amount on compound interest, was exact, that is, whether they took the interest too high or the several capitals too low, is not material. On whatever principle any of the calculations were made up, none of them found the debt to differ from the recital of the act, which asserted that the sums claimed were "very large." The last head of these debts the Directors compute at 2,465,680l. sterling. Of the existence of this debt the Directors heard nothing until 1776, and they say, that, "although they had repeatedly written to the Nabob of Arcot, and to their servants, respecting the debt, yet they had never been able to trace the origin thereof, or to obtain any satisfactory information on the subject."

The Court of Directors focused on carrying out the trust placed in them. They first looked into the total debt, which they calculated, with compound interest, to be £2,945,600. Whether their method of calculation, either regarding the original amounts or the compound interest, was accurate—specifically, whether they overestimated the interest or underestimated the principal—is not important. Regardless of how any of the calculations were made, they all confirmed that the debt matched the statement in the act, which claimed the amounts owed were "very large." The Directors estimated the last portion of these debts at £2,465,680. They didn't become aware of this debt until 1776 and stated that "even though they had repeatedly written to the Nabob of Arcot and their staff about the debt, they had never been able to trace its origin or obtain any satisfactory information on the subject."

The Court of Directors, after stating the circumstances under which the debts appeared to them to have been contracted, add as follows:—"For these reasons we should have thought it our duty to inquire very minutely into those debts, even if the act of Parliament had been silent on the subject, before we concurred in any measure for their payment. But with the positive injunctions of the act before us to examine into their nature and origin, we are indispensably bound to direct such an inquiry to be instituted." They then order the President and Council of Madras to enter into a full examination, &c., &c.

The Court of Directors, after explaining the circumstances in which the debts seemed to have been incurred, state: “For these reasons, we would have felt it necessary to investigate those debts very closely, even if the act of Parliament hadn’t addressed the issue, before we agreed to any action regarding their payment. However, with the explicit requirements of the act in front of us to look into their nature and origin, we are absolutely required to initiate such an inquiry.” They then instruct the President and Council of Madras to conduct a thorough examination, etc., etc.

The Directors, having drawn up their order to the Presidency on these principles, communicated the draught of the general letter in which those orders were contained to the board of his Majesty's ministers, and other servants lately constituted by Mr. Pitt's East India Act. These ministers, who had just carried through Parliament the bill ordering a specific inquiry, immediately drew up another letter, on a principle directly opposite to that which was prescribed by the act of Parliament and followed by the Directors. In these second orders, all idea of an inquiry into the justice and origin of the pretended debts, particularly of the last, the greatest, and the most obnoxious to suspicion, is abandoned. They are all admitted and established without any investigation whatsoever, (except some private conference with the agents of the claimants is to pass for an investigation,) and a fund for their discharge is assigned and set apart out of the revenues of the Carnatic. To this arrangement in favor of their servants, servants suspected of corruption and convicted of disobedience, the Directors of the East India Company were ordered to set their hands, asserting it to arise from their own conviction and opinion, in flat contradiction to their recorded sentiments, their strong remonstrance, and their declared sense of their duty, as well under their general trust and their oath as Directors, as under the express injunctions of an act of Parliament.

The Directors, after putting together their instructions for the Presidency based on these principles, shared a draft of the general letter containing those instructions with the board of His Majesty's ministers and other officials recently appointed by Mr. Pitt's East India Act. These ministers, who had just passed a bill in Parliament calling for a specific inquiry, quickly drafted another letter that was based on a principle completely opposite to the one established by the act of Parliament and followed by the Directors. In these new orders, any investigation into the legitimacy and origins of the alleged debts, especially the last one, which was the largest and most questionable, was completely dropped. All these debts were accepted and confirmed without any investigation at all (aside from some private discussions with the claimants' agents, which counted as an investigation), and a fund for their payment was allocated from the revenues of the Carnatic. The East India Company Directors were instructed to sign this arrangement that favored their officials, who were suspected of corruption and found guilty of disobedience, claiming it was their own belief and opinion, completely contradicting their previously stated views, their strong objections, and their clear understanding of their responsibilities under their general trust and oath as Directors, as well as under the specific requirements of an act of Parliament.

The principles upon which this summary proceeding was adopted by the ministerial board are stated by themselves in a number in the appendix to this speech.

The principles that led the ministerial board to adopt this summary proceeding are outlined by them in a section in the appendix of this speech.

By another section of the same act, the same Court of Directors were ordered to take into consideration and to decide on the indeterminate rights of the Rajah of Tanjore and the Nabob of Arcot; and in this, as in the former case, no power of appeal, revision, or alteration was reserved to any other. It was a jurisdiction, in a cause between party and party, given to the Court of Directors specifically. It was known that the territories of the former of these princes had been twice invaded and pillaged, and the prince deposed and imprisoned, by the Company's servants, influenced by the intrigues of the latter, and for the purpose of paying his pretended debts. The Company had, in the year 1775, ordered a restoration of the Rajah to his government, under certain conditions. The Rajah complained, that his territories had not been completely restored to him, and that no part of his goods, money, revenues, or records, unjustly taken and withheld from him, were ever returned. The Nabob, on the other hand, never ceased to claim the country itself, and carried on a continued train of negotiation, that it should again be given up to him, in violation of the Company's public faith.

By another section of the same act, the same Court of Directors was instructed to consider and decide on the indefinite rights of the Rajah of Tanjore and the Nabob of Arcot; and in this case, as in the previous one, no right of appeal, revision, or alteration was reserved for anyone else. It was a jurisdiction, in a dispute between parties, specifically granted to the Court of Directors. It was known that the territories of the former prince had been invaded and looted twice, and the prince had been deposed and imprisoned by the Company’s servants, who were influenced by the intrigues of the latter, all to settle his supposed debts. In 1775, the Company ordered the Rajah to be restored to his government under certain conditions. The Rajah complained that his territories had not been fully returned, and that none of his goods, money, revenues, or records, which were taken from him unjustly, had ever been returned. The Nabob, on the other hand, continually claimed ownership of the land itself and engaged in ongoing negotiations to have it returned to him, violating the Company’s public trust.

The Directors, in obedience to this part of the act, ordered an inquiry, and came to a determination to restore certain of his territories to the Rajah. The ministers, proceeding as in the former case, without hearing any party, rescinded the decision of the Directors, refused the restitution of the territory, and, without regard to the condition of the country of Tanjore, which had been within a few years four times plundered, (twice by the Nabob of Arcot, and twice by enemies brought upon it solely by the politics of the same Nabob, the declared enemy of that people,) and without discounting a shilling for their sufferings, they accumulate an arrear of about four hundred thousand pounds of pretended tribute to this enemy; and then they order the Directors to put their hands to a new adjudication, directly contrary to a judgment in a judicial character and trust solemnly given by them and entered on their records.

The Directors, following this part of the law, ordered an investigation and decided to return some of his territories to the Rajah. The ministers, acting as they did before, without listening to any side, overturned the Directors' decision, denied the return of the territory, and, without considering the situation in Tanjore—which had been looted four times in recent years (twice by the Nabob of Arcot and twice by enemies brought in solely due to the politics of the same Nabob, who was openly hostile to that community)—and without factoring in any compensation for their hardships, they piled up an alleged debt of about four hundred thousand pounds in tribute to this enemy. Then, they instructed the Directors to engage in a new ruling that went directly against a formal judicial decision they had previously issued and recorded.

These proceedings naturally called for some inquiry. On the 28th of February, 1785, Mr. Fox made the following motion in the House of Commons, after moving that the clauses of the act should be read:—"That the proper officer do lay before this House copies or extracts of all letters and orders of the Court of Directors of the United East India Company, in pursuance of the injunctions contained in the 37th and 38th clauses of the said act"; and the question being put, it passed in the negative by a very great majority.

These proceedings obviously required some investigation. On February 28, 1785, Mr. Fox made the following motion in the House of Commons, after requesting that the clauses of the act be read:—"That the appropriate officer should present to this House copies or extracts of all letters and orders from the Court of Directors of the United East India Company, in accordance with the instructions in the 37th and 38th clauses of the said act"; and when the question was raised, it was voted down by a significant majority.

The last speech in the debate was the following; which is given to the public, not as being more worthy of its attention than others, (some of which were of consummate ability,) but as entering more into the detail of the subject.

The last speech in the debate was the following; it's presented to the public not because it's more deserving of attention than others (some of which were exceptionally skilled), but because it goes into more detail about the subject.


SPEECH.

The times we live in, Mr. Speaker, have been distinguished by extraordinary events. Habituated, however, as we are, to uncommon combinations of men and of affairs, I believe nobody recollects anything more surprising than the spectacle of this day. The right honorable gentleman[1] whose conduct is now in question formerly stood forth in this House, the prosecutor of the worthy baronet[2] who spoke after him. He charged him with several grievous acts of malversation in office, with abuses of a public trust of a great and heinous nature. In less than two years we see the situation of the parties reversed; and a singular revolution puts the worthy baronet in a fair way of returning the prosecution in a recriminatory bill of pains and penalties, grounded on a breach of public trust relative to the government of the very same part of India. If he should undertake a bill of that kind, he will find no difficulty in conducting it with a degree of skill and vigor fully equal to all that have been exerted against him.

The times we're living in, Mr. Speaker, have been marked by extraordinary events. However, as used to unusual combinations of people and situations as we are, I don't think anyone remembers anything more surprising than what we see today. The right honorable gentleman[1] whose actions are currently under scrutiny, once stood in this House as the prosecutor of the esteemed baronet[2] who spoke after him. He accused him of several serious acts of misconduct in office, involving major abuses of public trust. In less than two years, we see the roles reversed; a remarkable turn of events now puts the esteemed baronet in a position to launch his own prosecution in a bill of penalties, based on a breach of public trust related to the governance of the very same part of India. If he decides to pursue that kind of bill, he will have no trouble handling it with a level of skill and energy equal to what has been used against him.

But the change of relation between these two gentlemen is not so striking as the total difference of their deportment under the same unhappy circumstances. Whatever the merits of the worthy baronet's defence might have been, he did not shrink from the charge. He met it with manliness of spirit and decency of behavior. What would have been thought of him, if he had held the present language of his old accuser? When articles were exhibited against him by that right honorable gentleman, he did not think proper to tell the House that we ought to institute no inquiry, to inspect no paper, to examine no witness. He did not tell us (what at that time he might have told us with some show of reason) that our concerns in India were matters of delicacy, that to divulge anything relative to them would be mischievous to the state. He did not tell us that those who would inquire into his proceedings were disposed to dismember the empire. He had not the presumption to say, that, for his part, having obtained, in his Indian presidency, the ultimate object of his ambition, his honor was concerned in executing with integrity the trust which had been legally committed to his charge: that others, not having been so fortunate, could not be so disinterested; and therefore their accusations could spring from no other source than faction, and envy to his fortune.

But the change in the relationship between these two gentlemen isn't as striking as the total difference in how they behave under the same unfortunate circumstances. No matter the strengths of the honorable baronet's defense, he didn't shy away from the accusation. He faced it with courage and proper conduct. What would people have thought of him if he had spoken like his former accuser does now? When charges were brought against him by that esteemed gentleman, he didn’t claim to the House that we shouldn’t start any inquiry, look at any documents, or question any witnesses. He didn’t argue (which at that time he could have done with some reason) that our interests in India were sensitive matters, and that revealing anything about them would harm the state. He didn’t say that those wishing to investigate his actions were trying to tear apart the empire. He wasn’t arrogant enough to claim that, for his part, since he had achieved his ultimate ambition in India, his honor depended on fulfilling the trust that had been legally placed in him with integrity: that others, not having been as lucky, couldn’t be as unbiased; and thus their accusations must come from either factionalism or jealousy of his success.

Had he been frontless enough to hold such vain, vaporing language in the face of a grave, a detailed, a specified matter of accusation, whilst he violently resisted everything which could bring the merits of his cause to the test,—had he been wild enough to anticipate the absurdities of this day,—that is, had he inferred, as his late accuser has thought proper to do, that he could not have been guilty of malversation in office, for this sole and curious reason, that he had been in office,—had he argued the impossibility of his abusing his power on this sole principle, that he had power to abuse,—he would have left but one impression on the mind of every man who heard him, and who believed him in his senses: that in the utmost extent he was guilty of the charge.

Had he been foolish enough to use such empty, pretentious language in the face of serious, detailed accusations while he fiercely fought against anything that could test the validity of his case—had he been reckless enough to predict the ridiculousness of this day—meaning, had he assumed, as his recent accuser seems to think, that he could not be guilty of misconduct in office simply because he held a position—had he claimed it was impossible for him to misuse his power solely on the basis that he had the power to misuse—it would have left everyone who heard him and still believed he had his wits about him with only one impression: that he was utterly guilty of the charges.

But, Sir, leaving these two gentlemen to alternate as criminal and accuser upon what principles they think expedient, it is for us to consider whether the Chancellor of the Exchequer and the Treasurer of the Navy, acting as a Board of Control, are justified by law or policy in suspending the legal arrangements made by the Court of Directors, in order to transfer the public revenues to the private emolument of certain servants of the East India Company, without the inquiry into the origin and justice of their claims prescribed by an act of Parliament.

But, Sir, while these two gentlemen take turns as the criminal and the accuser based on what they believe is suitable, it is up to us to consider whether the Chancellor of the Exchequer and the Treasurer of the Navy, functioning as a Board of Control, are legally or policy-wise justified in suspending the legal arrangements established by the Court of Directors. They are doing this to redirect public funds for the personal gain of certain employees of the East India Company, without conducting the investigation into the legitimacy and fairness of their claims as required by an act of Parliament.

It is not contended that the act of Parliament did not expressly ordain an inquiry. It is not asserted that this inquiry was not, with equal precision of terms, specially committed, under particular regulations, to the Court of Directors. I conceive, therefore, the Board of Control had no right whatsoever to intermeddle in that business. There is nothing certain in the principles of jurisprudence, if this be not undeniably true, that when, a special authority is given to any persons by name to do some particular act, that no others, by virtue of general powers, can obtain a legal title to intrude themselves into that trust, and to exercise those special functions in their place. I therefore consider the intermeddling of ministers in this affair as a downright usurpation. But if the strained construction by which they have forced themselves into a suspicious office (which every man delicate with regard to character would rather have sought constructions to avoid) were perfectly sound and perfectly legal, of this I am certain, that they cannot be justified in declining the inquiry which had been prescribed to the Court of Directors. If the Board of Control did lawfully possess the right of executing the special trust given to that court, they must take it as they found it, subject to the very same regulations which bound the Court of Directors. It will be allowed that the Court of Directors had no authority to dispense with either the substance or the mode of inquiry prescribed by the act of Parliament. If they had not, where in the act did the Board of Control acquire that capacity? Indeed, it was impossible they should acquire it. What must we think of the fabric and texture of an act of Parliament which should find it necessary to prescribe a strict inquisition, that should descend into minute regulations for the conduct of that inquisition, that should commit this trust to a particular description of men, and in the very same breath should enable another body, at their own pleasure, to supersede all the provisions the legislature had made, and to defeat the whole purpose, end, and object of the law? This cannot be supposed even of an act of Parliament conceived by the ministers themselves, and brought forth during the delirium of the last session.

It's not disputed that the act of Parliament clearly mandated an inquiry. It's not claimed that this inquiry wasn't explicitly assigned, under specific regulations, to the Court of Directors. Therefore, I believe the Board of Control had no right to interfere in this matter. The principles of law state that when a specific authority is granted to certain individuals to perform a particular task, no others, based on general powers, can claim the legal right to intrude into that responsibility and carry out those specific functions in their place. Hence, I view the ministers' interference in this case as a blatant usurpation. However, even if the far-fetched reasoning they used to insert themselves into a questionable role (which anyone concerned about their reputation would prefer to have avoided) were entirely valid and legal, I'm certain they cannot justify refusing the inquiry that was assigned to the Court of Directors. If the Board of Control truly had the right to perform the special duties given to that court, they must accept it as it was, bound by the same regulations that governed the Court of Directors. It’s acknowledged that the Court of Directors had no authority to bypass either the substance or the method of inquiry mandated by the act of Parliament. If they didn’t, where in the act did the Board of Control gain that ability? In fact, it was impossible for them to acquire it. What should we make of the structure and foundation of an act of Parliament that would deem it necessary to prescribe a rigorous inquiry, detailed in minute regulations for its conduct, entrusted to a specific group of people, and at the same time empower another body to override all the provisions set by the legislature, effectively undermining the entire purpose, goal, and intent of the law? Such a scenario cannot even be imagined for an act of Parliament conceived by the ministers themselves during the chaos of the last session.

My honorable friend has told you in the speech which introduced his motion, that fortunately this question is not a great deal involved in the labyrinths of Indian detail. Certainly not. But if it were, I beg leave to assure you that there is nothing in the Indian detail which is more difficult than in the detail of any other business. I admit, because I have some experience of the fact, that for the interior regulation of India a minute knowledge of India is requisite. But on any specific matter of delinquency in its government you are as capable of judging as if the same thing were done at your door. Fraud, injustice, oppression, peculation, engendered in India, are crimes of the same blood, family, and cast with those that are born and bred in England. To go no farther than the case before us: you are just as competent to judge whether the sum of four millions sterling ought or ought not to be passed from the public treasury into a private pocket without any title except the claim of the parties, when the issue of fact is laid in Madras, as when it is laid in Westminster. Terms of art, indeed, are different in different places; but they are generally understood in none. The technical style of an Indian treasury is not one jot more remote than the jargon of our own Exchequer from the train of our ordinary ideas or the idiom of our common language. The difference, therefore, in the two cases is not in the comparative difficulty or facility of the two subjects, but in our attention to the one and our total neglect of the other. Had this attention and neglect been regulated by the value of the several objects, there would be nothing to complain of. But the reverse of that supposition is true. The scene of the Indian abuse is distant, indeed; but we must not infer that the value of our interest in it is decreased in proportion as it recedes from our view. In our politics, as in our common conduct, we shall be worse than infants, if we do not put our senses under the tuition of our judgment, and effectually cure ourselves of that optical illusion which makes a brier at our nose of greater magnitude than an oak at five hundred yards' distance.

My esteemed friend has mentioned in the speech that introduced his motion that, fortunately, this issue isn’t overly complicated by the intricate details of India. That's certainly true. However, if it were, I want to assure you that there’s nothing in the details of India that’s any harder than in the details of any other matter. I acknowledge, because I have some experience with it, that understanding India requires a deep knowledge of the region. But on any specific case of wrongdoing in its government, you are just as capable of judging as if the same situation were happening right in front of you. Fraud, injustice, oppression, and embezzlement that occur in India are crimes of the same kind, nature, and character as those that arise in England. To speak of the current case: you are as able to decide whether the amount of four million pounds should or shouldn’t be moved from the public treasury to a private individual without any justification other than the parties' claims when the facts are based in Madras, just as you would if they were based in Westminster. The technical terms indeed vary from one place to another, but they’re usually not well understood anywhere. The formal language of an Indian treasury is not any more foreign than the lingo of our own Exchequer compared to our everyday thoughts or the common language we use. Therefore, the difference in these two situations isn’t about the relative difficulty or ease of the subjects, but rather in how much attention we pay to one and the total disregard we have for the other. If our attention and disregard were based on the value of each, there wouldn’t be anything to complain about. Unfortunately, the opposite is true. The situation of the abuses in India may be far away; however, we shouldn’t assume that the value of our interests there diminishes just because it’s out of sight. In our politics, as in our everyday lives, we will be worse than infants if we don’t let our judgment guide our senses and effectively correct ourselves from that visual illusion that makes a thorn right at our nose seem larger than an oak tree five hundred yards away.

I think I can trace all the calamities of this country to the single source of our not having had steadily before our eyes a general, comprehensive, well-connected, and well-proportioned view of the whole of our dominions, and a just sense of their true bearings and relations. After all its reductions, the British empire is still vast and various. After all the reductions of the House of Commons, (stripped as we are of our brightest ornaments and of our most important privileges,) enough are yet left to furnish us, if we please, with means of showing to the world that we deserve the superintendence of as large an empire as this kingdom ever held, and the continuance of as ample privileges as the House of Commons, in the plenitude of its power, had been habituated to assert. But if we make ourselves too little for the sphere of our duty, if, on the contrary, we do not stretch and expand our minds to the compass of their object, be well assured that everything about us will dwindle by degrees, until at length our concerns are shrunk to the dimensions of our minds. It is not a predilection to mean, sordid, home-bred cares that will avert the consequences of a false estimation of our interest, or prevent the shameful dilapidation into which a great empire must fall by mean reparations upon mighty ruins.

I believe I can trace all the problems in this country back to the fact that we haven't consistently had a clear, comprehensive, and well-structured view of our entire territory, along with a proper understanding of their true connections and relationships. Despite all the reductions, the British Empire is still large and diverse. Even with all the cuts to the House of Commons, (having lost our brightest stars and most important rights), we still have enough left to show the world that we deserve to oversee as large an empire as this kingdom has ever had, and to maintain as significant privileges as the House of Commons has historically asserted. However, if we shrink ourselves down to fit our duties, or if we fail to broaden our minds to match the scope of our responsibilities, be assured that everything around us will gradually diminish, until our concerns are reduced to the size of our minds. It’s not a preference for trivial, narrow, everyday worries that will prevent the fallout from misjudging our interests, or stop the shameful decline into which a great empire will fall if it only tries to make small repairs on massive ruins.

I confess I feel a degree of disgust, almost leading to despair, at the manner in which we are acting in the great exigencies of our country. There is now a bill in this House appointing a rigid inquisition into the minutest detail of our offices at home. The collection of sixteen millions annually, a collection on which the public greatness, safety, and credit have their reliance, the whole order of criminal jurisprudence, which holds together society itself, have at no time obliged us to call forth such powers,—no, nor anything like them. There is not a principle of the law and Constitution of this country that is not subverted to favor the execution of that project.[3] And for what is all this apparatus of bustle and terror? Is it because anything substantial is expected from it? No. The stir and bustle itself is the end proposed. The eye-servants of a short-sighted master will employ themselves, not on what is most essential to his affairs, but on what is nearest to his ken. Great difficulties have given a just value to economy; and our minister of the day must be an economist, whatever it may cost us. But where is he to exert his talents? At home, to be sure; for where else can he obtain a profitable credit for their exertion? It is nothing to him, whether the object on which he works under our eye be promising or not. If he does not obtain any public benefit, he may make regulations without end. Those are sure to pay in present expectation, whilst the effect is at a distance, and may be the concern of other times and other men. On these principles, he chooses to suppose (for he does not pretend more than to suppose) a naked possibility that he shall draw some resource out of crumbs dropped from the trenchers of penury; that something shall be laid in store from the short allowance of revenue-officers overloaded with duty and famished for want of bread,—by a reduction from officers who are at this very hour ready to batter the Treasury with what breaks through stone walls for an increase of their appointments. From the marrowless bones of these skeleton establishments, by the use of every sort of cutting and of every sort of fretting tool, he flatters himself that he may chip and rasp an empirical alimentary powder, to diet into some similitude of health and substance the languishing chimeras of fraudulent reformation.

I have to say that I feel a sense of disgust, almost leading to despair, at how we are behaving during this critical time for our country. There’s currently a bill in this House calling for a strict investigation into every little detail of our domestic offices. The collection of sixteen million annually, which our public importance, safety, and credibility depend on, and the entire system of criminal law that holds society together, have never required us to unleash such powers—not at any time. Every principle of law and the Constitution in this country has been undermined to support this plan. And what’s all this commotion and fear for? Is it because we expect something significant from it? No. The noise and chaos itself is the end goal. The people pleasing a shortsighted leader focus not on what truly matters for his interests, but on what is immediately in front of him. Major challenges have highlighted the importance of economy; our current minister must be an economist, no matter the cost to us. But where can he apply his skills? At home, of course; because where else can he gain credit for his efforts? It doesn’t matter to him whether the task he's working on is promising or not. If he doesn't achieve any public benefit, he can still create endless regulations. Those are guaranteed to yield immediate expectations, while the actual effects may be left for other times and other people to deal with. Based on these ideas, he chooses to believe (since he can only assume) a mere possibility that he’ll extract some resources from the scraps left by the needy; that something will be saved from the revenue officers who are weighed down with work and starving for lack of income—by cutting back on officers who are right now ready to hammer the Treasury for an increase in their salaries. From the lifeless remains of these skeletal establishments, through the use of all kinds of cutting and grinding tools, he comforts himself with the idea that he might chip away and scrape together a makeshift source of sustenance, to somehow revitalize the fading illusions of fraudulent reform.

Whilst he is thus employed according to his policy and to his taste, he has not leisure to inquire into those abuses in India that are drawing off money by millions from the treasures of this country, which are exhausting the vital juices from members of the state, where the public inanition is far more sorely felt than in the local exchequer of England. Not content with winking at these abuses, whilst he attempts to squeeze the laborious, ill-paid drudges of English revenue, he lavishes, in one act of corrupt prodigality, upon those who never served the public in any honest occupation at all, an annual income equal to two thirds of the whole collection of the revenues of this kingdom.

While he is busy pursuing his own interests and preferences, he doesn’t take the time to look into the issues in India that are draining millions from the treasures of this country, which are depleting the essential resources of the state. The public suffering is much more intense than what’s happening in the English treasury. He isn’t satisfied with simply ignoring these problems; as he tries to extract more from the hard-working, poorly paid workers of English revenue, he lavishly rewards those who have never contributed to the public good in any honest way with an annual income that's two-thirds of the total revenue collected in this kingdom.

Actuated by the same principle of choice, he has now on the anvil another scheme, full of difficulty and desperate hazard, which totally alters the commercial relation of two kingdoms, and, what end soever it shall have, may bequeath a legacy of heartburning and discontent to one of the countries, perhaps to both, to be perpetuated to the latest posterity. This project is also undertaken on the hope of profit. It is provided, that, out of some (I know not what) remains of the Irish hereditary revenue, a fund, at some time, and of some sort, should be applied to the protection of the Irish trade. Here we are commanded again to task our faith, and to persuade ourselves, that, out of the surplus of deficiency, out of the savings of habitual and systematic prodigality, the minister of wonders will provide support for this nation, sinking under the mountainous load of two hundred and thirty millions of debt. But whilst we look with pain at his desperate and laborious trifling, whilst we are apprehensive that he will break his back in stooping to pick up chaff and straws, he recovers himself at an elastic bound, and with a broadcast swing of his arm he squanders over his Indian field a sum far greater than the clear produce of the whole hereditary revenue of the kingdom of Ireland.[4]

Driven by the same principle of choice, he now has another plan in the works, full of challenges and serious risks, which completely changes the trade relationship between two countries. Regardless of its outcome, it could leave a legacy of resentment and dissatisfaction for one or possibly both countries, lasting for generations. This project is also based on the hope for profit. It’s suggested that from some (I’m not sure what) remnants of the Irish hereditary revenue, a fund should eventually be created to support Irish trade. Here, we’re again asked to stretch our belief and convince ourselves that, from the surplus of lack, from the savings of chronic and systematic wastefulness, the minister of wonders will find a way to support this nation, which is already struggling under a massive debt of two hundred and thirty million. But while we watch in despair as he clumsily juggles this task, worried he might hurt himself trying to pick up scraps, he suddenly springs back and, with a wide swing of his arm, squanders a sum much larger than the total income of all the hereditary revenue from the kingdom of Ireland.[4]

Strange as this scheme of conduct in ministry is, and inconsistent with all just policy, it is still true to itself, and faithful to its own perverted order. Those who are bountiful to crimes will be rigid to merit and penurious to service. Their penury is even held out as a blind and cover to their prodigality. The economy of injustice is to furnish resources for the fund of corruption. Then they pay off their protection to great crimes and great criminals by being inexorable to the paltry frailties of little men; and these modern flagellants are sure, with a rigid fidelity, to whip their own enormities on the vicarious back of every small offender.

As strange as this approach to ministry may be, and inconsistent with all reasonable policies, it remains true to itself and loyal to its own twisted system. Those who are generous toward wrongdoings will be strict with merit and stingy with service. Their miserly attitude is often used as a smokescreen for their extravagance. The economy of injustice serves to provide resources for corruption. They repay their support for major crimes and criminals by being merciless toward the minor weaknesses of ordinary people; and these modern punishing figures are sure, with unwavering precision, to inflict their own faults on the backs of every small offender.

It is to draw your attention to economy of quite another order, it is to animadvert on offences of a far different description, that my honorable friend has brought before you the motion of this day. It is to perpetuate the abuses which are subverting the fabric of your empire, that the motion is opposed. It is, therefore, with reason (and if he has power to carry himself through, I commend his prudence) that the right honorable gentleman makes his stand at the very outset, and boldly refuses all Parliamentary information. Let him admit but one step towards inquiry, and he is undone. You must be ignorant, or he cannot be safe. But before his curtain is let down, and the shades of eternal night shall veil our Eastern dominions from our view, permit me, Sir, to avail myself of the means which were furnished in anxious and inquisitive times to demonstrate out of this single act of the present minister what advantages you are to derive from permitting the greatest concern of this nation to be separated from the cognizance, and exempted even out of the competence, of Parliament. The greatest body of your revenue, your most numerous armies, your most important commerce, the richest sources of your public credit, (contrary to every idea of the known, settled policy of England,) are on the point of being converted into a mystery of state. You are going to have one half of the globe hid even from the common liberal curiosity of an English gentleman. Here a grand revolution commences. Mark the period, and mark the circumstances. In most of the capital changes that are recorded in the principles and system of any government, a public benefit of some kind or other has been pretended. The revolution commenced in something plausible, in something which carried the appearance at least of punishment of delinquency or correction of abuse. But here, in the very moment of the conversion of a department of British government into an Indian mystery, and in the very act in which the change commences, a corrupt private interest is set up in direct opposition to the necessities of the nation. A diversion is made of millions of the public money from the public treasury to a private purse. It is not into secret negotiations for war, peace, or alliance that the House of Commons is forbidden to inquire. It is a matter of account; it is a pecuniary transaction; it is the demand of a suspected steward upon ruined tenants and an embarrassed master that the Commons of Great Britain are commanded not to inspect. The whole tenor of the right honorable gentleman's argument is consonant to the nature of his policy. The system of concealment is fostered by a system of falsehood. False facts, false colors, false names of persons and things, are its whole support.

I want to draw your attention to a different kind of issue; my honorable friend has brought today's motion to highlight offenses of a different nature. The motion is opposed to the ongoing abuses that are undermining the foundation of your empire. Therefore, it’s understandable (and if he can manage it, I commend his caution) that the right honorable gentleman stands firm right from the beginning and clearly rejects all Parliamentary information. If he allows even a small opening for inquiry, he’s in trouble. You have to remain uninformed, or he can’t be safe. But before the curtain falls and eternal darkness hides our Eastern territories from our view, allow me, Sir, to use the resources provided during anxious and curious times to show you what advantages you will miss by letting the most significant concern of this nation be taken out of Parliament's oversight. The largest part of your revenue, your biggest armies, your most vital commerce, and the richest sources of your public credit—which goes against all established policies of England—are about to become a state secret. You’re going to have half the globe hidden even from the ordinary curiosity of an English gentleman. A major revolution is beginning. Pay attention to the moment and the circumstances. In most major changes recorded in the principles and systems of any government, there has been some sort of claimed public benefit. Revolutions typically start with something that seems reasonable, something that at least suggests punishing wrongdoing or correcting abuses. But here, at the very moment when a part of British government is being turned into an Indian secret, and as the change begins in , a corrupt private interest is established directly opposing the needs of the nation. Millions of public funds are shifted from the treasury into a private pocket. It is not hidden negotiations for war, peace, or alliances that the House of Commons is forbidden to investigate. This is an accounting matter; it is a financial transaction; it is about the demands of a questionable steward on ruined tenants and a troubled master that the Commons of Great Britain are told not to examine. The entire argument of the right honorable gentleman aligns with the nature of his policy. The system of concealment thrives on a system of falsehood. False facts, misleading appearances, and false names for people and things are its entire support.

Sir, I mean to follow the right honorable gentleman over that field of deception, clearing what he has purposely obscured, and fairly stating what it was necessary for him to misrepresent. For this purpose, it is necessary you should know, with some degree of distinctness, a little of the locality, the nature, the circumstances, the magnitude of the pretended debts on which this marvellous donation is founded, as well as of the persons from whom and by whom it is claimed.

Sir, I intend to pursue the honorable gentleman through that field of deception, clarifying what he has deliberately hidden and accurately presenting what he found it necessary to misrepresent. For this purpose, it’s important for you to understand, with some clarity, a bit about the location, the nature, the circumstances, and the extent of the supposed debts that this remarkable donation is based on, as well as the individuals involved in claiming it.

Madras, with its dependencies, is the second (but with a long interval, the second) member of the British empire in the East. The trade of that city, and of the adjacent territory, was not very long ago among the most flourishing in Asia. But since the establishment of the British power it has wasted away under an uniform gradual decline, insomuch that in the year 1779 not one merchant of eminence was to be found in the whole country.[5] During this period of decay, about six hundred thousand sterling pounds a year have been drawn off by English gentlemen on their private account, by the way of China alone.[6] If we add four hundred thousand, as probably remitted through other channels, and in other mediums, that is, in jewels, gold, and silver, directly brought to Europe, and in bills upon the British and foreign companies, you will scarcely think the matter overrated. If we fix the commencement of this extraction of money from the Carnatic at a period no earlier than the year 1760, and close it in the year 1780, it probably will not amount to a great deal less than twenty millions of money.

Madras, along with its territories, is the second member of the British Empire in the East, though there’s a significant gap in between. Not too long ago, the trade in that city and its surrounding areas was among the most prosperous in Asia. However, since the British took control, it has experienced a steady decline to the point where, in 1779, there wasn’t a single prominent merchant left in the entire country. During this decline, English gentlemen have siphoned off around six hundred thousand pounds a year for personal use, just through trade with China. If we estimate an additional four hundred thousand pounds being sent through other means, such as jewels, gold, and silver brought directly to Europe, along with bills from British and foreign companies, it’s hard to argue that this figure is inflated. If we start counting this money extraction from the Carnatic from around 1760 and end it in 1780, it likely totals close to twenty million pounds.

During the deep, silent flow of this steady stream of wealth which set from India into Europe, it generally passed on with no adequate observation; but happening at some periods to meet rifts of rocks that checked its course, it grew more noisy and attracted more notice. The pecuniary discussions caused by an accumulation of part of the fortunes of their servants in a debt from the Nabob of Arcot was the first thing which very particularly called for, and long engaged, the attention of the Court of Directors. This debt amounted to eight hundred and eighty thousand pounds sterling, and was claimed, for the greater part, by English gentlemen residing at Madras. This grand capital, settled at length by order at ten per cent, afforded an annuity of eighty-eight thousand pounds.[7]

During the steady flow of wealth from India to Europe, it usually went unnoticed. However, at certain points, when it encountered rocky obstacles, it became louder and drew more attention. The financial discussions surrounding an accumulation of part of their servants' fortunes, stemming from a debt owed by the Nabob of Arcot, were the first issues that specifically requested and held the attention of the Court of Directors for a long time. This debt totaled eight hundred and eighty thousand pounds sterling and was mainly claimed by English gentlemen living in Madras. Eventually, this substantial amount was settled at a rate of ten percent, generating an annual income of eighty-eight thousand pounds.[7]

Whilst the Directors were digesting their astonishment at this information, a memorial was presented to them from three gentlemen, informing them that their friends had lent, likewise, to merchants of Canton in China, a sum of not more than one million sterling. In this memorial they called upon the Company for their assistance and interposition with the Chinese government for the recovery of the debt. This sum lent to Chinese merchants was at twenty-four per cent, which would yield, if paid, an annuity of two hundred and forty thousand pounds.[8]

While the Directors were processing their shock at this information, a petition was presented to them from three gentlemen, informing them that their associates had also loaned no more than one million pounds to merchants in Canton, China. In this petition, they requested the Company’s help and intervention with the Chinese government to recover the debt. This amount lent to Chinese merchants was at a rate of twenty-four percent, which would yield, if paid, an annual income of two hundred and forty thousand pounds.[8]

Perplexed as the Directors were with these demands, you may conceive, Sir, that they did not find themselves very much disembarrassed by being made acquainted that they must again exert their influence for a new reserve of the happy parsimony of their servants, collected into a second debt from the Nabob of Arcot, amounting to two millions four hundred thousand pounds, settled at an interest of twelve per cent. This is known by the name of the Consolidation of 1777, as the former of the Nabob's debts was by the title of the Consolidation of 1767. To this was added, in a separate parcel, a little reserve, called the Cavalry Debt, of one hundred and sixty thousand pounds, at the same interest. The whole of these four capitals, amounting to four millions four hundred and forty thousand pounds, produced at their several rates, annuities amounting to six hundred and twenty-three thousand pounds a year: a good deal more than one third of the clear land-tax of England, at four shillings in the pound; a good deal more than double the whole annual dividend of the East India Company, the nominal masters to the proprietors in these funds. Of this interest, three hundred and eighty-three thousand two hundred pounds a year stood chargeable on the public revenues of the Carnatic.

Confused as the Directors were by these demands, you can imagine, Sir, that they didn’t feel relieved knowing they had to once again use their influence to secure a new reserve of the careful savings of their employees, which added up to a second debt from the Nabob of Arcot, totaling two million four hundred thousand pounds, set at an interest rate of twelve percent. This is referred to as the Consolidation of 1777, similar to the earlier debt of the Nabob known as the Consolidation of 1767. Additionally, there was a separate reserve, known as the Cavalry Debt, of one hundred sixty thousand pounds, also at the same interest rate. The total of these four amounts to four million four hundred forty thousand pounds, which generated annuities of six hundred twenty-three thousand pounds a year at their respective rates: significantly more than one third of the clear land tax in England, which is four shillings per pound; and well over double the entire annual dividend of the East India Company, the nominal owners to the shareholders in these funds. Out of this interest, three hundred eighty-three thousand two hundred pounds a year was charged to the public revenues of the Carnatic.

Sir, at this moment, it will not be necessary to consider the various operations which the capital and interest of this debt have successively undergone. I shall speak to these operations when I come particularly to answer the right honorable gentleman on each of the heads, as he has thought proper to divide them. But this was the exact view in which these debts first appeared to the Court of Directors, and to the world. It varied afterwards. But it never appeared in any other than a most questionable shape. When this gigantic phantom of debt first appeared before a young minister, it naturally would have justified some degree of doubt and apprehension. Such a prodigy would have filled any common man with superstitious fears. He would exorcise that shapeless, nameless form, and by everything sacred would have adjured it to tell by what means a small number of slight individuals, of no consequence or situation, possessed of no lucrative offices, without the command of armies or the known administration of revenues, without profession of any kind, without any sort of trade sufficient to employ a peddler, could have, in a few years, (as to some, even in a few months,) amassed treasures equal to the revenues of a respectable kingdom? Was it not enough to put these gentlemen, in the novitiate of their administration, on their guard, and to call upon them for a strict inquiry, (if not to justify them in a reprobation of those demands without any inquiry at all,) that, when all England, Scotland, and Ireland had for years been witness to the immense sums laid out by the servants of the Company in stocks of all denominations, in the purchase of lands, in the buying and building of houses, in the securing quiet seats in Parliament or in the tumultuous riot of contested elections, in wandering throughout the whole range of those variegated modes of inventive prodigality which sometimes have excited our wonder, sometimes roused our indignation, that, after all, India was four millions still in debt to them? India in debt to them! For what? Every debt, for which an equivalent of some kind or other is not given, is, on the face of it, a fraud. What is the equivalent they have given? What equivalent had they to give? What are the articles of commerce, or the branches of manufacture, which those gentlemen have carried hence to enrich India? What are the sciences they beamed out to enlighten it? What are the arts they introduced to cheer and to adorn it? What are the religious, what the moral institutions they have taught among that people, as a guide to life, or as a consolation when life is to be no more, that there is an eternal debt, a debt "still paying, still to owe," which must be bound on the present generation in India, and entailed on their mortgaged posterity forever? A debt of millions, in favor of a set of men whose names, with few exceptions, are either buried in the obscurity of their origin and talents or dragged into light by the enormity of their crimes!

Sir, right now, we don’t need to go into the various transactions that the capital and interest of this debt have gone through over time. I will address those transactions when I respond specifically to the honorable gentleman on each point, as he has chosen to break them down. But this is exactly how these debts were first viewed by the Court of Directors and the world. It changed later, but it never appeared in any other light than a very questionable one. When this massive specter of debt first came before a young minister, it naturally would have raised some doubts and fears. Anyone would be filled with superstitious dread by such a phenomenon. They would try to dispel that shapeless, nameless presence and, by everything sacred, would demand to know how a small number of insignificant individuals, with no prominent positions, without any lucrative jobs, lacking command over armies or control over known revenues, with no profession whatsoever, and no trade sufficient to employ a peddler, could, in just a few years—or in some cases, even just a few months—accumulate riches equivalent to the revenues of a respectable kingdom? Was it not enough to put these gentlemen, at the start of their administration, on alert, and to compel them to conduct a thorough investigation, or at the very least to justify their rejection of those demands without any inquiry at all, that, when all of England, Scotland, and Ireland had for years witnessed the enormous sums spent by the servants of the Company on stocks of all kinds, purchasing lands, buying and building houses, securing quiet seats in Parliament or the chaos of contested elections, and wandering through all the various means of extravagant spending that sometimes amazed us and sometimes outraged us, that after all this, India still owed four million to them? India in debt to them! For what? Every debt that doesn’t have a corresponding benefit is, on the surface, a fraud. What benefit have they provided? What benefit could they provide? What goods or industries have those gentlemen taken away to enrich India? What knowledge have they shared to enlighten it? What arts have they introduced to uplift and beautify it? What religious or moral teachings have they given to that people as guidance for life, or as comfort when life ends, that there is an eternal debt, a debt "still paying, still to owe," which will bind the current generation in India and be inherited by their burdened descendants forever? A debt of millions, owed to a group of men whose names, with a few exceptions, are either lost in obscurity or brought into light only by the severity of their crimes!

In my opinion the courage of the minister was the most wonderful part of the transaction, especially as he must have read, or rather the right honorable gentleman says he has read for him, whole volumes upon the subject. The volumes, by the way, are not by one tenth part so numerous as the right honorable gentleman has thought proper to pretend, in order to frighten you from inquiry; but in these volumes, such as they are, the minister must have found a full authority for a suspicion (at the very least) of everything relative to the great fortunes made at Madras. What is that authority? Why, no other than the standing authority for all the claims which the ministry has thought fit to provide for,—the grand debtor,—the Nabob of Arcot himself. Hear that prince, in the letter written to the Court of Directors, at the precise period whilst the main body of these debts were contracting. In his letter he states himself to be, what undoubtedly he is, a most competent witness to this point. After speaking of the war with Hyder Ali in 1768 and 1769, and of other measures which he censures, (whether right or wrong it signifies nothing,) and into which he says he had been led by the Company's servants, he proceeds in this manner:—"If all these things were against the real interests of the Company, they are ten thousand times more against mine, and against the prosperity of my country and the happiness of my people; for your interests and mine are the same. What were they owing to, then? To the private views of a few individuals, who have enriched themselves at the expense of your influence and of my country: for your servants HAVE NO TRADE IN THIS COUNTRY, neither do you pay them high wages; yet in a few years they return to England with many lacs of pagodas. How can you or I account for such immense fortunes acquired in so short a time, without any visible means of getting them?"

In my view, the minister's courage was the most impressive part of the situation, especially since he must have read, or rather the honorable gentleman claims he has read for him, entire volumes on the subject. By the way, the volumes are not nearly as numerous as the honorable gentleman pretends, likely to deter you from investigating; but in these volumes, however few, the minister must have found strong grounds for at least suspecting everything related to the huge fortunes made in Madras. What is that evidence? It is none other than the established source for all the claims that the ministry has chosen to support—the grand debtor, the Nabob of Arcot himself. Listen to that prince in the letter addressed to the Court of Directors, at the exact time when most of these debts were incurred. In his letter, he claims to be, what he undoubtedly is, a highly qualified witness to this matter. After discussing the war with Hyder Ali in 1768 and 1769, and other actions which he criticizes (whether he is right or wrong is irrelevant), which he says he was led into by the Company's agents, he continues in this way:—"If all these decisions were against the true interests of the Company, they are a thousand times more against mine, and against the well-being of my nation and the happiness of my people; for your interests and mine are the same. So what were they due to? The private objectives of a handful of individuals who have made themselves wealthy at the cost of your influence and my country: for your servants HAVE NO BUSINESS IN THIS COUNTRY, nor do you pay them high salaries; yet in a few years they go back to England with many lacs of pagodas. How can either you or I explain such gigantic fortunes made in such a short time, without any apparent means of acquiring them?"

When he asked this question, which involves its answer, it is extraordinary that curiosity did not prompt the Chancellor of the Exchequer to that inquiry which might come in vain recommended to him by his own act of Parliament. Does not the Nabob of Arcot tell us, in so many words, that there was no fair way of making the enormous sums sent by the Company's servants to England? And do you imagine that there was or could be more honesty and good faith in the demands for what remained behind in India? Of what nature were the transactions with himself? If you follow the train of his information, you must see, that, if these great sums were at all lent, it was not property, but spoil, that was lent; if not lent, the transaction was not a contract, but a fraud. Either way, if light enough could not be furnished to authorize a full condemnation of these demands, they ought to have been left to the parties, who best knew and understood each other's proceedings. It was not necessary that the authority of government should interpose in favor of claims whose very foundation was a defiance of that authority, and whose object and end was its entire subversion.

When he asked this question, along with its answer, it's remarkable that curiosity didn’t drive the Chancellor of the Exchequer to investigate something that might have been suggested by his own law. Doesn’t the Nabob of Arcot clearly state that there was no legitimate way to account for the huge sums sent by the Company’s officials to England? Do you really think there was or could be more honesty and integrity regarding the money that stayed behind in India? What were the dealings with him actually like? If you follow the trail of his information, you’ll see that if these large amounts were lent, it wasn’t property, but plunder that was lent; if they weren’t lent, the interaction wasn’t a contract, but a scam. In either case, if there wasn't enough evidence to fully condemn these claims, they should have been left to the parties involved, who knew and understood each other’s actions best. It wasn’t necessary for the government’s authority to step in on behalf of claims that fundamentally challenged that authority, and whose purpose was to undermine it entirely.

It may be said that this letter was written by the Nabob of Arcot in a moody humor, under the influence of some chagrin. Certainly it was; but it is in such humors that truth comes out. And when he tells you, from his own knowledge, what every one must presume, from the extreme probability of the thing, whether he told it or not, one such testimony is worth a thousand that contradict that probability, when the parties have a better understanding with each other, and when they have a point to carry that may unite them in a common deceit.

It can be said that this letter was written by the Nabob of Arcot in a bad mood, influenced by some annoyance. And it's true; it's during these moods that the truth often comes out. When he tells you, based on his own knowledge, what everyone else must assume due to its high likelihood, whether he says it or not, that one piece of evidence is worth a thousand that go against that likelihood, especially when the parties involved have a better understanding of each other and have something to gain that might bring them together in a shared deception.

If this body of private claims of debt, real or devised, were a question, as it is falsely pretended, between the Nabob of Arcot, as debtor, and Paul Benfield and his associates, as creditors, I am sure I should give myself but little trouble about it. If the hoards of oppression were the fund for satisfying the claims of bribery and peculation, who would wish to interfere between such litigants? If the demands were confined to what might be drawn from the treasures which the Company's records uniformly assert that the Nabob is in possession of, or if he had mines of gold or silver or diamonds, (as we know that he has none,) these gentlemen might break open his hoards or dig in his mines without any disturbance from me. But the gentlemen on the other side of the House know as well as I do, and they dare not contradict me, that the Nabob of Arcot and his creditors are not adversaries, but collusive parties, and that the whole transaction is under a false color and false names. The litigation is not, nor ever has been, between their rapacity and his hoarded riches. No: it is between him and them combining and confederating, on one side, and the public revenues, and the miserable inhabitants of a ruined country, on the other. These are the real plaintiffs and the real defendants in the suit. Refusing a shilling from his hoards for the satisfaction of any demand, the Nabob of Arcot is always ready, nay, he earnestly, and with eagerness and passion, contends for delivering up to these pretended creditors his territory and his subjects. It is, therefore, not from treasuries and mines, but from the food of your unpaid armies, from the blood withheld from the veins and whipped out of the backs of the most miserable of men, that we are to pamper extortion, usury, and peculation, under the false names of debtors and creditors of state.

If this collection of private debt claims, whether real or made up, were just a dispute between the Nabob of Arcot, as the debtor, and Paul Benfield and his associates, as creditors, I wouldn’t concern myself much about it. If the funds from oppression were set aside to settle claims of bribery and corruption, who would want to get involved in such a case? If the demands were limited to what could be drawn from the riches the Company’s records consistently claim the Nabob possesses, or if he had gold or silver mines or diamonds (which we know he does not), those gentlemen could break open his coffers or dig in his mines without any interference from me. But the folks on the opposite side of the House know as well as I do, and they wouldn’t dare to contradict me, that the Nabob of Arcot and his creditors are not real opponents, but colluding parties, and the entire scenario is under false pretenses and false names. The dispute is not, and has never been, between their greed and his hoarded wealth. No, it’s between him and them teaming up against the public revenue and the impoverished people of a devastated country. These are the true plaintiffs and the true defendants in this case. Refusing to give even a penny from his hoards to satisfy any claim, the Nabob of Arcot is always willing, in fact, he passionately argues to hand over his territory and his people to these so-called creditors. Therefore, it’s not from treasuries and mines, but from the pay of your unpaid armies, from the blood taken from the veins and beaten out of the backs of the most miserable people, that we are to support extortion, usury, and corruption, under the false labels of state debtors and creditors.

The great patron of these creditors, (to whose honor they ought to erect statues,) the right honorable gentleman,[9] in stating the merits which recommended them to his favor, has ranked them under three grand divisions. The first, the creditors of 1767; then the creditors of the cavalry loan; and lastly, the creditors of the loan in 1777. Let us examine them, one by one, as they pass in review before us.

The major supporter of these creditors, (to whom they should build statues in gratitude,) the distinguished gentleman,[9] in highlighting the qualities that earned their favor, has classified them into three main categories. First, the creditors from 1767; next, the creditors of the cavalry loan; and finally, the creditors from the 1777 loan. Let's look at them, one by one, as they come before us.

The first of these loans, that of 1767, he insists, has an indisputable claim upon the public justice. The creditors, he affirms, lent their money publicly; they advanced it with the express knowledge and approbation of the Company; and it was contracted at the moderate interest of ten per cent. In this loan, the demand is, according to him, not only just, but meritorious in a very high degree: and one would be inclined to believe he thought so, because he has put it last in the provision he has made for these claims.

The first of these loans, from 1767, he argues, has an undeniable right to public justice. The creditors, he states, lent their money openly; they provided it with the full knowledge and approval of the Company; and it was taken out at a reasonable interest rate of ten percent. In this loan, he believes the demand is not only fair but also highly commendable: one might think he felt this way because he listed it last in the arrangements he's made for these claims.

I readily admit this debt to stand the fairest of the whole; for, whatever may be my suspicions concerning a part of it, I can convict it of nothing worse than the most enormous usury. But I can convict, upon the spot, the right honorable gentleman of the most daring misrepresentation in every one fact, without any exception, that he has alleged in defence of this loan, and of his own conduct with regard to it. I will show you that this debt was never contracted with the knowledge of the Company; that it had not their approbation; that they received the first intelligence of it with the utmost possible surprise, indignation, and alarm.

I fully acknowledge this debt to be the most reasonable of the entire situation; because, while I might have my doubts about some aspects of it, I can only accuse it of the most outrageous interest rates. But I can immediately accuse the honorable gentleman of the most blatant misrepresentation regarding every single claim he has made in defense of this loan and his actions related to it. I will prove to you that this debt was never taken on with the Company's knowledge; that they did not approve it; and that they learned of it with complete surprise, outrage, and alarm.

So for from being previously apprised of the transaction from its origin, it was two years before the Court of Directors obtained any official intelligence of it. "The dealings of the servants with the Nabob were concealed from the first, until they were found out" (says Mr. Sayer, the Company's counsel) "by the report of the country." The Presidency, however, at last thought proper to send an official account. On this the Directors tell them, "To your great reproach, it has been concealed from us. We cannot but suspect this debt to have had its weight in your proposed aggrandizement of Mahomed Ali [the Nabob of Arcot]; but whether it has or has not, certain it is you are guilty of an high breach of duty in concealing it from us."

So, even though they were informed about the transaction from the beginning, it took two years before the Court of Directors received any official news about it. "The interactions of the servants with the Nabob were kept hidden from the start, until they were discovered," says Mr. Sayer, the Company's lawyer, "by the report from the region." The Presidency eventually deemed it necessary to send an official account. In response, the Directors told them, "To your great shame, it has been concealed from us. We can’t help but suspect that this debt may have influenced your plans to elevate Mahomed Ali [the Nabob of Arcot]; but whether it has or hasn’t, it’s clear that you are guilty of a serious breach of duty for concealing this from us."

These expressions, concerning the ground of the transaction, its effect, and its clandestine nature, are in the letters bearing date March 17, 1769. After receiving a more full account, on the 23d March, 1770, they state, that "Messrs. John Pybus, John Call, and James Bourchier, as trustees for themselves and others of the Nabob's private creditors, had proved a deed of assignment upon the Nabob and his son of FIFTEEN districts of the Nabob's country, the revenues of which yielded, in time of peace, eight lacs of pagodas [320,000l. sterling] annually; and likewise an assignment of the yearly tribute paid the Nabob from the Rajah of Tanjore, amounting to four lacs of rupees [40,000l.]." The territorial revenue at that time possessed by these gentlemen, without the knowledge or consent of their masters, amounted to three hundred and sixty thousand pounds sterling annually. They were making rapid strides to the entire possession of the country, when the Directors, whom the right honorable gentleman states as having authorized these proceedings, were kept in such profound ignorance of this royal acquisition of territorial revenue by their servants, that in the same letter they say, "This assignment was obtained by three of the members of your board in January, 1767; yet we do not find the least trace of it upon your Consultations until August, 1768, nor do any of your letters to us afford any information relative to such transactions till the 1st of November, 1768. By your last letters of the 8th of May, 1769, you bring the whole proceedings to light in one view."

These statements, regarding the basis of the transaction, its impact, and its secretive nature, are found in letters dated March 17, 1769. After receiving a more detailed account on March 23, 1770, they mention that "Messrs. John Pybus, John Call, and James Bourchier, acting as trustees for themselves and other private creditors of the Nabob, had established a deed of assignment on the Nabob and his son for FIFTEEN districts of the Nabob's territory, the revenues of which generated, in peacetime, eight lacs of pagodas [320,000l. sterling] annually; as well as an assignment of the annual tribute the Nabob received from the Rajah of Tanjore, totaling four lacs of rupees [40,000l.]." The annual territorial revenue at that time held by these individuals, without their superiors' knowledge or consent, was three hundred and sixty thousand pounds sterling. They were making significant progress toward complete control of the region, while the Directors, whom the right honorable gentleman claims authorized these actions, were kept so completely unaware of this royal acquisition of territorial revenue by their agents that in the same letter they state, "This assignment was secured by three members of your board in January 1767; however, we find not the slightest trace of it in your Consultations until August 1768, nor do any of your letters to us provide any details regarding such transactions until November 1, 1768. In your latest letters from May 8, 1769, you finally reveal the entire proceedings in one overview."

As to the previous knowledge of the Company, and its sanction to the debts, you see that this assertion of that knowledge is utterly unfounded. But did the Directors approve of it, and ratify the transaction, when it was known? The very reverse. On the same 3d of March, the Directors declare, "upon an impartial examination of the whole conduct of our late Governor and Council of Fort George [Madras], and on the fullest consideration, that the said Governor and Council have, in notorious violation of the trust reposed in them, manifestly preferred the interest of private individuals to that of the Company, in permitting the assignment of the revenues of certain valuable districts, to a very large amount, from the Nabob to individuals"; and then, highly aggravating their crimes, they add,—"We order and direct that you do examine, in the most impartial manner, all the above-mentioned transactions, and that you punish, by suspension, degradation, dismission, or otherwise, as to you shall seem meet, all and every such servant or servants of the Company who may by you be found guilty of any of the above offences." "We had" (say the Directors) "the mortification to find that the servants of the Company, who had been raised, supported, and owed their present opulence to the advantages gained in such service, have in this instance most unfaithfully betrayed their trust, abandoned the Company's interest, and prostituted its influence to accomplish the purposes of individuals, whilst the interest of the Company is almost wholly neglected, and payment to us rendered extremely precarious." Here, then, is the rock of approbation of the Court of Directors, on which the right honorable gentleman says this debt was founded. Any member, Mr. Speaker, who should come into the House, on my reading this sentence of condemnation of the Court of Directors against their unfaithful servants, might well imagine that he had heard an harsh, severe, unqualified invective against the present ministerial Board of Control. So exactly do the proceedings of the patrons of this abuse tally with those of the actors in it, that the expressions used in the condemnation of the one may serve for the reprobation of the other, without the change of a word.

Regarding the Company’s prior knowledge and approval of the debts, it’s clear that this claim is completely unfounded. But did the Directors approve and confirm the transaction once it was known? Quite the opposite. On March 3rd, the Directors stated, "after an impartial examination of the entire conduct of our former Governor and the Council of Fort George [Madras], and after thorough consideration, we declare that the said Governor and Council have, in blatant violation of the trust placed in them, clearly favored the interests of private individuals over those of the Company, by allowing the assignment of the revenues from certain valuable districts, amounting to a significant sum, from the Nabob to individuals"; and to further emphasize their wrongdoing, they added, "We order you to investigate all the above-mentioned transactions in the most impartial way, and to punish, through suspension, demotion, dismissal, or any other appropriate action, all servants of the Company found guilty of the above offenses." "It was distressing for us," (say the Directors) "to discover that the servants of the Company, who were raised, supported, and owe their current wealth to the advantages gained through such service, have, in this instance, deceitfully betrayed their trust, abandoned the Company's interests, and misused its influence to serve the purposes of individuals, while the Company's interests are nearly entirely neglected, making payments to us highly uncertain." Here is the foundation of the Court of Directors' approval, on which the right honorable gentleman claims this debt was based. Any member, Mr. Speaker, who enters the House after hearing this condemnation from the Court of Directors against their unfaithful servants might easily think they had heard a harsh, severe, and unqualified attack against the current ministerial Board of Control. The actions of the supporters of this abuse align so closely with those who committed it that the language used in condemning one could just as easily apply to the other without any changes.

To read you all the expressions of wrath and indignation fulminated in this dispatch against the meritorious creditors of the right honorable gentleman, who according to him have been so fully approved by the Company, would be to read the whole.

To go through all the expressions of anger and frustration directed in this message against the deserving creditors of the honorable gentleman, who according to him have been so entirely endorsed by the Company, would be to read the entire thing.

The right honorable gentleman, with an address peculiar to himself, every now and then slides in the Presidency of Madras, as synonymous to the Company. That the Presidency did approve the debt is certain. But the right honorable gentleman, as prudent in suppressing as skilful in bringing forward his matter, has not chosen to tell you that the Presidency were the very persons guilty of contracting this loan,—creditors themselves, and agents and trustees for all the other creditors. For this the Court of Directors accuse them of breach of trust; and for this the right honorable gentleman considers them as perfectly good authority for those claims. It is pleasant to hear a gentleman of the law quote the approbation of creditors as an authority for their own debt.

The honorable gentleman, with a unique way of speaking, occasionally suggests that the Presidency of Madras is the same as the Company. It's true that the Presidency approved the debt. However, the honorable gentleman, who is as skilled at hiding information as he is at presenting it, hasn't mentioned that the Presidency were the very people responsible for taking out this loan—they're both creditors and representatives for all the other creditors. For this reason, the Court of Directors accuses them of breaching their trust; yet, the honorable gentleman sees them as completely valid authority on those claims. It's quite amusing to hear a lawyer use creditor approval as a basis for their own debt.

How they came to contract the debt to themselves, how they came to act as agents for those whom they ought to have controlled, is for your inquiry. The policy of this debt was announced to the Court of Directors by the very persons concerned in creating it. "Till very lately," say the Presidency, "the Nabob placed his dependence on the Company. Now he has been taught by ill advisers that an interest out of doors may stand him in good stead. He has been made to believe that his private creditors have power and interest to overrule the Court of Directors."[10] The Nabob was not misinformed. The private creditors instantly qualified a vast number of votes; and having made themselves masters of the Court of Proprietors, as well as extending a powerful cabal in other places as important, they so completely overturned the authority of the Court of Directors at home and abroad, that this poor, baffled government was soon obliged to lower its tone. It was glad to be admitted into partnership with its own servants. The Court of Directors, establishing the debt which they had reprobated as a breach of trust, and which was planned for the subversion of their authority, settled its payments on a par with those of the public; and even so were not able to obtain peace, or even equality in their demands. All the consequences lay in a regular and irresistible train. By employing their influence for the recovery of this debt, their orders, issued in the same breath, against creating new debts, only animated the strong desires of their servants to this prohibited prolific sport, and it soon produced a swarm of sons and daughters, not in the least degenerated from the virtue of their parents.

How they ended up owing themselves money and acting as representatives for those they should have been controlling is something you should look into. The Court of Directors was informed about this debt policy by those directly involved in creating it. "Until recently," say the Presidency, "the Nabob relied on the Company. Now he’s been misled by bad advisors to think that outside interests could benefit him. He has come to believe that his private creditors have the power and influence to override the Court of Directors."[10] The Nabob was not wrong. The private creditors quickly gained a large number of votes and managed to dominate the Court of Proprietors, while also forming a powerful group elsewhere that was equally important. They completely undermined the authority of the Court of Directors both at home and abroad, forcing this struggling government to tone down its stance. They were relieved to be accepted as partners with their own employees. The Court of Directors, who had condemned the debt as a betrayal of trust and who had designed it to undermine their power, ended up agreeing to payments on par with public debts; and even then, they were unable to achieve peace or fairness in their demands. All the fallout followed a predictable and unstoppable path. By using their influence to recover this debt, their simultaneous orders against incurring new debts only fueled the strong desires of their employees for this forbidden but lucrative endeavor, quickly resulting in a proliferation of offspring that bore no less virtue than their parents.

From that moment the authority of the Court of Directors expired in the Carnatic, and everywhere else. "Every man," says the Presidency, "who opposes the government and its measures, finds an immediate countenance from the Nabob; even our discarded officers, however unworthy, are received into the Nabob's service."[11] It was, indeed, a matter of no wonderful sagacity to determine whether the Court of Directors, with their miserable salaries to their servants, of four or five hundred pounds a year, or the distributor of millions, was most likely to be obeyed. It was an invention beyond the imagination of all the speculatists of our speculating age, to see a government quietly settled in one and the same town, composed of two distinct members: one to pay scantily for obedience, and the other to bribe high for rebellion and revolt.

From that moment, the authority of the Court of Directors ended in the Carnatic and everywhere else. "Every person," says the Presidency, "who opposes the government and its policies, receives immediate support from the Nabob; even our dismissed officers, no matter how unworthy, are welcomed into the Nabob's service." It was, indeed, not surprising to figure out whether the Court of Directors, offering miserable salaries to their employees of four or five hundred pounds a year, or the one distributing millions, would be obeyed. It was beyond the imagination of all the thinkers in our speculative era to see a government comfortably established in one town, composed of two distinct parts: one that pays little for obedience and another that offers large bribes for rebellion and revolt.

The next thing which recommends this particular debt to the right honorable gentleman is, it seems, the moderate interest of ten per cent. It would be lost labor to observe on this assertion. The Nabob, in a long apologetic letter[12] for the transaction between him and the body of the creditors, states the fact as I shall state it to you. In the accumulation of this debt, the first interest paid was from thirty to thirty-six per cent; it was then brought down to twenty-five per cent; at length it was reduced to twenty; and there it found its rest. During the whole process, as often as any of these monstrous interests fell into an arrear, (into which they were continually falling,) the arrear, formed into a new capital,[13] was added to the old, and the same interest of twenty per cent accrued upon both. The Company, having got some scent of the enormous usury which prevailed at Madras, thought it necessary to interfere, and to order all interests to be lowered to ten per cent. This order, which contained no exception, though it by no means pointed particularly to this class of debts, came like a thunderclap on the Nabob. He considered his political credit as ruined; but to find a remedy to this unexpected evil, he again added to the old principal twenty per cent interest accruing for the last year. Thus a new fund was formed; and it was on that accumulation of various principals, and interests heaped upon interests, not on the sum originally lent, as the right honorable gentleman would make you believe, that ten per cent was settled on the whole.

The next thing that makes this particular debt appealing to the honorable gentleman is the moderate interest of ten percent. It would be pointless to comment on this claim. The Nabob, in a long apologetic letter[12] regarding the dealings between him and the group of creditors, lays out the facts as I will share them with you. In accumulating this debt, the initial interest paid ranged from thirty to thirty-six percent; it was then reduced to twenty-five percent; finally, it settled at twenty percent, where it remained. Throughout this entire process, whenever any of these outrageous interest rates fell into arrears (which happened constantly), the arrears were turned into new capital,[13] which was added to the old principal, and the same twenty percent interest accrued on both. The Company, having caught wind of the excessive usury in Madras, decided to intervene and ordered all interest rates to be lowered to ten percent. This order, which had no exceptions and didn't specifically target this category of debts, hit the Nabob like a thunderbolt. He believed his political reputation was ruined; however, to address this unexpected problem, he added twenty percent interest from the past year to the old principal. This created a new fund; and it was based on this accumulation of various principals and interests piled upon interests—not on the initial sum lent, as the honorable gentleman would have you believe—that ten percent was applied to the whole.

When you consider the enormity of the interest at which these debts were contracted, and the several interests added to the principal, I believe you will not think me so skeptical, if I should doubt whether for this debt of 880,000l. the Nabob ever saw 100,000l. in real money. The right honorable gentleman suspecting, with all his absolute dominion over fact, that he never will be able to defend even this venerable patriarchal job, though sanctified by its numerous issue, and hoary with prescriptive years, has recourse to recrimination, the last resource of guilt. He says that this loan of 1767 was provided for in Mr. Fox's India bill; and judging of others by his own nature and principles, he more than insinuates that this provision was made, not from any sense of merit in the claim, but from partiality to General Smith, a proprietor, and an agent for that debt. If partiality could have had any weight against justice and policy with the then ministers and their friends, General Smith had titles to it. But the right honorable gentleman knows as well as I do, that General Smith was very far from looking on himself as partially treated in the arrangements of that time; indeed, what man dared to hope for private partiality in that sacred plan for relief to nations?

When you think about the massive interest on these debts and the various fees added to the principal, I doubt you’ll think I’m overly skeptical if I question whether the Nabob actually received more than 100,000l. of the total 880,000l. in real cash. The right honorable gentleman, fully confident in his control over facts, seems to realize he can’t defend even this long-standing, traditional arrangement, despite its many outcomes and age. So, he resorts to accusations— the last refuge of guilt. He claims that this loan from 1767 was accounted for in Mr. Fox's India bill and suggests, based on his own character and principles, that this was not due to any merit of the claim but rather favoritism toward General Smith, who is a shareholder and an advocate for that debt. If favoritism could outweigh justice and policy among the ministers and their allies back then, General Smith had reasons to claim it. But the right honorable gentleman knows, just as I do, that General Smith did not feel he was treated unfairly in those arrangements; in fact, which person would expect special treatment in that critical plan for national relief?

It is not necessary that the right honorable gentleman should sarcastically call that time to our recollection. Well do I remember every circumstance of that memorable period. God forbid I should forget it! O illustrious disgrace! O victorious defeat! May your memorial be fresh and new to the latest generations! May the day of that generous conflict be stamped in characters never to be cancelled or worn out from the records of time! Let no man hear of us, who shall not hear, that, in a struggle against the intrigues of courts and the perfidious levity of the multitude, we fell in the cause of honor, in the cause of our country, in the cause of human nature itself! But if fortune should be as powerful over fame as she has been prevalent over virtue, at least our conscience is beyond her jurisdiction. My poor share in the support of that great measure no man shall ravish from me. It shall be safely lodged in the sanctuary of my heart,—never, never to be torn from thence, but with those holds that grapple it to life.

It’s unnecessary for the honorable gentleman to sarcastically remind us of that time. I remember every detail of that significant period vividly. God forbid I ever forget it! Oh, glorious disgrace! Oh, victorious defeat! May your memory remain fresh for future generations! May the day of that brave struggle be etched in indelible characters in the annals of history! Let no one hear about us who doesn’t know that, in our fight against the manipulations of politics and the fickle nature of the masses, we fell in the name of honor, in the name of our country, in the name of humanity itself! But if fate holds as much power over our reputation as it has over our virtues, at least our conscience remains beyond its reach. No one can take away my small part in supporting that great cause. It will forever be safely kept in the sanctuary of my heart—never, ever to be torn away, except by those bonds that tie it to life.

I say, I well remember that bill, and every one of its honest and its wise provisions. It is not true that this debt was ever protected or enforced, or any revenue whatsoever set apart for it. It was left in that bill just where it stood: to be paid or not to be paid out of the Nabob's private treasures, according to his own discretion. The Company had actually given it their sanction, though always relying for its validity on the sole security of the faith of him[14] who without their knowledge or consent entered into the original obligation. It had no other sanction; it ought to have had no other. So far was Mr. Fox's bill from providing funds for it, as this ministry have wickedly done for this, and for ten times worse transactions, out of the public estate, that an express clause immediately preceded, positively forbidding any British subject from receiving assignments upon any part of the territorial revenue, on any pretence whatsoever.[15]

I remember that bill clearly, along with all its fair and wise provisions. It's not true that this debt was ever backed or enforced, or that any funds were set aside for it. It was just left in that bill, to be paid or not paid from the Nabob's personal wealth, at his discretion. The Company actually approved it, but always relied solely on the faith of the person who entered into the initial obligation without their knowledge or consent. It had no other backing; it shouldn’t have had any. Mr. Fox's bill did not provide funds for it, unlike what this government has wrongly done for this and even worse situations, using the public estate. In fact, there was a specific clause right before it that explicitly forbade any British subject from receiving assignments on any part of the territorial revenue for any reason at all.

You recollect, Mr. Speaker, that the Chancellor of the Exchequer strongly professed to retain every part of Mr. Fox's bill which was intended to prevent abuse; but in his India bill, which (let me do justice) is as able and skilful a performance, for its own purposes, as ever issued from the wit of man, premeditating this iniquity,—

You remember, Mr. Speaker, that the Chancellor of the Exchequer insisted on keeping every part of Mr. Fox's bill that was meant to prevent misuse; however, in his India bill, which (to be fair) is as competent and skillful a work, for its own goals, as anything ever created by human intellect, planned this wrongdoing,—

This was to build it up and open Troy to the Greeks,—

expunged this essential clause, broke down the fence which was raised to cover the public property against the rapacity of his partisans, and thus levelling every obstruction, he made a firm, broad highway for sin and death, for usury and oppression, to renew their ravages throughout the devoted revenues of the Carnatic.

expunged this essential clause, broke down the fence that was put up to protect public property from the greed of his supporters, and by removing every obstacle, he created a wide, clear path for sin and death, for usury and oppression, to continue their devastation across the beleaguered resources of the Carnatic.

The tenor, the policy, and the consequences of this debt of 1767 are in the eyes of ministry so excellent, that its merits are irresistible; and it takes the lead to give credit and countenance to all the rest. Along with this chosen body of heavy-armed infantry, and to support it in the line, the right honorable gentleman has stationed his corps of black cavalry. If there be any advantage between this debt and that of 1769, according to him the cavalry debt has it. It is not a subject of defence: it is a theme of panegyric. Listen to the right honorable gentleman, and you will find it was contracted to save the country,—to prevent mutiny in armies,—to introduce economy in revenues; and for all these honorable purposes, it originated at the express desire and by the representative authority of the Company itself.

The importance, policy, and impact of this debt from 1767 are seen by the ministry as so outstanding that its value is undeniable; it leads the way in supporting and giving credibility to everything else. Together with this selected group of heavily armed infantry, to back it up on the front lines, the right honorable gentleman has positioned his unit of black cavalry. According to him, if there's an advantage between this debt and that of 1769, the cavalry debt clearly has the edge. This isn't just a topic for defense; it's a subject for praise. If you listen to the right honorable gentleman, you'll realize it was taken on to protect the country—to prevent army mutiny—to promote efficiency in revenues; and for all these honorable reasons, it was initiated at the express request and by the authorized representation of the Company itself.

First let me say a word to the authority. This debt was contracted, not by the authority of the Company, not by its representatives, (as the right honorable gentleman has the unparalleled confidence to assert,) but in the ever-memorable period of 1777, by the usurped power of those who rebelliously, in conjunction with the Nabob of Arcot, had overturned the lawful government of Madras. For that rebellion this House unanimously directed a public prosecution. The delinquents, after they had subverted government, in order to make to themselves a party to support them in their power, are universally known to have dealt jobs about to the right and to the left, and to any who were willing to receive them. This usurpation, which the right honorable gentleman well knows was brought about by and for the great mass of these pretended debts, is the authority which is set up by him to represent the Company,—to represent that Company which, from the first moment of their hearing of this corrupt and fraudulent transaction to this hour, have uniformly disowned and disavowed it.

First, let me address the authority. This debt was not contracted by the Company’s authority or its representatives, no matter how confidently the right honorable gentleman claims otherwise. Instead, it was incurred during the significant events of 1777, by the usurped power of those who, in rebellion and in alliance with the Nabob of Arcot, had overthrown the legitimate government of Madras. For this rebellion, this House unanimously called for a public prosecution. The wrongdoers, after dismantling the government, sought to create a faction to support their power, and it is well known that they distributed favors to anyone willing to accept them. This usurpation, which the right honorable gentleman knows was in large part caused by these so-called debts, is the authority he uses to represent the Company— the same Company that has consistently rejected and disavowed this corrupt and fraudulent transaction from the moment they first learned about it up to now.

So much for the authority. As to the facts, partly true, and partly colorable, as they stand recorded, they are in substance these. The Nabob of Arcot, as soon as he had thrown off the superiority of this country by means of these creditors, kept up a great army which he never paid. Of course his soldiers were generally in a state of mutiny.[16] The usurping Council say that they labored hard with their master, the Nabob, to persuade him to reduce these mutinous and useless troops. He consented; but, as usual, pleaded inability to pay them their arrears. Here was a difficulty. The Nabob had no money; the Company had no money; every public supply was empty. But there was one resource which no season has ever yet dried up in that climate. The soucars were at hand: that is, private English money-jobbers offered their assistance. Messieurs Taylor, Majendie, and Call proposed to advance the small sum of 160,000l. to pay off the Nabob's black cavalry, provided the Company's authority was given for their loan. This was the great point of policy always aimed at, and pursued through a hundred devices by the servants at Madras. The Presidency, who themselves had no authority for the functions they presumed to exercise, very readily gave the sanction of the Company to those servants who knew that the Company, whose sanction was demanded, had positively prohibited all such transactions.

So much for the authority. As for the facts, they’re partly true and partly misleading as recorded. In essence, here’s what happened: the Nabob of Arcot, once he broke free from the control of this country thanks to his creditors, maintained a large army that he never paid. Naturally, his soldiers were often in a state of rebellion.[16] The usurping Council claims they worked hard with their master, the Nabob, to convince him to reduce these rebellious and unnecessary troops. He agreed, but as usual, he claimed he couldn't pay them their back wages. This created a problem. The Nabob had no money; the Company had no money; every public supply was drained. However, there was one resource that has never run dry in that climate. The soucars were available: that is, private English money lenders were willing to help. Messieurs Taylor, Majendie, and Call offered to loan the small amount of 160,000l. to pay off the Nabob's black cavalry, as long as they had the Company’s authority for the loan. This was the key point of policy that the servants in Madras had always aimed for and pursued through many schemes. The Presidency, who themselves had no authority for the actions they were taking, quickly approved the Company’s backing for those servants who knew very well that the Company, whose approval they sought, had explicitly banned all such dealings.

However, so far as the reality of the dealing goes, all is hitherto fair and plausible; and here the right honorable gentleman concludes, with commendable prudence, his account of the business. But here it is I shall beg leave to commence my supplement: for the gentleman's discreet modesty has led him to cut the thread of the story somewhat abruptly. One of the most essential parties is quite forgotten. Why should the episode of the poor Nabob be omitted? When that prince chooses it, nobody can tell his story better. Excuse me, if I apply again to my book, and give it you from the first hand: from the Nabob himself.

However, as far as the reality of the situation goes, everything so far is fair and believable; and here the honorable gentleman wisely concludes his account of the matter. But this is where I'd like to start my addition: the gentleman's modesty has caused him to end the story a bit abruptly. One of the most important parties is completely overlooked. Why should the story of the poor Nabob be left out? When that prince chooses to share it, no one can tell his story better. Please excuse me for referring back to my book and giving it to you straight from the source: from the Nabob himself.

"Mr. Stratton became acquainted with this, and got Mr. Taylor and others to lend me four lacs of pagodas towards discharging the arrears of pay of my troops. Upon this, I wrote a letter of thanks to Mr. Stratton; and upon the faith of this money being paid immediately, I ordered many of my troops to be discharged by a certain day, and lessened the number of my servants. Mr. Taylor, &c., some time after acquainted me, that they had no ready money, but they would grant teeps payable in four months. This astonished me; for I did not know what might happen, when the sepoys were dismissed from my service. I begged of Mr. Taylor and the others to pay this sum to the officers of my regiments at the time they mentioned; and desired the officers, at the same time, to pacify and persuade the men belonging to them that their pay would be given to them at the end of four months, and that, till those arrears were discharged, their pay should be continued to them. Two years are nearly expired since that time, but Mr. Taylor has not yet entirely discharged the arrears of those troops, and I am obliged to continue their pay from that time till this. I hoped to have been able, by this expedient, to have lessened the number of my troops, and discharged the arrears due to them, considering the trifle of interest to Mr. Taylor and the others as no great matter; but instead of this, I am oppressed with the burden of pay due to those troops, and the interest, which is going on to Mr. Taylor from the day the teeps were granted to him." What I have read to you is an extract of a letter from the Nabob of the Carnatic to Governor Rumbold, dated the 22d, and received the 24th of March, 1779.[17]

"Mr. Stratton found out about this, and got Mr. Taylor and others to lend me four lacs of pagodas to cover the overdue pay of my troops. Because of this, I wrote a thank-you letter to Mr. Stratton; and relying on this money being paid right away, I ordered many of my troops to be let go by a certain date, and reduced the number of my servants. Some time later, Mr. Taylor and others informed me that they had no cash available, but they would provide teeps payable in four months. This shocked me because I didn’t know what might happen when the sepoys were released from my service. I asked Mr. Taylor and the others to pay this amount to the officers of my regiments at the stated time; and I requested the officers to reassure and persuade their men that their pay would be provided at the end of four months, and that, until those arrears were settled, their pay would continue. Nearly two years have passed since then, but Mr. Taylor still hasn't fully cleared the arrears of those troops, and I have had to keep paying them since that time. I hoped to reduce the number of my troops and settle the debts owed to them, thinking the small interest owed to Mr. Taylor and the others wouldn't be a big deal; but instead, I am burdened with the unpaid wages to those troops, along with the interest that has been accruing for Mr. Taylor since the day the teeps were granted to him. What I just shared is an excerpt from a letter from the Nabob of the Carnatic to Governor Rumbold, dated the 22nd, and received on the 24th of March, 1779.[17]

Suppose his Highness not to be well broken in to things of this kind, it must, indeed, surprise so known and established a bond-vender as the Nabob of Arcot, one who keeps himself the largest bond-warehouse in the world, to find that he was now to receive in kind: not to take money for his obligations, but to give his bond in exchange for the bond of Messieurs Taylor, Majendie, and Call, and to pay, besides, a good, smart interest, legally twelve per cent, (in reality, perhaps, twenty or twenty-four per cent,) for this exchange of paper. But his troops were not to be so paid, or so disbanded. They wanted bread, and could not live by cutting and shuffling of bonds. The Nabob still kept the troops in service, and was obliged to continue, as you have seen, the whole expense to exonerate himself from which he became indebted to the soucars.

Suppose His Highness isn't very familiar with matters like this. It must be quite a shock for a well-known and established bond dealer like the Nabob of Arcot, who runs the largest bond warehouse in the world, to learn that he was now to receive in kind—not taking money for his obligations, but giving his bond in exchange for the bond of Messieurs Taylor, Majendie, and Call, and also paying a significant interest, legally at twelve percent (but in reality, maybe twenty or twenty-four percent), for this paper exchange. However, his troops weren't going to be paid or disbanded that way. They needed food and couldn’t survive on just trading bonds. The Nabob kept the troops in service and, as you've seen, had to bear the entire cost to free himself from the debts he owed to the soucars.

Had it stood here, the transaction would have been of the most audacious strain of fraud and usury perhaps ever before discovered, whatever might have been practised and concealed. But the same authority (I mean the Nabob's) brings before you something, if possible, more striking. He states, that, for this their paper, he immediately handed over to these gentlemen something very different from paper,—that is, the receipt of a territorial revenue, of which, it seems, they continued as long in possession as the Nabob himself continued in possession of anything. Their payments, therefore, not being to commence before the end of four months, and not being completed in two years, it must be presumed (unless they prove the contrary) that their payments to the Nabob were made out of the revenues they had received from his assignment. Thus they condescended to accumulate a debt of 160,000l. with an interest of twelve per cent, in compensation for a lingering payment to the Nabob of 160,000l. of his own money.

If this had happened here, the deal would have been one of the most outrageous acts of fraud and usury ever discovered, no matter what was done and hidden. But the same authority (I mean the Nabob's) presents something even more shocking. He says that, for this paper, he immediately gave these gentlemen something very different from paper—that is, a receipt for a territorial revenue, which, it seems, they held onto for as long as the Nabob had anything. Since their payments weren’t set to begin for four months and wouldn’t be completed for two years, it must be assumed (unless they can prove otherwise) that their payments to the Nabob came from the revenues they received from his assignment. Thus, they agreed to incur a debt of 160,000l. at an interest of twelve per cent, as compensation for a delayed payment to the Nabob of 160,000l. of his own money.

Still we have not the whole. About two years after the assignment of those territorial revenues to these gentlemen, the Nabob receives a remonstrance from his chief manager in a principal province, of which this is the tenor. "The entire revenue of those districts is by your Highness's order set apart to discharge the tunkaws [assignments] granted to the Europeans. The gomastahs [agents] of Mr. Taylor to Mr. De Fries are there in order to collect those tunkaws; and as they receive all the revenue that is collected, your Highness's troops have seven or eight months' pay due, which they cannot receive, and are thereby reduced to the greatest distress. In such times it is highly necessary to provide for the sustenance of the troops, that they may be ready to exert themselves in the service of your Highness."

Still, we don't have the complete picture. About two years after those territorial revenues were assigned to these gentlemen, the Nabob receives a complaint from his chief manager in a major province, and this is what it says: "The total revenue of those districts has been set aside by your Highness's order to pay the tunkaws [assignments] granted to the Europeans. The gomastahs [agents] of Mr. Taylor to Mr. De Fries are there to collect those tunkaws; and since they receive all the revenue collected, your Highness's troops have seven or eight months’ pay due, which they cannot receive, and they are therefore in great distress. In these times, it is crucial to provide for the troops' sustenance so they can be ready to serve your Highness."

Here, Sir, you see how these causes and effects act upon one another. One body of troops mutinies for want of pay; a debt is contracted to pay them; and they still remain unpaid. A territory destined to pay other troops is assigned for this debt; and these other troops fall into the same state of indigence and mutiny with the first. Bond is paid by bond; arrear is turned into new arrear; usury engenders new usury; mutiny, suspended in one quarter, starts up in another; until all the revenues and all the establishments are entangled into one inextricable knot of confusion, from which they are only disengaged by being entirely destroyed. In that state of confusion, in a very few months after the date of the memorial I have just read to you, things were found, when the Nabob's troops, famished to feed English soucars, instead of defending the country, joined the invaders, and deserted in entire bodies to Hyder Ali.[18]

Here, Sir, you can see how these causes and effects influence each other. One group of soldiers revolts due to unpaid wages; a debt is incurred to pay them, and they remain unpaid. A region meant to supply funds for other soldiers is designated to cover this debt; those other soldiers become just as poor and rebellious as the first group. Indebts are settled with new debts; delays turn into further delays; exploitation creates more exploitation; unrest that is paused in one area erupts in another; until all revenues and systems are caught in a tangled mess that can only be resolved through complete destruction. In that state of chaos, just a few months after the date of the memorandum I just shared with you, it was found that the Nabob's troops, starving to pay English dues, switched sides and joined the invaders, abandoning their posts entirely to Hyder Ali.[18]

The manner in which this transaction was carried on shows that good examples are not easily forgot, especially by those who are bred in a great school. One of those splendid examples give me leave to mention, at a somewhat more early period; because one fraud furnishes light to the discovery of another, and so on, until the whole secret of mysterious iniquity bursts upon you in a blaze of detection. The paper I shall read you is not on record. If you please, you may take it on my word. It is a letter written from one of undoubted information in Madras to Sir John Clavering, describing the practice that prevailed there, whilst the Company's allies were under sale, during the time of Governor Winch's administration.

The way this transaction was handled shows that good examples are not easily forgotten, especially by those who come from a great institution. I’d like to mention one of those great examples from an earlier time; because one instance of fraud sheds light on another, and so forth, until the entire secret of hidden wrongdoing is revealed in a flash of exposure. The document I’m about to read is not officially recorded. If you’d like, you can take my word for it. It’s a letter from a reliable source in Madras to Sir John Clavering, explaining the practices that were common there while the Company's allies were being sold during Governor Winch's administration.

"One mode," says Clavering's correspondent, "of amassing money at the Nabob's cost is curious. He is generally in arrears to the Company. Here the Governor, being cash-keeper, is generally on good terms with the banker, who manages matters thus. The Governor presses the Nabob for the balance due from him; the Nabob flies to his banker for relief; the banker engages to pay the money, and grants his notes accordingly, which he puts in the cash-book as ready money; the Nabob pays him an interest for it at two and three per cent per mensem, till the tunkaws he grants on the particular districts for it are paid. Matters in the mean time are so managed that there is no call for this money for the Company's service till the tunkaws become due. By this means not a cash is advanced by the banker, though he receives a heavy interest from the Nabob, which is divided as lawful spoil."

"One way," says Clavering's correspondent, "to make money at the Nabob's expense is quite interesting. He usually owes the Company money. Here, the Governor, acting as the cash manager, typically has a good relationship with the banker, who handles things like this. The Governor pressures the Nabob to pay what he owes; the Nabob rushes to his banker for help; the banker agrees to pay the amount and issues his notes accordingly, which he records in the cash-book as available cash; the Nabob pays him interest at two to three percent per month until the tunkaws he issues for certain districts are settled. In the meantime, things are arranged so that there's no need for this money for the Company's use until the tunkaws are due. This way, the banker doesn't actually provide any cash, even though he earns a hefty interest from the Nabob, which is then shared as legal profit."

Here, Mr. Speaker, you have the whole art and mystery, the true free-mason secret, of the profession of soucaring; by which a few innocent, inexperienced young Englishmen, such as Mr. Paul Benfield, for instance, without property upon which any one would lend to themselves a single shilling, are enabled at once to take provinces in mortgage, to make princes their debtors, and to become creditors for millions.

Here, Mr. Speaker, you have the entire skill and mystery, the real secret of the profession of soucaring; through which a handful of naive, inexperienced young Englishmen, like Mr. Paul Benfield, for example, without any assets that anyone would lend them even a penny, are able to instantly mortgage provinces, make princes owe them money, and become creditors for millions.

But it seems the right honorable gentleman's favorite soucar cavalry have proved the payment before the Mayor's Court at Madras! Have they so? Why, then, defraud our anxiety and their characters of that proof? Is it not enough that the charges which I have laid before you have stood on record against these poor injured gentlemen for eight years? Is it not enough that they are in print by the orders of the East India Company for five years? After these gentlemen have borne all the odium of this publication and all the indignation of the Directors with such unexampled equanimity, now that they are at length stimulated into feeling are you to deny them their just relief? But will the right honorable gentleman be pleased to tell us how they came not to give this satisfaction to the Court of Directors, their lawful masters, during all the eight years of this litigated claim? Were they not bound, by every tie that can bind man, to give them this satisfaction? This day, for the first time, we hear of the proofs. But when were these proofs offered? In what cause? Who were the parties? Who inspected, who contested this belated account? Let us see something to oppose to the body of record which appears against them. The Mayor's Court! the Mayor's Court! Pleasant! Does not the honorable gentleman know that the first corps of creditors (the creditors of 1767) stated it as a sort of hardship to them, that they could not have justice at Madras, from the impossibility of their supporting their claims in the Mayor's Court? Why? Because, say they, the members of that court were themselves creditors, and therefore could not sit as judges.[19] Are we ripe to say that no creditor under similar circumstances was member of the court, when the payment which is the ground of this cavalry debt was put in proof?[20] Nay, are we not in a manner compelled to conclude that the court was so constituted, when we know there is scarcely a man in Madras who has not some participation in these transactions? It is a shame to hear such proofs mentioned, instead of the honest, vigorous scrutiny which the circumstances of such an affair so indispensably call for.

But it seems that the right honorable gentleman's favorite cavalry has shown proof of payment before the Mayor's Court in Madras! Really? Then why deny our concerns and their reputations this proof? Isn't it enough that the accusations I've presented to you have been recorded against these injured gentlemen for eight years? Isn’t it enough that they have been published by the orders of the East India Company for five years? After these gentlemen have endured all the backlash from this publication and the Directors' outrage with such remarkable calmness, now that they are finally moved to respond, are you going to deny them their rightful relief? But will the right honorable gentleman please explain why they didn’t provide this evidence to the Court of Directors, their legal superiors, in all eight years of this disputed claim? Weren’t they obligated, by every bond that can bind a person, to give them this proof? Today, for the first time, we hear about these proofs. But when were these proofs presented? In what case? Who were the parties involved? Who examined and contested this late account? Let's see something to counter the official record against them. The Mayor's Court! The Mayor's Court! How amusing! Doesn't the honorable gentleman realize that the initial group of creditors (the creditors of 1767) expressed it as a grievance that they couldn’t get justice in Madras due to the impossibility of supporting their claims in the Mayor's Court? Why? Because, they say, the members of that court were themselves creditors and therefore couldn’t serve as judges. Are we ready to claim that no creditor under similar circumstances was a member of the court when the payment that triggered this cavalry debt was evidence? Nay, aren’t we almost forced to conclude that the court was structured that way when we know there’s hardly anyone in Madras who hasn’t had some involvement in these transactions? It’s shameful to mention such proofs instead of the honest, thorough examination that the details of this situation so urgently require.

But his Majesty's ministers, indulgent enough to other scrutinies, have not been satisfied with authorizing the payment of this demand without such inquiry as the act has prescribed; but they have added the arrear of twelve per cent interest, from the year 1777 to the year 1784, to make a new capital, raising thereby 160 to 294,000l. Then they charge a new twelve per cent on the whole from that period, for a transaction in which it will be a miracle if a single penny will be ever found really advanced from the private stock of the pretended creditors.

But the king's ministers, lenient enough with other investigations, haven't been satisfied with just authorizing the payment of this demand without the inquiry that the act requires; instead, they've added the twelve percent interest owed from 1777 to 1784 to create a new total, increasing it from 160 to 294,000l. Then they apply another twelve percent on the entire amount from that time, for a deal in which it would be a miracle if even a single penny is ever found genuinely coming from the personal funds of the so-called creditors.

In this manner, and at such an interest, the ministers have thought proper to dispose of 294,000l. of the public revenues, for what is called the Cavalry Loan. After dispatching this, the right honorable gentleman leads to battle his last grand division, the consolidated debt of 1777. But having exhausted all his panegyric on the two first, he has nothing at all to say in favor of the last. On the contrary, he admits that it was contracted in defiance of the Company's orders, without even the pretended sanction of any pretended representatives. Nobody, indeed, has yet been found hardy enough to stand forth avowedly in its defence. But it is little to the credit of the age, that what has not plausibility enough to find an advocate has influence enough to obtain a protector. Could any man expect to find that protector anywhere? But what must every man think, when he finds that protector in the chairman of the Committee of Secrecy[21], who had published to the House, and to the world, the facts that condemn these debts, the orders that forbid the incurring of them, the dreadful consequences which attended them? Even in his official letter, when he tramples on his Parliamentary report, yet his general language is the same. Read the preface to this part of the ministerial arrangement, and you would imagine that this debt was to be crushed, with all the weight of indignation which could fall from a vigilant guardian of the public treasury upon those who attempted to rob it. What must be felt by every man who has feeling, when, after such a thundering preamble of condemnation, this debt is ordered to be paid without any sort of inquiry into its authenticity,—without a single step taken to settle even the amount of the demand,—without an attempt so much as to ascertain the real persons claiming a sum which rises in the accounts from one million three hundred thousand pound sterling to two million four hundred thousand pound, principal money,[22]—without an attempt made to ascertain the proprietors, of whom no list has ever yet been laid before the Court of Directors,—of proprietors who are known to be in a collusive shuffle, by which they never appear to be the same in any two lists handed about for their own particular purposes?

In this way, and at such an interest rate, the ministers have decided to allocate £294,000 of the public funds for what’s known as the Cavalry Loan. After addressing this, the right honorable gentleman brings forth his last major topic, the consolidated debt of 1777. But after praising the first two, he has nothing positive to say about the last one. In fact, he acknowledges that it was incurred against the Company’s orders, without even the supposed approval of any supposed representatives. No one, it seems, has been bold enough to defend it openly. Yet, it’s not great for our era that what lacks enough credibility to find a supporter has the power to secure a protector. Could anyone really expect to find such a protector anywhere? But what must everyone think when this protector is the chairman of the Committee of Secrecy[21], who has revealed to the House and the public the facts that condemn these debts, the orders that prevent accruing them, and the terrible consequences that followed? Even in his official letter, when he disregards his Parliamentary report, his overall tone remains the same. Read the preface to this part of the ministerial arrangement, and you might believe that this debt would be crushed with all the indignation that a vigilant guardian of the public treasury could express against those trying to plunder it. What must every compassionate person feel when, after such a thunderous introduction of condemnation, this debt is ordered to be paid without any inquiry into its legitimacy—without even a single step taken to verify the amount being claimed—without any attempt to determine the actual individuals requesting a sum that ranges in the accounts from £1,300,000 to £2,400,000 in principal,[22]—without any effort made to identify the owners, of whom no list has ever been presented to the Court of Directors—owners who are known to engage in a collusive game, making them appear differently in any two lists circulated for their own specific purposes?

My honorable friend who made you the motion has sufficiently exposed the nature of this debt. He has stated to you, that its own agents, in the year 1781, in the arrangement they proposed to make at Calcutta, were satisfied to have twenty-five per cent at once struck off from the capital of a great part of this debt, and prayed to have a provision made for this reduced principal, without any interest at all. This was an arrangement of their own, an arrangement made by those who best knew the true constitution of their own debt, who knew how little favor it merited,[23] and how little hopes they had to find any persons in authority abandoned enough to support it as it stood.

My respected friend who brought up this motion has clearly explained the nature of this debt. He mentioned that its own representatives, in 1781, during the arrangement they suggested in Calcutta, were willing to have twenty-five percent immediately deducted from the principal of a large part of this debt and requested that a provision be made for this reduced principal without any interest at all. This was an arrangement of their own, created by those who understood their debt best, who knew how little merit it had,[23] and how few hopes they had of finding any authorities brave enough to support it as it was.

But what corrupt men, in the fond imaginations of a sanguine avarice, had not the confidence to propose, they have found a Chancellor of the Exchequer in England hardy enough to undertake for them. He has cheered their drooping spirits. He has thanked the peculators for not despairing of their commonwealth. He has told them they were too modest. He has replaced the twenty-five per cent which, in order to lighten themselves, they had abandoned in their conscious terror. Instead of cutting off the interest, as they had themselves consented to do, with the fourth of the capital, he has added the whole growth of four years' usury of twelve per cent to the first overgrown principal; and has again grafted on this meliorated stock a perpetual annuity of six per cent, to take place from the year 1781. Let no man hereafter talk of the decaying energies of Nature. All the acts and monuments in the records of peculation, the consolidated corruption of ages, the patterns of exemplary plunder in the heroic times of Roman iniquity, never equalled the gigantic corruption of this single act. Never did Nero, in all the insolent prodigality of despotism, deal out to his prætorian guards a donation fit to be named with the largess showered down by the bounty of our Chancellor of the Exchequer on the faithful band of his Indian sepoys.

But what corrupt individuals, in their hopeful greed, didn’t have the nerve to suggest, they’ve found a Chancellor of the Exchequer in England bold enough to take on their cause. He has lifted their spirits. He has expressed gratitude to the embezzlers for not giving up on their nation. He has told them they were too humble. He has restored the twenty-five percent that they had given up in their aware fear to relieve their burdens. Instead of cutting off the interest, as they had agreed to do, along with a quarter of the capital, he has added four years’ worth of interest at twelve percent to the already inflated principal; and has again attached a perpetual annuity of six percent, to start from the year 1781. Let no one hereafter speak of the declining energies of Nature. All the acts and records of embezzlement, the accumulated corruption of ages, the examples of blatant theft from the heroic times of Roman wickedness, never matched the immense corruption of this single act. Never did Nero, in all his arrogant excess of despotism, hand out a gift that could compare to the bounty given by our Chancellor of the Exchequer to the loyal group of his Indian sepoys.

The right honorable gentleman[24] lets you freely and voluntarily into the whole transaction. So perfectly has his conduct confounded his understanding, that he fairly tells you that through the course of the whole business he has never conferred with any but the agents of the pretended creditors. After this, do you want more to establish a secret understanding with the parties,—to fix, beyond a doubt, their collusion and participation in a common fraud?

The honorable gentleman[24] invites you to take a look at the entire situation freely and voluntarily. His actions have so completely confused his reasoning that he openly admits that throughout the entire process, he has only spoken with the agents of the so-called creditors. After this, do you need any further proof to show there’s a hidden agreement between the parties—to confirm, without a doubt, their collusion and involvement in a shared fraud?

If this were not enough, he has furnished you with other presumptions that are not to be shaken. It is one of the known indications of guilt to stagger and prevaricate in a story, and to vary in the motives that are assigned to conduct. Try these ministers by this rule. In their official dispatch, they tell the Presidency of Madras that they have established the debt for two reasons: first, because the Nabob (the party indebted) does not dispute it; secondly, because it is mischievous to keep it longer afloat, and that the payment of the European creditors will promote circulation in the country. These two motives (for the plainest reasons in the world) the right honorable gentleman has this day thought fit totally to abandon. In the first place, he rejects the authority of the Nabob of Arcot. It would, indeed, be pleasant to see him adhere to this exploded testimony. He next, upon grounds equally solid, abandons the benefits of that circulation which was to be produced by drawing out all the juices of the body. Laying aside, or forgetting, these pretences of his dispatch, he has just now assumed a principle totally different, but to the full as extraordinary. He proceeds upon a supposition that many of the claims may be fictitious. He then finds, that, in a case where many valid and many fraudulent claims are blended together, the best course for their discrimination is indiscriminately to establish them all. He trusts, (I suppose,) as there may not be a fund sufficient for every description of creditors, that the best warranted claimants will exert themselves in bringing to light those debts which will not bear an inquiry. What he will not do himself he is persuaded will be done by others; and for this purpose he leaves to any person a general power of excepting to the debt. This total change of language and prevarication in principle is enough, if it stood alone, to fix the presumption of unfair dealing. His dispatch assigns motives of policy, concord, trade, and circulation: his speech proclaims discord and litigations, and proposes, as the ultimate end, detection.

If that wasn't enough, he has provided you with more assumptions that can't be shaken. One clear sign of guilt is to stumble and avoid the truth in a story and change the reasons given for actions. Use this standard to judge these ministers. In their official report, they tell the Presidency of Madras that they've established the debt for two reasons: first, because the Nabob (the party in debt) doesn’t dispute it; and second, because keeping it unresolved is harmful, and paying European creditors will help boost the economy in the country. These two reasons (for the simplest of reasons) the right honorable gentleman has today chosen to completely disregard. First, he dismisses the authority of the Nabob of Arcot. It would indeed be amusing to see him cling to this outdated testimony. Next, based on equally solid reasons, he abandons the benefits of that economic boost expected from extracting all the resources. Setting aside, or forgetting, the claims in his report, he has now adopted a completely different but equally strange principle. He operates on the assumption that many of the claims might be fake. He then decides that in a situation where many legitimate and many fraudulent claims are mixed, the best approach is to validate them all indiscriminately. He trusts (I suppose) that since there might not be enough funds for every type of creditor, the most legitimate claimants will take the initiative to uncover those debts that won’t stand up to scrutiny. What he won’t do himself, he believes will be done by others; and for that reason, he gives anyone a general power to dispute the debt. This complete change in language and shifting principles is enough, standing alone, to suggest unfair dealing. His report lists reasons of policy, unity, trade, and economic flow; his speech, however, announces conflict and legal battles, with detection as the ultimate goal.

But he may shift his reasons, and wind and turn as he will, confusion waits him at all his doubles. Who will undertake this detection? Will the Nabob? But the right honorable gentleman has himself this moment told us that no prince of the country can by any motive be prevailed upon to discover any fraud that is practised upon him by the Company's servants. He says what (with the exception of the complaint against the Cavalry Loan) all the world knows to be true: and without that prince's concurrence, what evidence can be had of the fraud of any the smallest of these demands? The ministers never authorized any person to enter into his exchequer and to search his records. Why, then, this shameful and insulting mockery of a pretended contest? Already contests for a preference have arisen among these rival bond-creditors. Has not the Company itself struggled for a preference for years, without any attempt at detection of the nature of those debts with which they contended? Well is the Nabob of Arcot attended to in the only specific complaint he has ever made. He complained of unfair dealing in the Cavalry Loan. It is fixed upon him with interest on interest; and this loan is excepted from all power of litigation.

But he can change his reasons and twist and turn however he likes; confusion is waiting for him at every turn. Who will take on this investigation? Will it be the Nabob? But the honorable gentleman just told us that no prince in the country can be persuaded by any reason to reveal any fraud perpetrated by the Company's workers. He says what everyone (except for the complaint about the Cavalry Loan) already knows to be true: and without that prince's approval, what evidence can we get of the fraud behind any of these minor claims? The ministers never authorized anyone to go into his treasury and check his records. So why this disgraceful and insulting sham of a supposed contest? Already, competitions for priority have emerged among these rival creditors. Hasn't the Company itself been fighting for priority for years, without any effort to uncover the nature of the debts they are battling over? The Nabob of Arcot has been heard regarding the only specific complaint he's ever made. He raised concerns about unfair practices in the Cavalry Loan. It has been burdened with compounded interest, and this loan is excluded from all legal disputes.

This day, and not before, the right honorable gentleman thinks that the general establishment of all claims is the surest way of laying open the fraud of some of them. In India this is a reach of deep policy. But what would be thought of this mode of acting on a demand upon the Treasury in England? Instead of all this cunning, is there not one plain way open,—that is, to put the burden of the proof on those who make the demand? Ought not ministry to have said to the creditors, "The person who admits your debt stands excepted to as evidence; he stands charged as a collusive party, to hand over the public revenues to you for sinister purposes. You say, you have a demand of some millions on the Indian Treasury; prove that you have acted by lawful authority; prove, at least, that your money has been bonâ fide advanced; entitle yourself to my protection by the fairness and fulness of the communications you make"? Did an honest creditor ever refuse that reasonable and honest test?

Today, the right honorable gentleman believes that settling all claims is the best way to expose some of the fraud involved. In India, this strategy shows deep insight. But what would be said about this approach if it were applied to a request for funds from the Treasury in England? Instead of all this underhandedness, isn’t there a straightforward solution—namely, to shift the burden of proof onto the claimants? Shouldn’t the ministry have told the creditors, "The person acknowledging your debt is considered an exception as evidence; they are implicated as a collaborator, trying to divert public funds to you for unethical reasons. You say you have a claim worth millions on the Indian Treasury; prove that you acted with legal authority; demonstrate at least that your money was actually advanced in good faith; earn my support through the honesty and transparency of your claims"? Has any honest creditor ever turned down such a fair and reasonable test?

There is little doubt that several individuals have been seduced by the purveyors to the Nabob of Arcot to put their money (perhaps the whole of honest and laborious earnings) into their hands, and that at such high interest as, being condemned at law, leaves them at the mercy of the great managers whom they trusted. These seduced creditors are probably persons of no power or interest either in England or India, and may be just objects of compassion. By taking, in this arrangement, no measures for discrimination and discovery, the fraudulent and the fair are in the first instance confounded in one mass. The subsequent selection and distribution is left to the Nabob. With him the agents and instruments of his corruption, whom he sees to be omnipotent in England, and who may serve him in future, as they have done in times past, will have precedence, if not an exclusive preference. These leading interests domineer, and have always domineered, over the whole. By this arrangement, the persons seduced are made dependent on their seducers; honesty (comparative honesty at least) must become of the party of fraud, and must quit its proper character and its just claims, to entitle itself to the alms of bribery and peculation.

There’s no doubt that a number of people have been lured by the dealers working for the Nabob of Arcot to hand over their money (possibly all their honest, hard-earned income) to them, often at such high interest rates that, when judged legally, leave them completely vulnerable to the powerful managers they trusted. These misled creditors are likely individuals without any influence or clout, either in England or India, and they may just be objects of pity. By failing to implement any methods for distinguishing between who is legitimate and who isn’t, the fraudulent and the honest get mixed together right from the start. The subsequent sorting and allocation are left up to the Nabob. He will prioritize the agents and tools of his corruption, who he knows are all-powerful in England, and who may support him in the future just as they have in the past, if not give them exclusive preference. These dominant interests have always held sway over everything. Through this setup, the people who have been deceived become dependent on those who deceived them; honesty (at least relatively speaking) ends up being part of fraud, having to abandon its rightful stance and legitimate claims to be worthy of the bribes and corrupt gains.

But be these English creditors what they may, the creditors most certainly not fraudulent are the natives, who are numerous and wretched indeed: by exhausting the whole revenues of the Carnatic, nothing is left for them. They lent bonâ fide; in all probability they were even forced to lend, or to give goods and service for the Nabob's obligations. They had no trusts to carry to his market. They had no faith of alliances to sell. They had no nations to betray to robbery and ruin. They had no lawful government seditiously to overturn; nor had they a governor, to whom it is owing that you exist in India, to deliver over to captivity, and to death in a shameful prison.[25]

But no matter what these English creditors might be, the real creditors who aren't fraudulent are the local people, who are far too numerous and truly suffering: by draining all the resources of the Carnatic, nothing is left for them. They lent in good faith; in all likelihood, they were even forced to lend or to offer goods and services to cover the Nabob's debts. They had no trusts to take to his market. They had no alliances to sell. They had no nations to betray to theft and destruction. They had no legitimate government to overthrow in a rebellion; nor did they have a governor, who is the reason you even exist in India, to hand over to captivity and a disgraceful death in prison.[25]

These were the merits of the principal part of the debt of 1777, and the universally conceived causes of its growth; and thus the unhappy natives are deprived of every hope of payment for their real debts, to make provision for the arrears of unsatisfied bribery and treason. You see in this instance that the presumption of guilt is not only no exception to the demands on the public treasury, but with these ministers it is a necessary condition to their support. But that you may not think this preference solely owing to their known contempt of the natives, who ought with every generous mind to claim their first charities, you will find the same rule religiously observed with Europeans too. Attend, Sir, to this decisive case. Since the beginning of the war, besides arrears of every kind, a bond-debt has been contracted at Madras, uncertain in its amount, but represented from four hundred thousand pound to a million sterling. It stands only at the low interest of eight per cent. Of the legal authority on which this debt was contracted, of its purposes for the very being of the state, of its publicity and fairness, no doubt has been entertained for a moment. For this debt no sort of provision whatever has been made. It is rejected as an outcast, whilst the whole undissipated attention of the minister has been employed for the discharge of claims entitled to his favor by the merits we have seen.

These were the key points about the main debt from 1777 and the generally accepted reasons for its increase; thus, the unfortunate locals have lost all hope of receiving payment for their legitimate debts, while provisions are made for the outstanding payments related to bribery and treason. In this case, you can see that the assumption of guilt is not just an exception to the demands on the public treasury, but for these ministers, it is a necessary condition for their support. But to ensure you don't think this favoritism is only due to their known disregard for the locals, who should rightfully receive anything generous, you'll find the same policy strictly applied to Europeans as well. Pay attention, Sir, to this critical example. Since the war began, in addition to all kinds of arrears, a bond debt has been incurred in Madras. Its exact amount is uncertain, but it is stated to be between four hundred thousand pounds and a million sterling, with a low interest rate of eight percent. No one has questioned the legal authority under which this debt was incurred, its necessity for the state's very existence, or its transparency and fairness. No provision has been made for this debt whatsoever. It is treated like an outcast, while the minister's complete focus has been on settling the claims that benefit him based on the merits we've discussed.

I have endeavored to find out, if possible, the amount of the whole of those demands, in order to see how much, supposing the country in a condition to furnish the fund, may remain to satisfy the public debt and the necessary establishments. But I have been foiled in my attempt.

I have tried to determine the total of those demands, to see how much, assuming the country can provide the funds, might be left to cover the public debt and essential services. However, I have been unsuccessful in my effort.

About one fourth, that is, about 220,000l., of the loan of 1767 remains unpaid. How much interest is in arrear I could never discover: seven or eight years' at least, which would make the whole of that debt about 396,000l. This stock, which the ministers in their instructions to the Governor of Madras state as the least exceptionable, they have thought proper to distinguish by a marked severity, leaving it the only one on which the interest is not added to the principal to beget a new interest.

About a quarter, or roughly 220,000l., of the loan from 1767 is still unpaid. I could never determine how much interest is overdue: it's at least seven or eight years, which would bring the total debt to around 396,000l.. This stock, which the ministers noted as the least problematic in their instructions to the Governor of Madras, has been singled out for harsh treatment, remaining the only one where the interest is not added to the principal to generate new interest.

The Cavalry Loan, by the operation of the same authority, is made up to 294,000l.; and this 294,000l., made up of principal and interest, is crowned with a new interest of twelve per cent.

The Cavalry Loan, under the same authority, amounts to 294,000l.; and this 294,000l., consisting of principal and interest, is now topped with a new interest rate of twelve percent.

What the grand loan, the bribery loan of 1777, may be is amongst the deepest mysteries of state. It is probably the first debt ever assuming the title of Consolidation that did not express what the amount of the sum consolidated was. It is little less than a contradiction in terms. In the debt of the year 1767 the sum was stated in the act of consolidation, and made to amount to 880,000l. capital. When this consolidation of 1777 was first announced at the Durbar, it was represented authentically at 2,400,000l. In that, or rather in a higher state, Sir Thomas Rumbold found and condemned it.[26] It afterwards fell into such a terror as to sweat away a million of its weight at once; and it sunk to 1,400,000l.[27] However, it never was without a resource for recruiting it to its old plumpness. There was a sort of floating debt of about four or five hundred thousand pounds more ready to be added, as occasion should require.

What the grand loan, the bribery loan of 1777, really is remains one of the greatest mysteries of state. It's likely the first debt labeled as Consolidation that doesn't specify the amount being consolidated. It's almost a contradiction in terms. In the debt from 1767, the amount was clearly stated in the consolidation act, totaling 880,000l. When the consolidation of 1777 was first announced at the Durbar, it was officially represented as 2,400,000l. In that, or rather in a greater form, Sir Thomas Rumbold discovered and condemned it.[26] It later experienced such a panic that it lost a million of its weight all at once, dropping to 1,400,000l.[27] However, it never ran out of ways to restore its previous size. There was a kind of floating debt of about four or five hundred thousand pounds ready to be added whenever needed.

In short, when you pressed this sensitive-plant, it always contracted its dimensions. When the rude hand of inquiry was withdrawn, it expanded in all the luxuriant vigor of its original vegetation. In the treaty of 1781, the whole of the Nabob's debt to private Europeans is by Mr. Sulivan, agent to the Nabob and his creditors, stated at 2,800,000l., which, if the Cavalry Loan and the remains of the debt of 1767 be subtracted, leaves it nearly at the amount originally declared at the Durbar in 1777: but then there is a private instruction to Mr. Sulivan, which, it seems, will reduce it again to the lower standard of 1,400,000l.

In short, when you touched this sensitive plant, it would always shrink. When the rough hand of curiosity was removed, it would expand with all the lush vigor of its original growth. In the treaty of 1781, Mr. Sulivan, the agent for the Nabob and his creditors, stated that the total debt owed by the Nabob to private Europeans was 2,800,000l.. If you subtract the Cavalry Loan and the remaining debt from 1767, it brings the amount close to what was originally declared at the Durbar in 1777. But then there is a private instruction to Mr. Sulivan that seems to reduce it again to the lower amount of 1,400,000l.

Failing in all my attempts, by a direct account, to ascertain the extent of the capital claimed, (where in all probability no capital was ever advanced,) I endeavored, if possible, to discover it by the interest which was to be paid. For that purpose, I looked to the several agreements for assigning the territories of the Carnatic to secure the principal and interest of this debt. In one of them,[28] I found, in a sort of postscript, by way of an additional remark, (not in the body of the obligation,) the debt represented at 1,400,000l.: but when I computed the sums to be paid for interest by instalments in another paper, I found they produced an interest of two millions, at twelve per cent; and the assignment supposed, that, if these instalments might exceed, they might also fall short of, the real provision for that interest.[29] Another instalment-bond was afterwards granted: in that bond the interest exactly tallies with a capital of 1,400,000l.:[30] but pursuing this capital through the correspondence, I lost sight of it again, and it was asserted that this instalment-bond was considerably short of the interest that ought to be computed to the time mentioned.[31]

After failing in all my attempts to directly determine the amount of capital being claimed (where it’s likely no capital was ever given), I tried to figure it out by looking at the interest that was supposed to be paid. To do this, I checked the various agreements for assigning the territories of the Carnatic to secure the principal and interest of this debt. In one of them,[28] I found, in a sort of postscript as an additional remark (not in the main part of the obligation), that the debt was stated to be 1,400,000l. But when I calculated the amounts to be paid for interest in installments in another document, I discovered that they amounted to an interest of two million at twelve percent; and the assignment suggested that while these installments might exceed, they could also fall short of the actual provision for that interest.[29] Another installment bond was later issued: in that bond, the interest matched exactly with a capital of 1,400,000l.:[30] but as I traced this capital through the correspondence, I lost track of it again, and it was claimed that this installment bond was significantly less than the interest that should be calculated up to the time mentioned.[31]

Here are, therefore, two statements of equal authority, differing at least a million from each other; and as neither persons claiming, nor any special sum as belonging to each particular claimant, is ascertained in the instruments of consolidation, or in the installment-bonds, a large scope was left to throw in any sums for any persons, as their merits in advancing the interest of that loan might require; a power was also left for reduction, in case a harder hand, or more scanty funds, might be found to require it. Stronger grounds for a presumption of fraud never appeared in any transaction. But the ministers, faithful to the plan of the interested persons, whom alone they thought fit to confer with on this occasion, have ordered the payment of the whole mass of these unknown, unliquidated sums, without an attempt to ascertain them. On this conduct, Sir, I leave you to make your own reflections.

Here are two statements of equal authority, differing by at least a million from each other; and since neither the people claiming nor any specific amount belonging to each particular claimant is identified in the consolidation documents or in the installment bonds, there was a lot of leeway to include any amounts for any individuals, depending on their contributions to the loan’s success; a provision was also left for reductions if a stricter approach or limited funds turned out to be necessary. You couldn't find stronger grounds for a presumption of fraud in any transaction. However, the ministers, sticking to the interests of the people they believed were the only ones worth consulting at this time, have ordered the payment of the entire collection of these unknown, unquantified amounts without trying to verify them. Based on this behavior, Sir, I leave it to you to draw your own conclusions.

It is impossible (at least I have found it impossible) to fix on the real amount of the pretended debts with which your ministers have thought proper to load the Carnatic. They are obscure; they shun inquiry; they are enormous. That is all you know of them.

It’s impossible (at least I’ve found it to be impossible) to determine the actual amount of the alleged debts that your ministers have chosen to impose on the Carnatic. They’re unclear; they avoid scrutiny; they’re massive. That’s all you know about them.

That you may judge what chance any honorable and useful end of government has for a provision that comes in for the leavings of these gluttonous demands, I must take it on myself to bring before you the real condition of that abused, insulted, racked, and ruined country; though in truth my mind revolts from it, though you will hear it with horror, and I confess I tremble when I think on these awful and confounding dispensations of Providence. I shall first trouble you with a few words as to the cause.

That you can assess what chance any respectable and beneficial goal of government has when it's dealing with the leftovers from these greedy demands, I feel it's necessary to present to you the true state of that mistreated, insulted, tortured, and devastated country; even though, honestly, I struggle to face it, and I know you will react with shock, I admit I get anxious when I think of these terrible and perplexing actions of Providence. First, I’ll share a few thoughts on the cause.

The great fortunes made in India, in the beginnings of conquest, naturally excited an emulation in all the parts and through the whole succession of the Company's service. But in the Company it gave rise to other sentiments. They did not find the new channels of acquisition flow with equal riches to them. On the contrary, the high flood-tide of private emolument was generally in the lowest ebb of their affairs. They began also to fear that the fortune of war might take away what the fortune of war had given. Wars were accordingly discouraged by repeated injunctions and menaces: and that the servants might not be bribed into them by the native princes, they were strictly forbidden to take any money whatsoever from their hands. But vehement passion is ingenious in resources. The Company's servants were not only stimulated, but better instructed by the prohibition. They soon fell upon a contrivance which answered their purposes far better than the methods which were forbidden: though in this also they violated an ancient, but they thought, an abrogated order. They reversed their proceedings. Instead of receiving presents, they made loans. Instead of carrying on wars in their own name, they contrived an authority, at once irresistible and irresponsible, in whose name they might ravage at pleasure; and being thus freed from all restraint, they indulged themselves in the most extravagant speculations of plunder. The cabal of creditors who have been the object of the late bountiful grant from his Majesty's ministers, in order to possess themselves, under the name of creditors and assignees, of every country in India, as fast as it should be conquered, inspired into the mind of the Nabob of Arcot (then a dependant on the Company of the humblest order) a scheme of the most wild and desperate ambition that I believe ever was admitted into the thoughts of a man so situated.[32] First, they persuaded him to consider himself as a principal member in the political system of Europe. In the next place, they held out to him, and he readily imbibed, the idea of the general empire of Hindostan. As a preliminary to this undertaking, they prevailed on him to propose a tripartite division of that vast country: one part to the Company; another to the Mahrattas; and the third to himself. To himself he reserved all the southern part of the great peninsula, comprehended under the general name of the Deccan.

The huge fortunes made in India during the early days of conquest naturally sparked competition among everyone involved in the Company’s service. However, within the Company, it led to different feelings. They found that the new opportunities for wealth didn’t bring them the same riches. Rather, the high tide of private gain was typically at its lowest for them. They also began to worry that the fortunes gained from war could be lost just as easily. As a result, wars were discouraged through repeated orders and threats: to prevent their employees from being bribed by local rulers, they were strictly forbidden from accepting any money from them. However, strong desires are clever in finding ways around such rules. The Company’s servants were not only motivated but also better educated by these restrictions. They quickly devised a method that served their needs far better than the forbidden approaches: though they thought they were changing things up, they were actually breaking an old order. They flipped their tactics. Instead of accepting gifts, they started making loans. Instead of waging wars in their own names, they created an authority that was both very powerful and unaccountable, under which they could pillage at will; and being free from any limits, they indulged in the wildest ambitions of theft. The group of creditors who recently received generous support from the King’s ministers, aiming to seize every region in India under the guise of creditors and assignees as quickly as it was conquered, planted a scheme of extreme and reckless ambition into the mind of the Nabob of Arcot (at that time a very low-ranking dependent of the Company) that I believe has never been conceived by someone in his position. First, they convinced him to see himself as a key player in Europe’s political system. Next, they presented him with, and he eagerly accepted, the idea of a vast empire in Hindostan. As a first step, they got him to propose a three-way division of that immense country: one section for the Company, another for the Mahrattas, and the last for himself. He claimed all of the southern part of the great peninsula, known collectively as the Deccan, for himself.

On this scheme of their servants, the Company was to appear in the Carnatic in no other light than as a contractor for the provision of armies, and the hire of mercenaries for his use and under his direction. This disposition was to be secured by the Nabob's putting himself under the guaranty of France, and, by the means of that rival nation, preventing the English forever from assuming an equality, much less a superiority, in the Carnatic. In pursuance of this treasonable project, (treasonable on the part of the English,) they extinguished the Company as a sovereign power in that part of India; they withdrew the Company's garrisons out of all the forts and strongholds of the Carnatic; they declined to receive the ambassadors from foreign courts, and remitted them to the Nabob of Arcot; they fell upon, and totally destroyed, the oldest ally of the Company, the king of Tanjore, and plundered the country to the amount of near five millions sterling; one after another, in the Nabob's name, but with English force, they brought into a miserable servitude all the princes and great independent nobility of a vast country.[33] In proportion to these treasons and violences, which ruined the people, the fund of the Nabob's debt grew and flourished.

On this plan for their servants, the Company was supposed to appear in the Carnatic only as a contractor for supplying armies and hiring mercenaries for his use and under his direction. This arrangement was to be secured by the Nabob getting the protection of France, and, through that rival nation, preventing the English from ever claiming equality, let alone superiority, in the Carnatic. As part of this treacherous scheme (treacherous on the part of the English), they eliminated the Company as a sovereign power in that part of India; they withdrew the Company's troops from all the forts and strongholds of the Carnatic; they refused to accept ambassadors from foreign courts and sent them back to the Nabob of Arcot; they attacked and completely destroyed the Company's oldest ally, the king of Tanjore, and plundered the region to the tune of nearly five million pounds; one after another, in the Nabob's name but using English forces, they enslaved all the princes and major independent nobles of a vast area. In line with these betrayals and acts of violence, which devastated the people, the amount of the Nabob's debt increased and thrived.

Among the victims to this magnificent plan of universal plunder, worthy of the heroic avarice of the projectors, you have all heard (and he has made himself to be well remembered) of an Indian chief called Hyder Ali Khan. This man possessed the western, as the Company, under the name of the Nabob of Arcot, does the eastern division of the Carnatic. It was among the leading measures in the design of this cabal (according to their own emphatic language) to extirpate this Hyder Ali.[34] They declared the Nabob of Arcot to be his sovereign, and himself to be a rebel, and publicly invested their instrument with the sovereignty of the kingdom of Mysore. But their victim was not of the passive kind. They were soon obliged to conclude a treaty of peace and close alliance with this rebel, at the gates of Madras. Both before and since that treaty, every principle of policy pointed out this power as a natural alliance; and on his part it was courted by every sort of amicable office. But the cabinet council of English creditors would not suffer their Nabob of Arcot to sign the treaty, nor even to give to a prince at least his equal the ordinary titles of respect and courtesy.[35] From that time forward, a continued plot was carried on within the divan, black and white, of the Nabob of Arcot, for the destruction of Hyder Ali. As to the outward members of the double, or rather treble government of Madras, which had signed the treaty, they were always prevented by some overruling influence (which they do not describe, but which cannot be misunderstood) from performing what justice and interest combined so evidently to enforce.[36]

Among the victims of this grand scheme of universal theft, fitting of the greedy ambition of its creators, you have all heard (and he has made sure to be well remembered) of an Indian chief named Hyder Ali Khan. This man controlled the western part, just as the Company, under the title of the Nabob of Arcot, governs the eastern division of the Carnatic. One of the main goals of this conspiracy (in their own emphatic words) was to exterminate this Hyder Ali.[34] They proclaimed the Nabob of Arcot to be his ruler, and him to be a rebel, openly granting their agent the authority over the kingdom of Mysore. However, their target was not one to simply give in. They soon had to negotiate a peace treaty and a close alliance with this rebel at the gates of Madras. Both before and after that treaty, every strategic principle indicated that this power was a natural ally; in return, he was pursued with every kind of friendly gesture. But the English creditors' council would not allow their Nabob of Arcot to sign the treaty, nor even to extend the usual titles of respect and courtesy to a prince at least his equal.[35] Since then, a continuous plot was carried out within the administration of the Nabob of Arcot, both among his advisors in the court and outsiders, aimed at the downfall of Hyder Ali. As for the external members of the multiple governments of Madras that signed the treaty, they were always prevented by some overriding influence (which they don’t specify, but which is quite clear) from taking actions that justice and interest combined clearly warranted.[36]

When at length Hyder Ali found that he had to do with men who either would sign no convention, or whom no treaty and no signature could bind, and who were the determined enemies of human intercourse itself, he decreed to make the country possessed by these incorrigible and predestinated criminals a memorable example to mankind. He resolved, in the gloomy recesses of a mind capacious of such things, to leave the whole Carnatic an everlasting monument of vengeance, and to put perpetual desolation as a barrier between him and those against whom the faith which holds the moral elements of the world together was no protection. He became at length so confident of his force, so collected in his might, that he made no secret whatsoever of his dreadful resolution. Having terminated his disputes with every enemy and every rival, who buried their mutual animosities in their common detestation against the creditors of the Nabob of Arcot, he drew from every quarter whatever a savage ferocity could add to his new rudiments in the arts of destruction; and compounding all the materials of fury, havoc, and desolation into one black cloud, he hung for a while on the declivities of the mountains. Whilst the authors of all these evils were idly and stupidly gazing on this menacing meteor, which blackened all their horizon, it suddenly burst, and poured down the whole of its contents upon the plains of the Carnatic. Then ensued a scene of woe, the like of which no eye had seen, no heart conceived, and which no tongue can adequately tell. All the horrors of war before known or heard of were mercy to that new havoc. A storm of universal fire blasted every field, consumed every house, destroyed every temple. The miserable inhabitants, flying from their flaming villages, in part were slaughtered; others, without regard to sex, to age, to the respect of rank or sacredness of function, fathers torn from children, husbands from wives, enveloped in a whirlwind of cavalry, and amidst the goading spears of drivers, and the trampling of pursuing horses, were swept into captivity in an unknown and hostile land. Those who were able to evade this tempest fled to the walled cities; but escaping from fire, sword, and exile, they fell into the jaws of famine.

When Hyder Ali realized he was dealing with people who would neither agree to any kind of agreement nor could be bound by any treaty or signature—people who were staunch enemies of all human interaction—he decided to make the region inhabited by these unchangeable and fated criminals an unforgettable example for humanity. He resolved, in the dark corners of a mind capable of such thoughts, to turn the entire Carnatic into a lasting monument of revenge and to create a perpetual wasteland as a barrier between himself and those for whom the principles that unite moral beings held no protection. Eventually, he grew so confident in his strength and so steady in his resolve that he openly revealed his dreadful intentions. After settling his conflicts with every enemy and rival, who buried their mutual hatreds under their shared disdain for the creditors of the Nabob of Arcot, he gathered every ounce of savage ferocity he could to enhance his newfound skills in destruction; combining all the elements of rage, devastation, and ruin into one ominous cloud, he lingered for a time on the slopes of the mountains. While the creators of all this chaos were idly and foolishly staring at this threatening storm that darkened their entire horizon, it suddenly unleashed itself, raining down its full wrath upon the plains of the Carnatic. What followed was a scene of anguish unlike anything seen before, no heart could imagine, and no words can fully describe. All the horrors of previously known or heard wars were merciful in comparison to this new devastation. A whirlwind of fire devastated every field, burned down every house, and destroyed every temple. The wretched inhabitants, fleeing from their burning villages, faced slaughter; others, regardless of gender, age, social status, or sacred duties—fathers torn from their children, husbands from their wives—were caught in a whirlwind of cavalry and amidst the prodding spears of soldiers and the stampede of pursuing horses, swept away into captivity in an unfamiliar and hostile land. Those who managed to escape this onslaught fled to fortified cities; but after avoiding fire, swords, and exile, they fell into the grip of famine.

The alms of the settlement, in this dreadful exigency, were certainly liberal; and all was done by charity that private charity could do: but it was a people in beggary; it was a nation which stretched out its hands for food. For months together, these creatures of sufferance, whose very excess and luxury in their most plenteous days had fallen short of the allowance of our austerest fasts, silent, patient, resigned, without sedition or disturbance, almost without complaint, perished by an hundred a day in the streets of Madras; every day seventy at least laid their bodies in the streets or on the glacis of Tanjore, and expired of famine in the granary of India. I was going to awake your justice towards this unhappy part of our fellow-citizens, by bringing before you some of the circumstances of this plague of hunger: of all the calamities which beset and waylay the life of man, this comes the nearest to our heart, and is that wherein the proudest of us all feels himself to be nothing more than he is: but I find myself unable to manage it with decorum; these details are of a species of horror so nauseous and disgusting, they are so degrading to the sufferers and to the hearers, they are so humiliating to human nature itself, that, on better thoughts, I find it more advisable to throw a pall over this hideous object, and to leave it to your general conceptions.

The charity from the settlement, in this terrible crisis, was indeed generous; everything that private charity could offer was done. But it was a of people begging; it was a nation reaching out for food. For months, these people, who had once lived in excess and luxury during the most plentiful of times, had suffered more than we do during our strictest fasts. They were silent, patient, resigned, without rebellion or unrest, almost without complaint, yet they were dying at a rate of a hundred a day in the streets of Madras; every single day, at least seventy of them laid their bodies in the streets or on the glacis of Tanjore and perished from starvation in the granary of India. I was about to appeal to your sense of justice for this unfortunate part of our fellow citizens by sharing some of the details of this hunger crisis: of all the disasters that confront us, this one strikes closest to our hearts and reminds even the proudest among us that we are just human. But I find myself unable to address it with the respect it deserves; the specifics are so horrifying and repulsive, so degrading to those who suffer and to those who hear about it, so humiliating to human nature itself, that upon reflecting, I believe it’s better to cover this dreadful reality and leave it to your general understanding.

For eighteen months,[37] without intermission, this destruction raged from the gates of Madras to the gates of Tanjore; and so completely did these masters in their art, Hyder Ali and his more ferocious son, absolve themselves of their impious vow, that, when the British armies traversed, as they did, the Carnatic for hundreds of miles in all directions, through the whole line of their march they did not see one man, not one woman, not one child, not one four-footed beast of any description whatever. One dead, uniform silence reigned over the whole region. With the inconsiderable exceptions of the narrow vicinage of some few forts, I wish to be understood as speaking literally. I mean to produce to you more than three witnesses, above all exception, who will support this assertion in its full extent. That hurricane of war passed through every part of the central provinces of the Carnatic. Six or seven districts to the north and to the south (and these not wholly untouched) escaped the general ravage.

For eighteen months,[37] nonstop, this devastation swept from the gates of Madras to the gates of Tanjore; and so completely did these skilled leaders, Hyder Ali and his even more ruthless son, rid themselves of their wicked vow that, when the British armies crossed the Carnatic for hundreds of miles in every direction, they didn’t encounter a single person—no man, no woman, no child, and not one four-legged animal of any kind. A profound silence filled the entire region. With the minor exceptions of the areas close to a few forts, I want to emphasize that I mean this literally. I plan to provide you with more than three indisputable witnesses who will confirm this claim in its entirety. That storm of war swept through every part of the central provinces of the Carnatic. Six or seven districts to the north and south (which were not entirely untouched) narrowly escaped the widespread destruction.

The Carnatic is a country not much inferior in extent to England. Figure to yourself, Mr. Speaker, the land in whose representative chair you sit; figure to yourself the form and fashion of your sweet and cheerful country from Thames to Trent, north and south, and from the Irish to the German Sea, east and west, emptied and embowelled (may God avert the omen of our crimes!) by so accomplished a desolation. Extend your imagination a little further, and then suppose your ministers taking a survey of this scene of waste and desolation. What would be your thoughts, if you should be informed that they were computing how much had been the amount of the excises, how much the customs, how much the land and malt tax, in order that they should charge (take it in the most favorable light) for public service, upon the relics of the satiated vengeance of relentless enemies, the whole of what England had yielded in the most exuberant seasons of peace and abundance? What would you call it? To call it tyranny sublimed into madness would be too faint an image; yet this very madness is the principle upon which the ministers at your right hand have proceeded in their estimate of the revenues of the Carnatic, when they were providing, not supply for the establishments of its protection, but rewards for the authors of its ruin.

The Carnatic is a country that's not much smaller than England. Picture this, Mr. Speaker: the land where you hold a representative position; imagine the shape and layout of your lovely and vibrant country from the Thames to the Trent, north and south, and from the Irish Sea to the German Sea, east and west, stripped bare and devastated (may God prevent this omen of our wrongdoings!) by such complete destruction. Now stretch your imagination a little further, and think about your ministers surveying this scene of ruin and loss. What would you think if you learned they were calculating the amount of taxes collected, how much from customs, and how much from land and malt taxes, just so they could charge (looking at it in the best possible way) for public service on the remains of the satisfied wrath of unyielding enemies, all of what England had produced in its richest times of peace and prosperity? What would you call that? Calling it tyranny elevated to madness would be too weak a description; yet this very madness is the basis upon which the ministers beside you have operated in their assessment of the revenues of the Carnatic, as they were preparing not for the protection of its needs, but for rewards to those responsible for its destruction.

Every day you are fatigued and disgusted with this cant, "The Carnatic is a country that will soon recover, and become instantly as prosperous as ever." They think they are talking to innocents, who will believe, that, by sowing of dragons' teeth, men may come up ready grown and ready armed. They who will give themselves the trouble of considering (for it requires no great reach of thought, no very profound knowledge) the manner in which mankind are increased, and countries cultivated, will regard all this raving as it ought to be regarded. In order that the people, after a long period of vexation and plunder, may be in a condition to maintain government, government must begin by maintaining them. Here the road to economy lies not through receipt, but through expense; and in that country Nature has given no short cut to your object. Men must propagate, like other animals, by the mouth. Never did oppression light the nuptial torch; never did extortion and usury spread out the genial bed. Does any of you think that England, so wasted, would, under such a nursing attendance, so rapidly and cheaply recover? But he is meanly acquainted with either England or India who does not know that England would a thousand times sooner resume population, fertility, and what ought to be the ultimate secretion from both, revenue, than such a country as the Carnatic.

Every day you feel exhausted and annoyed by this nonsense, "The Carnatic is a place that will soon bounce back and be as prosperous as ever." They act like they’re talking to naive people who will believe that planting dragons’ teeth will magically grow armed men. Those who take a moment to think about how people multiply and how lands are cultivated will see this ranting for what it really is. For the people, after enduring a long time of suffering and plunder, to be in a position to support a government, that government must first support them. Here, the path to saving money doesn't lie in income but in spending; and in this country, Nature hasn’t provided any shortcuts to your goals. People must reproduce, like other animals, through speaking. Oppression never sparked the wedding flame; extortion and usury never created a warm home. Does anyone think that England, so depleted, would recover so quickly and cheaply under such neglect? But anyone who knows either England or India understands that England would recover its population, fertility, and what should ultimately come from both, revenue, a thousand times faster than a place like the Carnatic.

The Carnatic is not by the bounty of Nature a fertile soil. The general size of its cattle is proof enough that it is much otherwise. It is some days since I moved that a curious and interesting map, kept in the India House, should be laid before you.[38] The India House is not yet in readiness to send it; I have therefore brought down my own copy, and there it lies for the use of any gentleman who may think such a matter worthy of his attention. It is, indeed, a noble map, and of noble things; but it is decisive against the golden dreams and sanguine speculations of avarice run mad. In addition to what you know must be the case in every part of the world, (the necessity of a previous provision of habitation, seed, stock, capital,) that map will show you that the uses of the influences of Heaven itself are in that country a work of art. The Carnatic is refreshed by few or no living brooks or running streams, and it has rain only at a season; but its product of rice exacts the use of water subject to perpetual command. This is the national bank of the Carnatic, on which it must have a perpetual credit, or it perishes irretrievably. For that reason, in the happier times of India, a number, almost incredible, of reservoirs have been made in chosen places throughout the whole country: they are formed, for the greater part, of mounds of earth and stones, with sluices of solid masonry; the whole constructed with admirable skill and labor, and maintained at a mighty charge. In the territory contained in that map alone, I have been at the trouble of reckoning the reservoirs, and they amount to upwards of eleven hundred, from the extent of two or three acres to five miles in circuit. From these reservoirs currents are occasionally drawn over the fields, and these watercourses again call for a considerable expense to keep them properly scoured and duly levelled. Taking the district in that map as a measure, there cannot be in the Carnatic and Tanjore fewer than ten thousand of these reservoirs of the larger and middling dimensions, to say nothing of those for domestic services, and the use of religious purification. These are not the enterprises of your power, nor in a style of magnificence suited to the taste of your minister. These are the monuments of real kings, who were the fathers of their people,—testators to a posterity which they embraced as their own. These are the grand sepulchres built by ambition,—but by the ambition of an insatiable benevolence, which, not contented with reigning in the dispensation of happiness during the contracted term of human life, had strained, with all the reachings and graspings of a vivacious mind, to extend the dominion of their bounty beyond the limits of Nature, and to perpetuate themselves through generations of generations, the guardians, the protectors, the nourishers of mankind.

The Carnatic isn't naturally fertile soil. The size of its cattle is proof enough of that. A few days ago, I moved that a fascinating and important map, kept at India House, should be presented to you.[38] India House isn't ready to send it yet; so I've brought my own copy, and it's available for any gentleman who thinks this information is worth his attention. It's truly a remarkable map, showcasing significant things; but it clearly contradicts the unrealistic ambitions and greedy dreams of those blinded by avarice. Besides what you already know must be true anywhere in the world (the need for housing, seeds, livestock, and capital), that map reveals that harnessing nature's resources in this region is an art form. The Carnatic has very few living brooks or flowing streams, and rain only comes in a season, yet its rice production requires water to be available at all times. This water is the lifeblood of the Carnatic’s economy; without it, everything would collapse irretrievably. That's why, in better times for India, an almost unbelievable number of reservoirs were constructed in ideal spots across the country. Most of them are made from earth and stone mounds, with strong sluices made from solid masonry; they were built with incredible skill and effort and are maintained at great expense. In the section of that map alone, I've counted the reservoirs, and they number over eleven hundred, varying from two or three acres to five miles around. Water is occasionally drawn from these reservoirs to irrigate fields, and maintaining these watercourses requires significant investment to keep them well-maintained and at the right level. When considering the area shown on that map, there must be at least ten thousand of these larger and medium-sized reservoirs in the Carnatic and Tanjore, not to mention those for household needs and for religious purification. These are not projects of your abilities, nor do they match the style of grandeur that appeals to your minister. These are the legacies of true kings, who cared for their people and considered future generations as their own. These are the impressive monuments created by ambition—but not the kind of ambition that seeks power. Instead, it's driven by an insatiable desire to help others, which aimed to extend the impact of their generosity beyond natural limits and to ensure their legacy as long-term protectors and nurturers of humanity.

Long before the late invasion, the persons who are objects of the grant of public money now before you had so diverted the supply of the pious funds of culture and population, that everywhere the reservoirs were fallen into a miserable decay.[39] But after those domestic enemies had provoked the entry of a cruel foreign foe into the country, he did not leave it, until his revenge had completed the destruction begun by their avarice. Few, very few indeed, of these magazines of water that are not either totally destroyed, or cut through with such gaps as to require a serious attention and much cost to reëstablish them, as the means of present subsistence to the people and of future revenue to the state.

Long before the recent invasion, those who are now the recipients of public funding had mismanaged the pious funds meant for culture and community development, leading to the widespread decay of resources. But once these domestic foes had invited a brutal foreign enemy into the country, he didn’t leave until he had exacted revenge, completing the destruction that their greed had started. Very few of these water reserves are intact; most are either completely destroyed or have such significant gaps that they require serious effort and considerable expense to restore, both for the immediate support of the people and for future revenue for the state.

What, Sir, would a virtuous and enlightened ministry do, on the view of the ruins of such works before them?—on the view of such a chasm of desolation as that which yawned in the midst of those countries, to the north and south, which still bore some vestiges of cultivation? They would have reduced all their most necessary establishments; they would have suspended the justest payments; they would have employed every shilling derived from the producing to reanimate the powers of the unproductive parts. While they were performing this fundamental duty, whilst they were celebrating these mysteries of justice and humanity, they would have told the corps of fictitious creditors, whose crimes were their claims, that they must keep an awful distance,—that they must silence their inauspicious tongues,—that they must hold off their profane, unhallowed paws from this holy work; they would have proclaimed, with a voice that should make itself heard, that on every country the first creditor is the plough,—that this original, indefeasible claim supersedes every other demand.

What would a virtuous and enlightened government do when faced with the ruins of such efforts? Looking at the vast emptiness surrounding those areas, to the north and south, that still showed some signs of cultivation? They would have cut back all their most essential services; they would have paused all their rightful payments; they would have used every single penny from those producing wealth to revive the lifeless parts. While doing this fundamental duty, while recognizing these principles of justice and humanity, they would have told the group of fake creditors, whose wrongdoings were the basis of their claims, to keep a respectful distance—that they needed to silence their negative voices—that they should stay away from this sacred work; they would have declared loudly enough to be heard that in every country, the primary creditor is the plough—and that this original, undeniable claim takes precedence over every other demand.

This is what a wise and virtuous ministry would have done and said. This, therefore, is what our minister could never think of saying or doing. A ministry of another kind would have first improved the country, and have thus laid a solid foundation for future opulence and future force. But on this grand point of the restoration of the country there is not one syllable to be found in the correspondence of our ministers, from the first to the last; they felt nothing for a land desolated by fire, sword, and famine: their sympathies took another direction; they were touched with pity for bribery, so long tormented with a fruitless itching of its palms; their bowels yearned for usury, that had long missed the harvest of its returning months;[40] they felt for peculation, which had been for so many years raking in the dust of an empty treasury; they were melted into compassion for rapine and oppression, licking their dry, parched, unbloody jaws. These were the objects of their solicitude. These were the necessities for which they were studious to provide.

This is what a wise and virtuous government would have done and said. This, therefore, is what our minister could never think of saying or doing. A different kind of government would have first improved the country and thus laid a solid foundation for future wealth and strength. But on this important issue of restoring the country, there isn’t a single word to be found in the correspondence of our ministers, from the beginning to the end; they felt nothing for a land devastated by fire, war, and famine: their sympathies went elsewhere; they were moved by pity for bribery, endlessly suffering from a futile longing for wealth; they empathized with usury, which had long missed out on the returns of its expected profits; they felt for corruption, which had been digging into an empty treasury for so many years; they were filled with compassion for theft and oppression, licking their dry, parched, bloodless lips. These were the things they cared about. These were the needs they were eager to address.

To state the country and its revenues in their real condition, and to provide for those fictitious claims, consistently with the support of an army and a civil establishment, would have been impossible; therefore the ministers are silent on that head, and rest themselves on the authority of Lord Macartney, who, in a letter to the Court of Directors, written in the year 1781, speculating on what might be the result of a wise management of the countries assigned by the Nabob of Arcot, rates the revenue, as in time of peace, at twelve hundred thousand pounds a year, as he does those of the king of Tanjore (which had not been assigned) at four hundred and fifty. On this Lord Macartney grounds his calculations, and on this they choose to ground theirs. It was on this calculation that the ministry, in direct opposition to the remonstrances of the Court of Directors, have compelled that miserable enslaved body to put their hands to an order for appropriating the enormous sum of 480,000l. annually, as a fund for paying to their rebellious servants a debt contracted in defiance of their clearest and most positive injunctions.

To present the country and its revenue accurately, while addressing those false claims that come with maintaining an army and a government, would have been impossible; so the ministers remain silent on that matter and rely on Lord Macartney's authority. In a letter to the Court of Directors from 1781, he speculated on the potential outcomes of effectively managing the territories assigned by the Nabob of Arcot, estimating the revenue during peacetime at 1.2 million pounds a year, and the revenue from the king of Tanjore (which had not been assigned) at 450,000 pounds. Lord Macartney based his calculations on this, and the ministers chose to base theirs on it as well. It was on this calculation that the ministry, going against the protests of the Court of Directors, forced that desperate, subjugated body to agree to an order allocating an enormous sum of 480,000 l. annually to pay their rebellious servants for a debt incurred in blatant disregard of their explicit and most definite orders.

The authority and information of Lord Macartney is held high on this occasion, though it is totally rejected in every other particular of this business. I believe I have the honor of being almost as old an acquaintance as any Lord Macartney has. A constant and unbroken friendship has subsisted between us from a very early period; and I trust he thinks, that, as I respect his character, and in general admire his conduct, I am one of those who feel no common interest in his reputation. Yet I do not hesitate wholly to disallow the calculation of 1781, without any apprehension that I shall appear to distrust his veracity or his judgment. This peace estimate of revenue was not grounded on the state of the Carnatic, as it then, or as it had recently, stood. It was a statement of former and better times. There is no doubt that a period did exist, when the large portion of the Carnatic held by the Nabob of Arcot might be fairly reputed to produce a revenue to that, or to a greater amount. But the whole had so melted away by the slow and silent hostility of oppression and mismanagement, that the revenues, sinking with the prosperity of the country, had fallen to about 800,000l. a year, even before an enemy's horse had imprinted his hoof on the soil of the Carnatic. From that view, and independently of the decisive effects of the war which ensued, Sir Eyre Coote conceived that years must pass before the country could be restored to its former prosperity, and production. It was that state of revenue (namely, the actual state before the war) which the Directors have opposed to Lord Macartney's speculation. They refused to take the revenues for more than 800,000l. In this they are justified by Lord Macartney himself, who, in a subsequent letter, informs the court that his sketch is a matter of speculation; it supposes the country restored to its ancient prosperity, and the revenue to be in a course of effective and honest collection. If, therefore, the ministers have gone wrong, they were not deceived by Lord Macartney: they were deceived by no man. The estimate of the Directors is nearly the very estimate furnished by the right honorable gentleman himself, and published to the world in one of the printed reports of his own committee;[41] but as soon as he obtained his power, he chose to abandon his account. No part of his official conduct can be defended on the ground of his Parliamentary information.

The authority and insights of Lord Macartney are highly regarded in this context, even though they're completely dismissed in every other aspect of this matter. I believe I have the honor of being one of the oldest acquaintances of Lord Macartney. We've had a constant and unbroken friendship since a very early time, and I trust he knows that, while I respect his character and generally admire his actions, I also have a genuine interest in his reputation. However, I have no hesitation in entirely rejecting the calculations from 1781, without fear of appearing to question his honesty or judgment. This revenue estimate was not based on the actual state of the Carnatic, either as it was then or as it had recently been. It reflected a time of former prosperity. There’s no doubt that there was a time when the significant portion of the Carnatic governed by the Nabob of Arcot could reasonably be said to generate a revenue that met or exceeded that amount. But the entire situation had deteriorated due to the slow and silent forces of oppression and mismanagement, causing revenues, which fell with the country’s prosperity, to drop to about 800,000l. a year, even before an enemy had set foot in the Carnatic. From this perspective, and apart from the major impacts of the later war, Sir Eyre Coote believed it would take years for the area to regain its former prosperity and production. It was this actual revenue state (specifically, the situation before the war) that the Directors contested against Lord Macartney's projections. They refused to accept revenues of more than 800,000l. In this stance, they are supported by Lord Macartney himself, who, in a later letter, informs the court that his projections are speculative; they assume the country is restored to its previous prosperity and that revenues are being effectively and honestly collected. Therefore, if the ministers made a mistake, it wasn't due to being misled by Lord Macartney; they weren't misled by anyone. The Directors’ estimate closely aligns with the one provided by the honorable gentleman himself, which was made public in one of his committee's printed reports;[41] but as soon as he gained his authority, he chose to retract his figures. None of his official actions can be justified based on his Parliamentary information.

In this clashing of accounts and estimates, ought not the ministry, if they wished to preserve even appearances, to have waited for information of the actual result of these speculations, before they laid a charge, and such a charge, not conditionally and eventually, but positively and authoritatively, upon a country which they all knew, and which one of them had registered on the records of this House, to be wasted, beyond all example, by every oppression of an abusive government, and every ravage of a desolating war? But that you may discern in what manner they use the correspondence of office, and that thereby you may enter into the true spirit of the ministerial Board of Control, I desire you, Mr. Speaker, to remark, that, through their whole controversy with the Court of Directors, they do not so much as hint at their ever having seen any other paper from Lord Macartney, or any other estimate of revenue than this of 1781. To this they hold. Here they take post; here they intrench themselves.

In this clash of opinions and estimates, shouldn’t the ministry, if they wanted to maintain even a semblance of credibility, have waited for actual results from these speculations before making a charge—and a charge that was not just conditional or eventual, but straightforward and authoritative—against a country that they all recognized, and which one of them had recorded in the records of this House, had been devastated beyond measure by relentless governmental abuse and the devastation of war? But so you can see how they utilize the correspondence from the office, and to truly understand the mindset of the ministerial Board of Control, I ask you, Mr. Speaker, to notice that throughout their entire argument with the Court of Directors, they don't even suggest they’ve seen any other document from Lord Macartney or any other revenue estimate besides this one from 1781. They cling to this. This is their position; this is where they fortify themselves.

When I first read this curious controversy between the ministerial board and the Court of Directors, common candor obliged me to attribute their tenacious adherence to the estimate of 1781 to a total ignorance of what had appeared upon the records. But the right honorable gentleman has chosen to come forward with an uncalled-for declaration; he boastingly tells you, that he has seen, read, digested, compared everything,—and that, if he has sinned, he has sinned with his eyes broad open. Since, then, the ministers will obstinately shut the gates of mercy on themselves, let them add to their crimes what aggravations they please. They have, then, (since it must be so,) wilfully and corruptly suppressed the information which they ought to have produced, and, for the support of peculation, have made themselves guilty of spoliation and suppression of evidence.[42] The paper I hold in my hand, which totally overturns (for the present, at least) the estimate of 1781, they have no more taken notice of, in their controversy with the Court of Directors, than if it had no existence. It is the report made by a committee appointed at Madras to manage the whole of the six countries assigned to the Company by the Nabob of Arcot. This committee was wisely instituted by Lord Macartney, to remove from himself the suspicion of all improper management in so invidious a trust; and it seems to have been well chosen. This committee has made a comparative estimate of the only six districts which were in a condition to be let to farm. In one set of columns they state the gross and net produce of the districts as let by the Nabob. To that statement they oppose the terms on which the same districts were rented for five years under their authority. Under the Nabob, the gross farm was so high as 570,000l. sterling. What was the clear produce? Why, no more than about 250,000l.; and this was the whole profit of the Nabob's treasury, under his own management of all the districts which were in a condition to be let to farm on the 27th of May, 1782. Lord Macartney's leases stipulated a gross produce of no more than about 530,000l.; but then the estimated net amount was nearly double the Nabob's. It, however, did not then exceed 480,000l.; and Lord Macartney's commissioners take credit for an annual revenue amounting to this clear sum. Here is no speculation; here is no inaccurate account clandestinely obtained from those who might wish, and were enabled, to deceive. It is the authorized, recorded state of a real, recent transaction. Here is not twelve hundred thousand pound,—not eight hundred. The whole revenue of the Carnatic yielded no more, in May, 1782, than four hundred and eighty thousand pounds: nearly the very precise sum which your minister, who is so careful of the public security, has carried from all descriptions of establishment to form a fund for the private emolument of his creatures.

When I first read about this strange dispute between the ministerial board and the Court of Directors, I initially thought their stubborn insistence on the 1781 estimate was due to their complete ignorance of what was on the records. But the honorable gentleman has chosen to step in with an unnecessary statement; he proudly claims he has seen, read, understood, and compared everything—and that if he has made mistakes, he has done so with his eyes wide open. Since the ministers are determined to close the door on mercy for themselves, they can add whatever additional crimes they like. They have, then, knowingly and dishonestly withheld information that they should have presented, and in supporting their corruption, they have become guilty of tampering and hiding evidence. The document I have in my hand, which completely overturns the 1781 estimate for now, has not even been acknowledged by them in their dispute with the Court of Directors as if it doesn’t exist. It is the report made by a committee appointed in Madras to oversee all six areas assigned to the Company by the Nabob of Arcot. This committee was sensibly established by Lord Macartney to shield himself from accusations of mismanagement in such a contentious role, and it seems to have been well-chosen. This committee has created a comparative estimate of the only six districts that were ready to be leased out. In one set of columns, they detail the gross and net production of the areas as rented out by the Nabob. They counter that with the terms under which the same districts were rented for five years under their authority. Under the Nabob, the gross rent was as high as 570,000 pounds sterling. What was the clear yield? Just about 250,000 pounds; and this was the total profit for the Nabob’s treasury, managing all the districts that were ready to be leased out on May 27, 1782. Lord Macartney’s leases promised a gross yield of only about 530,000 pounds; but the estimated net income was nearly double that of the Nabob. However, it then didn’t surpass 480,000 pounds; and Lord Macartney’s commissioners claim an annual income amounting to this exact figure. This is not speculation; this is not an inaccurate account secretly obtained from those who might wish to deceive. It is the authorized, recorded state of a real, recent transaction. This is not one million two hundred thousand pounds—not eight hundred thousand. The total revenue of the Carnatic amounted to no more, in May 1782, than four hundred and eighty thousand pounds: nearly the exact amount that your minister, so concerned about public security, has transferred from all types of funding to create a pool for the personal gain of his associates.

In this estimate, we see, as I have just observed, the Nabob's farms rated so high as 570,000l. Hitherto all is well: but follow on to the effective net revenue; there the illusion vanishes; and you will not find nearly so much as half the produce. It is with reason, therefore, Lord Macartney invariably, throughout the whole correspondence, qualifies all his views and expectations of revenue, and all his plans for its application, with this indispensable condition, that the management is not in the hands of the Nabob of Arcot. Should that fatal measure take place, he has over and over again told you that he has no prospect of realizing anything whatsoever for any public purpose. With these weighty declarations, confirmed by such a state of indisputable fact before them, what has been done by the Chancellor of the Exchequer and his accomplices? Shall I be believed? They have delivered over those very territories, on the keeping of which in the hands of the committee the defence of our dominions, and, what was more dear to them, possibly, their own job, depended,—they have delivered back again, without condition, without arrangement, without stipulation of any sort for the natives of any rank, the whole of those vast countries, to many of which he had no just claim, into the ruinous mismanagement of the Nabob of Arcot. To crown all, according to their miserable practice, whenever they do anything transcendently absurd, they preface this their abdication of their trust by a solemn declaration that they were not obliged to it by any principle of policy or any demand of justice whatsoever.

In this estimate, we see, as I just mentioned, the Nabob's farms valued at 570,000l. Up to this point, everything seems fine: but when you look at the actual net revenue, the illusion disappears; and you won’t find even half of the expected output. It’s with good reason, then, that Lord Macartney consistently qualifies all his views and expectations regarding revenue and all his plans for its use with the crucial condition that the management is not under the control of the Nabob of Arcot. If that disastrous decision occurs, he has repeatedly stated that he sees no chance of achieving anything for any public purpose. With these strong statements, backed by clear evidence in front of them, what action has been taken by the Chancellor of the Exchequer and his associates? Will anyone believe me? They have handed back those very territories, which were essential for the defense of our territories and, perhaps more importantly to them, their own interests, to the mismanagement of the Nabob of Arcot—without conditions, arrangements, or any stipulations for the natives of any rank. To top it all off, true to their unfortunate habit, whenever they do something utterly ridiculous, they start this relinquishment of their responsibility with a solemn declaration that they were not compelled to do so by any principle of policy or demand for justice whatsoever.

I have stated to you the estimated produce of the territories of the Carnatic in a condition to be farmed in 1782, according to the different managements into which they might fall; and this estimate the ministers have thought proper to suppress. Since that, two other accounts have been received. The first informs us, that there has been a recovery of what is called arrear, as well as of an improvement of the revenue of one of the six provinces which were let in 1782.[43] It was brought about by making a new war. After some sharp actions, by the resolution and skill of Colonel Fullarton several of the petty princes of the most southerly of the unwasted provinces were compelled to pay very heavy rents and tributes, who for a long time before had not paid any acknowledgment. After this reduction, by the care of Mr. Irwin, one of the committee, that province was divided into twelve farms. This operation raised the income of that particular province; the others remain as they were first farmed. So that, instead of producing only their original rent of 480,000l., they netted, in about two years and a quarter, 1,320,000l. sterling, which would be about 660,000l. a year, if the recovered arrear was not included. What deduction is to be made on account of that arrear I cannot determine, but certainly what would reduce the annual income considerably below the rate I have allowed.

I’ve shared with you the estimated yield of the Carnatic territories that could be farmed in 1782, based on the different management styles they might follow; however, the ministers decided to keep this estimate under wraps. Since then, we’ve received two more reports. The first tells us that there has been some recovery of what’s called arrears, as well as an increase in revenue from one of the six provinces that were leased in 1782. This was achieved through a new war. After some intense battles, thanks to the determination and skill of Colonel Fullarton, several of the minor princes in the southern regions of the untouched provinces were forced to pay substantial rents and tributes, something they hadn’t done in a long time. Following this reduction, with the efforts of Mr. Irwin from the committee, that province was split into twelve farms. This move boosted the revenue of that specific province; the others remained as they were originally farmed. Therefore, instead of generating just their initial rent of 480,000l., they earned a total of 1,320,000l. sterling in about two years and a quarter, which averages to about 660,000l. a year if we don’t count the recovered arrears. I can't determine how much needs to be deducted for those arrears, but it would certainly lower the annual income significantly below what I’ve projected.

The second account received is the letting of the wasted provinces of the Carnatic. This I understand is at a growing rent, which may or may not realize what it promises; but if it should answer, it will raise the whole, at some future time, to 1,200,000l.

The second account we've received is about the leasing of the neglected regions of the Carnatic. I've heard this is at an increasing rent, which may or may not fulfill its potential; however, if it works out, it could eventually raise the total to 1,200,000l.

You must here remark, Mr. Speaker, that this revenue is the produce of all the Nabob's dominions. During the assignment, the Nabob paid nothing, because the Company had all. Supposing the whole of the lately assigned territory to yield up to the most sanguine expectations of the right honorable gentleman, and suppose 1,200,000l. to be annually realized, (of which we actually know of no more than the realizing of six hundred thousand,) out of this you must deduct the subsidy and rent which the Nabob paid before the assignment,—namely, 340,000l. a year. This reduces back the revenue applicable to the new distribution made by his Majesty's ministers to about 800,000l. Of that sum five eighths are by them surrendered to the debts. The remaining three are the only fund left for all the purposes so magnificently displayed in the letter of the Board of Control: that is, for a new-cast peace establishment, a now fund for ordnance and fortifications, and a large allowance for what they call "the splendor of the Durbar."

You should note, Mr. Speaker, that this revenue comes from all of the Nabob's territories. During the assignment, the Nabob paid nothing because the Company received everything. Assuming the entire recently assigned territory meets even the highest expectations of the right honorable gentleman, and let’s say it generates 1,200,000 l. annually (though we actually only know of about six hundred thousand being generated), you must subtract the subsidy and rent the Nabob paid before the assignment—specifically, 340,000 l. a year. This brings the revenue available for the new distribution made by his Majesty's ministers down to about 800,000 l. Of that amount, five-eighths are allocated to debts. The remaining three-eighths are the only funds left for all the purposes so grandly outlined in the letter from the Board of Control: that is, for a new peace establishment, a new fund for ordnance and fortifications, and a substantial allowance for what they refer to as "the splendor of the Durbar."

You have heard the account of these territories as they stood in 1782. You have seen the actual receipt since the assignment in 1781, of which I reckon about two years and a quarter productive. I have stated to you the expectation from the wasted part. For realizing all this you may value yourselves on the vigor and diligence of a governor and committee that have done so much. If these hopes from the committee are rational, remember that the committee is no more. Your ministers, who have formed their fund for these debts on the presumed effect of the committee's management, have put a complete end to that committee. Their acts are rescinded; their leases are broken; their renters are dispersed. Your ministers knew, when they signed the death-warrant of the Carnatic, that the Nabob would not only turn all these unfortunate farmers of revenue out of employment, but that he has denounced his severest vengeance against them, for acting under British authority. With a knowledge of this disposition, a British Chancellor of the Exchequer and Treasurer of the Navy, incited by no public advantage, impelled by no public necessity, in a strain of the most wanton perfidy which has ever stained the annals of mankind, have delivered over to plunder, imprisonment, exile, and death itself, according to the mercy of such execrable tyrants as Amir-ul-Omrah and Paul Benfield, the unhappy and deluded souls who, untaught by uniform example, were still weak enough to put their trust in English faith.[44] They have gone farther: they have thought proper to mock and outrage their misery by ordering them protection and compensation. From what power is this protection to be derived, and from what fund is this compensation to arise? The revenues are delivered over to their oppressor; the territorial jurisdiction, from whence that revenue is to arise, and under which they live, is surrendered to the same iron hands: and that they shall be deprived of all refuge and all hope, the minister has made a solemn, voluntary declaration that he never will interfere with the Nabob's internal government.[45]

You’ve heard about these territories as they were in 1782. You’ve seen the actual receipt since the assignment in 1781, which I estimate has been about two years and a quarter of productivity. I’ve shared the expectations from the wasted parts. For all of this to happen, you should take pride in the energy and hard work of a governor and committee that have accomplished so much. If these hopes from the committee are rational, remember that the committee no longer exists. Your ministers, who set up their fund for these debts based on the assumed outcomes of the committee's management, have completely disbanded that committee. Their actions have been revoked; their leases are broken; their renters are scattered. Your ministers knew, when they signed the death-sentence of the Carnatic, that the Nabob would not only dismiss all these unfortunate revenue farmers from their jobs but also unleash his harshest punishment against them for acting under British authority. Knowing this, a British Chancellor of the Exchequer and Treasurer of the Navy, motivated by no public good and no public need, in an act of the most wanton betrayal ever recorded, have condemned the unfortunate and misled people who, despite consistent examples, were still naive enough to trust in British honesty, to plunder, imprisonment, exile, and even death at the mercy of such despicable tyrants as Amir-ul-Omrah and Paul Benfield.[44] They went even further: they deemed it appropriate to mock and insult their suffering by promising them protection and compensation. From what authority is this protection supposed to come, and from what source will this compensation arise? The revenues are handed over to their oppressor; the territorial jurisdiction, from which that revenue is generated and under which they live, is given over to the same iron grip: and to ensure that they are stripped of all refuge and hope, the minister has made a solemn declaration that he will never interfere with the Nabob’s internal governance.[45]

The last thing considered by the Board of Control among the debts of the Carnatic was that arising to the East India Company, which, after the provision for the cavalry, and the consolidation of 1777, was to divide the residue of the fund of 480,000l. a year with the lenders of 1767. This debt the worthy chairman, who sits opposite to me, contends to be three millions sterling. Lord Macartney's account of 1781 states it to be at that period 1,200,000l. The first account of the Court of Directors makes it 900,000l. This, like the private debt, being without any solid existence, is incapable of any distinct limits. Whatever its amount or its validity may be, one thing is clear: it is of the nature and quality of a public debt. In that light nothing is provided for it, but an eventual surplus to be divided with one class of the private demands, after satisfying the two first classes. Never was a more shameful postponing a public demand, which, by the reason of the thing, and the uniform practice of all nations, supersedes every private claim.

The last thing the Board of Control looked at among the debts of the Carnatic was the amount owed to the East India Company. After accounting for the cavalry and the consolidation of 1777, it was supposed to share the remaining fund of 480,000 l. a year with the lenders of 1767. The respectable chairman sitting across from me believes this debt to be three million pounds. Lord Macartney's account from 1781 states that at that time, it was 1,200,000 l. The initial report from the Court of Directors suggests it was 900,000 l. Like the private debt, this amount lacks any solid basis, making it impossible to define specifically. Regardless of its size or legitimacy, one thing is certain: it resembles a public debt. In that context, nothing has been set aside for it, except for a potential surplus to be shared with one class of private claims, after fulfilling the first two classes. There has never been a more disgraceful postponement of a public obligation, which, by its very nature and according to the consistent practice of all nations, takes precedence over any private claim.

Those who gave this preference to private claims consider the Company's as a lawful demand; else why did they pretend to provide for it? On their own principles they are condemned.

Those who favored private claims view the Company’s as a valid demand; otherwise, why would they have claimed to address it? By their own standards, they are judged.

But I, Sir, who profess to speak to your understanding and to your conscience, and to brush away from this business all false colors, all false appellations, as well as false facts, do positively deny that the Carnatic owes a shilling to the Company,—whatever the Company may be indebted to that undone country. It owes nothing to the Company, for this plain and simple reason: the territory charged with the debt is their own. To say that their revenues fall short, and owe them money, is to say they are in debt to themselves, which is only talking nonsense. The fact is, that, by the invasion of an enemy, and the ruin of the country, the Company, either in its own name, or in the names of the Nabob of Arcot and Rajah of Tanjore, has lost for several years what it might have looked to receive from its own estate. If men were allowed to credit themselves upon such principles, any one might soon grow rich by this mode of accounting. A flood comes down upon a man's estate in the Bedford Level of a thousand pounds a year, and drowns his rents for ten years. The Chancellor would put that man into the hands of a trustee, who would gravely make up his books, and for this loss credit himself in his account for a debt due to him of 10,000l. It is, however, on this principle the Company makes up its demands on the Carnatic. In peace they go the full length, and indeed more than the full length, of what the people can bear for current establishments; then they are absurd enough to consolidate all the calamities of war into debts,—to metamorphose the devastations of the country into demands upon its future production. What is this but to avow a resolution utterly to destroy their own country, and to force the people to pay for their sufferings to a government which has proved unable to protect either the share of the husbandman or their own? In every lease of a farm, the invasion of an enemy, instead of forming a demand for arrear, is a release of rent: nor for that release is it at all necessary to show that the invasion has left nothing to the occupier of the soil; though in the present case it would be too easy to prove that melancholy fact.[46] I therefore applauded my right honorable friend, who, when he canvassed the Company's accounts, as a preliminary to a bill that ought not to stand on falsehood of any kind, fixed his discerning eye and his deciding hand on these debts of the Company from the Nabob of Arcot and Rajah of Tanjore, and at one stroke expunged them all, as utterly irrecoverable: he might have added, as utterly unfounded.

But I, Sir, who aim to speak to your understanding and conscience, clearing away all misleading aspects of this matter, firmly deny that the Carnatic owes even a penny to the Company—no matter how much the Company might owe that devastated region. It owes nothing to the Company for this simple reason: the territory in question is theirs. To claim that they are in debt due to insufficient revenues is to say they owe money to themselves, which is just nonsense. The reality is that, due to enemy invasion and the devastation of the land, the Company, whether in its own name or in the names of the Nabob of Arcot and Rajah of Tanjore, has lost for several years what it could have expected to receive from its own territory. If people could account for themselves on such grounds, anyone could quickly get rich using this accounting method. If a flood devastates a man's estate in the Bedford Level, drowning his rents for ten years, the Chancellor would assign that man to a trustee who would seriously balance the books and credit him for a loss as a debt owed to him of 10,000l. However, it is on this principle that the Company calculates its demands on the Carnatic. In times of peace, they go to the extreme, and even beyond what the people can handle for regular expenses; then, they absurdly combine all the wartime disasters into debts—transforming the destruction of the land into future demands on its productivity. What is this but a declaration to completely ruin their own country and force the people to pay for their suffering to a government that has proven incapable of protecting either the farmers' share or their own? In any farm lease, an enemy's invasion, rather than creating a debt for overdue payments, serves as a rent release: and it is not necessary to prove that the invasion has left nothing for the landholder; though, in this instance, it would be all too easy to demonstrate that unfortunate fact.[46] I thus commend my honorable friend, who, when examining the Company’s accounts as a preliminary to a bill that must stand on truth, focused his keen eye and decisive hand on the debts of the Company from the Nabob of Arcot and Rajah of Tanjore, and with one decisive action wiped them all away as entirely uncollectible: he might have added, as totally unfounded.

On these grounds I do not blame the arrangement this day in question, as a preference given to the debt of individuals over the Company's debt. In my eye it is no more than the preference of a fiction over a chimera; but I blame the preference given to those fictitious private debts over the standing defence and the standing government. It is there the public is robbed. It is robbed in its army; it is robbed in its civil administration; it is robbed in its credit; it is robbed in its investment, which forms the commercial connection between that country and Europe. There is the robbery.

On these grounds, I don’t blame the arrangement in question today, which favors individual debts over the Company’s debts. To me, it’s just a preference for a fiction over an illusion; however, I do criticize the preference given to those fictitious private debts over the standing defense and the established government. That's where the public is getting robbed. The public is getting robbed in its army, robbed in its civil administration, robbed in its credit, and robbed in its investments, which create the commercial connection between that country and Europe. That’s where the robbery is.

But my principal objection lies a good deal deeper. That debt to the Company is the pretext under which all the other debts lurk and cover themselves. That debt forms the foul, putrid mucus in which are engendered the whole brood of creeping ascarides, all the endless involutions, the eternal knot, added to a knot of those inexpugnable tape-worms which devour the nutriment and eat up the bowels of India.[47] It is necessary, Sir, you should recollect two things. First, that the Nabob's debt to the Company carries no interest. In the next place, you will observe, that, whenever the Company has occasion to borrow, she has always commanded whatever she thought fit at eight per cent. Carrying in your mind these two facts, attend to the process with regard to the public and private debt, and with what little appearance of decency they play into each other's hands a game of utter perdition to the unhappy natives of India. The Nabob falls into an arrear to the Company. The Presidency presses for payment. The Nabob's answer is, "I have no money." Good! But there are soucars who will supply you on the mortgage of your territories. Then steps forward some Paul Benfield, and, from his grateful compassion to the Nabob, and his filial regard to the Company, he unlocks the treasures of his virtuous industry, and, for a consideration of twenty-four or thirty-six per cent on a mortgage of the territorial revenue, becomes security to the Company for the Nabob's arrear.

But my main issue goes much deeper. That debt to the Company is just the excuse that hides all the other debts. That debt is like the foul, rotten sludge where all sorts of problems breed, creating a whole range of complications, the endless struggles, and an overwhelming burden of those unstoppable parasites that consume the resources and exhaust the people of India.[47] You need to remember two things, Sir. First, that the Nabob's debt to the Company doesn’t accrue interest. Secondly, whenever the Company needs to borrow, it always demands whatever interest rate it sees fit, usually at eight percent. Keeping these two facts in mind, observe how the public and private debts intertwine, working together in a shameful game that leads to utter ruin for the unfortunate people of India. The Nabob falls behind on payments to the Company. The Presidency demands payment. The Nabob replies, "I have no money." Fine! But there are moneylenders ready to offer loans secured by your territories. Then along comes someone like Paul Benfield, who, out of his kindness toward the Nabob and loyalty to the Company, unleashes the wealth from his industriousness and, for a cut of twenty-four to thirty-six percent on a mortgage of the territorial revenue, becomes the guarantor for the Nabob's debt.

All this intermediate usury thus becomes sanctified by the ultimate view to the Company's payment. In this case, would not a plain man ask this plain question of the Company: If you know that the Nabob must annually mortgage his territories to your servants to pay his annual arrear to you, why is not the assignment or mortgage made directly to the Company itself? By this simple, obvious operation, the Company would be relieved and the debt paid, without the charge of a shilling interest to that prince. But if that course should be thought too indulgent, why do they not take that assignment with such interest to themselves as they pay to others, that is, eight per cent? Or if it were thought more advisable (why it should I know not) that he must borrow, why do not the Company lend their own credit to the Nabob for their own payment? That credit would not be weakened by the collateral security of his territorial mortgage. The money might still be had at eight per cent. Instead of any of these honest and obvious methods, the Company has for years kept up a show of disinterestedness and moderation, by suffering a debt to accumulate to them from the country powers without any interest at all; and at the same time have seen before their eyes, on a pretext of borrowing to pay that debt, the revenues of the country charged with an usury of twenty, twenty-four, thirty-six, and even eight-and-forty per cent, with compound interest,[48] for the benefit of their servants. All this time they know that by having a debt subsisting without any interest, which is to be paid by contracting a debt on the highest interest, they manifestly render it necessary to the Nabob of Arcot to give the private demand a preference to the public; and, by binding him and their servants together in a common cause, they enable him to form a party to the utter ruin of their own authority and their own affairs. Thus their false moderation, and their affected purity, by the natural operation of everything false and everything affected, becomes pander and bawd to the unbridled debauchery and licentious lewdness of usury and extortion.

All this middleman lending ends up being legitimized by the Company’s ultimate goal of getting paid. In this situation, wouldn’t a straightforward person ask the Company this simple question: If you know the Nabob has to mortgage his lands every year to your employees to settle his annual dues with you, why isn’t the mortgage done directly with the Company? By making this simple and obvious move, the Company would be off the hook and the debt would be paid without charging that prince even a penny in interest. But if that seems too lenient, why don’t they take that mortgage with the same interest they charge others, which is eight percent? Or if it’s believed that borrowing is necessary (I can’t understand why it would be), why doesn’t the Company extend its own credit to the Nabob for their own payment? That credit wouldn’t be weakened by the additional security of his land mortgage. The money could still be borrowed at eight percent. Instead of using any of these fair and clear solutions, the Company has for years maintained an appearance of selflessness and restraint by allowing a debt to accumulate from the local powers without any interest at all; meanwhile, they’ve watched as, under the guise of borrowing to pay that debt, the local revenues are subjected to exorbitant interest rates of twenty, twenty-four, thirty-six, and even forty-eight percent, compounded, for the benefit of their employees. All this time, they know that by having a debt that exists without interest, which must be paid off by taking on a debt with sky-high interest, they force the Nabob of Arcot to prioritize private demands over public interests; and, by tying him and their employees to a common cause, they allow him to create a faction that could ultimately destroy their own authority and operations. Thus, their false restraint and pretended integrity, by the natural result of everything false and pretentious, become complicit in the rampant indulgence and shameless exploitation of usury and extortion.

In consequence of this double game, all the territorial revenues have at one time or other been covered by those locusts, the English soucars. Not one single foot of the Carnatic has escaped them: a territory as large as England. During these operations what a scene has that country presented![49] The usurious European assignee supersedes the Nabob's native farmer of the revenue; the farmer flies to the Nabob's presence to claim his bargain; whilst his servants murmur for wages, and his soldiers mutiny for pay. The mortgage to the European assignee is then resumed, and the native farmer replaced,—replaced, again to be removed on the new clamor of the European assignee.[50] Every man of rank and landed fortune being long since extinguished, the remaining miserable last cultivator, who grows to the soil, after having his back scored by the farmer, has it again flayed by the whip of the assignee, and is thus, by a ravenous, because a short-lived succession of claimants, lashed from oppressor to oppressor, whilst a single drop of blood is left as the means of extorting a single grain of corn. Do not think I paint. Far, very far, from it: I do not reach the fact, nor approach to it. Men of respectable condition, men equal to your substantial English yeomen, are daily tied up and scourged to answer the multiplied demands of various contending and contradictory titles, all issuing from one and the same source. Tyrannous exaction brings on servile concealment; and that again calls forth tyrannous coercion. They move in a circle, mutually producing and produced; till at length nothing of humanity is left in the government, no trace of integrity, spirit, or manliness in the people, who drag out a precarious and degraded existence under this system of outrage upon human nature. Such is the effect of the establishment of a debt to the Company, as it has hitherto been managed, and as it ever will remain, until ideas are adopted totally different from those which prevail at this time.

As a result of this double game, all the territorial revenues have at one time or another been drained by those pests, the English soucars. Not a single inch of the Carnatic has escaped them: a region as large as England. Throughout these actions, what a scene that country has presented![49] The greedy European agent replaces the Nabob's local tax collector; the tax collector rushes to the Nabob to demand his share; while his staff grumbles about unpaid wages, and his soldiers revolt for their salaries. The mortgage to the European agent is then revived, and the local tax collector is reinstated,—only to be ousted again by the new demands of the European agent.[50] Every man of rank and land has long since disappeared, leaving only the miserable last farmer, who is tied to the land, after having been beaten by the tax collector, only to be whipped by the agent, and is thus, through a succession of greedy, short-lived claimants, shifted from one oppressor to the next, while a single drop of blood is exploited to extract a single grain of corn. Don’t think I exaggerate. Far from it: I don’t even come close to the truth. Respectable men, equal to your solid English farmers, are routinely tied up and whipped to meet the endless demands of various conflicting claims, all stemming from the same source. Oppressive demands lead to desperate concealment; and that, in turn, calls forth oppressive enforcement. They exist in a cycle, mutually creating and being created; until finally, nothing of humanity remains in the government, no trace of integrity, spirit, or manliness in the people, who endure a precarious and degraded existence under this brutal system. Such is the impact of the establishment of a debt to the Company, as it has been managed so far, and will continue to be, until completely different ideas are adopted from those that dominate today.

Your worthy ministers, supporting what they are obliged to condemn, have thought fit to renew the Company's old order against contracting private debts in future. They begin by rewarding the violation of the ancient law; and then they gravely reenact provisions, of which they have given bounties for the breach. This inconsistency has been well exposed.[51] But what will you say to their having gone the length of giving positive directions for contracting the debt which they positively forbid?

Your esteemed ministers, backing what they should be condemning, have decided to revive the Company's old rule against taking on private debts in the future. They start by rewarding the disregard for the old law, and then they seriously reenact rules that they have already incentivized breaking. This contradiction has been clearly pointed out.[51] But what do you think about their actually giving explicit instructions for taking on the debt that they are explicitly prohibiting?

I will explain myself. They order the Nabob, out of the revenues of the Carnatic, to allot four hundred and eighty thousand pounds a year, as a fund for the debts before us. For the punctual payment of this annuity, they order him to give soucar security.[52] When a soucar, that is, a money-dealer, becomes security for any native prince, the course is for the native prince to counter-secure the money-dealer, by making over to him in mortgage a portion of his territory equal to the sum annually to be paid, with an interest of at least twenty-four per cent. The point fit for the House to know is, who are these soucars to whom this security on the revenues in favor of the Nabob's creditors is to be given? The majority of the House, unaccustomed to these transactions, will hear with astonishment that these soucars are no other than the creditors themselves. The minister, not content with authorizing these transactions in a manner and to an extent unhoped for by the rapacious expectations of usury itself, loads the broken back of the Indian revenues, in favor of his worthy friends, the soucars, with an additional twenty-four per cent for being security to themselves for their own claims, for condescending to take the country in mortgage to pay to themselves the fruits of their own extortions.

I will explain myself. They instruct the Nabob to allocate four hundred and eighty thousand pounds a year from the revenues of the Carnatic as a fund for the debts we’re discussing. To ensure the timely payment of this annuity, they require him to provide soucar security.[52] When a soucar, meaning a money-lender, provides security for any native prince, the typical arrangement is for the native prince to counter-secure the money-lender by mortgaging a portion of his territory equal to the annual payment, with an interest rate of at least twenty-four percent. What the House needs to understand is who these soucars are to whom this security on the revenues for the Nabob's creditors is to be granted. Most of the House, unfamiliar with these dealings, will be shocked to learn that these soucars are, in fact, the creditors themselves. The minister, not satisfied with permitting these transactions in a way and to a degree beyond the greedy expectations of usury, burdens the already struggling Indian revenues in favor of his esteemed friends, the soucars, with an additional twenty-four percent for providing security for their own claims, simply for agreeing to take the country in mortgage to pay themselves the results of their own exploitation.

The interest to be paid for this security, according to the most moderate strain of soucar demand, comes to 118,000l. a year, which, added to the 480,000l. on which it is to accrue, will make the whole charge amount to 598,000l. a year,—as much as even a long peace will enable those revenues to produce. Can any one reflect for a moment on all those claims of debt, which the minister exhausts himself in contrivances to augment with new usuries, without lifting up his hands and eyes in astonishment at the impudence both of the claim and of the adjudication? Services of some kind or other these servants of the Company must have done, so great and eminent that the Chancellor of the Exchequer cannot think that all they have brought home is half enough. He hallooes after them, "Gentlemen, you have forgot a large packet behind you, in your hurry; you have not sufficiently recovered yourselves; you ought to have, and you shall have, interest upon interest upon a prohibited debt that is made up of interest upon interest. Even this is too little. I have thought of another character for you, by which you may add something to your gains: you shall be security to yourselves; and hence will arise a new usury, which shall efface the memory of all the usuries suggested to you by your own dull inventions."

The interest to be paid for this security, based on the most modest demand for money lending, amounts to £118,000 a year. When added to the £480,000 on which it is based, the total annual cost will be £598,000—just as much as a long period of peace will allow those revenues to generate. Can anyone pause for a moment to think about all those debt claims that the minister tirelessly tries to increase with new loans, without raising his hands and eyes in disbelief at the audacity of both the claim and the decision? These representatives of the Company must have provided services so significant that the Chancellor of the Exchequer cannot believe that what they’ve received is anywhere near enough. He calls out to them, "Gentlemen, you've left a large package behind in your rush; you haven't fully collected what is due to you; you should and will receive interest on top of interest on an already prohibited debt made up of interest on interest. Even that isn’t sufficient. I’ve come up with another role for you, through which you can increase your earnings: you will be your own guarantors, leading to a new type of interest that will erase the memory of all the interests suggested by your own uninspired ideas."

I have done with the arrangement relative to the Carnatic. After this it is to little purpose to observe on what the ministers have done to Tanjore. Your ministers have not observed even form and ceremony in their outrageous and insulting robbery of that country, whose only crime has been its early and constant adherence to the power of this, and the suffering of an uniform pillage in consequence of it. The debt of the Company from the Rajah of Tanjore is just of the same stuff with that of the Nabob of Arcot.

I've finished the arrangements regarding the Carnatic. After this, there’s little point in commenting on what the ministers have done to Tanjore. Your ministers have completely disregarded customary protocols in their outrageous and insulting theft from that country, which has only remained loyal to this power and has suffered continuous plunder as a result. The debt owed by the Rajah of Tanjore to the Company is exactly like that of the Nabob of Arcot.

The subsidy from Tanjore, on the arrear of which this pretended debt (if any there be) has accrued to the Company, is not, like that paid by the Nabob of Arcot, a compensation for vast countries obtained, augmented, and preserved for him; not the price of pillaged treasuries, ransacked houses, and plundered territories: it is a large grant, from a small kingdom not obtained by our arms; robbed, not protected, by our power; a grant for which no equivalent was ever given, or pretended to be given. The right honorable gentleman, however, bears witness in his reports to the punctuality of the payments of this grant of bounty, or, if you please, of fear. It amounts to one hundred and sixty thousand pounds sterling net annual subsidy. He bears witness to a further grant of a town and port, with an annexed district of thirty thousand pound a year, surrendered to the Company since the first donation. He has not borne witness, but the fact is, (he will not deny it,) that in the midst of war, and during the ruin and desolation of a considerable part of his territories, this prince made many very large payments. Notwithstanding these merits and services, the first regulation of ministry is to force from him a territory of an extent which they have not yet thought proper to ascertain,[53] for a military peace establishment the particulars of which they have not yet been pleased to settle.

The subsidy from Tanjore, on which this supposed debt (if it even exists) has been added to the Company's account, isn’t like the payment made by the Nabob of Arcot, which compensates for vast lands gained, expanded, and maintained for him; it’s not the cost of looted treasures, ransacked homes, and plundered lands: it’s a significant grant from a small kingdom that wasn’t acquired by our military force; it was taken, not safeguarded, by our influence; a grant for which no equivalent was ever provided or even claimed. However, the honorable gentleman acknowledges in his reports the regularity of the payments of this subsidy or, if you prefer, this grant out of fear. It totals one hundred and sixty thousand pounds sterling in net annual support. He also notes an additional grant of a town and port, along with a district yielding thirty thousand pounds a year, given to the Company since the initial donation. He hasn’t acknowledged, but the truth is, (he can’t deny it) that amidst the war and the devastation affecting a significant part of his territories, this ruler made several substantial payments. Despite these achievements and contributions, the first directive from the ministry is to extract from him a territory of a size they have yet to define,[53] for a military peace establishment whose details they haven’t yet chosen to clarify.

The next part of their arrangement is with regard to war. As confessedly this prince had no share in stirring up any of the former wars, so all future wars are completely out of his power; for he has no troops whatever, and is under a stipulation not so much as to correspond with any foreign state, except through the Company. Yet, in case the Company's servants should be again involved in war, or should think proper again to provoke any enemy, as in times past they have wantonly provoked all India, he is to be subjected to a new penalty. To what penalty? Why, to no less than the confiscation of all his revenues. But this is to end with the war, and they are to be faithfully returned? Oh, no! nothing like it. The country is to remain under confiscation until all the debt which the Company shall think fit to incur in such war shall be discharged: that is to say, forever. His sole comfort is, to find his old enemy, the Nabob of Arcot, placed in the very same condition.

The next part of their agreement deals with war. As it’s clear that this prince had nothing to do with starting any of the previous wars, all future wars are completely out of his hands; he has no troops at all and is not allowed to communicate with any foreign country, except through the Company. However, if the Company’s employees get involved in war again or decide to provoke an enemy, as they recklessly have in the past with all of India, he will face a new penalty. What kind of penalty? It’s nothing less than the confiscation of all his income. But will this end with the war, and will his revenues be returned? Oh, no! Nothing like that. The land will stay under confiscation until all the debt that the Company deems necessary to incur during that war is paid off: which basically means forever. His only comfort is knowing that his old rival, the Nabob of Arcot, is in the exact same situation.

The revenues of that miserable country were, before the invasion of Hyder, reduced to a gross annual receipt of three hundred and sixty thousand pound.[54] From this receipt the subsidy I have just stated is taken. This again, by payments in advance, by extorting deposits of additional sums to a vast amount for the benefit of their soucars, and by an endless variety of other extortions, public and private, is loaded with a debt, the amount of which I never could ascertain, but which is large undoubtedly, generating an usury the most completely ruinous that probably was ever heard of: that is, forty-eight per cent, payable monthly, with compound interest.[55]

The income of that unfortunate country, before Hyder's invasion, had dropped to a gross annual total of three hundred sixty thousand pounds.[54] From this income, the subsidy I mentioned earlier is taken. This amount is further burdened by advance payments, forced deposits of significant extra sums for the benefit of their merchants, and countless other public and private extortions. It carries a debt, the size of which I could never determine, but it's certainly large, generating an incredibly destructive interest rate that probably has ever been known: that is, forty-eight percent, payable monthly, with compound interest.[55]

Such is the state to which the Company's servants have reduced that country. Now come the reformers, restorers, and comforters of India. What have they done? In addition to all these tyrannous exactions, with all these ruinous debts in their train, looking to one side of an agreement whilst they wilfully shut their eyes to the other, they withdraw from Tanjore all the benefits of the treaty of 1762, and they subject that nation to a perpetual tribute of forty thousand a year to the Nabob of Arcot: a tribute never due, or pretended to be due, to him, even when he appeared to be something; a tribute, as things now stand, not to a real potentate, but to a shadow, a dream, an incubus of oppression. After the Company has accepted in subsidy, in grant of territory, in remission of rent, as a compensation for their own protection, at least two hundred thousand pound a year, without discounting a shilling for that receipt, the ministers condemn this harassed nation to be tributary to a person who is himself, by their own arrangement, deprived of the right of war or peace, deprived of the power of the sword, forbid to keep up a single regiment of soldiers, and is therefore wholly disabled from all protection of the country which is the object of the pretended tribute. Tribute hangs on the sword. It is an incident inseparable from real, sovereign power. In the present case, to suppose its existence is as absurd as it is cruel and oppressive. And here, Mr. Speaker, you have a clear exemplification of the use of those false names and false colors which the gentlemen who have lately taken possession of India choose to lay on for the purpose of disguising their plan of oppression. The Nabob of Arcot and Rajah of Tanjore have, in truth and substance, no more than a merely civil authority, held in the most entire dependence on the Company. The Nabob, without military, without federal capacity, is extinguished as a potentate; but then he is carefully kept alive as an independent and sovereign power, for the purpose of rapine and extortion,—for the purpose of perpetuating the old intrigues, animosities, usuries, and corruptions.

This is how the Company's employees have reduced that country. Now the reformers, restorers, and comforters of India enter the scene. What have they achieved? Besides all these oppressive demands and the devastating debts that follow, they focus on one side of an agreement while willfully ignoring the other. They take away from Tanjore all the advantages of the treaty of 1762 and force that nation to pay a yearly tribute of forty thousand to the Nabob of Arcot—a tribute that was never owed or even claimed when he was somewhat in power; a tribute that, as things stand now, goes to a mere shadow, a dream, an oppressive burden. After the Company has accepted at least two hundred thousand pounds a year in subsidies, grants of land, and rent reductions as compensation for their so-called protection, the ministers condemn this suffering nation to pay tribute to someone who, by their own agreement, has been stripped of the rights of war or peace, has no military power, is forbidden to maintain any soldiers, and is thus entirely unable to protect the very country that the supposed tribute is meant to benefit. Tribute is tied to real, sovereign power. Assuming it exists in this case is as absurd as it is cruel and oppressive. And here, Mr. Speaker, you have a clear example of the false names and deceitful appearances that the gentlemen who have recently taken control of India use to disguise their plan of oppression. The Nabob of Arcot and the Rajah of Tanjore truly have no more than a purely civil authority entirely reliant on the Company. The Nabob, lacking military and federal authority, has been extinguished as a ruler; yet he is carefully maintained as an independent and sovereign power for the purposes of theft and exploitation—for the purpose of perpetuating old schemes, rivalries, lendings, and corruption.

It was not enough that this mockery of tribute was to be continued without the correspondent protection, or any of the stipulated equivalents, but ten years of arrear, to the amount of 400,000l. sterling, is added to all the debts to the Company and to individuals, in order to create a new debt, to be paid (if at all possible to be paid in whole or in part) only by new usuries,—and all this for the Nabob of Arcot, or rather for Mr. Benfield and the corps of the Nabob's creditors and their soucars. Thus these miserable Indian princes are continued in their seats for no other purpose than to render them, in the first instance, objects of every species of extortion, and, in the second, to force them to become, for the sake of a momentary shadow of reduced authority, a sort of subordinate tyrants, the ruin and calamity, not the fathers and cherishers, of their people.

It wasn't enough that this mockery of tribute would continue without the necessary protection or any of the agreed compensations, but on top of that, ten years of back payments, totaling £400,000, are added to all the debts owed to the Company and individuals, creating a new debt that can only be paid—if at all—through more high-interest loans. All this is for the Nabob of Arcot, or rather for Mr. Benfield and the group of the Nabob's creditors and their moneylenders. These unfortunate Indian princes are kept in power only to be exploited in every way possible, and then forced to become a kind of minor tyrants for the sake of a fleeting illusion of reduced authority, bringing ruin and disaster to their people instead of being their protectors and nurturers.

But take this tribute only as a mere charge (without title, cause, or equivalent) on this people; what one step has been taken to furnish grounds for a just calculation and estimate of the proportion of the burden and the ability? None,—not an attempt at it. They do not adapt the burden to the strength, but they estimate the strength of the bearers by the burden they impose. Then what care is taken to leave a fund sufficient to the future reproduction of the revenues that are to bear all these loads? Every one, but tolerably conversant in Indian affairs, must know that the existence of this little kingdom depends on its control over the river Cavery. The benefits of Heaven to any community ought never to be connected with political arrangements, or made to depend on the personal conduct of princes, in which the mistake, or error, or neglect, or distress, or passion of a moment, on either side, may bring famine on millions, and ruin an innocent nation perhaps for ages. The means of the subsistence of mankind should be as immutable as the laws of Nature, let power and dominion take what course they may.—Observe what has been done with regard to this important concern. The use of this river is, indeed, at length given to the Rajah, and a power provided for its enjoyment at his own charge; but the means of furnishing that charge (and a mighty one it is) are wholly out off. This use of the water, which ought to have no more connection than clouds and rains and sunshine with the politics of the Rajah, the Nabob, or the Company, is expressly contrived as a means of enforcing demands and arrears of tribute. This horrid and unnatural instrument of extortion had been a distinguishing feature in the enormities of the Carnatic politics, that loudly called for reformation. But the food of a whole people is by the reformers of India conditioned on payments from its prince, at a moment that he is overpowered with a swarm of their demands, without regard to the ability of either prince or people. In fine, by opening an avenue to the irruption of the Nabob of Arcot's creditors and soucars, whom every man, who did not fall in love with oppression and corruption on an experience of the calamities they produced, would have raised wall before wall and mound before mound to keep from a possibility of entrance, a more destructive enemy than Hyder Ali is introduced into that kingdom. By this part of their arrangement, in which they establish a debt to the Nabob of Arcot, in effect and substance, they deliver over Tanjore, bound hand and foot, to Paul Benfield, the old betrayer, insulter, oppressor, and scourge of a country which has for years been an object of an unremitted, but, unhappily, an unequal struggle, between the bounties of Providence to renovate and the wickedness of mankind to destroy.

But take this tribute only as a simple charge (without title, cause, or equivalent) on this people; what steps have been taken to provide a fair calculation and assessment of the burden and the ability? None—there hasn’t even been an attempt. They don’t tailor the burden to the strength, but instead they gauge the strength of the bearers by the burden they impose. So, what effort is made to ensure there's enough left to sustain the future generation of revenues that have to carry all these loads? Anyone who is reasonably familiar with Indian affairs knows that this small kingdom's survival hinges on its control over the Cavery River. The blessings of Heaven for any community should never be tied to political arrangements or made to depend on the personal behavior of rulers, where a mistake, error, neglect, distress, or a moment of passion from either side could lead to famine for millions and ruin an innocent nation for potentially ages. The means of human sustenance should be as unchanging as the laws of Nature, regardless of what direction power and authority may take. Look at what’s been done regarding this crucial issue. The use of this river is finally granted to the Rajah, and a means is provided for his enjoyment at his own expense; but the resources for that expense (and it is a hefty one) are entirely cut off. This access to the water, which should be as disconnected from the politics of the Rajah, the Nabob, or the Company as clouds, rains, and sunshine, is deliberately designed as a way to enforce tax demands and overdue payments. This brutal and unnatural tool of extortion had become a defining feature of the abuses in Carnatic politics, screaming for reform. Yet the food of an entire population is conditioned by the reformers of India on payments from its prince, at a time when he is overwhelmed by a flurry of their demands, without considering the capabilities of either the prince or the people. In short, by opening a pathway to the encroachment of the Nabob of Arcot's creditors and soucars, whom anyone who isn’t enamored with oppression and corruption would have built wall after wall to keep out, a more destructive enemy than Hyder Ali is allowed into that kingdom. Through this part of their arrangement, establishing a debt to the Nabob of Arcot in effect and substance, they hand over Tanjore, bound hand and foot, to Paul Benfield, the old betrayer, insulter, oppressor, and scourge of a land that has for years been caught in an ongoing, but unfortunately uneven, struggle between the generosity of Providence to renew and the wickedness of humanity to destroy.

The right honorable gentleman[56] talks of his fairness in determining the territorial dispute between the Nabob of Arcot and the prince of that country, when he superseded the determination of the Directors, in whom the law had vested the decision of that controversy. He is in this just as feeble as he is in every other part. But it is not necessary to say a word in refutation of any part of his argument. The mode of the proceeding sufficiently speaks the spirit of it. It is enough to fix his character as a judge, that he never heard the Directors in defence of their adjudication, nor either of the parties in support of their respective claims. It is sufficient for me that he takes from the Rajah of Tanjore by this pretended adjudication, or rather from his unhappy subjects, 40,000l. a year of his and their revenue, and leaves upon his and their shoulders all the charges that can be made on the part of the Nabob, on the part of his creditors, and on the part of the Company, without so much as hearing him as to right or to ability. But what principally induces me to leave the affair of the territorial dispute between the Nabob and the Rajah to another day is this,—that, both the parties being stripped of their all, it little signifies under which of their names the unhappy, undone people are delivered over to the merciless soucars, the allies of that right honorable gentleman and the Chancellor of the Exchequer. In them ends the account of this long dispute of the Nabob of Arcot and the Rajah of Tanjore.

The right honorable gentleman[56] talks about his fairness in resolving the territorial dispute between the Nabob of Arcot and the prince of that region, when he overruled the decision of the Directors, who were legally responsible for settling that issue. He is just as weak in this matter as he is in everything else. However, there's no need to refute any part of his argument. The way this was handled clearly reflects its true nature. It's enough to establish his character as a judge that he never heard the Directors defend their ruling, nor did he listen to either party support their claims. What matters to me is that he takes 40,000l. a year in revenue from the Rajah of Tanjore, or rather from his unfortunate subjects, through this bogus ruling, while placing all the burdens that can be imposed from the Nabob, his creditors, and the Company onto their shoulders, without ever giving him a chance to present his case or defend himself. But what really makes me want to leave the discussion of the territorial dispute between the Nabob and the Rajah for another time is this—since both parties are completely stripped of everything, it hardly matters whose name the unfortunate people are handed over to the ruthless soucars, who are allies of that right honorable gentleman and the Chancellor of the Exchequer. This is where the long saga of the dispute between the Nabob of Arcot and the Rajah of Tanjore comes to an end.

The right honorable gentleman is of opinion that his judgment in this case can be censured by none but those who seem to act as if they were paid agents to one of the parties. What does he think of his Court of Directors? If they are paid by either of the parties, by which of them does he think they are paid? He knows that their decision has been directly contrary to his. Shall I believe that it does not enter into his heart to conceive that any person can steadily and actively interest himself in the protection of the injured and oppressed without being well paid for his service? I have taken notice of this sort of discourse some days ago, so far as it may be supposed to relate to me. I then contented myself, as I shall now do, with giving it a cold, though a very direct contradiction. Thus much I do from respect to truth. If I did more, it might be supposed, by my anxiety to clear myself, that I had imbibed the ideas which, for obvious reasons, the right honorable gentleman wishes to have received concerning all attempts to plead the cause of the natives of India, as if it were a disreputable employment. If he had not forgot, in his present occupation, every principle which ought to have guided him, and I hope did guide him, in his late profession, he would have known that he who takes a fee for pleading the cause of distress against power, and manfully performs the duty he has assumed, receives an honorable recompense for a virtuous service. But if the right honorable gentleman will have no regard to fact in his insinuations or to reason in his opinions, I wish him at least to consider, that, if taking an earnest part with regard to the oppressions exercised in India, and with regard to this most oppressive case of Tanjore in particular, can ground a presumption of interested motives, he is himself the most mercenary man I know. His conduct, indeed, is such that he is on all occasions the standing testimony against himself. He it was that first called to that case the attention of the House; the reports of his own committee are ample and affecting upon that subject;[57] and as many of us as have escaped his massacre must remember the very pathetic picture he made of the sufferings of the Tanjore country, on the day when he moved the unwieldy code of his Indian resolutions. Has he not stated over and over again, in his reports, the ill treatment of the Rajah of Tanjore (a branch of the royal house of the Mahrattas, every injury to whom the Mahrattas felt as offered to themselves) as a main cause of the alienation of that people from the British power? And does he now think that to betray his principles, to contradict his declarations, and to become himself an active instrument in those oppressions which he had so tragically lamented, is the way to clear himself of having been actuated by a pecuniary interest at the time when he chose to appear full of tenderness to that ruined nation?

The honorable gentleman believes that only those acting like paid agents for one of the parties can criticize his judgment in this case. What does he think of his Court of Directors? If they are compensated by either party, which one does he think it is? He knows their decision goes against his. Should I really believe he thinks that anyone can deeply and passionately advocate for the injured and oppressed without being well compensated for their efforts? I noticed this type of talk a few days ago, as it might relate to me. I’m content now, as I was then, to give it a cold, yet straightforward, denial. I do this out of respect for the truth. If I did more, it might be assumed that my eagerness to clear my name shows I have accepted the views the honorable gentleman wants everyone to have about those who advocate for the people of India, as if it's an unworthy pursuit. If he hadn’t forgotten, in his current role, the principles that should have guided him—and I hope did guide him—in his previous profession, he would understand that someone who takes a fee to argue for those in distress against power, and does their job with integrity, earns an honorable reward for their virtuous actions. However, if the honorable gentleman disregards facts in his insinuations or logic in his opinions, I at least hope he considers that if genuinely caring about the oppression faced in India, and particularly the severe case of Tanjore, suggests selfish motives, then he himself is the most self-serving individual I know. His actions constantly serve as evidence against himself. He was the one who first drew the House's attention to this case; the reports from his own committee are extensive and moving on the subject, and all of us who survived his onslaught must remember the very emotional depiction he painted of the suffering in Tanjore when he presented his lengthy set of Indian resolutions. Has he not repeatedly mentioned, in his reports, the mistreatment of the Rajah of Tanjore (a branch of the royal Mahratta family, where any injury to them is felt as an affront to themselves) as a primary reason for the detachment of that people from British authority? Does he sincerely believe that betraying his principles, contradicting his statements, and becoming an active participant in the very oppressions he so sorrowfully mourned is the way to prove he wasn’t motivated by financial interest when he chose to appear deeply caring towards that devastated nation?

The right honorable gentleman is fond of parading on the motives of others, and on his own. As to himself, he despises the imputations of those who suppose that anything corrupt could influence him in this his unexampled liberality of the public treasure. I do not know that I am obliged to speak to the motives of ministry, in the arrangements they have made of the pretended debts of Arcot and Tanjore. If I prove fraud and collusion with regard to public money on those right honorable gentlemen, I am not obliged to assign their motives; because no good motives can be pleaded in favor of their conduct. Upon that case I stand; we are at issue; and I desire to go to trial. This, I am sure, is not loose railing, or mean insinuation, according to their low and degenerate fashion, when they make attacks on the measures of their adversaries. It is a regular and juridical course; and unless I choose it, nothing can compel me to go further.

The honorable gentleman enjoys showcasing the motivations of others as well as his own. As for himself, he looks down on those who think that anything dishonest could sway him in his unprecedented generosity with public funds. I’m not sure I have to address the motives of the government regarding the so-called debts of Arcot and Tanjore. If I can prove fraud and collusion involving public money with those honorable gentlemen, I don’t need to explain their motives; no good motives can justify their actions. That’s my position; we’re at a disagreement, and I want to go to trial. I’m confident this isn’t just empty insults or petty insinuations like they often use against their opponents. This is a legitimate legal process, and unless I decide otherwise, nothing can force me to proceed further.

But since these unhappy gentlemen have dared to hold a lofty tone about their motives, and affect to despise suspicion, instead of being careful not to give cause for it, I shall beg leave to lay before you some general observations on what I conceive was their duty in so delicate a business.

But since these unfortunate men have chosen to adopt a higher moral stance regarding their intentions and pretend to look down on suspicion, rather than being cautious not to provoke it, I would like to present some general thoughts on what I believe their responsibilities were in such a sensitive matter.

If I were worthy to suggest any line of prudence to that right honorable gentleman, I would tell him that the way to avoid suspicion in the settlement of pecuniary transactions, in which great frauds have been very strongly presumed, is, to attend to these few plain principles:—First, to hear all parties equally, and not the managers for the suspected claimants only; not to proceed in the dark, but to act with as much publicity as possible; not to precipitate decision; to be religious in following the rules prescribed in the commission under which we act; and, lastly, and above all, not to be fond of straining constructions, to force a jurisdiction, and to draw to ourselves the management of a trust in its nature invidious and obnoxious to suspicion, where the plainest letter of the law does not compel it. If these few plain rules are observed, no corruption ought to be suspected; if any of them are violated, suspicion will attach in proportion; if all of them are violated, a corrupt motive of some kind or other will not only be suspected, but must be violently presumed.

If I were worthy to give any advice to that honorable gentleman, I would tell him that the way to avoid suspicion in financial dealings, which have been strongly suspected of involving fraud, is to follow these few simple principles:—First, to listen to all parties equally, not just the managers for the suspected claimants; not to operate in secrecy, but to be as open as possible; not to rush into decisions; to strictly follow the rules outlined in the commission we're working under; and finally, and most importantly, not to be tempted to stretch interpretations, to impose jurisdiction, or to take control of a trust that is naturally controversial and prone to suspicion when the straightforward wording of the law does not require it. If these few basic rules are followed, no corruption should be suspected; if any of them are broken, suspicion will arise accordingly; if all of them are broken, a corrupt motive of some kind will not only be suspected but must be strongly assumed.

The persons in whose favor all these rules have been violated, and the conduct of ministers towards them, will naturally call for your consideration, and will serve to lead you through a series and combination of facts and characters, if I do not mistake, into the very inmost recesses of this mysterious business. You will then be in possession of all the materials on which the principles of sound jurisprudence will found, or will reject, the presumption of corrupt motives, or, if such motives are indicated, will point out to you of what particular nature the corruption is.

The people who have been affected by all these broken rules and the way ministers have treated them will naturally require your attention. This will guide you through a series of facts and personalities, if I’m not mistaken, into the very core of this mysterious situation. You will then have all the information needed to establish, or dismiss, the idea of corrupt motives, or if such motives are evident, will clarify what kind of corruption it is.

Our wonderful minister, as you all know, formed a new plan, a plan insigne, recens, indictum ore alio, a plan for supporting the freedom of our Constitution by court intrigues, and for removing its corruptions by Indian delinquency. To carry that bold, paradoxical design into execution, sufficient funds and apt instruments became necessary. You are perfectly sensible that a Parliamentary reform occupies his thoughts day and night, as an essential member in this extraordinary project. In his anxious researches upon this subject, natural instinct, as well as sound policy, would direct his eyes and settle his choice on Paul Benfield. Paul Benfield is the grand Parliamentary reformer, the reformer to whom the whole choir of reformers bow, and to whom even the right honorable gentleman himself must yield the palm: for what region in the empire, what city, what borough, what county, what tribunal in this kingdom is not full of his labors? Others have been only speculators; he is the grand practical reformer; and whilst the Chancellor of the Exchequer pledges in vain the man and the minister, to increase the provincial members, Mr. Benfield has auspiciously and practically begun it. Leaving far behind him even Lord Camelford's generous design of bestowing Old Sarum on the Bank of England, Mr. Benfield has thrown in the borough of Cricklade to reinforce the county representation. Not content with this, in order to station a steady phalanx for all future reforms, this public-spirited usurer, amidst his charitable toils for the relief of India, did not forget the poor, rotten Constitution of his native country. For her, he did not disdain to stoop to the trade of a wholesale upholsterer for this House,—to furnish it, not with the faded tapestry figures of antiquated merit, such as decorate, and may reproach, some other houses, but with real, solid, living patterns of true modern virtue. Paul Benfield made (reckoning himself) no fewer than eight members in the last Parliament. What copious streams of pure blood must he not have transfused into the veins of the present!

Our amazing minister, as you all know, came up with a new plan, a plan insigne, recens, indictum ore alio, a plan aimed at protecting our Constitution’s freedom through court dealings and tackling its corruptions through Indian misconduct. To implement this bold and unusual strategy, we needed sufficient funds and capable people. You are all quite aware that Parliamentary reform is constantly on his mind as a crucial part of this extraordinary initiative. In his thorough exploration of this topic, natural instinct and sensible strategy would lead him to choose Paul Benfield. Paul Benfield is the ultimate Parliamentary reformer, the reformer to whom all others defer, and even the right honorable gentleman himself must recognize: for what area in the empire, what city, what borough, what county, what tribunal in this kingdom isn’t filled with his work? Others have merely speculated; he is the true hands-on reformer. While the Chancellor of the Exchequer makes empty pledges about the man and the minister to increase provincial representatives, Mr. Benfield has successfully taken action. Leaving far behind even Lord Camelford's generous plan to hand Old Sarum to the Bank of England, Mr. Benfield has brought in the borough of Cricklade to enhance county representation. Not satisfied with this, in order to establish a solid base for future reforms, this civic-minded financier, amidst his charitable efforts to help India, didn’t forget the weak, outdated Constitution of his homeland. For it, he didn’t hesitate to take on the role of a wholesale upholsterer for this House—to decorate it, not with the worn-out tapestry figures of outdated merit that adorn, and may shame, some other houses, but with real, substantial, contemporary examples of true modern virtue. Paul Benfield claimed he created no fewer than eight members in the last Parliament. What generous flows of pure energy must he have infused into the present!

But what is even more striking than the real services of this new-imported patriot is his modesty. As soon as he had conferred this benefit on the Constitution, he withdrew himself from our applause. He conceived that the duties of a member of Parliament (which with the elect faithful, the true believers, the Islam of Parliamentary reform, are of little or no merit, perhaps not much better than specious sins) might he as well attended to in India as in England, and the means of reformation to Parliament itself be far better provided. Mr. Benfield was therefore no sooner elected than he set off for Madras, and defrauded the longing eyes of Parliament. We have never enjoyed in this House the luxury of beholding that minion of the human race, and contemplating that visage which has so long reflected the happiness of nations.

But what’s even more impressive than the genuine contributions of this newly arrived patriot is his humility. As soon as he had made this significant contribution to the Constitution, he stepped back from our praise. He believed that the responsibilities of a member of Parliament (which, for the loyal supporters, the true believers, the Islam of Parliamentary reform, hold little merit, perhaps not much better than false pretenses) could be just as well managed in India as in England, and that the means for reforming Parliament itself could be provided much better. So, as soon as Mr. Benfield was elected, he headed off to Madras, leaving Parliament longing for his presence. We have never had the pleasure in this House of seeing that favorite of humanity and reflecting on the face that has so long mirrored the happiness of nations.

It was therefore not possible for the minister to consult personally with this great man. What, then, was he to do? Through a sagacity that never failed him in these pursuits, he found out, in Mr. Benfield's representative, his exact resemblance. A specific attraction, by which he gravitates towards all such characters, soon brought our minister into a close connection with Mr. Benfield's agent and attorney, that is, with the grand contractor, (whom I name to honor,) Mr. Richard Atkinson,—a name that will be well remembered as long as the records of this House, as long as the records of the British Treasury, as long as the monumental debt of England, shall endure.

It was therefore impossible for the minister to meet personally with this great man. So, what was he supposed to do? With his usual sharp insight, he discovered that Mr. Benfield's representative looked just like him. A natural attraction that he felt towards such characters quickly led our minister to establish a close relationship with Mr. Benfield's agent and attorney, namely the grand contractor, (whom I mention with respect,) Mr. Richard Atkinson—a name that will be remembered as long as the records of this House, the records of the British Treasury, and the monumental debt of England last.

This gentleman, Sir, acts as attorney for Mr. Paul Benfield. Every one who hears me is well acquainted with the sacred friendship and the steady mutual attachment that subsists between him and the present minister. As many members as chose to attend in the first session of this Parliament can best tell their own feelings at the scenes which were then acted. How much that honorable gentleman was consulted in the original frame and fabric of the bill, commonly called Mr. Pitt's India Bill, is matter only of conjecture, though by no means difficult to divine. But the public was an indignant witness of the ostentation with which the measure was made his own, and the authority with which he brought up clause after clause, to stuff and fatten the rankness of that corrupt act. As fast as the clauses were brought up to the table, they were accepted. No hesitation, no discussion. They were received by the new minister, not with approbation, but with implicit submission. The reformation may be estimated by seeing who was the reformer. Paul Benfield's associate and agent was held up to the world as legislator of Hindostan. But it was necessary to authenticate the coalition between the men of intrigue in India and the minister of intrigue in England by a studied display of the power of this their connecting link. Every trust, every honor, every distinction, was to be heaped upon him. He was at once made a Director of the India Company, made an alderman of London, and to be made, if ministry could prevail, (and I am sorry to say how near, how very near, they were prevailing,) representative of the capital of this kingdom. But to secure his services against all risk, he was brought in for a ministerial borough. On his part, he was not wanting in zeal for the common cause. His advertisements show his motives, and the merits upon which he stood. For your minister, this worn-out veteran submitted to enter into the dusty field of the London contest; and you all remember that in the same virtuous cause he submitted to keep a sort of public office or counting-house, where the whole business of the last general election was managed. It was openly managed by the direct agent and attorney of Benfield. It was managed upon Indian principles and for an Indian interest. This was the golden cup of abominations,—this the chalice of the fornications of rapine, usury, and oppression, which was held out by the gorgeous Eastern harlot,—which so many of the people, so many of the nobles of this land had drained to the very dregs. Do you think that no reckoning was to follow this lewd debauch? that no payment was to be demanded for this riot of public drunkenness and national prostitution? Here, you have it here before you! The principal of the grand election-manager must be indemnified; accordingly, the claims of Benfield and his crew must be put above all inquiry.

This guy, Sir, represents Mr. Paul Benfield. Everyone listening knows about the strong friendship and unwavering loyalty between him and the current minister. Those who attended the first session of this Parliament can best describe their feelings about the events that unfolded. It's unclear how much that honorable gentleman was involved in creating the bill popularly known as Mr. Pitt's India Bill, though it's not hard to guess. But the public witnessed with anger the way this measure was flaunted as his own, and the authority with which he introduced clause after clause to pad the already corrupt act. As soon as the clauses were presented, they were approved. There was no hesitation, no debate. The new minister accepted them not with approval, but with total obedience. The effectiveness of the reform can be judged by who was behind it. Paul Benfield's partner and agent was presented to the world as the legislator of Hindostan. But it was essential to prove the alliance between the schemers in India and the schemer in England with a deliberate show of this crucial link's power. Every trust, every honor, every distinction was showered upon him. He was made a Director of the India Company, became an alderman of London, and was set to become, if the ministry had its way (and I regret to say how close they were), the representative of the capital of this kingdom. To secure his commitments with no risks, he was brought in for a ministerial borough. He was certainly enthusiastic about the common goal. His ads reveal his intentions and the qualifications on which he relied. For your minister, this worn-out veteran agreed to step into the gritty arena of the London contest; and you all remember that, in the name of this noble cause, he took on a sort of public office or counting-house, where all the business of the last general election was handled. It was openly managed by Benfield's direct agent and attorney. It was run using Indian principles and for Indian interests. This was the golden cup of corruption—this was the chalice filled with the vices of plunder, lending, and oppression, offered by the luxurious Eastern seductress—which so many of the people, so many of the nobles in this land had drained to the very bottom. Do you believe there wouldn't be any consequences for this immoral excess? That no payment would be required for this public drunkenness and national disgrace? Here it is right in front of you! The head of the major election manager needs to be compensated; therefore, Benfield and his crew's claims must take precedence over any investigation.

For several years Benfield appeared as the chief proprietor, as well as the chief agent, director, and controller of this system of debt. The worthy chairman of the Company has stated the claims of this single gentleman on the Nabob of Arcot as amounting to five hundred thousand pound.[58] Possibly at the time of the chairman's state they might have been as high. Eight hundred thousand pound had been mentioned some time before;[59] and, according to the practice of shifting the names of creditors in these transactions, and reducing or raising the debt itself at pleasure, I think it not impossible that at one period the name of Benfield might have stood before those frightful figures. But my best information goes to fix his share no higher than four hundred thousand pounds. By the scheme of the present ministry for adding to the principal twelve per cent from the year 1777 to the year 1781, four hundred thousand pounds, that smallest of the sums ever mentioned for Mr. Benfield, will form a capital of 592,000l. at six per cent. Thus, besides the arrears of three years, amounting to 106,500l., (which, as fast as received, may be legally lent out at twelve per cent,) Benfield has received, by the ministerial grant before you, an annuity of 35,520l. a year, charged on the public revenues.

For several years, Benfield was the main owner, as well as the primary agent, director, and manager of this debt system. The respected chairman of the Company stated that this one person’s claims against the Nabob of Arcot amounted to five hundred thousand pounds.[58] At the time the chairman made this statement, they could have been even higher. Eight hundred thousand pounds had been mentioned earlier;[59] and given the way creditors' names can be shifted in these dealings, along with adjusting the debt itself at will, I think it’s possible that at one point, Benfield’s name may have appeared next to those alarming figures. However, my best information caps his claim at no more than four hundred thousand pounds. With the current administration’s plan to add twelve percent to the principal from 1777 to 1781, that four hundred thousand pounds, the smallest sum ever cited for Mr. Benfield, will grow into a total of 592,000l. at six percent. Additionally, aside from the arrears of three years amounting to 106,500l., which can be legally lent out at twelve percent as soon as they are received, Benfield has also been granted an annual payment of 35,520l. from the public revenues.

Our mirror of ministers of finance did not think this enough for the services of such a friend as Benfield. He found that Lord Macartney, in order to frighten the Court of Directors from the project of obliging the Nabob to give soucar security for his debt, assured them, that, if they should take that step, Benfield[60] would infallibly be the soucar, and would thereby become the entire master of the Carnatic. What Lord Macartney thought sufficient to deter the very agents and partakers with Benfield in his iniquities was the inducement to the two right honorable gentlemen to order this very soucar security to be given, and to recall Benfield to the city of Madras from the sort of decent exile into which he had been relegated by Lord Macartney. You must therefore consider Benfield as soucar security for 480,000l. a year, which, at twenty-four per cent, (supposing him contented with that profit,) will, with the interest of his old debt, produce an annual income of 149,520l. a year.

Our finance ministers didn’t think that was enough for someone as valuable as Benfield. He realized that Lord Macartney, in an effort to scare the Court of Directors away from pushing the Nabob to provide soucar security for his debt, assured them that if they went ahead with that plan, Benfield[60] would definitely become the soucar, giving him total control over the Carnatic. What Lord Macartney believed would be enough to dissuade even those involved with Benfield in his wrongdoing motivated the two honorable gentlemen to demand that this soucar security be issued and to recall Benfield to Madras from the sort of respectable exile Lord Macartney had put him in. You should therefore see Benfield as soucar security for 480,000l. a year, which, at twenty-four percent (assuming he’s happy with that return), along with the interest on his existing debt, will generate an annual income of 149,520l. a year.

Here is a specimen of the new and pure aristocracy created by the right honorable gentleman,[61] as the support of the crown and Constitution against the old, corrupt, refractory, natural interests of this kingdom; and this is the grand counterpoise against all odious coalitions of these interests. A single Benfield outweighs them all: a criminal, who long since ought to have fattened the region kites with his offal, is by his Majesty's ministers enthroned in the government of a great kingdom, and enfeoffed with an estate which in the comparison effaces the splendor of all the nobility of Europe. To bring a little more distinctly into view the true secret of this dark transaction, I beg you particularly to advert to the circumstances which I am going to place before you.

Here is a sample of the new and genuine aristocracy created by the esteemed gentleman,[61] serving as the backbone of the crown and Constitution against the old, corrupt, stubborn, natural interests of this kingdom; and this is the major counterbalance against any objectionable alliances of these interests. One individual, Benfield, outweighs them all: a criminal who should have long ago fed the scavenging kites with his remains is, by the ministers of His Majesty, placed in charge of a great kingdom and granted an estate that diminishes the grandeur of all the nobility in Europe. To clarify the true nature of this shady deal, I ask you to pay close attention to the details that I am about to present to you.

The general corps of creditors, as well as Mr. Benfield himself, not looking well into futurity, nor presaging the minister of this day, thought it not expedient for their common interest that such a name as his should stand at the head of their list. It was therefore agreed amongst them that Mr. Benfield should disappear, by making over his debt to Messrs. Taylor, Majendie, and Call, and should in return be secured by their bond.

The main group of creditors, along with Mr. Benfield himself, not looking ahead or predicting the minister of the day, decided it wasn't in their best interest for his name to top their list. They agreed that Mr. Benfield should remove himself by transferring his debt to Messrs. Taylor, Majendie, and Call, and in exchange, he would be secured by their bond.

The debt thus exonerated of so great a weight of its odium, and otherwise reduced from its alarming bulk, the agents thought they might venture to print a list of the creditors. This was done for the first time in the year 1783, during the Duke of Portland's administration. In this list the name of Benfield was not to be seen. To this strong negative testimony was added the further testimony of the Nabob of Arcot. That prince[62] (or rather Mr. Benfield for him) writes to the Court of Directors a letter[63] full of complaints and accusations against Lord Macartney, conveyed in such terms as were natural for one of Mr. Benfield's habits and education to employ. Amongst the rest he is made to complain of his Lordship's endeavoring to prevent an intercourse of politeness and sentiment between him and Mr. Benfield; and to aggravate the affront, he expressly declares Mr. Benfield's visits to be only on account of respect and of gratitude, as no pecuniary transaction subsisted between them.

The debt, now free from such a heavy burden of negativity and significantly reduced in size, led the agents to feel confident enough to publish a list of creditors. This was done for the first time in 1783, during the Duke of Portland's administration. In this list, the name Benfield was absent. This strong absence was further supported by the Nabob of Arcot. That prince[62] (or rather Mr. Benfield on his behalf) wrote to the Court of Directors in a letter[63] filled with complaints and accusations against Lord Macartney, expressed in language typical for someone with Mr. Benfield's background and education. Among other things, he complained that his Lordship was trying to prevent a polite and sentimental interaction between him and Mr. Benfield; to add insult to injury, he specifically stated that Mr. Benfield's visits were solely out of respect and gratitude, as there were no financial dealings between them.

Such, for a considerable space of time, was the outward form of the loan of 1777, in which Mr. Benfield had no sort of concern. At length intelligence arrived at Madras, that this debt, which had always been renounced by the Court of Directors, was rather like to become the subject of something more like a criminal inquiry than of any patronage or sanction from Parliament. Every ship brought accounts, one stronger than the other, of the prevalence of the determined enemies of the Indian system. The public revenues became an object desperate to the hopes of Mr. Benfield; he therefore resolved to fall upon his associates, and, in violation of that faith which subsists among those who have abandoned all other, commences a suit in the Mayor's Court against Taylor, Majendie, and Call, for the bond given to him, when he agreed to disappear for his own benefit as well as that of the common concern. The assignees of his debt, who little expected the springing of this mine, even from such an engineer as Mr. Benfield, after recovering their first alarm, thought it best to take ground on the real state of the transaction. They divulged the whole mystery, and were prepared to plead that they had never received from Mr. Benfield any other consideration for the bond than a transfer, in trust for himself, of his demand on the Nabob of Arcot. An universal indignation arose against the perfidy of Mr. Benfield's proceeding; the event of the suit was looked upon as so certain, that Benfield was compelled to retreat as precipitately as he had advanced boldly; he gave up his bond, and was reinstated in his original demand, to wait the fortune of other claimants. At that time, and at Madras, this hope was dull indeed; but at home another scene was preparing.

For a long time, that was the outward situation of the loan from 1777, in which Mr. Benfield had no involvement. Eventually, news reached Madras that this debt, which the Court of Directors had always disavowed, was likely to lead to something resembling a criminal investigation rather than any support or approval from Parliament. Every ship brought reports, each more alarming than the last, about the determined opponents of the Indian system. The public revenues became a desperate issue for Mr. Benfield; he decided to turn against his associates and, in breach of the trust that exists among those who have forsaken all else, filed a lawsuit in the Mayor's Court against Taylor, Majendie, and Call for the bond given to him when he agreed to step back for his own benefit and that of the common interest. The assignees of his debt, who never expected such a move from Mr. Benfield, quickly recovered from their shock and decided to base their defense on the actual circumstances of the transaction. They revealed the entire situation and were ready to argue that they had never received from Mr. Benfield any consideration for the bond other than a trust transfer of his claim against the Nabob of Arcot. A wave of outrage erupted against Mr. Benfield's treachery; the outcome of the lawsuit seemed so certain that he was forced to retreat just as quickly as he had moved forward; he gave up his bond and was restored to his original claim, awaiting the outcome with other claimants. At that time, in Madras, this hope seemed very bleak; but back home, another situation was developing.

It was long before any public account of this discovery at Madras had arrived in England, that the present minister and his Board of Control thought fit to determine on the debt of 1777. The recorded proceedings at this time knew nothing of any debt to Benfield. There was his own testimony, there was the testimony of the list, there was the testimony of the Nabob of Arcot, against it. Yet such was the ministers' feeling of the true secret of this transaction, that they thought proper, in the teeth of all these testimonies, to give him license to return to Madras. Here the ministers were under some embarrassment. Confounded between their resolution of rewarding the good services of Benfield's friends and associates in England, and the shame of sending that notorious incendiary to the court of the Nabob of Arcot, to renew his intrigues against the British government, at the time they authorize his return, they forbid him, under the severest penalties, from any conversation with the Nabob or his ministers: that is, they forbid his communication with the very person on account of his dealings with whom they permit his return to that city. To overtop this contradiction, there is not a word restraining him from the freest intercourse with the Nabob's second son, the real author of all that is done in the Nabob's name; who, in conjunction with this very Benfield, has acquired an absolute dominion over that unhappy man, is able to persuade him to put his signature to whatever paper they please, and often without any communication of the contents. This management was detailed to them at full length by Lord Macartney, and they cannot pretend ignorance of it.[64]

It took a while before any public report of this discovery in Madras made it to England, but the current minister and his Board of Control decided to address the debt from 1777. The records from that time had no mention of any debt to Benfield. There was his own testimony, the evidence from the list, and the testimony from the Nabob of Arcot against it. However, despite all of this information, the ministers felt they understood the true nature of this situation and chose to allow him to return to Madras. The ministers found themselves in a tricky position. Torn between their intention to reward Benfield's friends and associates in England and the embarrassment of sending that infamous troublemaker back to the court of the Nabob of Arcot to continue his scheming against the British government, they decided to allow his return while simultaneously forbidding him, under strict penalties, from having any conversations with the Nabob or his ministers. In other words, they prohibited him from talking to the very person whose dealings prompted his return to the city. To get around this contradiction, they didn’t place any restrictions on him having free interactions with the Nabob's second son, who is the real force behind everything done in the Nabob's name; this son, in partnership with Benfield, has gained complete control over the poor man, able to persuade him to sign whatever documents they want, often without him even knowing what they contain. Lord Macartney provided a detailed account of this situation to them, and they can no longer claim ignorance of it.[64]

I believe, after this exposure of facts, no man can entertain a doubt of the collusion of ministers with the corrupt interest of the delinquents in India. Whenever those in authority provide for the interest of any person, on the real, but concealed state of his affairs, without regard to his avowed, public, and ostensible pretences, it must be presumed that they are in confederacy with him, because they act for him on the same fraudulent principles on which he acts for himself. It is plain that the ministers were fully apprised of Benfield's real situation, which he had used means to conceal, whilst concealment answered his purposes. They were, or the person on whom they relied was, of the cabinet council of Benfield, in the very depth of all his mysteries. An honest magistrate compels men to abide by one story. An equitable judge would not hear of the claim of a man who had himself thought proper to renounce it. With such a judge his shuffling and prevarication would have damned his claims; such a judge never would have known, but in order to animadvert upon, proceedings of that character.

I believe that after looking at the facts, no one can doubt that the ministers were collaborating with the corrupt interests of wrongdoers in India. Whenever those in power act for someone based on the real, but hidden state of their affairs, ignoring their publicly stated intentions, it can be assumed that they are working together, because they operate on the same dishonest principles. It's clear that the ministers knew all about Benfield's actual situation, which he had worked to hide as long as it benefited him. They were either part of Benfield’s inner circle or relied on someone who was deeply involved in all his secrets. An honest magistrate ensures everyone sticks to the same story. A fair judge wouldn't consider the claim of someone who decided to give it up. In front of such a judge, their dishonesty and evasiveness would have ruined their claims; that judge would only have been aware of proceedings like that to criticize them.

I have thus laid before you, Mr. Speaker, I think with sufficient clearness, the connection of the ministers with Mr. Atkinson at the general election; I have laid open to you the connection of Atkinson with Benfield; I have shown Benfield's employment of his wealth in creating a Parliamentary interest to procure a ministerial protection; I have set before your eyes his large concern in the debt, his practices to hide that concern from the public eye, and the liberal protection which he has received from the minister. If this chain of circumstances does not lead you necessarily to conclude that the minister has paid to the avarice of Benfield the services done by Benfield's connections to his ambition, I do not know anything short of the confession of the party that can persuade you of his guilt. Clandestine and collusive practice can only be traced by combination and comparison of circumstances. To reject such combination and comparison is to reject the only means of detecting fraud; it is, indeed, to give it a patent and free license to cheat with impunity.

I have presented to you, Mr. Speaker, I believe quite clearly, the relationship between the ministers and Mr. Atkinson during the general election; I have revealed Atkinson's ties to Benfield; I have shown how Benfield used his wealth to create a Parliamentary interest in order to secure ministerial protection; I have laid out his significant involvement in the debt, his efforts to conceal that involvement from the public eye, and the generous protection he has received from the minister. If this series of events doesn't lead you to conclude that the minister has rewarded Benfield for the services his connections provided to his ambitions, I really don’t know what could convince you of his guilt other than a confession from the party involved. Secret and collusive practices can only be identified through the combination and comparison of circumstances. Ignoring such combinations and comparisons is to disregard the only means of uncovering fraud; it essentially gives it a license to cheat without consequence.

I confine myself to the connection of ministers, mediately or immediately, with only two persons concerned in this debt. How many others, who support their power and greatness within and without doors, are concerned originally, or by transfers of these debts, must be left to general opinion. I refer to the reports of the Select Committee for the proceedings of some of the agents in these affairs, and their attempts, at least, to furnish ministers with the means of buying General Courts, and even whole Parliaments, in the gross.[65]

I'm focusing on the involvement of ministers, either directly or indirectly, with just two individuals related to this debt. How many others, who bolster their power and influence both inside and outside, are involved originally or through transfers of these debts is something for public opinion to decide. I point to the reports from the Select Committee regarding the actions of some of the agents involved in these matters, as well as their efforts, at the very least, to provide ministers with ways to buy General Courts and even entire Parliaments outright.[65]

I know that the ministers will think it little less than acquittal, that they are not charged with having taken to themselves some part of the money of which they have made so liberal a donation to their partisans, though the charge may be indisputably fixed upon the corruption of their politics. For my part, I follow their crimes to that point to which legal presumptions and natural indications lead me, without considering what species of evil motive tends most to aggravate or to extenuate the guilt of their conduct. But if I am to speak my private sentiments, I think that in a thousand cases for one it would be far less mischievous to the public, and full as little dishonorable to themselves, to be polluted with direct bribery, than thus to become a standing auxiliary to the oppression, usury, and peculation of multitudes, in order to obtain a corrupt support to their power. It is by bribing, not so often by being bribed, that wicked politicians bring rum on mankind. Avarice is a rival to the pursuits of many. It finds a multitude of checks, and many opposers, in every walk of life. But the objects of ambition are for the few; and every person who aims at indirect profit, and therefore wants other protection than innocence and law, instead of its rival, becomes its instrument. There is a natural allegiance and fealty due to this domineering, paramount evil, from all the vassal vices, which acknowledge its superiority, and readily militate under its banners; and it is under that discipline alone that avarice is able to spread to any considerable extent, or to render itself a general, public mischief. It is therefore no apology for ministers, that they have not been bought by the East India delinquents, but that they have only formed an alliance with them for screening each other from justice, according to the exigence of their several necessities. That they have done so is evident; and the junction of the power of office in England with the abuse of authority in the East has not only prevented even the appearance of redress to the grievances of India, but I wish it may not be found to have dulled, if not extinguished, the honor, the candor, the generosity, the good-nature, which used formerly to characterize the people of England. I confess, I wish that some more feeling than I have yet observed for the sufferings of our fellow-creatures and fellow-subjects in that oppressed part of the world had manifested itself in any one quarter of the kingdom, or in any one large description of men.

I know the ministers will see it as almost an exoneration that they aren't accused of keeping any portion of the money they so generously donated to their supporters, even if the accusation of corruption in their politics is clearly established. Personally, I trace their crimes to the point that legal assumptions and natural indications lead me, without worrying about what type of evil motive might worsen or lessen the guilt of their actions. But if I'm to share my personal opinion, I believe that in a thousand instances, it would be far less harmful to the public, and just as little dishonorable to themselves, to be directly bribed than to become a constant supporter of the oppression, exploitation, and theft affecting many, just to secure a corrupt backing for their power. It's through bribery, rather than being bribed, that corrupt politicians wreak havoc on humanity. Greed competes with many pursuits. It faces numerous obstacles and opposition in every aspect of life. But the goals of ambition are scarce, and anyone seeking indirect gain, thus needing protection beyond innocence and the law, becomes an agent of greed instead of its rival. There is a natural loyalty owed to this dominating, overarching evil from all the subordinate vices that recognize its superiority and willingly fight under its flag; and it's under that discipline alone that greed can spread to any significant extent or become a widespread, public menace. Therefore, it is not an excuse for ministers that they haven't been bought by the East India wrongdoers, but that they’ve merely formed an alliance with them to shield one another from justice, based on their respective needs. It's clear that they have done so, and the combination of political power in England with the abuse of authority in the East has not only stifled even the appearance of addressing India's grievances, but I hope it hasn’t dulled, if not completely extinguished, the honor, integrity, generosity, and good-nature that used to define the people of England. I honestly wish I could see more compassion for the suffering of our fellow humans and fellow subjects in that oppressed region demonstrating itself from any part of the kingdom or from any large group of people.

That these oppressions exist is a fact no more denied than it is resented as it ought to be. Much evil has been done in India under the British authority. What has been done to redress it? We are no longer surprised at anything. We are above the unlearned and vulgar passion of admiration. But it will astonish posterity, when they read our opinions in our actions, that, after years of inquiry, we have found out that the sole grievance of India consisted in this, that the servants of the Company there had not profited enough of their opportunities, nor drained it sufficiently of its treasures,—when they shall hear that the very first and only important act of a commission specially named by act of Parliament is, to charge upon an undone country, in favor of a handful of men in the humblest ranks of the public service, the enormous sum of perhaps four millions of sterling money.

That these oppressions exist is a fact that can’t be denied, and it’s rightly resented. A lot of harm has been done in India under British rule. What has been done to fix it? We aren’t surprised by anything anymore. We’ve moved past the shallow and crude passion of admiration. But it will shock future generations, when they read our opinions and actions, that after years of investigation, we concluded that India’s only problem was that the Company’s representatives didn’t take enough advantage of their opportunities, nor extracted enough of its wealth. They will be amazed to hear that the very first and only significant act of a commission specifically named by an act of Parliament is to charge to an impoverished country, for the benefit of a small group of the lowest-ranking public servants, amounting to perhaps four million pounds.

It is difficult for the most wise and upright government to correct the abuses of remote, delegated power, productive of unmeasured wealth, and protected by the boldness and strength of the same ill-got riches. These abuses, full of their own wild native vigor, will grow and flourish under mere neglect. But where the supreme authority, not content with winking at the rapacity of its inferior instruments, is so shameless and corrupt as openly to give bounties and premiums for disobedience to its laws,—when it will not trust to the activity of avarice in the pursuit of its own gains,—when it secures public robbery by all the careful jealousy and attention with which it ought to protect property from such violence,—the commonwealth then is become totally perverted from its purposes; neither God nor man will long endure it; nor will it long endure itself. In that case, there is an unnatural infection, a pestilential taint, fermenting in the constitution of society, which fever and convulsions of some kind or other must throw off, or in which the vital powers, worsted in an unequal struggle, are pushed back upon themselves, and, by a reversal of their whole functions, fester to gangrene, to death,—and instead of what was but just now the delight and boast of the creation, there will be cast out in the face of the sun a bloated, putrid, noisome carcass, full of stench and poison, an offence, a horror, a lesson to the world.

It's hard for even the wisest and most just government to fix the problems caused by distant, delegated power, which generates immense wealth and is shielded by the audacity and strength of that ill-gotten money. These abuses thrive and grow stronger under simple neglect. However, when the supreme authority, instead of merely ignoring the greed of its lower officials, is so brazen and corrupt that it actually offers rewards for disobeying its laws—when it can't even rely on the natural greed for pursuing its own interests—when it actively supports public theft with the same careful scrutiny it should use to protect property from such violence—the commonwealth ends up completely perverted from its original purpose; neither God nor man will tolerate it for long, nor will it sustain itself. In that situation, there's an unnatural infection, a destructive sickness, festering within society's structure, which must result in some form of turmoil or else the vital forces, overwhelmed in a fight they can't win, turn against themselves and, through a reversal of their functions, rot away, leading to decay and death. Instead of what was just a moment ago the pride and joy of creation, there will be a swollen, rotten, repulsive carcass, emitting stench and poison, a disgrace, a horror, a warning to the world.

In my opinion, we ought not to wait for the fruitless instruction of calamity to inquire into the abuses which bring upon us ruin in the worst of its forms, in the loss of our fame and virtue. But the right honorable gentleman[66] says, in answer to all the powerful arguments of my honorable friend, "that this inquiry is of a delicate nature, and that the state will suffer detriment by the exposure of this transaction." But it is exposed; it is perfectly known in every member, in every particle, and in every way, except that which may lead to a remedy. He knows that the papers of correspondence are printed, and that they are in every hand.

In my opinion, we shouldn't wait for the pointless lessons of disaster to look into the abuses that lead to our downfall in the most severe way, which is the loss of our reputation and integrity. However, the right honorable gentleman[66] argues, in response to all the strong points made by my honorable friend, "that this investigation is sensitive, and that the state will be harmed by revealing this situation." But it's already out in the open; everyone knows about it in every detail, and in every way, except for the one that could lead to a solution. He knows that the correspondence papers are published and that they are in everyone's hands.

He and delicacy are a rare and a singular coalition. He thinks that to divulge our Indian politics may be highly dangerous. He! the mover, the chairman, the reporter of the Committee of Secrecy! he, that brought forth in the utmost detail, in several vast, printed folios, the most recondite parts of the politics, the military, the revenues of the British empire in India! With six great chopping bastards,[67] each as lusty as an infant Hercules, this delicate creature blushes at the sight of his new bridegroom, assumes a virgin delicacy; or, to use a more fit, as well as a more poetic comparison, the person so squeamish, so timid, so trembling lest the winds of heaven should visit too roughly, is expanded to broad sunshine, exposed like the sow of imperial augury, lying in the mud with all the prodigies of her fertility about her, as evidence of her delicate amours,—

He and delicacy make a rare and unique pair. He believes that revealing our Indian politics could be very risky. He! The mover, the chairman, the reporter of the Committee of Secrecy! He, who presented in great detail, in several large printed volumes, the most intricate aspects of the politics, the military, the finances of the British Empire in India! With six big, strong guys, each as robust as a baby Hercules, this delicate person turns red at the sight of his new husband, taking on a virginal delicacy; or, to put it in a more suitable and poetic way, the individual who is so sensitive, so nervous, so afraid that the winds of heaven might blow too harshly, is suddenly opened up to bright sunshine, exposed like the sow of imperial prophecy, lying in the mud surrounded by all the signs of her fertility, as proof of her delicate loves,—

Triginta capitum fœtus enixa jacebat,
Alba, just covering, white around the breasts of the child.

Whilst discovery of the misgovernment of others led to his own power, it was wise to inquire, it was safe to publish: there was then no delicacy; there was then no danger. But when his object is obtained, and in his imitation he has outdone the crimes that he had reprobated in volumes of reports and in sheets of bills of pains and penalties, then concealment becomes prudence, and it concerns the safety of the state that we should not know, in a mode of Parliamentary cognizance, what all the world knows but too well, that is, in what manner he chooses to dispose of the public revenues to the creatures of his politics.

While uncovering the mismanagement of others brought him power, it was smart to ask questions; it was safe to speak out then—there were no sensitivities and no threats. But after achieving his goals, and in trying to copy others, he committed worse offenses than those he had criticized in countless reports and endless bills of penalties. Then, secrecy became a matter of caution, and it was in the state's interest that we remain unaware, in a way recognized by Parliament, of what everyone else knows all too well: how he chooses to handle the public funds for his political allies.

The debate has been long, and as much so on my part, at least, as on the part of those who have spoken before me. But long as it is, the more material half of the subject has hardly been touched on: that is, the corrupt and destructive system to which this debt has been rendered subservient, and which seems to be pursued with at least as much vigor and regularity as ever. If I considered your ease or my own, rather than the weight and importance of this question, I ought to make some apology to you, perhaps some apology to myself, for having detained your attention so long. I know on what ground I tread. This subject, at one time taken up with so much fervor and zeal, is no longer a favorite in this House. The House itself has undergone a great and signal revolution. To some the subject is strange and uncouth; to several, harsh and distasteful; to the relics of the last Parliament it is a matter of fear and apprehension. It is natural for those who have seen their friends sink in the tornado which raged during the late shift of the monsoon, and have hardly escaped on the planks of the general wreck, it is but too natural for them, as soon as they make the rocks and quicksands of their former disasters, to put about their new-built barks, and, as much as possible, to keep aloof from this perilous lee shore.

The debate has been lengthy, and I've contributed just as much as those who spoke before me. However, despite its length, we’ve barely scratched the surface of the more significant part of the topic: the corrupt and destructive system that this debt has been subjected to, which seems to be pursued with as much energy and consistency as ever. If I were focused on your convenience or my own, rather than the seriousness and significance of this issue, I should perhaps apologize to you and to myself for keeping your attention for so long. I am aware of the topic I’m addressing. This subject, once approached with great passion and drive, is no longer popular in this House. The House itself has experienced a significant transformation. For some, the topic is unfamiliar and uncomfortable; for others, it feels harsh and unpleasant; to those remnants of the last Parliament, it stirs fear and anxiety. It’s natural for those who have watched their friends get swept away by the storm that raged during the recent political upheaval, and who barely survived on the remains of the overall disaster, to want to steer their newly constructed vessels as far away as possible from the dangerous rocks and quicksands of their past misfortunes.

But let us do what we please to put India from our thoughts, we can do nothing to separate it from our public interest and our national reputation. Our attempts to banish this importunate duty will only make it return upon us again and again, and every time in a shape more unpleasant than the former. A government has been fabricated for that great province; the right honorable gentleman says that therefore you ought not to examine into its conduct. Heavens! what an argument is this! We are not to examine into the conduct of the Direction, because it is an old government; we are not to examine into this Board of Control, because it is a new one. Then we are only to examine into the conduct of those who have no conduct to account for. Unfortunately, the basis of this new government has been laid on old, condemned delinquents, and its superstructure is raised out of prosecutors turned into protectors. The event has been such as might be expected. But if it had been otherwise constituted, had it been constituted even as I wished, and as the mover of this question had planned, the better part of the proposed establishment was in the publicity of its proceedings, in its perpetual responsibility to Parliament. Without this check, what is our government at home, even awed, as every European government is, by an audience formed of the other states of Europe, by the applause or condemnation of the discerning and critical company before which it acts? But if the scene on the other side of the globe, which tempts, invites, almost compels, to tyranny and rapine, be not inspected with the eye of a severe and unremitting vigilance, shame and destruction must ensue. For one, the worst event of this day, though it may deject, shall not break or subdue me. The call upon us is authoritative. Let who will shrink back, I shall be found at my post. Baffled, discountenanced, subdued, discredited, as the cause of justice and humanity is, it will be only the dearer to me. Whoever, therefore, shall at any time bring before you anything towards the relief of our distressed fellow-citizens in India, and towards a subversion of the present most corrupt and oppressive system for its government, in me shall find a weak, I am afraid, but a steady, earnest, and faithful assistant.

But no matter how much we try to avoid thinking about India, we can't detach it from our public interest and national reputation. Trying to ignore this uncomfortable obligation will only make it come back to haunt us, and each time it will be in a more unpleasant way than before. A government has been set up for that vast region; the honorable gentleman suggests that we shouldn't question its actions. What an absurd argument! We aren’t supposed to scrutinize the actions of the old administration because it’s established, nor look into this new Board of Control because it's fresh. So, we should only question those who have nothing to account for. Unfortunately, the foundation of this new government is made from old, condemned wrongdoers, and its structure is built of prosecutors turned into protectors. The outcome has been as one would expect. But if it had been set up differently, even if it had been set up the way I would have preferred, and how the person introducing this issue had envisioned, the key strength of the proposed system lies in the transparency of its actions and its ongoing accountability to Parliament. Without this oversight, what is our government at home, even if it is intimidated, as every European government is, by an audience made up of the other European states, reacting to the praise or condemnation of the discerning, critical crowd it faces? If we don’t keep a sharp, relentless watch on the situation on the other side of the world, which lures and almost forces us into tyranny and plunder, we will face shame and ruin. For me, the worst outcome of today, while it may be discouraging, will not break or overpower me. The call to action is clear. No matter who steps back, I will be present at my post. Frustrated, disheartened, beaten down, and discredited as the cause of justice and humanity may be, it will only be more precious to me. Therefore, anyone who brings before you any effort towards helping our distressed fellow citizens in India and towards overturning the current corrupt and oppressive governance system will find in me a weak, I'm afraid, but steadfast, earnest, and loyal supporter.

FOOTNOTES:

[1] Right Honorable Henry Dundas.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hon. Henry Dundas.

[2] Sir Thomas Rumbold, late Governor of Madras.

[2] Sir Thomas Rumbold, former Governor of Madras.

[3] Appendix, No. 1.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Appendix, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[4] The whole of the net Irish hereditary revenue is, on a medium of the last seven years, about 330,000l. yearly. The revenues of all denominations fall short more than 150,000l. yearly of the charges. On the present produce, if Mr. Pitt's scheme was to take place, he might gain from seven to ten thousand pounds a year.

[4] The total Irish hereditary revenue is, on average over the last seven years, about £330,000 a year. The revenues of all kinds fall short by more than £150,000 a year of the expenses. Based on the current figures, if Mr. Pitt's plan were to be implemented, he could earn between £7,000 and £10,000 a year.

[5] Mr. Smith's Examination before the Select Committee. Appendix, No. 2.

[5] Mr. Smith's Hearing before the Select Committee. Appendix, No. 2.

[6] Appendix, No. 2.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Appendix, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[7] Fourth Report, Mr. Dundas's Committee, p. 4.

[7] Fourth Report, Mr. Dundas's Committee, p. 4.

[8] A witness examined before the Committee of Secrecy says that eighteen per cent was the usual interest, but he had heard that more had been given. The above is the account which Mr. B. received.

[8] A witness questioned by the Committee of Secrecy states that the typical interest rate was eighteen percent, but he had heard that higher rates had been offered. This is the report that Mr. B. received.

[9] Mr. Dundas.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Mr. Dundas.

[10] For the threats of the creditors, and total subversion of the authority of the Company in favor of the Nabob's power and the increase thereby of his evil dispositions, and the great derangement of all public concerns, see Select Committee Fort St. George's letters, 21st November, 1769, and January 31st, 1770; September 11, 1772; and Governor Bourchier's letters to the Nabob of Arcot, 21st November, 1769, and December 9th, 1769.

[10] For the threats from creditors, the complete undermining of the Company's authority in favor of the Nabob's power, which in turn fueled his malicious intentions, and the significant disruption of all public affairs, refer to the Select Committee Fort St. George's letters dated November 21, 1769, and January 31, 1770; September 11, 1772; and Governor Bourchier's letters to the Nabob of Arcot from November 21, 1769, and December 9, 1769.

[11] "He [the Nabob] is in a great degree the cause of our present inability, by diverting the revenues of the Carnatic through private channels." "Even this peshcush [the Tanjore tribute], circumstanced as he and we are, he has assigned over to others, who now set themselves in opposition to the Company."—Consultations, October 11, 1769, on the 12th communicated to the Nabob.

[11] "He [the Nabob] is largely responsible for our current inability, as he is redirecting the revenues of the Carnatic through private channels." "Even this peshcush [the Tanjore tribute], given his situation and ours, he has handed over to others, who are now acting against the Company."—Consultations, October 11, 1769, on the 12th communicated to the Nabob.

[12] Nabob's letter to Governor Palk. Papers published by the Directors in 1775; and papers printed by the same authority, 1781.

[12] The Nabob's letter to Governor Palk. Documents released by the Directors in 1775; and documents printed by the same authority in 1781.

[13] See papers printed by order of a General Court in 1780, pp. 222 and 224; as also Nabob's letter to Governor Dupré, 19th July, 1771: "I have taken up loans by which I have suffered a loss of upwards of a crore of pagodas [four millions sterling] by interest on an heavy interest." Letter 15th January, 1772: "Notwithstanding I have taken much trouble, and have made many payments to my creditors, yet the load of my debt, which became so great by interest and compound interest, is not cleared."

[13] See papers printed by order of a General Court in 1780, pp. 222 and 224; as well as the Nabob's letter to Governor Dupré, July 19, 1771: "I've taken out loans that have caused me to lose over a crore of pagodas [four million pounds] due to high interest." Letter January 15, 1772: "Even though I've worked hard and made many payments to my creditors, the burden of my debt, which got so large because of interest and compound interest, is still not resolved."

[14] The Nabob of Arcot.

The Nabob of Arcot.

[15] Appendix, No. 3.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Appendix, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[16] See Mr. Dundas's 1st, 2d, and 3d Reports.

[16] See Mr. Dundas's 1st, 2nd, and 3rd Reports.

[17] See further Consultations, 3d February, 1778.

[17] See further Consultations, February 3, 1778.

[18] Mr. Dundas's 1st Report, pp. 26, 29, and Appendix, No. 2, 10, 18, for the mutinous state and desertion of the Nabob's troops for want of pay. See also Report IV. of the same committee.

[18] Mr. Dundas's 1st Report, pp. 26, 29, and Appendix, No. 2, 10, 18, about the rebellious behavior and desertion of the Nabob's troops due to lack of pay. Also, refer to Report IV. from the same committee.

[19] Memorial from the creditors to the Governor and Council, 22d January, 1770.

[19] Memorial from the creditors to the Governor and Council, 22nd January 1770.

[20] In the year 1778, Mr. James Call, one of the proprietors of this specific debt, was actually mayor. (Appendix to 2d Report of Mr. Dundas's committee, No. 65.) The only proof which appeared on the inquiry instituted in the General Court of 1781 was an affidavit of the lenders themselves, deposing (what nobody ever denied) that they had engaged and agreed to pay—not that they had paid—the sum of 160,000l. This was two years after the transaction; and the affidavit is made before George Proctor, mayor, an attorney for certain of the old creditors.—Proceedings of the President and Council of Fort St. George, 22d February, 1779.

[20] In 1778, Mr. James Call, one of the owners of this particular debt, was actually the mayor. (Appendix to 2d Report of Mr. Dundas's committee, No. 65.) The only evidence that came up during the investigation held in the General Court of 1781 was a sworn statement from the lenders themselves, stating (which no one ever disputed) that they had engaged and agreed to pay—not that they had paid—the amount of 160,000 l. This was two years after the deal, and the affidavit was sworn before George Proctor, the mayor, who was an attorney for some of the old creditors.—Proceedings of the President and Council of Fort St. George, 22d February, 1779.

[21] Right Honorable Henry Dundas.

Right Hon. Henry Dundas.

[22] Appendix to the 4th Report of Mr. Dundas's committee, No 15.

[22] Appendix to the 4th Report of Mr. Dundas's committee, No 15.

[23] "No sense of the common danger, in case of a war, can prevail on him [the Nabob of Arcot] to furnish the Company with what is absolutely necessary to assemble an army, though it is beyond a doubt that money to a large amount is now hoarded up in his coffers at Chepauk; and tunkaws are granted to individuals, upon some of his most valuable countries, for payment of part of those debts which he has contracted, and which certainly will not bear inspection, as neither debtor nor creditors have ever had the confidence to submit the accounts to our examination, though they expressed a wish to consolidate the debts under the auspices of this government, agreeably to a plan they had formed."—Madras Consultations, 20th July, 1778. Mr. Dundas's Appendix to 2nd Report, 143. See also last Appendix to ditto Report, No. 376, B.

[23] "The Nabob of Arcot shows no awareness of the common threat posed by a potential war, which prevents him from providing the Company with what is essential to assemble an army. It's clear that he is currently hoarding a significant amount of money in his coffers at Chepauk, while loans are issued to specific individuals against some of his most valuable territories to pay off part of the debts he has incurred. These debts definitely wouldn’t stand up to scrutiny, as neither the debtors nor the creditors have ever been willing to let us review the accounts, even though they expressed a desire to consolidate the debts under the guidance of this government, according to a plan they devised."—Madras Consultations, 20th July, 1778. Mr. Dundas's Appendix to 2nd Report, 143. See also last Appendix to ditto Report, No. 376, B.

[24] Transcriber's note: Footnote missing in original text.

[24] Transcriber's note: Footnote missing in original text.

[25] Lord Pigot

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Lord Pigot

[26] In Sir Thomas Rumbold's letter to the Court of Directors, March 15th, 1778, he represents it as higher, in the following manner:—"How shall I paint to you my astonishment, on my arrival here, when I was informed, that, independent of this four lacs of pagodas [the Cavalry Loan], independent of the Nabob's debt to his old creditors, and the money due to the Company, he had contracted a debt to the enormous amount of sixty-three lacs of pagodas [2,520,000l.]. I mention this circumstance to you with horror; for the creditors being in general servants of the Company renders my task, on the part of the Company, difficult and invidious." "I have freed the sanction of this government from so corrupt a transaction. It is in my mind the most venal of all proceedings to give the Company's protection to debts that cannot bear the light; and though it appears exceedingly alarming, that a country on which you are to depend for resources should be so involved as to be nearly three years' revenue in debt,—in a country, too, where one year's revenue can never be called secure, by men who know anything of the politics of this part of India." "I think it proper to mention to you, that, although the Nabob reports his private debt to amount to upwards of sixty lacs, yet I understand that it is not quite so much." Afterwards Sir Thomas Rumbold recommended this debt to the favorable attention of the Company, but without any sufficient reason for his change of disposition. However, he went no further.

[26] In Sir Thomas Rumbold's letter to the Court of Directors, March 15, 1778, he describes it like this: “How can I express my shock upon arriving here, when I learned that, aside from this four lacs of pagodas [the Cavalry Loan], independent of the Nabob's debt to his old creditors, and the money owed to the Company, he had taken on a debt of a staggering sixty-three lacs of pagodas [2,520,000l.]. I mention this to you with horror; because the creditors are mostly servants of the Company, making my responsibility on behalf of the Company difficult and thankless.” "I have kept this government from endorsing such a corrupt deal. To me, it’s the most disgraceful act to give the Company's protection to debts that cannot stand scrutiny; and while it seems extremely alarming that a region you depend on for resources should be nearly three years’ revenue in debt—in a place where one year's revenue is inherently insecure for anyone familiar with the politics of this part of India." "I should point out that although the Nabob claims his personal debt is over sixty lacs, I understand it is not quite that high.” Later, Sir Thomas Rumbold urged the Company to consider this debt favorably, yet he offered no valid explanation for his change of heart. However, he did not go any further.

[27] Nabob's proposals, November 25th, 1778; and memorial of the creditors, March 1st, 1779.

[27] Nabob's proposals, November 25, 1778; and memorial from the creditors, March 1, 1779.

[28] Nabob's proposals to his new consolidated creditors, November 25th, 1778.

[28] Nabob's proposals to his new consolidated creditors, November 25, 1778.

[29] Paper signed by the Nabob, 6th January, 1780.

[29] Document signed by the Nabob, January 6, 1780.

[30] Kistbundi to July 31, 1780.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Kistbundi to July 31, 1780.

[31] Governor's letter to the Nabob, 25th July, 1779.

[31] Governor's letter to the Nabob, July 25, 1779.

[32] Report of the Select Committee, Madras Consultations, January 7, 1771. See also papers published by the order of the Court of Directors in 1776; and Lord Macartney's correspondence with Mr. Hastings and the Nabob of Arcot. See also Mr. Dundas's Appendix, No 376, B. Nabob's propositions through Mr. Sulivan and Assam Khân, Art. 6, and indeed the whole.

[32] Report of the Select Committee, Madras Consultations, January 7, 1771. Also, refer to the documents published by the Court of Directors in 1776, along with Lord Macartney's correspondence with Mr. Hastings and the Nabob of Arcot. Additionally, check Mr. Dundas's Appendix, No 376, B. Nabob's proposals through Mr. Sulivan and Assam Khân, Art. 6, and really, the entire document.

[33] "The principal object of the expedition is, to get money from Tanjore to pay the Nabob's debt: if a surplus, to be applied in discharge of the Nabob's debts to his private creditors." (Consultations, March 20, 1771; and for further lights, Consultations, 12th June, 1771.) "We are alarmed lest this debt to individuals should have been the real motive for the aggrandizement of Mahomed Ali [the Nabob of Arcot], and that we are plunged into a war to put him in possession of the Mysore revenues for the discharge of the debt."—Letter from the Directors, March 17, 1769.

[33] "The main goal of the expedition is to get money from Tanjore to pay off the Nabob's debt; if there’s any leftover, it will be used to pay off the Nabob's debts to his private creditors." (Consultations, March 20, 1771; and for more information, Consultations, June 12, 1771.) "We are worried that this debt to individuals might have been the real reason for Mahomed Ali [the Nabob of Arcot] to gain power, and that we are drawn into a war to help him take the Mysore revenues to pay off the debt."—Letter from the Directors, March 17, 1769.

[34] Letter from the Nabob, May 1st, 1768; and ditto, 24th April, 1770, 1st October; ditto, 16th September, 1772, 16th March, 1773.

[34] Letter from the Nabob, May 1, 1768; and the same, April 24, 1770, October 1; the same, September 16, 1772, March 16, 1773.

[35] Letter from the Presidency at Madras to the Court of Directors, 27th June, 1769.

[35] Letter from the Presidency in Madras to the Court of Directors, June 27, 1769.

[36] Mr. Dundas's committee. Report L, Appendix, No. 29.

[36] Mr. Dundas's committee. Report L, Appendix, No. 29.

[37] Appendix, No. 4. Report of the Committee of Assigned Revenue.

[37] Appendix, No. 4. Report of the Committee of Assigned Revenue.

[38] Mr. Barnard's map of the Jaghire

[38] Mr. Barnard's map of the Jaghire

[39] See Report IV., Mr. Dundas's committee, p. 46.

[39] See Report IV., Mr. Dundas's committee, p. 46.

[40] Interest is rated in India by the month.

[40] In India, interest is calculated on a monthly basis.

[41] Mr. Dundas's committee. Rep. I. p. 9, and ditto, Rep. IV. 69, where the revenue of 1777 stated only at 22 lacs,—30 lacs stated as the revenue, "supposing the Carnatic to be properly managed."

[41] Mr. Dundas's committee. Rep. I. p. 9, and also in Rep. IV. 69, where the revenue for 1777 is reported as only 22 lacs,—30 lacs reported as the revenue, "assuming the Carnatic is well managed."

[42] See Appendix, No. 4. statement in the Report of the Committee of Assigned Revenue.

[42] See Appendix, No. 4. statement in the Report of the Committee of Assigned Revenue.

[43] The province of Tinnevelly.

The Tinnevelly province.

[44] Appendix, No. 5.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Appendix, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[45] See extract of their letter in the Appendix, No. 9.

[45] See a section of their letter in the Appendix, No. 9.

[46] "It is certain that the incursion of a few of Hyder's horse into the Jaghire, in 1767, cost the Company upwards of pagodas 27,000, in allowances for damages."—Consultations, February 11th, 1771.

[46] "It's clear that the invasion by a few of Hyder's cavalry into the Jaghire in 1767 cost the Company more than 27,000 pagodas, in damage allowances."—Consultations, February 11th, 1771.

[47] Proceeding at Madras, 11th February, 1769, and throughout the correspondence on this subject; particularly Consultations, October 4th, 1769, and the creditors' memorial, 20th January, 1770.

[47] This took place in Madras on February 11, 1769, and throughout the communication on this topic; especially in the Consultations on October 4, 1769, and the creditors' memorial dated January 20, 1770.

[48] Appendix, No. 7.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Appendix, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[49] For some part of these usurious transactions, see Consultation, 28th January, 1781; and for the Nabob's excusing his oppressions on account of these debts, Consultation, 26th November, 1770. "Still I undertook, first, the payment of the money belonging to the Company, who are my kind friends, and by borrowing, and mortgaging my jewels, &c., by taking from every one of my servants, in proportion to their circumstances, by fresh severities also on my country, notwithstanding its distressed state, as you know."—The Board's remark is as follows: after controverting some of the facts, they say, "That his countries are oppressed is most certain, but not from real necessity; his debts, indeed, have afforded him a constant pretence for using severities and cruel oppressions."

[49] For some details about these usurious transactions, see Consultation, January 28, 1781; and regarding the Nabob justifying his oppressions due to these debts, see Consultation, November 26, 1770. "Still, I took on the responsibility of paying the money owed to the Company, who are my generous friends, and by borrowing and mortgaging my jewels, etc., by taking from each of my servants, depending on their circumstances, and imposing new hardships on my country, despite its distressed condition, as you know."—The Board's response is as follows: after disputing some of the facts, they state, "That his countries are indeed oppressed is absolutely true, but not out of genuine necessity; his debts have certainly given him a constant excuse to impose severities and cruel oppressions."

[50] See Consultation, 28th January, 1781, where it is asserted, and not denied, that the Nabob's farmers of revenue seldom continue for three months together. From this the state of the country may be easily judged of.

[50] See Consultation, January 28, 1781, where it is stated, and not contested, that the Nabob's tax collectors rarely last more than three months at a time. This provides a clear picture of the country's condition.

[51] In Mr. Fox's speech.

In Mr. Fox's speech.

[52] The amended letter, Appendix, No. 9.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ The updated letter, Appendix, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[53] Appendix, No. 8.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Appendix, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[54] Mr. Petrie's evidence before the Select Committee, Appendix, No. 7.

[54] Mr. Petrie's testimony before the Select Committee, Appendix, No. 7.

[55] Appendix, No. 7.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Appendix, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[56] Mr. Dundas.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Mr. Dundas.

[57] See Report IV., Committee of Secrecy, pp. 73 and 74; and Appendix, in sundry places.

[57] See Report IV., Committee of Secrecy, pp. 73 and 74; and Appendix, in various places.

[58] Mr. Smith's protest.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Mr. Smith's protest.

[59] Madras correspondence on this subject.

[59] Correspondence from Madras about this topic.

[60] Appendix, No 6.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Appendix, No. 6.

[61] Right Honorable William Pitt.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Right Hon. William Pitt.

[62] Appendix, No. 10.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Appendix, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[63] Dated 13th October. For further illustration of the style in which these letters were written, and the principles on which they proceed, see letters from the Nabob to the Court of Directors, dated August 16th and September 7th, 1783, delivered by Mr. James Macpherson, minister to the Nabob, January 14, 1784. Appendix, No. 10.

[63] Dated October 13th. To better understand the way these letters were written and the principles behind them, check out the letters from the Nabob to the Court of Directors, dated August 16th and September 7th, 1783, delivered by Mr. James Macpherson, the minister to the Nabob, on January 14, 1784. Appendix, No. 10.

[64] Appendix, No. 6.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Appendix, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[65] Second Report of Select (General Smith's) Committee.

[65] Second Report of Select (General Smith's) Committee.

[66] Mr. Dundas.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Mr. Dundas.

[67] Six Reports of the Committee of Secrecy.

[67] Six Reports by the Committee of Secrecy.


APPENDIX.


No. 1.

CLAUSES OF MR PITT'S BILL.

Referred to from page __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__.

Appointing Commissioners to inquire into the Fees, Gratuities, Perquisites, Emoluments, which are, or have been lately, received in the several Public Offices therein mentioned; to examine into any Abuses which may exist in the same, &c.

Hiring Commissioners to look into the fees, tips, perks, and pay that are currently or have recently been received in the various public offices mentioned; to investigate any abuses that might exist there, etc.

And be it further enacted, that it shall and may be lawful to and for the said commissioners, or any two of them, and they are hereby empowered, authorized, and required, to examine upon oath (which oath they, or any two of them, are hereby authorized to administer) the several persons, of all descriptions, belonging to any of the offices or departments before mentioned, and all other persons whom the said commissioners, or any two of them, shall think fit to examine, touching the business of each office or department, and the fees, gratuities, perquisites, and emoluments taken therein, and touching all other matters and things necessary for the execution of the powers vested in the said commissioners by this act; all which persons are hereby required and directed punctually to attend the said commissioners, at such time and place as they, or any two of them, shall appoint, and also to observe and execute such orders and directions as the said commissioners, or any two of them, shall make or give for the purposes before mentioned.

And let it be further enacted that it is lawful for the mentioned commissioners, or any two of them, who are hereby empowered, authorized, and required, to examine under oath (which oath they, or any two of them, are authorized to administer) the various individuals of all types associated with any of the offices or departments mentioned earlier, and all other individuals that the said commissioners, or any two of them, decide to examine regarding the operations of each office or department, and the fees, tips, benefits, and earnings involved, as well as any other matters necessary for carrying out the powers granted to the said commissioners by this act; all such individuals are required to promptly attend the said commissioners at the time and place designated by them, or any two of them, and also to follow and carry out any orders and directions issued by the said commissioners, or any two of them, for the purposes mentioned above.

And be it enacted by the authority aforesaid, that the said commissioners, or any two of them, shall be and are hereby empowered to examine into any corrupt and fraudulent practices, or other misconduct, committed by any person or persons concerned in the management of any of the offices or departments hereinbefore mentioned; and for the better execution of this present act, the said commissioners, or any two of them, are hereby authorized to meet and sit, from time to time, in such place or places as they shall find most convenient, with, or without adjournment, and to send their precept or precepts, under their hands and seals, for any person or persons whatsoever, and for such books, papers, writings, or records, as they shall judge necessary for their information, relating to any of the offices or departments hereinbefore mentioned; and all bailiffs, constables, sheriffs, and other his Majesty's officers, are hereby required to obey and execute such orders and precepts aforesaid as shall be sent to them, or any of them, by the said commissioners, or any two of them, touching the premises.

And it is hereby enacted by the mentioned authority that the commissioners, or any two of them, are empowered to investigate any corrupt or fraudulent activities or other misconduct by anyone involved in managing any of the offices or departments mentioned earlier; and to better carry out this law, the commissioners, or any two of them, are authorized to meet and convene, as needed, in whatever locations they find most convenient, with or without adjournment, and to issue their orders, under their signatures and seals, for any individuals and for any books, papers, documents, or records they deem necessary for their investigation, related to any of the offices or departments mentioned earlier; and all bailiffs, constables, sheriffs, and other officials of His Majesty are required to follow and carry out the orders and requests issued to them, or any of them, by the commissioners, or any two of them, concerning this matter.


No. 2.

Referred to from page __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__.

NABOB OF ARCOT'S DEBTS.

Mr. George Smith being asked, Whether the debts of the Nabob of Arcot have increased since he knew Madras? he said, Yes, they have. He distinguishes his debts into two sorts: those contracted before the year 1766, and those contracted from that year to the year in which he left Madras.—Being asked, What he thinks is the original amount of the old debts? he said, Between twenty-three and twenty-four lacs of pagodas, as well as he can recollect.—Being asked, What was the amount of that debt when he left Madras? he said, Between four and five lacs of pagodas, as he understood.—Being asked, What was the amount of the new debt when he left Madras? he said, In November, 1777, that debt amounted, according to the Nabob's own account, and published at Chepauk, his place of residence, to sixty lacs of pagodas, independent of the old debt, on which debt of sixty lacs of pagodas the Nabob did agree to pay an interest of twelve per cent per annum.—Being asked, Whether this debt was approved of by the Court of Directors? he said, He does not know it was.—Being asked, Whether the old debt was recognized by the Court of Directors? he said, Yes, it has been; and the Court of Directors have sent out repeated orders to the President and Council of Madras to enforce its recovery and payment.—Being asked, If the interest upon the new debt is punctually paid? he said, It was not during his residence at Madras, from 1777 to 1779, in which period he thinks no more than five per cent interest was paid, in different dividends of two and one per cent.—Being asked, What is the usual course taken by the Nabob concerning the arrears of interest? he said, Not having ever lent him moneys himself, he cannot fully answer as to the mode of settling the interest with him.

Mr. George Smith was asked if the debts of the Nabob of Arcot have increased since he first arrived in Madras. He replied, "Yes, they have." He categorizes his debts into two types: those incurred before 1766 and those incurred from 1766 until he left Madras. When asked what he thinks the original amount of the old debts was, he estimated it to be between twenty-three and twenty-four lacs of pagodas, as best as he can remember. When asked what the amount of that debt was when he left Madras, he stated it was between four and five lacs of pagodas, as far as he understood. He was then asked what the amount of the new debt was when he left Madras, and he responded that in November 1777, that debt was reported by the Nabob himself, which was published at Chepauk, his residence, to be sixty lacs of pagodas, not including the old debt; the Nabob agreed to pay twelve percent interest per annum on this sixty lacs. When asked if this debt was approved by the Court of Directors, he said he was not aware that it was. When asked if the old debt was recognized by the Court of Directors, he confirmed that it has been, and that the Court has sent repeated orders to the President and Council of Madras to ensure its recovery and payment. When asked if the interest on the new debt was paid on time, he stated that it was not during his time in Madras from 1777 to 1779, during which he believes no more than five percent interest was paid in different installments of two and one percent. Finally, when asked about the usual approach taken by the Nabob regarding overdue interest, he said that since he has never personally lent him money, he cannot fully explain how interest settlements work with him.

Being asked, Whether he has reason to believe the sixty lacs of pagodas was all principal money really and truly advanced to the Nabob of Arcot, or a fictitious capital, made up of obligations given by him, where no money or goods were received, or which was increased by the uniting into it a greater interest than the twelve per cent expressed to be due on the capital? he said, He has no reason to believe that the sum of sixty lacs of pagodas was lent in money or goods to the Nabob, because that sum he thinks is of more value than all the money, goods, and chattels in the settlement; but he does not know in what mode or manner this debt of the Nabob's was incurred or accumulated.—Being asked, Whether it was not a general and well-grounded opinion at Madras, that a great part of this sum was accumulated by obligations, and was for services performed or to be performed for the Nabob? he said, He has heard that a part of this debt was given for the purposes mentioned in the above question, but he does not know that it was so.—Being asked, Whether it was the general opinion of the settlement? he said, He cannot say that it was the general opinion, but it was the opinion of a considerable part of the settlement.—Being asked, Whether it was the declared opinion of those that were concerned in the debt, or those that were not? he said, It was the opinion of both parties, at least such of them as he conversed with.—Being asked, Whether he has reason to believe that the interest really paid by the Nabob, upon obligations given, or money lent, did not frequently exceed twelve per cent? he said, Prior to the 1st of August, 1774, he had had reason to believe that a higher interest than twelve per cent was paid by the Nabob on moneys lent to him; but from and after that period, when the last act of Parliament took place in India, he does not know that more than twelve per cent had been paid by the Nabob, or received from him.—Being asked, Whether it is not his opinion that the Nabob has paid more than twelve per cent for money due since the 1st of August, 1774? he said, He has heard that he has, but he does not know it.—Being asked, Whether he has been told so by any considerable and weighty authority, that was like to know? he said, He has been so informed by persons who he believes had a very good opportunity of knowing it.—Being asked, Whether he was ever told so by the Nabob of Arcot himself? he said, He does not recollect that the Nabob of Arcot directly told him so, but from what he said he did infer that he paid a higher interest than twelve per cent.

When asked if he believed the sixty lacs of pagodas was all actual principal money really loaned to the Nabob of Arcot, or if it was a made-up amount based on obligations where no money or goods were exchanged, or possibly inflated with an interest greater than the twelve percent stated, he replied that he had no reason to think the sixty lacs of pagodas was lent in money or goods to the Nabob, as he believed that amount was worth more than all the money, goods, and property in the settlement. However, he was unsure how this debt of the Nabob was acquired or built up. When asked if it was a commonly held belief in Madras that a large part of this amount came from obligations for services rendered or to be rendered for the Nabob, he said he had heard part of this debt was for those reasons but couldn't confirm it. When questioned about whether it was the prevailing opinion in the settlement, he said he couldn't say it was the general view, but a significant number believed it. When asked if this opinion came from those involved in the debt or those who weren't, he replied it was the view of both groups, at least among those he spoke with. When asked if he believed the interest actually paid by the Nabob on obligations or loans often exceeded twelve percent, he said that before August 1, 1774, he had reason to think the Nabob paid more than twelve percent on money borrowed, but after that date, with the last parliamentary act in India, he didn't know if more than twelve percent had been paid or received. When asked if he thought the Nabob paid more than twelve percent for money owed since August 1, 1774, he said he had heard that he did, but he couldn't verify it. When asked if he had received this information from any significant and trustworthy authority, he said he was informed by people he believed had a good chance of knowing. When asked if the Nabob of Arcot himself ever told him this, he said he didn't remember the Nabob stating it directly but inferred from their conversations that he paid a higher interest than twelve percent.

Mr. Smith being asked, Whether, in the course of trade, he ever sold anything to the Nabob of Arcot? he said, In the year 1775 he did sell to the Nabob of Arcot pearls to the amount of 32,500 pagodas, for which the Nabob gave him an order or tankah on the country of Tanjore, payable in six months, without interest.—Being asked, Whether, at the time he asked the Nabob his price for the pearls, the Nabob beat down that price, as dealers commonly do? he said, No; so far from it, he offered him more than he asked by 1000 pagodas, and which he rejected.—Being asked, Whether, in settling a transaction of discount with the Nabob's agent, he was not offered a greater discount than 12l. per cent? he said, In discounting a soucar's bill for 180,000 pagodas, the Nabob's agent did offer him a discount of twenty-four per cent per annum, saving that it was the usual rate of discount paid by the Nabob; but which he would not accept of, thinking himself confined by the act of Parliament limiting the interest of moneys to twelve per cent, and accordingly he discounted the bill at twelve per cent per annum only.—Being asked, Whether he does not think those offers were made him because the Nabob thought he was a person of some consequence in the settlement? he said, Being only a private merchant, he apprehends that the offer was made to him more from its being a general practice than from any opinion of his importance.

Mr. Smith was asked whether, during his business dealings, he ever sold anything to the Nabob of Arcot. He replied that in 1775, he sold pearls worth 32,500 pagodas to the Nabob, who provided him with an order or tankah for the province of Tanjore, payable in six months without interest. When asked if, at the time he quoted the price for the pearls, the Nabob negotiated it down like dealers usually do, he said no; instead, the Nabob offered him 1,000 pagodas more than he had asked for, which Mr. Smith declined. When asked if he was offered a greater discount than 12l. per cent when settling a discount with the Nabob's agent, he explained that while discounting a soucar's bill for 180,000 pagodas, the Nabob's agent offered him a 24 percent per annum discount, stating it was the usual rate paid by the Nabob. However, he didn't accept it, thinking he was bound by the act of Parliament that limits interest to twelve percent, so he only discounted the bill at twelve percent per annum. Finally, when asked if he believed those offers were made because the Nabob thought he was a person of importance, he said that as a private merchant, he believed the offer was more a common practice than a reflection of his significance.


No. 3.

Referred to from p. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__.

A Bill for the Better Government of the Territorial Possessions and
Dependencies in India
.

[ONE OF MR FOX'S INDIA BILLS.]

And be it further enacted by the authority aforesaid, that the Nabob of Arcot, the Rajah of Tanjore, or any other native protected prince in India, shall not assign, mortgage, or pledge any territory or land whatsoever, or the produce or revenue thereof, to any British subject whatsoever; neither shall it be lawful to and for any British subject whatsoever to take or receive any such assignment, mortgage, or pledge; and the same are hereby declared to be null and void; and all payments or deliveries of produce or revenue, under any such assignment, shall and may be recovered back, by such native prince paying or delivering the same, from the person or persons receiving the same, or his or their representatives.

And it is further enacted by the above authority that the Nabob of Arcot, the Rajah of Tanjore, or any other native protected prince in India, cannot assign, mortgage, or pledge any territory or land, or the produce or revenue from it, to any British citizen. It is also not legal for any British citizen to accept any such assignment, mortgage, or pledge; these are hereby declared null and void. Any payments or deliveries of produce or revenue made under such assignments can be reclaimed by the native prince from the person or persons receiving them, or their representatives.


No. 4.

Referred to from pages __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ and __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

(COPY.)

27th May, 1782.

May 27, 1782.

Letter from the Committee of Assigned Revenue, to the President and Select Committee, dated 27th May, 1782; with Comparative Statement, and Minute thereon.

Letter from the Assigned Revenue Committee to the President and Select Committee, dated May 27, 1782; along with a Comparative Statement and a Minute on it.

To the Right Honorable LORD MACARTNEY, K.B., President, and Governor, &c., Select Committee of Fort St. George.

To the Right Honorable LORD MACARTNEY, K.B., President, and Governor, &c., Select Committee of Fort St. George.

MY LORD, AND GENTLEMEN,—

My Lord and Gentlemen, —

Although we have, in obedience to your commands of the 5th January, regularly laid before you our proceedings at large, and have occasionally addressed you upon such points as required your resolutions or orders for our guidance, we still think it necessary to collect and digest in a summary report those transactions in the management of the assigned revenue which have principally engaged our attention, and which, upon the proceeding, are too much intermixed with ordinary occurrences to be readily traced and understood.

Although we have, in accordance with your instructions from January 5th, regularly provided you with detailed reports of our activities and have occasionally reached out to you on matters that needed your decisions or orders for our direction, we still believe it's important to compile and summarize the key transactions related to the management of the assigned revenue that have mainly captured our focus. These transactions are often too mixed in with everyday events to be easily followed and understood.

Such a report may be formed with the greater propriety at this time, when your Lordship, &c., have been pleased to conclude your arrangements for the rent of several of the Nabob's districts. Our aim in it is briefly to explain the state of the Carnatic at the period of the Nabob's assignment,—the particular causes which existed to the prejudice of that assignment, after it was made,—and the measures which your Lordship, &c., have, upon our recommendation, adopted for removing those causes, and introducing a more regular and beneficial system of management in the country.

Such a report makes more sense right now, since you and your team have wrapped up your plans for the rent of various districts from the Nabob. Our goal is to briefly explain the situation in the Carnatic at the time of the Nabob's assignment—the specific issues that arose against that assignment after it was made—and the actions that you and your team have taken, based on our suggestions, to address those issues and implement a more organized and effective management system in the region.

Hyder Ali having entered the Carnatic with his whole force, about the middle of July, 1780, and employed fire and sword in its destruction for near eighteen months before the Nabob's assignment took place, it will not be difficult to conceive the state of the country at that period. In those provinces which were fully exposed to the ravages of horse, scarce a vestige remained either of population or agriculture: such of the miserable inhabitants as escaped the fury of the sword were either carried into the Mysore country or left to struggle under the horrors of famine. The Arcot and Trichinopoly districts began early to feel the effects of this desolating war. Tinnevelly, Madura, and Ramnadaporum, though little infested with Hyder's troops, became a prey to the incursions of the Polygars, who stripped them of the greatest part of the revenues. Ongole, Nellore, and Palnaud, the only remaining districts, had suffered, but in a small degree.

Hyder Ali entered the Carnatic with his entire army around mid-July 1780 and used violence and destruction for nearly eighteen months before the Nabob's assignment happened. It's easy to imagine the state of the country at that time. In the provinces that were severely impacted by cavalry attacks, hardly any signs of population or agriculture remained. The few miserable inhabitants who survived the violence were either taken to Mysore or left to deal with the horrors of famine. The Arcot and Trichinopoly regions started to feel the effects of this devastating war early on. Tinnevelly, Madura, and Ramnadaporum, though not heavily affected by Hyder's forces, fell victim to raids by the Polygars, who took away most of their revenues. Ongole, Nellore, and Palnaud, the only remaining areas, had suffered but to a lesser extent.

The misfortunes of war, however, were not the only evils which the Carnatic experienced. The Nabob's aumildars, and other servants, appear to have taken advantage of the general confusion to enrich themselves. A very small part of the revenue was accounted for; and so high were the ordinary expenses of every district, that double the apparent produce of the whole country would not have satisfied them.

The hardships of war weren't the only troubles faced by the Carnatic. The Nabob's aumildars and other officials seemed to exploit the chaos to line their own pockets. Only a tiny portion of the revenue was actually reported, and the usual expenses in each district were so high that even twice the reported output of the entire region wouldn't have been enough to cover them.

In this state, which we believe is no way exaggerated, the Company took charge of the assigned countries. Their prospect of relief from the heavy burdens of the war was, indeed, but little advanced by the Nabob's concession; and the revenues of the Carnatic seemed in danger of being irrecoverably lost, unless a speedy and entire change of system could be adopted.

In this situation, which we think is not exaggerated at all, the Company took control of the assigned countries. Their chances of getting relief from the heavy burdens of the war were hardly improved by the Nabob's concession; and the revenues of the Carnatic appeared to be at serious risk of being permanently lost, unless a quick and complete change of system could be implemented.

On our minutes of the 21st January we treated the subject of the assignment at some length, and pointed out the mischiefs which, in addition to the effects of the war, had arisen from what we conceived to be wrong and oppressive management. We used the freedom to suggest an entire alteration in the mode of realizing the revenues. We proposed a considerable and immediate reduction of expenses, and a total change of the principal aumildars who had been employed under the Nabob.

On our minutes from January 21st, we discussed the assignment in detail and highlighted the problems that, alongside the effects of the war, had come from what we believed to be poor and oppressive management. We took the liberty to suggest a complete overhaul of how the revenues were collected. We recommended a significant and immediate cut in expenses, as well as a complete replacement of the main aumildars who had been working under the Nabob.

Our ideas had the good fortune to receive your approbation; but the removal of the Nabob's servants being thought improper at that particular period of the collections, we employed our attention chiefly in preserving what revenue was left the country, and acquiring such materials as might lead to a more perfect knowledge of its former and present state.

Our ideas were lucky to get your approval; however, since removing the Nabob's servants was considered inappropriate at that time during the collections, we focused mainly on preserving what revenue was still in the country and gathering materials that could help us better understand its past and current condition.

These pursuits, as we apprehended, met with great obstructions from the conduct of the Nabob's servants. The orders they received were evaded under various pretexts; no attention was paid to the strong and repeated applications made to them for the accounts of their management; and their attachment to the Company's interest appeared, in every instance, so feeble, that we saw no prospect whatever of success, but in the appointment of renters under the Company's sole authority.

These efforts, as we understood, faced significant obstacles from the actions of the Nabob's servants. They ignored the orders they received under different excuses; no attention was given to our persistent requests for details about their management; and their commitment to the Company's interests seemed so weak in every case that we saw no chance of success other than by appointing renters solely under the Company's authority.

Upon this principle, we judged it expedient to recommend that such of the Nabob's districts as were in a state to be farmed out might be immediately let by a public advertisement, issued in the Company's name, and circulated through every province of the Carnatic; and, with the view of encouraging bidders, we proposed that the countries might be advertised for the whole period of the Nabob's assignment, and the security of the Company's protection promised in the fullest manner to such persons as might become renters.

Based on this principle, we thought it best to suggest that the Nabob's districts that were ready to be leased out should be immediately offered through a public advertisement issued in the Company's name, and distributed throughout every province of the Carnatic. To encourage bidders, we proposed that the regions be advertised for the entire duration of the Nabob's assignment, with the Company's protection guaranteed in the most reassuring way to those who might become tenants.

This plan had the desired effect; and the attempts which were secretly made to counteract it afforded an unequivocal proof of its necessity: but the advantages resulting from it were more pleasingly evinced by the number of proposals that were delivered, and by the terms which were in general offered for the districts intended to be farmed out.

This plan worked as intended, and the secret attempts to undermine it clearly showed how necessary it was: however, the benefits were even more evident from the number of proposals received and the generally favorable terms offered for the areas meant to be leased out.

Having so far attained the purposes of the assignment, our attention was next turned to the heavy expenses entailed upon the different provinces; and here, we confess, our astonishment was raised to the highest pitch. In the Trichinopoly country the standing disbursements appeared, by the Nabob's own accounts, to be one lac of rupees more than the receipts. In other districts the charges were not in so high a proportion, but still rated on a most extravagant scale; and we saw, by every account that was brought before us, the absolute necessity of retrenching considerably in all the articles of expense.

Having achieved the goals of the assignment so far, we next focused on the high costs incurred by the different provinces. Here, we must admit, our shock reached its peak. In the Trichinopoly area, the regular expenditures seemed, according to the Nabob's own reports, to exceed the income by one lac of rupees. In other districts, the expenses weren't as high, but they were still quite excessive. Every report presented to us highlighted the urgent need to cut back significantly on all expense items.

Our own reason, aided by such inquiries as we were able to make, suggested the alterations we have recommended to your Lordship, &c., under this head. You will observe that we have not acted sparingly, but we chose rather, in cases of doubt, to incur the hazard of retrenching too much than too little; because it would be easier, after any stated allowance for expenses, to add what might be necessary than to diminish. We hope, however, there will be no material increase in the articles, as they now stand.

Our own reasoning, along with the investigations we conducted, led us to suggest the changes we’ve recommended to your Lordship, etc., on this matter. You’ll notice that we haven’t been too cautious; instead, we preferred to take the risk of cutting back too much rather than too little in uncertain situations. This way, it’s simpler to add what's needed later after establishing any budget for expenses than to reduce what’s already been allocated. However, we hope there won’t be any significant increase in the items as they currently are.

One considerable charge upon the Nabob's country was for extraordinary sibbendies, sepoys, and horsemen, who appeared to us to be a very unnecessary incumbrance on the revenue. Your Lordship, &c., have determined to receive such of these people as will enlist into the Company's service, and discharge the rest. This measure will not only relieve the country of a heavy burden, but tend greatly to fix in the Company that kind of authority which is requisite for the due collection of the revenues.

One significant expense for the Nabob's territory was for extra soldiers, including infantry, cavalry, and horsemen, who seemed to us to be an unnecessary drain on the revenue. You and your associates have decided to keep those among them who are willing to join the Company’s service and let go of the rest. This decision will not only lighten the country’s financial load but will also help strengthen the Company's authority needed for proper tax collection.

In consequence of your determination respecting the Nabob's sepoys, &c., every charge under that head has been struck out of our account of expenses. If the whole number of these people be enlisted by the Company, there will probably be no more than sufficient to complete their ordinary military establishment. But should the present reduction of the Nabob's artillery render it expedient, after the war, to make any addition to the Company's establishment for the purposes of the assigned countries, the expense of such addition, whatever it be, must be deducted from the present account of savings.

As a result of your decision regarding the Nabob's sepoys, every expense related to that has been removed from our expense report. If the Company enlists all these individuals, there will likely only be enough to meet their usual military needs. However, if the current cut in the Nabob's artillery means that it’s necessary, after the war, to increase the Company's forces for the assigned territories, the cost of that addition, no matter how much it is, will need to be taken out of the current savings account.

In considering the charges of the several districts, in order to establish better regulations, we were careful to discriminate those incurred for troops, kept or supposed to be kept up for the defence of the country, from those of the sibbendy, servants, &c., for the cultivation of the lands and the collection of the revenues, as well as to pay attention, to such of the established customs of the country, ancient privileges of the inhabitants, and public charities, as were necessarily allowed, and appeared proper to be continued, but which, under the Nabob's government, were not only rated much higher, but had been blended under one confused and almost unintelligible title of expenses of the districts: so joined, perhaps, to afford pleas and means of secreting and appropriating great part of the revenues to other purposes than fairly appeared; and certainly betraying the utmost neglect and mismanagement, as giving latitude for every species of fraud and oppression. Such a system has, in the few latter years of the Nabob's necessities, brought all his countries into that situation from which nothing but the most rigid economy, strict observance of the conduct of managers, and the most conciliating attention to the rights of the inhabitants can possibly recover them.

When looking at the charges from the different districts to create better regulations, we made sure to separate those costs for troops, whether actually maintained or just assumed to be, for the defense of the country, from those related to local workers, servants, etc., for farming the land and collecting taxes. We also needed to consider the established customs, ancient privileges of the people, and public charities that were necessary and seemed right to continue, but which, under the Nabob's rule, were not only assessed at much higher rates but had been grouped together under an unclear and almost nonsensical category of district expenses. This was likely done to provide excuses and means to hide and misappropriate a large portion of the revenue for other uses than what was honest; and it certainly showed extreme neglect and mismanagement, allowing for all kinds of fraud and oppression. Such a system has, in the last few years due to the Nabob's demands, put all his territories in a position that can only be recovered through strict financial discipline, careful monitoring of managers, and genuine attention to the rights of the people.

It now only remains for us to lay before your Lordship, &c., the inclosed statement of the sums at which the districts lately advertised have been let, compared with the accounts of their produce delivered by the Nabob, and entered on our proceedings of the 21st January,—likewise a comparative view of the former and present expenses.

It now only remains for us to present to your Lordship, etc., the enclosed statement of the amounts for which the recently advertised districts have been leased, compared with the reports of their outputs provided by the Nabob, and recorded in our proceedings of January 21st—also a comparison of the previous and current expenses.

The Nabob's accounts of the produce of these districts state, as we have some reason to think, the sums which former renters engaged to pay to him, (and which were seldom, if ever, made good,) and not the sums actually produced by the districts; yet we have the satisfaction to observe that the present aggregate rents, upon an average, are equal to those accounts. Your Lordship, &c., cannot, indeed, expect, that, in the midst of the danger, invasion, and distress which assail the Carnatic on every side, the renters now appointed will be able at present to fulfil the terms of their leases; but we trust, from the measures we have taken, that very little, if any, of the actual collections will be lost, even during the war,—and that, on the return of peace and tranquillity, the renters will have it in their power fully to perform their respective agreements.

The Nabob's reports on the production from these areas suggest, as we have some reason to believe, the amounts that previous renters promised to pay him, (which were rarely, if ever, fulfilled,) rather than the actual production from the districts; however, we are pleased to note that the current total rents, on average, match those reports. Your Lordship, &c., cannot, of course, expect that, amid the danger, invasion, and distress threatening the Carnatic from all sides, the newly appointed renters will be able to meet the conditions of their leases right now; but we are optimistic, because of the measures we have implemented, that very little, if any, of the actual collections will be lost, even during the war,—and that, once peace and stability return, the renters will be able to fully honor their agreements.

We much regret that the situation of the Arcot province will not admit of the same settlement which has been made for the other districts; but the enemy being in possession of the capital, together with several other strongholds, and having entirely desolated the country, there is little room to hope for more from it than a bare subsistence to the few garrisons we have left there.

We deeply regret that the situation in the Arcot province will not allow for the same resolution that has been established for the other districts; however, with the enemy controlling the capital and several other strongholds, and having completely devastated the area, there is little hope for anything more than basic survival for the few garrisons we have remaining there.

We shall not fail to give our attention towards obtaining every information respecting this province that the present times will permit, and to take the first opportunity to propose such arrangements for the management as we may think eligible.

We will make sure to focus on getting all the information about this province that current times allow, and we will take the first chance we get to suggest any management arrangements we consider appropriate.

We have the honor to be

We’re honored to be

Your most obedient humble servants,

Your most obedient servants,

CHARLES OAKLEY,
EYLES IRWIN,
HALL PLUMER,
DAVID HALIBURTON,
GEORGE MOUBRAY.

CHARLES OAKLEY,
EYLES IRWIN,
HALL PLUMER,
DAVID HALIBURTON,
GEORGE MOUBRAY.

FORT ST. GEORGE, 27th May, 1782.

FORT ST. GEORGE, May 27, 1782.

A true copy.

An exact copy.

J. HUDLESTON, Sec.

J. Hudleston, Secretary

COMPARATIVE STATEMENT of the Revenues and Expenses of the Nellore, Ongole, Palnaud, Trichinopoly, Madura, and Tinnevelly Countries, while in the Hands of the Nabob, with those of the same Countries on the Terms of the Leases lately granted for Four Years, to commence with the Beginning of the Phazeley, 1192, or the 12th July, 1782. Abstracted from the Accounts received from the Nabob, and from the Rents stipulated for and Expenses allowed by the present Leases.

COMPARATIVE STATEMENT of the Revenues and Expenses of the Nellore, Ongole, Palnaud, Trichinopoly, Madura, and Tinnevelly Regions, while under the control of the Nabob, compared to the same Regions under the terms of the recent Four-Year Leases, starting from the beginning of Phazeley, 1192, or July 12, 1782. This data is summarized from the Accounts received from the Nabob, as well as the Rents agreed upon and Expenses permitted by the current Leases.

GROSS REVENUE.EXPENSES.NET REVENUE.
Annual Gross Rent by the Nabob's Account.
Average of the Four Years immediately preceding the present War.
Annual Rent by the present Leases, at an Average of Four Years. Annual Expenses by the Nabob's Accounts. Annual Expenses allowed by the present Leases at an Estimate. Reduction in the Annual Expenses. Net Revenue by the Nabob's Accounts. Net Revenue by the present Leases.Increase of Net Revenue.
 Star Pagodas.Star Pagodas.Star Pagodas.Star Pagodas.Star Pagodas.Star Pagodas.Star Pagodas.Star Pagodas.
Nellore and Sarapilly3,22,8303,61,9001,98,79433,0001,65,7941,24,0363,28,9002,04,864
Ongole1,10,967[68]55,00088,254...88,25422,71355,00032,287
Palnaud51,35553,50025,7215,69820,02325,63447,80222,168
Trichinopoly2,89,993[69]2,73,2142,82,14813,1432,63,0057,8452,54,0712,46,226
Madura1,02,75660,29063,71012,03751,67339,04648,2539,207
Tinnevelly5,65,5375,79,7131,64,09870,36893,7304,01,4395,09,3451,07,906
Total14,43,43813,83,6178,22,7251,40,2466,82,4796,20,71312,43,3716,22,658

N.B. In this statement, Madras Pagodas are calculated at 10 per cent Batta; Chuckrums at two thirds of a Porto Novo Pagoda, which are reckoned at 115 per 100 Star Pagodas; and Rupees at 350 per 100 Star Pagodas. To avoid fractions, the nearest integral numbers have been taken.

N.B. In this statement, Madras Pagodas are valued at 10 percent Batta; Chuckrums are valued at two thirds of a Porto Novo Pagoda, which are calculated at 115 per 100 Star Pagodas; and Rupees are valued at 350 per 100 Star Pagodas. To avoid fractions, the nearest whole numbers have been used.

Signed,

Signed,

CHARLES OAKLEY,
EYLES IRWIN,
HALL PLUMER,
DAVID HALIBURTON,
GEORGE MOUBRAY.

FORT ST. GEORGE, 27th May, 1782.

CHARLES OAKLEY,
EYLES IRWIN,
HALL PLUMER,
DAVID HALIBURTON,
GEORGE MOUBRAY.

FORT ST. GEORGE, May 27, 1782.


No. 5.

Referred to from page __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__.

Case of certain Persons renting the Assigned Lands wider the Authority of the East India Company.

Extract of a Letter from the President and Council of Fort St. George, 25th May, 1783.

One of them [the renters], Ram Chunder Raus, was, indeed, one of those unfortunate rajahs whose country, by being near to the territories of the Nabob, forfeited its title to independence, and became the prey of ambition and cupidity. This man, though not able to resist the Company's arms, employed in such a deed at the Nabob's instigation, had industry and ability. He acquired, by a series of services, even the confidence of the Nabob, who suffered him to rent apart of the country of which he had deprived him of the property. This man had afforded no motive for his rejection by the Nabob, but that of being ready to engage with the Company: a motive most powerful, indeed, but not to be avowed.

One of the renters, Ram Chunder Raus, was one of those unfortunate rajahs whose country, because it was close to the territories of the Nabob, lost its independence and became a victim of ambition and greed. This man, although unable to resist the Company's forces, used in such actions at the Nabob's urging, had hard work and skill. He gained, through a series of services, even the trust of the Nabob, who allowed him to lease part of the land that he had taken from him. This man had given no reason for the Nabob to reject him, other than his willingness to collaborate with the Company: a very powerful motive, indeed, but one that couldn't be openly acknowledged.

[This is the person whom the English instruments of the Nabob of Arcot have had the audacity to charge with a corrupt transaction with Lord Macartney, and, in support of that charge, to produce a forged letter from his Lordship's steward. The charge and letter the reader may see in this Appendix, under the proper head. It is asserted by the unfortunate prince above mentioned, that the Company first settled on the coast of Coromandel under the protection of one of his ancestors. If this be true, (and it is far from unlikely,) the world must judge of the return the descendant has met with. The case of another of the victims given up by the ministry, though not altogether so striking as the former, is worthy of attention. It is that of the renter of the Province of Nellore.]

[This is the person whom the English officials of the Nabob of Arcot have had the nerve to accuse of a corrupt deal with Lord Macartney and, to back up that accusation, to present a forged letter from his Lordship's steward. The accusation and letter can be found in this Appendix, under the appropriate section. The unfortunate prince mentioned above claims that the Company first established itself on the coast of Coromandel with the protection of one of his ancestors. If this is true (and it's not unlikely), the world should consider the outcome his descendant has faced. The situation of another victim sacrificed by the ministry, although not as dramatic as the previous one, also deserves attention. It involves the renter of the Province of Nellore.]

It is, with a wantonness of falsehood, and indifference to detection, asserted to you, in proof of the validity of the Nabob's objections, that this man's failures had already forced us to remove him: though in fact he has continued invariably in office; though our greatest supplies have been received from him; and that, in the disappointment of your remittances [the remittances from Bengal] and of other resources, the specie sent us from Nellore alone has sometimes enabled us to carry on the public business; and that the present expedition against the French must, without this assistance from the assignment, have been laid aside, or delayed until it might have become too late.

It is, with an outrageous falsehood and a complete disregard for being caught, claimed to you, as proof of the legitimacy of the Nabob's objections, that this man's failures had already forced us to let him go: although, in reality, he has consistently remained in his position; indeed, our largest supplies have come from him; and that, due to the disappointment of your remittances [the remittances from Bengal] and other resources, the money sent to us from Nellore alone has sometimes allowed us to continue our public business; and that the current expedition against the French would have had to be abandoned or postponed without this support from the assignment, until it might have become too late.

[This man is by the ministry given over to the mercy of persons capable of making charges on him "with a wantonness of falsehood, and indifference to detection." What is likely to happen to him and the rest of the victims may appear by the following.]

[This man has been turned over to the mercy of individuals who can make accusations against him "with a wantonness of falsehood, and indifference to detection." What is likely to happen to him and the other victims can be understood by the following.]


Letter to the Governor-General and Council, March 13th, 1782.

The speedy termination, to which the people were taught to look, of the Company's interference in the revenues, and the vengeance denounced against those who, contrary to the mandate of the Durbar, should be connected with them, as reported by Mr. Sullivan, may, as much as the former exactions and oppressions of the Nabob in the revenue, as reported by the commander-in-chief, have deterred some of the fittest men from offering to be concerned in it.

The quick end that people were told to expect regarding the Company's interference with the revenues, along with the threats made against anyone who, against the Durbar's orders, got involved with them, as reported by Mr. Sullivan, may, just like the previous demands and abuses by the Nabob in the revenue, as reported by the commander-in-chief, have discouraged some of the most suitable individuals from wanting to be involved in it.

The timid disposition of the Hindoo natives of this country was not likely to be insensible to the specimen of that vengeance given by his Excellency the Amir, who, upon the mere rumor, that a Bramin, of the name of Appagee Row, had given proposals to the Company for the rentership of Vellore, had the temerity to send for him, and to put him in confinement.

The shy nature of the Hindu people in this country was unlikely to ignore the example of vengeance demonstrated by his Excellency the Amir, who, simply upon hearing a rumor that a Brahmin named Appagee Row had made proposals to the Company for the rental of Vellore, boldly summoned him and had him imprisoned.

A man thus seized by the Nabob's sepoys within the walls of Madras gave a general alarm, and government found it necessary to promise the protection of the Company, in order to calm the apprehensions of the people.

A man seized by the Nabob's soldiers inside the walls of Madras raised a general alarm, prompting the government to promise the protection of the Company to ease the people's fears.


No. 6.

Referred to from pages __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ and __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

Extract of a Letter from the Council and Select Committee at Fort St. George, to the Governor-General and Council, dated 25th May, 1783.

In the prosecution of our duty, we beseech you to consider, as an act of strict and necessary justice, previous to reiteration of your orders for the surrender of the assignment, how far it would be likely to affect third persons who do not appear to have committed any breach of their engagements. You command us to compel our aumils to deliver over their respective charges as shall be appointed by the Nabob, or to retain their trust under his sole authority, if he shall choose to confirm them. These aumils are really renters; they were appointed in the room of the Nabob's aumils, and contrary to his wishes; they have already been rejected by him, and are therefore not likely to be confirmed by him. They applied to this government, in consequence of public advertisements in our name, as possessing in this instance the joint authority of the Nabob and the Company, and have entered into mutual and strict covenants with us, and we with them, relative to the certain districts not actually in the possession of the enemy; by which covenants, as they are bound to the punctual payment of their rents and due management of the country, so we, and our constituents, and the public faith, are in like manner bound to maintain them in the enjoyment of their leases, during the continuance of the term. That term was for five years, agreeably to the words of the assignment, which declare that the time of renting shall be for three or five years, as the Governor shall settle with the renters.—Their leases cannot be legally torn from them. Nothing but their previous breach of a part could justify our breach of the whole. Such a stretch and abuse of power would, indeed, not only savor of the assumption of sovereignty, but of arbitrary and oppressive despotism. In the present contest, whether the Nabob be guilty, or we be guilty, the renters are not guilty. Whichever of the contending parties has broken the condition of the assignment, the renters have not broken the condition of their leases. These men, in conducting the business of the assignment, have acted in opposition to the designs of the Nabob, in despite of the menaces denounced against all who should dare to oppose the mandates of the Durbar justice. Gratitude and humanity require that provision should be made by you, before you set the Nabob's ministers loose on the country, for the protection of the victims devoted to their vengeance.

In carrying out our duty, we urge you to think about, as a matter of fair and necessary justice, before repeating your orders for the surrender of the assignment, how it might impact innocent third parties who haven’t violated any agreements. You instruct us to force our aumils to hand over their respective charges as designated by the Nabob, or to keep their responsibilities under his sole direction, should he choose to approve them. These aumils are essentially renters; they were appointed in place of the Nabob’s aumils, against his wishes; he has already dismissed them, making it unlikely he will approve them again. They reached out to this government in response to public notices in our name, claiming to have the joint authority of the Nabob and the Company, and have made mutual and strict agreements with us, just as we have with them, concerning specific districts not currently under enemy control; by which agreements, as they are obligated to pay their rents on time and manage the land properly, we, our stakeholders, and public trust are also obligated to allow them to keep their leases for the duration of the term. That term was for five years, according to the assignment's wording, which states that the rental period shall be for three or five years, as the Governor determines with the renters. Their leases cannot be legitimately taken away from them. Only a prior breach on their part could justify our breach of the entire agreement. Such an overreach and misuse of power would not only feel like an assumption of sovereignty but also like arbitrary and oppressive tyranny. In the current conflict, whether the Nabob is at fault, or whether we are at fault, the renters are innocent. Regardless of which party has violated the terms of the assignment, the renters have not broken the conditions of their leases. These individuals, in managing the assignment, have acted against the Nabob’s intentions, despite the threats made against anyone who dared to challenge the orders of the Durbar justice. Compassion and humanity dictate that you make provisions before unleashing the Nabob's ministers on the land to protect those who are targeted by their vindictiveness.

Mr. Benfield, to secure the permanency of his power, and the perfection of his schemes, thought it necessary to render the Nabob an absolute stranger to the state of his affairs. He assured his Highness that full justice was not done to the strength of his sentiments and the keenness of his attacks, in the translations that were made by the Company's servants from the original Persian of his letters. He therefore proposed to him that they should for the future be transmitted in English.—Of the English language or writing his Highness or the Amir cannot read one word, though the latter can converse in it with sufficient fluency. The Persian language, as the language of the Mahomedan conquerors, and of the court of Delhi, as an appendage or signal of authority, was at all times particularly affected by the Nabob. It is the language of all acts of state, and all public transactions, among the Mussulman chiefs of Hindostan. The Nabob thought to have gained no inconsiderable point, in procuring the correspondence from our predecessors to the Rajah of Tanjore to be changed from the Mahratta language, which that Hindoo prince understands, to the Persian, which he disclaims understanding. To force the Rajah to the Nabob's language was gratifying the latter with a new species of subserviency. He had formerly contended with considerable anxiety, and, it was thought, no inconsiderable cost, for particular forms of address to be used towards him in that language. But all of a sudden, in favor of Mr. Benfield, he quits his former affections, his habits, his knowledge, his curiosity, the increasing mistrust of age, to throw himself upon the generous candor, the faithful interpretation, the grateful return, and eloquent organ of Mr. Benfield!—Mr. Benfield relates and reads what he pleases to his Excellency the Amir-ul-Omrah; his Excellency communicates with the Nabob, his father, in the language the latter understands. Through two channels so pure, the truth must arrive at the Nabob in perfect refinement; through this double trust, his Highness receives whatever impression it may be convenient to make on him: he abandons his signature to whatever paper they tell him contains, in the English language, the sentiments with which they had inspired him. He thus is surrounded on every side. He is totally at their mercy, to believe what is not true, and to subscribe to what he does not mean. There is no system so new, so foreign to his intentions, that they may not pursue in his name, without possibility of detection: for they are cautious of who approach him, and have thought prudent to decline, for him, the visits of the Governor, even upon the usual solemn and acceptable occasion of delivering to his Highness the Company's letters. Such is the complete ascendency gained by Mr. Benfield. It may be partly explained by the facts observed already, some years ago, by Mr. Benfield himself, in regard to the Nabob, of the infirmities natural to his advanced age, joined to the decays of his constitution. To this ascendency, in proportion as it grew, must chiefly be ascribed, if not the origin, at least the continuance and increase, of the Nabob's disunion with this Presidency: a disunion which creates the importance and subserves the resentments of Mr. Benfield; and an ascendency which, if you effect the surrender of the assignment, will entirely leave the exercise of power and accumulation of fortune at his boundless discretion: to him, and to the Amir-ul-Omrah, and to Seyd Assam Cawn, the assignment would in fact be surrendered. HE WILL (IF ANY) BE THE SOUCAR SECURITY; and security in this country is counter-secured by possession. You would not choose to take the assignment from the Company, to give it to individuals. Of the impropriety of its returning to the Nabob, Mr. Benfield would now again argue from his former observations, that, under his Highness's management, his country declined, his people emigrated, his revenues decreased, and his country was rapidly approaching to a state of political insolvency. Of Seyd Assam Cawn we judge only from the observations this letter already contains. But of the other two persons [Amir-ul-Omrah and Mr. Benfield] we undertake to declare, not as parties in a cause, or even as voluntary witnesses, but as executive officers, reporting to you, in the discharge of our duty, and under the impression of the sacred obligation which binds us to truth, as well as to justice, that, from every observation of their principles and dispositions, and every information of their character and conduct, they have prosecuted projects to the injury and danger of the Company and individuals; that it would be improper to trust, and dangerous to employ them, in any public or important situation; that the tranquillity of the Carnatic requires a restraint to the power of the Amir; and that the Company, whose service and protection Mr. Benfield has repeatedly and recently forfeited, would be more secure against danger and confusion, if he were removed from their several Presidencies.

Mr. Benfield, to secure his continued power and the success of his plans, believed it was essential to keep the Nabob completely unaware of the state of his affairs. He assured his Highness that the full force of his opinions and the intensity of his criticisms were not conveyed accurately in the translations made by the Company's staff from the original Persian of his letters. So, he suggested that from now on, they should be sent in English. The Highness or the Amir cannot read a word of English, although the latter can speak it fairly well. The Nabob always had a particular fondness for the Persian language, the language of the Muslim conquerors and the court of Delhi, as it symbolized authority. It is the language used for all state matters and public transactions among the Muslim leaders of Hindostan. The Nabob thought he scored a significant point by having the correspondence from our predecessors to the Rajah of Tanjore switched from the Mahratta language, which the Hindu prince understands, to Persian, which he claims not to understand. Forcing the Rajah to use the Nabob's language was a way of showing the latter a new form of submission. He had previously fought hard and incurred considerable expense to ensure that certain forms of address were used towards him in that language. However, suddenly, in favor of Mr. Benfield, he abandons his past loyalties, his habits, his knowledge, and his growing suspicions of age, to rely on the generosity, faithful interpretation, gratitude, and eloquent articulation of Mr. Benfield!—Mr. Benfield recounts and reads whatever he pleases to his Excellency the Amir-ul-Omrah; his Excellency communicates with the Nabob, his father, in the language the latter understands. Through these two reliable channels, the truth reaches the Nabob in ideal form; through this dual trust, his Highness receives whatever impression is convenient to create. He relinquishes his signature to any document they tell him contains, in English, the thoughts they have instilled in him. He is thus surrounded on all sides. He is completely at their mercy, believing what isn't true and signing what he doesn't mean. There is no scheme so novel, so contrary to his intentions, that they could not pursue in his name without being discovered: for they are careful about who approaches him and have deemed it wise to decline, on his behalf, the Governor's visits, even for the usual formal and acceptable occasion of delivering the Company's letters. Such is the total control Mr. Benfield has achieved. This can partly be explained by the observations made some years ago by Mr. Benfield himself regarding the Nabob, due to the natural frailties of his advanced age, compounded by the decline of his health. This control, as it grows, can be chiefly attributed, if not directly to its origin, at least to the continuation and increase of the Nabob's detachment from this Presidency: a disunion that enhances Mr. Benfield's importance and fuels his resentments; and this control, if you carry out the surrender of the assignment, would fully leave the exercise of power and accumulation of wealth entirely to his discretion: in reality, the assignment would be given over to him, the Amir-ul-Omrah, and Seyd Assam Cawn. HE WILL (IF ANY) BE THE SOUCAR SECURITY; and security in this country is safeguarded by possession. You would not want to take the assignment from the Company and give it to individuals. Regarding the inappropriateness of it returning to the Nabob, Mr. Benfield would again argue, based on his earlier observations, that under the Nabob's leadership, his territory declined, his people left, his income decreased, and his region was swiftly heading towards political bankruptcy. Our judgment of Seyd Assam Cawn is based solely on the observations already made in this letter. But regarding the other two individuals [Amir-ul-Omrah and Mr. Benfield], we declare, not as parties in a dispute or voluntary witnesses, but as executive officers fulfilling our duty and under the weight of the moral obligation to truth and justice, that from all our observations of their principles and tendencies and all information about their character and actions, they have pursued plans harmful to the Company and individuals; that it would be unwise to trust them, and dangerous to use them in any public or significant capacity; that the peace of the Carnatic requires limits on the Amir's power; and that the Company, which Mr. Benfield has repeatedly and recently failed to serve and safeguard, would be safer against threats and chaos if he were removed from their various Presidencies.

[After the above solemn declaration from so weighty an authority, the principal object of that awful and deliberate warning, instead of being "removed from the several Presidencies," is licensed to return to one of the principal of those Presidencies, and the grand theatre of the operations on account of which the Presidency recommends his total removal. The reason given is, for the accommodation of that very debt which has been the chief instrument of his dangerous practices, and the main cause of all the confusions in the Company's government.]

[After the serious statement from such an important authority, the main focus of that serious and careful warning, instead of being "removed from the various Presidencies," is allowed to come back to one of the key Presidencies, and the central stage of the actions that led to the Presidency's recommendation for his complete removal. The reason given is for the benefit of that very debt which has been the primary tool of his risky actions, and the main cause of all the chaos in the Company's governance.]


No. 7.

Referred to from pp. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__, and __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__.

Extracts from the Evidence of Mr. Petrie, late Resident for the Company at Tanjore, given to the Select Committee, relative to the Revenues and State of the Country, &c., &c.

9th May, 1782.

May 9, 1782.

William Petrie, Esq., attending according to order, was asked, In what station he was in the Company's service? he said, He went to India in the year 1765, a writer upon the Madras establishment: he was employed, during the former war with Hyder Ali, in the capacity of paymaster and commissary to part of the army, and was afterwards paymaster and commissary to the army in the first siege of Tanjore, and the subsequent campaigns; then secretary to the Secret Department from 1772 to 1775; he came to England in 1775, and returned again to Madras the beginning of 1778; he was resident at the durbar of the Rajah of Tanjore from that time to the month of May; and from that time to January, 1780, was chief of Nagore and Carrical, the first of which was received from the Rajah of Tanjore, and the second was taken from the French.—Being asked, Who sent him to Tanjore? he said, Sir Thomas Rumbold, and the Secret Committee.—Being then asked, Upon what errand? he said, He went first up with a letter from the Company to the Rajah of Tanjore: he was directed to give the Rajah the strongest assurances that he should be kept in possession of his country, and every privilege to which he had been restored; he was likewise directed to negotiate with the Rajah of Tanjore for the cession of the seaport and district of Nagore in lieu of the town and district of Devicotta, which he had promised to Lord Pigot: these were the principal, and, to the best of his recollection at present, the only objects in view, when he was first sent up to Tanjore. In the course of his stay at Tanjore, other matters of business occurred between the Company and the Rajah, which came under his management as resident at that durbar.—Being asked, Whether the Rajah did deliver up to him the town and the annexed districts of Nagore voluntarily, or whether he was forced to it? he said, When he made the first proposition to the Rajah, agreeable to the directions he had received from the Secret Committee at Madras, in the most free, open, and liberal manner, the Rajah told him the seaport of Nagore was entirely at the service of his benefactors, the Company, and that he was happy in having that opportunity of testifying his gratitude to them. These may be supposed to be words of course; but, from every experience which he had of the Rajah's mind and conduct, whilst he was at Tanjore, he has reason to believe that his declarations of gratitude to the Company were perfectly sincere. He speaks to the town of Nagore at present, and a certain district,—not of the districts to the amount of which they afterwards received. The Rajah asked him, To what amount he expected a jaghire to the Company? And the witness further said, That he acknowledged to the committee that he was not instructed upon that head; that he wrote for orders to Madras, and was directed to ask the Rajah for a jaghire to a certain amount; that this gave rise to a long negotiation, the Rajah representing to him his inability to make such a gift to the Company as the Secret Committee at Madras seemed to expect; while he (the witness) on the other hand, was directed to make as good a bargain as he could for the Company. From the view that he then took of the Rajah's finances, from the situation of his country, and from the load of debt which pressed hard upon him, he believes he at different times, in his correspondence with the government, represented the necessity of their being moderate in their demands, and it was at last agreed to accept of the town of Nagore, valued at a certain annual revenue, and a jaghire annexed to the town, the whole amounting to 250,000 rupees.—Being asked, Whether it did turn out so valuable? he said, He had not a doubt but it would turn out more, as it was let for more than that to farmers at Madras, if they had managed the districts properly; but they were strangers to the manners and customs of the people; when they came down, they oppressed the inhabitants, and threw the whole district into confusion; the inhabitants, many of them, left the country, and deserted the cultivation of their lands; of course the farmers were disappointed of their collections, and they have since failed, and the Company have lost a considerable part of what the farmers were to pay for the jaghire.—Being asked, Who these farmers were? he said, One of them was the renter of the St. Thomé district, near Madras, and the other, and the most responsible, was a Madras dubash.—Being asked, Whom he was dubash to? he said, To Mr. Cass-major.

William Petrie, Esq., appeared as scheduled and was asked what position he held in the Company's service. He replied that he went to India in 1765 as a writer for the Madras establishment. During the previous war with Hyder Ali, he served as paymaster and commissary for part of the army, and later as paymaster and commissary during the first siege of Tanjore and subsequent campaigns. From 1772 to 1775, he was secretary to the Secret Department. He returned to England in 1775 and went back to Madras at the beginning of 1778. From that point until May, he was a resident at the durbar of the Rajah of Tanjore. After that, until January 1780, he was chief of Nagore and Carrical, with the first area given to him by the Rajah of Tanjore and the second taken from the French. When asked who sent him to Tanjore, he said it was Sir Thomas Rumbold and the Secret Committee. When asked for what purpose, he explained that he initially went with a letter from the Company to the Rajah of Tanjore. He was instructed to assure the Rajah that he would retain control of his territory and all the rights he had been restored. He was also directed to negotiate with the Rajah of Tanjore for the handover of the seaport and district of Nagore in exchange for the town and district of Devicotta, which he had promised to Lord Pigot. These were the main objectives, and to the best of his recollection, the only ones in focus when he was first sent to Tanjore. During his time at Tanjore, other business matters arose between the Company and the Rajah that he managed as the resident at the durbar. When asked if the Rajah gave him the town and related districts of Nagore voluntarily or under pressure, he stated that when he first proposed this to the Rajah, following the instructions he received from the Secret Committee in Madras, the Rajah responded that the seaport of Nagore was entirely at the disposal of his benefactors, the Company, and that he was pleased to have the opportunity to show his gratitude to them. These might seem like standard phrases, but based on his experiences with the Rajah's mindset and actions while he was in Tanjore, he believes that the Rajah's expressions of gratitude to the Company were genuinely heartfelt. He is currently referring to the town of Nagore and a specific district—not the total number of districts they later acquired. The Rajah asked him how much he expected to secure for the Company in terms of a jaghire. The witness acknowledged to the committee that he was not instructed on that matter; he wrote to Madras for guidance and was told to ask the Rajah for a jaghire of a certain amount. This led to extensive negotiations, as the Rajah explained his inability to give such a gift to the Company as the Secret Committee in Madras seemed to anticipate, while he was directed to make the best deal possible for the Company. Based on his understanding of the Rajah's finances, the state of his country, and the heavy debt he was under, he believes he communicated the need for the Company to be reasonable in their demands. Ultimately, it was agreed to accept the town of Nagore, valued at a specific annual revenue, along with a jaghire associated with the town, totaling 250,000 rupees. When asked if this turned out to be that valuable, he said he had no doubt it would have been worth more if it had been managed properly, as it was rented out for more than that by farmers in Madras; but they were unfamiliar with the customs and practices of the locals. When they arrived, they mistreated the residents and disrupted the entire district. Many locals left, abandoning their lands, which left the farmers unable to collect their dues, resulting in significant losses for the Company from what the farmers were expected to pay for the jaghire. When asked who these farmers were, he said one was the renter of the St. Thomé district near Madras, and the other, the more responsible one, was a Madras dubash. When asked who he worked for as a dubash, he replied that it was for Mr. Cass-major.

Being asked, Whether the lease was made upon higher terms than the district was rated to him by the Rajah? he said, It was.—Being then asked, What reason was assigned why the district was not kept under the former management by aumildars, or let to persons in the Tanjore country acquainted with the district? he said, No reasons were assigned: he was directed from Madras to advertise them to be let to persons of the country; but before he received any proposal, he received accounts that they were let at Madras, in consequence of public advertisements which had been made there: he believes, indeed, there were very few men in those districts responsible enough to have been intrusted with the management of those lands.—Being asked, Whether, at the time he was authorized to negotiate for Nagore in the place of Devicotta, Devicotta was given up to the Rajah? he said, No.—Being asked, Whether the Rajah of Tanjore did not frequently desire that the districts of Arnee and Hanamantagoody should be restored to him, agreeable to treaty, and the Company's orders to Lord Pigot? he said, Many a time; and he transmitted his representations regularly to Madras.—Being then asked, Whether those places were restored to him? he said, Not while he was in India.

When asked if the lease was made at a higher rate than what the Rajah rated the district to him, he said it was. When asked why the district wasn't managed by aumildars or rented to people in Tanjore who knew the area, he replied that no reasons were given. He was instructed from Madras to advertise for local people to lease it, but before he got any offers, he found out it was leased in Madras due to public ads that had been placed there. He believes there were actually very few people in those districts trustworthy enough to manage those lands. When asked if, at the time he was authorized to negotiate for Nagore instead of Devicotta, Devicotta had been handed over to the Rajah, he said no. When asked if the Rajah of Tanjore didn't often ask for the districts of Arnee and Hanamantagoody to be returned to him according to treaty and the Company's orders to Lord Pigot, he said many times, and he regularly sent his requests to Madras. When asked if those places were returned to him, he said not while he was in India.

Being asked, Whether he was not authorized and required by the Presidency at Madras to demand a large sum of money over and above the four lacs of pagodas that were to be annually paid by a grant of the Rajah, made in the time of Lord Pigot? he said, He was: to the amount, he believes, of four lacs of pagodas, commonly known by the name of deposit-money.—Being asked, Whether the Rajah did not frequently plead his inability to pay that money? he said, He did every time he mentioned it, and complained loudly of the demand.—Being asked, Whether he thinks those complaints were well founded? he says, He thinks the Rajah of Tanjore was not only not in a state of ability to pay the deposit-money, but that the annual payment of four lacs of pagodas was more than his revenues could afford.—Being asked, Whether he was not frequently obliged to borrow money, in order to pay the instalments of the annual payments, and such parts as he paid of the deposit? he said, Yes, he was.—Being asked, Where he borrowed the money? he said, He believes principally from soucars or native bankers, and some at Madras, as he told him.—Being asked, Whether he told him that his credit was very good, and that he borrowed upon moderate interest? he said, That he told him he found great difficulties in raising money, and was obliged to borrow at a most exorbitant interest, even some of it at forty-eight per cent, and he believes not a great deal under it. He desired him (the witness) to speak to one of the soucars or bankers at Tanjore to accommodate him with a loan of money: that man showed him an account between him and the Rajah, from which it appeared that he charged forty-eight per cent, besides compound interest.—Being asked, Whether the sums duo were large? he said, Yes, they were considerable; though he does not recollect the amount.—Being asked, Whether the banker lent the money? he said, He would not, unless the witness could procure him payment of his old arrears.

Being asked whether he was authorized and required by the Presidency in Madras to demand a large sum of money in addition to the four lacs of pagodas that were supposed to be paid annually by a grant from the Rajah during Lord Pigot's time, he replied that he was; he believed it was about four lacs of pagodas, commonly referred to as deposit money. Being asked if the Rajah often claimed he couldn't pay that money, he said he did every time he brought it up and complained loudly about the demand. When asked if he thought those complaints were justified, he said he believed the Rajah of Tanjore was actually unable to pay the deposit money and that the annual payment of four lacs of pagodas was more than his revenues could handle. When asked if he was often forced to borrow money to make the annual payments and the portions he paid of the deposit, he said yes, he was. When asked where he borrowed the money, he said he believed it was mainly from soucars or native bankers, and some from Madras, as he had mentioned. When asked if he had said that his credit was very good and that he borrowed at reasonable interest, he replied that he told him he faced great difficulty in raising money and had to borrow at extremely high interest rates, with some of it at forty-eight percent or close to that. He asked the witness to speak to a soucar or banker in Tanjore to help him get a loan: that man showed him an account between himself and the Rajah, revealing that he charged forty-eight percent interest plus compound interest. Being asked if the sums owed were large, he said yes, they were significant, though he didn't remember the exact amount. Being asked if the banker lent the money, he said he wouldn't unless the witness could arrange for payment of his old debts.

Being asked, What notice did the government of Madras take of the king of Tanjore's representations of the state of his affairs, and his inability to pay? he said, He does not recollect, that, in their correspondence with him, there was any reasoning upon the subject; and in his correspondence with Sir Thomas Rumbold, upon the amount of the jaghire, he seemed very desirous of adapting the demand of government to the Rajah's circumstances; but, whilst he stayed at Tanjore, the Rajah was not exonerated from any part of his burdens.—Being asked, Whether they ever desired the Rajah to make up a statement of his accounts, disbursements, debts, and payments to the Company, in order to ascertain whether the country was able to pay the increasing demands upon it? he said, Through him he is certain they never did.—Being then asked, If he ever heard whether they did through any one else? he said, He never did.

When asked what response the government of Madras had to the king of Tanjore's concerns about his situation and his inability to pay, he replied that he didn't remember any discussion on the topic in their correspondence. In his exchanges with Sir Thomas Rumbold regarding the amount of the jaghire, he seemed quite eager to adjust the government's demands to the Rajah's situation. However, during his time in Tanjore, the Rajah was not relieved of any of his obligations. When asked if they ever requested the Rajah to provide a summary of his accounts, expenses, debts, and payments to the Company to determine if the region could meet the growing financial demands, he said he was sure they never did through him. When asked if he ever heard of them doing so through anyone else, he replied that he never did.

Being asked, Whether the Rajah is not bound to furnish the cultivators of land with seed for their crops, according to the custom of the country? he said, The king of Tanjore, as proprietor of the land, always makes advances of money for seed for the cultivation of the land.—Being then asked, If money beyond his power of furnishing should be extorted from him, might it not prevent, in the first instance, the means of cultivating the country? he said, It certainly does; he knows it for a fact; and he knows, that, when he left the country, there were several districts which were uncultivated from that cause.—Being asked, Whether it is not necessary to be at a considerable expense in order to keep up the mounds and watercourses? he said, A very considerable one annually.—Being asked, What would be the consequence, if money should fail for that? he said, In the first instance, the country would be partially supplied with water, some districts would be overflowed, and others would be parched.—Being asked, Whether there is not a considerable dam called the Anicut, on the keeping up of which the prosperity of the country greatly depends, and which requires a great expense? he said, Yes, there is: the whole of the Tanjore country is admirably well supplied with water, nor can he conceive any method could be fallen upon more happily adapted to the cultivation and prosperity of the country; but, as the Anicut is the source of that prosperity, any injury done to that must essentially affect all the other works in the country: it is a most stupendous piece of masonry, but, from the very great floods, frequently requiring repairs, which if neglected, not only the expense of repairing must be greatly increased, but a general injury done to the whole country.—Being asked, Whether that dam has been kept in as good preservation since the prevalence of the English government as before? he said, From his own knowledge he cannot tell, but from everything he has read or heard of the former prosperity and opulence of the kings of Tanjore, he should suppose not.—Being asked, Whether he does not know of several attempts that have been made to prevent the repair, and even to damage the work? he said, The Rajah himself frequently complained of that to him, and he has likewise heard it from others at Tanjore.—Being asked, Who it was that attempted those acts of violence? he said, He was told it was the inhabitants of the Nabob's country adjoining to the Anicut.—Being asked, Whether they were not set on or instigated by the Nabob? he answered, The Rajah said so.—And being asked, What steps the President and Council took to punish the authors and prevent those violences? he said, To the best of his recollection, the Governor told him he would make inquiries into it, but he does not know that any inquiries were made; that Sir Thomas Rumbold, the Governor, informed him that he had laid his representations with respect to the Anicut before the Nabob, who denied that his people had given any interruption to the repairs of that work.

When asked whether the Rajah is required to provide farmers with seed for their crops, as per local custom, he said, The king of Tanjore, as the owner of the land, always gives out loans for seed for farming the land.—When asked if it would hinder farming in the country if he were pressured for money beyond what he could provide, he said, It definitely does; he knows this for sure, and he saw that when he left the country, there were several regions that were uncultivated for that reason.—When asked if a significant expense is necessary to maintain the dikes and irrigation systems, he said, It is a considerable annual expense.—When asked what would happen if funds for that ran dry, he said, Initially, the country would have limited water supply; some areas would be flooded while others would be dry.—When asked if there is a major dam called the Anicut, whose maintenance is crucial for the country’s prosperity and requires substantial costs, he said, Yes, there is: the entire Tanjore region is well supplied with water, and he can’t imagine a better method suited for the cultivation and prosperity of the area; however, since the Anicut is the source of that success, any damage to it would significantly impact all other projects in the region: it is an impressive piece of engineering, but it frequently needs repairs due to heavy floods, and neglecting those repairs would not only increase the costs but also cause widespread harm to the entire area.—When asked if the dam has been maintained as well under English rule as it was before, he said, From what he knows, he can't say, but based on everything he has read or heard about the past wealth and success of the Tanjore kings, he would assume not.—When asked if he knew of multiple attempts to prevent repairs and even damage the structure, he said, The Rajah often complained about this to him, and he has also heard it from others in Tanjore.—When asked who was behind those violent acts, he said he was told it was the residents of the Nabob's territory near the Anicut.—When asked if they were encouraged or provoked by the Nabob, he answered, The Rajah said they were.—And when asked what actions the President and Council took to punish those responsible and prevent such violence, he said, To the best of his recollection, the Governor told him he would look into it, but he doesn’t know if any inquiries were actually made; that Sir Thomas Rumbold, the Governor, informed him he had presented his concerns regarding the Anicut to the Nabob, who denied that his people had disrupted the repairs on that project.


10th May.

May 10.

Being asked, What he thinks the real clear receipt of the revenues of Tanjore were worth when he left it? he said, He cannot say what was the net amount, as he does not know the expense of the Rajah's collection; but while he was at Tanjore, he understood from the Rajah himself, and from his ministers, that the gross collection did not exceed nine lacs of pagodas (360,000l.).—Being asked, Whether he thinks the country could pay the eight lacs of pagodas which had been demanded to be paid in the course of one year? he said, Clearly not.—Being asked, Whether there was not an attempt made to remove the Rajah's minister, upon some delay in payment of the deposit? he said, The Governor of Madras wrote to that effect, which he represented to the Rajah.—Being asked, Who was mentioned to succeed to the minister that then was, in case he should be removed? he said, When Sir Hector Munro came afterwards to Tanjore, the old daubiere was mentioned, and recommended to the Rajah as successor to his then dewan.—Being asked, Of what age was the daubiere at that time? he said, Of a very great age: upwards of fourscore.—Being asked, Whether a person called Kanonga Saba Pilla was not likewise named? he said, Yes, he was: he was recommended by Sir Thomas Rumbold; and one recommendation, as well as I can recollect, went through me.—Being asked, What was the reason of his being recommended? he said, He undertook to pay off the Rajah's debts, and to give security for the regular payment of the Rajah's instalments to the Company.—Being asked, Whether he offered to give any security for preserving the country from oppression, and for supporting the dignity of the Rajah and his people? he said, He does not know that he did, or that it was asked of him.—Being asked, Whether he was a person agreeable to the Rajah? he said, He was not.—Being asked, Whether he was not a person who had fled out of the country to avoid the resentment of the Rajah? he said, He was.—Being asked, Whether he was not charged by the Rajah with malpractices, and breach of trust relative to his effects? he said, He was; but he told the Governor that he would account for his conduct, and explain everything to the satisfaction of the Rajah.—Being asked, Whether the Rajah did not consider this man as in the interest of his enemies, and particularly of the Nabob of Arcot and Mr. Benfield? he said, He does not recollect that he did mention that to him: he remembers to have heard him complain of a transaction between Kanonga Saba Pilla and Mr. Benfield; but he told him he had been guilty of a variety of malpractices in his administration, that he had oppressed the people, and defrauded him.—Being asked, In what branch of business the Rajah had formerly employed him? he said, He was at one time, he believes, renter of the whole country, was supposed to have great influence with the Rajah, and was in fact dewan some time.—Being asked, Whether the nomination of that man was not particularly odious to the Rajah? he said, He found the Rajah's mind so exceedingly averse to that man, that he believes he would almost as soon have submitted to his being deposed as to submit to the nomination of that man to be his prime-minister.

When asked what he thinks the actual net revenues of Tanjore were worth when he left, he said he couldn’t specify the net amount because he didn’t know the expenses of the Rajah's collection. However, while he was in Tanjore, he learned from the Rajah and his ministers that the total collection didn’t exceed nine lacs of pagodas (360,000 l). When asked if he thinks the country could pay the eight lacs of pagodas that were demanded to be paid within a year, he said definitely not. When asked about an attempt to remove the Rajah's minister due to a delay in payment of the deposit, he replied that the Governor of Madras wrote to that effect, which he conveyed to the Rajah. When asked who was suggested as a possible successor to the minister if he was removed, he said that when Sir Hector Munro later came to Tanjore, the old daubiere was mentioned and recommended to the Rajah as a replacement for the then dewan. When asked about the age of the daubiere at that time, he said he was quite old—over eighty. When asked if a person named Kanonga Saba Pilla was also mentioned, he confirmed that he was and that he was recommended by Sir Thomas Rumbold; he recalled that one of the recommendations came through him. When asked why he was recommended, he said it was because he promised to pay off the Rajah's debts and provide security for the regular payment of the Rajah's instalments to the Company. When asked if he offered any security to protect the country from oppression and maintain the dignity of the Rajah and his people, he said he didn’t know if he did that or if it was requested of him. When asked if he was someone agreeable to the Rajah, he said he was not. When asked if he was someone who had fled the country to avoid the Rajah's wrath, he confirmed that he was. When asked if the Rajah charged him with misconduct and breach of trust regarding his property, he responded that he was but he told the Governor he would explain his actions and clarify everything to the Rajah's satisfaction. When asked if the Rajah considered this man as aligned with his enemies, especially the Nabob of Arcot and Mr. Benfield, he said he didn’t recall the Rajah mentioning that; however, he remembered hearing him complain about a deal between Kanonga Saba Pilla and Mr. Benfield, saying he had committed various misdeeds during his administration that led to the oppression of the people and defrauding the Rajah. When asked what kind of business the Rajah previously employed him in, he said he believed he was once the renter of the whole country and was thought to have significant influence with the Rajah, and he actually served as dewan for a while. When asked if the nomination of that man was particularly disliked by the Rajah, he said he found the Rajah extremely against that man, to the point that he believed the Rajah would prefer to accept his own deposition rather than endorse that man as his prime minister.


13th May.

May 13th.

Mr. Petrie being asked, Whether he was informed by the Rajah, or by others, at Tanjore or Madras, that Mr. Benfield, whilst he managed the revenues at Tanjore, during the usurpation of the Nabob, did not treat the inhabitants with great rigor? he said, He did hear from the Rajah that Mr. Benfield did treat the inhabitants with rigor during the time he had anything to do with the administration of the revenues of Tanjore.—Being asked, If he recollects in what particulars? he said, The Rajah particularly complained that grain had been delivered out to the inhabitants, for the purposes of cultivation, at a higher price than the market price of grain in the country; he cannot say the actual difference of price, but it struck him at the time as something very considerable.—Being asked, Whether that money was all recovered from the inhabitants? he said, The Rajah of Tanjore told him that the money was all recovered from the inhabitants.—Being asked, Whether he did not hear that the Nabob exacted from the country of Tanjore, whilst he was in possession of it? he said, From the accounts which he received at Tanjore of the revenues for a number of years past, it appeared that the Nabob collected from the country, while he was in possession, rather more than sixteen lacs of pagodas annually; whereas, when he was at Tanjore, it did not yield more than nine lacs.—Being asked, From whence that difference arose? he said, When Tanjore was conquered for the Nabob, he has been told that many thousand of the native inhabitants fled from the country, some into the country of Mysore, and others into the dominions of the Mahrattas; he understood from the same authority, that, while the Nabob was in possession of the country, many inhabitants from the Carnatic, allured by the superior fertility and opulence of Tanjore, and encouraged by the Nabob, took up their residence there, which enabled the Nabob to cultivate the whole country; and upon the restoration of the Rajah, he has heard that the Carnatic inhabitants were carried back to their own country, which left a considerable blank in the population, which was not replaced while he was there, principally owing to an opinion which prevailed through the country that the Rajah's government was not to be permanent, but that another revolution was fast approaching. During the Nabob's government, the price of grain was considerably higher (owing to a very unusual scarcity in the Carnatic) than when he was in Tanjore.—Being asked, Whether he was ever in the Marawar country? he said, Yes; he was commissary to the army in that expedition.—Being asked, Whether that country was much wasted by the war? he said, Plunder was not permitted to the army, nor did the country suffer from its operations, except in causing many thousands of the inhabitants, who had been employed in the cultivation of the country, to leave it.—Being asked, Whether he knows what is done with the palace and inhabitants of Ramnaut? he said, The town was taken by storm, but not plundered by the troops; it was immediately delivered up to the Nabob's eldest son.—Being asked, Whether great riches were not supposed to be in that palace and temple? he said, It was universally believed so.—Being asked, What account was given of them? he said, He cannot tell; everything remained in the possession of the Nabob.—Being asked, What became of the children and women of the family of the prince of that country? he said, The Rajah was a minor; the government was in the hands of the Ranny, his mother: from general report he has heard they were carried to Trichinopoly, and placed in confinement there.—Being asked, Whether he perceived any difference in the face of the Carnatic when he first knew it and when he last knew it? he said, He thinks he did, particularly in its population.—Being asked, Whether it was better or worse? he said, It was not so populous.—Being asked, What is the condition of the Nabob's eldest son? he said, He was in the Black Town of Madras, when he left the country.—Being asked, Whether he was entertained there in a manner suitable to his birth and expectations? he said, No: he lived there without any of those exterior marks of splendor which princes of his rank in India are particularly fond of.—Being asked, Whether he has not heard that his appointments were poor and mean? he said, He has heard that they were not equal to his rank and expectations.—Being asked, Whether he had any share in the government? he said, He believes none: for some years past the Nabob has delegated most of the powers of government to his second son.—Being asked, Whether the Rajah did not complain to him of the behavior of Mr. Benfield to himself personally; and what were the particulars? he said, He did so, and related to him the following particulars. About fifteen days after Lord Pigot's confinement, Mr. Benfield came to Tanjore, and delivered the Rajah two letters from the then Governor, Mr. Stratton,—one public, and the other private. He demanded an immediate account of the presents which had been made to Lord Pigot, payment of the tunkahs which he (Mr. Benfield) had received from the Nabob upon the country, and that the Rajah should only write such letters to the Madras government as Mr. Benfield should approve and give to him. The Rajah answered, that he did not acknowledge the validity of any demands made by the Nabob upon the country; that those tunkahs related to accounts which he (the Rajah) had no concern with; that he never had given Lord Pigot any presents, but Lord Pigot had given him many; and that as to his correspondence with the Madras government, he would not trouble Mr. Benfield, because he would write his letters himself. That the Rajah told the witness, that by reason of this answer he was much threatened, in consequence of which he desired Colonel Harper, who then commanded at Tanjore, to be present at his next interview with Mr. Benfield; when Mr. Benfield denied many parts of the preceding conversation, and threw the blame upon his interpreter, Comroo. When Mr. Benfield found (as the Rajah informed him) that he could not carry these points which had brought him to Tanjore, he prepared to set off for Madras; that the Rajah sent him a letter which he had drawn out in answer to one which Mr. Benfield had brought him; that Mr. Benfield disapproved of the answer, and returned it by Comroo to the durbar, who did not deliver it into the Rajah's hands, but threw it upon the ground, and expressed himself improperly to him.

Mr. Petrie was asked whether he was informed by the Rajah or by others at Tanjore or Madras that Mr. Benfield, while managing the revenues at Tanjore during the Nabob's usurpation, treated the residents harshly. He replied that he heard from the Rajah that Mr. Benfield did treat the inhabitants harshly during his administration of Tanjore's revenues. When asked if he remembered the specifics, he said the Rajah complained that grain was provided to the residents for cultivation at a higher price than the market price in the area; he couldn't recall the exact price difference, but it struck him as significant at the time. He was then asked if that money was fully recovered from the residents, to which he said the Rajah told him that all the money was indeed recovered. When asked if he heard that the Nabob collected money from Tanjore while in control, he stated that based on past accounts of the revenues, it seemed the Nabob collected over sixteen lacs of pagodas annually, whereas during his time in Tanjore, it yielded only nine lacs. When asked where that difference came from, he explained that after the Nabob conquered Tanjore, he was told many native inhabitants fled, some to Mysore and others to the Mahratta territories. He also understood from that same source that many inhabitants from the Carnatic, attracted by Tanjore's fertility and wealth and encouraged by the Nabob, settled there, which allowed the Nabob to farm the entire region. He had heard that once the Rajah was restored, many of the Carnatic residents were taken back to their homeland, leaving a significant population gap that wasn't filled while he was there, mainly due to a widespread belief that the Rajah’s government wouldn’t last and that another upheaval was imminent. Under the Nabob's government, grain prices were considerably higher than when he was in Tanjore, due to an unusual scarcity in the Carnatic. When asked if he had ever been in the Marawar region, he confirmed that he was a commissary for the army during that expedition. When questioned if the war devastated that country, he said there was no plunder allowed, and the area didn't suffer from military actions, aside from causing many thousands of laborers, who worked the land, to leave. When asked about the palace and residents of Ramnaut, he responded that the town was taken by storm but not plundered by the troops; it was immediately turned over to the Nabob's eldest son. When asked if there was believed to be great wealth in that palace and temple, he said it was widely considered so. When asked what was said about it, he replied that he couldn’t say; everything remained in the Nabob's possession. When asked what happened to the prince's family, he stated that the Rajah was a minor, and his mother, the Ranny, was in charge. From general reports, he heard they were taken to Trichinopoly and put under confinement there. When asked if he noticed any difference in the Carnatic’s appearance from when he first knew it to when he last knew it, he indicated there was indeed a difference, particularly regarding its population. When asked whether it was better or worse, he said it was less populated. When asked about the Nabob's eldest son, he mentioned that he was in the Black Town of Madras when he left the region. When asked if he was treated suitably for his status and expectations, he said no; he lived there without the typical signs of luxury that princes of his rank in India usually favoured. When questioned if he heard that his allowances were inadequate and not up to his status, he affirmed that he had heard they were not sufficient. When asked if he had any role in the government, he said he believed he had none, as the Nabob had delegated most of his governmental powers to his second son for several years. When asked whether the Rajah complained to him about Mr. Benfield’s personal conduct and what the specifics were, he stated that he did, sharing the following details. About fifteen days after Lord Pigot's confinement, Mr. Benfield came to Tanjore and delivered two letters to the Rajah from the Governor, Mr. Stratton—one public and one private. He demanded an immediate account of the gifts made to Lord Pigot, payment of the tunkahs he (Mr. Benfield) had received from the Nabob on the country, and that the Rajah only write letters to the Madras government that Mr. Benfield approved and provided to him. The Rajah replied that he did not recognize the validity of any demands made by the Nabob upon the country; that those tunkahs related to matters he had nothing to do with; that he never gave Lord Pigot any gifts, but that Lord Pigot had given him many; and that as for his correspondence with the Madras government, he would not trouble Mr. Benfield because he would write his letters himself. The Rajah informed the witness that because of this response, he felt heavily threatened, which led him to ask Colonel Harper, who was in charge at Tanjore, to be present during his next meeting with Mr. Benfield. During this meeting, Mr. Benfield denied many aspects of the previous conversation and blamed it on his interpreter, Comroo. When Mr. Benfield learned (as the Rajah informed him) that he couldn't achieve the objectives that brought him to Tanjore, he prepared to leave for Madras; the Rajah sent him a letter he drafted in response to one that Mr. Benfield had brought him. Mr. Benfield disapproved of the reply, returned it via Comroo to the durbar, who did not hand it to the Rajah but instead tossed it on the ground and made inappropriate remarks to him.

Being asked, Whether it was at the king of Tanjore's desire, that such persons as Mr. Benfield and Comroo had been brought into his presence? he said, The Rajah told him, that, when Lord Pigot came to Tanjore, to restore him to his dominions, Comroo, without being sent for, or desired to come to the palace, had found means to get access to his person: he made an offer of introducing Mr. Benfield to the Rajah, which he declined.—Being asked, Whether the military officer commanding there protected the Rajah from the intrusion of such people? he said, The Rajah did not tell him that he called upon the military officer to prevent these intrusions, but that he desired Colonel Harper to be present as a witness to what might pass between him and Mr. Benfield.—Being asked, If it is usual for persons of the conditions and occupations of Mr. Benfield and Comroo to intrude themselves into the presence of the princes of the country, and to treat them with such freedom? he said, Certainly it is not: less there than in any other country.—Being asked, Whether the king of Tanjore has no ministers to whom application might be made to transact such business as Mr. Benfield and Comroo had to do in the country? he said, Undoubtedly: his minister is the person whose province it is to transact that business.—Being asked, Before the invasion of the British troops into Tanjore, what would have been the consequence, if Mr. Benfield had intruded himself into the Rajah's presence, and behaved in that manner? he said, He could not say what would have been the consequence; but the attempt would have been madness, and could not have happened.—Being asked, Whether the Rajah had not particular exceptions to Comroo, and thought he had betrayed him in very essential points? he said, Yes, he had.—Being asked, Whether the Rajah has not been apprised that the Company have made stipulations that their servants should not interfere in the concerns of his government? he said, He signified it to the Rajah, that it was the Company's positive orders, and that any of their servants so interfering would incur their highest displeasure.

When asked if it was at the king of Tanjore's request that people like Mr. Benfield and Comroo were brought to see him, he replied that the Rajah told him that when Lord Pigot came to Tanjore to restore him to his lands, Comroo, without being invited or asked to come to the palace, managed to gain access to him. Comroo offered to introduce Mr. Benfield to the Rajah, but the Rajah declined. When asked if the military officer in charge was protecting the Rajah from such intrusions, he said the Rajah didn’t mention he had called upon the military officer to stop these intrusions, but he did want Colonel Harper present as a witness to what might happen between him and Mr. Benfield. When asked if it’s common for people like Mr. Benfield and Comroo to intrude upon the princes of the country and treat them so casually, he responded that it definitely is not: it’s less acceptable here than in any other country. When asked if the king of Tanjore has no ministers who could handle the business Mr. Benfield and Comroo had in the country, he said undoubtedly he does; his minister is responsible for that. When asked what the consequences would have been if Mr. Benfield had intruded upon the Rajah before the British troops invaded Tanjore and behaved that way, he said he couldn’t predict the outcome, but the attempt would have been madness and could not have happened. When asked if the Rajah had specific issues with Comroo and believed he had betrayed him in critical ways, he said yes, he did. When asked if the Rajah had been informed that the Company had made agreements that their servants should not interfere in his government, he said he made it clear to the Rajah that it was the Company’s strict orders, and that any of their servants doing so would face severe consequences.


No. 8.

Referred to from p. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, etc.

Commissioners' Amended Clauses for the Fort St. George Dispatch, relative to the Indeterminate Mights and Pretensions of the Nabob of Arcot and Rajah of Tanjore.

In our letter of the 28th January last we stated the reasonableness of our expectation that certain contributions towards the expenses of the war should be made by the Rajah of Tanjore. Since writing that letter, we have received one from the Rajah, of the 15th of October last, which contains at length his representations of his inability to make such further payment. We think it unnecessary here to discuss whether these representations are or are not exaggerated, because, from the explanations we have given of our wishes for a new arrangement in future, both with the Nabob of Arcot and the Rajah of Tanjore, and the directions we have given you to carry that arrangement into execution, we think it impolitic to insist upon any demands upon the Rajah for the expenses of the late war, beyond the sum of four lacs of pagodas annually: such a demand might tend to interrupt the harmony which should prevail between the Company and the Rajah, and impede the great objects of the general system we have already so fully explained to you.

In our letter dated January 28th, we mentioned our reasonable expectation that certain contributions towards the war expenses should be made by the Rajah of Tanjore. Since then, we've received a letter from the Rajah, dated October 15th, which details his reasons for being unable to make further payments. We believe it's unnecessary to debate whether his reasons are exaggerated, because based on the explanations we've provided regarding our desire for a new arrangement in the future with both the Nabob of Arcot and the Rajah of Tanjore, along with the instructions we've given you to implement that arrangement, we think it's unwise to demand any further contributions from the Rajah for the expenses of the recent war, beyond the amount of four lacs of pagodas per year. Such a demand could disrupt the harmony that should exist between the Company and the Rajah and hinder the key objectives of the overall system we've explained to you.

But although it is not our opinion that any further claim should be made on the Rajah for his share of the extraordinary expenses of the late war, it is by no means our intention in any manner to affect the just claim which the Nabob has on the Rajah for the arrears due to him on account of peshcush, for the regular payment of which we became guaranty by the treaty of 1762; but we have already expressed to you our hopes that the Nabob may be induced to allow these arrears and the growing payments, when due, to be received by the Company, and carried in discharge of his debt to us. You are at the same time to use every means to convince him, that, when this debt shall be discharged, it is our intention, as we are bound by the above treaty, to exert ourselves to the utmost of our power to insure the constant and regular payment of it into his own hands.

But while we don't think any further claims should be made on the Rajah for his share of the extra costs from the recent war, we also don't want to affect the valid claim that the Nabob has on the Rajah for the overdue peshcush payments, for which we became guarantors by the treaty of 1762. We've already shared our hopes that the Nabob can be persuaded to let the Company receive these overdue payments and the future payments as they come due, to offset his debt to us. At the same time, you should do everything you can to assure him that once this debt is cleared, it is our intention, as stipulated in the treaty, to do our utmost to ensure the constant and regular payment of it directly into his hands.

We observe, by the plan sent to us by our Governor of Fort St. George, on the 30th October, 1781, that an arrangement is there proposed for the receipt of those arrears from the Rajah in three years.

We see from the plan sent to us by our Governor of Fort St. George on October 30, 1781, that there is a proposal for receiving those overdue payments from the Rajah over the next three years.

We are unable to decide how far this proposal may be consistent with the present state of the Rajah's resources; but we direct you to use all proper means to bring these arrears to account as soon as possible, consistently with a due attention to this consideration.

We can't determine how this proposal aligns with the current state of the Rajah's resources; however, we instruct you to use all appropriate methods to resolve these overdue payments as soon as possible, while keeping this consideration in mind.

CLAUSES H.

You will observe, that, by the 38th section of the late act of Parliament, it is enacted, that, for settling upon a permanent foundation the present indeterminate rights of the Nabob of Arcot and the Rajah of Tanjore with respect to each other, we should take into our immediate consideration the said indeterminate rights and pretensions, and take and pursue such measures as in our judgment and discretion shall be best calculated to ascertain and settle the same, according to the principles and the terms and stipulations contained in the treaty of 1762 between the said Nabob and the said Rajah.

You will see that, according to the 38th section of the recent act of Parliament, it is stated that, in order to establish a permanent framework for the current unclear rights of the Nabob of Arcot and the Rajah of Tanjore concerning each other, we should urgently address these unclear rights and claims, and take and implement such actions as we believe are best suited to clarify and resolve them, based on the principles, terms, and agreements outlined in the treaty of 1762 between the Nabob and the Rajah.

On a retrospect of the proceedings transmitted to us from your Presidency, on the subject of the disputes which have heretofore arisen between the Nabob and the Rajah, we find the following points remain unadjusted, viz.

Looking back at the proceedings sent to us from your Presidency about the disputes that have come up between the Nabob and the Rajah, we see that the following points are still unresolved, namely:

1st, Whether the jaghire of Arnee shall be enjoyed by the Nabob, or delivered up, either to the Rajah, or the descendants of Tremaul Row, the late jaghiredar.

1st, Whether the jaghire of Arnee will be kept by the Nabob or handed over to either the Rajah or the descendants of Tremaul Row, the late jaghiredar.

2d, Whether the fort and district of Hanamantagoody, which is admitted by both parties to be within the Marawar, ought to be possessed by the Nabob, or to be delivered up by him to the Rajah.

2d, Whether the fort and area of Hanamantagoody, which is acknowledged by both sides to be in the Marawar, should belong to the Nabob or be handed over by him to the Rajah.

3rd, To whom the government share of the crop of the Tanjore country, of the year 1775-6, properly belongs.

3rd, To whom the government’s share of the crop from the Tanjore region for the year 1775-6 rightfully belongs.

Lastly, Whether the Rajah has a right, by usage and custom, or ought, from the necessity of the case, to be permitted to repair such part of the Anicut, or dam and banks of the Cavery, as lie within the district of Trichinopoly, and to take earth and sand in the Trichinopoly territory for the repairs of the dam and banks within either or both of those districts.

Lastly, whether the Rajah has the right, based on usage and custom, or should, due to necessity, be allowed to repair any part of the Anicut, or dam and banks of the Cavery, that lies within the Trichinopoly district, and to take earth and sand from the Trichinopoly area for the repairs of the dam and banks in either or both of those districts.

In order to obtain a complete knowledge of the facts and circumstances relative to the several points in dispute, and how far they are connected with the treaty of 1762, we have with great circumspection examined into all the materials before us on these subjects, and will proceed to state to you the result of our inquiries and deliberations.

To fully understand the facts and situations regarding the various points of disagreement and their connection to the treaty of 1762, we have carefully reviewed all the information we have on these topics and will now share the outcome of our investigations and discussions with you.

The objects of the treaty of 1762 appear to be restricted to the arrears of tribute to be paid to the Nabob for his past claims, and to the quantum of the Rajah's future tribute or peshcush; the cancelling of a certain bond given by the Rajah's father to the father of the Nabob; the confirmation to the Rajah of the districts of Coveladdy and Elangaud, and the restoration of Tremaul Row to his jaghire of Arnee, in condescension to the Rajah's request, upon certain stipulations, viz., that the fort of Arnee and Doby Gudy should be retained by the Nabob; that Tremaul Row should not erect any fortress, walled pagoda, or other stronghold, nor any wall round his dwelling-house exceeding eight feet high or two feet thick, and should in all things behave himself with due obedience to the government; and that he should pay yearly, in the month of July, unto the Nabob or his successors, the sum of ten thousand rupees: the Rajah thereby becoming the security for Tremaul Row, that he should in all things demean and behave himself accordingly, and pay yearly the stipulated sum.

The treaty of 1762 seems mainly focused on the outstanding tribute owed to the Nabob for his previous claims, as well as the amount of future tribute or peshcush that the Rajah will need to pay. It includes the cancellation of a bond that the Rajah's father had given to the Nabob's father, confirms the Rajah's ownership of the districts of Coveladdy and Elangaud, and returns Tremaul Row to his jaghire of Arnee at the Rajah's request, under certain conditions. These conditions are that the Nabob will keep control of the forts at Arnee and Doby Gudy, that Tremaul Row cannot build any fortifications, walled pagoda, or any other stronghold, and cannot have a wall around his house that is taller than eight feet or thicker than two feet . He must also act in accordance with the government and pay the Nabob or his successors ten thousand rupees each July. The Rajah will guarantee that Tremaul Row will follow these terms and pay the agreed amount yearly.

Upon a review of this treaty, the only point now in dispute, which appears to us to be so immediately connected with it as to bring it within the strict line of our duty to ascertain and settle according to the terms and stipulations of the treaty, is that respecting Arnee. For, although the other points enumerated may in some respects have a relation to that treaty, yet, as they are foreign to the purposes expressed in it, and could not be in the contemplation of the contracting parties at the time of making it, those disputes cannot in our comprehension fall within the line of description of rights and pretensions to be now ascertained and settled by us, according to any of the terms and stipulations of it.

After reviewing this treaty, the only issue currently in dispute that seems directly related to it, and which we believe falls under our responsibility to clarify and resolve according to the treaty's terms and conditions, is the matter concerning Arnee. While the other issues listed may relate to the treaty in some ways, they are not aligned with the purposes stated in it and were likely not envisioned by the parties involved when it was created. Therefore, these disputes don't seem to fit within our scope of determining and resolving rights and claims based on the treaty’s terms and conditions.

In respect to the jaghire of Arnee, we do not find that our records afford us any satisfactory information by what title the Rajah claims it, or what degree of relationship or connection has subsisted between the Rajah and the Killadar of Arnee, save only that by the treaty of 1762 the former became the surety for Tremaul Row's performance of his engagements specified therein, as the conditions for his restoration to that jaghire; on the death of Tremaul Row, we perceive that he was succeeded by his widow, and after her death, by his grandson Seneewasarow, both of whom were admitted to the jaghire by the Nabob.

Regarding the jaghire of Arnee, our records don’t provide clear information about the title the Rajah uses to claim it, or what kind of relationship or connection exists between the Rajah and the Killadar of Arnee. The only detail we have is that, by the treaty of 1762, the Rajah became the guarantor for Tremaul Row's obligations outlined in that treaty, which were conditions for his return to that jaghire. After Tremaul Row died, his widow succeeded him, and following her death, his grandson Seneewasarow took over, both of whom were allowed to hold the jaghire by the Nabob.

From your Minutes of Consultation of the 31st October, 1770, and the Nabob's letter to the President of the 21st March, 1771, and the two letters from Rajah Beerbur Atchenur Punt (who we presume was then the Nabob's manager at Arcot) of the 16th and 18th March, referred to in the Nabob's letter, and transmitted therewith to the President, we observe, that, previous to the treaty of 1762, Mr. Pigot concurred in the expediency of the Nabob's taking possession of this jaghire, on account of the troublesome and refractory behavior of the Arnee braminees, by their affording protection to all disturbers, who, by reason of the little distance between Arnee and Arcot, fled to the former, and were there protected, and not given up, though demanded;—that, though the jaghire was restored in 1762, it was done under such conditions and restrictions as were thought best calculated to preserve the peace and good order of the place and due obedience to government;—that, nevertheless, the braminees (quarrelling among themselves) did afterwards, in express violation of the treaty, enlist and assemble many thousand sepoys, and other troops; that they erected gaddies and other small forts, provided themselves with wall-pieces, small guns, and other warlike stores, and raised troubles and disturbances in the neighborhood of the city of Arcot and the forts of Arnee and Shaw Gaddy; and that, finally, they imprisoned the hircarrahs of the Nabob, sent with his letters and instructions, in pursuance of the advice of your board, to require certain of the braminees to repair to the Nabob at Chepauk, and, though peremptorily required to repair thither, paid no regard to those, or to any other orders from the circar.

From your Minutes of Consultation from October 31st, 1770, the Nabob's letter to the President dated March 21st, 1771, and the two letters from Rajah Beerbur Atchenur Punt (who we assume was the Nabob's manager in Arcot) dated March 16th and 18th, referred to in the Nabob's letter and sent to the President, we note that prior to the treaty of 1762, Mr. Pigot agreed it was necessary for the Nabob to take control of this jaghire due to the troublesome and defiant behavior of the Arnee braminees, who provided protection to all troublemakers. Because of the close proximity between Arnee and Arcot, these troublemakers fled to Arnee for refuge and were not handed over, despite demands. Although the jaghire was restored in 1762, it was returned under conditions and restrictions deemed necessary to maintain peace, good order, and proper obedience to the government. Despite this, the braminees, conflicting among themselves, later violated the treaty by recruiting and gathering many thousands of sepoys and other troops. They built gaddies and other small forts, equipped themselves with wall pieces, small guns, and other military supplies, causing unrest and disturbances around the city of Arcot and the forts of Arnee and Shaw Gaddy. Ultimately, they imprisoned the hircarrahs of the Nabob, who were sent with his letters and instructions, following your board's directive, to order certain braminees to meet with the Nabob at Chepauk. Despite being firmly instructed to go there, they ignored those orders and any others from the circar.

By the 13th article contained in the instructions given by the Nabob to Mr. Dupré, as the basis for negotiating the treaty made with the Rajah in 1771, the Nabob required that the Arnee district should be delivered up to the circar, because the braminees had broken the conditions which they were to have observed. In the answers given by the Rajah to these propositions, he says, "I am to give up to the circar the jaghire district of Arnee"; and on the 7th of November, 1771, the Rajah, by letter to Seneewasarow, who appears by your Consultations and country correspondence to have been the grandson of Tremaul Row, and to have been put in possession of the jaghire at your recommendation, (on the death of his grandmother,) writes, acquainting him that he had given the Arnee country, then in his (Seneewasarow's) possession, to the Nabob, to whose aumildars Seneewasarow was to deliver up the possession of the country. And in your letter to us of the 28th February, 1772, you certified the district of Arnee to be one of the countries acquired by this treaty, and to be of the estimated value of two lacs of rupees per annum.

By the 13th article in the instructions given by the Nabob to Mr. Dupré, which served as the foundation for the treaty negotiated with the Rajah in 1771, the Nabob required that the Arnee district be handed over to the circar because the bramines had violated the conditions they were meant to uphold. In his response to these proposals, the Rajah stated, "I will surrender the jaghire district of Arnee to the circar"; and on November 7, 1771, the Rajah wrote a letter to Seneewasarow, who, according to your Consultations and correspondence, seems to have been the grandson of Tremaul Row and was granted the jaghire at your suggestion following his grandmother's death, informing him that he had transferred the Arnee territory, which was then under Seneewasarow's control, to the Nabob, to whom Seneewasarow was to surrender possession of the region. In your letter to us dated February 28, 1772, you confirmed that the Arnee district was one of the territories acquired through this treaty and was valued at an estimated two lacs of rupees per year.

In our orders dated the 12th of April, 1775, we declared our determination to replace the Rajah upon the throne of his ancestors, upon certain terms and conditions, to be agreed upon for the mutual benefit of himself and the Company, without infringing the rights of the Nabob. We declared that our faith stood pledged by the treaty of 1762 to obtain payment of the Rajah's tribute to the Nabob, and that for the insuring such payment the fort of Tanjore should be garrisoned by our troops. We directed that you should pay no regard to the article of the treaty of 1771 which respected the alienation of part of the Rajah's dominions; and we declared, that, if the Nabob had not a just title to those territories before the conclusion of the treaty, we denied that he obtained any right thereby, except such temporary sovereignty, for securing the payment of his expenses, as is therein mentioned.

In our orders dated April 12, 1775, we announced our decision to restore the Rajah to the throne of his ancestors, based on certain terms and conditions that would benefit both him and the Company, while respecting the rights of the Nabob. We stated that our commitment was guaranteed by the treaty of 1762 to secure the payment of the Rajah's tribute to the Nabob, and to ensure that payment, the fort of Tanjore would be occupied by our troops. We instructed that you should ignore article of the treaty of 1771 concerning the transfer of part of the Rajah's territories; and we asserted that if the Nabob did not have a rightful claim to those territories before the treaty was finalized, then he did not gain any rights from it, except for the temporary authority mentioned there, which was solely for covering his expenses.

These instructions appear to have been executed in the month of April, 1776; and by your letter of the 14th May following you certified to us that the Rajah had been put into the possession of the whole country his father held in 1762, when the treaty was concluded with the Nabob; but we do not find that you came to any resolution, either antecedent or subsequent to this advice, either for questioning or impeaching the right of the Nabob to the sovereignty of Arnee, or expressive of any doubt of his title to it. Nevertheless, we find, that, although the Board passed no such resolution, yet your President, in his letter to the Nabob of the 30th July and 24th August, called upon his Highness to give up the possession of Arnee to the Rajah; and the Rajah himself, in several letters to us, particularly in those of 21st October, 1776, and the 7th of June, 1777, expressed his expectation of our orders for delivering up that fort and district to him; and so recently as the 15th of October, 1783, he reminds us of his former application, and states, that the country of Arnee being guarantied to him by the Company, it of course is his right, but that it has not been given up to him, and he therefore earnestly entreats our orders for putting him into the possession of it. We also observe by your letter of the 14th of October, 1779, that the Rajah had not then accounted for the Nabob's peshcush since his restoration, but had assigned as a reason for his withdrawing it, that the Nabob had retained from him the district of Arnee, with a certain other district, (Hanamantagoody,) which is made the subject of another part of our present dispatches.

These instructions seem to have been carried out in April 1776; and in your letter dated May 14th of the following year, you confirmed that the Rajah had taken possession of all the land his father held in 1762, when the treaty was signed with the Nabob. However, we don't see any resolution from you, either before or after this information, questioning or challenging the Nabob's right to the sovereignty of Arnee, nor expressing any doubt about his title to it. Still, we note that although the Board did not pass any such resolution, your President, in his letters to the Nabob on July 30th and August 24th, urged His Highness to surrender control of Arnee to the Rajah. The Rajah himself, in several letters to us, particularly on October 21st, 1776, and June 7th, 1777, conveyed his expectation of our orders to hand over that fort and region to him. As recently as October 15th, 1783, he reminded us of his earlier request and stated that since the Company guaranteed the country of Arnee to him, it is naturally his right, but it has not yet been handed over to him. Therefore, he earnestly requests our orders to put him in possession of it. We also note from your letter dated October 14th, 1779, that the Rajah had not accounted for the Nabob's peshcush since his restoration, claiming that he withheld it because the Nabob had kept the district of Arnee along with another district, Hanamantagoody, which is addressed in another section of our current dispatches.

We have thus stated to you the result of our inquiry into the grounds of the dispute relative to Arnee; and as the research has offered no evidence in support of the Rajah's claim, nor even any lights whereby we can discover in what degree of relationship, by consanguinity, caste, or other circumstances, the Rajah now stands, or formerly stood, with the Killadar of Arnee, or the nature of his connection with or command over that district, or the authority he exercised or assumed previous to the treaty of 1771, we should think ourselves highly reprehensible in complying with the Rajah's request,—and the more so, as it is expressly stated, in the treaty of 1762, that this fort and district were then in the possession of the Nabob, as well as the person of the jaghiredar, on account of his disobedience, and were restored him by the Nabob, in condescension to the Rajah's request, upon such terms and stipulations as could not, in our judgment, have been imposed by the one or submitted to by the other, if the sovereignty of the one or the dependency of the other had been at that time a matter of doubt.

We have laid out the findings of our investigation into the reasons behind the dispute concerning Arnee. Since our research found no evidence to support the Rajah's claim, nor any information that reveals the nature of his relationship—whether by blood, caste, or other factors—with the Killadar of Arnee, or his connection to that area, or the authority he had before the treaty of 1771, we would consider it wrong to meet the Rajah's request. This is especially true given that the treaty of 1762 explicitly states that this fort and district were under the control of the Nabob, along with the jaghiredar, due to his disobedience, and were later returned to him by the Nabob in response to the Rajah's request, under terms that, in our view, wouldn’t have been imposed or accepted if there had been any doubt about the sovereignty of one or the dependency of the other.

Although these materials have not furnished us with evidence in support of the Rajah's claim, they are far from satisfactory to evince the justice of or the political necessity for the Nabob's continuing to withhold the jaghire from the descendants of Tremaul Row; his hereditary right to that jaghire seems to us to have been fully recognized by the stipulations of the treaty of 1762, and so little doubted, that, on his death, his widow was admitted by the Nabob to hold it, on account, as may be presumed, of the nonage of his grandson and heir, Seneewasarow, who appears to have been confirmed in the jaghire, on her death, by the Nabob, as the lineal heir and successor to his grandfather.

Although these materials haven't provided us with evidence supporting the Rajah's claim, they don't satisfactorily show the justice of or the political need for the Nabob to continue denying the jaghire to the descendants of Tremaul Row. His hereditary right to that jaghire seems to have been fully acknowledged by the terms of the treaty of 1762, and it was so little questioned that, upon his death, his widow was allowed by the Nabob to hold it, likely because of the youth of his grandson and heir, Seneewasarow, who appears to have been confirmed in the jaghire by the Nabob upon her death as the direct heir and successor to his grandfather.

With respect to Seneewasarow, it does not appear, by any of the Proceedings in our possession, that he was concerned in the misconduct of the braminees, complained of by the Nabob in the year 1770, which rendered it necessary for his Highness to take the jaghire into his own hands, or that he was privy to or could have prevented those disturbances.

Regarding Seneewasarow, it doesn't seem, based on the Proceedings we have, that he was involved in the misconduct of the bramines, which the Nabob complained about in 1770, leading to his Highness taking over the jaghire, nor that he knew about or could have stopped those disturbances.

We therefore direct, that, if the heir of Tremaul Row is not at present in possession of the jaghire, and has not, by any violation of the treaty, or act of disobedience, incurred a forfeiture thereof, he be forthwith restored to the possession of it, according to the terms and stipulations of the treaty of 1762. But if any powerful motive of regard to the peace and tranquillity of the Carnatic shall in your judgment render it expedient to suspend the execution of these orders, in that case you are with all convenient speed to transmit to us your proceedings thereupon, with the full state of the facts, and of the reasons which have actuated your conduct.

We therefore order that if the heir of Tremaul Row is currently not in possession of the jaghire and has not violated the treaty or acted disobediently to forfeit it, he should be promptly restored to it based on the terms and conditions of the treaty of 1762. However, if you believe that there are important reasons related to the peace and stability of the Carnatic that make it necessary to delay these orders, then you are to inform us as quickly as possible about your actions, along with a complete account of the facts and the reasons behind your decisions.

We have before given it as our opinion that the stipulations of the treaty of 1762 do not apply to the points remaining to be decided. But the late act of Parliament having, from the nature of our connection with the two powers in the Carnatic, pointed out the expediency, and even necessity, of settling the several matters in dispute between them by a speedy and permanent arrangement, we now proceed to give you our instructions upon, the several other heads of disputes before enumerated.

We have previously stated that the terms of the treaty of 1762 do not apply to the points still under consideration. However, the recent act of Parliament, given our relationship with the two powers in the Carnatic, has highlighted the importance, and even the necessity, of resolving the various matters in dispute between them through a quick and lasting arrangement. Therefore, we are now providing you with our instructions on the other disputes listed earlier.

With respect to the fort and district of Hanamantagoody, we observe, that, on the restoration of the Rajah in 1776, you informed us in your letter of the 14th of May, That the Rajah had been put into possession of the whole of the country his father held in 1762, when the treaty was concluded with the Nabob; and on the 25th of June you came to the resolution of putting the Rajah into possession of Hanamantagoody, on the ground of its appearing, on reference to the Nabob's instructions to Mr. Dupré in June, 1762, to his reply, and to the Rajah's representations of 25th March, 1771, that Hanamantagoody was actually in the hands of the late Rajah at the time of making the treaty of 1762. We have referred as well to those papers as to all the other proceedings on this subject, and must confess they fall very short of demonstrating to us the truth of that fact. And we find, by the Secret Consultations of Fort William of the 7th of August, 1776, that the same doubt was entertained by our Governor-General and Council.

Regarding the fort and district of Hanamantagoody, we note that, following the restoration of the Rajah in 1776, you informed us in your letter dated May 14 that the Rajah had regained control of all the territory his father held in 1762 when the treaty was signed with the Nabob. On June 25, you decided to restore the Rajah's control over Hanamantagoody because it appeared, based on the Nabob's instructions to Mr. Dupré in June 1762, his response, and the Rajah's statements from March 25, 1771, that Hanamantagoody was indeed under the late Rajah's control at the time the 1762 treaty was made. We have reviewed those documents as well as all other related proceedings and must admit they do not sufficiently prove that fact to us. Additionally, we see from the Secret Consultations of Fort William on August 7, 1776, that the same uncertainty was shared by our Governor-General and Council.

But whether, in point of fact, the late Rajah was or was not in possession of Hanamantagoody in 1762, it is notorious that the Nabob had always claimed the dominion of the countries of which this fort and district are a part.

But whether the late Rajah actually had control of Hanamantagoody in 1762 or not, it's well-known that the Nabob always claimed authority over the regions that include this fort and district.

We observe that the Nabob is now in the actual possession of this fort and district; and we are not warranted, by any document we have seen, to concur with the wishes of the Rajah to dispossess him.

We see that the Nabob currently holds this fort and area; and we have no documents to support the Rajah's desire to remove him.

With regard to the government share of the crop of 1775-6, we observe by the dobeer's memorandum, recited in your Consultations of the 13th of May, 1776, that it was the established custom of the Tanjore country to gather in the harvest and complete the collections within the month of March, but that, for the causes therein particularly stated, the harvest (and of course the collection of the government share of the crop) was delayed till the month of March was over. We also observe that the Rajah was not restored to his kingdom until the 11th of April, 1776; and from hence we infer, that, if the harvest and collection had been finished at the usual time, the Nabob (being then sovereign of the country) would have received the full benefit of that year's crop.

Regarding the government’s share of the 1775-6 crop, we note from the dobeer's memorandum mentioned in your consultations on May 13, 1776, that it was the usual practice in the Tanjore region to harvest and complete collections by the end of March. However, due to the specific reasons outlined there, the harvest (and consequently the collection of the government’s share) was postponed until after March. We also note that the Rajah wasn't reinstated to his throne until April 11, 1776; therefore, we can conclude that if the harvest and collection had been completed on time, the Nabob (who was the ruling authority at that time) would have fully benefited from that year’s crop.

Although the harvest and collection were delayed beyond the usual time, yet we find by the Proceedings of your government, and particularly by Mr. Mackay's Minute of the 29th of May, 1776, and also by the dobeer's account, that the greatest part of the grain was cut down whilst the Nabob remained in the government of the country.

Although the harvest and collection were delayed past the usual time, we see from the Proceedings of your government, especially from Mr. Mackay's Minute dated May 29, 1776, and also from the dobeer's account, that most of the grain was harvested while the Nabob was still in charge of the country.

It is difficult, from the contradictory allegations on the subject, to ascertain what was the precise amount of the collections made after the Nabob ceased to have the possession of the country. But whatever it was, it appears from General Stuart's letter of the 2d of April, 1777, that it had been asserted with good authority that the far greater part of the government share of the crop was plundered by individuals, and never came to account in the Rajah's treasury.

It’s hard to determine the exact amount collected after the Nabob lost control of the territory, given the conflicting claims about it. However, from General Stuart's letter dated April 2, 1777, it seems credible sources stated that most of the government’s share of the harvest was stolen by individuals and never made it to the Rajah's treasury.

Under all the circumstances of this case, we must be of opinion that the government share of the crop of 1776 belonged to the Nabob, as the then reigning sovereign of the kingdom of Tanjore, he being, de facto, in the full and absolute possession of the government thereof; and consequently that the assignments made by him of the government share of the crop were valid.

Given all the circumstances of this case, we believe that the government share of the 1776 crop belonged to the Nabob, as the then reigning sovereign of the kingdom of Tanjore, who was, de facto, in full and absolute control of the government; therefore, the assignments he made of the government share of the crop were valid.

Nevertheless, we would by no means be understood by this opinion to suggest that any further demands ought to be made upon the Rajah, in respect of such parts of the government share of the crop as were collected by his people.

Nevertheless, we definitely don't mean to imply that any additional demands should be made on the Rajah regarding the parts of the government’s share of the crop that were collected by his people.

For, on the contrary, after so great a length of time as hath elapsed, we should think it highly unjust that the Rajah should be now compelled either to pay the supposed balances, whatever they may be, or be called upon to render a specific account of the collection made by his people.

For, on the contrary, after such a long time has passed, we should find it very unfair that the Rajah should now be forced to either pay the supposed debts, whatever they may be, or be asked to provide a detailed account of the money collected by his people.

The Rajah has already, in his letter to Governor Stratton of the 21st of April, 1777, given his assurance, that the produce of the preceding year, accounted for to him, was little more than one lac of pagodas; and as you have acquainted us, by your letter of the 14th of October, 1779, that the Rajah has actually paid into our treasury one lac of pagodas, by way of deposit, on account of the Nabob's claims to the crop, till our sentiments should be known, we direct you to surcease any further demands from the Rajah on that account.

The Rajah has already assured Governor Stratton in his letter dated April 21, 1777, that the income from the previous year, which was reported to him, was just over one lac of pagodas. Since you've informed us in your letter of October 14, 1779, that the Rajah has actually deposited one lac of pagodas into our treasury in relation to the Nabob's claims on the crop, until we clarify our position, we instruct you to stop any further requests from the Rajah on that matter.

We learn by the Proceedings, and particularly by the Nabob's letter to Lord Pigot of the 6th of July, 1776, that the Nabob, previous to the restoration of the Rajah, actually made assignments or granted tunkaws of the whole of his share of the crop to his creditors and troops; and that your government, (entertaining the same opinion as we do upon the question of right to that share,) by letter to the Rajah of the 20th of August, 1776, recommended to him "to restore to Mr. Benfield (one of the principal assignees or tunkaw-holders of the Nabob) the grain of the last year, which was in possession of his people, and said to be forcibly taken from them,—and farther, to give Mr. Benfield all reasonable assistance in recovering such debts as should appear to have been justly due to him from the inhabitants; and acquainted the Rajah that it had been judged by a majority of the Council that it was the Company's intention to let the Nabob have the produce of the crop of 1776, but that you had no intention that the Rajah should be accountable for more than the government share, whatever that might be; and that you did not mean to do more than recommend to him to see justice done, leaving the manner and time to himself." Subsequent representations appear to have been made to the Rajah by your government on the same subject, in favor of the Nabob's mortgages.

We learn from the Proceedings, especially from the Nabob's letter to Lord Pigot dated July 6, 1776, that before restoring the Rajah, the Nabob actually assigned or granted tunkaws of his entire crop share to his creditors and troops. Your government, sharing our view on the right to that share, wrote to the Rajah on August 20, 1776, advising him “to return to Mr. Benfield (one of the main assignees or tunkaw-holders of the Nabob) the grain from last year that was in the hands of his people and said to have been taken from them forcefully—and furthermore, to give Mr. Benfield all reasonable help in recovering any debts that seemed justly owed to him by the locals;” and informed the Rajah that a majority of the Council believed it was the Company’s intention to allow the Nabob to receive the produce from the 1776 crop, but you did not expect the Rajah to be accountable for more than the government share, whatever that might be. You also indicated that your only aim was to recommend that he ensure justice was served, leaving the method and timing up to him. Further representations seem to have been made to the Rajah by your government on the same matter, favoring the Nabob's mortgages.

In answer to these applications, the Rajah, in his letter to Mr. Stratton of the 12th January, 1777, acquainted you "that he had given orders respecting the grain which Mr. Benfield had heaped up in his country; and with regard to the money due to him by the farmers, that he had desired Mr. Benfield to bring accounts of it, that he might limit a time for the payment of it proportionably to their ability, and that the necessary orders for stopping this money out of the inhabitants' share of the crop had been sent to the ryots and aumildars; that Mr. Benfield's gomastah was then present there, and oversaw his affairs; and that in everything that was just he (the Rajah) willingly obeyed our Governor and Council."

In response to these requests, the Rajah, in his letter to Mr. Stratton dated January 12, 1777, informed you "that he had given instructions about the grain that Mr. Benfield had stored in his territory; and regarding the money owed to him by the farmers, he had asked Mr. Benfield to provide accounts so he could set a deadline for payment based on what they could afford, and that the necessary instructions to withhold this money from the inhabitants' share of the crop had been sent to the ryots and aumildars; that Mr. Benfield's gomastah was currently there and overseeing his affairs; and that in all matters that were fair, he (the Rajah) willingly complied with our Governor and Council."

Our opinion being that the Rajah ought to be answerable for no more than the amount of what he admits was collected by his people for the government share of the crop; and the Proceedings before us not sufficiently explaining whether, in the sum which the Rajah, by his before-mentioned letter of the 21st April, 1777, admits to have collected, are included those parts of the government share of the crop which were taken by his people from Mr. Benfield, or from any other of the assignees or tunkaw-holders; and uninformed, as we also are, what compensation the Rajah has or has not made to Mr. Benfield, or any other of the parties from whom the grain was taken by the Rajah's people; or whether, by means of the Rajah's refusal so to do, or from any other circumstance, any of the persons dispossessed of their grain may have had recourse to the Nabob for satisfaction: we are, for these reasons, incompetent to form a proper judgment what disposition ought in justice to be made of the one lac of pagodas deposited by the Rajah. But as our sentiments and intentions are so fully expressed upon the whole subject, we presume you, who are upon the spot, can have no doubt or difficulty in making such an application of the deposit as will be consistent with those principles of justice whereon our sentiments are founded. But should any such difficulty suggest itself, you will suspend any application of the deposit, until you have fully explained the same to us, and have received our further orders.

We believe that the Rajah should only be responsible for the amount he acknowledges was collected by his people for the government’s share of the crop. The documents we have do not clearly explain if the amount the Rajah admitted to collecting in his letter dated April 21, 1777, includes the parts of the government share of the crop that his people took from Mr. Benfield or any other assignees or tunkaw-holders. We also lack information on whether the Rajah has compensated Mr. Benfield or any other parties from whom his people took the grain, and we’re unclear if any of the individuals who were deprived of their grain sought compensation from the Nabob due to the Rajah’s refusal to address the situation or any other circumstances. For these reasons, we cannot properly determine what should justly be done with the one lac of pagodas that the Rajah deposited. However, since we have clearly expressed our views and intentions on this matter, we trust that you, being on-site, will have no trouble applying the deposit in a way that aligns with our principles of justice. If you do encounter any issues, please hold off on making any applications of the deposit until you’ve fully explained the situation to us and received further instructions.

With respect to the repairs of the Anicut and banks of the Cavery we have upon various occasions fully expressed to you our sentiments, and in particular in our general letter of the 4th July, 1777, we referred you to the investigation and correspondence on that subject of the year 1764, and to the report made by Mr. James Bourchier, on his personal survey of the waters, and to several letters of the year 1765 and 1767; we also, by our said general letter, acquainted you that it appeared to us perfectly reasonable that the Rajah should be permitted to repair those banks, and the Anicut, in the same manner as had been practised in times past; and we directed you to establish such regulations, by reference to former usage, for keeping the said banks in repair, as would be effectual, and remove all cause of complaint in future.

Regarding the repairs to the Anicut and the banks of the Cavery, we've shared our views with you on several occasions, particularly in our general letter dated July 4, 1777. In that letter, we referred you to the investigations and correspondence from 1764, along with Mr. James Bourchier's report based on his personal survey of the waters and several letters from 1765 and 1767. We also communicated in our general letter that we believe it’s entirely reasonable for the Rajah to be allowed to repair those banks and the Anicut, just as was done in the past. We instructed you to establish regulations, based on previous practices, to ensure those banks are kept in good repair and to eliminate any future complaints.

Notwithstanding such our instructions, the Rajah, in his letter to us of the 15th October, 1783, complains of the destruction of the Anicut; and as the cultivation of the Tanjore country appears, by all the surveys and reports of our engineers employed on that service, to depend altogether on a supply of water by the Cavery, which can only be secured by keeping the Anicut and banks in repair, we think it necessary to repeat to you our orders of the 4th July, 1777, on the subject of those repairs.

Despite our previous instructions, the Rajah, in his letter to us dated October 15, 1783, expresses concern about the destruction of the Anicut. Since the farming in the Tanjore region seems to rely entirely on water supply from the Cavery, which can only be ensured by maintaining the Anicut and its banks, we find it necessary to reiterate our orders from July 4, 1777, regarding those repairs.

And further, as it appears by the survey and report of Mr. Pringle, that those repairs are attended with a much heavier expense, when done with materials taken from the Tanjore district, than with those of Trichinopoly, and that the last-mentioned materials are far preferable to the other, it is our order, that, if any occurrences should make it necessary or expedient, you apply to the Nabob, in our name, to desire that his Highness will permit proper spots of ground to be set out, and bounded by proper marks on the Trichinopoly side, where the Rajah and his people may at all times take sand and earth sufficient for these repairs; and that his Highness will grant his lease of such spots of land for a certain term of years to the Company, at a reasonable annual rent, to the intent that through you the cultivation of the Tanjore country may be secured, without infringing or impairing the rights of the Nabob.

And also, according to Mr. Pringle's survey and report, it's clear that repairs are much more expensive when using materials from the Tanjore district compared to those from Trichinopoly, and that the latter materials are significantly better. Therefore, we order that if any situation arises that makes it necessary or wise, you should reach out to the Nabob on our behalf and ask him to allow suitable areas to be designated and marked on the Trichinopoly side, where the Rajah and his people can always take enough sand and earth for these repairs. Additionally, we ask that his Highness grants a lease of these lands to the Company for a set number of years at a fair annual rent, ensuring that the cultivation of the Tanjore region is protected without violating or undermining the Nabob's rights.

If any attempts have been or shall be hereafter made to divert the water from the Cavery into the Coleroon, by contracting the current of the Upper or Lower Cavery, by planting long grass, as mentioned in Mr. Pringle's report, or by any other means, we have no doubt his Highness, on a proper representation to him in our name, will prevent his people from taking any measures detrimental to the Tanjore country, in the prosperity of which his Highness, as well as the Company, is materially interested.

If any attempts have been made or will be made in the future to divert water from the Cauvery into the Coleroon, by narrowing the flow of the Upper or Lower Cauvery, by planting tall grass, as stated in Mr. Pringle's report, or by any other method, we are confident that his Highness, with a proper request from us, will stop his people from taking any actions that could harm the Tanjore region, which is significantly important to both his Highness and the Company.

Should you succeed in reconciling the Nabob to this measure, we think it but just that the proposed lease shall remain no longer in force than whilst the Rajah shall be punctual in the payment of the annual peshcush to the Nabob, as well as the rent to be reserved for the spots of ground. And in order effectually to remove all future occasions of jealousy and complaint between the parties,—that the Rajah, on the one hand, may be satisfied that all necessary works for the cultivation of his country will be made and kept in repair, and that the Nabob, on the other hand, may be satisfied that no encroachment on his rights can be made, nor any works detrimental to the fertility of his country erected,—we think it proper that it should be recommended to the parties, as a part of the adjustment of this very important point, that skilful engineers, appointed by the Company, be employed at the Rajah's expense to conduct all the necessary works, with the strictest attention to the respective rights and interests of both parties. This will remove every probability of injury or dispute. But should either party unexpectedly conceive themselves to be injured, immediate redress might be obtained by application to the government of Madras, under whose appointment the engineer will act, without any discussion between the parties, which might disturb that harmony which it is so much the wish of the Company to establish and preserve, as essential to the prosperity and peace of the Carnatic.

If you manage to convince the Nabob about this plan, we think it's fair that the proposed lease should only remain in effect as long as the Rajah promptly pays the annual peshcush to the Nabob, along with the rent for the land. To effectively eliminate any future issues of jealousy and complaints between both parties—so that the Rajah can be assured that all necessary work for cultivating his land will be completed and maintained, and that the Nabob can be sure there will be no infringement on his rights or any actions that could harm his land’s fertility—we suggest that as part of resolving this very important matter, skilled engineers, appointed by the Company, be hired at the Rajah's expense to carry out all necessary work while paying close attention to the rights and interests of both parties. This will help avoid any chance of harm or disputes. However, if either party feels wronged unexpectedly, they can seek immediate resolution by contacting the government of Madras, under whose authority the engineer will operate, without any disagreements between the parties, which could disrupt the harmony that the Company wishes to establish and maintain, as it is vital for the prosperity and peace of the Carnatic.

Having now, in obedience to the directions of the act of Parliament, upon the fullest consideration of the indeterminate rights and pretensions of the Nabob and Rajah, pointed out such measures and arrangements as in our judgment and discretion will be best calculated to ascertain and settle the same, we hope, that, upon a candid consideration of the whole system, although each of the parties may feel disappointed in our decision on particular points, they will be convinced that we have been guided in our investigation by principles of strict justice and impartiality, and that the most anxious attention has been paid to the substantial interests of both parties, and such a general and comprehensive plan of arrangement proposed as will most effectually prevent all future dissatisfaction.

Following the guidelines of the Parliament act, and after thoroughly reviewing the unclear rights and claims of the Nabob and Rajah, we have outlined the measures and arrangements that we believe will best clarify and resolve these issues. We hope that, after a fair examination of the entire situation, even if each party may be disappointed by our decisions on specific matters, they will recognize that our investigation was driven by principles of strict justice and impartiality. We have paid close attention to the significant interests of both parties and have proposed a broad and comprehensive plan that will effectively prevent any future dissatisfaction.

Approved by the Board.

HENRY DUNDAS,
WALSINGHAM,
W.W. GRENVILLE,
MULGRAVE.

WHITEHALL, October 27, 1784.

Approved by the Board.

HENRY DUNDAS,
WALSINGHAM,
W.W. GRENVILLE,
MULGRAVE.

WHITEHALL, October 27, 1784.


No. 9.

Referred to from pages __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ and __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

Extract of a Letter from the Court of Directors to the President and Council of Fort St. George, as amended and approved by the Board of Control.

We have taken into our consideration the several advices and papers received from India, relative to the assignment of the revenues of the Carnatic, from the conclusion of the Bengal treaty to the date of your letter in October, 1783, together with the representations of the Nabob of the Carnatic upon that subject; and although we might contend that the agreement should subsist till we are fully reimbursed his Highness's proportion of the expenses of the war, yet, from a principle of moderation, and personal attachment to our old ally, his Highness the Nabob of the Carnatic, for whose dignity and happiness we are ever solicitous, and to cement more strongly, if possible, that mutual harmony and confidence which our connection makes so essentially necessary for our reciprocal safety and welfare, and for removing from his mind every idea of secret design on our part to lessen his authority over the internal government of the Carnatic, and the collection and administration of its revenues, we have resolved that the assignment shall be surrendered; and we do accordingly direct our President, in whose name the assignment was taken, without delay, to surrender the same to his Highness. But while we have adopted this resolution, we repose entire confidence in his Highness, that, actuated by the same motives of liberality, and feelings of old friendship and alliance, he will cheerfully and instantly accede to such arrangements as are necessary to be adopted for our common safety, and for preserving the respect, rights, and interests we enjoy in the Carnatic. The following are the heads and principles of such an arrangement as we are decisively of opinion must be adopted for these purposes, viz.

We have considered the various advice and documents received from India regarding the assignment of the revenues of the Carnatic, from the end of the Bengal treaty to your letter in October 1783, along with the Nabob of the Carnatic's views on the matter. While we could argue that the agreement should stand until we are fully reimbursed for his Highness's share of the war expenses, we choose to act out of moderation and loyalty to our longtime ally, his Highness the Nabob of the Carnatic, whose dignity and well-being we always care about. We aim to strengthen the harmony and trust that our relationship requires for our mutual safety and welfare, and to eliminate any suspicion he might have about our intentions to undermine his authority over the internal governance of the Carnatic, as well as the collection and management of its revenues. Therefore, we have decided to surrender the assignment, and we direct our President, in whose name the assignment was made, without delay, to hand it over to his Highness. While we have made this decision, we fully trust that his Highness, motivated by the same generosity and feelings of long-standing friendship and alliance, will promptly agree to the necessary arrangements for our shared safety and to maintain the respect, rights, and interests we hold in the Carnatic. Below are the key points and principles of such an arrangement that we firmly believe must be adopted for these purposes:

That, for making a provision for discharging the Nabob's just debts to the Company and individuals, (for the payment of which his Highness has so frequently expressed the greatest solicitude,) the Nabob shall give soucar security for the punctual payment, by instalments, into the Company's treasury, of twelve lacs of pagodas per annum, (as voluntarily proposed by his Highness,) until those debts, with interest, shall be discharged; and shall also consent that the equitable provision lately made by the British legislature for the liquidation of those debts, and such resolutions and determinations as we shall hereafter make, under the authority of that provision for the liquidation and adjustment of the said debts, bonâ fide incurred, shall be carried into full force and effect.

To ensure that the Nabob can settle his legitimate debts to the Company and individuals (for which his Highness has repeatedly shown deep concern), the Nabob will provide soucar security for the timely payment, in installments, of twelve lacs of pagodas each year (as his Highness has voluntarily suggested) until those debts, along with interest, are fully paid off; and he will also agree that the fair arrangement recently established by the British legislature for paying off these debts, and any resolutions or decisions we make in the future, under the authority of that arrangement for resolving and settling those debts that were bonâ fide incurred, will be fully implemented.

Should any difficulty arise between his Highness and our government of Fort St. George, in respect to the responsibility of the soucar security, or the times and terms of the instalments, it is our pleasure that you pay obedience to the orders and resolutions of our Governor-General and Council of Bengal in respect thereto, not doubting but the Nabob will in such case consent to abide by the determination of our said supreme government.

If any issues come up between his Highness and our government at Fort St. George regarding the responsibility of the soucar security, or the timing and conditions of the payments, we expect you to follow the orders and decisions of our Governor-General and Council of Bengal on this matter, confident that the Nabob will agree to accept the decision of our supreme government.

Although, from the great confidence we repose in the honor and integrity of the Nabob, and from an earnest desire not to subject him to any embarrassment on this occasion, we have not proposed any specific assignment of territory or revenue for securing the payments aforesaid, we nevertheless think it our duty, as well to the private creditors, whose interests in this respect have been so solemnly intrusted to us by the late act of Parliament, as from regard to the debt due to the Company, to insist on a declaration, that, in the event of the failure of the security proposed, or in default of payment at the stipulated periods, we reserve to ourselves full right to demand of the Nabob such additional security, by assignment on his country, as shall be effectual for answering the purposes of the agreement.

Although we have great confidence in the honor and integrity of the Nabob and genuinely want to avoid putting him in a difficult position this time, we have not suggested any specific allocation of territory or revenue to secure the payments mentioned earlier. Still, we feel it’s our responsibility, both to the private creditors whose interests have been entrusted to us by the recent act of Parliament and out of concern for the debt owed to the Company, to insist on a statement that, in case the proposed security fails or if payment is not made by the agreed deadlines, we reserve the right to request from the Nabob such additional security, through an assignment of his territory, that will effectively ensure the fulfillment of the agreement.

After having conciliated the mind of the Nabob to this measure, and adjusted the particulars, you are to carry the same into execution by a formal deed between his Highness and the Company, according to the tenor of these instructions.

After winning the support of the Nabob for this plan and finalizing the details, you are to put it into action through an official agreement between his Highness and the Company, following the guidelines of these instructions.

As the administration of the British interests and connections in India has in some respects assumed a new shape by the late act of Parliament, and a general peace in India has been happily accomplished, the present appears to us to be the proper period, and which cannot without great imprudence be omitted, to settle and arrange, by a just and equitable treaty, a plan for the future defence and protection of the Carnatic, both in time of peace and war, on a solid and lasting foundation.

As the management of British interests and relations in India has taken on a new form due to the recent act of Parliament, and a general peace in India has been successfully achieved, we believe this is the right time, and one that would be very unwise to miss, to establish and organize, through a fair and just treaty, a plan for the future defense and protection of the Carnatic, both in times of peace and war, on a strong and enduring foundation.

For the accomplishment of this great and necessary object, we direct you, in the name of the Company, to use your utmost endeavors to impress the expediency of, and the good effects to be derived from this measure, so strongly upon the minds of the Nabob and the Rajah of Tanjore, as to prevail upon them, jointly or separately, to enter into one or more treaty or treaties with the Company, grounded on this principle of equity: That all the contracting parties shall be bound to contribute jointly to the support of the military force and garrisons, as well in peace as in war.

To achieve this important goal, we ask you, on behalf of the Company, to make every effort to emphasize to the Nabob and the Rajah of Tanjore the importance and benefits of this measure. We want you to persuade them, either together or separately, to enter into one or more treaties with the Company based on this principle of fairness: that all parties involved will be obligated to jointly support the military forces and garrisons in both peacetime and wartime.

That the military peace establishment shall be forthwith settled and adjusted by the Company, in pursuance of the authority and directions given to them by the late act of Parliament.

That the military peace arrangement shall be promptly established and adjusted by the Company, following the authority and instructions provided to them by the recent act of Parliament.

As the payment of the troops and garrisons, occasional expenses in the repairs and improvements of fortifications, and other services incidental to a military establishment, must of necessity be punctual and accurate, no latitude of personal assurance or reciprocal confidence of either of the parties on the other must be accepted or required; but the Nabob and Rajah must of necessity specify particular districts and revenues for securing the due and regular payment of their contributions into the treasury of the Company, with whom the charge of the defence of the coast, and of course the power of the sword, must be exclusively intrusted, with power for the Company, in case of failure or default of such payments at the stipulated times and seasons, to enter upon and possess such districts, and to let the same to renters, to be confirmed by the Nabob and the Rajah respectively; but, trusting that in the execution of this part of the arrangement no undue obstruction will be given by either of those powers, we direct that this part of the treaty be coupled with a most positive assurance, on our part, of our determination to support the dignity and authority of the Nabob and Rajah in the exclusive administration of the civil government and revenues of their respective countries;—and further, that, in case of any hostility committed against the territories of either of the contracting parties on the coast of Coromandel, the whole revenues of their respective territories shall be considered as one common stock, to be appropriated in the common cause of their defence; that the Company, on their part, shall engage to refrain, during the war, from the application of any part of their revenues to any commercial purposes whatsoever, but apply the whole, save only the ordinary charges of their civil government, to the purposes of the war; that the Nabob and the Rajah shall in like manner engage, on their parts, to refrain, during the war, from the application of any part of their revenues, save only what shall be actually necessary for the support of themselves and the civil government of their respective countries, to any other purposes than that of defraying the expenses of such military operations as the Company may find it necessary to carry on for the common safety of their interests on the coast of Coromandel.

Since the payment for the troops and garrisons, occasional expenses for repairs and upgrades to fortifications, and other services related to a military establishment must always be timely and precise, there can be no leeway for personal assurance or mutual trust between either party. The Nabob and Rajah must clearly specify certain districts and revenues to ensure the proper and regular payment of their contributions to the Company’s treasury, which is exclusively tasked with the defense of the coast and, by extension, the exercise of military power. Should there be a failure or delay in these payments at the agreed times, the Company has the authority to take control of those districts and lease them out to renters, subject to confirmation by the Nabob and the Rajah respectively. We trust that neither of these parties will unduly obstruct this part of the agreement; therefore, we commit to firmly supporting the dignity and authority of the Nabob and Rajah in their sole management of the civil government and revenues of their countries. Additionally, if there is any hostility directed at the territories of either party along the coast of Coromandel, the total revenues of their respective territories will be treated as a common pool to be used for their mutual defense. The Company agrees to refrain from using any portion of their revenues for commercial purposes during the war and will instead dedicate all except the usual costs of their civil government to the war effort. Similarly, the Nabob and the Rajah will also refrain from using their revenues for anything other than covering necessary expenses for themselves and their civil governments, directing the rest toward funding the military operations that the Company deems necessary for the shared safety of their interests along the coast of Coromandel.

And to obviate any difficulties or misunderstanding which might arise from leaving indeterminate the sum necessary to be appropriated for the civil establishment of each of the respective powers, that the sum be now ascertained which is indispensably necessary to be applied to those purposes, and which is to be held sacred under every emergency, and set apart previous to the application of the rest of the revenues, as hereby stipulated, for the purposes of mutual or common defence against any enemy, for clearing the incumbrance which may have become necessarily incurred in addition to the expenditure of those revenues which must be always deemed part of the war establishment. This we think absolutely necessary; as nothing can tend so much to the preservation of peace, and to prevent the renewal of hostilities, as the early putting the finances of the several powers upon a clear footing, and the showing to all other powers that the Company, the Nabob, and the Rajah are firmly united in one common cause, and combined in one system of permanent and vigorous defence, for the preservation of their respective territories and the general tranquillity.

And to avoid any difficulties or misunderstandings that might come from leaving the amount needed for the civil establishment of each power unclear, the amount that is absolutely necessary for these purposes should now be determined. This amount should be treated as sacred in every emergency and set aside before the rest of the revenues are used, as stipulated here, for mutual or common defense against any enemy, for clearing any obligations that may have been necessarily incurred in addition to the expenditure of those revenues, which must always be considered part of the war establishment. We believe this is essential, as nothing can help maintain peace and prevent the resurgence of hostilities more effectively than establishing clear financial arrangements among the various powers and demonstrating to all other powers that the Company, the Nabob, and the Rajah are firmly united in a common cause and working together in a system of permanent and strong defense to protect their respective territories and ensure overall tranquility.

That the whole aggregate revenue of the contracting parties shall, during the war, be under the application of the Company, and shall continue as long after the war as shall be necessary, to discharge the burdens contracted by it; but it must be declared that this provision shall in no respect extend to deprive either the Nabob or the Rajah of the substantial authority necessary to the collection of the revenues of their respective countries. But it is meant that they shall faithfully perform the conditions of this arrangement; and if a division of any part of the revenues to any other than the stipulated purposes shall take place, the Company shall be entitled to take upon themselves the collection of the revenue.

That the entire total revenue of the contracting parties shall, during the war, be managed by the Company, and shall continue to do so as long after the war as necessary to fulfill the obligations incurred by it; however, it must be stated that this provision will not in any way deprive either the Nabob or the Rajah of the essential authority needed to collect the revenues of their respective territories. It is intended that they will faithfully adhere to the terms of this arrangement; and if any part of the revenues is allocated for purposes other than those agreed upon, the Company shall have the right to take over the collection of the revenue.

The Company are to engage, during the time they shall administer the revenues, to produce to the other contracting parties regular accounts of the application thereof to the purposes stipulated by the treaty, and faithfully apply them in support of the war.

The Company will, while managing the revenues, provide the other parties involved with regular reports on how the funds are being used for the purposes outlined in the treaty and will use them responsibly to support the war.

And, lastly, as the defence of the Carnatic is thus to rest with the Company, the Nabob shall be satisfied of the propriety of avoiding all unnecessary expense, and will therefore agree not to maintain a greater number of troops than shall be necessary for the support of his dignity and the splendor of the durbar, which number shall be specified in the treaty; and if any military aid is requisite for the security and collection of his revenues, other than the fixed establishment employed to enforce the ordinary collections and preserve the police of the country, the Company must be bound to furnish him with such aid: the Rajah of Tanjore must likewise become bound by similar engagements, and be entitled to similar aid.

And finally, since the defense of the Carnatic will be the responsibility of the Company, the Nabob will recognize the need to avoid unnecessary expenses and will agree not to keep more troops than necessary to support his status and the grandeur of the court, with that number specified in the treaty. If additional military assistance is needed for the safety and collection of his revenues—beyond the regular forces used for standard collections and maintaining order in the country—the Company will be obligated to provide such assistance. The Rajah of Tanjore will also be required to agree to similar conditions and will be entitled to similar support.

As, in virtue of the powers vested in Lord Macartney by the agreement of December, 1781, sundry leases, of various periods, have been granted to renters, we direct that you apply to the Nabob, in our name, for his consent that they may be permitted to hold their leases to the end of the stipulated term; and we have great reliance[70] on the liberality and spirit of accommodation manifested by the Nabob on so many occasions, that he will be disposed to acquiesce in a proposition so just and reasonable. But if, contrary to our expectations, his Highness should be impressed with any particular aversion to comply with this proposition, we do not desire you to insist upon it as an essential part of the arrangement to take place between us; but, in that event, you must take especial care to give such indemnification to the renters for any loss they may sustain as you judge to be reasonable.

Since Lord Macartney has the authority from the agreement made in December 1781, several leases for different periods have been granted to tenants. We ask that you reach out to the Nawab on our behalf to request his approval for them to continue holding their leases until the end of the agreed term. We trust in the generosity and willingness to accommodate that the Nawab has shown on many occasions, and we believe he will agree to a proposition that is fair and reasonable. However, if, contrary to our expectations, his Highness has a strong disinclination to accept this proposal, we don’t want you to push it as a crucial part of the agreement between us. In that case, you must make sure to provide adequate compensation to the tenants for any losses they might incur, as you see fit.

It equally concerns the honor of our government, that such natives as may have been put in any degree of authority over the collections, in consequence of the deed of assignment, and who have proved faithful to their trust, shall not suffer inconvenience on account of their fidelity.

It is also important for the honor of our government that any locals who have been given any level of authority over the collections due to the deed of assignment, and who have been loyal to their responsibilities, should not face any difficulties because of their loyalty.

Having thus given our sentiments at large, as well for the surrender of the assignment as with regard to those arrangements which we think necessary to adopt in consequence thereof, we cannot dismiss this subject without expressing our highest approbation of the ability, moderation, and command of temper with which our President at Madras has conducted himself in the management of a very delicate and embarrassing situation. His conduct, and that of the Select Committee of Fort St. George, in the execution of the trust delegated to Lord Macartney by the Nabob Mahomed Ali, has been vigorous and effectual, for the purpose of realizing as great a revenue, at a crisis of necessity, as the nature of the case admitted; and the imputation of corruption, suggested in some of the Proceedings, appears to be totally groundless and unwarranted.

Having shared our thoughts in detail, both about the assignment's surrender and the arrangements we believe are necessary as a result, we cannot conclude this topic without expressing our highest appreciation for the skill, restraint, and self-control with which our President in Madras has handled a very sensitive and challenging situation. His actions, along with those of the Select Committee of Fort St. George, in carrying out the trust given to Lord Macartney by Nabob Mahomed Ali, have been strong and effective in generating as much revenue as possible during a time of urgent need, given the circumstances; the accusations of corruption mentioned in some of the Proceedings seem completely unfounded and unjustified.

While we find so much to applaud, it is with regret we are induced to advert to anything which may appear worthy of blame: as the step of issuing the Torana Chits in Lord Macartney's own name can only be justified upon the ground of absolute necessity;[71] and as his Lordship had every reason to believe that the demand, when made, would be irksome and disagreeable to the feelings of Mahomed Ali, every precaution ought to have been used and more time allowed for proving that necessity, by previous acts of address, civility, and conciliation, applied for the purposes of obtaining his authority to such a measure. It appears to us that more of this might have been used; and therefore we cannot consider the omission of it as blameless, consistent with our wishes of sanctifying no act contrary to the spirit of the agreement, or derogatory to the authority of the Nabob of the Carnatic, in the exercise of any of his just rights in the government of the people under his authority.

While there's a lot to praise, we regret that we must mention something that might deserve criticism: issuing the Torana Chits in Lord Macartney's name can only be justified by absolute necessity; and since his Lordship had every reason to believe that making this demand would be troubling and uncomfortable for Mahomed Ali, every precaution should have been taken, and more time should have been allowed to demonstrate that necessity through previous acts of respect, politeness, and goodwill, aimed at gaining his approval for such a measure. It seems to us that more of this could have been done; therefore, we can't view the lack of it as excusable, in line with our intention of not endorsing any action that goes against the spirit of the agreement or undermines the authority of the Nabob of the Carnatic in exercising his rightful governance over his people.

We likewise observe, the Nabob has complained that no official communication was made to him of the peace, for near a month after the cessation of arms took place. This, and every other mark of disrespect to the Nabob, will ever appear highly reprehensible in our eyes; and we direct that you do, upon all occasions, pay the highest attention to him and his family.

We also notice that the Nabob has expressed his frustration that he wasn’t officially informed about the peace agreement until nearly a month after the fighting ended. This, along with any other signs of disrespect towards the Nabob, will always seem very unacceptable to us; we instruct you to always show him and his family the utmost respect.

Lord Macartney, in his Minute of the 9th of September last, has been fully under our consideration. We shall ever applaud the prudence and foresight of our servants which induces them to collect and communicate to us every opinion, or even ground of suspicion they may entertain, relative to any of the powers in India with whose conduct our interest and the safety of our settlements is essentially connected. At the same time we earnestly recommend that those opinions and speculations be communicated to us with prudence, discretion, and all possible secrecy, and the terms in which they are conveyed be expressed in a manner as little offensive as possible to the powers whom they may concern and into whose hands they may fall.[72]

Lord Macartney’s note from September 9th has been thoroughly reviewed by us. We will always commend the wisdom and foresight of our staff for gathering and sharing every opinion or even suspicion they might have about any of the powers in India that could impact our interests and the safety of our settlements. At the same time, we strongly advise that those opinions and speculations be communicated to us with care, discretion, and as much confidentiality as possible, and that the way they are expressed be as inoffensive as possible to the powers involved, especially if they fall into their hands.[72]

We next proceed to give you our sentiments respecting the private debts of the Nabob; and we cannot but acknowledge that the origin and justice, both of the loan of 1767, and the loan of 1777, commonly called the Cavalry Loan, appear to us clear and indisputable, agreeable to the true sense and spirit of the late act of Parliament.

We will now share our thoughts on the private debts of the Nabob; and we must admit that the origins and fairness of both the loan from 1767 and the 1777 loan, often referred to as the Cavalry Loan, seem clear and undeniable to us, in accordance with the true meaning and intention of the recent act of Parliament.

In speaking of the loan of 1767, we are to be understood as speaking of the debt as constituted by the original bonds of that year, bearing interest at 10l. per cent; and therefore, if any of the Nabob's creditors, under a pretence that their debts made part of the consolidated debt of 1767, although secured by bonds of a subsequent date, carrying an interest exceeding 10l. per cent, shall claim the benefit of the following orders, we direct that you pay no regard to such claims, without further especial instructions for that purpose.

When we talk about the loan from 1767, we mean the debt established by the original bonds from that year, which had an interest rate of 10l. per cent. Therefore, if any of the Nabob's creditors, claiming that their debts were part of the consolidated debt of 1767, despite being secured by bonds issued later and carrying an interest rate higher than 10l. per cent, attempt to benefit from the following orders, we instruct you to disregard such claims unless you receive specific instructions to do otherwise.

With respect to the consolidated debt of 1777, it certainly stands upon a less favorable footing. So early as the 27th March, 1769, it was ordered by our then President and Council of Fort St. George, that, for the preventing all persons living under the Company's protection from having any dealings with any of the country powers or their ministers without the knowledge or consent of the Board, an advertisement should be published, by fixing it up at the sea-gate, and sending round a copy to the Company's servants and inhabitants, and to the different subordinates, and our garrisons, and giving it out in general orders, stating therein that the President and Council did consider the irreversible order of the Court of Directors of the year 1714 (whereby their people were prohibited from having any dealings with the country governments in money matters) to be in full force and vigor, and thereby expressly forbidding all servants of the Company, and other Europeans under their jurisdiction, to make loans or have any money transactions with any of the princes or states in India, without special license and permission of the President and Council for the time being, except only in the particular cases there mentioned, and declaring that any wilful deviation therefrom should be deemed a breach of orders, and treated as such. And on the 4th of March, 1778, it was resolved by our President and Council of Fort St George, that the consolidated debt of 1777 was not, on any respect whatever, conducted under the auspices or protection of that government; and on the circumstance of the consolidation of the said debt being made known to us, we did, on the 23rd of December, 1778, write to you in the following terms: "Your account of the Nabob's private debts is very alarming; but from whatever cause or causes those debts have been contracted or increased, we hereby repeat our orders, that the sanction of the Company be on no account given to any kind of security for the payment or liquidation of any part thereof, (except by the express authority of the Court of Directors,) on any account or pretence whatever."

With regard to the consolidated debt of 1777, it definitely stands on a less favorable ground. As early as March 27, 1769, our then President and Council of Fort St. George ordered that to prevent all individuals living under the Company's protection from dealing with any local powers or their ministers without the Board's knowledge or consent, an announcement should be made. This would involve posting it at the sea gate, sending copies to the Company's servants and residents, various subordinates, and our garrisons, and including it in general orders. It stated that the President and Council viewed the irreversible order from the Court of Directors from 1714 (which prohibited their people from interacting with local governments in financial matters) as still in full effect. This explicitly forbade all Company servants and other Europeans under their control from making loans or engaging in any financial transactions with any princes or states in India without the specific license and permission of the current President and Council, except for the particular cases mentioned. It declared that any deliberate deviation from this would be considered a breach of orders and dealt with accordingly. On March 4, 1778, our President and Council of Fort St. George resolved that the consolidated debt of 1777 was, in any regard, not conducted under the auspices or protection of that government; and upon learning about the consolidation of this debt, we wrote to you on December 23, 1778, stating: "Your account of the Nabob's private debts is very alarming; but regardless of the reasons those debts were contracted or increased, we hereby repeat our orders that the Company's approval must not be given under any circumstances for any type of security for the payment or settlement of any part of it (except with the explicit authority of the Court of Directors), under any circumstances or pretenses whatsoever."

The loan of 1777, therefore, has no sanction or authority from us; and in considering the situation and circumstances of this loan, we cannot omit to observe, that the creditors could not be ignorant how greatly the affairs of the Nabob were at that time deranged, and that his debt to the Company was then very considerable,—the payment of which the parties took the most effectual means to postpone, by procuring an assignment of such specific revenues for the discharge of their own debts as alone could have enabled the Nabob to have discharged that of the Company.

The loan of 1777, therefore, has no approval or authority from us; and in looking at the situation surrounding this loan, we can't help but note that the creditors must have known how much the Nabob's affairs were in disarray at that time, and that his debt to the Company was quite substantial. The parties took significant steps to delay payment by securing an assignment of specific revenues that could have allowed the Nabob to pay off his debt to the Company.

Under all these circumstances, we should be warranted to refuse our aid or protection in the recovery of this loan. But when we consider the inexpediency of keeping the subject of the Nabob's debts longer afloat than is absolutely necessary,—when we consider how much the final conclusion of this business will tend to promote tranquillity, credit, and circulation of property in the Carnatic,—and when we consider that the debtor concurs with the creditor in establishing the justice of those debts consolidated in 1777 into gross sums, for which bonds were given, liable to be transferred to persons different from the original creditors, and having no share or knowledge of the transactions in which the debts originated, and of course how little ground there is to expect any substantial good to result from an unlimited investigation into them, we have resolved so far to recognize the justice of those debts as to extend to them that protection which, upon more forcible grounds, we have seen cause to allow to the other two classes of debts. But although we so far adopt the general presumption in their favor as to admit them to a participation in the manner hereafter directed, we do not mean to debar you from receiving any complaints against those debts of 1777, at the instance either of the Nabob himself, or of other creditors injured by their being so admitted, or by any other persons having a proper interest, or stating reasonable grounds of objection; and if any complaints are offered, we order that the grounds of all such be attentively examined by you, and be transmitted to us, together with the evidence adduced in support of them, for our final decision; and as we have before directed that the sum of twelve lacs of pagodas, to be received annually from the Nabob, should be paid into our treasury, it is our order that the same be distributed according to the following arrangement.

Given all these circumstances, we should be justified in refusing our assistance or protection in recovering this loan. However, when we consider that it's impractical to keep the issue of the Nabob's debts in discussion longer than necessary—when we realize how much resolving this matter will help promote stability, credit, and the flow of property in the Carnatic—and when we acknowledge that both the debtor and creditor agree on the legitimacy of those debts that were consolidated in 1777 into total amounts, for which bonds were issued and can be transferred to parties other than the original creditors, who have no involvement or knowledge of the circumstances surrounding the debts, and therefore how little benefit we can expect from an extensive investigation into them, we have decided to acknowledge the validity of these debts enough to grant them the protection which we have previously deemed appropriate for the other two categories of debts. Nevertheless, while we accept the general assumption in their favor to the extent of allowing them to partake as outlined later, we don't intend to prevent you from addressing any complaints regarding the 1777 debts, either from the Nabob himself or from other creditors harmed by their acceptance, or from any other parties with a legitimate interest or who present reasonable objections; if any complaints are submitted, we instruct you to thoroughly examine the basis of all such issues and send them to us, along with the evidence supporting them, for our final decision; and as we have previously instructed that the sum of twelve lacs of pagodas, to be received annually from the Nabob, should be deposited into our treasury, we order that it be distributed according to the following plan.

That the debt be made up in the following manner, viz.

That the debt be settled in the following way, namely.

The debt consolidated in 1767 to be made up to the end of the year 1784, with the current interest at ten per cent.

The debt consolidated in 1767 is to be settled by the end of the year 1784, with the current interest set at ten percent.

The Cavalry Loan to be made up to the same period, with the current interest at twelve per cent.

The Cavalry Loan will be adjusted to match the same timeframe, with the current interest rate at twelve percent.

The debt consolidated in 1777 to be made up to the same period, with the current interest at twelve per cent, to November, 1781, and from thence with the current interest at six per cent.

The debt consolidated in 1777 is to be settled for the same period, with the current interest at twelve percent until November 1781, and after that with the current interest at six percent.

The twelve lacs annually to be received are then to be applied,—

The twelve lacs received each year will then be used,—

1. To the growing interest on the Cavalry Loan, at twelve per cent.

1. To the increasing interest in the Cavalry Loan, at twelve percent.

2. To the growing interest on the debt of 1777, at six per cent.

2. Regarding the increasing interest on the debt from 1777, at six percent.

The remainder to be equally divided: one half to be applied to the extinction of the Company's debt; the other half to be applied to the payment of growing interest at 10l. per cent, and towards the discharge of the principal of the debt of 1767.

The rest will be split equally: half will go towards paying off the Company's debt; the other half will cover the accruing interest at 10l per cent and help pay down the principal of the 1767 debt.

This arrangement to continue till the principal of the debt 1767 is discharged.

This plan will remain in effect until the principal of the debt from 1767 is paid off.

The application of the twelve lacs is, then, to be,—

The use of the twelve lacs is, then, to be,—

1. To the interest of the debt of 1777, as above. The remainder to be then equally divided,—one half towards the discharge of the current interest and principal of the Cavalry Loan, and the other half towards the discharge of the Company's debt.

1. For the interest on the debt from 1777, as mentioned above. The rest will be then equally divided—half will go toward paying off the current interest and principal of the Cavalry Loan, and the other half will go toward paying off the Company's debt.

When the Cavalry Loan shall be thus discharged, there shall then be paid towards the discharge of the Company's debt seven lacs.

When the Cavalry Loan is paid off, seven lacs will be paid towards paying off the Company's debt.

To the growing interest and capital of the 1777 loan, five lacs.

To the increasing interest and funds from the 1777 loan, five lacs.

When the Company's debt shall be discharged, the whole is then to be applied in discharge of the debt 1777.

When the Company's debt is paid off, the entire amount will then be used to settle the debt from 1777.

If the Nabob shall be prevailed upon to apply the arrears and growing payments of the Tanjore peshcush in further discharge of his debts, over and above the twelve lacs of pagodas, we direct that the whole of that payment, when made, shall be applied towards the reduction of the Company's debt.

If the Nabob can be convinced to use the overdue and upcoming payments of the Tanjore peshcush to further pay off his debts, in addition to the twelve lacs of pagodas, we direct that the entire amount of that payment, when made, should be used to reduce the Company's debt.

We have laid down these general rules of distribution, as appearing to us founded on justice, and the relative circumstances of the different debts; and therefore we give our authority and protection to them only on the supposition that they who ask our protection acquiesce in the condition upon which it is given; and therefore we expressly order, that, if any creditor of the Nabob, a servant of the Company, or being under our protection, shall refuse to express his acquiescence in these arrangements, he shall not only be excluded from receiving any share of the fund under your distribution, but shall be prohibited from taking any separate measures to recover his debt from the Nabob: it being one great inducement to our adopting this arrangement, that the Nabob shall be relieved from all further disquietude by the importunities of his individual creditors, and be left at liberty to pursue those measures for the prosperity of his country which the embarrassments of his situation have hitherto deprived him of the means of exerting. And we further direct, that, if any creditor shall be found refractory, or disposed to disturb the arrangement we have suggested, he shall be dismissed the service, and sent home to England.

We have established these general rules for distribution, which we believe are based on fairness and the specific circumstances of each debt; and so we give our authority and protection to these rules only if those seeking our protection agree to the terms upon which it is granted. Therefore, we clearly state that if any creditor of the Nabob, an employee of the Company, or someone under our protection refuses to accept these arrangements, they will not only be barred from receiving any portion of the funds being distributed but will also be prohibited from taking any individual actions to recover their debt from the Nabob. One of the main reasons for adopting this arrangement is to ensure that the Nabob is free from the stress of constant demands from individual creditors, allowing him the freedom to work towards the betterment of his country, which the difficulties of his situation have previously hindered. Additionally, we instruct that if any creditor is found to be uncooperative or disruptive to the proposed arrangement, they will be dismissed from the service and sent back to England.

The directions we have given only apply to the three classes of debts which have come under our observation. It has been surmised that the Nabob has of late contracted further debts: if any of these are due to British subjects, we forbid any countenance or protection whatever to be given to them, until the debt is fully investigated, the nature of it reported home, and our special instructions upon it received.

The guidelines we've provided only apply to the three types of debts we've seen. It's been speculated that the Nabob has recently taken on more debts: if any of these are owed to British citizens, we prohibit any support or protection from being offered to them until the debt is thoroughly examined, the details reported back home, and we've received our specific instructions on the matter.

We cannot conclude this subject without adverting in the strongest terms to the prohibitions which have from time to time issued under the authority of different Courts of Directors against any of our servants, or of those under our protection, having any money transactions with any of the country powers, without the knowledge and previous consent of our respective governments abroad. We are happy to find that the Nabob, sensible of the great embarrassments, both to his own and the Company's affairs, which the enormous amount of their private claims have occasioned, is willing to engage not to incur any new debts with individuals, and we think little difficulty will be found in persuading his Highness into a positive stipulation for that purpose. And though the legislature has thus humanely interfered in behalf of such individuals as might otherwise have been reduced to great distress by the past transactions, we hereby, in the most pointed and positive terms, repeat our prohibition upon this subject, and direct that no person, being a servant of the Company, or being under our protection, shall, on any pretence whatever, be concerned in any loan or other money transaction with any of the country powers, unless with the knowledge and express permission of our respective governments. And if any of our servants, or others, being under our protection, shall be discovered in any respect counteracting these orders, we strictly enjoin you to take the first opportunity of sending them home to England, to be punished as guilty of disobedience of orders, and no protection or assistance of the Company shall be given for the recovery of any loans connected with such transactions. Your particular attention to this subject is strictly enjoined; and any connivance on your parts to a breach of our orders upon it will incur our highest displeasure. In order to put an end to those intrigues which have been so successfully carried on at the Nabob's durbar, we repeat our prohibition in the strongest terms respecting any intercourse between British subjects and the Nabob and his family; as we are convinced that such an intercourse has been carried on greatly to the detriment and expense of the Nabob, and merely to the advantage of individuals. We therefore direct that all persons who shall offend against the letter and spirit of this necessary order, whether in the Company's service or under their protection, be forthwith sent to England.

We cannot wrap up this topic without strongly mentioning the bans that have periodically come from various Courts of Directors against any of our employees, or those under our protection, engaging in any financial dealings with local powers without the knowledge and prior consent of our governments abroad. We're pleased to note that the Nabob, understanding the significant complications both for himself and the Company caused by the large amount of private claims, is willing to commit to not taking on any new debts with individuals. We believe it will be easy to persuade his Highness to make a definite agreement on this matter. While the legislature has kindly intervened on behalf of those who might otherwise suffer from past dealings, we want to firmly reiterate our ban on this subject. No person, whether a Company employee or under our protection, shall, under any circumstances, be involved in any loan or other financial dealings with local powers without the knowledge and explicit permission of our respective governments. If any of our employees or those under our protection are found to be violating these orders, we insist that you promptly send them back to England to face punishment for disobeying orders. Moreover, the Company will not provide any protection or assistance for the recovery of any loans tied to such dealings. Your careful attention to this matter is required; any negligence on your part regarding our orders will result in our utmost disapproval. To put a stop to the intrigues that have been successfully carried out at the Nabob's court, we strongly reiterate our ban on any interactions between British subjects and the Nabob and his family, as we believe such interactions have greatly harmed the Nabob while benefiting individuals. Therefore, we direct that anyone who violates this essential order, whether in the Company's service or under its protection, be immediately sent back to England.

Approved by the Board.
HENRY DUNDAS,
WALSINGHAM,
W.W. GRENVILLE,
MULGRAVE.
WHITEHALL, 15th Oct. 1784.

Approved by the Board.
HENRY DUNDAS,
WALSINGHAM,
W.W. GRENVILLE,
MULGRAVE.
WHITEHALL, 15th Oct. 1784.


Extract from the Representation of the Court of Directors of the East India Company.

MY LORDS AND GENTLEMEN,—

Ladies and gentlemen,—

It is with extreme concern that we express a difference of opinion with your right honorable board, in this early exercise of your controlling power; but in so novel an institution, it can scarce be thought extraordinary, if the exact boundaries of our respective functions and duties should not at once, on either side, be precisely and familiarly understood, and therefore confide in your justice and candor for believing that we have no wish to invade or frustrate the salutary purposes of your institution, as we on our part are thoroughly satisfied that you have no wish to encroach on the legal powers of the East India Company. We shall proceed to state our objections to such of the amendments as appear to us to be either insufficient, inexpedient, or unwarranted.

It is with great concern that we express a difference of opinion with your honorable board in this early exercise of your authority; however, in such a new institution, it’s hardly surprising that the exact boundaries of our respective roles and responsibilities may not be clearly understood by either side right away. Therefore, we trust your fairness and understanding in believing that we have no intention to undermine or obstruct the beneficial goals of your organization, just as we are confident that you have no intention to overstep the legal powers of the East India Company. We will now outline our objections to those amendments that we find to be either inadequate, impractical, or unjustified.

6th. Concerning the private debts of the Nabob of Arcot, and the application of the fund of twelve lacs of pagodas per annum.

6th. Regarding the personal debts of the Nabob of Arcot, and the use of the fund of twelve lacs of pagodas each year.

Under this head you are pleased, in lieu of our paragraphs, to substantiate at once the justice of all those demands which the act requires us to investigate, subject only to a right reserved to the Nabob, or any other party concerned, to question the justice of any debt falling within the last of the three classes. We submit, that at least the opportunity of questioning, within the limited time, the justice of any of the debts, ought to have been fully preserved; and supposing the first and second classes to stand free from imputation, (as we incline to believe they do,) no injury can result to individuals from such discussion: and we further submit to your consideration, how far the express direction of the act to examine the nature and origin of the debts has been by the amended paragraphs complied with; and whether at least the rate of interest, according to which the debts arising from soucar assignment of the land-revenues to the servants of the Company, acting in the capacity of native bankers, have been accumulated, ought not to be inquired into, as well as the reasonableness of the deduction of twenty-five per cent which the Bengal government directed to be made from a great part of the debts on certain conditions. But to your appropriation of the fund our duty requires that we should state our strongest dissent. Our right to be paid the arrears of those expenses by which, almost to our own ruin, we have preserved the country and all the property connected with it from falling a prey to a foreign conqueror, surely stands paramount to all claims for former debts upon the revenues of a country so preserved, even if the legislature had not expressly limited the assistance to be given the private creditors to be such as should be consistent with our own rights. The Nabob had, long before passing the act, by treaty with our Bengal government, agreed to pay us seven lacs of pagodas, as part of the twelve lacs, in liquidation of those arrears; of which seven lacs the arrangement you have been pleased to lay down would take away from us more than the half, and give it to private creditors, of whose demands there are only about a sixth part which do not stand in a predicament that you declare would not entitle them to any aid or protection from us in the recovery thereof, were it not upon grounds of expediency, as will more particularly appear by the annexed estimate. Until our debt shall be discharged, we can by no means consent to give up any part of the seven lacs to the private creditors; and we humbly apprehend that in this declaration we do not exceed the limits of the authority and rights vested in us.

Under this heading, you are pleased to immediately confirm the validity of all the demands that the act requires us to assess, subject only to the right of the Nabob or any other interested party to challenge the legitimacy of any debt falling into the last of the three categories. We argue that individuals should at least have the opportunity to question the validity of any of the debts within the given time frame; and assuming that the first and second categories are free from issues (as we tend to believe they are), no harm will come to individuals from such scrutiny. Additionally, we seek your thoughts on how well the amended paragraphs comply with the act's explicit requirement to investigate the nature and origins of the debts; and whether the interest rate on debts arising from the soucar assignment of land revenues to the Company's employees, acting as native bankers, should not also be examined, as well as the justification for the twenty-five percent reduction that the Bengal government directed to be applied to a significant portion of the debts under certain conditions. However, regarding your allocation of the fund, we must express our strongest disagreement. Our right to receive the back payments for those expenses that have nearly led to our own downfall while we have safeguarded the country and all related property from being conquered by a foreign power surely takes precedence over all claims for past debts against the revenues of a saved country, even if the legislature had not specifically limited the assistance to private creditors in a way that aligns with our own rights. The Nabob had previously agreed, through a treaty with our Bengal government, to pay us seven lacs of pagodas as part of the twelve lacs owed for settling those back payments; however, the arrangement you propose would take away more than half of that amount and allocate it to private creditors, of whom only about one-sixth have claims that you have indicated do not entitle them to any assistance or protection from us in their recovery, except on expediency grounds, as will be more clearly outlined in the attached estimate. Until our debt is settled, we cannot agree to relinquish any portion of the seven lacs to the private creditors; and we respectfully believe that in this statement we are not exceeding the scope of the authority and rights granted to us.


THE RIGHT HONORABLE THE COMMISSIONERS FOR THE AFFAIRS OF INDIA.

The Representation of the Court of Directors of the East India Company.

My Lords and Gentlemen,—

Ladies and Gentlemen,

The Court, having duly attended to your reasonings and decisions on the subjects of Arnee and Hanamantagoody, beg leave to observe, with due deference to your judgment, that the directions we had given in these paragraphs which did not obtain your approbation still appear to us to have been consistent with justice, and agreeable to the late act of Parliament, which pointed out to us, as we apprehended, the treaty of 1762 as our guide.

The Court, having carefully considered your thoughts and decisions about Arnee and Hanamantagoody, would like to respectfully point out that the guidelines we provided in these paragraphs, which you did not approve, still seem to us to be in line with justice and in accordance with the recent act of Parliament. We understood that the treaty of 1762 was our reference point.

Signed by order of the said Court,

Signed by the order of the mentioned Court,

THO. MORTON, Sec.

THO. MORTON, Secretary.

EAST INDIA HOUSE, the 3rd November, 1784.

EAST INDIA HOUSE, November 3, 1784.


Extract of a Letter from the Commissioners for the Affairs of India, to the Court of Directors, dated 3rd November, 1784, in Answer to their Remonstrance.

SIXTH ARTICLE.

We think it proper, considering the particular nature of the subject, to state to you the following remarks on that part of your representation which relates to the plan for the discharging of the Nabob's debts.

We believe it’s appropriate, given the specific nature of the topic, to share the following comments regarding that part of your proposal that pertains to the plan for paying off the Nabob's debts.

1st. You compute the revenue which the Carnatic may be expected to produce only at twenty lacs of pagodas. If we concurred with you in this opinion, we should certainly feel our hopes of advantage to all the parties from this arrangement considerably diminished. But we trust that we are not too sanguine on this head, when we place the greatest reliance on the estimate transmitted to you by your President of Fort St. George, having there the best means of information upon the fact, and stating it with a particular view to the subject matter of these paragraphs. Some allowance, we are sensible, must be made for the difference of collection in the Nabob's hands, but, we trust, not such as to reduce the receipt nearly to what you suppose.

1st. You estimate that the revenue from the Carnatic will only be about twenty lacs of pagodas. If we agreed with you on this, we would definitely feel that our hopes for benefiting all parties from this arrangement would be significantly reduced. However, we believe we’re not being overly optimistic when we place our trust in the estimate provided to you by your President of Fort St. George, who has the best access to information on this matter and has communicated it specifically regarding the topics in these paragraphs. We acknowledge that some adjustment needs to be made for the differences in collection in the Nabob's hands, but, we hope it won't be enough to bring the revenue down to what you anticipate.

2ndly. In making up the amount of the private debts, you take in compound interest at the different rates specified in our paragraph. This it was not our intention to allow; and lest any misconception should arise on the spot, we have added an express direction that the debts be made up with simple interest only, from the time of their respective consolidation. Clause F f.

2ndly. When calculating the total of the private debts, you should include compound interest at the various rates mentioned in our paragraph. It was not our intention to permit this; and to avoid any misunderstanding on the spot, we have included a clear instruction that the debts should be calculated with simple interest only, starting from the time they were consolidated. Clause F f.

3rdly. We have also the strongest grounds to believe that the debts will be in other respects considerably less than they are now computed by you; and consequently, the Company's annual proportion of the twelve lacs will be larger than it appears on your estimate. But even on your own statement of it, if we add to the 150,000l., or 3,75,000 pagodas, (which you take as the annual proportion to be received by the Company for five years to the end of 1789,) the annual amount of the Tanjore peshcush for the same period, and the arrears on the peshcush, (proposed by Lord Macartney to be received in three years,) the whole will make a sum not falling very short of pagodas 35,00,000, the amount of pagodas 7,00,000 per annum for the same period. And if we carry our calculations farther, it will appear, that, both by the plan proposed by the Nabob and adopted in your paragraphs, and by that which we transmitted to you, the debt from the Nabob, if taken at 3,000,000l., will be discharged nearly at the same period, viz., in the course of the eleventh year. We cannot, therefore, be of opinion that there is the smallest ground for objecting to this arrangement, as injurious to the interests of the Company, even if the measure were to be considered on the mere ground of expediency, and with a view only to the wisdom of reëstablishing credit and circulation in a commercial settlement, without any consideration of those motives of attention to the feelings and honor of the Nabob, of humanity to individuals, and of justice to persons in your service and living under your protection, which have actuated the legislature, and which afford not only justifiable, but commendable grounds for your conduct.

3rdly. We also firmly believe that the debts will turn out to be much less than what you’ve currently estimated. As a result, the Company’s annual share of the twelve lacs will be greater than what your estimate shows. However, even based on your own figures, if we add the 150,000l., or 375,000 pagodas, which you consider the annual portion the Company will receive for the five years ending in 1789, along with the annual amount of the Tanjore peshcush for the same period and the back payments on the peshcush (which Lord Macartney proposed to collect over three years), the total would be nearly pagodas 35,00,000, or pagodas 7,00,000 each year for that period. Furthermore, if we extend our calculations, it will show that, based on both the plan proposed by the Nabob and the one we sent you, the debt from the Nabob, if set at 3,000,000l., will almost be fully paid off by the eleventh year. Therefore, we cannot agree that there is any valid reason to object to this arrangement as harmful to the Company’s interests, even if this measure is considered merely for practical reasons and aimed solely at the wisdom of restoring credit and circulation in a commercial setting, without considering the motives related to the feelings and honor of the Nabob, compassion for individuals, and justice for those in your service and under your protection, which have motivated the legislature and provide not only justifiable but commendable reasons for your actions.

Impressed with this conviction, we have not made any alteration in the general outlines of the arrangement which we had before transmitted to you. But, as the amount of the Nabob's revenue is matter of uncertain conjecture, and as it does not appear just to us that any deficiency should fall wholly on any one class of these debts, we have added a direction to your government of Fort St. George, that, if, notwithstanding the provisions contained in our former paragraphs, any deficiency should arise, the payments of what shall be received shall be made in the same proportion which would have obtained in the division of the whole twelve lacs, had they been paid.

Impressed by this belief, we haven't changed the general structure of the plan we previously shared with you. However, since the amount of the Nabob’s revenue is uncertain, and it doesn’t seem fair to us that any shortfall should fall entirely on one category of these debts, we have instructed your government at Fort St. George that, if a shortfall occurs despite the provisions outlined in our earlier statements, the payments received should be distributed in the same proportion as they would have been if the total of twelve lacs had been paid.


No. 10.

Referred to from page __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__.

[The following extracts are subjoined, to show the matter and the style of representation employed by those who have obtained that ascendency over the Nabob of Arcot which is described in the letter marked No. 6 of the present Appendix, and which is so totally destructive of the authority and credit of the lawful British government at Madras. The charges made by these persons have been solemnly denied by Lord Macartney; and to judge from the character of the parties accused and accusing, they are probably void of all foundation. But as the letters are in the name and under the signature of a person of great rank and consequence among the natives,—as they contain matter of the most serious nature,—as they charge the most enormous crimes, and corruptions of the grossest kind, on a British governor,—and as they refer to the Nabob's minister in Great Britain for proof and further elucidation of the matters complained of,—common decency and common policy demanded an inquiry into their truth or falsehood. The writing is obviously the product of some English pen. If, on inquiry, these charges should be made good, (a thing very unlikely,) the party accused would become a just object of animadversion. If they should be found (as in all probability they would be found) false and calumnious, and supported by forgery, then the censure would fall on the accuser; at the same time the necessity would be manifest for proper measures towards the security of government against such infamous accusations. It is as necessary to protect the honest fame of virtuous governors as it is to punish the corrupt and tyrannical. But neither the Court of Directors nor the Board of Control have made any inquiry into the truth or falsehood of these charges. They have covered over the accusers and accused with abundance of compliments; they have insinuated some oblique censures; and they have recommended perfect harmony between the chargers of corruption and peculation and the persons charged with these crimes.]

[The following excerpts are provided to demonstrate the issues and the style of representation used by those who have gained influence over the Nabob of Arcot, as described in the letter labeled No. 6 in this Appendix, which undermines the authority and credibility of the legitimate British government in Madras. Lord Macartney has firmly denied the accusations made by these individuals, and judging by the reputations of both the accusers and the accused, these claims are likely unfounded. However, because the letters are written in the name and signed by a person of significant rank and importance among the locals—because they address issues of utmost seriousness—because they accuse a British governor of enormous crimes and serious corruption—and because they reference the Nabob's minister in Great Britain for proof and further explanation of the complaints—basic decency and practical policy require an investigation into their truth or falsehood. The writing clearly comes from an English source. If, after investigation, these charges are found to be valid (which is highly unlikely), the accused party would justly become the target of criticism. If the charges are likely to be proven false and defamatory, and possibly supported by forgery, then the blame would shift to the accuser; simultaneously, the necessity for appropriate measures to safeguard the government against such disgraceful accusations would become evident. It is as vital to protect the good reputation of virtuous governors as it is to penalize the corrupt and tyrannical. Yet neither the Court of Directors nor the Board of Control has conducted an investigation into the truth or falsehood of these charges. They have showered both the accusers and the accused with plenty of compliments; they have hinted at some indirect criticisms; and they have urged complete harmony between those charging with corruption and embezzlement and the individuals accused of these crimes.]

13th October, 1782. Extract of a Translation of a Letter from the Nabob of Arcot to the Chairman of the Court of Directors of the East India Company.

Fatally for me, and for the public interest, the Company's favor and my unbounded confidence have been lavished on a man totally unfit for the exalted station in which he has been placed, and unworthy of the trusts that have been reposed in him. When I speak of one who has so deeply stabbed my honor, my wounds bleed afresh, and I must be allowed that freedom of expression which the galling reflection of my injuries and my misfortunes naturally draws from me. Shall your servants, unchecked, unrestrained, and unpunished, gratify their private views and ambition at the expense of my honor, my peace, and my happiness, and to the ruin of my country, as well as of all your affairs? No sooner had Lord Macartney obtained the favorite object of his ambition than he betrayed the greatest insolence towards me, the most glaring neglect of the common civilities and attentions paid me by all former governors in the worst of times, and even by the most inveterate of my enemies. He insulted my servants, endeavored to defame my character by unjustly censuring my administration, and extended his boundless usurpation to the whole government of my dominions, in all the branches of judicature and police; and, in violation of the express articles of the agreements, proceeded to send renters into the countries, unapproved of by me, men of bad character, and unequal to my management or responsibility. Though he is chargeable with the greatest acts of cruelty, even to the shedding the blood and cutting off the noses and ears of my subjects, by those exercising his authority in the countries, and that even the duties of religion and public worship have been interrupted or prevented, and though he carries on all his business by the arbitrary exertion of military force, yet does he not collect from the countries one fourth of the revenue that should be produced. The statement he pretends to hold forth of expected revenue is totally fallacious, and can never be realized under the management of his Lordship, in the appointment of renters totally disqualified, rapacious, and irresponsible, who are actually embezzling and dissipating the public revenues that should assist in the support of the war. Totally occupied by his private views, and governed by his passions, he has neglected or sacrificed all the essential objects of public good, and by want of coöperation with Sir Eyre Coote, and refusal to furnish the army with the necessary supplies, has rendered the glorious and repeated victories of the gallant general ineffectual to the expulsion of our cruel enemy. To cover his insufficiency, and veil the discredit attendant on his failure in every measure, he throws out the most illiberal expressions, and institutes unjust accusations against me; and in aggravation of all the distresses imposed upon me, he has abetted the meanest calumniators to bring forward false charges against me and my son, Amir-ul-Omrah, in order to create embarrassment, and for the distress of my mind. My papers and writings sent to you must testify to the whole world the malevolence of his designs, and the means that have been used to forward them. He has violently seized and opened all letters addressed to me and my servants, on my public and private affairs. My vackeel, that attended him according to ancient custom, has been ignominiously dismissed from his presence, and not suffered to approach the Government-House. He has in the meanest manner, and as he thought in secret, been tampering and intriguing with my family and relations for the worst of purposes. And if I express the agonies of my mind under these most pointed injuries and oppressions, and complain of the violence and injustice of Lord Macartney, I am insulted by his affected construction that my communications are dictated by the insinuations of others, at the same time that his conscious apprehensions for his misconduct have produced the most abject applications to me to smother my feelings, and entreaties to write in his Lordship's favor to England, and to submit all my affairs to his direction. When his submissions have failed to mould me to his will, he has endeavored to effect his purposes by menaces of his secret influence with those in power in England, which he pretends to assert shall be effectual to confirm his usurpation, and to deprive me, and my family, in succession, of my rights of sovereignty and government forever. To such a length have his passions and violences carried him, that all my family, my dependants, and even my friends and visitors, are persecuted with the strongest marks of his displeasure. Every shadow of authority in my person is taken from me, and respect to my name discouraged throughout the whole country. When an officer of high rank in his Majesty's service was some time since introduced to me by Lord Macartney, his Lordship took occasion to show a personal derision and contempt of me. Mr. Richard Sulivan, who has attended my durbar under the commission of the Governor-General and Council of Bengal, has experienced his resentment; and Mr. Benfield, with whom I have no business, and who, as he has been accustomed to do for many years, has continued to pay me his visits of respect, has felt the weight of his Lordship's displeasure, and has had every unmerited insinuation thrown out against him, to prejudice him, and deter him from paying me his compliments as usual.

Unfortunately for me and for the public good, the Company's support and my complete trust have been given to a man who is completely unfit for the high position he holds and unworthy of the responsibilities entrusted to him. When I think of someone who has so greatly wounded my honor, my wounds feel fresh again, and I must be allowed the freedom to express myself, which my injuries and misfortunes naturally compel me to do. Shall your servants, unrestrained and unpunished, pursue their personal ambitions at the cost of my honor, my peace, and my happiness, leading to the downfall of my country, as well as your interests? As soon as Lord Macartney achieved his primary goal, he showed me the greatest disrespect, neglecting the common courtesies afforded to me by previous governors, even during the toughest times, and by even my fiercest enemies. He disrespected my servants, tried to ruin my reputation by unjustly criticizing my administration, and extended his unchecked control over the entire governance of my territories, into all judicial and police matters. In violation of the explicit terms of our agreements, he began sending renters into the regions without my approval, men of poor character who were unfit for any management or responsibility. Even though he is guilty of inhumane acts, including the bloodshed and mutilation of my subjects by those acting under his authority, even disrupting religious practices and public worship, he still does not collect even a quarter of the revenue that should be generated. His claims about expected revenue are completely false and will never be achieved under his leadership, given that he appoints totally unqualified, greedy, and irresponsible renters who are currently misappropriating and squandering public funds that should support the war. Completely focused on his private interests and driven by his emotions, he has neglected or sacrificed the critical needs of the public good. His lack of cooperation with Sir Eyre Coote and refusal to provide necessary supplies to the army have rendered the glorious victories of the brave general ineffective against our cruel enemy. To hide his incompetence and cover up the shame associated with his failures, he makes the most ungracious remarks and unfounded accusations against me; and to add to my distress, he has encouraged the lowest slanderers to bring false charges against me and my son, Amir-ul-Omrah, to frustrate me and cause me mental anguish. My documents and writings sent to you must demonstrate to the world the malignancy of his intentions and the methods used to advance them. He has violently seized and opened all letters addressed to me and my servants, regarding my public and private matters. My vakeel, who accompanied him as per ancient custom, has been disgracefully dismissed and not allowed to approach the Government House. In a lowly manner, believing he was acting in secret, he has been scheming and meddling with my family and relatives for the worst purposes. If I express the pain in my heart from these direct injuries and injustices, and complain about Lord Macartney's violence and injustices, he dismisses my concerns by insinuating that my words are influenced by others, while his own guilt for his misconduct has led him to make cowardly appeals to me to silence my feelings, begging me to write favorably about him to England and to hand over all my affairs to his management. When his pleas fail to bend me to his will, he has attempted to achieve his aims through threats of his supposed influence with those in power in England, claiming it will be enough to solidify his usurpation and strip me and my family of our rights to sovereignty and governance forever. His emotions and violence have gone so far that all my family, my dependents, and even my friends and visitors are being targeted with evident signs of his anger. Every semblance of authority I possess is stripped away, while respect for my name is discouraged throughout the country. Recently, when an officer of high rank in his Majesty's service was introduced to me by Lord Macartney, his Lordship took the opportunity to show personal mockery and disdain towards me. Mr. Richard Sulivan, who has attended my darbar under the commission of the Governor-General and Council of Bengal, has faced his ire; and Mr. Benfield, with whom I have no dealings, and who has regularly visited me out of respect for many years, has felt the burden of his Lordship's displeasure, facing unfounded insinuations thrown against him to tarnish his reputation and discourage him from visiting me as he usually does.

Thus, Gentlemen, have you delivered me over to a stranger; to a man unacquainted with government and business, and too opinionated to learn; to a man whose ignorance and prejudices operate to the neglect of every good measure, or the liberal coöperation with any that wish well to the public interests; to a man who, to pursue his own passions, plans, and designs, will certainly ruin all mine, as well as the Company's affairs. His mismanagement and obstinacy have caused the loss of many lacs of my revenues, dissipated and embezzled, and every public consideration sacrificed to his vanity and private views. I beg to offer an instance in proof of my assertions, and to justify the hope I have that you will cause to be made good to me all the losses I have sustained by the maladministration and bad practices of your servants, according to all the account of receipts of former years, and which I made known to Lord Macartney, amongst other papers of information, in the beginning of his management in the collections. The district of Ongole produced annually, upon a medium of many years, 90,000 pagodas; but Lord Macartney, upon receiving a sum of money from Ramchundry[73] let it out to him, in April last, for the inadequate rent of 50,000 pagodas per annum, diminishing, in this district alone, near half the accustomed revenues. After this manner hath he exercised his powers over the countries, to suit his own purposes and designs; and this secret mode has he taken to reduce the collections.

So, gentlemen, have you handed me over to a stranger? To a man who knows nothing about government and business and is too stubborn to learn; to a man whose ignorance and biases undermine every good initiative and the cooperation of anyone who genuinely cares about the public's interests; to someone who, in pursuing his own passions, plans, and schemes, is sure to ruin not only my interests but also the Company’s operations. His poor management and stubbornness have led to the loss of countless lacs of my revenues, wasted and misappropriated, with every public concern sacrificed to his vanity and personal agenda. I would like to provide an example to support my claims and justify my hope that you will compensate me for all the losses I have faced due to the mismanagement and unethical practices of your employees, based on all the receipts from previous years, which I presented to Lord Macartney, along with other documents, at the start of his oversight of the collections. The Ongole district used to generate about 90,000 pagodas annually, over many years. However, after receiving a payment from Ramchundry, Lord Macartney leased it out for a mere 50,000 pagodas a year, nearly cutting the district’s usual revenue in half. This is how he has exercised his authority over the regions, for his own interests; and this secretive approach has been his strategy to decrease the collections.


1st November, 1782. Copy of a Letter from the Nabob of Arcot to the Court of Directors, &c. Received 7th April, 1783.

The distresses which I have set forth in my former letters are now increased to such an alarming pitch by the imprudent measures of your Governor, and by the arbitrary and impolitic conduct pursued with the merchants and importers of grain, that the very existence of the Fort of Madras seems at stake, and that of the inhabitants of the settlement appears to have been totally overlooked: many thousands have died, and continue hourly to perish of famine, though the capacity of one of your youngest servants, with diligence and attention, by doing justice, and giving reasonable encouragement to the merchants, and by drawing the supplies of grain which the northern countries would have afforded, might have secured us against all those dreadful calamities. I had with much difficulty procured and purchased a small quantity of rice, for the use of myself, my family, and attendants, and with a view of sending off the greatest part of the latter to the northern countries, with a little subsistence in their hands. But what must your surprise be, when you learn that even this rice was seized by Lord Macartney, with a military force! and thus am I unable to provide for the few people I have about me, who are driven to such extremity and misery that it gives me pain to behold them. I have desired permission to get a little rice from the northern countries for the subsistence of my people, without its being liable to seizure by your sepoys: this even has been refused me by Lord Macartney. What must your feelings be, on such wanton cruelty exercised towards me, when you consider, that, of thousands of villages belonging to me, a single one would have sufficed for my subsistence!

The difficulties I described in my previous letters have now increased to such an alarming level due to your Governor's reckless decisions and the unfair treatment of merchants and grain importers, that the very survival of the Fort of Madras is in jeopardy, and the well-being of the settlement’s residents seems to have been completely ignored: countless individuals have died, and many continue to suffer from starvation, even though a diligent and careful approach from one of your youngest servants could have ensured that we received the grain supplies from the northern regions, protecting us from these terrible hardships. I had managed, with great effort, to purchase a small amount of rice for myself, my family, and my staff, planning to send most of it to the northern regions to help them survive. But what must your shock be when you find out that even this rice was confiscated by Lord Macartney, using military force! Now I am left unable to care for the few people with me, who are in such desperate straits that it pains me to see their suffering. I requested permission to obtain a bit of rice from the northern regions for my people’s survival, ensuring it wouldn’t be taken by your sepoys: this request was also denied by Lord Macartney. What must you feel, witnessing such wanton cruelty inflicted upon me, considering that a single one of the thousands of villages I own would have been enough for my survival!


22d March, 1783. Translation of a Letter from the Nabob of Arcot to the Chairman and Directors of the East India Company. Received from Mr. James Macpherson, 1st January, 1784.

I am willing to attribute this continued usurpation to the fear of detection in Lord Macartney: he dreads the awful day when the scene of his enormities will be laid open, at my restoration to my country, and when the tongues of my oppressed subjects will be unloosed, and proclaim aloud the cruel tyrannies they have sustained. These sentiments of his Lordship's designs are corroborated by his sending, on the 10th instant, two gentlemen to me and my son, Amir-ul-Omrah; and these gentlemen from Lord Macartney especially set forth to me, and to my son, that all dependence on the power of the superior government of Bengal to enforce the intentions of the Company to restore my country was vain and groundless,—that the Company confided in his Lordship's judgment and discretion, and upon his representations, and that if I, and my son, Amir-ul-Omrah, would enter into friendship with Lord Macartney, and sign a paper declaring all my charges and complaints against him to be false, that his Lordship might be induced to write to England that all his allegations against me and my son were not well founded, and, notwithstanding his declarations to withhold my country, yet, on these considerations, it might be still restored to me.

I believe Lord Macartney's ongoing takeover is driven by his fear of being exposed; he dreads the day when the truth about his wrongdoings will come to light when I return to my country, and when my oppressed people will finally speak out about the cruel tyranny they've endured. His motives are supported by his sending, on the 10th of this month, two men to me and my son, Amir-ul-Omrah. These men specifically told us that relying on the authority of the superior government of Bengal to enforce the Company’s plans to restore my country was pointless. They claimed that the Company trusted Lord Macartney's judgment and discretion, and on his word, if my son and I agreed to make peace with Lord Macartney and sign a document stating that all my accusations against him were false, then his Lordship might be persuaded to write to England saying that his claims against me and my son were unfounded. Despite his claims about withholding my country, these factors might still lead to its restoration.

What must be your feelings for your ancient and faithful friend, on his receiving such insults to his honor and understanding from your principal servant, armed with your authority! From these manoeuvres, amongst thousands I have experienced, the truth must evidently appear to you, that I have not been loaded with those injuries and oppressions from motives of public service, but to answer the private views and interests of his Lordship and his secret agents: some papers to this point are inclosed; others, almost without number, must be submitted to your justice, when time and circumstances shall enable me fully to investigate those transactions. This opportunity will not permit the full representation of my load of injuries and distresses: I beg leave to refer you to my minister, Mr. Macpherson, for the papers, according to the inclosed list, which accompanied my last dispatches by the Rodney, which I fear have failed; and my correspondence with Lord Macartney subsequent to that period, such as I have been able to prepare for this opportunity, are inclosed.

What must you be feeling for your long-time and loyal friend, seeing him face such insults to his honor and understanding from your main servant, acting on your authority! From these tactics, among the countless ones I've experienced, it must be clear to you that I haven't suffered these injuries and oppressions for the sake of public service, but to fulfill the personal goals and interests of his Lordship and his hidden agents: some papers on this matter are enclosed; many others must be presented to your fairness when time and circumstances allow me to fully investigate these events. This message doesn’t allow me to fully detail my burdens and struggles: I kindly ask you to refer to my minister, Mr. Macpherson, for the papers listed in the enclosed document, which accompanied my last dispatches via the Rodney, which I fear may have been lost; and my correspondence with Lord Macartney after that time, as much as I've been able to prepare for this opportunity, is enclosed.

Notwithstanding all the violent acts and declarations of Lord Macartney, yet a consciousness of his own misconduct was the sole incentive to the menaces and overtures he has held out in various shapes. He has been insultingly lavish in his expressions of high respect for my person; has had the insolence to say that all his measures flowed from his affectionate regard alone; has presumed to say that all his enmity and oppression were levelled at my son, Amir-ul-Omrah, to whom he before acknowledged every aid and assistance; and his Lordship being without any just cause or foundation for complaint against us, or a veil to cover his own violences, he has now had recourse to the meanness and has dared to intimate of my son, in order to intimidate me and to strengthen his own wicked purposes, to be in league with our enemies the French. You must doubtless be astonished, no less at the assurance than at the absurdity of such a wicked suggestion.

Despite all the violent actions and statements from Lord Macartney, his awareness of his own wrongdoing is the only reason behind the threats and proposals he has made in various forms. He has insultingly overexpressed his so-called high respect for me; he has had the audacity to claim that all his actions come from his affectionate regard; he has even had the nerve to say that his hostility and oppression were directed at my son, Amir-ul-Omrah, to whom he previously acknowledged providing help. With no legitimate reason to complain about us or any cover for his own wrongdoings, he has now resorted to the lowly tactic of insinuating that my son is colluding with our enemies, the French, in an attempt to intimidate me and further his own wicked agenda. You must surely be astonished, both at the nerve and the absurdity of such a despicable accusation.


IN THE NABOB'S OWN HAND.

P.S. In my own handwriting I acquainted Mr. Hastings, as I now do my ancient friends the Company, with the insult offered to my honor and understanding, in the extraordinary propositions sent to me by Lord Macartney, through two gentlemen, on the 10th instant, so artfully veiled with menaces, hopes, and promises. But how can Lord Macartney add to his enormities, after his wicked and calumniating insinuations, so evidently directed against me and my family, through my faithful, my dutiful, and beloved son, Amir-ul-Omrah, who, you well know, has been ever born and bred amongst the English, whom I have studiously brought up in the warmest sentiments of affection and attachment to them,—sentiments that in his maturity have been his highest ambition to improve, insomuch that he knows no happiness but in the faithful support of our alliance and connection with the English nation?

P.S. I personally informed Mr. Hastings, just as I now do my long-time friends at the Company, about the insult to my honor and understanding from the outrageous proposals sent to me by Lord Macartney through two gentlemen on the 10th of this month, cleverly disguised with threats, hopes, and promises. But how can Lord Macartney make his actions any worse after his malicious and slanderous insinuations clearly aimed at me and my family, through my loyal, dutiful, and beloved son, Amir-ul-Omrah, who, as you know, has been raised among the English? I have intentionally raised him with strong feelings of love and attachment to them—feelings that have become his greatest ambition as he grew up, to the point that he finds no happiness except in the steadfast support of our alliance and connection with the English nation?

12th August, and Postscript of the 16th August, 1783. Translation of a Letter to the Chairman and Directors of the East India Company. Received from Mr. James Macpherson, 14th January, 1784.

Your astonishment and indignation will be equally raised with mine, when you hear that your President has dared, contrary to your intention, to continue to usurp the privileges and hereditary powers of the Nabob of the Carnatic, your old and unshaken friend, and the declared ally of the king of Great Britain.

Your shock and anger will match mine when you hear that your President has dared, against your wishes, to keep taking the privileges and hereditary powers of the Nabob of the Carnatic, your longtime and steadfast friend, who is also the declared ally of the king of Great Britain.

I will not take up your time by enumerating the particular acts of Lord Macartney's violence, cruelty, and injustice: they, indeed, occur too frequently, and fall upon me and my devoted subjects and country too thick, to be regularly related. I refer you to my minister, Mr. James Macpherson, for a more circumstantial account of the oppressions and enormities by which he has brought both mine and the Company's affairs to the brink of destruction. I trust that such flagrant violations of all justice, honor, and the faith of treaties will receive the severest marks of your displeasure, and that Lord Macartney's conduct, in making use of your name and authority as a sanction for the continuance of his usurpation, will be disclaimed with the utmost indignation, and followed with the severest punishment. I conceive that his Lordship's arbitrary retention of my country and government can only originate in his insatiable cravings, in his implacable malevolence against me, and through fear of detection, which must follow the surrender of the Carnatic into my hands, of those nefarious proceedings which are now suppressed by the arm of violence and power.

I won’t waste your time listing the specific acts of violence, cruelty, and injustice committed by Lord Macartney: they happen far too often and hit me and my loyal subjects and country too hard to be detailed. I direct you to my minister, Mr. James Macpherson, for a more detailed account of the oppressions and atrocities that have brought both my interests and the Company's affairs to the edge of ruin. I hope that such blatant violations of justice, honor, and treaty obligations will provoke your strongest disapproval, and that Lord Macartney’s actions, in using your name and authority to justify his continued usurpation, will be rejected with the utmost outrage and punished severely. I believe that his Lordship’s wrongful hold on my country and government stems only from his endless greed, his relentless hatred toward me, and the fear of being exposed, which would follow if the Carnatic were handed back to me, regarding those wicked actions that are currently suppressed by force and power.

I did not fail to represent to the supreme government of Bengal the deplorable situation to which I was reduced, and the unmerited persecutions I have unremittingly sustained from Lord Macartney; and I earnestly implored them to stretch forth a saving arm, and interpose that controlling power which was vested in them, to check rapacity and presumption, and preserve the honor and faith of the Company from violation. The Governor-General and Council not only felt the cruelty and injustice I had suffered, but were greatly alarmed for the fatal consequences that might result from the distrust of the country powers in the professions of the English, when they saw the Nabob of the Carnatic, the friend of the Company, and the ally of Great Britain, thus stripped of his rights, his dominions, and his dignity, by the most fraudulent means, and under the mask of friendship. The Bengal government had already heard both the Mahrattas and the Nizam urge, as an objection to an alliance with the English, the faithless behavior of Lord Macartney to a prince whose life had been devoted and whose treasures had been exhausted in their service and support; and they did not hesitate to give positive orders to Lord Macartney for the restitution of my government and authority, on such terms as were not only strictly honorable, but equally advantageous to my friends the Company: for they justly thought that my honor and dignity and sovereign rights were the first objects of my wishes and ambition. But how can I paint my astonishment at Lord Macartney's presumption in continuing his usurpation after their positive and reiterated mandates, and, as if nettled by their interference, which he disdained, in redoubling the fury of his violence, and sacrificing the public and myself to his malice and ungovernable passions?

I made sure to inform the highest government of Bengal about the terrible situation I found myself in and the unfair persecution I kept facing from Lord Macartney. I urgently begged them to step in and use their authority to stop greed and arrogance, and to protect the honor and integrity of the Company from being undermined. The Governor-General and Council not only recognized the cruelty and injustice I had endured, but they were also very concerned about the serious fallout that could arise from the local powers distrusting the English. This was particularly true when they saw the Nabob of the Carnatic, a supporter of the Company and ally of Great Britain, stripped of his rights, lands, and dignity through deceitful means while pretending to be a friend. The Bengal government had already heard both the Mahrattas and the Nizam point out, as a reason not to ally with the English, Lord Macartney's betrayal of a prince who dedicated his life and depleted his resources in their service. They did not hesitate to order Lord Macartney to restore my government and authority on terms that were not only fully honorable but also beneficial to my friends at the Company. They rightly believed that my honor, dignity, and sovereign rights were my top priorities. But how can I express my disbelief at Lord Macartney's arrogance in continuing his takeover despite their clear and repeated orders and, as if irritated by their intervention, he responded by intensifying his violence and endangering both the public and myself out of his spite and uncontrollable rage?

I am, Gentlemen, at a loss to conceive where his usurpation will stop and have an end. Has he not solemnly declared that the assignment was only made for the support of war? and if neither your instructions nor the orders of his superiors at Bengal were to be considered as effectual, has not the treaty of peace virtually determined the period of his tyrannical administration? But so far from surrendering the Carnatic into my hands, he has, since that event, affixed advertisements to the walls and gates of the Black Town for letting to the best bidder the various districts for the term of three years,—and has continued the Committee of Revenue, which you positively ordered to be abolished, to whom he has allowed enormous salaries, from 6000 to 4000 pagodas per annum, which each member has received from the time of his appointment, though his Lordship well knows that most of them are by your orders disqualified by being my principal creditors.

I’m, Gentlemen, at a loss to understand where his takeover will stop and end. Has he not officially stated that the assignment was only for the support of the war? And if neither your instructions nor the orders from his superiors in Bengal are to be considered effective, hasn’t the peace treaty essentially set a limit on his oppressive rule? But instead of handing over the Carnatic to me, he has since that event posted notices on the walls and gates of the Black Town, offering the various districts to the highest bidder for a period of three years—and he has kept the Revenue Committee, which you specifically ordered to be dissolved, allowing them massive salaries, from 6000 to 4000 pagodas a year, which each member has been receiving since their appointment, even though he knows that most of them are disqualified by your orders since they are my main creditors.

If those acts of violence and outrage had been productive of public advantage, I conceive his Lordship might have held them forward in extenuation of his conduct; but whilst he cloaks his justification under the veil of your records, it is impossible to refute his assertions or to expose to you their fallacy; and when he is no longer able to support his conduct by argument, he refers to those records, where, I understand, he has exercised all his sophistry and malicious insinuations to render me and my family obnoxious in the eyes of the Company and the British nation. And when the glorious victories of Sir Eyre Coote have been rendered abortive by a constant deficiency of supplies,—and when, since the departure of that excellent general to Bengal, whose loss I must ever regret, a dreadful famine, at the close of last year, occasioned by his Lordship's neglect to lay up a sufficient stock of grain at a proper season, and from his prohibitory orders to private merchants,—and when no exertion has been made, nor advantage gained over the enemy,—when Hyder's death and Tippoo's return to his own dominions operated in no degree for the benefit of our affairs,—in short, when all has been a continued series of disappointment and disgrace under Lord Macartney's management, (and in him alone has the management been vested,)—I want words to convey those ideas of his insufficiency, ignorance, and obstinacy which I am convinced you would entertain, had you been spectators of his ruinous and destructive conduct.

If those acts of violence and outrage had brought some public benefit, I believe his Lordship might have highlighted them to justify his actions. However, by hiding his justification behind your records, it’s impossible to argue against his claims or reveal their falseness. When he can't back up his actions with reasoning, he turns to those records, where I understand he has used all his tricks and malicious suggestions to make me and my family look bad in the eyes of the Company and the British nation. And when the great victories of Sir Eyre Coote have been undermined by a persistent shortage of supplies, and since the departure of that excellent general to Bengal, whose absence I will always regret, a horrible famine at the end of last year occurred due to his Lordship’s failure to stockpile enough grain in time and his bans on private merchants. And when no effort has been made and no advantage gained over the enemy—when Hyder's death and Tippoo's return to his own lands did nothing to help our situation—in short, when everything has been a continuous series of disappointment and disgrace under Lord Macartney’s leadership, which he alone has held—I struggle to find words that express the ideas of his incompetence, ignorance, and stubbornness that I’m sure you would share if you had witnessed his damaging and destructive conduct.

But against me, and my son, Amir-ul-Omrah, has his Lordship's vengeance chiefly been exerted: even the Company's own subordinate zemindars have found better treatment, probably because they were more rich; those of Nizanagoram have been permitted, contrary to your pointed orders, to hold their rich zemindaries at the old disproportionate rate of little more than a sixth part of the real revenue; and my zemindar of Tanjore, though he should have regarded himself equally concerned with us in the event of the war, and from whose fertile country many valuable harvests have been gathered in, which have sold at a vast price, has, I understand, only contributed, last year, towards the public exigencies, the very inconsiderable sum of one lac of pagodas, and a few thousand pagodas' worth of grain.

But against me and my son, Amir-ul-Omrah, has his Lordship's anger been mainly directed: even the Company's own lower-level landlords have received better treatment, probably because they are wealthier; those in Nizanagoram have been allowed, in spite of your clear orders, to keep their rich lands at the old unfair rate of just over a sixth of the actual revenue; and my landlord in Tanjore, who should have felt equally invested in the outcome of the war, and from whose fertile land many valuable harvests have been collected and sold for a high price, has only contributed, last year, a rather insignificant sum of one lakh of pagodas, along with a few thousand pagodas' worth of grain.

I am much concerned to acquaint you that ever since the peace a dreadful famine has swept away many thousands of the followers and sepoys' families of the army, from Lord Macartney's neglect to send down grain to the camp, though the roads are crowded with vessels: but his Lordship has been too intent upon his own disgraceful schemes to attend to the wants of the army. The negotiation with Tippoo, which he has set on foot through the mediation of Monsieur Bussy, has employed all his thoughts, and to the attainment of that object he will sacrifice the dearest interests of the Company to gratify his malevolence against me, and for his own private advantages. The endeavor to treat with Tippoo, through the means of the French, must strike you, Gentlemen, as highly improper and impolitic; but it must raise your utmost indignation to hear, that, by intercepted letters from Bussy to Tippoo, as well as from their respective vakeels, and from various accounts from Cuddalore, we have every reason to conclude that his Lordship's secretary, Mr. Staunton, when at Cuddalore, as his agent to settle the cessation of arms with the French, was informed of all their operations and projects, and consequently that Lord Macartney has secretly connived at Monsieur Bussy's recommendation to Tippoo to return into the Carnatic, as the means of procuring the most advantageous terms, and furnishing Lord Macartney with the plea of necessity for concluding a peace after his own manner: and what further confirms the truth of this fact is, that repeated reports, as well as the alarms of the inhabitants to the westward, leave us no reason to doubt that Tippoo is approaching towards us. His Lordship has issued public orders that the garrison store of rice, for which we are indebted to the exertions of the Bengal government, should be immediately disposed of, and has strictly forbid all private grain to be sold; by which act he effectually prohibits all private importation of grain, and may eventually cause as horrid a famine as that which we experienced at the close of last year from the same shortsighted policy and destructive prohibitions of Lord Macartney.

I’m very concerned to inform you that since the peace, a terrible famine has affected thousands of families of our soldiers and sepoys, due to Lord Macartney's failure to send grain to the camp, even though the roads are filled with ships. His Lordship has been too focused on his own shameful plans to care for the needs of the army. The negotiations with Tippoo, which he has started through Monsieur Bussy's mediation, have consumed all his attention, and for the sake of achieving this goal, he will sacrifice the Company's most important interests to satisfy his grudge against me and for his own personal gain. The attempt to negotiate with Tippoo through the French must seem to you, Gentlemen, both inappropriate and unwise; but it should outrage you to learn that intercepted letters from Bussy to Tippoo, as well as communications from their respective agents and various reports from Cuddalore, give us every reason to believe that his Lordship's secretary, Mr. Staunton, while at Cuddalore to negotiate the ceasefire with the French, was informed of all their plans and maneuvers. It follows that Lord Macartney has secretly supported Monsieur Bussy's suggestion to Tippoo to return to Carnatic as a way to secure the best possible terms, while giving Lord Macartney the excuse he needs to negotiate a peace in his own way: and what further confirms this fact is that repeated reports and the concerns of the residents to the west make us confident that Tippoo is moving toward us. His Lordship has issued public orders to immediately sell off the rice stockpile, for which we owe the efforts of the Bengal government, and has strictly forbidden the sale of private grain. This action effectively prevents any private import of grain, potentially leading to a famine as horrific as the one we faced at the end of last year due to Lord Macartney's same short-sighted policies and destructive prohibitions.

But as he has the fabrication of the records in his own hands, he trusts to those partial representations of his character and conduct, because the signatures of those members of government whom he seldom consults are affixed, as a public sanction; but you may form a just idea of their correctness and propriety, when you are informed that his Lordship, upon my noticing the heavy disbursements made for secret service money, ordered the sums to be struck off, and the accounts to be erased from the cash-book of the Company; and I think I cannot give you a better proof of his management of my country and revenues than by calling your attention to his conduct in the Ongole province, and by referring you to his Lordship's administration of your own jaghire, from whence he has brought to the public account the sum of twelve hundred pagodas for the last year's revenue, yet blazons forth his vast merits and exertions, and expects to receive the thanks of his Committee and Council.

But since he controls the creation of the records, he relies on those biased representations of his character and actions, because the signatures of government officials he rarely consults are attached, serving as public approval; however, you can get a clear idea of how accurate and appropriate they are when I mention that his Lordship, after I pointed out the significant expenditures made for secret service funds, ordered the amounts to be removed and the entries to be deleted from the Company's cash book; and I believe I can't provide you with a better example of his management of my country and its revenues than by highlighting his actions in the Ongole province and referring you to his Lordship's administration of your own jaghire, from which he has brought to the public account the sum of twelve hundred pagodas for last year's revenue, yet he boasts of his tremendous merits and efforts and expects to be thanked by his Committee and Council.

I will beg leave to refer you to my minister, James Macpherson, Esq., for a more particular account of my sufferings and miseries, to whom I have transmitted copies of all papers that passed with his Lordship.

I would like to direct you to my minister, James Macpherson, Esq., for a more detailed account of my sufferings and hardships, to whom I have sent copies of all the documents that were exchanged with his Lordship.

I cannot conclude without calling your attention to the situation of my different creditors, whose claims are the claims of justice, and whose demands I am bound by honor and every moral obligation to discharge; it is not, therefore, without great concern I have heard insinuations tending to question the legality of their right to the payment of those just debts: they proceeded from advances made by them openly and honorably for the support of my own and the public affairs. But I hope the tongue of calumny will never drown the voice of truth and justice; and while that is heard, the wisdom of the English nation cannot fail to accede to an effectual remedy for their distresses, by any arrangement in which their claims may be duly considered and equitably provided for: and for this purpose, my minister, Mr. Macpherson, will readily subscribe, in my name, to any agreement you may think proper to adopt, founded on the same principles with either of the engagements I entered into with the supreme government of Bengal for our mutual interest and advantage.

I can’t wrap this up without bringing your attention to the situation with my various creditors, whose claims are just and rightful, and whose demands I feel obligated by honor and every moral duty to fulfill. It’s with great concern that I’ve heard suggestions questioning the legality of their right to receive payment for these legitimate debts: these debts arose from advances they made openly and honorably to support my own matters as well as public affairs. However, I trust that the voice of truth and justice will never be silenced by slander; as long as that voice is heard, the wisdom of the English nation will surely lead to an effective solution for their struggles through any arrangement that properly considers and fairly addresses their claims. To this end, my minister, Mr. Macpherson, will gladly agree, in my name, to any arrangement you think is appropriate, based on the same principles as the agreements I made with the supreme government of Bengal for our mutual benefit.

I always pray for your happiness and prosperity.

I always wish for your happiness and success.


6th September, and Postscript of 7th September, 1783. Translation of a Letter from the Nabob of Arcot to the Chairman and Directors of the East India Company. Received from Mr. James Macpherson, 14th January, 1784.

I refer you, Gentlemen, to my inclosed duplicate, as well as to my minister, Mr. Macpherson, for the particulars of my sufferings. There is no word or action of mine that is not perverted; and though it was my intention to have sent my son, Amir-ul-Omrah, who is well versed in my affairs, to Bengal, to impress those gentlemen with a full sense of my situation, yet I find myself obliged to lay it aside, from the insinuations of the calumniating tongue of Lord Macartney, that takes every license to traduce every action of my life and that of my son. I am informed that Lord Macartney, at this late moment, intends to write a letter: I am ignorant of the subject, but fully perceive, that, by delaying to send it till the very eve of the dispatch, he means to deprive me of all possibility of communicating my reply, and forwarding it for the information of my friends in England. Conscious of the weak ground on which he stands, he is obliged to have recourse to these artifices to mislead the judgment, and support for a time his unjustifiable measures by deceit and imposition. I wish only to meet and combat his charges and allegations fairly and openly, and I have repeatedly and urgently demanded to be furnished with copies of those parts of his fabricated records relative to myself; but as he well knows I should refute his sophistry, I cannot be surprised at his refusal, though I lament that it prevents you, Gentlemen, from a clear investigation of his conduct towards me.

I refer you, Gentlemen, to the enclosed duplicate, as well as to my minister, Mr. Macpherson, for the details of my suffering. There’s no word or action of mine that hasn’t been twisted; and although I intended to send my son, Amir-ul-Omrah, who understands my affairs well, to Bengal to help those gentlemen fully grasp my situation, I now find myself forced to set that aside because of the malicious insinuations spread by Lord Macartney, who takes every chance to slander every action of my life and my son’s. I’ve been informed that Lord Macartney, at this late hour, plans to write a letter: I have no idea what it’s about, but I can clearly see that by delaying it until the very last minute, he means to prevent me from communicationg my response and sending it to my friends in England. Aware of how weak his position is, he resorts to these tactics to mislead judgment and temporarily support his unjust actions through deceit and trickery. I only wish to confront and challenge his accusations openly and honestly, and I have repeatedly and urgently asked to receive copies of those parts of his fabricated records related to me; but as he knows I could easily debunk his arguments, I can’t be surprised by his refusal, though I regret that it stops you, Gentlemen, from thoroughly investigating his behavior towards me.

Inclosed you have a translation of an arzee from the Killidar of Vellore. I have thousands of the same kind; but this, just now received, will serve to give you some idea of the miseries brought upon this my devoted country, and the wretched inhabitants that remain in it, by the oppressive hand of Lord Macartney's management: nor will the embezzlements of collections thus obtained, when brought before you in proof, appear less extraordinary,—which shall certainly be done in due time.

Enclosed is a translation of a report from the Killidar of Vellore. I have thousands more like this; but this one, just received, will give you some sense of the suffering inflicted on my devoted country and the miserable people still living here by Lord Macartney's oppressive management. The misappropriations of funds obtained in this way will seem just as surprising when presented to you as evidence, which will definitely be done in due time.

Translation of an Arzee, in the Persian Language, from Uzzim-ul-Doen Cawn, the Killidar of Vellore, to the Nabob, dated 1st September, 1783. Inclosed in the Nabob's Letter to the Court of Directors, September, 1783.

Translation of an Arzee, in the Persian Language, from Uzzim-ul-Doen Cawn, the Killidar of Vellore, to the Nabob, dated September 1, 1783. Inclosed in the Nabob's Letter to the Court of Directors, September, 1783.

I have repeatedly represented to your Highness the violences and oppressions exercised by the present aumildar [collector of revenue], of Lord Macartney's appointment, over the few remaining inhabitants of the districts of Vellore, Amboor, Saulguda, &c.

I have repeatedly informed your Highness about the violence and oppression carried out by the current aumildar [collector of revenue], appointed by Lord Macartney, against the few remaining residents of the districts of Vellore, Amboor, Saulguda, etc.

The outrages and violences now committed are of that astonishing nature as were never known or heard of during the administration of the Circar. Hyder Naik, the cruellest of tyrants, used every kind of oppression in the Circar countries; but even his measures were not like those now pursued. Such of the inhabitants as had escaped the sword and pillage of Hyder Naik, by taking refuge in the woods, and within the walls of Vellore, &c., on the arrival of Lord Macartney's aumildar to Vellore, and in consequence of his cowle of protection and support, most cheerfully returned to the villages, set about the cultivation of the lands, and with great pains rebuilt their cottages.—But now the aumildar has imprisoned the wives and children of the inhabitants, seized the few jewels that were on the bodies of the women, and then, before the faces of their husbands, flogged them, in order to make them produce other jewels and effects, which he said they had buried somewhere under ground, and to make the inhabitants bring him money, notwithstanding there was yet no cultivation in the country. Terrified with the flagellations, some of them produced their jewels and wearing-apparel of their women, to the amount of ten or fifteen pagodas, which they had hidden; others, who declared they had none, the aumildar flogged their women severely, tied cords around their breasts, and tore the sucking children from their teats, and exposed them to the scorching heat of the sun. Those children died, as did the wife of Ramsoamy, an inhabitant of Bringpoor. Even this could not stir up compassion in the breast of the aumildar. Some of the children that were somewhat large he exposed to sale. In short, the violences of the aumildar are so astonishing, that the people, on seeing the present situation, remember the loss of Hyder with regret. With whomsoever the aumildar finds a single measure of natchinee or rice, he takes it away from him, and appropriates it to the expenses of the sibindy that he keeps up. No revenues are collected from the countries, but from the effects of the poor, wretched inhabitants. Those ryots [yeomen] who intended to return to their habitations, hearing of those violences, have fled for refuge, with their wives and children, into Hyder's country. Every day is ushered in and closed with these violences and disturbances. I have no power to do anything; and who will hear what I have to say? My business is to inform your Highness, who are my master. The people bring their complaints to me, and I tell them I will write to your Highness.[74]

The shocking acts of violence happening now are unlike anything seen or heard during the Circar's rule. Even Hyder Naik, the most brutal tyrant, employed every form of oppression in the Circar territories; yet his actions pale in comparison to what's happening today. Those who managed to escape Hyder Naik’s sword and looting by hiding in the woods or within the walls of Vellore, returned to their villages when Lord Macartney's aumildar arrived, bringing promises of protection and support. They happily resumed farming and painstakingly rebuilt their homes. But now, the aumildar has imprisoned the wives and children of the people, taken the few jewels that women wore, and brutally beat the men in front of their families to force them to reveal buried treasures and to extort money from them, despite the lack of agricultural activity in the area. Fearful of the beatings, some produced hidden jewels and clothing worth ten or fifteen pagodas; others who claimed they had nothing saw their women severely beaten, with cords tied around their breasts. Babies were ripped from nursing mothers and exposed to the blazing sun, resulting in the death of those infants, including the child of Ramsoamy, a resident of Bringpoor. Even this cruelty failed to evoke any sympathy from the aumildar. Some older children were sold off. In short, the aumildar's actions are so horrifying that the people now wish for the days of Hyder with sadness. He confiscates even the smallest measure of natchinee or rice from anyone he finds, using it to cover the costs of his operations. No revenue is collected from the land but comes instead from the suffering of the impoverished inhabitants. Ryots who planned to return home, hearing of these atrocities, have fled with their families back to Hyder's territory. Each day begins and ends with more violence and chaos. I feel powerless to intervene, and who will listen to what I have to say? My duty is to inform your Highness, my master. The people come to me with their grievances, and I assure them I will write to you.

Translation of a Tellinga Letter from Veira Permaul, Head Dubash to Lord Macartney, in his own Handwriting, to Rajah Ramchunda, the Renter of Ongole. Dated 25th of the Hindoo month Mausay, in the year Plavanamal, corresponding to 5th March, 1782.

Translation of a Letter from Veira Permaul, Head Dubash to Lord Macartney, in his own Handwriting, to Rajah Ramchunda, the Renter of Ongole. Dated 25th of the Hindu month Mausay, in the year Plavanamal, corresponding to 5th March, 1782.

I present my respects to you, and am very well here, wishing to hear frequently of your welfare.

I send my regards and I'm doing well here, hoping to hear from you often about how you are doing.

Your peasher Vancatroyloo has brought the Visseel Bakees, and delivered them to me, as also what you sent him for me to deliver to my master, which I have done. My master at first refused to take it, because he is unacquainted with your disposition, or what kind of a person you are. But after I made encomiums on your goodness and greatness of mind, and took my oath to the same, and that it would not become public, but be held as precious as our lives, my master accepted it. You may remain satisfied that I will get the Ongole business settled in your name; I will cause the jamaubundee to be settled agreeable to your desire. It was formerly the Nabob's intention to give this business to you, as the Governor knows full well, but did not at that time agree to it, which you must be well acquainted with.

Your messenger Vancatroyloo has brought the Visseel Bakees and delivered them to me, as well as what you sent him to give to my master, which I’ve done. At first, my master refused to accept it because he doesn’t know you well or what kind of person you are. But after I praised your kindness and great character and swore it would remain confidential and be treasured as much as our lives, my master accepted it. You can be assured that I will get the Ongole business resolved in your name; I will ensure the jamaubundee is settled according to your wishes. It was previously the Nabob's intention to award this business to you, as the Governor knows very well, but he didn’t agree to it at that time, which I’m sure you are aware of.

Your peasher Vancatroyloo is a very careful, good man; he is well experienced in business; he has bound me by an oath to keep all this business secret, and that his own, yours, and my lives are responsible for it. I write this letter to you with the greatest reluctance, and I signified the same to your peasher, and declared that I would not write to you by any means. To this the peasher urged, that, if I did not write to his master, how could he know to whom he (the peasher) delivered the money, and what must his master think of it? Therefore I write you this letter, and send it by my servant Ramanah, accompanied by the peasher's servant, and it will come safe to your hands. After perusal, you will send it back to me immediately: until I receive it, I don't like to eat my victuals or take any sleep. Your peasher took his oath, and urged me to write this for your satisfaction, and has engaged to me that I shall have this letter returned to me in the space of twelve days.

Your merchant Vancatroyloo is a very careful, good man; he is experienced in business; he has sworn me to keep all this business secret, and that our lives—his, yours, and mine—depend on it. I write this letter to you very reluctantly, and I expressed the same to your merchant, stating that I wouldn’t write to you under any circumstances. In response, the merchant insisted that, if I didn’t write to his master, how would he know to whom he (the merchant) was delivering the money, and what would his master think about it? So, I’m sending you this letter through my servant Ramanah, along with the merchant's servant, ensuring it will reach you safely. After you read it, please send it back to me right away: until I receive it, I can’t eat or sleep well. Your merchant took his oath and urged me to write this for your peace of mind, and he promised that this letter will be returned to me within twelve days.

The present Governor is not like the former Governors: he is a very great man in Europe; and all the great men of Europe are much obliged, to him for his condescension in accepting the government of this place. It is his custom, when he makes friendship with any one, to continue it always; and if he is at enmity with any one, he never will desist till he has worked his destruction. He is now exceedingly displeased with the Nabob, and you will understand by-and-by that the Nabob's business cannot be carried on; he (the Nabob) will have no power to do anything in his own affairs: you have, therefore, no room to fear him; you may remain with a contented mind. I desired the Governor to write you a letter for your satisfaction: the Governor said he would do so, when the business was settled. This letter you must peruse as soon as possible, and send it back with all speed by the bearer, Ramadoo, accompanied by three or four of your people, to the end that no accident may happen on the road. These people must be ordered to march in the night only, and to arrive here with the greatest dispatch. You sent ten mangoes for my master and two for me, all of which I have delivered to my master, thinking that ten was not sufficient to present him with. I write this for your information, and salute you with ten thousand respects.

The current Governor is quite different from previous Governors: he is a highly respected figure in Europe, and all the important people there are very grateful for his willingness to take on the leadership of this place. He tends to maintain friendships for life, and if he has a feud with someone, he won’t stop until he brings about their downfall. Right now, he is very angry with the Nabob, and you'll understand shortly that the Nabob won't be able to manage his own affairs; he won't have any power. So, you really have nothing to worry about; you can stay calm. I asked the Governor to write you a letter for your peace of mind, and he said he would do that once matters were resolved. You should read this letter as soon as you get it and send it back quickly with Ramadoo, the messenger, along with three or four of your people, to make sure nothing goes wrong on the way. These people should only travel at night and get here as fast as they can. You sent ten mangoes for my master and two for me, and I've given all of them to my master, thinking ten wouldn’t be enough as a gift for him. I'm writing this to keep you informed and send you my best regards.

I, Muttu Kistnah, of Madras Patnam, dubash, declare that I perfectly understand the Gentoo language, and do most solemnly affirm that the foregoing is a true translation of the annexed paper writing from the Gentoo language.

I, Muttu Kistnah, from Madras Patnam, declare that I completely understand the Gentoo language, and I solemnly affirm that the above is a true translation of the attached document from the Gentoo language.

(Signed)

(Signed)

Muttu Kistnah.

Muttu Kistnah.

FOOTNOTES:

[68] In this statement, the Ongole country, though it is included under the head of gross revenue, has been let for a certain sum, exclusive of charges. If the expenses specified in the Nabob's vassool accounts for this district are added, the present gross revenue even would appear to exceed the Nabob's; and as the country is only let for one year, there may hereafter be an increase of its revenue.

[68] In this statement, the Ongole region, although categorized under gross revenue, has been rented for a specific amount, not including expenses. If we factor in the costs mentioned in the Nabob's collection accounts for this area, the current gross revenue would seem to surpass the Nabob's; and since the region is only leased for one year, there could be an increase in its revenue in the future.

[69] The Trichinopoly countries let for the above sum, exclusive of the expenses of sibbendy and saderwared, amounting, by the Nabob's accounts, to rupees 1,30,00 per annum, which are to be defrayed by the renter. And the jaghires of Amir-ul-Omrah and the Begum are not included in the present lease.

[69] The Trichinopoly territories are leased for the amount mentioned above, not counting the costs of sibbendy and saderwared, which total, according to the Nabob’s accounts, 1,30,00 rupees per year, and these expenses will be paid by the renter. The jaghires of Amir-ul-Omrah and the Begum are not part of this lease.

[70] For the ground of this "great reliance," see the papers in this Appendix, No. 5. as also the Nabob's letters to the Court of Directors in this Appendix, No. 10.

[70] For the reason behind this "great reliance," refer to the documents in this Appendix, No. 5. Also, look at the Nabob's letters to the Court of Directors in this Appendix, No. 10.

[71] For the full proof of this necessity, Lord Macartney's whole correspondence on the subject may be referred to. Without the act here condemned, not one of the acts commended in the preceding paragraph could be performed. By referring to the Nabob's letters in this Appendix it will be seen what sort of task a governor has on his hands, who is to use, according to the direction of this letter, "acts of address, civility, and conciliation," and to pay, upon all occasions, the highest attention, to persons who at the very time are falsely, and in the grossest terms, accusing him of peculation, corruption, treason, and every species of malversation in office. The recommendation, under menaces of such behavior, and under such circumstances, conveys a lesson the tendency of which cannot be misunderstood.

[71] For a complete proof of this necessity, you can check Lord Macartney's entire correspondence on the topic. Without this condemned action, none of the recommended actions in the previous paragraph could take place. By looking at the Nabob's letters in this Appendix, you can see the kind of challenges a governor faces when trying to employ, as directed in this letter, "acts of address, civility, and conciliation," while also paying, on all occasions, the highest attention to individuals who at that very moment are falsely and outrageously accusing him of theft, corruption, treason, and all forms of misconduct in office. The suggestion, made under threats of such treatment and in such circumstances, teaches a lesson that is impossible to misinterpret.

[72] The delicacy here recommended, in the expressions concerning conduct "with which the safety of our settlements is essentially connected," is a lesson of the same nature with the former. Dangerous designs, if truly such, ought to be expressed according to their nature and qualities. And as for the secrecy recommended concerning the designs here alluded to, nothing can be more absurd; as they appear very fully and directly in the papers published by the authority of the Court of Directors in 1775, and may be easily discerned from the propositions for the Bengal treaty, published in the Reports of the Committee of Secrecy, and in the Reports of the Select Committee. The keeping of such secrets too long has been one cause of the Carnatic war, and of the ruin of our affairs in India.

[72] The caution recommended here, regarding conduct "that is essentially linked to the safety of our settlements," is a lesson similar to the previous one. Dangerous plans, if they truly are, should be articulated based on their nature and characteristics. As for the secrecy suggested about the plans mentioned, nothing could be more ridiculous; they are clearly outlined in the papers published by the authority of the Court of Directors in 1775, and can easily be identified from the proposals for the Bengal treaty found in the Reports of the Committee of Secrecy and in the Reports of the Select Committee. Keeping such secrets for too long has contributed to the Carnatic war and the decline of our operations in India.

[73] See Tellinga letter, at the end of this correspondence.

[73] Check the letter from Tellinga at the end of this correspondence.

[74] The above-recited practices, or practices similar to them, have prevailed in almost every part of the miserable countries on the coast of Coromandel for near twenty years past. That they prevailed as strongly and generally as they could prevail, under the administration of the Nabob, there can be no question, notwithstanding the assertion in the beginning of the above petition; nor will it ever be otherwise, whilst affairs are conducted upon the principles which influence the present system. Whether the particulars here asserted are true or false neither the Court of Directors nor their ministry have thought proper to inquire. If they are true, in order to bring them to affect Lord Macartney, it ought to be proved that the complaint was made to him, and that he had refused redress. Instead of this fair course, the complaint is carried to the Court of Directors.—The above is one of the documents transmitted by the Nabob, in proof of his charge of corruption against Lord Macartney. If genuine, it is conclusive, at least against Lord Macartney's principal agent and manager. If it be a forgery, (as in all likelihood it is,) it is conclusive against the Nabob and his evil counsellors, and folly demonstrates, if anything further were necessary to demonstrate, the necessity of the clause in Mr. Fox's bill prohibiting the residence of the native princes in the Company's principal settlements,—which clause was, for obvious reasons, not admitted into Mr. Pitt's. It shows, too, the absolute necessity of a severe and exemplary punishment on certain of his English evil counsellors and creditors, by whom such practices are carried on.

[74] The practices mentioned above, or similar ones, have been common in nearly all the unfortunate regions along the coast of Coromandel for almost twenty years. There's no doubt that they occurred as strongly and widely as possible under the rule of the Nabob, regardless of the claim made at the start of the above petition; this will remain true as long as things are managed according to the current system. Whether the claims made here are true or false, neither the Court of Directors nor their administration have seen fit to look into it. If they are true, to hold Lord Macartney accountable, it must be proven that the complaint was made to him, and that he refused to provide a solution. Instead of following this reasonable path, the complaint is brought to the Court of Directors. The above document was sent by the Nabob as evidence for his accusation of corruption against Lord Macartney. If it's authentic, it decisively implicates at least Lord Macartney's main agent and overseer. If it's forged, (which is highly likely), it will conclusively point the finger at the Nabob and his corrupt advisors, and it further illustrates the need for the clause in Mr. Fox's bill that prevents native princes from living in the Company's main settlements—this clause was not included in Mr. Pitt's bill for clear reasons. It also highlights the urgent need for serious and exemplary punishment of certain English advisors and creditors who enable such practices.


SUBSTANCE OF THE SPEECH

IN THE

DEBATE ON THE ARMY ESTIMATES

IN THE HOUSE OF COMMONS,

On Tuesday, February 9, 1790

UNDERSTANDING

A DISCUSSION OF THE PRESENT SITUATION OF AFFAIRS IN FRANCE.


Mr. Burke's speech on the report of the army estimates has not been correctly stated in some of the public papers. It is of consequence to him not to be misunderstood. The matter which incidentally came into discussion is of the most serious importance. It is thought that the heads and substance of the speech will answer the purpose sufficiently. If, in making the abstract, through defect of memory in the person who now gives it, any difference at all should be perceived from the speech as it was spoken, it will not, the editor imagines, be found in anything which may amount to a retraction of the opinions he then maintained, or to any softening in the expressions in which they were conveyed.

Mr. Burke's speech about the army budget hasn't been accurately reported in some of the media. It's important for him to avoid being misunderstood. The topics that came up during the discussion are extremely important. It's believed that the main points of the speech will serve their purpose well enough. If, while summarizing, there are any inaccuracies due to the memory of the person providing this summary, the editor believes these will not reflect any change in the opinions he expressed or any softening in the way he conveyed them.

Mr. Burke spoke a considerable time in answer to various arguments, which had been insisted upon by Mr. Grenville and Mr. Pitt, for keeping an increased peace establishment, and against an improper jealousy of the ministers, in whom a full confidence, subject to responsibility, ought to be placed, on account of their knowledge of the real situation of affairs, the exact state of which it frequently happened that they could not disclose without violating the constitutional and political secrecy necessary to the well-being of their country.

Mr. Burke spoke for quite a while in response to the various arguments made by Mr. Grenville and Mr. Pitt about maintaining a larger peace establishment and against an unnecessary distrust of the ministers. He emphasized that there should be full confidence in them, as long as they are held accountable, due to their understanding of the actual situations at hand. Often, they couldn't share the exact details without breaching the constitutional and political confidentiality essential for the country's well-being.

Mr. Burke said in substance, That confidence might become a vice, and jealousy a virtue, according to circumstances. That confidence, of all public virtues, was the most dangerous, and jealousy in an House of Commons, of all public vices, the most tolerable,—- especially where the number and the charge of standing armies in time of peace was the question.

Mr. Burke stated essentially that confidence could turn into a vice and jealousy could be seen as a virtue, depending on the circumstances. He argued that confidence, more than any other public virtue, was the most dangerous, while jealousy, among all public vices, was the most acceptable—especially when the discussion involved the number and cost of standing armies during peacetime.

That in the annual Mutiny Bill the annual army was declared to be for the purpose of preserving the balance of power in Europe. The propriety of its being larger or smaller depended, therefore, upon the true state of that balance. If the increase of peace establishments demanded of Parliament agreed with the manifest appearance of the balance, confidence in ministers as to the particulars would be very proper. If the increase was not at all supported by any such appearance, he thought great jealousy might be, and ought to be, entertained on that subject.

That in the yearly Mutiny Bill, the annual army was stated to be for the purpose of maintaining the balance of power in Europe. The appropriateness of it being larger or smaller depended on the actual state of that balance. If the increase of peace forces requested by Parliament matched the obvious signs of the balance, then it would be reasonable to have confidence in the ministers regarding the specifics. If the increase wasn't supported by any such signs, he believed there should be significant concern about that issue.

That he did not find, on a review of all Europe, that, politically, we stood in the smallest degree of danger from any one state or kingdom it contained, nor that any other foreign powers than our own allies were likely to obtain a considerable preponderance in the scale.

That he did not find, after reviewing all of Europe, that we were in any political danger from any state or kingdom within it, nor that any foreign powers other than our own allies were likely to gain a significant advantage.

That France had hitherto been our first object in all considerations concerning the balance of power. The presence or absence of France totally varied every sort of speculation relative to that balance.

That France had always been our main focus in all discussions about the balance of power. The presence or absence of France completely changed every kind of speculation related to that balance.

That France is at this time, in a political light, to be considered as expunged out of the system of Europe. Whether she could ever appear in it again, as a leading power, was not easy to determine; but at present be considered France as not politically existing; and most assuredly it would take up much time to restore her to her former active existence: Gallos quoque in bellis floruisse audivimus might possibly be the language of the rising generation. He did not mean to deny that it was our duty to keep our eye on that nation, and to regulate our preparation by the symptoms of her recovery.

France is currently, in political terms, seen as being removed from the European system. It's hard to say if she could ever return as a major power; for now, we should consider France as not politically existing. It would definitely take a long time to restore her to her former active status: We have also heard that the Gauls flourished in wars might very well be what the next generation says. I’m not saying we should ignore that country; it’s our responsibility to watch her and adjust our preparations based on signs of her recovery.

That it was to her strength, not to her form of government, which we were to attend; because republics, as well as monarchies, were susceptible of ambition, jealousy, and anger, the usual causes of war.

That it was her strength, not her form of government, that we should focus on; because republics, just like monarchies, could be influenced by ambition, jealousy, and anger, which are the typical causes of war.

But if, while France continued in this swoon, we should go on increasing our expenses, we should certainly make ourselves less a match for her when it became our concern to arm.

But if, while France was still in this daze, we kept raising our expenses, we would definitely weaken our ability to compete when it was time for us to arm ourselves.

It was said, that, as she had speedily fallen, she might speedily rise again. He doubted this. That the fall from an height was with an accelerated velocity; but to lift a weight up to that height again was difficult, and opposed by the laws of physical and political gravitation.

It was said that since she had fallen quickly, she could rise again just as fast. He didn't believe that. He knew that falling from a height happened quickly, but lifting something back up to that height was hard and worked against the rules of both physical and political gravity.

In a political view, France was low indeed. She had lost everything, even to her name.

In terms of politics, France was in a bad place. She had lost everything, even her name.

Huge trunk lies on the shore, Avolsumque humeris head, and without name body. [75]

He was astonished at it; he was alarmed at it; he trembled at the uncertainty of all human greatness.

He was amazed by it; he was worried about it; he shook at the unpredictability of all human greatness.

Since the House had been prorogued in the summer much work was done in France. The French had shown themselves the ablest architects of ruin that had hitherto existed in the world. In that very short space of time they had completely pulled down to the ground their monarchy, their church, their nobility, their law, their revenue, their army, their navy, their commerce, their arts, and their manufactures. They had done their business for us as rivals in a way in which twenty Ramillies or Blenheims could never have done it. Were we absolute conquerors, and France to lie prostrate at our feet, we should be ashamed to send a commission to settle their affairs which could impose so hard a law upon the French, and so destructive of all their consequence as a nation, as that they had imposed upon themselves.

Since the House had been suspended for the summer, a lot of work was done in France. The French had proven themselves to be the most skilled architects of destruction the world had ever seen. In that short period, they had completely dismantled their monarchy, church, nobility, law, revenue, army, navy, commerce, arts, and industries. They had done more harm to us as rivals than twenty Ramillies or Blenheims ever could. If we were total conquerors and France was at our mercy, we would be embarrassed to send a commission to settle their issues that could enforce such harsh rules on the French—rules that were so damaging to their standing as a nation—that they had imposed on themselves.

France, by the mere circumstance of its vicinity, had been, and in a degree always must be, an object of our vigilance, either with regard to her actual power or to her influence and example. As to the former he had spoken; as to the latter (her example) he should say a few words: for by this example our friendship and our intercourse with that nation had once been, and might again become, more dangerous to us than their worst hostility.

France, simply because it's nearby, has always been and will likely always be something we need to keep an eye on, both in terms of its actual power and its influence and example. He had already talked about the former; now, regarding the latter (its example), he wants to say a few things: because of this example, our friendship and interactions with that country were once, and could become again, more risky for us than their worst enmity.

In the last century, Louis the Fourteenth had established a greater and better disciplined military force than ever had been before seen in Europe, and with it a perfect despotism. Though that despotism was proudly arrayed in manners, gallantry, splendor, magnificence, and even covered over with the imposing robes of science, literature, and arts, it was, in government, nothing better than a painted and gilded tyranny,—in religion, a hard, stern intolerance, the fit companion and auxiliary to the despotic tyranny which prevailed in its government. The same character of despotism insinuated itself into every court of Europe,—the same spirit of disproportioned magnificence,—the same love of standing armies, above the ability of the people. In particular, our then sovereigns, King Charles and King James, fell in love with the government of their neighbor, so flattering to the pride of kings. A similarity of sentiments brought on connections equally dangerous to the interests and liberties of their country. It were well that the infection had gone no farther than the throne. The admiration of a government flourishing and successful, unchecked in its operations, and seeming, therefore, to compass its objects more speedily and effectually, gained something upon all ranks of people. The good patriots of that day, however, struggled against it. They sought nothing more anxiously than to break off all communication with France, and to beget a total alienation from its councils and its example,—which, by the animosity prevalent between the abettors of their religious system and the assertors of ours, was in some degree effected.

In the last century, Louis XIV established a stronger and better-disciplined military force than had ever been seen in Europe, along with a perfect dictatorship. Although this dictatorship was proudly dressed in manners, gallantry, splendor, magnificence, and even cloaked with the impressive robes of science, literature, and the arts, it was, in terms of governance, nothing more than a decorated and gilded tyranny—in religion, it was a harsh, strict intolerance, the perfect partner and support for the despotic tyranny that dominated its government. This same type of despotism seeped into every court in Europe—the same spirit of disproportionate grandeur—the same preference for standing armies that exceeded what the people could support. In particular, our then-sovereigns, King Charles and King James, became enamored with the governance of their neighbor, which was so flattering to royal pride. A similar mindset led to connections that were equally hazardous to the interests and freedoms of their country. It was fortunate that the influence didn't extend beyond the throne. The admiration for a flourishing and successful government, unrestrained in its actions, and therefore seeming to achieve its goals more quickly and effectively, gained some traction among all social classes. However, the good patriots of that time fought against it. They desperately sought to cut off all ties with France and to create a complete separation from its decisions and examples—which, due to the animosity that existed between the supporters of their religious system and the advocates of ours, was somewhat achieved.

This day the evil is totally changed in France: but there is an evil there. The disease is altered; but the vicinity of the two countries remains, and must remain; and the natural mental habits of mankind are such, that the present distemper of France is far more likely to be contagious than the old one: for it is not quite easy to spread a passion for servitude among the people; but in all evils of the opposite kind our natural inclinations are flattered. In the case of despotism, there is the fœdum crimen servitutis: in the last, the falsa SPECIES libertatis; and accordingly, as the historian says, pronis auribus accipitur.

This day, the situation has completely changed in France: but there is still a problem there. The issue has evolved; however, the proximity of the two countries remains and will continue to do so. The natural tendencies of people are such that the current troubles in France are much more likely to spread than the previous ones: it's not exactly easy to instill a desire for servitude among the people; but with all problems of the opposite nature, our natural inclinations are pleased. In the case of despotism, there is the fœdum crimen servitutis: and in the last, the falsa SPECIES libertatis; and thus, as the historian says, pronis auribus accipitur.

In the last age we were in danger of being entangled by the example of France in the net of a relentless despotism. It is not necessary to say anything upon that example. It exists no longer. Our present danger from the example of a people whose character knows no medium is, with regard to government, a danger from anarchy: a danger of being led, through an admiration of successful fraud and violence, to an imitation of the excesses of an irrational, unprincipled, proscribing, confiscating, plundering, ferocious, bloody, and tyrannical democracy. On the side of religion, the danger of their example is no longer from intolerance, but from atheism: a foul, unnatural vice, foe to all the dignity and consolation of mankind; which seems in France, for a long time, to have been embodied into a faction, accredited, and almost avowed.

In recent times, we faced the risk of being trapped by France's example in a harsh dictatorship. There's no need to elaborate on that example, as it no longer exists. Currently, our threat from a people with no middle ground in their character is, in terms of government, a risk of anarchy: a danger of being swayed by a fascination with successful deceit and violence, leading us to mimic the excesses of a reckless, unprincipled, persecuting, confiscating, looting, brutal, bloody, and tyrannical democracy. Regarding religion, the danger presented by their example is no longer intolerance, but atheism: a vile, unnatural vice that undermines all the dignity and comfort of humanity; which seems to have become entrenched in a faction in France, officially recognized and almost accepted.

These are our present dangers from France. But, in his opinion, the very worst part of the example set is in the late assumption of citizenship by the army, and the whole of the arrangement, or rather disarrangement, of their military.

These are our current threats from France. However, in his view, the worst aspect is the army's recent claim to citizenship, along with the entire organization, or rather disorganization, of their military.

He was sorry that his right honorable friend (Mr. Fox) had dropped even a word expressive of exultation on that circumstance, or that he seemed of opinion that the objection from standing armies was at all lessened by it. He attributed this opinion of Mr. Fox entirely to his known zeal for the best of all causes, liberty. That it was with a pain inexpressible he was obliged to have even the shadow of a difference with his friend, whose authority would always be great with him, and with all thinking people,—Quæ maxima semper censetur nobis, et ERIT quæ maxima semper;—his confidence in Mr. Fox was such, and so ample, as to be almost implicit. That he was not ashamed to avow that degree of docility. That, when the choice is well made, it strengthens, instead of oppressing our intellect. That he who calls in the aid of an equal understanding doubles his own. He who profits of a superior understanding raises his powers to a level with the height of the superior understanding he unites with. He had found the benefit of such a junction, and would not lightly depart from it. He wished almost, on all occasions, that his sentiments were understood to be conveyed in Mr. Fox's words. And that he wished, as amongst the greatest benefits he could wish the country, an eminent share of power to that right honorable gentleman; because he knew that to his great and masterly understanding he had joined the greatest possible degree of that natural moderation which is the best corrective of power: that he was of the most artless, candid, open, and benevolent disposition; disinterested in the extreme; of a temper mild and placable even to a fault; without one drop of gall in his whole constitution.

He regretted that his respected friend (Mr. Fox) had even expressed a hint of triumph about that situation, or that he seemed to think the objection regarding standing armies was in any way diminished by it. He believed Mr. Fox's opinion stemmed entirely from his well-known passion for the greatest cause of all, liberty. It caused him indescribable pain to have even a slight disagreement with his friend, whose opinion would always hold significant weight with him and with all reasonable people,—Quæ maxima semper censetur nobis, et ERIT quæ maxima semper;—his confidence in Mr. Fox was so deep and generous that it was almost unquestioning. He wasn’t ashamed to admit that level of openness. When a choice is made wisely, it enhances rather than stifles our intellect. Those who seek help from an equal understanding amplify their own. Those who benefit from a superior understanding elevate their own abilities to match the higher understanding they join with. He had experienced the advantages of such a partnership and wouldn’t easily part with it. He often wished that his thoughts could be expressed in Mr. Fox's words. He also hoped, as one of the greatest benefits he could wish for the country, for a significant share of power to go to that honorable gentleman; because he knew that Mr. Fox combined his vast and masterful intellect with an exceptional degree of natural moderation, which is the best check on power: that he was the most sincere, candid, open, and kind-hearted person; completely selfless; of a temperament that was gentle and forgiving even to a fault; without a trace of bitterness in his entire character.

That the House must perceive, from his coming forward to mark an expression or two of his best friend, how anxious he was to keep the distemper of France from the least countenance in England, where he was sure some wicked persons had shown a strong disposition to recommend an imitation of the French spirit of reform. He was so strongly opposed to any the least tendency towards the means of introducing a democracy like theirs, as well as to the end itself, that, much as it would afflict him, if such a thing could be attempted, and that any friend of his could concur in such measures, (he was far, very far, from believing they could,) he would abandon his best friends, and join with his worst enemies, to oppose either the means or the end,—and to resist all violent exertions of the spirit of innovation, so distant from all principles of true and safe reformation: a spirit well calculated to overturn states, but perfectly unfit to amend them.

The House must understand, from his willingness to highlight a few words from his close friend, how concerned he was about preventing the issues of France from gaining any support in England, where he knew some malicious individuals had shown a strong tendency to promote mimicking the French reformist attitude. He was completely against any hint of adopting the methods that could lead to a democracy like theirs, as well as the very idea itself; although it would deeply trouble him if such a thing were attempted, and if any friend of his could support such actions (he was very far from believing they could), he would turn against his closest allies and stand with his fiercest opponents to fight both the methods and the idea itself. He aimed to resist all extreme attempts at innovation, which strayed far from the principles of true and safe reform: a spirit that could easily upend governments but was totally incapable of improving them.

That he was no enemy to reformation. Almost every business in which he was much concerned, from the first day he sat in that House to that hour, was a business of reformation; and when he had not been employed in correcting, he had been employed in resisting abuses. Some traces of this spirit in him now stand on their statute-book. In his opinion, anything which unnecessarily tore to pieces the contexture of the state not only prevented all real reformation, but introduced evils which would call, but perhaps call in vain, for new reformation.

That he was no opponent of change. Almost every issue he was deeply involved in, from the first day he joined that House to now, was about making reforms; and when he wasn’t focused on fixing things, he was busy fighting against abuses. Some evidence of this determination is now recorded in their laws. In his view, anything that unnecessarily disrupted the fabric of the state not only hindered genuine reform but also created problems that would demand, though possibly in vain, for further reforms.

That he thought the French nation very unwise. What they valued themselves on was a disgrace to them. They had gloried (and some people in England had thought fit to take share in that glory) in making a Revolution, as if revolutions were good things in themselves. All the horrors and all the crimes of the anarchy which led to their Revolution, which attend its progress, and which may virtually attend it in its establishment, pass for nothing with the lovers of revolutions. The French have made their way, through the destruction of their country, to a bad constitution, when they were absolutely in possession of a good one. They were in possession of it the day the states met in separate orders. Their business, had they been either virtuous or wise, or had been left to their own judgment, was to secure the stability and independence of the states, according to those orders, under the monarch on the throne. It was then their duty to redress grievances.

He believed the French nation was very unwise. What they took pride in was actually shameful for them. They celebrated (and some people in England thought it was right to join in that celebration) their Revolution, as if revolutions were good things by nature. All the horrors and crimes of the chaos that led to their Revolution, that accompanied its progress, and that may continue with its establishment, mean nothing to revolution enthusiasts. The French have reached a poor constitution through the destruction of their country, even when they had a good one. They had a solid constitution on the day the states convened in separate orders. Their responsibility, if they had been either virtuous or wise, or if had been left to their own judgment, was to ensure the stability and independence of the states, according to those orders, under the reigning monarch. At that point, it was their duty to address grievances.

Instead of redressing grievances, and improving the fabric of their state, to which they were called by their monarch and sent by their country, they were made to take a very different course. They first destroyed all the balances and counterpoises which serve to fix the state and to give it a steady direction, and which furnish sure correctives to any violent spirit which may prevail in any of the orders. These balances existed in their oldest constitution, and in the constitution of this country, and in the constitution of all the countries in Europe. These they rashly destroyed, and then they melted down the whole into one incongruous, ill-connected mass.

Instead of addressing complaints and improving their state as their monarch called for and their country needed, they took a completely different path. They first dismantled all the checks and balances that are meant to stabilize the state and provide a steady direction, which serve as reliable corrections to any extreme attitudes that may arise in any group. These checks and balances were part of their original constitution, the constitution of this country, and the constitutions of all the countries in Europe. They foolishly destroyed these, and then they fused everything into a chaotic, disorganized mess.

When they had done this, they instantly, and with the most atrocious perfidy and breach of all faith among men, laid the axe to the root of all property, and consequently of all national prosperity, by the principles they established and the example they set, in confiscating all the possessions of the Church. They made and recorded a sort of institute and digest of anarchy, called the Rights of Man, in such a pedantic abuse of elementary principles as would have disgraced boys at school: but this declaration of rights was worse than trifling and pedantic in them; as by their name and authority they systematically destroyed every hold of authority by opinion, religious or civil, on the minds of the people. By this mad declaration they subverted the state, and brought on such calamities as no country, without a long war, has ever been known to suffer, and which may in the end produce such a war, and perhaps many such.

After they did this, they immediately and with the most terrible betrayal broke all trust among people by attacking the foundation of all property, and therefore all national prosperity, through the principles they set and the example they followed in seizing all the Church’s possessions. They created and documented a sort of institute and digest of chaos, called the Rights of Man, in such a pedantic misuse of basic principles that it would have shamed schoolboys: but this declaration of rights was more than just trivial and pedantic for them; by using their name and authority, they systematically undermined every form of authority, religious or civil, in the minds of the people. This reckless declaration destabilized the state and led to calamities that no country has ever experienced without a prolonged war, which may ultimately lead to such a war, and perhaps many more.

With them the question was not between despotism and liberty. The sacrifice they made of the peace and power of their country was not made on the altar of freedom. Freedom, and a better security for freedom than that they have taken, they might have had without any sacrifice at all. They brought themselves into all the calamities they suffer, not that through them they might obtain a British constitution; they plunged themselves headlong into those calamities to prevent themselves from settling into that constitution, or into anything resembling it.

With them, the issue wasn't about choosing between oppression and freedom. The sacrifice they made of their country's peace and power wasn't done for the sake of freedom. They could have achieved freedom, along with better protection for it than what they've chosen, without making any sacrifices at all. They brought upon themselves all the suffering they endure, not to gain a British constitution; they threw themselves into those hardships to avoid settling into that constitution or anything similar.

That, if they should perfectly succeed in what they propose, as they are likely enough to do, and establish a democracy, or a mob of democracies, in a country circumstanced like France, they will establish a very bad government,—a very bad species of tyranny.

That, if they manage to completely succeed in what they intend, which is quite possible, and create a democracy, or a collection of democracies, in a country like France, they will end up establishing a really poor government—a terrible form of tyranny.

That the worst effect of all their proceeding was on their military, which was rendered an army for every purpose but that of defence. That, if the question was, whether soldiers were to forget they were citizens, as an abstract proposition, he could have no difference about it; though, as it is usual, when abstract principles are to be applied, much was to be thought on the manner of uniting the character of citizen and soldier. But as applied to the events which had happened in France, where the abstract principle was clothed with its circumstances, he thought that his friend would agree with him, that what was done there furnished no matter of exultation, either in the act or the example. These soldiers were not citizens, but base, hireling mutineers, and mercenary, sordid deserters, wholly destitute of any honorable principle. Their conduct was one of the fruits of that anarchic spirit from the evils of which a democracy itself was to be resorted to, by those who were the least disposed to that form, as a sort of refuge. It was not an army in corps and with discipline, and embodied under the respectable patriot citizens of the state in resisting tyranny. Nothing like it. It was the case of common soldiers deserting from their officers, to join a furious, licentious populace. It was a desertion to a cause the real object of which was to level all those institutions, and to break all those connections, natural and civil, that regulate and hold together the community by a chain of subordination: to raise soldiers against their officers, servants against their masters, tradesmen against their customers, artificers against their employers, tenants against their landlords, curates against their bishops, and children against their parents. That this cause of theirs was not an enemy to servitude, but to society.

The worst outcome of all their actions was on their military, which became an army for every purpose except defense. If the question was whether soldiers should forget they were citizens, as a general idea, he had no disagreement with that; although, as often happens when applying abstract principles, a lot needed to be considered about how to combine the roles of citizen and soldier. But regarding the events that occurred in France, where the abstract principle was shaped by its context, he believed his friend would agree with him that what happened there wasn’t something to celebrate, either in the action or the example. These soldiers were not citizens; they were nothing but mercenary traitors, completely lacking any honorable principles. Their actions were one of the results of the chaotic spirit, which, ironically, a democracy itself was turned to by those least inclined towards that form, as a refuge. It was not an organized army with discipline, made up of respectable, patriotic citizens of the state resisting tyranny. Far from it. It was a situation where common soldiers abandoned their officers to join a wild, lawless mob. It was a betrayal to a cause whose true goal was to dismantle all those institutions and break all those connections—natural and civil—that organize and hold together the community through a chain of subordination: raising soldiers against their officers, servants against their masters, tradespeople against their customers, workers against their employers, tenants against their landlords, clergy against their bishops, and children against their parents. This cause of theirs was not against servitude, but against society.

He wished the House to consider how the members would like to have their mansions pulled down and pillaged, their persons abused, insulted, and destroyed, their title-deeds brought out and burned before their faces, and themselves and their families driven to seek refuge in every nation throughout Europe, for no other reason than this, that, without any fault of theirs, they were born gentlemen and men of property, and were suspected of a desire to preserve their consideration and their estates. The desertion in France was to aid an abominable sedition, the very professed principle of which was an implacable hostility to nobility and gentry, and whose savage war-whoop was, "A l'Aristocrate!"—by which senseless, bloody cry they animated one another to rapine and murder; whilst abetted by ambitious men of another class, they were crushing everything respectable and virtuous in their nation, and to their power disgracing almost every name by which we formerly knew there was such a country in the world as France.

He wanted the House to think about how the members would feel if their mansions were torn down and looted, their people mistreated, insulted, and destroyed, their property deeds brought out and burned in front of them, and themselves and their families forced to seek refuge in every country across Europe, for no other reason than that, without any fault of their own, they were born gentlemen and property owners, and were suspected of wanting to keep their status and estates. The unrest in France was to support a disgusting uprising, whose openly stated goal was to have an unyielding hostility towards the nobility and gentry, and whose savage battle cry was, "A l'Aristocrate!"—by which senseless, bloody shout they incited each other to robbery and murder; while backed by ambitious people from another class, they were destroying everything respectable and virtuous in their nation, and in their wake tarnishing almost every name by which we once recognized that there was such a country as France.

He knew too well, and he felt as much as any man, how difficult it was to accommodate a standing army to a free constitution, or to any constitution. An armed disciplined body is, in its essence, dangerous to liberty; undisciplined, it is ruinous to society. Its component parts are in the latter case neither good citizens nor good soldiers. What have they thought of in France, under such a difficulty as almost puts the human faculties to a stand? They have put their army under such a variety of principles of duty, that it is more likely to breed litigants, pettifoggers, and mutineers than soldiers.[76] They have set up, to balance their crown army, another army, deriving under another authority, called a municipal army,—a balance of armies, not of orders. These latter they have destroyed with every mark of insult and oppression. States may, and they will best, exist with a partition of civil powers. Armies cannot exist under a divided command. This state of things he thought in effect a state of war, or at best but a truce, instead of peace, in the country.

He knew all too well, and he understood just like anyone else, how tough it was to align a standing army with a free constitution, or any constitution for that matter. An armed, disciplined group is inherently a threat to liberty; if it's undisciplined, it can be destructive to society. In the latter case, its members are neither good citizens nor good soldiers. What have they been thinking in France, faced with a challenge that almost halts human reasoning? They've placed their army under such a mix of duties that it's more likely to produce litigators, schemers, and rebels than actual soldiers.[76] They have established, to counter their royal army, another force under a different authority, referred to as a municipal army—a balance of armies, not of orders. They have wiped out the latter with every form of insult and oppression. States can exist, and thrive, with a division of civil powers. Armies cannot function under a split command. He believed this situation was essentially a state of war, or at best just a truce, rather than true peace, in the country.

What a dreadful thing is a standing army for the conduct of the whole or any part of which no man is responsible! In the present state of the French crown army, is the crown responsible for the whole of it? Is there any general who can be responsible for the obedience of a brigade, any colonel for that of a regiment, any captain for that of a company? And as to the municipal army, reinforced as it is by the new citizen deserters, under whose command are they? Have we not seen them, not led by, but dragging, their nominal commander, with a rope about his neck, when they, or those whom they accompanied, proceeded to the most atrocious acts of treason and murder? Are any of these armies? Are any of these citizens?

What a terrible thing a standing army is when no one is accountable for the actions of all or even part of it! In the current state of the French crown army, is the crown responsible for its entirety? Is there any general who can be held accountable for a brigade's obedience, any colonel for a regiment's, or any captain for a company's? And what about the municipal army, bolstered by the new citizen deserters—who commands them? Haven't we seen them, not led by, but dragging their supposed leader along with a rope around his neck, as they or those they were with committed the most atrocious acts of treason and murder? Are any of these armies really armies? Are any of these people truly citizens?

We have in such a difficulty as that of fitting a standing army to the state, he conceived, done much better. We have not distracted our army by divided principles of obedience. We have put them under a single authority, with a simple (our common) oath of fidelity; and we keep the whole under our annual inspection. This was doing all that could be safely done.

We have faced challenges in aligning a standing army with the state, he thought, but we’ve handled it much better. We haven’t confused our army with conflicting principles of obedience. We’ve placed them under one authority, with a straightforward (our shared) oath of loyalty; and we oversee the entire force with an annual review. This was everything that could be responsibly achieved.

He felt some concern that this strange thing called a Revolution in France should be compared with the glorious event commonly called the Revolution in England, and the conduct of the soldiery on that occasion compared with the behavior of some of the troops of France in the present instance. At that period, the Prince of Orange, a prince of the blood-royal in England, was called in by the flower of the English aristocracy to defend its ancient Constitution, and not to level all distinctions. To this prince, so invited, the aristocratic leaders who commanded the troops went over with their several corps, in bodies, to the deliverer of their country. Aristocratic leaders brought up the corps of citizens who newly enlisted in this cause. Military obedience changed its object; but military discipline was not for a moment interrupted in its principle. The troops were ready for war, but indisposed to mutiny.

He was worried that this strange thing called a Revolution in France should be compared to the glorious event typically known as the Revolution in England, and that the conduct of the soldiers during that time should be compared to the behavior of some of the troops in France now. Back then, the Prince of Orange, a member of the English royal family, was called in by the elite of English society to protect its traditional Constitution, not to eliminate all social distinctions. To this prince, who was invited, the aristocratic leaders commanding the troops joined him with their respective units to support the liberator of their country. The aristocratic leaders also brought in the newly enlisted citizen troops for this cause. Military loyalty shifted its focus, but military discipline remained intact. The troops were prepared for battle but were not inclined to mutiny.

But as the conduct of the English armies was different, so was that of the whole English nation at that time. In truth, the circumstances of our Revolution (as it is called) and that of France are just the reverse of each other in almost every particular, and in the whole spirit of the transaction. With us it was the case of a legal monarch attempting arbitrary power; in France it is the case of an arbitrary monarch beginning, from whatever cause, to legalize his authority. The one was to be resisted, the other was to be managed and directed; but in neither case was the order of the state to be changed, lest government might be ruined, which ought only to be corrected and legalized. With us we got rid of the man, and preserved the constituent parts of the state. There they get rid of the constituent parts of the state, and keep the man. What we did was in truth and substance, and in a constitutional light, a revolution, not made, but prevented. We took solid securities; we settled doubtful questions; we corrected anomalies in our law. In the stable, fundamental parts of our Constitution we made no revolution,—no, nor any alteration at all. We did not impair the monarchy. Perhaps it might be shown that we strengthened it very considerably. The nation kept the same ranks, the same orders, the same privileges, the same franchises, the same rules for property, the same subordinations, the same order in the law, in the revenue, and in the magistracy,—the same lords, the same commons, the same corporations, the same electors.

But while the actions of the English armies were different, so was the behavior of the entire English nation at that time. In reality, the circumstances of our Revolution (as it’s called) and that of France are almost completely opposite in every way and in the overall spirit of the events. For us, it was about a legal monarch trying to seize arbitrary power; in France, it’s about an arbitrary monarch starting, for whatever reason, to legitimize his authority. One was to be resisted, while the other needed to be managed and guided; but in neither case was the order of the state supposed to change, so that governance wouldn’t be destroyed, which should only be corrected and legalized. We got rid of the person, while keeping the essential parts of the state. There, they are discarding the essential parts of the state while keeping the person. What we did was truly and fundamentally a revolution in a constitutional sense, not one made, but prevented. We took strong measures; we resolved uncertain issues; we corrected inconsistencies in our laws. In the stable, foundational aspects of our Constitution, we didn’t create a revolution—no, nor did we make any changes at all. We didn’t undermine the monarchy. In fact, it could be argued that we significantly strengthened it. The nation maintained the same ranks, the same orders, the same privileges, the same rights, the same property laws, the same hierarchies, the same legal order, revenue system, and magistracy— the same lords, the same commons, the same corporations, the same voters.

The Church was not impaired. Her estates, her majesty, her splendor, her orders and gradations, continued the same. She was preserved in her full efficiency, and cleared only of a certain intolerance, which was her weakness and disgrace. The Church and the State were the same after the Revolution that they were before, but better secured in every part.

The Church was not affected. Her properties, her dignity, her grandeur, her ranks and levels, continued to be the same. She was maintained in her full strength and only rid of a particular intolerance, which was her flaw and shame. The Church and the State were the same after the Revolution as they were before, but better protected in every aspect.

Was little done because a revolution was not made in the Constitution? No! Everything was done; because we commenced with reparation, not with ruin. Accordingly, the state flourished. Instead of lying as dead, in a sort of trance, or exposed, as some others, in an epileptic fit, to the pity or derision of the world, for her wild, ridiculous, convulsive movements, impotent to every purpose but that of dashing out her brains against the pavement, Great Britain rose above the standard even of her former self. An era of a more improved domestic prosperity then commenced, and still continues, not only unimpaired, but growing, under the wasting hand of time. All the energies of the country were awakened. England never preserved a firmer countenance or a more vigorous arm to all her enemies and to all her rivals. Europe under her respired and revived. Everywhere she appeared as the protector, assertor, or avenger of liberty. A war was made and supported against fortune itself. The treaty of Ryswick, which first limited the power of France, was soon after made; the grand alliance very shortly followed, which shook to the foundations the dreadful power which menaced the independence of mankind. The states of Europe lay happy under the shade of a great and free monarchy, which knew how to be great without endangering its own peace at home or the internal or external peace of any of its neighbors.

Was anything accomplished because there wasn't a revolution in the Constitution? No! A lot was achieved; we started with rebuilding rather than destruction. As a result, the state thrived. Instead of lying lifeless in a daze, or being exposed like some others in a chaotic spasm, drawing the world's pity or ridicule with its wild, ridiculous, convulsive actions, and futilely banging its head against the ground, Great Britain rose above even its former glory. A period of improved domestic prosperity began and continues, not only intact but growing, even as time takes its toll. All the country's energies were awakened. England has never shown a steadier face or a stronger resolve against its enemies and rivals. Europe breathed easier and revived under its influence. Everywhere, it stood as the protector, defender, or avenger of liberty. A war was fought and sustained against adversity itself. The Treaty of Ryswick, which first curtailed France's power, was signed soon after; the grand alliance quickly followed, shaking the foundations of the terrible power that threatened the independence of humanity. The nations of Europe flourished under the protection of a great and free monarchy that knew how to be powerful without risking its own peace or the internal or external peace of its neighbors.

Mr. Burke said he should have felt very unpleasantly, if he had not delivered these sentiments. He was near the end of his natural, probably still nearer the end of his political career. That he was weak and weary, and wished for rest. That he was little disposed to controversies, or what is called a detailed opposition. That at his time of life, if he could not do something by some sort of weight of opinion, natural or acquired, it was useless and indecorous to attempt anything by mere struggle. Turpe senex miles. That he had for that reason little attended the army business, or that of the revenue, or almost any other matter of detail, for some years past. That he had, however, his task. He was far from condemning such opposition; on the contrary, he most highly applauded it, where a just occasion existed for it, and gentlemen had vigor and capacity to pursue it. Where a great occasion occurred, he was, and, while he continued in Parliament, would be, amongst the most active and the most earnest,—as he hoped he had shown on a late event. With respect to the Constitution itself, he wished few alterations in it,—happy if he left it not the worse for any share he had taken in its service.

Mr. Burke said he would have felt very uncomfortable if he hadn’t shared these thoughts. He was nearing the end of his life, and probably even closer to the end of his political career. He felt weak and tired and wanted peace. He wasn’t really interested in debates or what people call detailed opposition. At his age, if he couldn’t achieve something through some kind of influence, whether natural or gained, it was pointless and improper to try to do it through mere struggle. Turpe senex miles. For this reason, he had paid little attention to military affairs, revenue issues, or almost any other detailed matters for the past few years. However, he had his responsibilities. He was certainly not against such opposition; on the contrary, he strongly supported it when there was a valid reason and when others had the energy and ability to pursue it. When significant issues arose, he had been, and as long as he remained in Parliament, would be among the most active and the most fervent—he hoped he had demonstrated this during a recent event. Regarding the Constitution itself, he preferred to see few changes—hoping he left it not worse for having participated in its service.


Mr. Fox then rose, and declared, in substance, that, so far as regarded the French army, he went no farther than the general principle, by which that army showed itself indisposed to be an instrument in the servitude of their fellow-citizens, but did not enter into the particulars of their conduct. He declared that he did not affect a democracy: that he always thought any of the simple, unbalanced governments bad: simple monarchy, simple aristocracy, simple democracy,—he held them all imperfect or vicious; all were bad by themselves; the composition alone was good. That these had been always his principles, in which he had agreed with his friend Mr. Burke,—of whom he had said many kind and flattering things, which Mr. Burke, I take it for granted, will know himself too well to think he merits from anything but Mr. Fox's acknowledged good-nature. Mr. Fox thought, however, that, in many cases, Mr. Burke was rather carried too far by his hatred to innovation.

Mr. Fox then stood up and stated that, regarding the French army, he wouldn't go further than the general idea that this army was unwilling to be a tool for the oppression of their fellow citizens, but he wouldn't get into the specifics of their actions. He made it clear that he didn't profess to be a democrat; he always believed that any of the straightforward, unbalanced types of government were problematic: straightforward monarchy, straightforward aristocracy, and straightforward democracy—he viewed all of them as flawed or harmful; each was bad on its own; only their combination was good. These had always been his beliefs, which he shared with his friend Mr. Burke—of whom he had said many kind and complimentary things, which Mr. Burke, I assume, knows he doesn't deserve except for Mr. Fox's acknowledged good nature. However, Mr. Fox thought that, in many cases, Mr. Burke was somewhat excessively driven by his disdain for change.

Mr. Burke said, he well knew that these had been Mr. Fox's invariable opinions; that they were a sure ground for the confidence of his country. But he had been fearful that cabals of very different intentions would be ready to make use of his great name, against his character and sentiments, in order to derive a credit to their destructive machinations.

Mr. Burke said he knew that these had always been Mr. Fox's consistent beliefs and that they provided solid grounds for his country's trust. However, he was worried that groups with very different agendas would exploit his prominent name to undermine his character and views in order to gain legitimacy for their harmful plans.

Mr. Sheridan then rose, and made a lively and eloquent speech against Mr. Burke; in which, among other things, he said that Mr. Burke had libelled the National Assembly of France, and had cast out reflections on such characters as those of the Marquis de La Fayette and Mr. Bailly.

Mr. Sheridan then stood up and delivered a spirited and articulate speech against Mr. Burke, in which he stated that Mr. Burke had defamed the National Assembly of France and had made disparaging remarks about figures like the Marquis de La Fayette and Mr. Bailly.

Mr. Burke said, that he did not libel the National Assembly of France, whom he considered very little in the discussion of these matters. That he thought all the substantial power resided in the republic of Paris, whose authority guided, or whose example was followed by, all the republics of France. The republic of Paris had an army under their orders, and not under those of the National Assembly.

Mr. Burke stated that he did not defame the National Assembly of France, which he regarded as having minimal influence in these discussions. He believed that all the real power was held by the republic of Paris, whose authority directed or whose example was emulated by all the republics in France. The republic of Paris had an army under its command, not under that of the National Assembly.

N.B. As to the particular gentlemen, I do not remember that Mr. Burke mentioned either of them,—certainly not Mr. Bailly. He alluded, undoubtedly, to the case of the Marquis de La Fayette; but whether what he asserted of him be a libel on him must be left to those who are acquainted with the business.

N.B. Regarding the specific gentlemen, I don’t recall Mr. Burke mentioning either of them—certainly not Mr. Bailly. He was definitely referring to the case of the Marquis de La Fayette; however, whether what he claimed about him is slander is something that must be determined by those familiar with the matter.

Mr. Pitt concluded the debate with becoming gravity and dignity, and a reserve on both sides of the question, as related to France, fit for a person in a ministerial situation. He said, that what he had spoken only regarded France when she should unite, which he rather thought she soon might, with the liberty she had acquired, the blessings of law and order. He, too, said several civil things concerning the sentiments of Mr. Burke, as applied to this country.

Mr. Pitt wrapped up the debate with appropriate seriousness and dignity, maintaining a balanced view on both sides of the issue regarding France, which was suitable for someone in a ministerial position. He mentioned that his comments only applied to France when it eventually unites, which he believed could happen soon, with the freedom it had gained and the benefits of law and order. He also expressed several respectful thoughts about Mr. Burke's opinions in relation to this country.

FOOTNOTES:

[75] Mr. Burke probably had in his mind the remainder of the passage, and was filled with some congenial apprehensions:—

[75] Mr. Burke was likely thinking about the rest of the passage and felt some familiar concerns:—

This is the end of Priam's fate; this is how it ended for him. The fate brought forth, seeing Troy burned and fallen. Pergama, once proud among so many peoples and lands Regnatorem Asiæ. A huge trunk lies on the shore,
He carried his head on his shoulders, and his body was nameless.
At me then for the first time a cruel fear surrounded me.
I was stunned: the image of my father on the chariot appeared.

[76] They are Sworn to obey the king, the nation, and the law.

[76] They promise to follow the king, the country, and the law.


REFLECTIONS

ON THE

REVOLUTION IN FRANCE,

AND ON

THE PROCEEDINGS IN CERTAIN SOCIETIES IN LONDON RELATIVE TO THAT EVENT:

IN A LETTER

MEANT TO BE SENT TO A GENTLEMAN IN PARIS.

1790.


It may not be unnecessary to inform the reader that the following Reflections had their origin in a correspondence between the author and a very young gentleman at Paris, who did him the honor of desiring his opinion upon the important transactions which then, and ever since have, so much occupied the attention of all men. An answer was written some time in the month of October, 1789; but it was kept back upon prudential considerations. That letter is alluded to in the beginning of the following sheets. It has been since forwarded to the person to whom it was addressed. The reasons for the delay in sending it were assigned in a short letter to the same gentleman. This produced on his part a new and pressing application for the author's sentiments.

It may be worth mentioning that the following reflections originated from a correspondence between the author and a very young man in Paris, who honored the author by asking for his opinion on the significant events that have captured everyone's attention then and since. An answer was drafted sometime in October 1789, but it was held back for practical reasons. That letter is referenced at the beginning of the following pages. It has since been sent to the individual it was meant for. The reasons for the delay in sending it were explained in a brief letter to the same gentleman. This led to a new and urgent request from him for the author's thoughts.

The author began a second and more full discussion on the subject. This he had some thoughts of publishing early in the last spring; but the matter gaining upon him, he found that what he had undertaken not only far exceeded the measure of a letter, but that its importance required rather a more detailed consideration than at that time he had any leisure to bestow upon it. However, having thrown down his first thoughts in the form of a letter, and, indeed, when he sat down to write, having intended it for a private letter, he found it difficult to change the form of address, when his sentiments had grown into a greater extent and had received another direction. A different plan, he is sensible, might be more favorable to a commodious division and distribution of his matter.

The author started a more comprehensive discussion on the topic. He thought about publishing it early last spring, but as the idea developed, he realized that what he had started was not only much more than just a letter, but also needed more careful consideration than he could give at the time. Nevertheless, after he had written down his initial thoughts as a letter, he found it hard to change the way he addressed it since his ideas had expanded and taken a new direction. He recognizes that a different approach might allow for a better organization and presentation of his material.


REFLECTIONS

ON

THE REVOLUTION IN FRANCE.

Dear Sir,—You are pleased to call again, and with some earnestness, for my thoughts on the late proceedings in France. I will not give you reason to imagine that I think my sentiments of such value as to wish myself to be solicited about them. They are of too little consequence to be very anxiously either communicated or withheld. It was from attention to you, and to you only, that I hesitated at the time when you first desired to receive them. In the first letter I had the honor to write to you, and which at length I send, I wrote neither for nor from any description of men; nor shall I in this. My errors, if any, are my own. My reputation alone is to answer for them.

Dear Sir, — You’re eager to hear my thoughts on the recent events in France. I don’t want you to think my opinions are so important that I should be constantly asked about them. They really don’t matter enough for me to feel strongly about sharing or holding back. It was only out of respect for you that I hesitated when you first asked for them. In the first letter I had the privilege to send you, which I’m now forwarding, I didn’t write for or on behalf of any specific group of people, and I won’t do so in this one either. Any mistakes I make are solely my own. My reputation is all that’s at stake here.

You see, Sir, by the long letter I have transmitted to you, that, though I do most heartily wish that France may be animated by a spirit of rational liberty, and that I think you bound, in all honest policy, to provide a permanent body in which that spirit may reside, and an effectual organ by which it may act, it is my misfortune to entertain great doubts concerning several material points in your late transactions.

You see, Sir, from the long letter I've sent you, that while I sincerely hope France can embrace a spirit of rational freedom, and I believe it’s your duty, in all honesty, to establish a lasting entity for that spirit to thrive and an effective way for it to operate, I unfortunately have serious doubts about several important aspects of your recent actions.

You imagined, when you wrote last, that I might possibly be reckoned among the approvers of certain proceedings in France, from the solemn public seal of sanction they have received from two clubs of gentlemen in London, called the Constitutional Society, and the Revolution Society.

You thought, when you last wrote, that I might be counted among those who approve of certain actions in France, given the official endorsement they’ve received from two gentlemen’s clubs in London, known as the Constitutional Society and the Revolution Society.

I certainly have the honor to belong to more clubs than one in which the Constitution of this kingdom and the principles of the glorious Revolution are held in high reverence; and I reckon myself among the most forward in my zeal for maintaining that Constitution and those principles in their utmost purity and vigor. It is because I do so that I think it necessary for me that there should be no mistake. Those who cultivate the memory of our Revolution, and those who are attached to the Constitution of this kingdom, will take good care how they are involved with persons who, under the pretext of zeal towards the Revolution and Constitution, too frequently wander from their true principles, and are ready on every occasion to depart from the firm, but cautious and deliberate, spirit which produced the one and which presides in the other. Before I proceed to answer the more material particulars in your letter, I shall beg leave to give you such information as I have been able to obtain of the two clubs which have thought proper, as bodies, to interfere in the concerns of France,—first assuring you that I am not, and that I have never been, a member of either of those societies.

I have the honor of being part of more than one group that holds the Constitution of this kingdom and the principles of the glorious Revolution in high regard. I consider myself one of the most passionate supporters of upholding that Constitution and those principles in their fullest authenticity and strength. Because of this, I believe it’s important to clarify things. Those who honor the memory of our Revolution and are committed to the Constitution of this kingdom should be careful about getting involved with people who, under the guise of enthusiasm for the Revolution and Constitution, often stray from their true principles and are quick to abandon the strong, yet careful and thoughtful, spirit that forged both. Before I respond to the more significant details in your letter, I would like to share what I’ve learned about the two groups that have chosen, as organizations, to intervene in the affairs of France—first assuring you that I am not, and have never been, a member of either of those societies.

The first, calling itself the Constitutional Society, or Society for Constitutional Information, or by some such title, is, I believe, of seven or eight years' standing. The institution of this society appears to be of a charitable, and so far of a laudable nature: it was intended for the circulation, at the expense of the members, of many books which few others would be at the expense of buying, and which might lie on the hands of the booksellers, to the great loss of an useful body of men. Whether the books so charitably circulated were ever as charitably read is more than I know. Possibly several of them have been exported to France, and, like goods not in request here, may with you have found a market. I have heard much talk of the lights to be drawn from books that are sent from hence. What improvements they have had in their passage (as it is said some liquors are meliorated by crossing the sea) I cannot tell; but I never heard a man of common judgment or the least degree of information speak a word in praise of the greater part of the publications circulated by that society; nor have their proceedings been accounted, except by some of themselves, as of any serious consequence.

The first group, calling itself the Constitutional Society, or Society for Constitutional Information, or something similar, has been around for about seven or eight years. This society seems to have a charitable and, so far, commendable purpose: it was meant to distribute many books, funded by the members, that few others would pay for, which might otherwise sit unsold at bookstores, resulting in a significant loss for a useful group of people. Whether the books that were distributed so generously were ever read with the same goodwill is unclear to me. It's possible that several of them were sent to France and, like products that aren't in demand here, might have found a market with you. I've heard a lot of talk about the insights to be gained from books sent from here. What improvements they’ve experienced on their journey (as some drinks are said to get better by crossing the ocean) I can't say; but I've never heard anyone with common sense or any degree of knowledge speak positively about most of the publications distributed by that society; nor have their actions been seen, except by a few of their own members, as having any real significance.

Your National Assembly seems to entertain much the same opinion that I do of this poor charitable club. As a nation, you reserved the whole stock of your eloquent acknowledgments for the Revolution Society, when their fellows in the Constitutional were in equity entitled to some share. Since you have selected the Revolution Society as the great object of your national thanks and praises, you will think me excusable in making its late conduct the subject of my observations. The National Assembly of France has given importance to these gentlemen by adopting them; and they return the favor by acting as a committee in England for extending the principles of the National Assembly. Henceforward we must consider them as a kind of privileged persons, as no inconsiderable members in the diplomatic body. This is one among the revolutions which have given splendor to obscurity and distinction to undiscerned merit. Until very lately I do not recollect to have heard of this club. I am quite sure that it never occupied a moment of my thoughts,—nor, I believe, those of any person out of their own set. I find, upon inquiry, that, on the anniversary of the Revolution in 1688, a club of Dissenters, but of what denomination I know not, have long had the custom of hearing a sermon in one of their churches, and that afterwards they spent the day cheerfully, as other clubs do, at the tavern. But I never heard that any public measure or political system, much less that the merits of the constitution of any foreign nation, had been the subject of a formal proceeding at their festivals, until, to my inexpressible surprise, I found them in a sort of public capacity, by a congratulatory address, giving an authoritative sanction to the proceedings of the National Assembly in France.

Your National Assembly seems to share the same opinion I have about this poor charitable club. As a nation, you devoted all your eloquent acknowledgments to the Revolution Society, while those associated with the Constitutional group were just as deserving of recognition. Now that you’ve chosen the Revolution Society as the main focus of your national gratitude and praise, you can understand why I want to comment on their recent actions. The National Assembly of France has given these gentlemen a sense of importance by adopting them, and they are returning the favor by acting as a committee in England to promote the principles of the National Assembly. From now on, we must view them as somewhat privileged individuals, significant members of the diplomatic body. This is one of those revolutions that has brought glory to obscurity and distinction to unnoticed merit. Until very recently, I don’t recall having heard of this club. I’m quite sure it never crossed my mind—nor, I believe, the minds of anyone outside their own group. Upon investigation, I found that on the anniversary of the Revolution in 1688, a club of Dissenters—though I don’t know what kind—has long had the tradition of listening to a sermon in one of their churches, and afterwards, they would spend the day happily, like other clubs, at the tavern. However, I had never heard of any public measure or political agenda, let alone the merits of the constitution of any foreign nation, being formally discussed at their gatherings until, to my utter astonishment, I discovered them acting in a public capacity by issuing a congratulatory address that gave authoritative support to the actions of the National Assembly in France.

In the ancient principles and conduct of the club, so far at least as they were declared, I see nothing to which I could take exception. I think it very probable, that, for some purpose, new members may have entered among them,—and that some truly Christian politicians, who love to dispense benefits, but are careful to conceal the hand which distributes the dole, may have made them the instruments of their pious designs. Whatever I may have reason to suspect concerning private management, I shall speak of nothing as of a certainty but what is public.

In the old rules and behavior of the club, at least as they were expressed, I can’t find anything to disagree with. I think it’s likely that, for some reason, new members may have joined them—and that some genuinely Christian politicians, who enjoy giving out favors but prefer to keep their contributions hidden, might have used them to carry out their good intentions. Regardless of any suspicions I may have about private dealings, I will only discuss what is public as if it’s a certainty.

For one, I should be sorry to be thought directly or indirectly concerned in their proceedings. I certainly take my full share, along with the rest of the world, in my individual and private capacity, in speculating on what has been done, or is doing, on the public stage, in any place, ancient or modern,—in the republic of Rome, or the republic of Paris; but having no general apostolical mission, being a citizen of a particular state, and being bound up, in a considerable degree, by its public will, I should think it at least improper and irregular for me to open a formal public correspondence with the actual government of a foreign nation, without the express authority of the government under which I live.

For one thing, I would be sorry to be seen as involved in their actions, either directly or indirectly. I definitely share in the curiosity, like everyone else in the world, regarding what has happened or is happening on the public stage, whether in ancient or modern times—in the republic of Rome or the republic of Paris. However, since I don’t have any official mission, I’m a citizen of a specific state, and I am quite tied to its public will, I would consider it at least improper and out of line for me to engage in formal public communication with the current government of a foreign nation without the clear permission of the government I belong to.

I should be still more unwilling to enter into that correspondence under anything like an equivocal description, which to many, unacquainted with our usages, might make the address in which I joined appear as the act of persons in some sort of corporate capacity, acknowledged by the laws of this kingdom, and authorized to speak the sense of some part of it. On account of the ambiguity and uncertainty of unauthorized general descriptions, and of the deceit which may be practised under them, and not from mere formality, the House of Commons would reject the most sneaking petition for the most trifling object, under that mode of signature to which you have thrown open the folding-doors of your presence-chamber, and have ushered into your National Assembly with as much ceremony and parade, and with as great a bustle of applause, as if you had been visited by the whole representative majesty of the whole English nation. If what this society has thought proper to send forth had been a piece of argument, it would have signified little whose argument it was. It would be neither the more nor the less convincing on account of the party it came from. But this is only a vote and resolution. It stands solely on authority; and in this case it is the mere authority of individuals, few of whom appear. Their signatures ought, in my opinion, to have been annexed to their instrument. The world would then have the means of knowing how many they are, who they are, and of what value their opinions may be, from their personal abilities, from their knowledge, their experience, or their lead and authority in this state. To me, who am but a plain man, the proceeding looks a little too refined and too ingenious; it has too much the air of a political stratagem, adopted for the sake of giving, under a high-sounding name, an importance to the public declarations of this club, which, when the matter came to be closely inspected, they did not altogether so well deserve. It is a policy that has very much the complexion of a fraud.

I am even more reluctant to engage in that correspondence under any ambiguous description, which to many people unfamiliar with our customs might make the address I joined seem like the act of individuals in some sort of official capacity, recognized by the laws of this country, and authorized to express the views of some part of it. Because of the ambiguity and uncertainty of unauthorized general descriptions, and the deception they can create, the House of Commons would dismiss even the humblest petition for the smallest request under that type of signature that you've opened with great pomp and circumstance, and welcomed into your National Assembly with as much fanfare and applause as if you had been visited by the entire representative power of the English nation. If what this society has chosen to put forth had been a piece of reasoning, it wouldn't matter whose argument it was. It wouldn't be any more or less persuasive based on who it came from. But this is only a vote and resolution. It relies solely on authority; in this case, it's just the authority of individuals, most of whom are not visible. I believe their signatures should have been attached to their statement. Then, the world would have a way of knowing how many they are, who they are, and the value of their opinions based on their personal abilities, their knowledge, their experience, or their influence and authority in this state. To me, as a straightforward person, this approach seems a little too elaborate and clever; it has too much of the feel of a political maneuver, aimed at giving, under an impressive name, a significance to the public statements of this group that, when closely examined, they do not entirely merit. It has a quality that feels very much like a deception.

I flatter myself that I love a manly, moral, regulated liberty as well as any gentleman of that society, be he who he will; and perhaps I have given as good proofs of my attachment to that cause, in the whole course of my public conduct. I think I envy liberty as little as they do to any other nation. But I cannot stand forward, and give praise or blame to anything which relates to human actions and human concerns on a simple view of the object, as it stands stripped of every relation, in all the nakedness and solitude of metaphysical abstraction. Circumstances (which with some gentlemen pass for nothing) give in reality to every political principle its distinguishing color and discriminating effect. The circumstances are what render every civil and political scheme beneficial or noxious to mankind. Abstractedly speaking, government, as well as liberty, is good; yet could I, in common sense, ten years ago, have felicitated France on her enjoyment of a government, (for she then had a government,) without inquiry what the nature of that government was, or how it was administered? Can I now congratulate the same nation upon its freedom? Is it because liberty in the abstract may be classed amongst the blessings of mankind, that I am seriously to felicitate a madman who has escaped from the protecting restraint and wholesome darkness of his cell on his restoration to the enjoyment of light and liberty? Am I to congratulate a highwayman and murderer who has broke prison upon the recovery of his natural rights? This would be to act over again the scene of the criminals condemned to the galleys, and their heroic deliverer, the metaphysic Knight of the Sorrowful Countenance.

I take pride in believing that I value a strong, moral, and regulated freedom just as much as any gentleman in that society, whoever he may be; and I think I have provided solid evidence of my commitment to that cause throughout my public life. I don't envy freedom any more than they envy it from other nations. However, I can't just step up and give praise or criticism to anything related to human actions and human issues based solely on a simple view of the object, as it exists completely stripped of all context, in the bare isolation of philosophical abstraction. The circumstances (which some gentlemen consider irrelevant) actually give every political principle its unique shade and distinguishing impact. It's the circumstances that make any civil and political plan either beneficial or harmful to humanity. Speaking in abstract terms, government, just like freedom, is good; but could I, using common sense, have congratulated France ten years ago on having a government (since she indeed had one) without inquiring about the nature of that government or how it was run? Can I now celebrate the same country for its freedom? Is it because freedom in abstract terms is seen as one of humanity's blessings that I should genuinely congratulate a madman who has escaped the protective restraint and beneficial darkness of his cell on his return to light and liberty? Should I celebrate a highway robber and murderer who has broken out of prison for reclaiming his natural rights? That would be like replaying the scene of the criminals sentenced to the galleys and their heroic savior, the philosophical Knight of the Sorrowful Countenance.

When I see the spirit of liberty in action, I see a strong principle at work; and this, for a while, is all I can possibly know of it. The wild gas, the fixed air, is plainly broke loose: but we ought to suspend our judgment until the first effervescence is a little subsided, till the liquor is cleared, and until we see something deeper than the agitation of a troubled and frothy surface. I must be tolerably sure, before I venture publicly to congratulate men upon a blessing, that they have really received one. Flattery corrupts both the receiver and the giver; and adulation is not of more service to the people than to kings. I should therefore suspend my congratulations on the new liberty of France, until I was informed how it had been combined with government, with public force, with the discipline and obedience of armies, with the collection of an effective and well-distributed revenue, with morality and religion, with solidity and property, with peace and order, with civil and social manners. All these (in their way) are good things, too; and without them, liberty is not a benefit whilst it lasts, and is not likely to continue long. The effect of liberty to individuals is, that they may do what they please: we ought to see what it will please them to do, before we risk congratulations, which may be soon turned into complaints. Prudence would dictate this in the case of separate, insulated, private men. But liberty, when men act in bodies, is power. Considerate people, before they declare themselves, will observe the use which is made of power,—and particularly of so trying a thing as new power in new persons, of whose principles, tempers, and dispositions they have little or no experience, and in situations where those who appear the most stirring in the scene may possibly not be the real movers.

When I see the spirit of freedom in action, I recognize a strong principle at work, and for now, that's all I can really know about it. The wild gas, the fixed air, is clearly breaking free: but we should hold off on making judgments until the initial excitement calms down, until the situation settles, and until we can see something more profound than the turmoil of a disturbed and frothy surface. I need to be fairly certain before I openly congratulate people on a blessing that they have truly received one. Flattery corrupts both the person being flattered and the one giving it; and excessive praise is no more beneficial to the people than it is to kings. Therefore, I should delay my congratulations on France's newfound freedom until I learn how it connects with governance, public authority, military discipline and obedience, the collection of a functional and fairly distributed revenue, morality and religion, stability and property, peace and order, and civil and social behavior. All of these (in their own way) are good things, too; and without them, freedom isn't much of a benefit while it lasts and isn’t likely to last long. The impact of freedom on individuals is that they can do whatever they want: we should see what they choose to do before we risk offering congratulations, which may soon turn into complaints. Caution would guide this in the case of separate, isolated individuals. But freedom, when people act collectively, is power. Thoughtful individuals will observe how power is used—especially in the case of such a sensitive issue as new power in new people, whose principles, attitudes, and tendencies they have little or no experience with, and in situations where those who seem the most active in the scene might not be the true instigators.

All these considerations, however, were below the transcendental dignity of the Revolution Society. Whilst I continued in the country, from whence I had the honor of writing to you, I had but an imperfect idea of their transactions. On my coming to town, I sent for an account of their proceedings, which had been published by their authority, containing a sermon of Dr. Price, with the Duke de Rochefoucault's and the Archbishop of Aix's letter and several other documents annexed. The whole of that publication, with the manifest design of connecting the affairs of France with those of England, by drawing us into an imitation of the conduct of the National Assembly, gave me a considerable degree of uneasiness. The effect of that conduct upon the power, credit, prosperity, and tranquillity of France became every day more evident. The form of constitution to be settled, for its future polity, became more clear. We are now in a condition to discern with tolerable exactness the true nature of the object held up to our imitation. If the prudence of reserve and decorum dictates silence in some circumstances, in others prudence of a higher order may justify us in speaking our thoughts. The beginnings of confusion with us in England are at present feeble enough; but with you we have seen an infancy still more feeble growing by moments into a strength to heap mountains upon mountains, and to wage war with Heaven itself. Whenever our neighbor's house is on fire, it cannot be amiss for the engines to play a little on our own. Better to be despised for too anxious apprehensions than ruined by too confident a security.

All these considerations, however, were beneath the elevated status of the Revolution Society. While I was still in the country, from where I had the privilege of writing to you, I had only a limited understanding of their activities. Once I arrived in town, I requested an account of their proceedings, which had been published by their authority, including a sermon by Dr. Price, along with letters from the Duke de Rochefoucauld and the Archbishop of Aix, as well as several other attached documents. The entire publication, clearly aimed at linking the events in France with those in England by encouraging us to imitate the actions of the National Assembly, made me quite uneasy. The impact of that behavior on the power, reputation, prosperity, and peace of France became increasingly clear each day. The structure of the constitution to be established for its future governance became more evident. We can now fairly accurately understand the true nature of the example presented for our imitation. If the wisdom of restraint and propriety suggests we remain silent in certain situations, in others, a higher form of prudence may justify us expressing our views. The signs of confusion here in England are currently fairly weak; however, with you, we've witnessed a still weaker beginning rapidly gaining strength to pile up troubles and challenge the heavens themselves. Whenever our neighbor's house is on fire, it makes sense for us to take a small precaution with our own. It’s better to be viewed with disdain for being overly cautious than to face destruction from being overly confident.

Solicitous chiefly for the peace of my own country, but by no means unconcerned for yours, I wish to communicate more largely what was at first intended only for your private satisfaction. I shall still keep your affairs in my eye, and continue to address myself to you. Indulging myself in the freedom of epistolary intercourse, I beg leave to throw out my thoughts and express my feelings just as they arise in my mind, with very little attention to formal method. I set out with the proceedings of the Revolution Society; but I shall not confine myself to them. Is it possible I should? It looks to me as if I were in a great crisis, not of the affairs of France alone, but of all Europe, perhaps of more than Europe. All circumstances taken together, the French Revolution is the most astonishing that has hitherto happened in the world. The most wonderful things are brought about in many instances by means the most absurd and ridiculous, in the most ridiculous modes, and apparently by the most contemptible instruments. Everything seems out of nature in this strange chaos of levity and ferocity, and of all sorts of crimes jumbled together with all sorts of follies. In viewing this monstrous tragi-comic scene, the most opposite passions necessarily succeed and sometimes mix with each other in the mind: alternate contempt and indignation, alternate laughter and tears, alternate scorn and horror.

Concerned mainly for the peace of my own country, but not indifferent to yours, I want to share more than what was initially meant just for your private enjoyment. I'll continue to keep an eye on your affairs and stay in touch with you. Allowing myself the freedom of letter writing, I’d like to share my thoughts and feelings as they come to me, without worrying too much about formal style. I’ll start with the actions of the Revolution Society, but I won’t limit myself to just that. How could I? It seems to me that we're at a critical moment, not just for France, but for all of Europe, and possibly beyond. All things considered, the French Revolution is the most astonishing event that has ever happened in the world. Incredible things often come about through the most absurd and ridiculous means, in the most outrageous ways, and seemingly by the most contemptible tools. Everything feels unnatural in this bizarre mix of frivolity and violence, with all kinds of crimes tangled up with all kinds of foolishness. As I watch this monstrous tragi-comic scene unfold, I find myself feeling the most contrasting emotions that often clash and sometimes blend in my mind: alternating between contempt and indignation, between laughter and tears, and between scorn and horror.

It cannot, however, be denied that to some this strange scene appeared in quite another point of view. Into them it inspired no other sentiments than those of exultation and rapture. They saw nothing in what has been done in France but a firm and temperate exertion of freedom,—so consistent, on the whole, with morals and with piety as to make it deserving not only of the secular applause of dashing Machiavelian politicians, but to render it a fit theme for all the devout effusions of sacred eloquence.

However, it can't be denied that for some, this strange scene looked entirely different. It brought them feelings of joy and exhilaration. They viewed everything happening in France as a strong and measured expression of freedom—one that, overall, aligned with morals and faith so well that it not only deserved the praise of bold, cunning politicians but also became a suitable topic for uplifting religious speeches.


On the forenoon of the fourth of November last, Doctor Richard Price, a Non-Conforming minister of eminence, preached at the Dissenting meeting-house of the Old Jewry, to his club or society, a very extraordinary miscellaneous sermon, in which there are some good moral and religious sentiments, and not ill expressed, mixed up with a sort of porridge of various political opinions and reflections: but the Revolution in France is the grand ingredient in the caldron. I consider the address transmitted by the Revolution Society to the National Assembly, through Earl Stanhope, as originating in the principles of the sermon, and as a corollary from them. It was moved by the preacher of that discourse. It was passed by those who came reeking from the effect of the sermon, without any censure or qualification, expressed or implied. If, however, any of the gentlemen concerned shall wish to separate the sermon from the resolution, they know how to acknowledge the one and to disavow the other. They may do it: I cannot.

On the morning of November 4th last year, Doctor Richard Price, a prominent Non-Conforming minister, preached a rather extraordinary and diverse sermon at the Dissenting meeting house in the Old Jewry to his group. The sermon included some solid moral and religious ideas, expressed decently, mixed in with a jumble of various political opinions and reflections: but the Revolution in France is the main focus in this mix. I see the address sent by the Revolution Society to the National Assembly, through Earl Stanhope, as stemming from the principles of the sermon and as a result of them. It was initiated by the preacher of that sermon. It was approved by those who had just come from the effects of the sermon, without any censure or qualification, either stated or implied. If, however, any of the gentlemen involved want to separate the sermon from the resolution, they know how to acknowledge one and disown the other. They can do that; I cannot.

For my part, I looked on that sermon as the public declaration of a man much connected with literary caballers and intriguing philosophers, with political theologians and theological politicians, both at home and abroad. I know they set him up as a sort of oracle; because, with the best intentions in the world, he naturally philippizes, and chants his prophetic song in exact unison with their designs.

For my part, I saw that sermon as the public announcement of someone deeply involved with artistic elites and scheming philosophers, with politically-minded theologians and theologically-minded politicians, both locally and internationally. I know they regarded him as a kind of oracle because, despite his good intentions, he naturally philippizes and sings his prophetic tune in perfect harmony with their agendas.

That sermon is in a strain which I believe has not been heard in this kingdom, in any of the pulpits which are tolerated or encouraged in it, since the year 1648,—when a predecessor of Dr. Price, the Reverend Hugh Peters, made the vault of the king's own chapel at St. James's ring with the honor and privilege of the saints, who, with the "high praises of God in their mouths, and a two-edged sword in their hands, were to execute judgment on the heathen, and punishments upon the people; to bind their kings with chains, and their nobles with fetters of iron."[77] Few harangues from the pulpit, except in the days of your League in France, or in the days of our Solemn League and Covenant in England, have ever breathed less of the spirit of moderation than this lecture in the Old Jewry. Supposing, however, that something like moderation were visible in this political sermon, yet politics and the pulpit are terms that have little agreement. No sound ought to be heard in the church but the healing voice of Christian charity. The cause of civil liberty and civil government gains as little as that of religion by this confusion of duties. Those who quit their proper character to assume what does not belong to them are, for the greater part, ignorant both of the character they leave and of the character they assume. Wholly unacquainted with the world, in which they are so fond of meddling, and inexperienced in all its affairs, on which they pronounce with so much confidence, they have nothing of politics but the passions they excite. Surely the church is a place where one day's truce ought to be allowed to the dissensions and animosities of mankind.

That sermon is in a style that I believe hasn't been heard in this country from any of the pulpits that are allowed or encouraged here since 1648—when Dr. Price's predecessor, the Reverend Hugh Peters, filled the king's own chapel at St. James's with the honor and privilege of the saints, who, with the "high praises of God in their mouths, and a two-edged sword in their hands, were to execute judgment on the heathen, and punishments upon the people; to bind their kings with chains, and their nobles with fetters of iron."[77] Few speeches from the pulpit, except during the times of your League in France or during our Solemn League and Covenant in England, have ever shown less spirit of moderation than this lecture in the Old Jewry. However, even if there were a hint of moderation in this political sermon, politics and the pulpit don’t really mix well. The church should only be filled with the healing voice of Christian charity. The cause of civil liberty and government gains just as little as that of religion from this mix-up of responsibilities. Those who abandon their true role to take on what doesn’t belong to them are mostly ignorant of both the role they leave behind and the role they try to take on. Completely unfamiliar with the world they so eagerly meddle in, and inexperienced in all its affairs which they comment on with such confidence, they have nothing of politics but the passions they stir up. Surely, the church is a place where a day's truce should be allowed from the conflicts and animosities of humanity.

This pulpit style, revived after so long a discontinuance, had to me the air of novelty, and of a novelty not wholly without danger. I do not charge this danger equally to every part of the discourse. The hint given to a noble and reverend lay-divine, who is supposed high in office in one of our universities,[78] and other lay-divines "of rank and literature," may be proper and seasonable, though somewhat new. If the noble Seekers should find nothing to satisfy their pious fancies in the old staple of the national Church, or in all the rich variety to be found in the well-assorted warehouses of the Dissenting congregations, Dr. Price advises them to improve upon Non-Conformity, and to set up, each of them, a separate meeting-house upon his own particular principles.[79] It is somewhat remarkable that this reverend divine should be so earnest for setting up new churches, and so perfectly indifferent concerning the doctrine which may be taught in them. His zeal is of a curious character. It is not for the propagation of his own opinions, but of any opinions. It is not for the diffusion of truth, but for the spreading of contradiction. Let the noble teachers but dissent, it is no matter from whom or from what. This great point once secured, it is taken for granted their religion will be rational and manly. I doubt whether religion would reap all the benefits which the calculating divine computes from this "great company of great preachers." It would certainly be a valuable addition of nondescripts to the ample collection of known classes, genera, and species, which at present beautify the hortus siccus of Dissent. A sermon from a noble duke, or a noble marquis, or a noble earl, or baron bold, would certainly increase and diversify the amusements of this town, which begins to grow satiated with the uniform round of its vapid dissipations. I should only stipulate that these new Mess-Johns in robes and coronets should keep some sort of bounds in the democratic and levelling principles which are expected from their titled pulpits. The new evangelists will, I dare say, disappoint the hopes that are conceived of them. They will not become, literally as well as figuratively, polemic divines,—nor be disposed so to drill their congregations, that they may, as in former blessed times, preach their doctrines to regiments of dragoons and corps of infantry and artillery. Such arrangements, however favorable to the cause of compulsory freedom, civil and religious, may not be equally conducive to the national tranquillity. These few restrictions I hope are no great stretches of intolerance, no very violent exertions of despotism.

This pulpit style, revived after a long absence, felt new to me, and not entirely without risk. I don’t believe this risk applies equally to every part of the message. The suggestion made to a prominent and respected layperson, who is thought to hold a high position in one of our universities,[78] and other laypeople "of rank and literature," may be appropriate and timely, even if it is somewhat novel. If the noble Seekers find nothing to satisfy their spiritual desires in the traditional offerings of the national Church, or in the diverse choices available in the well-stocked stores of the Dissenting congregations, Dr. Price advises them to improve upon Non-Conformity and establish their own meeting-houses based on their individual beliefs.[79] It is quite surprising that this respected divine is so passionate about starting new churches while being completely indifferent to the doctrines that may be taught in them. His enthusiasm is peculiar. It isn’t for promoting his own views, but for any views at all. It’s not about spreading truth, but about spreading disagreement. As long as the esteemed teachers dissent, it doesn’t matter from whom or from what. Once this crucial point is established, it is assumed their religion will be rational and mature. I wonder if religion would truly benefit from all the advantages that the analytical divine expects from this "great company of great preachers." It would certainly add a valuable assortment of new types to the extensive collection of known categories, genera, and species that currently enhance the hortus siccus of Dissent. A sermon from a noble duke, or a noble marquis, or a noble earl, or an adventurous baron would undoubtedly add to and diversify the entertainments of this town, which is starting to feel bored with its monotonous routine of bland distractions. I would only ask that these new Mess-Johns in robes and coronets maintain some boundaries regarding the democratic and leveling principles expected from their titled pulpits. I suspect the new evangelists will fall short of the expectations set for them. They won’t become, literally and figuratively, controversial divines,—nor train their congregations to preach their beliefs to regiments of cavalry and groups of infantry and artillery, as was done in the blessed times of old. While such arrangements may be favorable to the cause of compulsory freedom, both civil and religious, they might not be equally beneficial to national peace. I hope these few restrictions aren't seen as extreme intolerance or excessive tyranny.

But I may say of our preacher, "Utinam nugis tota illa dedisset et tempora sævitiæ." All things in this his fulminating bull are not of so innoxious a tendency. His doctrines affect our Constitution in its vital parts. He tells the Revolution Society, in this political sermon, that his Majesty "is almost the only lawful king in the world, because the only one who owes his crown to the choice of his people." As to the kings of the world, all of whom (except one) this arch-pontiff of the rights of men, with all the plenitude and with more than the boldness of the Papal deposing power in its meridian fervor of the twelfth century, puts into one sweeping clause of ban and anathema, and proclaims usurpers by circles of longitude and latitude over the whole globe, it behooves them to consider how they admit into their territories these apostolic missionaries, who are to tell their subjects they are not lawful kings. That is their concern. It is ours, as a domestic interest of some moment, seriously to consider the solidity of the only principle upon which these gentlemen acknowledge a king of Great Britain to be entitled to their allegiance.

But I can say about our preacher, "Utinam nugis tota illa dedisset et tempora sævitiæ." Not everything in this explosive message is harmless. His beliefs impact our Constitution in critical ways. He tells the Revolution Society in this political sermon that his Majesty "is almost the only lawful king in the world because he is the only one who owes his crown to the choice of his people." Regarding the kings of the world, all of whom (except one) this chief advocate for the rights of men, with all the authority and even more audacity than the Papal deposing power at its peak in the twelfth century, condemns in one sweeping declaration, branding them as usurpers by their geographical coordinates around the globe, it is important for them to consider how they allow these apostolic missionaries into their lands, who will tell their subjects that they are not lawful kings. That is their issue. For us, as a significant domestic concern, it is essential to seriously evaluate the foundation of the only principle that these individuals recognize as valid for a king of Great Britain to claim their loyalty.

This doctrine, as applied to the prince now on the British throne, either is nonsense, and therefore neither true nor false, or it affirms a most unfounded, dangerous, illegal, and unconstitutional position. According to this spiritual doctor of politics, if his Majesty does not owe his crown to the choice of his people, he is no lawful king. Now nothing can be more untrue than that the crown of this kingdom is so held by his Majesty. Therefore, if you follow their rule, the king of Great Britain, who most certainly does not owe his high office to any form of popular election, is in no respect better than the rest of the gang of usurpers, who reign, or rather rob, all over the face of this our miserable world, without any sort of right or title to the allegiance of their people. The policy of this general doctrine, so qualified, is evident enough. The propagators of this political gospel are in hopes their abstract principle (their principle that a popular choice is necessary to the legal existence of the sovereign magistracy) would be overlooked, whilst the king of Great Britain was not affected by it. In the mean time the ears of their congregations would be gradually habituated to it, as if it were a first principle admitted without dispute. For the present it would only operate as a theory, pickled in the preserving juices of pulpit eloquence, and laid by for future use. Condo et compono quæ mox depromere passim. By this policy, whilst our government is soothed with a reservation in its favor, to which it has no claim, the security which it has in common with all governments, so far as opinion is security, is taken away.

This belief, when applied to the current prince on the British throne, is either nonsense and thus neither true nor false, or it supports a baseless, dangerous, illegal, and unconstitutional position. According to this spiritual guide of politics, if his Majesty doesn’t owe his crown to the choice of his people, he’s not a lawful king. Nothing could be further from the truth than the idea that his Majesty holds this crown in that way. Therefore, if you follow their logic, the King of Great Britain, who certainly does not owe his position to any kind of popular election, is in no way better than the rest of the gang of usurpers who rule—or rather steal—across this miserable world, without any legitimate right or title to their people's loyalty. The intent behind this general doctrine is quite clear. The promoters of this political belief hope their abstract principle (that a popular choice is essential for the legal existence of the sovereign) will be overlooked while the King of Great Britain remains unaffected by it. In the meantime, the ears of their followers would gradually get used to it, as if it were a fundamental principle accepted without question. For now, it would only serve as a theory, preserved in the eloquent speeches from the pulpit and set aside for future use. Condo et compono quæ mox depromere passim. Through this strategy, while our government is comforted by a claim in its favor to which it has no right, the security it shares with all governments, as far as public opinion is concerned, is compromised.

Thus these politicians proceed, whilst little notice is taken of their doctrines; but when they come to be examined upon the plain meaning of their words and the direct tendency of their doctrines, then equivocations and slippery constructions come into play. When they say the king owes his crown to the choice of his people, and is therefore the only lawful sovereign in the world, they will perhaps tell us they mean to say no more than that some of the king's predecessors have been called to the throne by some sort of choice, and therefore he owes his crown to the choice of his people. Thus, by a miserable subterfuge, they hope to render their proposition safe by rendering it nugatory. They are welcome to the asylum they seek for their offence, since they take refuge in their folly. For, if you admit this interpretation, how does their idea of election differ from our idea of inheritance? And how does the settlement of the crown in the Brunswick line, derived from James the First, come to legalize our monarchy rather than that of any of the neighboring countries? At some time or other, to be sure, all the beginners of dynasties were chosen by those who called them to govern. There is ground enough for the opinion that all the kingdoms of Europe were at a remote period elective, with more or fewer limitations in the objects of choice. But whatever kings might have been here or elsewhere a thousand years ago, or in whatever manner the ruling dynasties of England or France may have begun, the king of Great Britain is at this day king by a fixed rule of succession, according to the laws of his country; and whilst the legal conditions of the compact of sovereignty are performed by him, (as they are performed,) he holds his crown in contempt of the choice of the Revolution Society, who have not a single vote for a king amongst them, either individually or collectively: though I make no doubt they would soon erect themselves into an electoral college, if things were ripe to give effect to their claim. His Majesty's heirs and successors, each in his time and order, will come to the crown with the same contempt of their choice with which his Majesty has succeeded to that he wears.

So these politicians carry on, while not much attention is paid to their beliefs; but when their words and the actual consequences of their ideas are put under scrutiny, then we see all kinds of vague language and tricky interpretations. When they say the king gets his crown because of the people's choice, claiming he's the only lawful ruler out there, they might argue they're just pointing out that some of the king's predecessors were brought to the throne through some kind of choice, and that's why he owes his crown to the people's choice. In this pathetic attempt, they hope to make their statement safe by making it meaningless. They can find the protection they seek for their wrongdoing because they rely on their foolishness. If you accept this interpretation, how does their idea of election differ from our idea of inheritance? And how does the transfer of the crown to the Brunswick line, which comes from James the First, legitimize our monarchy more than that of any of the neighboring countries? At one point, it's true that all the founders of dynasties were chosen by those who appointed them to rule. There's enough reason to believe that all the kingdoms of Europe were elective at some distant point, with varying limits on who could be chosen. But regardless of what kings may have been like here or elsewhere a thousand years ago, or how the ruling dynasties of England or France might have begun, the king of Great Britain today is king according to a fixed rule of succession, as established by his country's laws; and while he upholds the legal requirements of his position (which he does), he holds his crown in disregard of the choice of the Revolution Society, who don’t have a single vote for a king among them, either alone or together: though I don’t doubt they would quickly form themselves into an electoral college if the situation was right to act on their claim. His Majesty's heirs and successors, each in their own time and order, will take the crown with the same disregard for their choice that His Majesty did when he took the one he wears.

Whatever may be the success of evasion in explaining away the gross error fact, which supposes that his Majesty (though he holds it in concurrence with the wishes) owes his crown to the choice of his people, yet nothing can evade their full, explicit declaration concerning the principle of a right in the people to choose,—which right is directly maintained, and tenaciously adhered to. All the oblique insinuations concerning election bottom in this proposition, and are referable to it. Lest the foundation of the king's exclusive legal title should pass for a mere rant of adulatory freedom, the political divine proceeds dogmatically to assert,[80] that, by the principles of the Revolution, the people of England have acquired three fundamental rights, all of which, with him, compose one system, and lie together in one short sentence: namely, that we have acquired a right

Whatever the success of evasion in downplaying the obvious error fact, which assumes that his Majesty (even though he agrees with the wishes) owes his crown to the choice of his people, nothing can dismiss their clear and straightforward statement about the principle of the right of the people to choose—this right is firmly maintained and strongly upheld. All the indirect hints about elections are based on this idea and can be traced back to it. To ensure that the foundation of the king's exclusive legal title isn't dismissed as mere flattery, the political divine boldly states,[80] that, according to the principles of the Revolution, the people of England have acquired three fundamental rights, all of which, along with him, form one system and can be summarized in one short sentence: namely, that we have acquired a right

1. "To choose our own governors."

"To choose our own leaders."

2. "To cashier them for misconduct."

2. "To fire them for misbehavior."

3. "To frame a government for ourselves."

3. "To create a government for ourselves."

This new, and hitherto unheard-of bill of rights, though made in the name of the whole people, belongs to those gentlemen and their faction only. The body of the people of England have no share in it. They utterly disclaim it. They will resist the practical assertion of it with their lives and fortunes. They are bound to do so by the laws of their country, made at the time of that very Revolution which is appealed to in favor of the fictitious rights claimed by the society which abuses its name.

This new and completely unheard-of bill of rights, while presented as representing everyone, actually belongs only to those gentlemen and their group. The general public in England has no part in it. They completely reject it. They will fight against the practical enforcement of it with their lives and resources. They are obligated to do so by the laws of their country, established during the very Revolution that is referred to in support of the made-up rights claimed by the group that misuses its name.

These gentlemen of the Old Jewry, in all their reasonings on the Revolution of 1688, have a revolution which happened in England about forty years before, and the late French Revolution, so much before their eyes and in their hearts, that they are constantly confounding all the three together. It is necessary that we should separate what they confound. We must recall their erring fancies to the acts of the Revolution which we revere, for the discovery of its true principles. If the principles of the Revolution of 1688 are anywhere to be found, it is in the statute called the Declaration of Right. In that most wise, sober, and considerate declaration, drawn up by great lawyers and great statesmen, and not by warm and inexperienced enthusiasts, not one word is said, nor one suggestion made, of a general right "to choose our own governors, to cashier them for misconduct, and to form a government for ourselves."

These gentlemen from the Old Jewry, in all their discussions about the Revolution of 1688, are so influenced by the earlier revolution in England about forty years prior, and the recent French Revolution, that they constantly mix them all together. We need to clarify what they are confusing. We must remind them of the specific actions of the Revolution that we respect, in order to discover its true principles. If the principles of the Revolution of 1688 can be found anywhere, it's in the statute called the Declaration of Right. In that wise, measured, and thoughtful declaration, created by respected lawyers and statesmen, not by passionate and inexperienced young people, there is not a single word or suggestion about a general right "to choose our own governors, to dismiss them for misconduct, and to form a government for ourselves."

This Declaration of Right (the act of the 1st of William and Mary, sess. 2, ch. 2) is the corner-stone of our Constitution, as reinforced, explained, improved, and in its fundamental principles forever settled. It is called "An act for declaring the rights and liberties of the subject, and for settling the succession of the crown." You will observe that these rights and this succession are declared in one body, and bound indissolubly together.

This Declaration of Rights (the act of the 1st of William and Mary, sess. 2, ch. 2) is the foundation of our Constitution, reinforced, clarified, improved, and its fundamental principles permanently established. It is known as "An act for declaring the rights and liberties of the subject, and for settling the succession of the crown." You will notice that these rights and this succession are declared together as one, and are inextricably linked.

A few years after this period, a second opportunity offered for asserting a right of election to the crown. On the prospect of a total failure of issue from King William, and from the princess, afterwards Queen Anne, the consideration of the settlement of the Crown, and of a further security for the liberties of the people, again came before the legislature. Did they this second time make any provision for legalizing the crown on the spurious Revolution principles of the Old Jewry? No. They followed the principles which prevailed in the Declaration of Right; indicating with more precision the persons who were to inherit in the Protestant line. This act also incorporated, by the same policy, our liberties and an hereditary succession in the same act. Instead of a right to choose our own governors, they declared that the succession in that line (the Protestant line drawn from James the First) was absolutely necessary "for the peace, quiet, and security of the realm," and that it was equally urgent on them "to maintain a certainty in the succession thereof, to which the subjects may safely have recourse for their protection." Both these acts, in which are heard the unerring, unambiguous oracles of Revolution policy, instead of countenancing the delusive gypsy predictions of a "right to choose our governors," prove to a demonstration how totally adverse the wisdom of the nation was from turning a case of necessity into a rule of law.

A few years later, another chance arose to assert a right to the crown. With the potential for King William and Princess Anne, who later became Queen Anne, to have no heirs, the discussion about who would settle the Crown and further secure the people's liberties came back to the legislature. Did they make any provisions this time to legalize the crown based on the questionable principles from the old times? No. They adhered to the principles established in the Declaration of Right, clearly indicating who should inherit in the Protestant line. This act also incorporated our liberties and hereditary succession within the same law. Instead of a right to choose our own leaders, they stated that the succession in the Protestant line, descending from James the First, was absolutely necessary "for the peace, quiet, and security of the realm," and that it was equally important for them "to maintain a certainty in the succession, to which the subjects can safely turn for their protection." Both these acts, reflecting the clear and resolute guidance of Revolution policy, instead of supporting the misleading claims about a "right to choose our leaders," clearly demonstrate how opposed the nation's wisdom was to turning a necessity into a legal norm.

Unquestionably there was at the Revolution, in the person of King William, a small and a temporary deviation from the strict order of a regular hereditary succession; but it is against all genuine principles of jurisprudence to draw a principle from a law made in a special case and regarding an individual person. Privilegium non transit in exemplum. If ever there was a time favorable for establishing the principle that a king of popular choice was the only legal king, without all doubt it was at the Revolution. Its not being done at that time is a proof that the nation was of opinion it ought not to be done at any time. There is no person so completely ignorant of our history as not to know that the majority in Parliament, of both parties, were so little disposed to anything resembling that principle, that at first they were determined to place the vacant crown, not on the head of the Prince of Orange, but on that of his wife, Mary, daughter of King James, the eldest born of the issue of that king, which they acknowledged as undoubtedly his. It would be to repeat a very trite story, to recall to your memory all those circumstances which demonstrated that their accepting King William was not properly a choice; but to all those who did not wish in effect to recall King James, or to deluge their country in blood, and again to bring their religion, laws, and liberties into the peril they had just escaped, it was an act of necessity, in the strictest moral sense in which necessity can be taken.

Without a doubt, during the Revolution, King William marked a small and temporary deviation from the usual hereditary succession. However, it goes against true legal principles to create a precedent from a law made for a specific case and regarding a specific person. Privilegium non transit in exemplum. If there was ever a moment that supported the idea that a king chosen by the people was the only legal king, it was undoubtedly during the Revolution. The fact that this was not established at that time suggests that the nation believed it shouldn't be done at any time. There is no one completely unaware of our history who doesn't know that the majority in Parliament, from both parties, were so opposed to this idea that they initially decided to place the vacant crown not on the Prince of Orange but on his wife, Mary, the daughter of King James, who was acknowledged as undoubtedly his firstborn. It would be a common retelling to remind you of all the details that showed their acceptance of King William wasn't really a choice; however, for those who did not wish to effectively restore King James, or to flood their country with bloodshed, and to once again put their religion, laws, and liberties at the risk they had just escaped, it was a matter of necessity, in the strictest moral sense of the term.

In the very act in which, for a time, and in a single case, Parliament departed from the strict order of inheritance, in favor of a prince who, though not next, was, however, very near in the line of succession, it is curious to observe how Lord Somers, who drew the bill called the Declaration of Right, has comported himself on that delicate occasion. It is curious to observe with what address this temporary solution of continuity is kept from the eye; whilst all that could be found in this act of necessity to countenance the idea of an hereditary succession is brought forward, and fostered, and made the most of, by this great man, and by the legislature who followed him. Quitting the dry, imperative style of an act of Parliament, he makes the Lords and Commons fall to a pious legislative ejaculation, and declare that they consider it "as a marvellous providence, and merciful goodness of God to this nation, to preserve their said Majesties' royal persons most happily to reign over us on the throne of their ancestors, for which, from the bottom of their hearts, they return their humblest thanks and praises." The legislature plainly had in view the Act of Recognition of the first of Queen Elizabeth, chap. 3rd, and of that of James the First, chap. 1st, both acts strongly declaratory of the inheritable nature of the crown; and in many parts they follow, with a nearly literal precision, the words, and even the form of thanksgiving which is found in these old declaratory statutes.

In the moment when Parliament temporarily strayed from the traditional order of inheritance to favor a prince who, while not the immediate heir, was still very close in the line of succession, it’s interesting to see how Lord Somers, who drafted the bill known as the Declaration of Right, handled that sensitive situation. It’s intriguing to note how this temporary solution for continuity is kept under wraps while any element of the act that could suggest the idea of hereditary succession is highlighted, nurtured, and emphasized by this influential figure and the legislature that followed him. Moving away from the dry, stiff language typical of parliamentary acts, he gets the Lords and Commons to engage in a solemn legislative declaration, stating that they view it "as a marvelous providence and merciful goodness of God to this nation, to preserve their said Majesties' royal persons most happily to reign over us on the throne of their ancestors, for which, from the bottom of their hearts, they return their humblest thanks and praises." The legislature clearly had in mind the Act of Recognition from the first of Queen Elizabeth, chapter 3, and that of James the First, chapter 1, both of which strongly affirmed the inheritable nature of the crown; and in many respects, they closely echo the words and even the form of gratitude found in these historical declaratory statutes.

The two Houses, in the act of King William, did not thank God that they had found a fair opportunity to assert a right to choose their own governors, much less to make an election the only lawful title to the crown. Their having been in a condition to avoid the very appearance of it, as much as possible, was by them considered as a providential escape. They threw a politic, well-wrought veil over every circumstance tending to weaken the rights which in the meliorated order of succession they meant to perpetuate, or which might furnish a precedent for any future departure from what they had then settled forever. Accordingly, that they might not relax the nerves of their monarchy, and that they might preserve a close conformity to the practice of their ancestors, as it appeared in the declaratory statutes of Queen Mary[81] and Queen Elizabeth, in the next clause they vest, by recognition, in their Majesties all the legal prerogatives of the crown, declaring "that in them they are most fully, rightfully, and entirely invested, incorporated, united, and annexed." In the clause which follows, for preventing questions, by reason of any pretended titles to the crown, they declare (observing also in this the traditionary language, along with the traditionary policy of the nation, and repeating as from a rubric the language of the preceding acts of Elizabeth and James) that on the preserving "a certainty in the SUCCESSION thereof the unity, peace, and tranquillity of this nation doth, under God, wholly depend."

The two Houses, in the act of King William, didn’t express gratitude to God for finding a good opportunity to claim the right to choose their own governors, let alone to make that election the only lawful way to the crown. They saw their ability to avoid even the appearance of this as a fortunate escape. They skillfully obscured every aspect that might undermine the rights they intended to secure in the improved order of succession or that could set a precedent for any future deviations from what they had established permanently. Therefore, to avoid weakening the monarchy and to closely follow the practices of their ancestors, as seen in the declaratory statutes of Queen Mary[81] and Queen Elizabeth, they officially recognize that all the legal prerogatives of the crown are vested in their Majesties, stating that in them they are most fully, rightfully, and entirely invested, incorporated, united, and annexed. In the following clause, to prevent any questions arising from supposed claims to the crown, they declare (also using the traditional language and policy of the nation, repeating the wording from the previous acts of Elizabeth and James) that preserving "a certainty in the SUCCESSION thereof the unity, peace, and tranquillity of this nation doth, under God, wholly depend."

They knew that a doubtful title of succession would but too much resemble an election, and that an election would be utterly destructive of the "unity, peace, and tranquillity of this nation," which they thought to be considerations of some moment. To provide for these objects, and therefore to exclude forever the Old Jewry doctrine of "a right to choose our own governors," they follow with a clause containing a most solemn pledge, taken from the preceding act of Queen Elizabeth,—as solemn a pledge as ever was or can be given in favor of an hereditary succession, and as solemn a renunciation as could be made of the principles by this society imputed to them:—"The Lords Spiritual and Temporal, and Commons, do, in the name of all the people aforesaid, most humbly and faithfully submit themselves, their heirs, and posterities forever; and do faithfully promise that they will stand to, maintain, and defend their said Majesties, and also the limitation of the crown, herein specified and contained, to the utmost of their powers," &c., &c.

They understood that an uncertain claim to succession would closely resemble an election, and that an election would completely undermine the "unity, peace, and tranquility of this nation," which they believed were important considerations. To address these issues, and to permanently dismiss the Old Jewry principle of "the right to choose our own governors," they included a clause with a very serious pledge, taken from the prior act of Queen Elizabeth—one of the most serious pledges ever made in support of hereditary succession, and a strong rejection of the principles this society accused them of:—"The Lords Spiritual and Temporal, and Commons, do, in the name of all the people aforementioned, most humbly and faithfully submit themselves, their heirs, and posterities forever; and do faithfully promise that they will support, uphold, and defend their said Majesties, and also the limitation of the crown, as specified and contained herein, to the best of their abilities," & etc., & etc.

So far is it from being true that we acquired a right by the Revolution to elect our kings, that, if we had possessed it before, the English nation did at that time most solemnly renounce and abdicate it, for themselves, and for all their posterity forever. These gentlemen may value themselves as much as they please on their Whig principles; but I never desire to be thought a better Whig than Lord Somers, or to understand the principles of the Revolution better than those by whom it was brought about, or to read in the Declaration of Right any mysteries unknown to those whose penetrating style has engraved in our ordinances, and in our hearts, the words and spirit of that immortal law.

It's far from true that we gained the right to choose our kings through the Revolution; if we had that right before, the English people formally rejected and gave it up for themselves and all future generations. These individuals can take pride in their Whig beliefs as much as they want, but I don't wish to be seen as a better Whig than Lord Somers or to claim I understand the principles of the Revolution better than those who actually made it happen or to find any hidden meanings in the Declaration of Right that aren't already clear to those whose insightful writing has etched the words and spirit of that enduring law into our laws and hearts.

It is true, that, aided with the powers derived from force and opportunity, the nation was at that time, in some sense, free to take what course it pleased for filling the throne,—but only free to do so upon the same grounds on which they might have wholly abolished their monarchy, and every other part of their Constitution. However, they did not think such bold changes within their commission. It is, indeed, difficult, perhaps impossible, to give limits to the mere abstract competence of the supreme power, such as was exercised by Parliament at that time; but the limits of a moral competence, subjecting, even in powers more indisputably sovereign, occasional will to permanent reason, and to the steady maxims of faith, justice, and fixed fundamental policy, are perfectly intelligible, and perfectly binding upon those who exercise any authority, under any name, or under any title, in the state. The House of Lords, for instance, is not morally competent to dissolve the House of Commons,—no, nor even to dissolve itself, nor to abdicate, if it would, its portion in the legislature of the kingdom. Though a king may abdicate for his own person, he cannot abdicate for the monarchy. By as strong, or by a stronger reason, the House of Commons cannot renounce its share of authority. The engagement and pact of society, which generally goes by the name of the Constitution, forbids such invasion and such surrender. The constituent parts of a state are obliged to hold their public faith with each other, and with all those who derive any serious interest under their engagements, as much as the whole state is bound to keep its faith with separate communities: otherwise, competence and power would soon be confounded, and no law be left but the will of a prevailing force. On this principle, the succession of the crown has always been what it now is, an hereditary succession by law: in the old line it was a succession by the Common Law; in the new by the statute law, operating on the principles of the Common Law, not changing the substance, but regulating the mode and describing the persons. Both these descriptions of law are of the same force, and are derived from an equal authority, emanating from the common agreement and original compact of the state, communi sponsione reipublicæ, and as such are equally binding on king, and people too, as long as the terms are observed, and they continue the same body politic.

It’s true that, with the power gained from force and opportunity, the nation was in a sense free to choose any path it wanted for filling the throne—but only free to do so under conditions that would allow them to completely abolish their monarchy and any other part of their Constitution. However, they didn’t believe such drastic changes were within their authority. It is indeed difficult, maybe impossible, to set limits on the sheer abstract power of the supreme authority, like that exercised by Parliament at that time; but the limits of moral competence, which require that even the most unquestionable powers occasionally submit to permanent reason and the steady principles of faith, justice, and established fundamental policy, are completely understandable and absolutely binding on anyone who holds any kind of authority, under any title, in the state. The House of Lords, for example, doesn’t have the moral authority to dissolve the House of Commons—nor even to dissolve itself or to give up its role in the kingdom’s legislature. While a king may abdicate for himself, he cannot abdicate for the monarchy. By the same or even stronger reasoning, the House of Commons cannot relinquish its share of authority. The social contract, commonly known as the Constitution, prohibits such encroachment and surrender. The parts of a state are required to uphold their public commitments to each other and to everyone who has a significant interest under these agreements, just as the entire state is obligated to honor its commitments to different communities. Otherwise, competence and power would soon become indistinguishable, leaving only the will of a dominating force as law. Based on this principle, the succession of the crown has always been what it is now: an hereditary succession by law. In the old system, it was a succession by Common Law; in the new system, it's governed by statute law, which operates on the principles of Common Law, not changing the essence but regulating the method and identifying the individuals. Both types of law carry the same weight and come from the same authority, arising from the common agreement and original compact of the state, communi sponsione reipublicæ, and are thus equally binding on both the king and the people as long as the terms are upheld and they remain the same political entity.

It is far from impossible to reconcile, if we do not suffer ourselves to be entangled in the mazes of metaphysic sophistry, the use both of a fixed rule and an occasional deviation,—the sacredness of an hereditary principle of succession in our government with a power of change in its application in cases of extreme emergency. Even in that extremity, (if we take the measure of our rights by our exercise of them at the Revolution,) the change is to be confined to the peccant part only,—to the part which produced the necessary deviation; and even then it is to be effected without a decomposition of the whole civil and political mass, for the purpose of originating a new civil order out of the first elements of society.

It’s definitely possible to find a balance, as long as we don't get caught up in complicated metaphysical arguments, between having a fixed rule and allowing for occasional exceptions—the importance of having a hereditary system of succession in our government while still having the ability to change how it works in cases of extreme emergency. Even in such emergencies, (if we gauge our rights by how we exercised them during the Revolution,) the changes should be limited to the problematic part only—the part that caused the necessary departure; and even then, it should be done without breaking down the entire civil and political structure to create a new societal order from scratch.

A state without the means of some change is without the means of its conservation. Without such means it might even risk the loss of that part of the Constitution which it wished the most religiously to preserve. The two principles of conservation and correction operated strongly at the two critical periods of the Restoration and Revolution, when England found itself without a king. At both those periods the nation had lost the bond of union in their ancient edifice: they did not, however, dissolve the whole fabric. On the contrary, in both cases they regenerated the deficient part of the old Constitution through the parts which were not impaired. They kept these old parts exactly as they were, that the part recovered might be suited to them. They acted by the ancient organized states in the shape of their old organization, and not by the organic moleculæ of a disbanded people. At no time, perhaps, did the sovereign legislature manifest a more tender regard to that fundamental principle of British constitutional policy than at the time of the Revolution, when it deviated from the direct line of hereditary succession. The crown was carried somewhat out of the line in which it had before moved; but the new line was derived from the same stock. It was still a line of hereditary descent; still an hereditary descent in the same blood, though an hereditary descent qualified with Protestantism. When the legislature altered the direction, but kept the principle, they showed that they held it inviolable.

A state without the ability to make some changes is unable to sustain itself. Without that ability, it might even risk losing the part of the Constitution it wanted to preserve most devoutly. The two principles of preservation and correction were strongly at work during the critical times of the Restoration and Revolution when England was without a king. During both of these periods, the nation had lost the unity of their historical structure; however, they did not completely dismantle the entire system. Instead, in both cases, they revitalized the weakened part of the old Constitution through the unaffected parts. They kept those old parts just as they were so that the recovered section would fit in with them. They operated within the framework of organized states as they had originally been shaped, rather than through the individual elements of a disbanded society. Perhaps there was never a time when the sovereign legislature showed more respect for that fundamental principle of British constitutional policy than during the Revolution when it strayed from the direct line of hereditary succession. The crown was carried slightly off the path it had previously followed; but the new path still came from the same lineage. It remained a line of hereditary descent; still a hereditary descent from the same bloodline, albeit one qualified by Protestantism. When the legislature changed the direction, while maintaining the principle, it demonstrated their commitment to keeping it intact.

On this principle, the law of inheritance had admitted some amendment in the old time, and long before the era of the Revolution. Some time after the Conquest great questions arose upon the legal principles of hereditary descent. It became a matter of doubt whether the heir per capita or the heir per stirpes was to succeed; but whether the heir per capita gave way when the heirdom per stirpes took place, or the Catholic heir when the Protestant was preferred, the inheritable principle survived with a sort of immortality through all transmigrations,—

On this principle, the law of inheritance had undergone some changes in the past, long before the Revolution. After the Conquest, significant questions emerged about the legal principles of hereditary descent. It became uncertain whether the heir per capita or the heir per stirpes should inherit. However, whether the heir per capita was replaced when the inheritance per stirpes occurred, or whether the Catholic heir was displaced in favor of the Protestant, the principle of inheritance persisted with a kind of immortality through all transitions,—

Many years The fortune of the home shifts, and ancestors are counted among their ancestors.

This is the spirit of our Constitution, not only in its settled course, but in all its revolutions. Whoever came in, or however he came in, whether he obtained the crown by law or by force, the hereditary succession was either continued or adopted.

This is the essence of our Constitution, not just in its established path, but in all its changes. Whoever arrives, or however they arrive, whether they gain the throne legally or through force, the hereditary succession is either maintained or accepted.

The gentlemen of the Society for Revolutions see nothing in that of 1688 but the deviation from the Constitution; and they take the deviation from the principle for the principle. They have little regard to the obvious consequences of their doctrine, though they may see that it leaves positive authority in very few of the positive institutions of this country. When such an unwarrantable maxim is once established, that no throne is lawful but the elective, no one act of the princes who preceded this era of fictitious election can be valid. Do these theorists mean to imitate some of their predecessors, who dragged the bodies of our ancient sovereigns out of the quiet of their tombs? Do they mean to attaint and disable backwards all the kings that have reigned before the Revolution, and consequently to stain the throne of England with the blot of a continual usurpation? Do they mean to invalidate, annul, or to call into question, together with the titles of the whole line of our kings, that great body of our statute law which passed under those whom they treat as usurpers? to annul laws of inestimable value to our liberties,—of as great value at least as any which have passed at or since the period of the Revolution? If kings who did not owe their crown to the choice of their people had no title to make laws, what will become of the statute De tallagio non concedendo? of the Petition of Right? of the act of Habeas Corpus? Do these new doctors of the rights of men presume to assert that King James the Second, who came to the crown as next of blood, according to the rules of a then unqualified succession, was not to all intents and purposes a lawful king of England, before he had done any of those acts which were justly construed into an abdication of his crown? If he was not, much trouble in Parliament might have been saved at the period these gentlemen commemorate. But King James was a bad king with a good title, and not an usurper. The princes who succeeded according to the act of Parliament which settled the crown on the Electress Sophia and on her descendants, being Protestants, came in as much by a title of inheritance as King James did. He came in according to the law, as it stood at his accession to the crown; and the princes of the House of Brunswick came to the inheritance of the crown, not by election, but by the law, as it stood at their several accessions, of Protestant descent and inheritance, as I hope I have shown sufficiently.

The members of the Society for Revolutions see nothing in the events of 1688 except a break from the Constitution; they confuse the deviation from the principle with the principle itself. They pay little attention to the clear consequences of their views, even though it's apparent that it leaves real authority in very few of this country’s established institutions. Once such an unjust principle is accepted—that no throne is legitimate unless elected—then any actions taken by the monarchs before this era of made-up elections are invalid. Are these theorists planning to replicate the actions of some of their predecessors who disturbed the graves of our former kings? Do they intend to discredit and undermine all the kings who ruled before the Revolution, tainting the English throne with a legacy of continuous usurpation? Do they plan to invalidate, annul, or question the legitimacy of the entire lineage of our kings, along with the significant body of our laws that were enacted under those they label as usurpers? Will they cancel laws of immense importance to our freedoms—laws that are at least as crucial as any passed at or after the time of the Revolution? If kings who didn’t gain their crowns through their people’s choice lack the right to make laws, what will happen to the statute De tallagio non concedendo?, the Petition of Right?, and the Habeas Corpus act? Do these new advocates for human rights really claim that King James II, who ascended to the throne as the next in line according to the rules of succession at that time, was not, in every practical sense, a lawful king of England before he committed any acts that could be interpreted as giving up his crown? If that’s true, much effort in Parliament could have been avoided during the period these gentlemen discuss. But King James was a poor king with a legitimate title, not an usurper. The princes who succeeded him based on the parliamentary act that settled the crown on Electress Sophia and her descendants arrived with just as much of an inheritance claim as King James did. He ascended according to the law as it existed when he took the crown, and the princes of the House of Brunswick inherited the crown, not through election, but by law, as it stood at their respective accessions, being of Protestant descent and inheritance, as I hope I have clearly demonstrated.

The law by which this royal family is specifically destined to the succession is the act of the 12th and 13th of King William. The terms of this act bind "us, and our heirs, and our posterity, to them, their heirs, and their posterity," being Protestants, to the end of time, in the same words as the Declaration of Right had bound us to the heirs of King William and Queen Mary. It therefore secures both an hereditary crown and an hereditary allegiance. On what ground, except the constitutional policy of forming an establishment to secure that kind of succession which is to preclude a choice of the people forever, could the legislature have fastidiously rejected the fair and abundant choice which our own country presented to them, and searched in strange lands for a foreign princess, from whose womb the line of our future rulers were to derive their title to govern millions of men through a series of ages?

The law that establishes this royal family's claim to the throne is the act from the 12th and 13th years of King William's reign. This act binds "us, and our heirs, and our posterity, to them, their heirs, and their posterity," being Protestants, for all time, in the same way the Declaration of Right bound us to the heirs of King William and Queen Mary. It thus ensures both a hereditary crown and a hereditary allegiance. What reason, other than the constitutional policy of creating an establishment to guarantee this type of succession—one that permanently removes the possibility of a popular choice—could have led the legislature to dismiss the fair and plentiful options our own country offered and instead look elsewhere for a foreign princess, from whom the lineage of our future rulers would get their right to govern millions over generations?

The Princess Sophia was named in the act of settlement of the 12th and 13th of King William, for a stock and root of inheritance to our kings, and not for her merits as a temporary administratrix of a power which she might not, and in fact did not, herself ever exercise. She was adopted for one reason, and for one only,—because, says the act, "the most excellent Princess Sophia, Electress and Duchess Dowager of Hanover, is daughter of the most excellent Princess Elizabeth, late Queen of Bohemia, daughter of our late sovereign lord King James the First, of happy memory, and is hereby declared to be the next in succession in the Protestant line," &c., &c.; "and the crown shall continue to the heirs of her body, being Protestants." This limitation was made by Parliament, that through the Princess Sophia an inheritable line not only was to be continued in future, but (what they thought very material) that through her it was to be connected with the old stock of inheritance in King James the First; in order that the monarchy might preserve an unbroken unity through all ages, and might be preserved (with safety to our religion) in the old approved mode by descent, in which, if our liberties had been once endangered, they had often, through all storms and struggles of prerogative and privilege, been preserved. They did well. No experience has taught us that in any other course or method than that of an hereditary crown our liberties can be regularly perpetuated and preserved sacred as our hereditary right. An irregular, convulsive movement may be necessary to throw off an irregular, convulsive disease. But the course of succession is the healthy habit of the British Constitution. Was it that the legislature wanted, at the act for the limitation of the crown in the Hanoverian line, drawn through the female descendants of James the First, a due sense of the inconveniences of having two or three, or possibly more, foreigners in succession to the British throne? No!—they had a due sense of the evils which might happen from such foreign rule, and more than a due sense of them. But a more decisive proof cannot be given of the full conviction of the British nation that the principles of the Revolution did not authorize them to elect kings at their pleasure, and without any attention to the ancient fundamental principles of our government, than their continuing to adopt a plan of hereditary Protestant succession in the old line, with all the dangers and all the inconveniences of its being a foreign line full before their eyes, and operating with the utmost force upon their minds.

The Princess Sophia was named in the act of settlement of the 12th and 13th of King William, as a basis for the inheritance of our kings, and not for her qualities as a temporary administrator of a power she might not, and in fact did not, ever exercise herself. She was chosen for one reason only—because, as the act states, "the most excellent Princess Sophia, Electress and Duchess Dowager of Hanover, is the daughter of the most excellent Princess Elizabeth, late Queen of Bohemia, daughter of our late sovereign Lord King James the First, of happy memory, and is hereby declared to be the next in succession in the Protestant line," etc., etc.; "and the crown shall continue to the heirs of her body, being Protestants." This limitation was established by Parliament, so that through Princess Sophia, an inheritable line would not only continue in the future, but (as they deemed very important) that it would be connected to the original line of inheritance from King James the First; to ensure that the monarchy maintained an unbroken unity through the ages, and could be preserved (with safety to our religion) in the time-tested way of descent, through which, if our liberties had ever been threatened, they had often been protected throughout all struggles for prerogative and privilege. They made the right choice. No experience has shown us that any other approach than that of an hereditary crown can regularly preserve and safeguard our liberties as an inherent right. A disruptive, forceful change may be necessary to rid ourselves of an irregular, chaotic problem. But the line of succession is the healthy practice of the British Constitution. Did the legislature lack an understanding, at the act for the limitation of the crown in the Hanoverian line, of the problems with having two or three, or possibly more, foreigners in line for the British throne? No!—they understood all too well the potential issues that could arise from foreign rule. However, a clear indicator of the British nation’s belief that the principles of the Revolution did not give them the right to elect kings at will, disregarding the ancient fundamental principles of our government, is their choice to maintain a plan of hereditary Protestant succession in the old line, fully aware of the dangers and inconveniences of it being a foreign line, operating with significant influence on their minds.

A few years ago I should be ashamed to overload a matter so capable of supporting itself by the then unnecessary support of any argument; but this seditious, unconstitutional doctrine is now publicly taught, avowed, and printed. The dislike I feel to revolutions, the signals for which have so often been given from pulpits,—the spirit of change that is gone abroad,—the total contempt which prevails with you, and may come to prevail with us, of all ancient institutions, when set in opposition to a present sense of convenience, or to the bent of a present inclination,—all these considerations make it not unadvisable, in my opinion, to call back our attention to the true principles of our own domestic laws, that you, my French friend, should begin to know, and that we should continue to cherish them. We ought not, on either side of the water, to suffer ourselves to be imposed upon by the counterfeit wares which some persons, by a double fraud, export to you in illicit bottoms, as raw commodities of British growth, though wholly alien to our soil, in order afterwards to smuggle them back again into this country, manufactured after the newest Paris fashion of an improved liberty.

A few years ago, I would have felt ashamed to overly discuss a matter that could stand on its own without needing extra arguments. But now, this rebellious and unconstitutional idea is being openly taught, acknowledged, and printed. My objection to revolutions is strong, especially since the calls for them have frequently come from pulpits—the spirit of change is everywhere—and the widespread disregard for old institutions, when compared to immediate convenience or current trends, is concerning. All these factors make it wise, in my opinion, to revisit the fundamental principles of our own domestic laws, which you, my French friend, should come to understand, and that we should continue to value. We should not let ourselves, on either side of the ocean, be misled by fake goods that some people smuggle to you as British products, even though they don’t actually come from our land, only to then bring them back here, altered in the latest Paris style of supposed liberty.

The people of England will not ape the fashions they have never tried, nor go back to those which they have found mischievous on trial. They look upon the legal hereditary succession of their crown as among their rights, not as among their wrongs,—as a benefit, not as a grievance,—as a security for their liberty, not as a badge of servitude. They look on the frame of their commonwealth, such as it stands, to be of inestimable value; and they conceive the undisturbed succession of the crown to be a pledge of the stability and perpetuity of all the other members of our Constitution.

The people of England won’t imitate fashions they’ve never experienced, nor will they return to those they’ve found harmful after trying. They see the legal hereditary succession of their crown as one of their rights, not a wrongdoing—something beneficial, not a grievance—as a guarantee of their freedom, not a mark of servitude. They view the structure of their commonwealth, as it is, as incredibly valuable; and they believe the undisturbed succession of the crown represents the stability and longevity of all the other parts of our Constitution.

I shall beg leave, before I go any further, to take notice of some paltry artifices which the abettors of election as the only lawful title to the crown are ready to employ, in order to render the support of the just principles of our Constitution a task somewhat invidious. These sophisters substitute a fictitious cause, and feigned personages, in whose favor they suppose you engaged, whenever you defend the inheritable nature of the crown. It is common with them to dispute as if they were in a conflict with some of those exploded fanatics of slavery who formerly maintained, what I believe no creature now maintains, "that the crown is held by divine, hereditary, and indefeasible right." These old fanatics of single arbitrary power dogmatized as if hereditary royalty was the only lawful government in the world,—just as our new fanatics of popular arbitrary power maintain that a popular election is the sole lawful source of authority. The old prerogative enthusiasts, it is true, did speculate foolishly, and perhaps impiously too, as if monarchy had more of a divine sanction than any other mode of government,—and as if a right to govern by inheritance were in strictness indefeasible in every person who should be found in the succession to a throne, and under every circumstance, which no civil or political right can be. But an absurd opinion concerning the king's hereditary right to the crown does not prejudice one that is rational, and bottomed upon solid principles of law and policy. If all the absurd theories of lawyers and divines were to vitiate the objects in which they are conversant, we should have no law and no religion left in the world. But an absurd theory on one side of a question forms no justification for alleging a false fact or promulgating mischievous maxims on the other.

I’d like to take a moment before I continue to point out some petty tricks that those who support elections as the only legitimate way to the throne are ready to use in order to make the defense of our Constitution's core principles seem like a difficult task. These manipulators create a fake cause and false figures, assuming it’s them you’re defending when you argue for the inheritable nature of the crown. They often argue as if they're battling some of those outdated fanatics of slavery who used to claim, a belief that I doubt anyone still holds, that "the crown is held by divine, hereditary, and indefeasible right." These old fanatics of absolute power insisted that hereditary royalty was the only legitimate form of government, just as our new fanatics of popular power claim that a popular election is the only rightful source of authority. It’s true that the old advocates of prerogative speculated foolishly, and perhaps even irreverently, as if monarchy had more divine approval than any other government style; and as if the right to govern by inheritance were strictly indefeasible for anyone in the line of succession to a throne under all circumstances, which no civil or political right can be. But an absurd opinion about a king’s hereditary right to the crown doesn't undermine a rational view based on solid legal and policy principles. If all the ridiculous theories of lawyers and religious scholars were to invalidate the subjects they deal with, we would have no law and no religion left in the world. However, just because there’s an absurd theory on one side of a debate doesn’t justify making false claims or spreading harmful ideas on the other side.


The second claim of the Revolution Society is "a right of cashiering their governors for misconduct." Perhaps the apprehensions our ancestors entertained of forming such a precedent as that "of cashiering for misconduct" was the cause that the declaration of the act which implied the abdication of King James was, if it had any fault, rather too guarded and too circumstantial.[82] But all this guard, and all this accumulation of circumstances, serves to show the spirit of caution which predominated in the national councils, in a situation in which men irritated by oppression, and elevated by a triumph over it, are apt to abandon themselves to violent and extreme courses; it shows the anxiety of the great men who influenced the conduct of affairs at that great event to make the Revolution a parent of settlement, and not a nursery of future revolutions.

The second claim of the Revolution Society is "the right to remove their governors for misconduct." Maybe the concerns our ancestors had about setting a precedent for "removing governors for misconduct" led to the declaration that implied the abdication of King James being, if anything, a bit too cautious and detailed.[82] But all this caution and all these details show the careful spirit that prevailed in the national councils, especially in a situation where people, upset by oppression and uplifted by their victory over it, might be tempted to take extreme actions; it reflects the concern of the prominent figures who shaped the events of that time to ensure the Revolution led to stability, not to future revolts.

No government could stand a moment, if it could be blown down with anything so loose and indefinite as an opinion of "misconduct." They who led at the Revolution grounded their virtual abdication of King James upon no such light and uncertain principle. They charged him with nothing less than a design, confirmed by a multitude of illegal overt acts, to subvert the Protestant Church and State, and their fundamental, unquestionable laws and liberties: they charged him with having broken the original contrast between king and people. This was more than misconduct. A grave and overruling necessity obliged them to take the step they took, and took with infinite reluctance, as under that most rigorous of all laws. Their trust for the future preservation of the Constitution was not in future revolutions. The grand policy of all their regulations was to render it almost impracticable for any future sovereign to compel the states of the kingdom to have again recourse to those violent remedies. They left the crown, what in the eye and estimation of law it had ever been, perfectly irresponsible. In order to lighten the crown still further, they aggravated responsibility on ministers of state. By the statute of the first of King William, sess. 2d, called "the act for declaring the rights and liberties of the subject, and for settling the succession of the crown," they enacted that the ministers should serve the crown on the terms of that declaration. They secured soon after the frequent meetings of Parliament, by which the whole government would be under the constant inspection and active control of the popular representative and of the magnates of the kingdom. In the next great constitutional act, that of the 12th and 13th of King William, for the further limitation of the crown, and better securing the rights and liberties of the subject, they provided "that no pardon under the great seal of England should be pleadable to an impeachment by the Commons in Parliament." The rule laid down for government in the Declaration of Right, the constant inspection of Parliament, the practical claim of impeachment, they thought infinitely a better security not only for their constitutional liberty, but against the vices of administration, than the reservation of a right so difficult in the practice, so uncertain in the issue, and often so mischievous in the consequences, as that "cashiering their governors."

No government could survive for long if it could be easily toppled by something as vague and unclear as an opinion of "misconduct." Those who led the Revolution based their decision to remove King James on much stronger and more certain grounds. They accused him of nothing less than attempting, supported by numerous illegal actions, to subvert the Protestant Church and State, along with their fundamental, unquestionable laws and freedoms: they accused him of breaking the original contract between the king and the people. This was more than just misconduct. A serious and unavoidable necessity forced them to take the actions they did, which they approached with deep reluctance, as if following the strictest of all laws. They did not rely on future revolutions for the ongoing protection of the Constitution. The main strategy behind all their regulations was to make it nearly impossible for any future king to drive the states of the kingdom back to those extreme measures. They left the crown, in the eyes of the law, exactly the same as it had always been—completely untouchable. To lessen the power of the crown even more, they increased the accountability of state ministers. By the law passed in the first year of King William, sess. 2d, known as "the act for declaring the rights and liberties of the subject, and for settling the succession of the crown," they specified that ministers should serve the crown under the terms of that declaration. They soon ensured the frequent meetings of Parliament, through which the entire government would be under the constant scrutiny and active oversight of both the popular representatives and the notable figures of the kingdom. In the next major constitutional act, that of the 12th and 13th of King William, aimed at further limiting the crown and better securing the rights and freedoms of the citizens, they stipulated "that no pardon under the great seal of England should be valid against an impeachment by the Commons in Parliament." The principles outlined for government in the Declaration of Right, the ongoing oversight of Parliament, and the practical right of impeachment, they believed provided far better protection not only for their constitutional liberty but also against administrative corruption, compared to the uncertain and often harmful repercussions of formally "removing their governors."

Dr. Price, in this sermon,[83] condemns, very properly, the practice of gross adulatory addresses to kings. Instead of this fulsome style, he proposes that his Majesty should be told, on occasions of congratulation, that "he is to consider himself as more properly the servant than the sovereign of his people." For a compliment, this new form of address does not seem to be very soothing. Those who are servants in name, as well as in effect, do not like to be told of their situation, their duty, and their obligations. The slave in the old play tells his master, "Hæc commemeratio est quasi exprobratio." It is not pleasant as compliment; it is not wholesome as instruction. After all, if the king were to bring himself to echo this new kind of address, to adopt it in terms, and even to take the appellation of Servant of the People as his royal style, how either he or we should be much mended by it I cannot imagine. I have seen very assuming letters signed, "Your most obedient, humble servant." The proudest domination that ever was endured on earth took a title of still greater humility than that which is now proposed for sovereigns by the Apostle of Liberty. Kings and nations were trampled upon by the foot of one calling himself "The Servant of Servants"; and mandates for deposing sovereigns were sealed with the signet of "The Fisherman."

Dr. Price, in this sermon,[83] rightly criticizes the practice of excessively flattering addresses to kings. Instead of this over-the-top style, he suggests that His Majesty should be informed, on occasions of congratulations, that "he should see himself more as the servant than the sovereign of his people." For a compliment, this new form of address doesn’t seem very comforting. Those who are servants both in name and in reality don’t appreciate being reminded of their situation, duties, and obligations. The slave in the old play says to his master, "Hæc commemeratio est quasi exprobratio." It’s not pleasant as a compliment; it doesn’t serve well as instruction. After all, if the king were to accept this new way of speaking, to adopt it in practice, and even to take on the title of Servant of the People as his royal designation, I can’t see how either he or we would actually benefit from it. I’ve seen very arrogant letters signed, "Your most obedient, humble servant." The most arrogant rule ever endured on earth took a title of even greater humility than what is being suggested for kings by the Apostle of Liberty. Kings and nations were oppressed by one calling himself "The Servant of Servants"; and mandates for deposing sovereigns were sealed with the signet of "The Fisherman."

I should have considered all this as no more than a sort of flippant, vain discourse, in which, as in an unsavory fume, several persons suffer the spirit of liberty to evaporate, if it were not plainly in support of the idea, and a part of the scheme, of "cashiering kings for misconduct." In that light it is worth some observation.

I should have seen all of this as just a casual, vain conversation, where, like an unpleasant smell, a few people let the spirit of liberty fade away, if it wasn't clearly backing the idea and part of the plan of "removing kings for wrongdoing." In that context, it deserves some attention.

Kings, in one sense, are undoubtedly the servants of the people, because their power has no other rational end than that of the general advantage; but it is not true that they are, in the ordinary sense, (by our Constitution, at least,) anything like servants,—the essence of whose situation is to obey the commands of some other, and to be removable at pleasure. But the king of Great Britain obeys no other person; all other persons are individually, and collectively too, under him, and owe to him a legal obedience. The law, which knows neither to flatter nor to insult, calls this high-magistrate, not our servant, as this humble divine calls him, but "our sovereign lord the king"; and we, on our parts, have learned to speak only the primitive language of the law, and not the confused jargon of their Babylonian pulpits.

Kings, in one way, are definitely the servants of the people because their power only serves the common good; however, it’s not accurate to say they are, in the usual sense (according to our Constitution, at least), anything like servants—whose role is to follow the orders of someone else and can be dismissed at will. But the king of Great Britain does not answer to anyone else; everyone else, both individually and collectively, is under him and owes him legal obedience. The law, which neither flatters nor insults, refers to this high magistrate not as our servant, as this humble divine calls him, but as "our sovereign lord the king"; and we, for our part, have learned to only speak the straightforward language of the law, not the mixed-up jargon of their confusing pulpits.

As he is not to obey us, but we are to obey the law in him, our Constitution has made no sort of provision towards rendering him, as a servant, in any degree responsible. Our Constitution knows nothing of a magistrate like the Justicia of Aragon,—nor of any court legally appointed, nor of any process legally settled, for submitting the king to the responsibility belonging to all servants. In this he is not distinguished from the commons and the lords, who, in their several public capacities, can never be called to an account for their conduct; although the Revolution Society chooses to assert, in direct opposition to one of the wisest and most beautiful parts of our Constitution, that "a king is no more than the first servant of the public, created by it, and responsible to it."

As he is not meant to follow our commands, but we are meant to follow the law through him, our Constitution doesn’t include any provisions to hold him, as a servant, accountable in any way. Our Constitution doesn’t recognize a magistrate like the Justicia of Aragon, nor any officially appointed court, nor any established legal process for holding the king accountable like all other servants. In this regard, he is not different from the common people and the lords, who, in their various public roles, can never be held responsible for their actions; even though the Revolution Society claims, in direct opposition to one of the wisest and most beautiful parts of our Constitution, that "a king is no more than the first servant of the public, created by it, and responsible to it."

Ill would our ancestors at the Revolution have deserved their fame for wisdom, if they had found no security for their freedom, but in rendering their government feeble in its operations and precarious in its tenure,—if they had been able to contrive no better remedy against arbitrary power than civil confusion. Let these gentlemen state who that representative public is to whom they will affirm the king, as a servant, to be responsible. It will be then time enough for me to produce to them the positive statute law which affirms that he is not.

Our ancestors at the Revolution wouldn't have deserved their fame for wisdom if they had only secured their freedom by making the government weak and unstable—if they could only come up with chaos as a solution to arbitrary power. Let these gentlemen explain who this representative public is to whom they claim the king, as a servant, is responsible. It will then be the right time for me to show them the actual laws that state he is not.

The ceremony of cashiering kings, of which these gentlemen talk so much at their ease, can rarely, if ever, be performed without force. It then becomes a case of war, and not of constitution. Laws are commanded to hold their tongues amongst arms; and tribunals fall to the ground with the peace they are no longer able to uphold. The Revolution of 1688 was obtained by a just war, in the only case in which any war, and much more a civil war, can be just. "Justa bella quibus NECESSARIA." The question of dethroning, or, if these gentlemen, like the phrase better, "cashiering kings," will always be, as it has always been, an extraordinary question of state, and wholly out of the law: a question (like all other questions of state) of dispositions, and of means, and of probable consequences, rather than of positive rights. As it was not made for common abuses, so it is not to be agitated by common minds. The speculative line of demarcation, where obedience ought to end and resistance must begin, is faint, obscure, and not easily definable. It is not a single act or a single event which determines it. Governments must be abused and deranged indeed, before it can be thought of; and the prospect of the future must be as bad as the experience of the past. When things are in that lamentable condition, the nature of the disease is to indicate the remedy to those whom Nature has qualified to administer in extremities this critical, ambiguous, bitter potion to a distempered state. Times and occasions and provocations will teach their own lessons. The wise will determine from the gravity of the case; the irritable, from sensibility to oppression; the high-minded, from disdain and indignation at abusive power in unworthy hands; the brave and bold, from the love of honorable danger in a generous cause: but, with or without right, a revolution will be the very last resource of the thinking and the good.

The ceremony of removing kings, which these gentlemen casually discuss, can rarely, if ever, be done without force. It then becomes a matter of war, not of constitution. Laws are silenced in the presence of arms, and courts collapse along with the peace they're unable to maintain. The Revolution of 1688 was achieved through a just war, in the only scenario where any war, especially a civil war, can be justified. "Justa bella quibus NECESSARIA." The question of dethroning, or as these gentlemen prefer to say, "removing kings," will always be, as it has always been, an extraordinary state matter that lies entirely outside the law: a question (like all other state questions) of conditions, means, and potential outcomes, rather than of absolute rights. It wasn't designed for common abuses, so it shouldn't be debated by common minds. The theoretical line that indicates where obedience should end and resistance should begin is faint, unclear, and hard to define. It's not determined by a single act or event. Governments must be seriously mismanaged before this can even be considered; and the outlook for the future has to be as dire as the experiences of the past. When conditions reach such a regrettable state, the nature of the issue reveals the remedy to those whom Nature has prepared to handle, in critical times, this complex, uncertain, and bitter treatment for an ailing state. Times, circumstances, and provocations will instruct their own lessons. The wise will assess the seriousness of the situation; the sensitive will react to oppression; the noble will feel disdain and anger at wrongful power in unworthy hands; and the brave will be motivated by a love for honorable risks in a noble cause: but, with or without justification, a revolution will be the last resort for the thoughtful and the righteous.


The third head of right asserted by the pulpit of the Old Jewry, namely, the "right to form a government for ourselves," has, at least, as little countenance from anything done at the Revolution, either in precedent or principle, as the two first of their claims. The Revolution was made to preserve our ancient indisputable laws and liberties, and that ancient constitution of government which is our only security for law and liberty. If you are desirous of knowing the spirit of our Constitution, and the policy which predominated in that great period which has secured it to this hour, pray look for both in our histories, in our records, in our acts of Parliament and journals of Parliament, and not in the sermons of the Old Jewry, and the after-dinner toasts of the Revolution Society. In the former you will find other ideas and another language. Such a claim is as ill-suited to our temper and wishes as it is unsupported by any appearance of authority. The very idea of the fabrication of a new government is enough to fill us with disgust and horror. We wished at the period of the Revolution, and do now wish, to derive all we possess as an inheritance from our forefathers. Upon that body and stock of inheritance we have taken care not to inoculate any scion alien to the nature of the original plant. All the reformations we have hitherto made have proceeded upon the principle of reference to antiquity; and I hope, nay, I am persuaded, that all those which possibly may be made hereafter will be carefully formed upon analogical precedent, authority, and example.

The third point of right claimed by the pulpit of the Old Jewry, specifically the "right to form a government for ourselves," has, at least, as little support from anything that happened during the Revolution, either in terms of precedent or principle, as the first two claims. The Revolution was carried out to preserve our ancient undeniable laws and freedoms, and to maintain the ancient system of government that ensures our security for law and freedom. If you want to understand the spirit of our Constitution and the policies that dominated the significant period that has secured it to this day, look for both in our histories, our records, our Acts of Parliament and journals, not in the sermons from the Old Jewry or the after-dinner toasts of the Revolution Society. In the former, you'll find different ideas and a different language. Such a claim is completely out of touch with our mindset and desires, and lacks any semblance of authority. The mere thought of creating a new government disgusts and horrifies us. We wanted during the Revolution, and still want, to inherit everything we have as an inheritance from our forefathers. We have made sure not to introduce anything foreign to the essence of our original inheritance. Every reform we've made so far has been based on the principle of referencing our past; and I hope, or rather, I'm convinced, that any future reforms will also be carefully based on analogous precedent, authority, and example.

Our oldest reformation is that of Magna Charta. You will see that Sir Edward Coke, that great oracle of our law, and indeed all the great men who follow him, to Blackstone,[84] are industrious to prove the pedigree of our liberties. They endeavor to prove that the ancient charter, the Magna Charta of King John, was connected with another positive charter from Henry the First, and that both the one and the other were nothing more than a reaffirmance of the still more ancient standing law of the kingdom. In the matter of fact, for the greater part, these authors appear to be in the right; perhaps not always: but if the lawyers mistake in some particulars, it proves my position still the more strongly; because it demonstrates the powerful prepossession towards antiquity with which the minds of all our lawyers and legislators, and of all the people whom they wish to influence, have been always filled, and the stationary policy of this kingdom in considering their most sacred rights and franchises as an inheritance.

Our oldest reform is the Magna Carta. You'll see that Sir Edward Coke, that great authority on our law, along with all the other prominent figures who came after him, like Blackstone, are eager to trace the history of our freedoms. They try to show that the ancient charter, the Magna Carta of King John, was linked to another formal charter from Henry the First, and that both were merely reaffirmations of the even older laws of the kingdom. In fact, for the most part, these authors seem to be correct; maybe not all the time. But if the lawyers get some details wrong, it actually supports my point even more strongly because it highlights the strong inclination towards tradition that has always filled the minds of our lawyers and lawmakers, as well as the people they aim to influence, viewing their most sacred rights and freedoms as an inheritance.

In the famous law of the 3rd of Charles the First, called the Petition of Right, the Parliament says to the king, "Your subjects have inherited this freedom": claiming their franchises, not on abstract principles, "as the rights of men," but as the rights of Englishmen, and as a patrimony derived from their forefathers. Selden, and the other profoundly learned men who drew this Petition of Right, were as well acquainted, at least, with all the general theories concerning the "rights of men" as any of the discoursers in our pulpits or on your tribune: full as well as Dr. Price, or as the Abbé Sièyes. But, for reasons worthy of that practical wisdom which superseded their theoretic science, they preferred this positive, recorded, hereditary title to all which can be dear to the man and the citizen to that vague, speculative right which exposed their sure inheritance to be scrambled for and torn to pieces by every wild, litigious spirit.

In the well-known law from the 3rd of Charles the First, called the Petition of Right, Parliament tells the king, "Your subjects have inherited this freedom": asserting their rights not based on abstract ideas, "as the rights of men," but as the rights of Englishmen, rooted in a legacy from their ancestors. Selden and the other highly knowledgeable figures who drafted this Petition of Right were just as familiar with all the general theories about "the rights of men" as any of the speakers in our churches or on your podium: just as much as Dr. Price or Abbé Sièyes. Yet, for reasons that reflect their practical wisdom, which surpassed their theoretical studies, they chose this concrete, documented, hereditary right over any vague, speculative entitlement that could expose their established inheritance to be fought over and destroyed by every reckless, litigious person.

The same policy pervades all the laws which have since been made for the preservation of our liberties. In the 1st of William and Mary, in the famous statute called the Declaration of Right, the two Houses utter not a syllable of "a right to frame a government for themselves." You will see that their whole care was to secure the religion, laws, and liberties that had been long possessed, and had been lately endangered. "Taking[85] into their most serious consideration the best means for making such an establishment that their religion, laws, and liberties might not be in danger of being again subverted," they auspicate all their proceedings by stating as some of those best means, "in the first place," to do "as their ancestors in like cases have usually done for vindicating their ancient rights and liberties, to declare";—and then they pray the king and queen "that it may be declared and enacted that all and singular the rights and liberties asserted and declared are the true ancient and indubitable rights and liberties of the people of this kingdom."

The same policy runs through all the laws that have been created since then to protect our freedoms. In the 1st of William and Mary, in the well-known statute called the Declaration of Right, the two Houses do not mention "a right to create a government for themselves." You'll see that their main focus was on safeguarding the religion, laws, and freedoms that had been held for a long time and were recently threatened. "Taking[85] into serious consideration the best ways to establish their religion, laws, and liberties so that they might not be at risk of being undermined again," they start all their actions by stating some of those best ways, "in the first place," to do "as their ancestors have typically done in similar situations to defend their ancient rights and liberties, to declare";—and then they ask the king and queen "that it may be declared and enacted that all and singular the rights and liberties asserted and declared are the true ancient and undeniable rights and liberties of the people of this kingdom."

You will observe, that, from Magna Charta to the Declaration of Right, it has been the uniform policy of our Constitution to claim and assert our liberties as an entailed inheritance derived to us from our forefathers, and to be transmitted to our posterity,—as an estate specially belonging to the people of this kingdom, without any reference whatever to any other more general or prior right. By this means our Constitution preserves an unity in so great a diversity of its parts. We have an inheritable crown, an inheritable peerage, and a House of Commons and a people inheriting privileges, franchises, and liberties from a long line of ancestors.

You will notice that, from the Magna Carta to the Declaration of Rights, our Constitution has consistently aimed to claim and affirm our freedoms as an entailed inheritance passed down to us from our ancestors, to be handed down to our descendants—like an estate that exclusively belongs to the people of this kingdom, without considering any other more general or earlier rights. This approach allows our Constitution to maintain unity despite the significant diversity of its components. We have a crown that can be inherited, a peerage that can be inherited, and a House of Commons along with a people inheriting privileges, rights, and freedoms from a long line of forebears.

This policy appears to me to be the result of profound reflection,—or rather the happy effect of following Nature, which is wisdom without reflection, and above it. A spirit of innovation is generally the result of a selfish temper and confined views. People will not look forward to posterity, who never look backward to their ancestors. Besides, the people of England well know that the idea of inheritance furnishes a sure principle of conservation, and a sure principle of transmission, without at all excluding a principle of improvement. It leaves acquisition free; but it secures what it acquires. Whatever advantages are obtained by a state proceeding on these maxims are locked fast as in a sort of family settlement, grasped as in a kind of mortmain forever. By a constitutional policy working after the pattern of Nature, we receive, we hold, we transmit our government and our privileges, in the same manner in which we enjoy and transmit our property and our lives. The institutions of policy, the goods of fortune, the gifts of Providence, are handed down to us, and from us, in the same course and order. Our political system is placed in a just correspondence and symmetry with the order of the world, and with the mode of existence decreed to a permanent body composed of transitory parts,—wherein, by the disposition of a stupendous wisdom, moulding together the great mysterious incorporation of the human race, the whole, at one time, is never old or middle-aged or young, but, in a condition of unchangeable constancy, moves on through the varied tenor of perpetual decay, fall, renovation, and progression. Thus, by preserving the method of Nature in the conduct of the state, in what we improve we are never wholly new, in what we retain we are never wholly obsolete. By adhering in this manner and on those principles to our forefathers, we are guided, not by the superstition of antiquarians, but by the spirit of philosophic analogy. In this choice of inheritance we have given to our frame of polity the image of a relation in blood: binding up the Constitution of our country with our dearest domestic ties; adopting our fundamental laws into the bosom of our family affections; keeping inseparable, and cherishing with the warmth of all their combined and mutually reflected charities, our state, our hearths, our sepulchres, and our altars.

This policy seems to be the result of deep thought—or rather, the fortunate outcome of following Nature, which represents wisdom without needing reflection, and is above it. A spirit of innovation often stems from a selfish mindset and narrow views. Those who don't look back at their ancestors won't think about future generations. Moreover, the people of England know well that the idea of inheritance provides a solid principle of conservation and a reliable principle of transmission, all while allowing for improvement. It keeps acquisition open; but it safeguards what it acquires. Any benefits gained by a government that operates on these principles are securely held like a family agreement, grasped as if they were inalienable forever. By a constitutional approach that mirrors Nature, we receive, hold, and pass down our government and our rights in the same way we enjoy and hand down our property and our lives. The structures of policy, the fortunes, and the blessings from Providence are passed down to us and from us in the same sequence and order. Our political system is properly aligned and balanced with the order of the world and the existence prescribed for a permanent entity made of temporary parts—where, through a remarkable wisdom that molds the great mysterious unity of the human race, the whole is never simply old, middle-aged, or young, but, in a state of unchanging continuity, progresses through ongoing cycles of decay, fall, renewal, and advancement. Thus, by maintaining the method of Nature in governing the state, in what we improve we are never entirely new, and in what we keep we are never completely outdated. By adhering to our forefathers in this way and on these principles, we are guided not by the superstitions of antiquarians, but by the insight of philosophical analogy. In choosing inheritance, we have shaped our political framework to mirror blood relations: tying our country's Constitution to our closest family bonds; integrating our fundamental laws into our family affections; inseparably connecting and nurturing, with the warmth of their combined and mutually reflected love, our state, our homes, our cemeteries, and our places of worship.

Through the same plan of a conformity to Nature in our artificial institutions, and by calling in the aid of her unerring and powerful instincts to fortify the fallible and feeble contrivances of our reason, we have derived several other, and those no small benefits, from considering our liberties in the light of an inheritance. Always acting as if in the presence of canonized forefathers, the spirit of freedom, leading in itself to misrule and excess, is tempered with an awful gravity. This idea of a liberal descent inspires us with a sense of habitual native dignity, which prevents that upstart insolence almost inevitably adhering to and disgracing those who are the first acquirers of any distinction. By this means our liberty becomes a noble freedom. It carries an imposing and majestic aspect. It has a pedigree and illustrating ancestors. It has its bearings and its ensigns armorial. It has its gallery of portraits, its monumental inscriptions, its records, evidences, and titles. We procure reverence to our civil institutions on the principle upon which Nature teaches us to revere individual men: on account of their age, and on account of those from whom they are descended. All your sophisters cannot produce anything better adapted to preserve a rational and manly freedom than the course that we have pursued, who have chosen our nature rather than our speculations, our breasts rather than our inventions, for the great conservatories and magazines of our rights and privileges.

By sticking to a plan that aligns our artificial institutions with Nature, and by relying on her reliable and strong instincts to support our weak and imperfect reasoning, we’ve gained several significant benefits from viewing our freedoms as an inheritance. Always acting as though we are in the presence of revered ancestors, the spirit of freedom, which can sometimes lead to chaos and excess, is tempered by a serious respect. The idea of a noble lineage gives us a sense of inherent dignity that protects us from the arrogant behavior that often comes with being the first to achieve any distinction. This way, our freedom becomes a more honorable one. It has a grand and impressive presence, with a lineage and distinguished ancestors. It has its direction and its heraldry. It has its collection of portraits, memorial inscriptions, records, evidence, and titles. We earn respect for our civil institutions based on the same principle that Nature teaches us to respect individuals: because of their age and their heritage. No amount of clever arguments can offer a better way to maintain a reasonable and dignified freedom than the path we have taken, choosing our nature over our theories, our hearts over our inventions, as the true guardians and stores of our rights and privileges.


You might, if you pleased, have profited of our example, and have given to your recovered freedom a correspondent dignity. Your privileges, though discontinued, were not lost to memory. Your Constitution, it is true, whilst you were out of possession, suffered waste and dilapidation; but you possessed in some parts the walls, and in all the foundations, of a noble and venerable castle. You might have repaired those walls; you might have built on those old foundations. Your Constitution was suspended before it was perfected; but you had the elements of a Constitution very nearly as good as could be wished. In your old states you possessed that variety of parts corresponding with the various descriptions of which your community was happily composed; you had all that combination and all that opposition of interests, you had that action and counteraction, which, in the natural and in the political world, from the reciprocal struggle of discordant powers draws out the harmony of the universe. These opposed and conflicting interests, which you considered as so great a blemish in your old and in our present Constitution, interpose a salutary check to all precipitate resolutions. They render deliberation a matter, not of choice, but of necessity; they make all change a subject of compromise, which naturally begets moderation; they produce temperaments, preventing the sore evil of harsh, crude, unqualified reformations, and rendering all the headlong exertions of arbitrary power, in the few or in the many, forever impracticable. Through that diversity of members and interests, general liberty had as many securities as there were separate views in the several orders; whilst by pressing down the whole by the weight of a real monarchy, the separate parts would have been prevented from warping and starting from their allotted places.

If you wanted to, you could have learned from our example and given your regained freedom a fitting respect. Your rights, though put on hold, were not forgotten. Your Constitution, while you were without it, did suffer some neglect and decay; however, you still had parts of the structure and all the foundations of a great and respected castle. You could have repaired those walls and built upon those old foundations. Your Constitution was stalled before it was fully formed; yet you had nearly all the elements of a Constitution that could be ideally wished for. In your previous states, you had that mix of parts that matched the different groups your community was happily made of; you had all the combinations and all the conflicting interests, you had the action and counteraction, which, in both the natural and political worlds, creates the harmony of the universe through the ongoing struggle between discordant powers. Those opposing interests, which you saw as a significant flaw in both your old and our current Constitution, provide a necessary check to any hasty decisions. They make deliberation a requirement, not an option; they turn every change into a matter of compromise, which naturally fosters moderation; they create temperaments, preventing the serious problems of harsh, crude, unqualified reforms, and ensuring that all reckless uses of arbitrary power, whether by a few or many, would forever be impossible. Because of that diversity of members and interests, general liberty had as many safeguards as there were different perspectives in the various groups; while by keeping everything under the pressure of a true monarchy, the individual parts would have been prevented from straying from their designated roles.

You had all these advantages in your ancient states; but you chose to act as if you had never been moulded into civil society, and had everything to begin anew. You began ill, because you began by despising everything that belonged to you. You set up your trade without a capital. If the last generations of your country appeared without much lustre in your eyes, you might have passed them by, and derived your claims from a more early race of ancestors. Under a pious predilection for those ancestors, your imaginations would have realized in them a standard of virtue and wisdom beyond the vulgar practice of the hour; and you would have risen with the example to whose imitation you aspired. Respecting your forefathers, you would have been taught to respect yourselves. You would not have chosen to consider the French as a people of yesterday, as a nation of low-born, servile wretches until the emancipating year of 1789. In order to furnish, at the expense of your honor, an excuse to your apologists here for several enormities of yours, you would not have been content to be represented as a gang of Maroon slaves, suddenly broke loose from the house of bondage, and therefore to be pardoned for your abuse of the liberty to which you were not accustomed, and were ill fitted. Would it not, my worthy friend, have been wiser to have you thought, what I for one always thought you, a generous and gallant nation, long misled to your disadvantage by your high and romantic sentiments of fidelity, honor, and loyalty; that events had been unfavorable to you, but that you were not enslaved through any illiberal or servile disposition; that, in your most devoted submission, you were actuated by a principle of public spirit; and that it was your country you worshipped, in the person of your king? Had you made it to be understood, that, in the delusion of this amiable error, you had gone further than your wise ancestors,—that you were resolved to resume your ancient privileges, whilst you preserved the spirit of your ancient and your recent loyalty and honor; or if, diffident of yourselves, and not clearly discerning the almost obliterated Constitution of your ancestors, you had looked to your neighbors in this land, who had kept alive the ancient principles and models of the old common law of Europe, meliorated and adapted to its present state,—by following wise examples you would have given new examples of wisdom to the world. You would have rendered the cause of liberty venerable in the eyes of every worthy mind in every nation. You would have shamed despotism from the earth, by showing that freedom was not only reconcilable, but, as, when well disciplined, it is, auxiliary to law. You would have had an unoppressive, but a productive revenue. You would have had a flourishing commerce to feed it. You would have had a free Constitution, a potent monarchy, a disciplined army, a reformed and venerated clergy,—a mitigated, but spirited nobility, to lead your virtue, not to overlay it; you would have had a liberal order of commons, to emulate and to recruit that nobility; you would have had a protected, satisfied, laborious, and obedient people, taught to seek and to recognize the happiness that is to be found by virtue in all conditions,—in which consists the true moral equality of mankind, and not in that monstrous fiction which, by inspiring false ideas and vain expectations into men destined to travel in the obscure walk of laborious life, serves only to aggravate and embitter that real inequality which it never can remove, and which the order of civil life establishes as much for the benefit of those whom it must leave in an humble state as those whom it is able to exalt to a condition more splendid, but not more happy. You had a smooth and easy career of felicity and glory laid open to you, beyond anything recorded in the history of the world; but you have shown that difficulty is good for man.

You had so many advantages in your ancient states, but you decided to act as if you had never been shaped into a civil society and had everything to start from scratch. You started off poorly because you began by looking down on everything that belonged to you. You set up your trade without any capital. If the previous generations of your country didn’t seem impressive to you, you could have simply overlooked them and traced your lineage back to earlier ancestors. With a genuine fondness for those ancestors, you might have idealized them as paragons of virtue and wisdom, beyond the common practices of your time; and you would have aspired to their example. By honoring your forefathers, you would have learned to honor yourselves. You wouldn’t have seen the French as yesterday’s people, as a nation of low-born, servile individuals until the liberating year of 1789. In order to justify some of your misdeeds here at the cost of your dignity, you shouldn’t have been satisfied to be portrayed as a group of escaped slaves suddenly breaking free from bondage and thus excused for your misuse of the liberty you were unaccustomed to and ill-prepared for. Would it not, my dear friend, have been smarter to be seen, as I have always seen you, as a noble and brave nation, long misled to your detriment by your lofty and romantic ideals of fidelity, honor, and loyalty; that circumstances were against you, but that you weren’t enslaved due to any unworthy or servile nature; that in your most devoted submission, you were driven by a sense of public spirit; and that it was your country you revered, embodied in your king? Had you made it clear that, in the illusion of this admirable flaw, you had fallen further than your wise ancestors—that you were determined to reclaim your ancient rights while preserving the essence of your loyalty and honor from both the past and the present; or if, unsure of yourselves, and not seeing clearly the nearly erased Constitution of your forefathers, you had looked to your neighbors in this land who had kept alive the old principles and models of Europe’s common law, improved and adapted to current conditions,—by following wise examples you would have set new examples of wisdom for the world. You would have made the cause of liberty respected by every honorable mind in every nation. You would have driven despotism from the Earth, showing that freedom is not only compatible but, when well-maintained, supportive of law. You would have had a fair but productive revenue. You would have had thriving commerce to sustain it. You would have had a liberal Constitution, a strong monarchy, a trained army, a reformed and respected clergy,—a tempered, but spirited nobility to guide your virtue, not overshadow it; you would have had a progressive order of commons to inspire and replenish that nobility; you would have had a protected, content, hardworking, and obedient populace, trained to seek and acknowledge the happiness found through virtue in all circumstances,—where true moral equality among humans resides, and not in that absurd notion that, by instilling false ideas and empty hopes into people destined for the humble path of hard work, only serves to heighten and worsen the real inequality that it can never eliminate, and which the structure of civil life establishes just as much for the benefit of those it must leave in a humble state as for those it can elevate to a more splendid but not necessarily happier condition. You had a smooth and easy path to happiness and glory laid out before you, beyond anything ever recorded in the history of the world; but you have shown that challenges are good for humanity.

Compute your gains; see what is got by those extravagant and presumptuous speculations which have taught your leaders to despise all their predecessors, and all their contemporaries, and even to despise themselves, until the moment in which they became truly despicable. By following those false lights, France has bought undisguised calamities at a higher price than any nation has purchased the most unequivocal blessings. France has bought poverty by crime. France has not sacrificed her virtue to her interest; but she has abandoned her interest, that she might prostitute her virtue. All other nations have begun the fabric of a new government, or the reformation of an old, by establishing originally, or by enforcing with greater exactness, some rites or other of religion. All other people have laid the foundations of civil freedom in severer manners, and a system of a more austere and masculine morality. France, when she let loose the reins of regal authority, doubled the license of a ferocious dissoluteness in manners, and of an insolent irreligion in opinions and practices,—and has extended through all ranks of life, as if she were communicating some privilege, or laying open some secluded benefit, all the unhappy corruptions that usually were the disease of wealth and power. This is one of the new principles of equality in France.

Calculate your losses; look at what comes from those reckless and arrogant speculations that have led your leaders to look down on all their predecessors, their contemporaries, and even themselves, until the point where they became truly contemptible. By chasing those false illusions, France has paid for clear disasters at a cost greater than any nation has paid for the most obvious blessings. France has purchased poverty through crime. France hasn't sacrificed her integrity for profit; instead, she has given up her interests to sell her integrity. Other nations have started creating a new government or reforming an old one by initially establishing or enforcing some form of religious practice more strictly. Other people have built the foundations of civil freedom in tougher ways and with a more disciplined and masculine morality. France, when it released the grip of royal power, intensified the license for a wild recklessness in behavior and a brazen irreligion in beliefs and actions,—and has spread through all levels of society, as if she were granting some privilege or revealing a hidden benefit, all the unfortunate corruptions that usually afflict wealth and power. This is one of the new principles of equality in France.

France, by the perfidy of her leaders, has utterly disgraced the tone of lenient council in the cabinets of princes, and disarmed it of its most potent topics. She has sanctified the dark, suspicious maxims of tyrannous distrust, and taught kings to tremble at (what will hereafter be called) the delusive plausibilities of moral politicians. Sovereigns will consider those who advise them to place an unlimited confidence in their people as subverters of their thrones,—as traitors who aim at their destruction, by leading their easy good-nature, under specious pretences, to admit combinations of bold and faithless men into a participation of their power. This alone (if there were nothing else) is an irreparable calamity to you and to mankind. Remember that your Parliament of Paris told your king, that, in calling the states together, he had nothing to fear but the prodigal excess of their zeal in providing for the support of the throne. It is right that these men should hide their heads. It is right that they should bear their part in the ruin which their counsel has brought on their sovereign and their country. Such sanguine declarations tend to lull authority asleep,—to encourage it rashly to engage in perilous adventures of untried policy,—to neglect those provisions, preparations, and precautions which distinguish benevolence from imbecility, and without which no man can answer for the salutary effect of any abstract plan of government or of freedom. For want of these, they have seen the medicine of the state corrupted into its poison. They have seen the French rebel against a mild and lawful monarch, with more fury, outrage, and insult than ever any people has been known to rise against the most illegal usurper or the most sanguinary tyrant. Their resistance was made to concession; their revolt was from protection; their blow was aimed at a hand holding out graces, favors, and immunities.

France, through the betrayal of its leaders, has completely tarnished the idea of lenient advice in royal councils and stripped it of its most powerful arguments. She has embraced the dark, suspicious principles of oppressive distrust and taught kings to fear what will later be called the misleading plausibility of moral politicians. Rulers will see those who advise them to trust their people unconditionally as threats to their power—traitors aiming to destroy them by exploiting their naive good nature and leading them to let untrustworthy individuals share in their authority. This alone is, if nothing else, an irreversible disaster for you and for humanity. Remember that your Parliament of Paris warned your king that, by convening the states, he had nothing to fear except their zealous excess in supporting the throne. It’s only fair that these men should hide away. It's just that they should share in the ruin their advice has caused for their sovereign and their country. Such overly optimistic statements serve to lull authority into complacency—encouraging it to recklessly embark on risky, untested policies—neglecting the measures, preparations, and precautions that separate genuine goodwill from incompetence, and without which no one can ensure the beneficial effect of any theoretical government or freedom. Because of this negligence, they have seen the remedy for the state turned into poison. They have witnessed the French rise up against a kind and lawful monarch with more fury, violence, and insult than any people has ever shown against the most illegal usurper or the bloodiest tyrant. Their resistance was aimed at concessions; their rebellion was against protection; their attack targeted a hand extending grace, favors, and immunity.

This was unnatural. The rest is in order. They have found their punishment in their success. Laws overturned; tribunals subverted; industry without vigor; commerce expiring; the revenue unpaid, yet the people impoverished; a church pillaged, and a state not relieved; civil and military anarchy made the constitution of the kingdom; everything human and divine sacrificed to the idol of public credit, and national bankruptcy the consequence; and, to crown all, the paper securities of new, precarious, tottering power, the discredited paper securities of impoverished fraud and beggared rapine, held out as a currency for the support of an empire, in lieu of the two great recognized species that represent the lasting, conventional credit of mankind, which disappeared and hid themselves in the earth from whence they came, when the principle of property, whose creatures and representatives they are, was systematically subverted.

This was unnatural. Everything else is in order. They've found their punishment in their success. Laws have been overturned; tribunals have been subverted; industry lacks energy; commerce is dying; the revenue is unpaid, yet the people are impoverished; a church has been plundered, and a state remains unreformed; civil and military chaos has become the constitution of the kingdom; everything human and divine has been sacrificed to the idol of public credit, leading to national bankruptcy; and, to top it all off, the paper securities of a new, unstable, shaky power, the discredited paper securities of impoverished fraud and destitute plunder, are being presented as a currency to support an empire, replacing the two main recognized forms that represent the lasting, conventional credit of humanity, which have disappeared and hidden themselves back in the ground where they came from, when the principle of property, whose products and representatives they are, was systematically undermined.

Were all these dreadful things necessary? Were they the inevitable results of the desperate struggle of determined patriots, compelled to wade through blood and tumult to the quiet shore of a tranquil and prosperous liberty? No! nothing like it. The fresh ruins of France, which shock our feelings wherever we can turn our eyes, are not the devastation of civil war: they are the sad, but instructive monuments of rash and ignorant counsel in time of profound peace. They are the display of inconsiderate and presumptuous, because unresisted and irresistible authority. The persons who have thus squandered away the precious treasure of their crimes, the persons who have made this prodigal and wild waste of public evils, (the last stake reserved for the ultimate ransom of the state,) have met in their progress with little, or rather with no opposition at all. Their whole march was more like a triumphal procession than the progress of a war. Their pioneers have gone before them, and demolished and laid everything level at their feet. Not one drop of their blood have they shed in the cause of the country they have ruined. They have made no sacrifices to their projects of greater consequence than their shoe-buckles, whilst they were imprisoning their king, murdering their fellow-citizens, and bathing in tears and plunging in poverty and distress thousands of worthy men and worthy families. Their cruelty has not even been the base result of fear. It has been the effect of their sense of perfect safety, in authorizing treasons, robberies, rapes, assassinations, slaughters, and burnings, throughout their harassed land. But the cause of all was plain from the beginning.

Were all these terrible things necessary? Were they the unavoidable outcomes of the desperate struggle of determined patriots, forced to wade through blood and chaos to reach the calm shore of peaceful and prosperous freedom? No! Nothing like it. The fresh ruins of France, which shock us wherever we look, are not the result of civil war; they are the sad but instructive monuments of rash and ignorant decisions made during a time of deep peace. They show inconsiderate and arrogant authority, which went unchallenged and was unstoppable. The people who have wasted the precious resources of their crimes, who have recklessly and wildly squandered public welfare (the last hope reserved for the ultimate salvation of the state), faced little to no opposition in their journey. Their entire march resembled a victory parade rather than the progress of a war. Their supporters went ahead of them, destroying and leveling everything in their way. Not one drop of their blood has been shed for the country they have destroyed. They haven't made any sacrifices for their plans more significant than their shoe-buckles while they were imprisoning their king, murdering their fellow citizens, and plunging thousands of deserving men and families into tears, poverty, and distress. Their cruelty has not even stemmed from fear; it has resulted from their sense of complete safety while permitting treason, robbery, rape, assassination, slaughter, and arson throughout their beleaguered land. But the cause of all this was clear from the start.


This unforced choice, this fond election of evil, would appear perfectly unaccountable, if we did not consider the composition of the National Assembly: I do not mean its formal constitution, which, as it now stands, is exceptionable enough, but the materials of which in a great measure it is composed, which is of ten thousand times greater consequence than all the formalities in the world. If we were to know nothing of this assembly but by its title and function, no colors could paint to the imagination anything more venerable. In that light, the mind of an inquirer, subdued by such an awful image as that of the virtue and wisdom of a whole people collected into one focus, would pause and hesitate in condemning things even of the very worst aspect. Instead of blamable, they would appear only mysterious. But no name, no power, no function, no artificial institution whatsoever, can make the men, of whom any system of authority is composed, any other than God, and Nature, and education, and their habits of life have made them. Capacities beyond these the people have not to give. Virtue and wisdom may be the objects of their choice; but their choice confers neither the one nor the other on those upon whom they lay their ordaining hands. They have not the engagement of Nature, they have not the promise of Revelation for any such powers.

This effortless choice, this deliberate selection of evil, would seem completely inexplicable if we didn’t take into account the makeup of the National Assembly: I’m not talking about its official structure, which is questionable enough as it is, but the people who make it up, which is far more important than any formalities. If we knew nothing about this assembly except its title and purpose, it would conjure up a sense of reverence. In that context, the mind of someone seeking answers, overwhelmed by such a powerful image of the virtue and wisdom of an entire people gathered in one place, would hesitate to condemn things even if they seemed very bad. Instead of being blameworthy, they would seem merely mysterious. But no title, no power, no official role, or any made-up institution can change the men who make up any system of authority. They are shaped by God, nature, education, and their life experiences. The people have no more to offer than these capabilities. Virtue and wisdom may be what they aspire to, but their choice does not bestow either one on those they choose to empower. They do not have the backing of nature, nor do they have the promise of revelation for any such powers.

After I had read over the list of the persons and descriptions elected into the Tiers État, nothing which they afterwards did could appear astonishing. Among them, indeed, I saw some of known rank, some of shining talents; but of any practical experience in the state not one man was to be found. The best were only men of theory. But whatever the distinguished few may have been, it is the substance and mass of the body which constitutes its character, and must finally determine its direction. In all bodies, those who will lead must also, in a considerable degree, follow. They must conform their propositions to the taste, talent, and disposition of those whom they wish to conduct: therefore, if an assembly is viciously or feebly composed in a very great part of it, nothing but such a supreme degree of virtue as very rarely appears in the world, and for that reason cannot enter into calculation, will prevent the men of talents disseminated through it from becoming only the expert instruments of absurd projects. If, what is the more likely event, instead of that unusual degree of virtue, they should be actuated by sinister ambition and a lust of meretricious glory, then the feeble part of the assembly, to whom at first they conform, becomes, in its turn, the dupe and instrument of their designs. In this political traffic, the leaders will be obliged to bow to the ignorance of their followers, and the followers to become subservient to the worst designs of their leaders.

After I read the list of people and their descriptions elected into the Tiers État, nothing they did afterward could surprise me. Among them, I saw some with notable status and impressive talents; however, there wasn’t a single person with practical experience in governance. The best were merely theoretical thinkers. Yet, regardless of how distinguished a few may be, it’s the overall composition of the group that defines its character and will ultimately shape its direction. In any group, those who lead must also, to a significant extent, follow. They need to tailor their ideas to the tastes, skills, and attitudes of those they aim to lead: therefore, if the assembly is largely made up of weak or flawed members, only an extraordinarily high level of virtue, which is very rare, could prevent the talented individuals within it from becoming mere tools of nonsensical plans. If, as is more likely, they are driven instead by selfish ambition and a desire for superficial glory, then the weaker members of the assembly, to whom they initially adjust, will become, in turn, the victims and tools of their schemes. In this political exchange, the leaders will have to bow to the ignorance of their followers, and the followers will end up serving the worst intentions of their leaders.

To secure any degree of sobriety in the propositions made by the leaders in any public assembly, they ought to respect, in some degree perhaps to fear, those whom they conduct. To be led any otherwise than blindly, the followers must be qualified, if not for actors, at least for judges; they must also be judges of natural weight and authority. Nothing can secure a steady and moderate conduct in such assemblies, but that the body of them should be respectably composed, in point of condition in life, of permanent property, of education, and of such habits as enlarge and liberalize the understanding.

To achieve any level of seriousness in the ideas presented by leaders in public gatherings, they should respect, if not somewhat fear, the people they lead. To follow effectively rather than blindly, the followers need to be qualified, if not as participants, at least as judges; they must also possess a sense of natural weight and authority. The only way to ensure steady and reasonable behavior in such gatherings is for the group to be made up of individuals of respectable status in terms of life condition, lasting wealth, education, and habits that broaden and elevate understanding.

In the calling of the States-General of France, the first thing that struck me was a great departure from the ancient course. I found the representation for the third estate composed of six hundred persons. They were equal in number to the representatives of both the other orders. If the orders were to act separately, the number would not, beyond the consideration of the expense, be of much moment. But when it became apparent that the three orders were to be melted down into one, the policy and necessary effect of this numerous representation became obvious. A very small desertion from either of the other two orders must throw the power of both into the hands of the third. In fact, the whole power of the state was soon resolved into that body. Its due composition became, therefore, of infinitely the greater importance.

In calling the States-General of France, the first thing that stood out to me was a significant break from tradition. I saw that the representation for the third estate was made up of six hundred people. They matched the number of representatives from the other two estates combined. If the estates were to act separately, the number wouldn't matter much aside from the cost. But when it became clear that the three estates were going to come together as one, the strategy and necessary impact of such a large representation became clear. Even a small departure from either of the other two estates could shift power entirely to the third. In fact, the entire power of the state quickly consolidated within that group. Thus, its proper makeup became even more crucial.

Judge, Sir, of my surprise, when I found that a very great proportion of the Assembly (a majority, I believe, of the members who attended) was composed of practitioners in the law. It was composed, not of distinguished magistrates, who had given pledges to their country of their science, prudence, and integrity,—not of leading advocates, the glory of the bar,—not of renowned professors in universities,—but for the far greater part, as it must in such a number, of the inferior, unlearned, mechanical, merely instrumental members of the profession. There were distinguished exceptions; but the general composition was of obscure provincial advocates, of stewards of petty local jurisdictions, country attorneys, notaries, and the whole train of the ministers of municipal litigation, the fomenters and conductors of the petty war of village vexation. From the moment I read the list, I saw distinctly, and very nearly as it has happened, all that was to follow.

Judge, Sir, I was very surprised to see that a large portion of the Assembly (a majority, I believe, of the attending members) was made up of lawyers. It was not filled with distinguished judges, who have proven their expertise, wisdom, and integrity to their country—not with leading advocates, the pride of the bar—not with renowned university professors—but mostly, as is often the case in large groups, by the lesser, untrained, mechanical, merely functional members of the profession. There were notable exceptions; however, the majority were obscure local advocates, stewards of small local jurisdictions, country lawyers, notaries, and the entire group of those involved in municipal disputes, the instigators and managers of the minor conflicts of village grievances. From the moment I read the list, I could clearly see, almost exactly as it happened, everything that would follow.

The degree of estimation in which any profession is held becomes the standard of the estimation in which the professors hold themselves. Whatever the personal merits of many individual lawyers might have been, (and in many it was undoubtedly very considerable,) in that military kingdom no part of the profession had been much regarded, except the highest of all, who often united to their professional offices great family splendor, and were invested with great power and authority. These certainly were highly respected, and even with no small degree of awe. The next rank was not much esteemed; the mechanical part was in a very low degree of repute.

The level of respect given to any profession sets the standard for how its professionals view themselves. While many individual lawyers may have had notable personal qualities (and many certainly did), in that military society, the profession wasn't highly regarded overall, except for the top tier, who often combined their professional roles with significant family prestige and held substantial power and authority. These individuals were certainly very respected and even approached with a certain level of awe. The next tier wasn't held in much esteem; the practical side of the profession was considered to have very little regard.

Whenever the supreme authority is vested in a body so composed, it must evidently produce the consequences of supreme authority placed in the hands of men not taught habitually to respect themselves,—who had no previous fortune in character at stake,—who could not be expected to bear with moderation or to conduct with discretion a power which they themselves, more than any others, must be surprised to find in their hands. Who could flatter himself that these men, suddenly, and as it were by enchantment, snatched from the humblest rank of subordination, would not be intoxicated with their unprepared greatness? Who could conceive that men who are habitually meddling, daring, subtle, active, of litigious dispositions and unquiet minds, would easily fall back into their old condition of obscure contention, and laborious, low, and unprofitable chicane? Who could doubt but that, at any expense to the state, of which they understood nothing, they must pursue their private interests, which they understood but too well? It was not an event depending on chance or contingency. It was inevitable; it was necessary; it was planted in the nature of things. They must join (if their capacity did not permit them to lead) in any project which could procure to them a litigious constitution,—which could lay open to them those innumerable lucrative jobs which follow in the train of all great convulsions and revolutions in the state, and particularly in all great and violent permutations of property. Was it to be expected that they would attend to the stability of property, whose existence had always depended upon whatever rendered property questionable, ambiguous, and insecure? Their objects would be enlarged with their elevation; but their disposition, and habits, and mode of accomplishing their designs must remain the same.

Whenever the highest authority is given to a group like this, it clearly leads to the outcomes of supreme power being in the hands of people who don't typically respect themselves—who had no previous reputation to protect—who can't be expected to handle their newfound power with restraint or make wise decisions, especially since they must be just as surprised to find themselves in this position. Who could think that these individuals, suddenly and almost magically pulled from the lowest ranks of subordination, wouldn't be overwhelmed by their unexpected status? Who could imagine that people who are typically intrusive, bold, cunning, active, litigious, and restless would easily revert to their old state of obscure conflict and tedious, petty maneuvering? Who could doubt that, regardless of the cost to the state, about which they knew nothing, they would relentlessly pursue their personal interests, which they understood all too well? This was not a random or chance event. It was unavoidable; it was essential; it was part of the nature of things. They must join (if they weren't capable of leading) in any initiative that could grant them a litigious structure— that could open up for them the countless profitable opportunities that often arise during significant upheavals and revolutions in the state, especially in times of great and violent shifts in property. Was it reasonable to expect that they would care about the stability of property, whose existence had always depended on whatever made property uncertain, vague, and unsafe? Their goals would expand with their rise to power; however, their tendencies, habits, and methods for achieving their ambitions would remain unchanged.

Well! but these men were to be tempered and restrained by other descriptions, of more sober minds and more enlarged understandings. Were they, then, to be awed by the supereminent authority and awful dignity of a handful of country clowns, who have seats in that assembly, some of whom are said not to be able to read and write,—and by not a greater number of traders, who, though somewhat more instructed, and more conspicuous in the order of society, had never known anything beyond their counting-house? No! both these descriptions were more formed to be overborne and swayed by the intrigues and artifices of lawyers than to become their counterpoise. With such a dangerous disproportion, the whole must needs be governed by them.

Well! But these men needed to be balanced and controlled by others who had more sober minds and broader understandings. Were they really supposed to be intimidated by the impressive authority and serious dignity of a few country bumpkins who sit in that assembly, some of whom reportedly can’t read or write, and by even fewer traders who, while slightly better educated and more prominent in society, had never experienced anything beyond their own businesses? No! Both of these groups were more likely to be overwhelmed and manipulated by the schemes and tricks of lawyers than to stand as a balance against them. With such a dangerous imbalance, everything was bound to be controlled by those lawyers.

To the faculty of law was joined a pretty considerable proportion of the faculty of medicine. This faculty had not, any more than that of the law, possessed in France its just estimation. Its professors, therefore, must have the qualities of men not habituated to sentiments of dignity. But supposing they had ranked as they ought to do, and as with us they do actually, the sides of sick-beds are not the academies for forming statesmen and legislators. Then came the dealers in stocks and funds, who must be eager, at any expense, to change their ideal paper wealth for the more solid substance of land. To these were joined men of other descriptions, from whom as little knowledge of or attention to the interests of a great state was to be expected, and as little regard to the stability of any institution,—men formed to be instruments, not controls.—Such, in general, was the composition of the Tiers État in the National Assembly; in which was scarcely to be perceived the slightest traces of what we call the natural landed interest of the country.

To the law faculty was added a significant portion of the medical faculty. This faculty, much like the law faculty, had not been properly valued in France. As a result, its professors lacked the qualities typical of people accustomed to feelings of dignity. However, if they had been regarded as they should be, like they actually are with us, the people at the bedsides of the sick were not the right places for training statesmen and lawmakers. Next came the investors in stocks and bonds, who were eager to convert their theoretical paper wealth into tangible land, no matter the cost. They were joined by individuals from from whom little knowledge or concern for the interests of a large state could be expected, and just as little regard for the stability of any institution—people shaped to be tools, not decision-makers. This, in general, was the makeup of the Tiers État in the National Assembly, where barely a hint of what we refer to as the natural landed interest of the country could be found.

We know that the British House of Commons, without shutting its doors to any merit in any class, is, by the sure operation of adequate causes, filled with everything illustrious in rank, in descent, in hereditary and in acquired opulence, in cultivated talents, in military, civil, naval, and politic distinction, that the country can afford. But supposing, what hardly can be supposed as a case, that the House of Commons should be composed in the same manner with the Tiers État in France,—would this dominion of chicane be borne with patience, or even conceived without horror? God forbid I should insinuate anything derogatory to that profession which is another priesthood, administering the rights of sacred justice! But whilst I revere men in the functions which belong to them, and would do as much as one man can do to prevent their exclusion from any, I cannot, to flatter them, give the lie to Nature. They are good and useful in the composition; they must be mischievous, if they preponderate so as virtually to become the whole. Their very excellence in their peculiar functions may be far from a qualification for others. It cannot escape observation, that, when men are too much confined to professional and faculty habits, and, as it were, inveterate in the recurrent employment of that narrow circle, they are rather disabled than qualified for whatever depends on the knowledge of mankind, on experience in mixed affairs, on a comprehensive, connected view of the various, complicated, external, and internal interests which go to the formation of that multifarious thing called a State.

We know that the British House of Commons, while open to merit from all classes, is naturally filled with everything distinguished in rank, heritage, wealth, education, and achievements in military, civil, naval, and political arenas that the country has to offer. But if, hypothetically, the House of Commons were made up like the Tiers État in France—would this dominance of trickery be tolerated calmly or even imagined without horror? God forbid I should imply anything negative about that profession, which is like a priesthood, administering the rights of sacred justice! While I respect the men in their roles and would do everything I can to ensure they aren't excluded from any position, I can't, to flatter them, deny the reality. They play an important and beneficial role in the assembly; however, they could become harmful if they dominate to the point of being the whole. Their expertise in their specific roles may not qualify them for others. It's hard to ignore that when people are too confined to professional and specialized habits, becoming set in their limited roles, they are actually more disabled than qualified in matters that require understanding of human nature, experience in diverse situations, and a broad, connected view of the many, complicated interests—both external and internal—that contribute to what we call a State.

After all, if the House of Commons were to have an wholly professional and faculty composition, what is the power of the House of Commons, circumscribed and shut in by the immovable barriers of laws, usages, positive rules of doctrine and practice, counterpoised by the House of Lords, and every moment of its existence at the discretion of the crown to continue, prorogue, or dissolve us? The power of the House of Commons, direct or indirect, is, indeed, great: and long may it be able to preserve its greatness, and the spirit belonging to true greatness, at the full!—and it will do so, as long as it can keep the breakers of law in India from becoming the makers of law for England. The power, however, of the House of Commons, when least diminished, is as a drop of water in the ocean, compared to that residing in a settled majority of your National Assembly. That assembly, since the destruction of the orders, has no fundamental law, no strict convention, no respected usage to restrain it. Instead of finding themselves obliged to conform to a fixed constitution, they have a power to make a constitution which shall conform to their designs. Nothing in heaven or upon earth can serve as a control on them. What ought to be the heads, the hearts, the dispositions, that are qualified, or that dare, not only to make laws under a fixed constitution, but at one heat to strike out a totally new constitution for a great kingdom, and in every part of it, from the monarch on the throne to the vestry of a parish? But

After all, if the House of Commons were to be made up entirely of professionals and academics, what power would it hold, restricted by the unchangeable boundaries of laws, customs, established rules of doctrine and practice, balanced against the House of Lords, and with its very existence dependent on the crown's choice to continue, suspend, or dissolve it? The power of the House of Commons, whether direct or indirect, is indeed considerable; may it long continue to maintain its significance and the essence of true greatness!—and it will, as long as it can prevent lawbreakers in India from becoming lawmakers for England. However, the power of the House of Commons, even at its strongest, is like a drop in the ocean when compared to that of a stable majority in your National Assembly. That assembly, since the orders were destroyed, has no fundamental law, no strict conventions, no respected customs to limit it. Rather than being required to stick to a set constitution, they have the ability to create a constitution that fits their goals. Nothing in heaven or on earth can restrict them. What should the leaders, the hearts, the attitudes be, that are capable of not just making laws under a fixed constitution, but also boldly drafting an entirely new constitution for a major kingdom, affecting every level of it, from the monarch on the throne to the church council of a parish? But

"Only fools rush into situations that even the wise avoid."

In such a state of unbounded power, for undefined and undefinable purposes, the evil of a moral and almost physical inaptitude of the man to the function must be the greatest we can conceive to happen in the management of human affairs.

In a situation of unlimited power, without clear or definable goals, the greatest evil we can imagine in managing human affairs is the moral and almost physical inability of a person to fulfill their role.

Having considered the composition of the third estate, as it stood in its original frame, I took a view of the representatives of the clergy. There, too, it appeared that full as little regard was had to the general security of property, or to the aptitude of the deputies for their public purposes, in the principles of their election. That election was so contrived as to send a very large proportion of mere country curates to the great and arduous work of new-modelling a state: men who never had seen the state so much as in a picture; men who knew nothing of the world beyond the bounds of an obscure village; who, immersed in hopeless poverty, could regard all property, whether secular or ecclesiastical, with no other eye than that of envy; among whom must be many who, for the smallest hope of the meanest dividend in plunder, would readily join in any attempts upon a body of wealth in which they could hardly look to have any share, except in a general scramble. Instead of balancing the power of the active chicaners in the other assembly, these curates must necessarily become the active coadjutors, or at best the passive instruments, of those by whom they had been habitually guided in their petty village concerns. They, too, could hardly be the most conscientious of their kind, who, presuming upon their incompetent understanding, could intrigue for a trust which led them from their natural relation to their flocks, and their natural spheres of action, to undertake the regeneration of kingdoms. This preponderating weight, being added to the force of the body of chicane in the Tiers État, completed that momentum of ignorance, rashness, presumption, and lust of plunder, which nothing has been able to resist.

Having looked at the makeup of the third estate, as it was originally structured, I examined the representatives of the clergy. Here, too, it seemed that there was just as little consideration for the overall security of property or for the suitability of the deputies for their public roles in the principles of their election. That election was designed to send a large number of mere country curates to the challenging task of reshaping a state: men who had never seen the state even in a picture; men who knew nothing of the world beyond their small, obscure villages; who, trapped in hopeless poverty, viewed all property, whether secular or religious, with nothing but envy; among whom were likely many who, for the slightest chance at the smallest share of plunder, would eagerly join any efforts against a body of wealth that they could hardly hope to access, except in a general scramble. Instead of balancing the power of the active schemers in the other assembly, these curates would inevitably become active helpers or, at best, passive tools for those who had repeatedly guided them in their trivial village matters. They were hardly the most principled among their kind, who, assuming their inadequate understanding, could scheme for a position that took them away from their natural role with their flocks and their usual responsibilities, to tackle the regeneration of kingdoms. This dominating force, added to the weight of the scheming group in the Tiers État, completed that momentum of ignorance, recklessness, arrogance, and greed for plunder that nothing has managed to resist.

To observing men it must have appeared from the beginning, that the majority of the third estate, in conjunction with such a deputation from the clergy as I have described, whilst it pursued the destruction of the nobility, would inevitably become subservient to the worst designs of individuals in that class. In the spoil and humiliation of their own order these individuals would possess a sure fund for the pay of their new followers. To squander away the objects which made the happiness of their fellows would be to them no sacrifice at all. Turbulent, discontented men of quality, in proportion as they are puffed up with personal pride and arrogance, generally despise their own order. One of the first symptoms they discover of a selfish and mischievous ambition is a profligate disregard of a dignity which they partake with others. To be attached to the subdivision, to love the little platoon we belong to in society, is the first principle (the germ, as it were) of public affections. It is the first link in the series by which we proceed towards a love to our country and to mankind. The interest of that portion of social arrangement is a trust in the hands of all those who compose it; and as none but bad men would justify it in abuse, none but traitors would barter it away for their own personal advantage.

To observers, it must have been clear from the start that most of the third estate, along with the clergy I mentioned, while trying to dismantle the nobility, would inevitably fall under the influence of the most reckless individuals from that class. In the ruin and humiliation of their own group, these individuals would have a guaranteed source of funding for their new followers. Wasting the things that brought happiness to their peers would mean nothing to them. Turbulent, dissatisfied nobles, as they swell with personal pride and arrogance, generally look down on their own class. One of the first signs of their selfish and harmful ambition is a blatant disregard for a dignity they share with others. Being attached to our community and loving the small group we belong to in society is the foundation of public affection. It’s the first link in the chain that leads to a love for our country and humanity. The interests of that part of society are a responsibility shared by everyone in it; and since only bad people would justify abusing it, only traitors would sell it out for personal gain.

There were, in the time of our civil troubles in England, (I do not know whether you have any such in your Assembly in France,) several persons, like the then Earl of Holland, who by themselves or their families had brought an odium on the throne by the prodigal dispensation of its bounties towards them, who afterwards joined in the rebellions arising from the discontents of which they were themselves the cause: men who helped to subvert that throne to which they owed, some of them, their existence, others all that power which they employed to ruin their benefactor. If any bounds are set to the rapacious demands of that sort of people, or that others are permitted to partake in the objects they would engross, revenge and envy soon fill up the craving void that is left in their avarice. Confounded by the complication of distempered passions, their reason is disturbed; their views become vast and perplexed,—to others inexplicable, to themselves uncertain. They find, on all sides, bounds to their unprincipled ambition in any fixed order of things; but in the fog and haze of confusion all is enlarged, and appears without any limit.

During the period of our civil unrest in England, (I'm not sure if you have anything similar in your Assembly in France,) there were several individuals, like the then Earl of Holland, who brought shame upon the throne—either by themselves or through their families—due to the excessive generosity of the crown towards them. Later, these same individuals participated in the rebellions that arose from the grievances they had caused themselves: men who helped undermine the throne that had provided them with their livelihoods and the power they used to betray their benefactor. If there are any limits placed on the greedy demands of these types of people, or if others are allowed to share in what they want to keep for themselves, revenge and jealousy quickly fill the gap left by their greed. Overwhelmed by a mix of uncontrolled emotions, their reasoning falters; their ambitions become vast and confusing—incomprehensible to others and uncertain to themselves. They find, on every side, obstacles to their unprincipled desires in any established order, but in the fog and haze of confusion, everything appears expanded and limitless.

When men of rank sacrifice all ideas of dignity to an ambition without a distinct object, and work with low instruments and for low ends, the whole composition becomes low and base. Does not something like this now appear in France? Does it not produce something ignoble and inglorious: a kind of meanness in all the prevalent policy; a tendency in all that is done to lower along with individuals all the dignity and importance of the state? Other revolutions have been conducted by persons who, whilst they attempted or affected changes in the commonwealth, sanctified their ambition by advancing the dignity of the people whose peace they troubled. They had long views. They aimed at the rule, not at the destruction of their country. They were men of great civil and great military talents, and if the terror, the ornament of their age. They were not like Jew brokers contending with each other who could best remedy with fraudulent circulation and depreciated paper the wretchedness and ruin brought on their country by their degenerate councils. The compliment made to one of the great bad men of the old stamp (Cromwell) by his kinsman, a favorite poet of that time, shows what it was he proposed, and what indeed to a great degree he accomplished in the success of his ambition:—

When influential people abandon their sense of dignity for an ambition that lacks a clear goal, and engage in basic tasks for trivial purposes, it brings the entire situation down to a low and shameful level. Doesn't this seem to be happening in France now? Doesn't it lead to something disgraceful and dishonorable: a kind of pettiness in the ruling policies; a tendency for everything done to diminish the dignity and significance of the state along with the individuals? Other revolutions were led by people who, while they sought or pretended to make changes in the society, sanctified their ambitions by elevating the dignity of the people whose peace they disrupted. They had long-term visions. They aimed at governance, not at the destruction of their country. They were individuals with remarkable civil and military skills, and if terror was an ornament of their time, they were not like moneylenders squabbling over who could better fix the misery and devastation caused by their corrupt leadership with deceitful practices and worthless currency. The praise given to one of the notorious figures of the past (Cromwell) by his relative, a popular poet of that era, illustrates what he intended to achieve and what he largely fulfilled in his rise to power:—

"Still as you rise, the state, exalted too," Finds no trouble while it's changed by you;
Changed like the world's grand stage, when it's without sound. The rising sun's vulgar lights destroy.

These disturbers were not so much like men usurping power as asserting their natural place in society. Their rising was to illuminate and beautify the world. Their conquest over their competitors was by outshining them. The hand, that, like a destroying angel, smote the country, communicated to it the force and energy under which it suffered. I do not say, (God forbid!) I do not say that the virtues of such men were to be taken as a balance to their crimes; but they were some corrective to their effects. Such was, as I said, our Cromwell. Such were your whole race of Guises, Condés, and Colignys. Such the Richelieus, who in more quiet times acted in the spirit of a civil war. Such, as better men, and in a less dubious cause, were your Henry the Fourth, and your Sully, though nursed in civil confusions, and not wholly without some of their taint. It is a thing to be wondered at, to see how very soon France, when she had a moment to respire, recovered and emerged from the longest and most dreadful civil war that ever was known in any nation. Why? Because, among all their massacres, they had not slain the mind in their country. A conscious dignity, a noble pride, a generous sense of glory and emulation, was not extinguished. On the contrary, it was kindled and inflamed. The organs also of the state, however shattered, existed. All the prizes of honor and virtue, all the rewards, all the distinctions, remained. But your present confusion, like a palsy, has attacked the fountain of life itself. Every person in your country, in a situation to be actuated by a principle of honor, is disgraced and degraded, and can entertain no sensation of life, except in a mortified and humiliated indignation. But this generation will quickly pass away. The next generation of the nobility will resemble the artificers and clowns, and money-jobbers, usurers, and Jews, who will be always their fellows, sometimes their masters. Believe me, Sir, those who attempt to level never equalize. In all societies consisting of various descriptions of citizens, some description must be uppermost. The levellers, therefore, only change and pervert the natural order of things: they load the edifice of society by setting up in the air what the solidity of the structure requires to be on the ground. The associations of tailors and carpenters, of which the republic (of Paris, for instance) is composed, cannot be equal to the situation into which, by the worst of usurpations, an usurpation on the prerogatives of Nature, you attempt to force them.

These disruptors weren't so much like people seizing power as they were claiming their rightful place in society. Their rise was meant to illuminate and enhance the world. Their victory over their rivals came from outshining them. The hand that struck the country like a destructive angel brought with it the force and energy that caused its suffering. I'm not saying, (God forbid!) I'm not saying that the qualities of such people should balance out their wrongdoings; but they did provide some correction to their impacts. Such was, as I mentioned, our Cromwell. Such were your entire line of Guises, Condés, and Colignys. Such were the Richelieus, who acted in a civil war spirit during more peaceful times. Such, as better individuals, and for a less questionable cause, were your Henry the Fourth and your Sully, even though they were raised in civil turmoil and carried some of its stains. It's remarkable to see how quickly France, when given a chance to breathe, recovered and emerged from the longest and most terrible civil war ever seen in any nation. Why? Because, amid all the massacres, they hadn't killed the spirit of their country. A sense of dignity, noble pride, and a generous feeling of glory and competition were not extinguished. On the contrary, they were ignited and intensified. The structures of the state, however battered, still existed. All the honors and virtues, all the rewards and distinctions, remained intact. But your current chaos, like a debilitating illness, has attacked the very source of life itself. Everyone in your country who could be driven by a sense of honor is disgraced and degraded, experiencing only a sense of life through mortified and humiliated anger. But this generation will soon fade away. The next generation of nobles will resemble craftsmen and commoners, along with moneylenders, usurers, and Jews, who will always be their companions, sometimes their superiors. Believe me, Sir, those who try to bring everyone down to the same level never truly equalize. In all societies made up of various types of citizens, one type must be dominant. The levellers, therefore, only change and distort the natural order of things: they burden society by placing what should be grounded in the air. The associations of tailors and carpenters, from which the republic (of Paris, for instance) is formed, cannot match the situation into which, through the worst kind of usurpation, an assault on the rights of Nature, you are trying to push them.

The Chancellor of France, at the opening of the States, said, in a tone of oratorial flourish, that all occupations were honorable. If he meant only that no honest employment was disgraceful, he would not have gone beyond the truth. But in asserting that anything is honorable, we imply some distinction in its favor. The occupation of a hair-dresser, or of a working tallow-chandler, cannot be a matter of honor to any person,—to say nothing of a number of other more servile employments. Such descriptions of men ought not to suffer oppression from the state; but the state suffers oppression, if such as they, either individually or collectively, are permitted to rule. In this you think you are combating prejudice, but you are at war with Nature.[86]

The Chancellor of France, at the start of the States, said in a grandiloquent tone that all jobs are honorable. If he meant only that no honest work is shameful, he would be telling the truth. But by claiming that anything is honorable, we imply it has some merit. The job of a hairdresser or a working tallow-chandler can't be seen as honorable by anyone—not to mention many other more menial jobs. People in such positions shouldn’t be oppressed by the state; however, the state faces oppression if people like them, individually or collectively, are allowed to govern. In this, you think you're fighting against prejudice, but you are at odds with Nature.[86]

I do not, my dear Sir, conceive you to be of that sophistical, captious spirit, or of that uncandid dullness, as to require, for every general observation or sentiment, an explicit detail of the correctives and exceptions which reason will presume to be included in all the general propositions which come from reasonable men. You do not imagine that I wish to confine power, authority, and distinction to blood and names and titles. No, Sir. There is no qualification for government but virtue and wisdom, actual or presumptive. Wherever they are actually found, they have, in whatever state, condition, profession, or trade, the passport of Heaven to human place and honor. Woe to the country which would madly and impiously reject the service of the talents and virtues, civil, military, or religious, that are given to grace and to serve it; and would condemn to obscurity everything formed to diffuse lustre and glory around a state! Woe to that country, too, that, passing into the opposite extreme, considers a low education, a mean, contracted view of things, a sordid, mercenary occupation, as a preferable title to command! Everything ought to be open,—but not indifferently to every man. No rotation, no appointment by lot, no mode of election operating in the spirit of sortition or rotation, can be generally good in a government conversant in extensive objects; because they have no tendency, direct or indirect, to select the man with a view to the duty, or to accommodate the one to the other. I do not hesitate to say that the road to eminence and power, from obscure condition, ought not to be made too easy, nor a thing too much of course. If rare merit be the rarest of all rare things, it ought to pass through some sort of probation. The temple of honor ought to be seated on an eminence. If it be opened through virtue, let it be remembered, too, that virtue is never tried but by some difficulty and some struggle.

I don’t believe, my dear Sir, that you’re the kind of person who would require specific details about every general observation or sentiment, expecting to see all the qualifications and exceptions that reason would typically include. You surely don’t think that I want to limit power, authority, and status to just aristocracy, names, and titles. No, Sir. The only qualifications for leadership should be virtue and wisdom, either actual or presumed. Wherever these qualities are genuinely found, no matter the state, condition, profession, or trade, they have the blessing of Heaven for a place of honor among people. Woe to the nation that foolishly and irreverently dismisses the contributions of talent and virtue—whether civil, military, or religious—that are meant to enrich and serve it, and that would condemn anything capable of bringing light and glory to its society to obscurity! Woe to that nation, too, that swings too far the other way, seeing low education, a limited perspective, or a selfish, profit-driven career as a better justification for authority! Everything should be accessible, but not equally for everyone. No rotations, random selections, or elected positions based purely on chance can be generally effective in a government that deals with broad issues; because they don’t truly aim to select the right person for the job or align the individual with the role. I firmly believe that the path to prominence and power, especially from humble beginnings, shouldn’t be too easy, nor should it be taken for granted. Since genuine merit is incredibly rare, it should undergo some form of testing. The temple of honor should be situated on high ground. If it is opened through virtue, it should be noted that virtue is only proven through challenges and struggles.

Nothing is a due and adequate representation of a state, that does not represent its ability, as well as its property. But as ability is a vigorous and active principle, and as property is sluggish, inert, and timid, it never can be safe from the invasions of ability, unless it be, out of all proportion, predominant in the representation. It must be represented, too, in great masses of accumulation, or it is not rightly protected. The characteristic essence of property, formed out of the combined principles of its acquisition and conservation, is to be unequal. The great masses, therefore, which excite envy, and tempt rapacity, must be put out of the possibility of danger. Then they form a natural rampart about the lesser properties in all their gradations. The same quantity of property which is by the natural course of things divided among many has not the same operation. Its defensive power is weakened as it is diffused. In this diffusion each man's portion is less than what, in the eagerness of his desires, he may flatter himself to obtain by dissipating the accumulations of others. The plunder of the few would, indeed, give but a share inconceivably small in the distribution to the many. But the many are not capable of making this calculation; and those who lead them to rapine never intend this distribution.

Nothing accurately represents a state if it doesn’t reflect both its capabilities and its property. However, since ability is dynamic and active, while property is slow, passive, and cautious, property will never be safe from being overrun by ability unless it is overwhelmingly dominant in representation. It also needs to be represented in large quantities; otherwise, it won’t be properly safeguarded. The fundamental nature of property, shaped by its methods of acquisition and preservation, is to be unequal. Therefore, large amounts that provoke jealousy and invite greed must be secured from any threats. They create a natural barrier for the smaller properties in all their various levels. The same amount of property that is distributed among many behaves differently. Its defensive strength diminishes as it spreads out. In this spread, each person's share is smaller than what they might hope to gain by taking from the resources of others. The plundering of a few would, in reality, result in an impossibly small share for the many. Yet, the many are not able to make this calculation, and those who incite them to theft never plan for that distribution.

The power of perpetuating our property in our families is one of the most valuable and interesting circumstances belonging to it, and that which tends the most to the perpetuation of society itself. It makes our weakness subservient to our virtue; it grafts benevolence even upon avarice. The possessors of family wealth, and of the distinction which attends hereditary possession, (as most concerned in it,) are the natural securities for this transmission. With us the House of Peers is formed upon this principle. It is wholly composed of hereditary property and hereditary distinction, and made, therefore, the third of the legislature, and, in the last event, the sole judge of all property in all its subdivisions. The House of Commons, too, though not necessarily, yet in fact, is always so composed, in the far greater part. Let those large proprietors be what they will, (and they have their chance of being amongst the best,) they are, at the very worst, the ballast in the vessel of the commonwealth. For though hereditary wealth, and the rank which goes with it, are too much idolized by creeping sycophants, and the blind, abject admirers of power, they are too rashly slighted in shallow speculations of the petulant, assuming, short-sighted coxcombs of philosophy. Some decent, regulated preëminence, some preference (not exclusive appropriation) given to birth, is neither unnatural, nor unjust, nor impolitic.

The ability to pass down our property within our families is one of the most valuable and interesting aspects of it, and it's what helps sustain society itself. It turns our weaknesses into strengths; it even connects generosity to greed. Those who hold family wealth and the status that comes with inherited property are the natural guardians of this transfer. In our system, the House of Peers is based on this idea. It's entirely made up of hereditary property and inherited status, making it the third part of our legislature and, ultimately, the sole authority on all property in its various forms. The House of Commons, too, although not exclusively, is mostly composed in this way. Regardless of who the large landowners are (and they might have the chance to be among the best), at the very least, they're the stabilizing force in the commonwealth. While hereditary wealth and the associated rank are often too heavily idolized by ingratiating sycophants and blind followers of power, they are also too often dismissed by the superficial, arrogant, and shortsighted critics of philosophy. Some level of respectable, regulated superiority and some preference given to birth (not total ownership) is neither unnatural nor unfair, nor is it bad policy.

It is said that twenty-four millions ought to prevail over two hundred thousand. True; if the constitution of a kingdom be a problem of arithmetic. This sort of discourse does well enough with the lamp-post for its second: to men who may reason calmly it is ridiculous The will of the many, and their interest, must very often differ; and great will be the difference when they make an evil choice. A government of five hundred country attorneys and obscure curates is not good for twenty-four millions of men, though it were chosen by eight-and-forty millions; nor is it the better for being guided by a dozen of persons of quality who have betrayed their trust in order to obtain that power. At present, you seem in everything to have strayed out of the high road of Nature. The property of France does not govern it. Of course property is destroyed, and rational liberty has no existence. All you have got for the present is a paper circulation, and a stock-jobbing constitution: and as to the future, do you seriously think that the territory of France, upon the republican system of eighty-three independent municipalities, (to say nothing of the parts that compose them,) can ever be governed as one body, or can ever be set in motion by the impulse of one mind? When the National Assembly has completed its work, it will have accomplished its ruin. These commonwealths will not long bear a state of subjection to the republic of Paris. They will not bear that this one body should monopolize the captivity of the king, and the dominion over the assembly calling itself national. Each will keep its own portion of the spoil of the Church to itself; and it will not suffer either that spoil, or the more just fruits of their industry, or the natural produce of their soil, to be sent to swell the insolence or pamper the luxury of the mechanics of Paris. In this they will see none of the equality, under the pretence of which they have been tempted to throw off their allegiance to their sovereign, as well as the ancient constitution of their country. There can be no capital city in such a constitution as they have lately made. They have forgot, that, when they framed democratic governments, they had virtually dismembered their country. The person whom they persevere in calling king has not power left to him by the hundredth part sufficient to hold together this collection of republics. The republic of Paris will endeavor, indeed, to complete the debauchery of the army, and illegally to perpetuate the Assembly, without resort to its constituents, as the means of continuing its despotism. It will make efforts, by becoming the heart of a boundless paper circulation, to draw everything to itself: but in vain. All this policy in the end will appear as feeble as it is now violent.

It’s said that twenty-four million should outnumber two hundred thousand. That’s true, if governing a kingdom is just a math problem. This kind of talk sounds good when you're under a lamp-post. For people who can think clearly, it’s absurd. The will and interests of the majority often clash, and the gap will be huge when they make a bad choice. A government made up of five hundred country lawyers and unknown clergy isn’t suited for twenty-four million people, even if it was elected by forty-eight million. It doesn’t get any better if it’s run by a handful of nobles who have betrayed their duty to gain that power. Right now, it seems like you’ve completely lost your way from natural order. The property of France doesn’t govern it. Naturally, property is being destroyed, and true liberty doesn’t exist. All you have now is a paper currency and a stock-jobbing constitution. As for the future, do you really believe that France, organized as eighty-three independent municipalities (not counting the parts that make them up), can ever be governed as a single entity or act in unison? When the National Assembly finishes its work, it’ll only lead to its own downfall. These municipalities won’t tolerate being controlled by the Paris republic for long. They won’t accept a single body holding the king captive and dominating the assembly that calls itself national. Each will keep its share of the Church's spoils to itself, and they won’t allow either that property or the rightful earnings from their work, or the natural resources from their land, to support the arrogance or luxury of the workers in Paris. They won’t see any of the equality they were promised when they were urged to abandon their loyalty to their king and the old constitution of their country. There can’t be a capital city under the type of constitution they’ve recently created. They have forgotten that by forming democratic governments, they have essentially broken their country apart. The person they still insist on calling a king doesn’t have nearly enough power to hold this collection of republics together. The Paris republic will indeed try to corrupt the army further and illegally sustain the Assembly without consulting its constituents as a way to maintain its tyranny. It will attempt to become the center of a limitless paper currency to draw everything to itself, but it will all be in vain. In the end, this strategy will prove as weak as it is now aggressive.


If this be your actual situation, compared to the situation to which you were called, as it were by the voice of God and man, I cannot find it in my heart to congratulate you on the choice you have made, or the success which has attended your endeavors. I can as little recommend to any other nation a conduct grounded on such principles and productive of such effects. That I must leave to those who can see further into your affairs than I am able to do, and who best know how far your actions are favorable to their designs. The gentlemen of the Revolution Society, who were so early in their congratulations, appear to be strongly of opinion that there is some scheme of politics relative to this country, in which your proceedings may in some way be useful. For your Dr. Price, who seems to have speculated himself into no small degree of fervor upon this subject, addresses his auditors in the following very remarkable words:—"I cannot conclude without recalling particularly to your recollection a consideration which I have more than once alluded to, and which probably your thoughts have been all along anticipating; a consideration with which my mind is impressed more than can express: I mean the consideration of the favorableness of the present times to all exertions in the cause of liberty."

If this is your actual situation, compared to the situation you were called to, as if by the voice of God and man, I can't genuinely congratulate you on the choice you've made or the success you've achieved. I wouldn't recommend any other nation to follow a course of action based on such principles and yielding such results. I must leave this to those who can see deeper into your affairs than I can and who know best how far your actions benefit their goals. The members of the Revolution Society, who were quick to congratulate you, seem to strongly believe there is some political strategy related to this country where your actions might somehow be beneficial. Your Dr. Price, who appears to have fervently speculated on this topic, expresses to his audience the following noteworthy words:—"I cannot conclude without reminding you specifically of a point I have mentioned more than once, one that you have likely been anticipating all along; a point that weighs heavily on my mind: I mean the consideration of the favorableness of the present times to all efforts in the cause of liberty."

It is plain that the mind of this political preacher was at the time big with some extraordinary design; and it is very probable that the thoughts of his audience, who understood him better than I do, did all along run before him in his reflection, and in the whole train of consequences to which it led.

It’s clear that this political speaker was filled with some remarkable idea; and it’s likely that the thoughts of his audience, who understood him better than I do, consistently anticipated his reflections and the entire chain of consequences that followed.

Before I read that sermon, I really thought I had lived in a free country; and it was an error I cherished, because it gave me a greater liking to the country I lived in. I was, indeed, aware that a jealous, ever-waking vigilance, to guard the treasure of our liberty, not only from invasion, but from decay and corruption, was our best wisdom and our first duty. However, I considered that treasure rather as a possession to be secured than as a prize to be contended for. I did not discern how the present time came to be so very favorable to all exertions in the cause of freedom. The present time differs from any other only by the circumstance of what is doing in France. If the example of that nation is to have an influence on this, I can easily conceive why some of their proceedings which have an unpleasant aspect, and are not quite reconcilable to humanity, generosity, good faith, and justice, are palliated with so much milky good-nature towards the actors, and borne with so much heroic fortitude towards the sufferers. It is certainly not prudent to discredit the authority of an example we mean to follow. But allowing this, we are led to a very natural question:—What is that cause of liberty, and what are those exertions in its favor, to which the example of France is so singularly auspicious? Is our monarchy to be annihilated, with all the laws, all the tribunals, and all the ancient corporations of the kingdom? Is every landmark of the country to be done away in favor of a geometrical and arithmetical constitution? Is the House of Lords to be voted useless? Is Episcopacy to be abolished? Are the Church lands to be sold to Jews and jobbers, or given to bribe new-invented municipal republics into a participation in sacrilege? Are all the taxes to be voted grievances, and the revenue reduced to a patriotic contribution or patriotic presents? Are silver shoe-buckles to be substituted in the place of the land-tax and the malt-tax, for the support of the naval strength of this kingdom? Are all orders, ranks, and distinctions to be confounded, that out of universal anarchy, joined to national bankruptcy, three or four thousand democracies should be formed into eighty-three, and that they may all, by some sort of unknown attractive power, be organized into one? For this great end is the army to be seduced from its discipline and its fidelity, first by every kind of debauchery, and then by the terrible precedent of a donative in the increase of pay? Are the curates to be seduced from their bishops by holding out to them the delusive hope of a dole out of the spoils of their own order? Are the citizens of London to be drawn from their allegiance by feeding them at the expense of their fellow-subjects? Is a compulsory paper currency to be substituted in the place of the legal coin of this kingdom? Is what remains of the plundered stock of public revenue to be employed in the wild project of maintaining two armies to watch over and to fight with each other? If these are the ends and means of the Revolution Society, I admit they are well assorted; and France may furnish them for both with precedents in point.

Before I read that sermon, I really thought I lived in a free country; it was a belief I held onto because it made me appreciate my country even more. I knew that constant vigilance to protect our liberty from invasion and decay was our best wisdom and first duty. However, I saw that liberty more as something to be secured than as something to fight for. I didn’t understand why the current moment was so favorable for efforts toward freedom. The present time is different only because of what’s happening in France. If that nation’s example affects us, I can see why some of their actions, which seem unpleasant and clash with humanity, generosity, good faith, and justice, are met with so much goodwill toward the actors and so much bravery toward the victims. It’s certainly not wise to undermine the validity of an example we intend to follow. But with that in mind, we naturally ask: What is the cause of liberty, and what efforts in its favor does the French example support so well? Are we going to dismantle our monarchy, along with all the laws, courts, and ancient institutions of the kingdom? Will we erase every landmark to create a geometric and arithmetic constitution? Is the House of Lords going to be deemed useless? Is Episcopacy going to be abolished? Are church lands going to be sold to Jews and traders or given to entice newly invented municipal republics into complicity? Are all taxes going to be seen as grievances and reduced to patriotic contributions or gifts? Are silver shoe-buckles going to replace the land tax and malt tax for supporting this kingdom’s naval strength? Are all orders, ranks, and distinctions going to be merged, so that out of total chaos and national bankruptcy, three or four thousand democracies become eighty-three, and somehow, they all unite through some unknown attractive force? For this grand goal, is the army seduced from its discipline and loyalty, first by all kinds of indulgence, and then by the terrifying example of increased pay? Are curates going to be led away from their bishops by the false hope of a share of the spoils of their own order? Are London citizens going to be drawn away from their allegiance by being fed at the expense of their fellow citizens? Is a forced paper currency going to replace the legal coin of this kingdom? Will what remains of the looted public revenue be used in the reckless plan of maintaining two armies to watch over and fight with each other? If these are the goals and methods of the Revolution Society, I admit they fit well together; and France can certainly provide examples for them both.

I see that your example is held out to shame us. I know that we are supposed a dull, sluggish race, rendered passive by finding our situation tolerable, and prevented by a mediocrity of freedom from ever attaining to its full perfection. Your leaders in France began by affecting to admire, almost to adore, the British Constitution; but as they advanced, they came to look upon it with a sovereign contempt. The friends of your National Assembly amongst us have full as mean an opinion of what was formerly thought the glory of their country. The Revolution Society has discovered that the English nation is not free. They are convinced that the inequality in our representation is a "defect in our Constitution so gross and palpable as to make it excellent chiefly in form and theory";[87]—that a representation in the legislature of a kingdom is not only the basis of all constitutional liberty in it, but of "all legitimate government; that without it a government is nothing but an usurpation";—that, "when the representation is partial, the kingdom possesses liberty only partially; and if extremely partial, it gives only a semblance; and if not only extremely partial, but corruptly chosen, it becomes a nuisance." Dr. Price considers this inadequacy of representation as our fundamental grievance; and though, as to the corruption of this semblance of representation, he hopes it is not yet arrived to its full perfection of depravity, he fears that "nothing will be done towards gaining for us this essential blessing, until some great abuse of power again provokes our resentment, or some great calamity again alarms our fears, or perhaps till the acquisition of a pure and equal representation by other countries, whilst we are mocked with the shadow, kindles our shame." To this he subjoins a note in these words:—"A representation chosen chiefly by the Treasury, and a few thousands of the dregs of the people, who are generally paid for their votes."

I see that your example is meant to shame us. I know we're seen as a dull, sluggish group, made passive by the tolerability of our situation, and held back by a mediocre level of freedom that prevents us from reaching its full potential. Your leaders in France started by pretending to admire, almost to worship, the British Constitution; but as they progressed, they began to regard it with complete disdain. Supporters of your National Assembly among us have a similarly low opinion of what was once considered the pride of their nation. The Revolution Society has realized that the English nation is not free. They are convinced that the inequality in our representation is a "defect in our Constitution so gross and palpable that it makes it excellent mainly in form and theory";[87]—that representation in a nation's legislature is not only the foundation of all constitutional liberty but of "all legitimate government; that without it, a government is merely an usurpation";—that, "when the representation is partial, the kingdom possesses liberty only partially; and if extremely partial, it provides only a semblance; and if not only extremely partial but also corruptly chosen, it becomes a nuisance." Dr. Price views this lack of proper representation as our fundamental grievance; and although he hopes the corruption of this semblance of representation hasn't yet reached its peak levels of depravity, he fears that "nothing will be done to secure for us this essential blessing, until some great abuse of power again stirs our anger, or some great calamity again triggers our fears, or perhaps until the achievement of a pure and equal representation by other countries, while we are mocked with the shadow, ignites our shame." He adds a note saying:—"A representation chosen mainly by the Treasury, and a few thousand of the dregs of the people, who are generally paid for their votes."

You will smile here at the consistency of those democratists who, when they are not on their guard, treat the humbler part of the community with the greatest contempt, whilst, at the same time, they pretend to make them the depositories of all power. It would require a long discourse to point out to you the many fallacies that lurk in the generality and equivocal nature of the terms "inadequate representation." I shall only say here, in justice to that old-fashioned Constitution under which we have long prospered, that our representation has been found perfectly adequate to all the purposes for which a representation of the people can be desired or devised. I defy the enemies of our Constitution to show the contrary. To detail the particulars in which it is found so well to promote its ends would demand a treatise on our practical Constitution. I state here the doctrine of the revolutionists, only that you and others may see what an opinion these gentlemen entertain of the Constitution of their country, and why they seem to think that some great abuse of power, or some great calamity, as giving a chance for the blessing of a Constitution according to their ideas, would be much palliated to their feelings; you see why they are so much enamored of your fair and equal representation, which being once obtained, the same effects might follow. You see they consider our House of Commons as only "a semblance," "a form," "a theory," "a shadow," "a mockery," perhaps "a nuisance."

You'll find it amusing how consistent those democratists are who, when they're not paying attention, show the greatest disdain for the less privileged members of society, while at the same time pretending to place all power in their hands. It would take a long discussion to highlight the many flaws hidden in the vague and ambiguous phrases like "inadequate representation." I'll just say, in fairness to that old-fashioned Constitution under which we've thrived, that our representation has proven to be entirely adequate for all the purposes for which we need a representation of the people. I challenge the critics of our Constitution to prove otherwise. Outlining the specifics of how it effectively achieves its goals would require a comprehensive analysis of our practical Constitution. I'm presenting the views of the revolutionists just so you and others can understand what these individuals really think of their country's Constitution, and why they believe that a major abuse of power or a disaster might create an opportunity for a Constitution that aligns with their ideals, which would somewhat ease their concerns; you see why they are so taken with your fair and equal representation, believing that once it's achieved, similar outcomes could follow. They view our House of Commons as merely "a facade," "a form," "a theory," "a shadow," "a mockery," or perhaps even "a nuisance."

These gentlemen value themselves on being systematic, and not without reason. They must therefore look on this gross and palpable defect of representation, this fundamental grievance, (so they call it,) as a thing not only vicious in itself, but as rendering our whole government absolutely illegitimate, and not at all better than a downright usurpation. Another revolution, to get rid of this illegitimate and usurped government, would of course be perfectly justifiable, if not absolutely necessary. Indeed, their principle, if you observe it with any attention, goes much further than to an alteration in the election of the House of Commons; for, if popular representation, or choice, is necessary to the legitimacy of all government, the House of Lords is, at one stroke, bastardized and corrupted in blood. That House is no representative of the people at all, even in "semblance" or "in form." The case of the crown is altogether as bad. In vain the crown may endeavor to screen itself against these gentlemen by the authority of the establishment made on the Revolution. The Revolution, which is resorted to for a title, on their system, wants a title itself. The Revolution is built, according to their theory, upon a basis not more solid than our present formalities, as it was made by a House of Lords not representing any one but themselves, and by a House of Commons exactly such as the present, that is, as they term it, by a mere "shadow and mockery" of representation.

These gentlemen take pride in being organized, and they have good reason to. They must therefore look at this obvious and serious flaw in representation, this core grievance (as they call it), not just as something wrong in itself, but as something that makes our entire government completely illegitimate, no better than an outright usurpation. Another revolution to eliminate this illegitimate and usurped government would obviously be fully justifiable, if not absolutely necessary. In fact, if you pay close attention, their principle goes much further than just changing the election of the House of Commons; for if popular representation or choice is essential for the legitimacy of any government, the House of Lords becomes, all at once, completely illegitimate and corrupt in its authority. That House isn’t a representative of the people at all, not even in "appearance" or "form." The situation with the crown is just as bad. The crown may try in vain to defend itself against these gentlemen by relying on the authority established during the Revolution. The Revolution, which they use as a justification, itself lacks legitimacy according to their framework. The Revolution is based on a foundation no more solid than our current formalities, as it was carried out by a House of Lords that represented no one but themselves, and by a House of Commons just like the one we have now, which they describe as a mere "shadow and mockery" of representation.

Something they must destroy, or they seem to themselves to exist for no purpose. One set is for destroying the civil power through the ecclesiastical; another for demolishing the ecclesiastic through the civil. They are aware that the worst consequences might happen to the public in accomplishing this double ruin of Church and State; but they are so heated with their theories, that they give more than hints that this ruin, with all the mischiefs that must lead to it and attend it, and which to themselves appear quite certain, would not be unacceptable to them, or very remote from their wishes. A man amongst them of great authority, and certainly of great talents, speaking of a supposed alliance between Church and State, says, "Perhaps we must wait for the fall of the civil powers, before this most unnatural alliance be broken. Calamitous, no doubt, will that time be. But what convulsion in the political world ought to be a subject of lamentation, if it be attended with so desirable an effect?" You see with what a steady eye these gentlemen are prepared to view the greatest calamities which can befall their country!

Something they need to destroy, or they feel like they exist for no reason. One group is focused on undermining civil authority through the church; another is about tearing down the church through civil means. They realize that the worst outcomes could happen to the public in bringing about this double destruction of Church and State; but they are so consumed by their theories that they imply this destruction, along with all the chaos it would cause, which seems certain to them, wouldn't be unwelcome or far from their desires. A highly respected and talented man among them, discussing a supposed alliance between Church and State, says, "Maybe we must wait for the collapse of the civil powers before this unnatural alliance can be severed. That moment will surely be disastrous. But what upheaval in the political world should we mourn if it leads to such a desirable outcome?" You can see how calmly these individuals are prepared to face the greatest disasters that could happen to their country!

It is no wonder, therefore, that, with these ideas of everything in their Constitution and government at home, either in Church or State, as illegitimate and usurped, or at best as a vain mockery, they look abroad with an eager and passionate enthusiasm. Whilst they are possessed by these notions, it is vain to talk to them of the practice of their ancestors, the fundamental laws of their country, the fixed form of a Constitution whose merits are confirmed by the solid test of long experience and an increasing public strength and national prosperity. They despise experience as the wisdom of unlettered men; and as for the rest, they have wrought under ground a mine that will blow up, at one grand explosion, all examples of antiquity, all precedents, charters, and acts of Parliament. They have "the rights of men." Against these there can be no prescription; against these no argument is binding: these admit no temperament and no compromise: anything withheld from their full demand is so much of fraud and injustice. Against these their rights of men let no government look for security in the length of its continuance, or in the justice and lenity of its administration. The objections of these speculatists, if its forms do not quadrate with their theories, are as valid against such an old and beneficent government as against the most violent tyranny or the greenest usurpation. They are always at issue with governments, not on a question of abuse, but a question of competency and a question of title. I have nothing to say to the clumsy subtilty of their political metaphysics. Let them be their amusement in the schools.

It's no surprise, then, that with these views about everything in their Constitution and government at home, whether in Church or State, being seen as illegitimate and usurped or, at best, as a mere joke, they look outward with eager and passionate enthusiasm. While they hold onto these beliefs, it's pointless to discuss the practices of their ancestors, the fundamental laws of their country, or the established form of a Constitution whose value is proven by the solid tests of long experience and growing public strength and national prosperity. They dismiss experience as the wisdom of uneducated people; and as for the rest, they have secretly created a force that will, in one huge explosion, destroy all examples from the past, all precedents, charters, and acts of Parliament. They claim to have "the rights of men." There can be no tradition against these rights; no argument is effective against them: these rights allow for no moderation or compromise: anything denied from their full demands is seen as fraud and injustice. Governments should not expect security from the length of their existence, or from the fairness and leniency of their administration against these claims of rights. The objections from these theorists, if the government's forms don’t align with their ideas, are as valid against a well-established and beneficial government as they are against the most oppressive tyranny or the newest usurpation. They always conflict with governments, not over issues of abuse, but over questions of capabilities and legitimacy. I have nothing to say about the awkward subtleties of their political theories. Let that be their distraction in academic circles.

She boasts in the court Aeolus will reign, with the winds locked away in a prison.

But let them not break prison to burst like a Levanter, to sweep the earth with their hurricane, and to break up the fountains of the great deep to overwhelm us!

But let's not let them escape the prison to unleash like a violent storm, to sweep across the earth with their fury, and to break the foundations of the deep to drown us!

Far am I from denying in theory, full as far is my heart from withholding in practice, (if I were of power to give or to withhold,) the real rights of men. In denying their false claims of right, I do not mean to injure those which are real, and are such as their pretended rights would totally destroy. If civil society be made for the advantage of man, all the advantages for which it is made become his right. It is an institution of beneficence; and law itself is only beneficence acting by a rule. Men have a right to live by that rule; they have a right to justice, as between their fellows, whether their fellows are in politic function or in ordinary occupation. They have a right to the fruits of their industry, and to the means of making their industry fruitful. They have a right to the acquisitions of their parents, to the nourishment and improvement of their offspring, to instruction in life and to consolation in death. Whatever each man can separately do, without trespassing upon others, he has a right to do for himself; and he has a right to a fair portion of all which society, with all its combinations of skill and force, can do in his favor. In this partnership all men have equal rights; but not to equal things. He that has but five shillings in the partnership has as good a right to it as he that has five hundred pounds has to his larger proportion; but he has not a right to an equal dividend in the product of the joint stock. And as to the share of power, authority, and direction which each individual ought to have in the management of the state, that I must deny to be amongst the direct original rights of man in civil society; for I have in my contemplation the civil social man, and no other. It is a thing to be settled by convention.

I don't deny in theory, and my heart doesn't hold back in practice (if I had the power to give or take away), the **real** rights of individuals. When I reject their false claims of rights, I don’t mean to undermine the real ones, which their fake rights would completely destroy. If civil society exists for the benefit of people, all the benefits it provides become their rights. It is a system of goodwill; the law itself is just goodwill applied through rules. People have the right to live by those rules; they have a right to justice with each other, whether they are in political roles or ordinary jobs. They have a right to the results of their labor and to the means of making their work successful. They have a right to their parents’ legacy, to nurture and educate their children, to guidance in life, and to comfort in death. Whatever any individual can do on their own, without infringing on others, they have the right to do for themselves; and they have the right to a fair share of everything society, with all its skills and resources, can provide for their benefit. In this partnership, everyone has equal rights, but not to equal things. Someone with five shillings in the partnership has just as much right to it as someone with five hundred pounds has to their larger share; but they do not have a right to an equal divide of the joint profits. As for the share of power, authority, and direction that each person should have in managing the state, I must deny that it falls under the direct original rights of individuals in civil society; I am focused on the individual within civil society, and nothing else. It is something to be determined by agreement.

If civil society be the offspring of convention, that convention must be its law. That convention must limit and modify all the descriptions of constitution which are formed under it. Every sort of legislative, judicial, or executory power are its creatures. They can have no being in any other state of things; and how can any man claim, under the conventions of civil society, rights which do not so much as suppose its existence,—rights which are absolutely repugnant to it? One of the first motives to civil society, and which becomes one of its fundamental rules, is, that no man should be judge in his own cause. By this each person has at once divested himself of the first fundamental right of uncovenanted man, that is, to judge for himself, and to assert his own cause. He abdicates all right to be his own governor. He inclusively, in a great measure, abandons the right of self-defence, the first law of Nature. Men cannot enjoy the rights of an uncivil and of a civil state together. That he may obtain justice, he gives up his right of determining what it is in points the most essential to him. That he may secure some liberty, he makes a surrender in trust of the whole of it.

If civil society is the result of agreements, then those agreements must serve as its law. They must shape and adjust all the frameworks of government that arise within it. Every type of legislative, judicial, or executive power is a product of this society. They can't exist in any other context; so how can anyone claim, under the agreements of civil society, rights that don't even acknowledge its existence—rights that are entirely opposed to it? One of the primary motivations for forming civil society, which becomes one of its core principles, is that no one should be the judge in their own case. By doing this, each person effectively gives up the first fundamental right of an independent individual, which is to judge for themselves and advocate for their own cause. They forfeit any right to govern themselves. Consequently, they largely abandon the right to self-defense, the basic law of Nature. People cannot enjoy the rights of both an uncivilized and a civilized state at the same time. To obtain justice, they relinquish their right to determine what justice is in areas that matter most to them. To gain some freedom, they trustingly surrender all of it.

Government is not made in virtue of natural rights, which may and do exist in total independence of it,—and exist in much greater clearness, and in a much greater degree of abstract perfection: but their abstract perfection is their practical defect. By having a right to everything they want everything. Government is a contrivance of human wisdom to provide for human wants. Men have a right that these wants should be provided for by this wisdom. Among these wants is to be reckoned the want, out of civil society, of a sufficient restraint upon their passions. Society requires not only that the passions of individuals should be subjected, but that even in the mass and body, as well as in the individuals, the inclinations of men should frequently be thwarted, their will controlled, and their passions brought into subjection. This can only be done by a power out of themselves, and not, in the exercise of its function, subject to that will and to those passions which it is its office to bridle and subdue. In this sense the restraints on men, as well as their liberties, are to be reckoned among their rights. But as the liberties and the restrictions vary with times and circumstances, and admit of infinite modifications, they cannot be settled upon any abstract rule; and nothing is so foolish as to discuss them upon that principle.

Government doesn't stem from natural rights, which can exist independently of it and are often clearer and more perfectly abstract. However, this abstract perfection can be a practical flaw. When everyone has a right to everything, they want everything. Government is a way for people to manage their needs. Individuals have a right to have those needs met. Among these needs is the necessity for some restraint on their passions outside of civil society. Society requires that not only should individual passions be controlled, but also that, collectively, people's desires should often be curbed, their wills guided, and their passions managed. This can only happen through a power that comes from outside themselves, which isn’t influenced by the desires and passions that it is meant to regulate. In this sense, both the constraints on individuals and their freedoms are considered their rights. However, since freedoms and restrictions change with circumstances and can be modified in countless ways, they can't be defined by any abstract rule; discussing them on that basis is utterly foolish.

The moment you abate anything from the full rights of men each to govern himself, and suffer any artificial, positive limitation upon those rights, from that moment the whole organization of government becomes a consideration of convenience. This it is which makes the constitution of a state, and the due distribution of its powers, a matter of the most delicate and complicated skill. It requires a deep knowledge of human nature and human necessities, and of the things which facilitate or obstruct the various ends which are to be pursued by the mechanism of civil institutions. The state is to have recruits to its strength and remedies to its distempers. What is the use of discussing a man's abstract right to food or medicine? The question is upon the method of procuring and administering them. In that deliberation I shall always advise to call in the aid of the farmer and the physician, rather than the professor of metaphysics.

The moment you take away any part of a person's rights to self-govern, and allow any imposed restrictions on those rights, the entire structure of government becomes a matter of convenience. This is what turns the constitution of a state and the proper distribution of its powers into something that requires careful and complex expertise. It demands a deep understanding of human nature and needs, along with what helps or hinders the various goals pursued by civil institutions. The state needs to strengthen itself and address its issues. What's the point of talking about a person's theoretical right to food or medicine? The real question is about how to obtain and provide them. In that discussion, I would always recommend bringing in the farmer and the doctor instead of a metaphysics professor.

The science of constructing a commonwealth, or renovating it, or reforming it, is, like every other experimental science, not to be taught a priori. Nor is it a short experience that can instruct us in that practical science; because the real effects of moral causes are not always immediate, but that which in the first instance is prejudicial may be excellent in its remoter operation, and its excellence may arise even from the ill effects it produces in the beginning. The reverse also happens; and very plausible schemes, with very pleasing commencements, have often shameful and lamentable conclusions. In states there are often some obscure and almost latent causes, things which appear at first view of little moment, on which a very great part of its prosperity or adversity may most essentially depend. The science of government being, therefore, so practical in itself, and intended for such practical purposes, a matter which requires experience, and even more experience than any person can gain in his whole life, however sagacious and observing he may be, it is with infinite caution that any man ought to venture upon pulling down an edifice which has answered in any tolerable degree for ages the common purposes of society, or on building it up again without having models and patterns of approved utility before his eyes.

The science of building or renewing, or reforming a society is, like any other experimental science, not something that can be learned purely from theory. It's not a brief experience that can teach us this practical science; because the true effects of moral causes are not always immediate. What seems harmful at first may turn out to be beneficial in the long run, and its benefits may even come from the negative effects it initially produces. The opposite can also be true; seemingly great ideas with appealing starts often end in disgrace and disappointment. In societies, there are often some hidden and almost latent causes—things that seem insignificant at first glance—upon which a large part of its success or failure may greatly depend. Since the science of government is so practical and aimed at real-world outcomes, it requires experience, and even more experience than any individual can gather in a full lifetime, no matter how insightful and observant they are. Therefore, any person should be extremely cautious before attempting to dismantle a structure that has functioned reasonably well for ages to meet the basic needs of society, or before trying to rebuild it without having successful models and examples to guide them.

These metaphysic rights entering into common life, like rays of light which pierce into a dense medium, are, by the laws of Nature, refracted from their straight line. Indeed, in the gross and complicated mass of human passions and concerns, the primitive rights of men undergo such a variety of refractions and reflections that it becomes absurd to talk of them as if they continued in the simplicity of their original direction. The nature of man is intricate; the objects of society are of the greatest possible complexity: and therefore no simple disposition or direction of power can be suitable either to man's nature or to the quality of his affairs. When I hear the simplicity of contrivance aimed at and boasted of in any new political constitutions, I am at no loss to decide that the artificers are grossly ignorant of their trade or totally negligent of their duty. The simple governments are fundamentally defective, to say no worse of them. If you were to contemplate society in but one point of view, all these simple modes of polity are infinitely captivating. In effect each would answer its single end much more perfectly than the more complex is able to attain all its complex purposes. But it is better that the whole, should be imperfectly and anomalously answered than that while some parts are provided for with great exactness, others might be totally neglected, or perhaps materially injured, by the over-care of a favorite member.

These fundamental rights, when they enter everyday life, are like beams of light that get bent as they pass through a dense medium, because of the laws of nature. In fact, within the chaotic mix of human emotions and interests, people's basic rights experience so many twists and turns that it's ridiculous to talk about them as if they remain straightforward. Human nature is complex, and society's issues are incredibly intricate; therefore, no simple structure of power can truly suit either human nature or the nature of societal matters. When I hear people brag about the simplicity of design in any new political systems, it's clear to me that those creating them are either completely clueless about their craft or seriously neglecting their responsibilities. Simple governments have fundamental flaws, to put it mildly. If you were to look at society from just one perspective, all these straightforward forms of governance seem incredibly appealing. In reality, each would accomplish its single purpose much more effectively than a more complex system can handle all its various goals. However, it's better for the whole to be answered in a flawed and inconsistent way than for some areas to be taken care of precisely while others are completely overlooked or even harmed by over-focusing on a favored part.

The pretended rights of these theorists are all extremes; and in proportion as they are metaphysically true, they are morally and politically false. The rights of men are in a sort of middle, incapable of definition, but not impossible to be discerned. The rights of men in governments are their advantages; and these are often in balances between differences of good,—in compromises sometimes between good and evil, and sometimes between evil and evil. Political reason is a computing principle: adding, subtracting, multiplying, and dividing, morally, and not metaphysically or mathematically, true moral denominations.

The supposed rights these theorists claim are all extremes; and the more they are true in a philosophical sense, the more they are false in a moral and political sense. The rights of individuals exist in a sort of middle, which can't be defined but can be recognized. The rights of people within governments are their benefits; and these often involve balancing different ideals of good—sometimes making compromises between good and bad, and sometimes between bad and worse. Political reasoning is a practical principle: adding, subtracting, multiplying, and dividing, in moral terms, and not in philosophical or mathematical ones.

By these theorists the right of the people is almost always sophistically confounded with their power. The body of the community, whenever it can come to act, can meet with no effectual resistance; but till power and right are the same, the whole body of them has no right inconsistent with virtue, and the first of all virtues, prudence. Men have no right to what is not reasonable, and to what is not for their benefit; for though a pleasant writer said, "Liceat perire poetis," when one of them, in cold blood, is said to have leaped into the flames of a volcanic revolution, "ardentem frigidus Ætnam insiluit," I consider such a frolic rather as an unjustifiable poetic license than as one of the franchises of Parnassus; and whether he were poet, or divine, or politician, that chose to exercise this kind of right, I think that more wise, because more charitable, thoughts would urge me rather to save the man than to preserve his brazen slippers as the monuments of his folly.

By these theorists, people's rights are often confusingly mixed up with their power. The community can act without facing any real resistance whenever it’s able to come together; however, until power and rights are the same, the entire community doesn't have rights that go against virtue, and the most important of all virtues is prudence. People have no right to things that are unreasonable or not in their best interest; for although a witty writer once said, "Liceat perire poetis," regarding a poet who supposedly jumped into the fiery chaos of a volcanic revolution, "ardentem frigidus Ætnam insiluit," I see such an act as more of an unjustifiable poetic whim than as a privilege of Parnassus. Whether that person was a poet, a divine figure, or a politician choosing to act on this kind of right, I believe that more thoughtful and compassionate considerations would lead me to save the person rather than keep their flashy slippers as reminders of their foolishness.


The kind of anniversary sermons to which a great part of what I write refers, if men are not shamed out of their present course, in commemorating the fact, will cheat many out of the principles and deprive them of the benefits of the Revolution they commemorate. I confess to you, Sir, I never liked this continual talk of resistance and revolution, or the practice of making the extreme medicine of the Constitution its daily bread. It renders the habit of society dangerously valetudinary; it is taking periodical doses of mercury sublimate, and swallowing down repeated provocatives of cantharides to our love of liberty.

The kind of anniversary sermons that much of what I write refers to, if people aren’t shamed out of their current path, in celebrating the fact, will rob many of their principles and deny them the benefits of the Revolution they celebrate. I’ll be honest with you, Sir, I’ve never liked this constant talk of resistance and revolution, or the practice of using the extreme remedies of the Constitution as if they were everyday solutions. It makes the habits of society dangerously weak; it’s like taking periodic doses of mercury and repeatedly swallowing stimulants that provoke our love of liberty.

This distemper of remedy, grown habitual, relaxes and wears out, by a vulgar and prostituted use, the spring of that spirit which is to be exerted on great occasions. It was in the most patient period of Roman servitude that themes of tyrannicide made the ordinary exercise of boys at school,—cum perimit sævos classis numerosa tyrannos. In the ordinary state of things, it produces in a country like ours the worst effects, even on the cause of that liberty which it abuses with the dissoluteness of an extravagant speculation. Almost all the high-bred republicans of my time have, after a short space, become the most decided, thorough-paced courtiers; they soon left the business of a tedious, moderate, but practical resistance, to those of us whom, in the pride and intoxication of their theories, they have slighted as not much better than Tories. Hypocrisy, of course, delights in the most sublime speculations; for, never intending to go beyond speculation, it costs nothing to have it magnificent. But even in cases where rather levity than fraud was to be suspected in these ranting speculations, the issue has been much the same. These professors, finding their extreme principles not applicable to cases which call only for a qualified, or, as I may say, civil and legal resistance, in such cases employ no resistance at all. It is with them a war or a revolution, or it is nothing. Finding their schemes of politics not adapted to the state of the world in which they live, they often come to think lightly of all public principle, and are ready, on their part, to abandon for a very trivial interest what they find of very trivial value. Some, indeed, are of more steady and persevering natures; but these are eager politicians out of Parliament, who have little to tempt them to abandon their favorite projects. They have some change in the Church or State, or both, constantly in their view. When that is the case, they are always bad citizens, and perfectly unsure connections. For, considering their speculative designs as of infinite value, and the actual arrangement of the state as of no estimation, they are, at best, indifferent about it. They see no merit in the good, and no fault in the vicious management of public affairs; they rather rejoice in the latter, as more propitious to revolution. They see no merit or demerit in any man, or any action, or any political principle, any further than as they may forward or retard their design of change; they therefore take up, one day, the most violent and stretched prerogative, and another time the wildest democratic ideas of freedom, and pass from the one to the other without any sort of regard to cause, to person, or to party.

This ineffective remedy, which has become a habit, dulls and wears down the energy needed for significant moments through its common and excessive use. In the most patient times of Roman servitude, discussions about killing tyrants were normal classroom lessons—cum perimit sævos classis numerosa tyrannos. In our usual circumstances, it has the worst effects on a country like ours, even harming the very liberty it misuses with the recklessness of wild thinking. Almost all the high-minded republicans of my time have quickly turned into loyal courtiers; they soon abandoned the tedious but practical resistance in favor of those of us whom, in their arrogance and excitement over their theories, they dismissed as not much better than Tories. Hypocrisy, of course, thrives on the grandest theories. Since it never intends to move beyond speculation, it doesn’t cost much to have such lofty ideas. However, even when there’s more foolishness than deceit in these grandiose theories, the outcomes are quite similar. These theorists, finding their extreme principles irrelevant in situations that only require a moderate, or as I might say, civil and legal resistance, simply don’t engage at all. For them, it’s either war or revolution, or nothing. When they realize their political ideas don’t fit the actual state of the world, they often begin to undervalue all public principles and are ready to abandon what they consider trivial for very minor benefits. Some, indeed, are more consistent and persistent, but these are eager politicians outside of Parliament who aren’t tempted to give up their favorite projects. They always have some change in the Church or the State, or both, in their sights. When that’s the case, they make terrible citizens and utterly unreliable allies. Since they regard their theoretical plans as infinitely valuable and the current state of affairs as worthless, they are, at best, indifferent towards it. They see no virtue in the good and no fault in the poor management of public affairs; in fact, they seem to take joy in the latter as it favors revolution. They see no merit or fault in any individual, action, or political principle unless it affects their quest for change; they switch between one day embracing the most extreme and stretched claims of power and the next adopting the wildest democratic ideas of freedom, moving from one to the other with no concern for cause, person, or party.

In France you are now in the crisis of a revolution, and in the transit from one form of government to another: you cannot see that character of men exactly in the same situation in which we see it in this country. With us it is militant, with you it is triumphant; and you know how it can act, when its power is commensurate to its will. I would not be supposed to confine those observations to any description of men, or to comprehend all men of any description within them,—no, far from it! I am as incapable of that injustice as I am of keeping terms with those who profess principles of extremes, and who, under the name of religion, teach little else than wild and dangerous politics. The worst of these politics of revolution is this: they temper and harden the breast, in order to prepare it for the desperate strokes which are sometimes used in extreme occasions. But as these occasions may never arrive, the mind receives a gratuitous taint; and the moral sentiments suffer not a little, when no political purpose is served by the depravation. This sort of people are so taken up with their theories about the rights of man, that they have totally forgot his nature. Without opening one new avenue to the understanding, they have succeeded in stopping up those that lead to the heart. They have perverted in themselves, and in those that attend to them, all the well-placed sympathies of the human breast.

In France, you are currently in the middle of a revolution, moving from one type of government to another. You can't see the character of people in the same way we see it here. For us, it’s about fighting; for you, it’s about victory. And you know how that can act when its power matches its desires. I don't mean to limit these observations to any specific type of person, nor do I think they apply to all people of any kind—far from it! I'm just as incapable of that injustice as I am of tolerating those who hold extreme views and who, under the guise of religion, teach little more than radical and dangerous politics. The worst part of these revolutionary politics is that they harden the heart to prepare it for the desperate actions sometimes taken in extreme situations. But since these situations may never come, the mind gets a harmful influence, and moral feelings suffer significantly when no political goal justifies such corruption. These people are so focused on their theories about human rights that they have completely forgotten human nature. Without opening any new paths to understanding, they have managed to close off those that lead to compassion. They have twisted both themselves and those who listen to them, disrupting all the natural sympathies of the human heart.

This famous sermon of the Old Jewry breathes nothing but this spirit through all the political part. Plots, massacres, assassinations, seem to some people a trivial price for obtaining a revolution. A cheap, bloodless reformation, a guiltless liberty, appear flat and vapid to their taste. There must be a great change of scene; there must be a magnificent stage effect; there must be a grand spectacle to rouse the imagination, grown torpid with the lazy enjoyment of sixty years' security, and the still unanimating repose of public prosperity. The preacher found them all in the French Revolution. This inspires a juvenile warmth through his whole frame. His enthusiasm kindles as he advances; and when he arrives at his peroration, it is in a full blaze. Then viewing, from the Pisgah of his pulpit, the free, moral, happy, flourishing, and glorious state of France, as in a bird-eye landscape of a promised land, he breaks out into the following rapture:—

This well-known sermon from the Old Jewry conveys only this spirit throughout the political part. Conspiracies, massacres, and assassinations seem to some people a minor cost for achieving a revolution. A simple, bloodless reform or a guilt-free freedom feels dull and uninspiring to them. They crave a significant change of scene; there needs to be a magnificent spectacle; there must be a grand display to stir their imagination, dulled by the comfortable enjoyment of sixty years of security and the still, energizing calm of public prosperity. The preacher found all of this in the French Revolution. This fills him with youthful passion. His excitement grows as he continues, and when he reaches his conclusion, it’s in full force. Then, looking from the vantage point of his pulpit at the free, moral, happy, thriving, and glorious state of France, like a bird's-eye view of a promised land, he bursts out in the following rapture:—

"What an eventful period is this! I am thankful that I have lived to it; I could almost say, Lord, now lettest thou thy servant depart in peace, for mine eyes have seen thy salvation.—I have lived to see a diffusion of knowledge which has undermined superstition and error.—I have lived to see the rights of men better understood than ever, and nations panting for liberty which seemed to have lost the idea of it.—I have lived to see thirty millions of people, indignant and resolute, spurning at slavery, and demanding liberty with an irresistible voice; their king led in triumph, and an arbitrary monarch surrendering himself to his subjects."[88]

"What an eventful time this is! I am thankful to have lived through it; I could almost say, Lord, now let your servant depart in peace, for my eyes have seen your salvation.—I have lived to witness a spread of knowledge that has challenged superstition and ignorance.—I have lived to see the rights of people understood better than ever, with nations yearning for freedom that had seemed lost.—I have lived to see thirty million people, outraged and determined, rejecting slavery and demanding freedom with an unstoppable voice; their king led in victory, and an arbitrary monarch surrendering to his subjects."[88]

Before I proceed further, I have to remark that Dr. Price seems rather to overvalue the great acquisitions of light which he has obtained and diffused in this age. The last century appears to me to have been quite as much enlightened. It had, though in a different place, a triumph as memorable as that of Dr. Price; and some of the great preachers of that period partook of it as eagerly as he has done in the triumph of France. On the trial of the Reverend Hugh Peters for high treason, it was deposed, that, when King Charles was brought to London for his trial, the Apostle of Liberty in that day conducted the triumph. "I saw," says the witness, "his Majesty in the coach with six horses, and Peters riding before the king triumphing." Dr. Price, when he talks as if he had made a discovery, only follows a precedent; for, after the commencement of the king's trial, this precursor, the same Dr. Peters, concluding a long prayer at the royal chapel at Whitehall, (he had very triumphantly chosen his place,) said, "I have prayed and preached these twenty years; and now I may say with old Simeon, Lord, now lettest thou thy servant depart in peace, for mine eyes have seen thy salvation."[89] Peters had not the fruits of his prayer; for he neither departed so soon as he wished, nor in peace. He became (what I heartily hope none of his followers may be in this country) himself a sacrifice to the triumph which he led as pontiff. They dealt at the Restoration, perhaps, too hardly with this poor good man. But we owe it to his memory and his sufferings, that he had as much illumination and as much zeal, and had as effectually undermined all the superstition and error which might impede the great business he was engaged in, as any who follow and repeat after him in this age, which would assume to itself an exclusive title to the knowledge of the rights of men, and all the glorious consequences of that knowledge.

Before I go any further, I have to say that Dr. Price seems to overvalue the significant insights he has gained and shared in this era. To me, the last century was just as enlightening. It had, albeit in a different context, a triumph that was as notable as Dr. Price's, and some of the great speakers of that time celebrated it just as passionately as he has celebrated the triumph in France. During the trial of Reverend Hugh Peters for treason, it was testified that when King Charles was brought to London for his trial, the "Apostle of Liberty" of that time led the triumph. "I saw," said the witness, "his Majesty in the coach with six horses, and Peters riding before the king triumphing." When Dr. Price talks as if he has made a discovery, he's really just following a precedent; for after the start of the king's trial, this precursor, the same Dr. Peters, after a lengthy prayer at the royal chapel at Whitehall (he had very triumphantly chosen his spot), said, "I have prayed and preached for these twenty years; and now I can say with old Simeon, Lord, now lettest thou thy servant depart in peace, for mine eyes have seen thy salvation."[89] Peters didn't get the results he hoped for; he neither left as soon as he wanted nor in peace. He became (what I sincerely hope none of his followers will be in this country) a sacrifice to the triumph he led as a leader. They treated this poor, good man too harshly during the Restoration, perhaps. But we owe it to his memory and his sacrifices that he had as much insight and zeal, and had as effectively dismantled all the superstition and error that might hinder the great work he was involved in, as anyone who follows and repeats after him in this era, which claims an exclusive title to the knowledge of human rights and all the glorious outcomes of that knowledge.

After this sally of the preacher of the Old Jewry, which differs only in place and time, but agrees perfectly with the spirit and letter of the rapture of 1648, the Revolution Society, the fabricators of governments, the heroic band of cashierers of monarchs, electors of sovereigns, and leaders of kings in triumph, strutting with a proud consciousness of the diffusion of knowledge, of which every member had obtained so large a share in the donative, were in haste to make a generous diffusion of the knowledge they had thus gratuitously received. To make this bountiful communication, they adjourned from the church in the Old Jewry to the London Tavern, where the same Dr. Price, in whom the fumes of his oracular tripod were not entirely evaporated, moved and carried the resolution, or address of congratulation, transmitted by Lord Stanhope to the National Assembly of France.

After this outburst from the preacher of the Old Jewry, which only changes in location and timing but aligns perfectly with the essence and intent of the excitement of 1648, the Revolution Society—creators of governments, the brave group that fires monarchs, elects sovereigns, and leads kings in victory, confidently flaunting their knowledge, which each member had received in abundance from the gift—was eager to share the knowledge they had received for free. To make this generous exchange, they moved from the church in the Old Jewry to the London Tavern, where the same Dr. Price, still drawing from the lingering inspiration of his prophetic pedestal, proposed and secured the resolution, or message of congratulations, sent by Lord Stanhope to the National Assembly of France.

I find a preacher of the Gospel profaning the beautiful and prophetic ejaculation, commonly called "Nunc dimittis," made on the first presentation of our Saviour in the temple, and applying it, with an inhuman and unnatural rapture, to the most horrid, atrocious, and afflicting spectacle that perhaps ever was exhibited to the pity and indignation of mankind. This "leading in triumph," a thing in its best form unmanly and irreligious, which fills our preacher with such unhallowed transports, must shock, I believe, the moral taste of every well-born mind. Several English were the stupefied and indignant spectators of that triumph. It was (unless we have been strangely deceived) a spectacle more resembling a procession of American savages entering into Onondaga after some of their murders called victories, and leading into hovels hung round with scalps their captives overpowered with the scoffs and buffets of women as ferocious as themselves, much more than it resembled the triumphal pomp of a civilized martial nation;—if a civilized nation, or any men who had a sense of generosity, were capable of a personal triumph over the fallen and afflicted.

I see a preacher of the Gospel misusing the beautiful and prophetic phrase commonly known as "Nunc dimittis," originally spoken during the first presentation of our Savior in the temple, and applying it, with an inhumane and unnatural excitement, to the most horrific, atrocious, and distressing event that perhaps has ever drawn the pity and anger of humanity. This "leading in triumph," which at its best is unmanly and irreligious, is met with such unholy passion from our preacher that it must shock the moral sensibilities of every decent person. Many English were the stunned and outraged witnesses of that triumph. It was (unless we’ve been quite misled) a sight that resembled more a procession of American savages returning to Onondaga after one of their murderously dubbed victories, leading their captives into settlements adorned with scalps, mocked and beaten by women as fierce as themselves, rather than the glorious display of a civilized martial nation;—if a civilized nation, or anyone with a sense of honor, could even conceive of a personal triumph over the fallen and suffering.

This, my dear Sir, was not the triumph of France. I must believe, that, as a nation, it overwhelmed you with shame and horror. I must believe that the National Assembly find themselves in a state of the greatest humiliation in not being able to punish the authors of this triumph or the actors in it, and that they are in a situation in which any inquiry they may make upon the subject must be destitute even of the appearance of liberty or impartiality. The apology of that assembly is found in their situation; but when we approve what they must bear, it is in us the degenerate choice of a vitiated mind.

This, my dear Sir, wasn't a victory for France. I have to believe that, as a nation, it left you feeling ashamed and horrified. I must believe that the National Assembly is experiencing the greatest humiliation for being unable to punish the people responsible for this so-called triumph or those involved in it, and that they are in a position where any investigation they pursue will lack even the appearance of freedom or fairness. The justification of that assembly lies in their circumstances; however, when we condone what they *must* endure, it's a sign of a corrupted mindset on our part.

With a compelled appearance of deliberation, they vote under the dominion of a stern necessity. They sit in the heart, as it were, of a foreign republic: they have their residence in a city whose constitution has emanated neither from the charter of their king nor from their legislative power. There they are surrounded by an army not raised either by the authority of their crown or by their command, and which, if they should order to dissolve itself, would instantly dissolve them. There they sit, after a gang of assassins had driven away some hundreds of the members; whilst those who held the same moderate principles, with more patience or better hope, continued every day exposed to outrageous insults and murderous threats. There a majority, sometimes real, sometimes pretended, captive itself, compels a captive king to issue as royal edicts, at third hand, the polluted nonsense of their most licentious and giddy coffee-houses. It is notorious that all their measures are decided before they are debated. It is beyond doubt, that, under the terror of the bayonet, and the lamp-post, and the torch to their houses, they are obliged to adopt all the crude and desperate measures suggested by clubs composed of a monstrous medley of all conditions, tongues, and nations. Among these are found persons in comparison of whom Catiline would be thought scrupulous, and Cethegus a man of sobriety and moderation. Nor is it in these clubs alone that the public measures are deformed into monsters. They undergo a previous distortion in academies, intended as so many seminaries for these clubs, which are set up in all the places of public resort. In these meetings of all sorts, every counsel, in proportion as it is daring and violent and perfidious, is taken for the mark of superior genius. Humanity and compassion are ridiculed as the fruits of superstition and ignorance. Tenderness to individuals is considered as treason to the public. Liberty is always to be estimated perfect as property is rendered insecure. Amidst assassination, massacre, and confiscation, perpetrated or meditated, they are forming plans for the good order of future society. Embracing in their arms the carcasses of base criminals, and promoting their relations on the title of their offences, they drive hundreds of virtuous persons to the same end, by forcing them to subsist by beggary or by crime.

With a forced look of seriousness, they vote under a harsh necessity. They sit, so to speak, in a foreign government: they live in a city whose laws come from neither their king’s charter nor their own legislative power. They are surrounded by an army that was not raised by the authority of their crown or by their orders, which, if they were told to disband, would instantly turn on them. They sit there after a group of assassins chased away hundreds of members; meanwhile, those who shared the same moderate views, either through more patience or better hope, continue to face constant insults and deadly threats. There, a majority—sometimes real, sometimes fake—forces a captive king to issue royal decrees that repeat the twisted nonsense from their most outrageous and reckless coffeehouses. It’s well-known that all their decisions are made before they are discussed. Without a doubt, under the threat of violence, including bayonets and threats to their homes, they are forced to go along with all the harsh and desperate ideas proposed by clubs made up of a chaotic mix of all kinds of people. Among them are individuals compared to whom Catiline would seem cautious, and Cethegus would seem sober and moderate. And it's not only in these clubs that public policies are twisted into monstrous forms. They are first distorted in schools, which serve as breeding grounds for these clubs, set up in all public spaces. In these mixed gatherings, any daring, violent, or deceitful advice is seen as a sign of great intelligence. Humanity and compassion are mocked as products of superstition and ignorance. Caring for individuals is viewed as betrayal to the public. Liberty is always seen as perfect when property feels insecure. Amidst assassination, massacre, and both carried out or planned confiscations, they are making plans for the orderly future society. Clinging to the bodies of lowly criminals and promoting their relatives because of their crimes, they force hundreds of good people into the same situation, making them survive through begging or crime.

The Assembly, their organ, acts before them the farce of deliberation with as little decency as liberty. They act like the comedians of a fair, before a riotous audience; they act amidst the tumultuous cries of a mixed mob of ferocious men, and of women lost to shame, who, according to their insolent fancies, direct, control, applaud, explode them, and sometimes mix and take their seats amongst them,—domineering over them with a strange mixture of servile petulance and proud, presumptuous authority. As they have inverted order in all things, the gallery is in the place of the house. This assembly, which overthrows kings and kingdoms, has not even the physiognomy and aspect of a grave legislative body,—nec color imperii, nec frons erat ulla senatûs. They have a power given to them, like that of the Evil Principle, to subvert and destroy,—but none to construct, except such machines as may be fitted for further subversion and further destruction.

The Assembly, their governing body, plays out a ridiculous show of discussion with as little respect as freedom. They behave like entertainers at a fair, in front of a chaotic crowd; they act among the raucous shouts of a mixed group of ruthless men and shameless women, who, in their arrogant whims, direct, control, cheer, and undermine them, sometimes even mingling and taking their seats among them—dominating with a bizarre blend of submissive irritation and arrogant authority. Since they have overturned order in everything, the gallery now sits where the house should be. This assembly, which topples kings and nations, lacks the demeanor and appearance of a serious legislative body—nec color imperii, nec frons erat ulla senatûs. They wield a power granted to them, like that of a malevolent force, to cause chaos and destruction—but none to build, except for creating devices that serve only to further undermine and destroy.

Who is it that admires, and from the heart is attached to national representative assemblies, but must turn with horror and disgust from such a profane burlesque and abominable perversion of that sacred institute? Lovers of monarchy, lovers of republics, must alike abhor it. The members of your Assembly must themselves groan under the tyranny of which they have all the shame, none of the direction, and little of the profit. I am sure many of the members who compose even the majority of that body must feel as I do, notwithstanding the applauses of the Revolution Society. Miserable king! miserable assembly! How must that assembly be silently scandalized with those of their members who could call a day which seemed to blot the sun out of heaven "un beau jour"![90] How must they be inwardly indignant at hearing others who thought fit to declare to them, "that the vessel of the state would fly forward in her course towards regeneration with more speed than ever," from the stiff gale of treason and murder which preceded our preacher's triumph! What must they have felt, whilst, with outward patience and inward indignation, they heard of the slaughter of innocent gentlemen in their houses, that "the blood spilled was not the most pure"! What must they have felt, when they were besieged by complaints of disorders which shook their country to its foundations, at being compelled coolly to tell the complainants that they were under the protection of the law, and that they would address the king (the captive king) to cause the laws to be enforced for their protection, when the enslaved ministers of that captive king had formally notified to them that there were neither law nor authority nor power left to protect! What must they have felt at being obliged, as a felicitation on the present new year, to request their captive king to forget the stormy period of the last, on account of the great good which he was likely to produce to his people,—to the complete attainment of which good they adjourned the practical demonstrations of their loyalty, assuring him of their obedience when he should no longer possess any authority to command!

Who admires and truly cares for national representative assemblies, yet must turn away in horror and disgust from such a corrupt parody and terrible distortion of that important institution? Supporters of both monarchy and republics must equally loathe it. The members of your Assembly must suffer under the tyranny that brings them shame, offers no guidance, and provides little benefit. I’m sure that many of the members, even those in the majority, must feel like I do, despite the cheers of the Revolution Society. Poor king! Poor assembly! How must that assembly be silently appalled by those members who could refer to a day that seemed to darken the sun as "un beau jour"![90] How must they feel inside, hearing others declare, "that the vessel of the state would race forward towards renewal faster than ever," despite the harsh winds of treason and murder that preceded our speaker’s triumph! What must they have felt, while they patiently sat with outrage inside, upon hearing about the slaughter of innocent gentlemen in their homes, that "the blood spilled was not the purest"! What must they have felt when bombarded with complaints about the chaos shaking their country to its core, only to be forced to calmly tell the complainants that they were protected by the law, and that they would approach the king (the captive king) to ensure the laws were enforced for their safety, when the imprisoned ministers of that captive king had officially informed them that there was no longer any law, authority, or power to protect? What must they have felt being compelled, as a congratulations for the new year, to ask their captive king to overlook the turbulent past year, because of the great good that he was likely to bring to his people,—to fully achieve which good they postponed showing their loyalty, assuring him of their obedience when he would no longer have any authority to command!

This address was made with much good-nature and affection, to be sure. But among the revolutions in France must be reckoned a considerable revolution in their ideas of politeness. In England we are said to learn manners at second-hand from your side of the water, and that we dress our behavior in the frippery of France. If so, we are still in the old cut, and have not so far conformed to the new Parisian mode of good breeding as to think it quite in the most refined strain of delicate compliment (whether in condolence or congratulation) to say, to the most humiliated creature that crawls upon the earth, that great public benefits are derived from the murder of his servants, the attempted assassination of himself and of his wife, and the mortification, disgrace, and degradation that he has personally suffered. It is a topic of consolation which our ordinary of Newgate would be too humane to use to a criminal at the foot of the gallows. I should have thought that the hangman of Paris, now that he is liberalized by the vote of the National Assembly, and is allowed his rank and arms in the Herald's College of the rights of men, would be too generous, too gallant a man, too full of the sense of his new dignity, to employ that cutting consolation to any of the persons whom the lèze-nation might bring under the administration of his executive powers.

This speech was delivered with a lot of good humor and warmth, for sure. However, among the changes happening in France, we also have to acknowledge a major shift in their views on politeness. In England, people say we learn manners second-hand from you across the ocean and that we dress our behavior in the fancy styles of France. If that’s true, we’re still stuck in the old ways and haven't quite adapted to the new Parisian standards of etiquette, at least not enough to believe that it’s proper to tell the most humiliated person on earth that major public benefits come from the murder of his servants, the attempted assassination of himself and his wife, and the humiliation, disgrace, and degradation he has personally endured. It’s a comforting thought that even the common hangman at Newgate wouldn't use to console a criminal standing at the gallows. I would have thought that the hangman of Paris, now that he’s been liberalized by the vote of the National Assembly and permitted his rank and coat of arms in the Herald's College of human rights, would be too kind, too noble a person, too aware of his new dignity to use such harsh consolation on any individuals the lèze-nation might bring under his executive powers.

A man is fallen indeed, when he is thus flattered. The anodyne draught of oblivion, thus drugged, is well calculated to preserve a galling wakefulness, and to feed the living ulcer of a corroding memory. Thus to administer the opiate potion of amnesty, powdered with all the ingredients of scorn and contempt, is to hold to his lips, instead of "the balm of hurt minds," the cup of human misery full to the brim, and to force him to drink it to the dregs.

A man has truly fallen when he is flattered this way. The soothing drink of forgetfulness, laced with the right additives, is sure to keep him painfully aware and to feed the persistent wound of a troubling memory. Giving him the drug of forgiveness, mixed with all the elements of disdain and disrespect, is like offering him a cup filled to the top with human suffering instead of "the balm of hurt minds," and forcing him to swallow every last drop.

Yielding to reasons at least as forcible as those which were so delicately urged in the compliment on the new year, the king of France will probably endeavor to forget these events and that compliment. But History, who keeps a durable record of all our acts, and exercises her awful censure over the proceedings of all sorts of sovereigns, will not forget either those events, or the era of this liberal refinement in the intercourse of mankind. History will record, that, on the morning of the sixth of October, 1789, the king and queen of France, after a day of confusion, alarm, dismay, and slaughter, lay down, under the pledged security of public faith, to indulge nature in a few hours of respite, and troubled, melancholy repose. From this sleep the queen was first startled by the voice of the sentinel at her door, who cried out to her to save herself by flight,—that this was the last proof of fidelity he could give,—that they were upon him, and he was dead. Instantly he was cut down. A band of cruel ruffians and assassins, reeking with his blood, rushed into the chamber of the queen, and pierced with a hundred strokes of bayonets and poniards the bed, from whence this persecuted woman had but just time to fly almost naked, and, through ways unknown to the murderers, had escaped to seek refuge at the feet of a king and husband not secure of his own life for a moment.

Yielding to reasons at least as strong as those delicately presented in the New Year’s compliment, the king of France will likely try to forget these events and that compliment. But History, who records all our actions and scrutinizes the actions of all types of rulers, won’t forget those events or the period of this liberal refinement in human interaction. History will note that on the morning of October 6, 1789, the king and queen of France, after a day filled with confusion, fear, despair, and violence, laid down, under the assurance of public trust, to rest their bodies for a few hours and find troubled, sad repose. The queen was first awakened from her sleep by the voice of the sentinel at her door, who shouted for her to escape—saying this would be the last act of loyalty he could provide—that they were coming for him and he was dead. He was cut down immediately. A group of cruel thugs and murderers, dripping with his blood, burst into the queen’s chamber and stabbed the bed with countless jabs from bayonets and daggers, from where this persecuted woman barely managed to escape, almost naked, and had found a way unknown to her attackers to flee and seek refuge at the feet of a king and husband who wasn’t secure in his own life for even a moment.

This king, to say no more of him, and this queen, and their infant children, (who once would have been the pride and hope of a great and generous people,) were then forced to abandon the sanctuary of the most splendid palace in the world, which they left swimming in blood, polluted by massacre, and strewed with scattered limbs and mutilated carcasses. Thence they were conducted into the capital of their kingdom. Two had been selected from the unprovoked, unresisted, promiscuous slaughter which was made of the gentlemen of birth and family who composed the king's body-guard. These two gentlemen, with all the parade of an execution of justice, were cruelly and publicly dragged to the block, and beheaded in the great court of the palace. Their heads were stuck upon spears, and led the procession; whilst the royal captives who followed in the train were slowly moved along, amidst the horrid yells, and shrilling screams, and frantic dances, and infamous contumelies, and all the unutterable abominations of the furies of hell, in the abused shape of the vilest of women. After they had been made to taste, drop by drop, more than the bitterness of death, in the slow torture of a journey of twelve miles, protracted to six hours, they were, under a guard composed of those very soldiers who had thus conducted them through this famous triumph, lodged in one of the old palaces of Paris, now converted into a Bastile for kings.

This king, not to say more about him, and this queen, along with their young children, (who once would have been the pride and hope of a great and generous people,) were then forced to leave the sanctuary of the most magnificent palace in the world, which they departed drenched in blood, tainted by massacre, and littered with severed limbs and mutilated bodies. They were then taken to the capital of their kingdom. Two had been chosen from the unprovoked, uncontested, indiscriminate slaughter of the nobles who made up the king's bodyguard. These two gentlemen, with all the appearance of a just execution, were cruelly and publicly dragged to the block and beheaded in the grand court of the palace. Their heads were placed on spears, leading the procession; while the royal captives who followed were slowly moved along amidst the horrific yells, piercing screams, frenzied dancing, contemptuous insults, and all the unfathomable horrors unleashed by the furies of hell, taking the form of the most vile women. After being made to experience, drop by drop, a bitterness greater than death, in the agonizing stretch of a twelve-mile journey that took six hours, they were, under a guard made up of those very soldiers who had led them through this infamous triumph, confined in one of the old palaces of Paris, now turned into a prison for kings.

Is this a triumph to be consecrated at altars, to be commemorated with grateful thanksgiving, to be offered to the Divine Humanity with fervent prayer and enthusiastic ejaculation?—These Theban and Thracian orgies, acted in France, and applauded only in the Old Jewry, I assure you, kindle prophetic enthusiasm in the minds but of very few people in this kingdom: although a saint and apostle, who may have revelations of his own, and who has so completely vanquished all the mean superstitions of the heart, may incline to think it pious and decorous to compare it with the entrance into the world of the Prince of Peace, proclaimed in an holy temple by a venerable sage, and not long before not worse announced by the voice of angels to the quiet innocence of shepherds.

Is this a victory to be celebrated at altars, to be marked with sincere gratitude, to be offered to the Divine Humanity with heartfelt prayer and excited expression?—These Theban and Thracian ceremonies, performed in France and praised only in the Old Jewry, I assure you, inspire prophetic zeal in the minds of very few people in this kingdom: although a saint and apostle, who might have his own revelations and who has completely overcome all the petty superstitions of the heart, may feel it’s respectful and appropriate to compare it to the arrival of the Prince of Peace, proclaimed in a holy temple by a wise sage, and not long before that, heralded by the voices of angels to the innocent shepherds.

At first I was at a loss to account for this fit of unguarded transport. I knew, indeed, that the sufferings of monarchs make a delicious repast to some sort of palates. There were reflections which might serve to keep this appetite within some bounds of temperance. But when I took one circumstance into my consideration, I was obliged to confess that much allowance ought to be made for the society, and that the temptation was too strong for common discretion: I mean, the circumstance of the Io Pæan of the triumph, the animating cry which called for "all the BISHOPS to be hanged on the lamp-posts,"[91] might well have brought forth a burst of enthusiasm on the foreseen consequences of this happy day. I allow to so much enthusiasm some little deviation from prudence. I allow this prophet to break forth into hymns of joy and thanksgiving on an event which appears like the precursor of the Millennium, and the projected Fifth Monarchy, in the destruction of all Church establishments. There was, however, (as in all human affairs there is,) in the midst of this joy, something to exercise the patience of these worthy gentlemen, and to try the long-suffering of their faith. The actual murder of the king and queen, and their child, was wanting to the other auspicious circumstances of this "beautiful day". The actual murder of the bishops, though called for by so many holy ejaculations, was also wanting. A group of regicide and sacrilegious slaughter was, indeed, boldly sketched, but it was only sketched. It unhappily was left unfinished, in this great history-piece of the massacre of innocents. What hardy pencil of a great master, from the school of the rights of men, will finish it, is to be seen hereafter. The age has not yet the complete benefit of that diffusion of knowledge that has undermined superstition and error; and the king of France wants another object or two to consign to oblivion, in consideration of all the good which is to arise from his own sufferings, and the patriotic crimes of an enlightened age.[92]

At first, I couldn't understand why I felt this overwhelming excitement. I realized that the pain of kings can be quite appealing to some people. There were thoughts that could help keep this appetite in check. But when I considered one particular thing, I had to admit that a lot of leeway should be given to the crowd, and the urge was too strong for ordinary judgment: specifically, the celebratory call for "all the BISHOPS to be hanged on the lamp-posts,"[91] could easily have prompted a surge of joy about the expected results of this fortunate day. I can understand a bit of excitement straying from caution. I can accept that this prophet might burst into songs of happiness and praise for an event that seems like it’s the beginning of a better era, leading to the end of all Church institutions. However, there was, as there often is in human affairs, something to test the patience of those good men and to challenge their enduring faith. The actual killing of the king, queen, and their child was missing from the other promising events of this "beautiful day." The actual killing of the bishops, even though it was called for by so many fervent cries, was also absent. A plan for regicide and sacrilegious murder was certainly laid out, but it was just a draft. Sadly, it remained unfinished in this grand narrative of the slaughter of innocents. Which bold artist from the school of human rights will complete it, remains to be seen in the future. The times haven't yet fully benefited from the spread of knowledge that has challenged superstition and ignorance; and the king of France needs a few more targets to forget, considering all the good that is expected to come from his own suffering and the noble deeds of an enlightened age.[92]

Although this work of our new light and knowledge did not go to the length that in all probability it was intended it should be carried, yet I must think that such treatment of any human creatures must be shocking to any but those who are made for accomplishing revolutions. But I cannot stop here. Influenced by the inborn feelings of my nature, and not being illuminated by a single ray of this new-sprung modern light, I confess to you, Sir, that the exalted rank of the persons suffering, and particularly the sex, the beauty, and the amiable qualities of the descendant of so many kings and emperors, with the tender age of royal infants, insensible only through infancy and innocence of the cruel outrages to which their parents were exposed, instead of being a subject of exultation, adds not a little to my sensibility on that most melancholy occasion.

Although this work of our new understanding and knowledge didn’t go as far as it likely intended, I still believe that the treatment of any human beings must be shocking to everyone except those meant for causing upheavals. But I can’t stop here. Driven by the natural feelings within me, and not being enlightened by even a single spark of this new modern light, I must confess to you, Sir, that the high status of those suffering, especially the gender, the beauty, and the kind qualities of the descendant of so many kings and emperors, along with the tender age of royal infants, who are unaware only due to their youth and innocence of the cruel injustices faced by their parents, instead of being a reason for celebration, deeply intensifies my emotions on this saddening occasion.

I hear that the august person who was the principal object of our preacher's triumph, though he supported himself, felt much on that shameful occasion. As a man, it became him to feel for his wife and his children, and the faithful guards of his person that were massacred in cold blood about him; as a prince, it became him to feel for the strange and frightful transformation of his civilized subjects, and to be more grieved for them than solicitous for himself. It derogates little from his fortitude, while it adds infinitely to the honor of his humanity. I am very sorry to say it, very sorry indeed, that such personages are in a situation in which it is not unbecoming in us to praise the virtues of the great.

I hear that the esteemed person who was the main focus of our preacher's celebration, even though he held himself up, felt deeply during that disgraceful event. As a man, he should have empathized with his wife and children, as well as the loyal guards around him who were brutally killed; as a prince, he should have been more concerned about the horrifying change in his civilized subjects than about his own situation. This doesn’t diminish his courage, and it greatly enhances the dignity of his humanity. I'm truly sorry to say this, very sorry indeed, but individuals like him find themselves in a position where it’s not inappropriate for us to commend the virtues of the great.

I hear, and I rejoice to hear, that the great lady, the other object of the triumph, has borne that day, (one is interested that beings made for suffering should suffer well,) and that she bears all the succeeding days, that she bears the imprisonment of her husband, and her own captivity, and the exile of her friends, and the insulting adulation of addresses, and the whole weight of her accumulated wrongs, with a serene patience, in a manner suited to her rank and race, and becoming the offspring of a sovereign distinguished for her piety and her courage; that, like her, she has lofty sentiments; that she feels with the dignity of a Roman matron; that in the last extremity she will save herself from the last disgrace; and that, if she must fall, she will fall by no ignoble hand.

I hear, and I'm glad to hear, that the great lady, the other focus of the triumph, has managed to endure that day (it's interesting to see beings made for suffering handle it well), and that she continues to endure all the following days. She endures her husband's imprisonment, her own captivity, the exile of her friends, the mocking praise of speeches, and the heavy burden of her accumulated wrongs with calm patience, in a way that reflects her status and lineage, fitting the child of a sovereign known for her faith and bravery; that, like her, she has high ideals; that she experiences emotions with the dignity of a Roman matron; that in her greatest crisis she will save herself from the utmost shame; and that, if she must fall, she will not do so at the hands of an ignoble foe.

It is now sixteen or seventeen years since I saw the queen of France, then the Dauphiness, at Versailles; and surely never lighted on this orb, which she hardly seemed to touch, a more delightful vision. I saw her just above the horizon, decorating and cheering the elevated sphere she just began to move in,—glittering like the morning-star, full of life and splendor and joy. Oh! what a revolution! and what an heart must I have, to contemplate without emotion that elevation and that fall! Little did I dream, when she added titles of veneration to those of enthusiastic, distant, respectful love, that she should ever be obliged to carry the sharp antidote against disgrace concealed in that bosom! little did I dream that I should have lived to see such disasters fallen upon her in a nation of gallant men, in a nation of men of honor, and of cavaliers! I thought ten thousand swords must have leaped from their scabbards to avenge even a look that threatened her with insult. But the age of chivalry is gone. That of sophisters, economists, and calculators has succeeded; and the glory of Europe is extinguished forever. Never, never more, shall we behold that generous loyalty to rank and sex, that proud submission, that dignified obedience, that subordination of the heart, which kept alive, even in servitude itself, the spirit of an exalted freedom! The unbought grace of life, the cheap defence of nations, the nurse of manly sentiment and heroic enterprise, is gone! It is gone, that sensibility of principle, that chastity of honor, which felt a stain like a wound, which inspired courage whilst it mitigated ferocity, which ennobled whatever it touched, and under which vice itself lost half its evil by losing all its grossness!

It’s been about sixteen or seventeen years since I saw the queen of France, then the Dauphiness, at Versailles; and there’s never been a more delightful sight in this world, which she barely seemed to touch. I saw her just above the horizon, brightening and uplifting the elevated sphere she was just beginning to enter, sparkling like the morning star, full of life, splendor, and joy. Oh, what a change! And what kind of heart must I have to look at her rise and fall without feeling anything? Little did I imagine, when she began receiving titles of respect along with those of enthusiastic, distant love, that she would ever need to hide the sharp pain of disgrace in her heart! I never thought I’d live to see such disasters befall her in a nation of brave men, in a nation of honorable men and knights! I thought thousands of swords would leap from their scabbards to avenge even a look that threatened her with insult. But the age of chivalry is over. It’s been replaced by an era of sophists, economists, and calculators; and the glory of Europe is extinguished forever. Never again will we witness that noble loyalty to rank and gender, that proud submission, that dignified obedience, and that deep-seated respect that kept alive, even in servitude, the spirit of true freedom! The unpurchased beauty of life, the affordable defense of nations, the nurturer of manly sentiment and heroic deeds, is gone! That sensibility of principle, that purity of honor, which felt a stain like a wound, inspired courage while softening brutality, ennobled everything it touched, and under which vice itself lost much of its evil by losing all its crudeness, is gone!

This mixed system of opinion and sentiment had its origin in the ancient chivalry; and the principle, though varied in its appearance by the varying state of human affairs, subsisted and influenced through a long succession of generations, even to the time we live in. If it should ever be totally extinguished, the loss, I fear, will be great. It is this which has given its character to modern Europe. It is this which has distinguished it under all its forms of government, and distinguished it to its advantage, from the states of Asia, and possibly from those states which flourished in the most brilliant periods of the antique world. It was this, which, without confounding ranks, had produced a noble equality, and handed it down through all the gradations of social life. It was this opinion which mitigated kings into companions, and raised private men to be fellows with kings. Without force or opposition, it subdued the fierceness of pride and power; it obliged sovereigns to submit to the soft collar of social esteem, compelled stern authority to submit to elegance, and gave a domination, vanquisher of laws, to be subdued by manners.

This mixed system of opinion and sentiment originated in ancient chivalry, and while it has changed with the shifting state of human affairs, it has persisted and influenced many generations, even up to today. If it were ever completely extinguished, the loss would be significant, I fear. This system has given character to modern Europe. It has set Europe apart under all kinds of governments and has distinguished it to its advantage from the states of Asia, and possibly from those civilizations that thrived in the most brilliant periods of the ancient world. It created a noble equality without mixing ranks and passed it down through all levels of social life. This opinion softened kings into companions and elevated common people to be equals with kings. Without force or opposition, it tamed the harshness of pride and power; it forced rulers to yield to the gentle grip of social esteem, compelled stern authority to embrace grace, and allowed a kind of dominance that transcended laws to be subdued by manners.

But now all is to be changed. All the pleasing illusions which made power gentle and obedience liberal, which harmonized the different shades of life, and which by a bland assimilation incorporated into politics the sentiments which beautify and soften private society, are to be dissolved by this new conquering empire of light and reason. All the decent drapery of life is to be rudely torn off. All the superadded ideas, furnished from the wardrobe of a moral imagination, which the heart owns and the understanding ratifies, as necessary to cover the defects of our naked, shivering nature, and to raise it to dignity in our own estimation, are to be exploded, as a ridiculous, absurd, and antiquated fashion.

But now everything is about to change. All the comforting illusions that made power kind and obedience generous, that brought together the various aspects of life, and that softly blended the feelings that enhance and soften private society into politics, are about to be shattered by this new conquering empire of light and reason. All the decent coverings of life are going to be roughly ripped away. All the extra ideas, supplied from the wardrobe of moral imagination, which the heart recognizes and the mind agrees are necessary to hide the flaws of our bare, vulnerable nature, and to elevate it in our own eyes, are going to be dismissed as a ridiculous, absurd, and outdated trend.

On this scheme of things, a king is but a man, a queen is but a woman, a woman is but an animal,—and an animal not of the highest order. All homage paid to the sex in general as such, and without distinct views, is to be regarded as romance and folly. Regicide, and parricide, and sacrilege, are but fictions of superstition, corrupting jurisprudence by destroying its simplicity. The murder of a king, or a queen, or a bishop, or a father, are only common homicide,—and if the people are by any chance or in any way gainers by it, a sort of homicide much the most pardonable, and into which we ought not to make too severe a scrutiny.

In this view of the world, a king is just a man, a queen is just a woman, and a woman is just an animal—not even one of the highest types. Any respect shown to women as a group, without specific reasons, should be seen as romantic nonsense. Killing a king, a queen, a bishop, or a father is really just regular murder, and if the people benefit from it in any way, it’s a much more forgivable kind of murder, and we shouldn’t scrutinize it too harshly.

On the scheme of this barbarous philosophy, which is the offspring of cold hearts and muddy understandings and which is as void of solid wisdom as it is destitute of all taste and elegance, laws are to be supported only by their own terrors, and by the concern which each individual may find in them from his own private speculations, or can spare to them from his own private interests. In the groves of their academy, at the end of every visto, you see nothing but the gallows. Nothing is left which engages the affections on the part of the commonwealth. On the principles of this mechanic philosophy, our institutions can never be embodied, if I may use the expression, in persons,—so as to create in us love, veneration, admiration, or attachment. But that sort of reason which banishes the affections is incapable of filling their place. These public affections, combined with manners, are required sometimes as supplements, sometimes as correctives, always as aids to law. The precept given by a wise man, as well as a great critic, for the construction of poems, is equally true as to states:—"Non satis est pulchra esse poemata, dulcia sunto." There ought to be a system of manners in every nation which a well-formed mind would be disposed to relish. To make us love our country, our country ought to be lovely.

According to this brutal philosophy, which comes from cold hearts and unclear minds and lacks real wisdom as much as it does taste and elegance, laws should only be upheld by their own fear and by the concerns each person has from their own thoughts or what they can gain from their own interests. In the groves of their academy, at the end of every path, all you see is the gallows. There's nothing that connects us emotionally to the community. Based on this mechanical philosophy, our institutions can never be embodied, if I may use the term, in people—to create feelings of love, respect, admiration, or attachment. But that kind of reasoning, which pushes away emotions, cannot take their place. These public feelings, combined with manners, are necessary at times as additions, sometimes as corrections, and always as support for the law. The advice given by a wise man and a great critic for writing poems is just as true for states:—"Non satis est pulchra esse poemata, dulcia sunto." Every nation should have a set of manners that a well-formed mind would appreciate. To make us love our country, our country should be beautiful.

But power, of some kind or other, will survive the shock in which manners and opinions perish; and it will find other and worse means for its support. The usurpation, which, in order to subvert ancient institutions, has destroyed ancient principles, will hold power by arts similar to those by which it has acquired it. When the old feudal and chivalrous spirit of fealty, which, by freeing kings from fear, freed both kings and subjects from the precautions of tyranny, shall be extinct in the minds of men, plots and assassinations will be anticipated by preventive murder and preventive confiscation, and that long roll of grim and bloody maxims which form the political code of all power not standing on its own honor and the honor of those who are to obey it. Kings will be tyrants from policy, when subjects are rebels from principle.

But some form of power will endure the shock that destroys customs and beliefs; it will find other, even harsher means to maintain itself. The takeover, which aimed to dismantle old institutions by erasing ancient principles, will cling to power through methods similar to those it used to gain it. When the old feudal and chivalrous spirit of loyalty, which liberated kings from fear and both kings and subjects from the need for tyranny, is gone from people's minds, plots and assassinations will be met with preemptive killings and confiscations. This will lead to a long list of grim and bloody rules that make up the political code of any power that doesn't rely on its own honor and the honor of those who are meant to obey it. Kings will be tyrants by choice when subjects are rebels by principle.

When ancient opinions and rules of life are taken away, the loss cannot possibly be estimated. From that moment we have no compass to govern us, nor can we know distinctly to what port we steer. Europe, undoubtedly, taken in a mass, was in a flourishing condition the day on which your Revolution was completed. How much of that prosperous state was owing to the spirit of our old manners and opinions is not easy to say; but as such causes cannot be indifferent in their operation, we must presume, that, on the whole, their operation was beneficial.

When ancient beliefs and rules for living are removed, the loss is impossible to measure. From that point on, we have no direction to guide us, and we can't clearly know where we're headed. Europe, undoubtedly, was doing well on the day your Revolution was finished. It's hard to say how much of that success was due to the strength of our old customs and beliefs, but since such influences can’t be ignored, we must assume that, overall, their effect was positive.

We are but too apt to consider things in the state in which we find them, without sufficiently adverting to the causes by which they have been produced, and possibly may be upheld. Nothing is more certain than that our manners, our civilization, and all the good things which are connected with manners and with, civilization, have, in this European world of ours, depended for ages upon two principles, and were, indeed, the result of both combined: I mean the spirit of a gentleman, and the spirit of religion. The nobility and the clergy, the one by profession, and the other by patronage, kept learning in existence, even in the midst of arms and confusions, and whilst governments were rather in their causes than formed. Learning paid back what it received to nobility and to priesthood, and paid it with usury, by enlarging their ideas, and by furnishing their minds. Happy, if they had all continued to know their indissoluble union, and their proper place! Happy, if learning, not debauched by ambition, had been satisfied to continue the instructor, and not aspired to be the master! Along with its natural protectors and guardians, learning will be cast into the mire and trodden down under the hoofs of a swinish multitude.[93]

We often tend to view things just as they are, without really thinking about the reasons behind how they came to be and how they might be maintained. It's clear that our manners, our civilization, and all the good things associated with both have, in this European world of ours, depended for centuries on two key principles, and were really the result of both working together: the spirit of a gentleman and the spirit of religion. The nobility and the clergy, one through profession and the other through support, kept knowledge alive even in times of conflict and uncertainty, while governments were still in the process of formation. Knowledge returned what it received to both the nobility and the clergy, often surpassing it by expanding their ideas and enriching their understanding. Wouldn’t it have been wonderful if they had all recognized their inseparable connection and their rightful roles? How fortunate it would have been if knowledge, untainted by ambition, had been happy to remain the teacher instead of trying to become the ruler! Without its natural protectors and guardians, knowledge will find itself in the dirt, trampled by a greedy and foolish crowd.[93]

If, as I suspect, modern letters owe more than they are always willing to own to ancient manners, so do other interests which we value full as much as they are worth. Even commerce, and trade, and manufacture, the gods of our economical politicians, are themselves perhaps but creatures, are themselves but effects, which, as first causes, we choose to worship. They certainly grew under the same shade in which learning flourished. They, too, may decay with their natural protecting principles. With you, for the present at least, they all threaten to disappear together. Where trade and manufactures are wanting to a people, and the spirit of nobility and religion remains, sentiment supplies, and not always ill supplies, their place; but if commerce and the arts should be lost in an experiment to try how well a state may stand without these old fundamental principles, what sort of a thing must be a nation of gross, stupid, ferocious, and at the same time poor and sordid barbarians, destitute of religion, honor, or manly pride, possessing nothing at present, and hoping for nothing hereafter?

If, as I think, modern writing owes more than it admits to ancient customs, so do other values we hold dear. Even commerce, trade, and manufacturing—the gods of our economic politicians—might just be their creations, mere outcomes that we choose to revere as the original causes. They certainly developed in the same environment where learning thrived. They, too, could decline with the basic principles that protect them. For now at least, they all seem threatened to fade away together. When a society lacks trade and manufacturing, but still retains a spirit of nobility and religion, sentiment often steps in and can sometimes do so effectively. However, if commerce and the arts were to vanish in a test of how well a state could function without these foundational principles, what kind of nation would emerge? A nation of crude, ignorant, violent, and at the same time impoverished and miserable barbarians, lacking in religion, honor, or dignity, owning nothing now and anticipating nothing in the future?

I wish you may not be going fast, and by the shortest cut, to that horrible and disgustful situation. Already there appears a poverty of conception, a coarseness and vulgarity, in all the proceedings of the Assembly and of all their instructors. Their liberty is not liberal. Their science is presumptuous ignorance. Their humanity is savage and brutal.

I hope you're not rushing into that awful and disgusting situation. There’s already a lack of imagination, a crudeness and vulgarity, in everything the Assembly and their leaders are doing. Their idea of freedom isn’t really free. Their knowledge is just arrogant ignorance. Their notion of humanity is savage and brutal.

It is not clear whether in England we learned those grand and decorous principles and manners, of which considerable traces yet remain, from you, or whether you took them from us. But to you, I think, we trace them best. You seem to me to be gentis incunabula nostræ. France has always more or less influenced manners in England; and when your fountain is choked up and polluted, the stream will not run long or not run clear with us, or perhaps with any nation. This gives all Europe, in my opinion, but too close and connected a concern in what is done in France. Excuse me, therefore, if I have dwelt too long on the atrocious spectacle of the sixth of October, 1789, or have given too much scope to the reflections which have arisen in my mind on occasion of the most important of all revolutions, which may be dated from that day: I mean a revolution in sentiments, manners, and moral opinions. As things now stand, with everything respectable destroyed without us, and an attempt to destroy within us every principle of respect, one is almost forced to apologize for harboring the common feelings of men.

It's unclear whether we picked up those grand and proper principles and manners that still linger in England from you, or if you got them from us. But I believe we can trace them back to you most clearly. To me, you are gentis incunabula nostræ. France has always had a certain influence on manners in England; and when your source is blocked and polluted, the flow won't last long or be clear with us, or perhaps with any nation. This, in my opinion, gives all of Europe too strong a connection to what's happening in France. So, I apologize if I've spent too much time on the horrific events of October 6, 1789, or if I’ve allowed too much reflection on what arose in my mind regarding the most significant revolution, which can be traced back to that day: I mean a revolution in sentiments, manners, and moral views. Given the current state of things, with everything respectable destroyed outside of us, and an effort to eliminate every principle of respect within us, one almost feels compelled to apologize for holding onto common human feelings.


Why do I feel so differently from the Reverend Dr. Price, and those of his lay flock who will choose to adopt the sentiments of his discourse?—For this plain reason: Because it is natural I should; because we are so made as to be affected at such spectacles with melancholy sentiments upon the unstable condition of mortal prosperity, and the tremendous uncertainty of human greatness; because in those natural feelings we learn great lessons; because in events like these our passions instruct our reason; because, when kings are hurled from their thrones by the Supreme Director of this great drama, and become the objects of insult to the base and of pity to the good, we behold such disasters in the moral as we should behold a miracle in the physical order of things. We are alarmed into reflection; our minds (as it has long since been observed) are purified by terror and pity; our weak, unthinking pride is humbled under the dispensations of a mysterious wisdom. Some tears might be drawn from me, if such a spectacle were exhibited on the stage. I should be truly ashamed of finding in myself that superficial, theatric sense of painted distress, whilst I could exult over it in real life. With such a perverted mind, I could never venture to show my face at a tragedy. People would think the tears that Garrick formerly, or that Siddons not long since, have extorted from me, were the tears of hypocrisy; I should know them to be the tears of folly.

Why do I feel so differently from Reverend Dr. Price and those in his congregation who decide to embrace his views?—For this simple reason: Because it’s natural for me to; because we are built to feel melancholy at such events regarding the fragile nature of human success and the terrifying unpredictability of greatness; because in those natural feelings, we learn important lessons; because in situations like these, our emotions guide our reasoning; because when kings are thrown from their thrones by the Supreme Director of this grand performance and become targets of scorn for the lowly and pity for the virtuous, we witness such tragedies morally just as we would see a miracle in the physical world. We are prompted to reflect; our minds (as has long been observed) are cleansed by fear and compassion; our fragile, thoughtless pride is humbled by a mysterious wisdom. I might shed tears if such a scene played out on stage. I would be genuinely ashamed to realize that I could feel that shallow, theatrical sense of fake sorrow while being able to celebrate it in real life. With such a warped perspective, I could never show my face at a tragedy. People would think the tears that Garrick once drew from me, or that Siddons evoked not long ago, were tears of insincerity; I would know them to be tears of foolishness.

Indeed, the theatre is a better school of moral sentiments than churches where the feelings of humanity are thus outraged. Poets who have to deal with an audience not yet graduated in the school of the rights of men, and who must apply themselves to the moral constitution of the heart, would not dare to produce such a triumph as a matter of exultation. There, where men follow their natural impulses, they would not bear the odious maxims of a Machiavelian policy, whether applied to the attainment of monarchical or democratic tyranny. They would reject them on the modern, as they once did on the ancient stage, where they could not bear even the hypothetical proposition of such wickedness in the mouth of a personated tyrant, though suitable to the character he sustained. No theatric audience in Athens would bear what has been borne in the midst of the real tragedy of this triumphal day: a principal actor weighing, as it were in scales hung in a shop of horrors, so much actual crime against so much contingent advantage,—and after putting in and out weights, declaring that the balance was on the side of the advantages. They would not bear to see the crimes of new democracy posted as in a ledger against the crimes of old despotism, and the book-keepers of politics finding democracy still in debt, but by no means unable or unwilling to pay the balance. In the theatre, the first intuitive glance, without any elaborate process of reasoning, would show that this method of political computation would justify every extent of crime. They would see, that, on these principles, even where the very worst acts were not perpetrated, it was owing rather to the fortune of the conspirators than to their parsimony in the expenditure of treachery and blood. They would soon see that criminal means, once tolerated, are soon preferred. They present a shorter cut to the object than through the highway of the moral virtues. Justifying perfidy and murder for public benefit, public benefit would soon become the pretext, and perfidy and murder the end,—until rapacity, malice, revenge, and fear more dreadful than revenge, could satiate their insatiable appetites. Such must be the consequences of losing, in the splendor of these triumphs of the rights of men, all natural sense of wrong and right.

The theater is actually a better school for moral values than churches, where human feelings are often disrespected. Poets, who are trying to connect with an audience that hasn’t yet learned about human rights, focus on the moral makeup of the heart. They wouldn’t dare celebrate such a victory. In a space where people act on their natural instincts, they wouldn’t tolerate the disgusting principles of a Machiavellian strategy, whether it leads to a monarchy or a democracy. They would reject such ideas, just like audiences did in ancient times, who couldn't even handle the mere suggestion of evil coming from a character portraying a tyrant, even if it made sense for that character. No audience in Athens would accept what we’ve tolerated amidst the real tragedy of today’s triumphant events: a leading performer weighing real crimes against possible benefits as if at a horror show, adjusting the scales and claiming the advantages win. They wouldn't want to see the wrongdoings of a new democracy added up against the offenses of an old tyranny, with political accountants finding democracy still owing, but capable and willing to pay up. In the theater, an immediate reaction would make it clear that such political calculations could justify any crime. They would realize that, based on these principles, even when the worst acts weren’t committed, it was more about the luck of the conspirators than their restraint in committing treachery and violence. It wouldn’t take long for them to see that once criminal methods are accepted, they quickly become the preferred choice. They offer a quicker way to achieve goals compared to the difficult path of moral virtues. Justifying betrayal and murder for the sake of the public good would soon turn public good into an excuse, with betrayal and murder as the real goal—until greed, malice, revenge, and a fear even worse than revenge satisfied their insatiable cravings. This is what happens when we lose all sense of right and wrong in the glow of these triumphs for human rights.

But the reverend pastor exults in this "leading in triumph," because, truly, Louis the Sixteenth was "an arbitrary monarch": that is, in other words, neither more nor less than because he was Louis the Sixteenth, and because he had the misfortune to be born king of France, with the prerogatives of which a long line of ancestors, and a long acquiescence of the people, without any act of his, had put him in possession. A misfortune it has indeed turned out to him, that he was born king of France. But misfortune is not crime, nor is indiscretion always the greatest guilt. I shall never think that a prince, the acts of whose whole reign were a series of concessions to his subjects, who was willing to relax his authority, to remit his prerogatives, to call his people to a share of freedom not known, perhaps not desired, by their ancestors,—such a prince, though he should be subject to the common frailties attached to men and to princes, though he should have once thought it necessary to provide force against the desperate designs manifestly carrying on against his person and the remnants of his authority,—though all this should be taken into consideration, I shall be led with great difficulty to think he deserves the cruel and insulting triumph of Paris, and of Dr. Price. I tremble for the cause of liberty, from such an example to kings. I tremble for the cause of humanity, in the unpunished outrages of the most wicked of mankind. But there are some people of that low and degenerate fashion of mind that they look up with a sort of complacent awe and admiration to kings who know to keep firm in their seat, to hold a strict hand over their subjects, to assert their prerogative, and, by the awakened vigilance of a severe despotism, to guard against the very first approaches of freedom. Against such as these they never elevate their voice. Deserters from principle, listed with fortune, they never see any good in suffering virtue, nor any crime in prosperous usurpation.

But the reverend pastor takes great pleasure in this "triumphant victory," because, honestly, Louis the Sixteenth was "an absolute monarch": in other words, just because he was Louis the Sixteenth, and because he unfortunately happened to be born as the king of France, with the rights that a long line of ancestors and the people's long acceptance—unrelated to any actions of his—had given him. It has indeed turned out to be a misfortune for him that he was born king of France. But misfortune is not a crime, nor is foolishness always the worst sin. I can never believe that a prince, whose entire reign was filled with concessions to his subjects, who was willing to ease his authority, give up some of his rights, and offer his people a share of freedom that maybe their ancestors didn’t even know about or desire—such a prince, even if he should be subject to the common flaws that come with being human and being a prince, even if he once thought it necessary to take measures against the desperate plots clearly aimed at him and the remnants of his power—taking all this into account, I would find it hard to believe he deserves the cruel and humiliating triumph in Paris and from Dr. Price. I worry for the cause of liberty because of such examples set for kings. I worry for the cause of humanity, given the unpunished acts of the worst individuals in society. Yet, there are some people with such a low and corrupt mindset that they look up to kings who know how to hold on to their power, maintain strict control over their subjects, assert their rights, and, through the watchful eye of harsh despotism, protect against the very first signs of freedom. They never raise their voices against figures like these. Traitors to principle and followers of fortune, they see no value in virtuous suffering and no crime in prosperous usurpation.

If it could have been made clear to me that the king and queen of France (those, I mean, who were such before the triumph) were inexorable and cruel tyrants, that they had formed a deliberate scheme for massacring the National Assembly, (I think I have seen something like the latter insinuated in certain publications,) I should think their captivity just. If this be true, much more ought to have been done, but done, in my opinion, in another manner. The punishment of real tyrants is a noble and awful act of justice; and it has with truth been said to be consolatory to the human mind. But if I were to punish a wicked king, I should regard the dignity in avenging the crime. Justice is grave and decorous, and in its punishments rather seems to submit to a necessity than to make a choice. Had Nero, or Agrippina, or Louis the Eleventh, or Charles the Ninth been the subject,—if Charles the Twelfth of Sweden, after the murder of Patkul, or his predecessor, Christina, after the murder of Monaldeschi, had fallen into your hands, Sir, or into mine, I am sure our conduct would have been different.

If it had been made clear to me that the king and queen of France (the ones who were in power before the triumph) were ruthless and cruel tyrants, and that they had a planned plot to massacre the National Assembly (I believe I have seen hints of this in some publications), I would consider their imprisonment justified. If this is true, far more should have been done, but in my view, it should have been done differently. Punishing real tyrants is a noble and serious act of justice; it has been rightly said to be comforting to the human spirit. However, if I were to punish an evil king, I would focus on the dignity involved in avenging the crime. Justice is serious and dignified, and in its punishments, it seems to yield to necessity rather than make a choice. If someone like Nero, Agrippina, Louis the Eleventh, or Charles the Ninth were involved—if Charles the Twelfth of Sweden, after Patkul's murder, or his predecessor, Christina, after Monaldeschi's murder, had fallen into your hands, Sir, or mine, I know our approach would have been different.

If the French king, or king of the French, (or by whatever name he is known in the new vocabulary of your Constitution,) has in his own person and that of his queen really deserved these unavowed, but unavenged, murderous attempts, and those frequent indignities more cruel than murder, such a person would ill deserve even that subordinate executory trust which I understand is to be placed in him; nor is he fit to be called chief in a nation which he has outraged and oppressed. A worse choice for such an office in a new commonwealth than that of a deposed tyrant could not possibly be made. But to degrade and insult a man as the worst of criminals, and afterwards to trust him in your highest concerns, as a faithful, honest, and zealous servant, is not consistent in reasoning, nor prudent in policy, nor safe in practice. Those who could make such an appointment must be guilty of a more flagrant breach of trust than any they have yet committed against the people. As this is the only crime in which your leading politicians could have acted inconsistently, I conclude that there is no sort of ground for these horrid insinuations. I think no better of all the other calumnies.

If the French king, or king of the French, (or whatever title he's referred to in the new language of your Constitution), genuinely deserves these hidden, yet unpunished, murderous attempts and those frequent humiliations that are more brutal than murder, then such a person does not even deserve the minor executive role that I understand is to be assigned to him; nor is he suited to be called the leader of a nation that he has disrespected and oppressed. There couldn't be a worse choice for such a position in a new commonwealth than a deposed tyrant. However, to belittle and insult a man as the worst kind of criminal and then expect him to handle your most important matters as a loyal, honest, and dedicated servant is neither logical in reasoning, nor wise in strategy, nor safe in practice. Those who could make such an appointment must be committing a greater betrayal of trust than any they have previously committed against the people. Since this is the only crime where your prominent politicians could act inconsistently, I believe there’s no basis for these horrific suggestions. I hold the same view regarding all the other slanders.

In England, we give no credit to them. We are generous enemies; we are faithful allies. We spurn from us with disgust and indignation the slanders of those who bring us their anecdotes with the attestation of the flower-de-luce on their shoulder. We have Lord George Gordon fast in Newgate; and neither his being a public proselyte to Judaism, nor his having, in his zeal against Catholic priests and all sorts of ecclesiastics, raised a mob (excuse the term, it is still in use here) which pulled down all our prisons, have preserved to him a liberty of which he did not render himself worthy by a virtuous use of it. We have rebuilt Newgate, and tenanted the mansion. We have prisons almost as strong as the Bastile, for those who dare to libel the queens of France. In this spiritual retreat let the noble libeller remain. Let him there meditate on his Talmud, until he learns a conduct more becoming his birth and parts, and not so disgraceful to the ancient religion to which he has become a proselyte,—or until some persons from your side of the water, to please your new Hebrew brethren, shall ransom him. He may then be enabled to purchase, with the old hoards of the synagogue, and a very small poundage on the long compound interest of the thirty pieces of silver, (Dr. Price has shown us what miracles compound interest will perform in 1790 years,) the lands which are lately discovered to have been usurped by the Gallican Church. Send us your Popish Archbishop of Paris, and we will send you our Protestant Rabbin. We shall treat the person you send us in exchange like a gentleman and an honest man, as he is: but pray let him bring with him the fund of his hospitality, bounty, and charity; and, depend upon it, we shall never confiscate a shilling of that honorable and pious fund, nor think of enriching the Treasury with the spoils of the poor-box.

In England, we don’t give them any credit. We are generous enemies and loyal allies. We reject with disgust and anger the slanders from those who come to us with their stories, badge displayed proudly on their shoulder. We have Lord George Gordon locked up in Newgate; and neither his public conversion to Judaism nor his instigation of a mob (forgive the term, it’s still in use here) that destroyed all our prisons has earned him the freedom he doesn't deserve by using it well. We have rebuilt Newgate and filled it with inmates. We have prisons as strong as the Bastille for those who dare to slander the queens of France. In this spiritual retreat, let the noble slanderer stay. Let him meditate on his Talmud until he learns behavior more fitting for his status and less shameful for the ancient faith he has converted to—or until some people from your side of the ocean, wanting to please your new Hebrew friends, manage to ransom him. He might then be able to buy back, with the old treasures of the synagogue and a tiny portion of the substantial compound interest on the thirty pieces of silver (Dr. Price has shown us what amazing things compound interest can do over 1790 years), the lands that have recently been revealed to have been taken over by the Gallican Church. Send us your Catholic Archbishop of Paris, and we’ll send you our Protestant Rabbi. We will treat the person you send to us in exchange like a gentleman and an honest man, as he is; but please let him bring with him the resources of hospitality, generosity, and charity; and rest assured, we will never seize a single penny of that honorable and charitable fund, nor will we consider enriching the Treasury with the spoils of the poor box.

To tell you the truth, my dear Sir, I think the honor of our nation to be somewhat concerned in the disclaimer of the proceedings of this society of the Old Jewry and the London Tavern. I have no man's proxy. I speak only from myself, when I disclaim, as I do with all possible earnestness, all communion with the actors in that triumph, or with the admirers of it. When I assert anything else, as concerning the people of England, I speak from observation, not from authority; but I speak from the experience I have had in a pretty extensive and mixed communication with the inhabitants of this kingdom, of all descriptions and ranks, and after a course of attentive observation, begun in early life, and continued for near forty years. I have often been astonished, considering that we are divided from you but by a slender dike of about twenty-four miles, and that the mutual intercourse between the two countries has lately been very great, to find how little you seem to know of us. I suspect that this is owing to your forming a judgment of this nation from certain publications, which do, very erroneously, if they do at all, represent the opinions and dispositions generally prevalent in England. The vanity, restlessness, petulance, and spirit of intrigue of several petty cabals, who attempt to hide their total want of consequence in bustle and noise, and puffing and mutual quotation of each other, makes you imagine that our contemptuous neglect of their abilities is a general mark of acquiescence in their opinions. No such thing, I assure you. Because half a dozen grasshoppers under a fern make the field ring with their importunate chink, whilst thousands of great cattle reposed beneath the shadow of the British oak chew the cud and are silent, pray do not imagine that those who make the noise are the only inhabitants of the field,—that, of course, they are many in number,—or that, after all, they are other than the little, shrivelled, meagre, hopping, though loud and troublesome insects of the hour.

To be honest, my dear Sir, I think our nation's reputation is somewhat affected by the disavowal of the actions of this society at the Old Jewry and the London Tavern. I don't have anyone's proxy. I speak solely for myself when I firmly deny any connection with those involved in that celebration, or with its supporters. When I talk about other matters concerning the people of England, I base my comments on observation rather than authority; however, my views come from extensive and varied interactions with people from all walks of life in this country, built on nearly forty years of attentive observation starting from my early years. I have often been surprised, given that we are only separated by a narrow stretch of around twenty-four miles and our countries have interacted quite a bit recently, at how little you seem to understand about us. I suspect this stems from your forming opinions about our nation based on certain publications that very inaccurately, if at all, reflect the general views and sentiments prevalent in England. The vanity, restlessness, irritability, and scheming antics of several small groups, who try to mask their complete lack of significance through noise and commotion, lead you to think that our dismissive indifference to their capabilities is a sign of agreement with their views. That’s not the case, I assure you. Just because a handful of grasshoppers under a fern make a racket with their persistent chirping, while thousands of large cattle resting in the shade of the British oak quietly chew their cud, please don’t assume that those making noise are the only ones in the field—nor that they are numerous—nor that they are anything more than the small, shriveled, noisy, and bothersome insects of the moment.

I almost venture to affirm that not one in a hundred amongst us participates in the "triumph" of the Revolution Society. If the king and queen of France and their children were to fall into our hands by the chance of war, in the most acrimonious of all hostilities, (I deprecate such an event, I deprecate such hostility,) they would be treated with another sort of triumphal entry into London. We formerly have had a king of France in that situation: you have read how he was treated by the victor in the field, and in what manner he was afterwards received in England. Four hundred years have gone over us; but I believe we are not materially changed since that period. Thanks to our sullen resistance to innovation, thanks to the cold sluggishness of our national character, we still bear the stamp of our forefathers. We have not (as I conceive) lost the generosity and dignity of thinking of the fourteenth century; nor as yet have we subtilized ourselves into savages. We are not the converts of Rousseau; we are not the disciples of Voltaire; Helvetius has made no progress amongst us. Atheists are not our preachers; madmen are not our lawgivers. We know that we have made no discoveries, and we think that no discoveries are to be made, in morality,—nor many in the great principles of government, nor in the ideas of liberty, which were understood long before we were born altogether as well as they will be after the grave has heaped its mould upon our presumption, and the silent tomb shall have imposed its law on our pert loquacity. In England we have not yet been completely embowelled of our natural entrails: we still feel within us, and we cherish and cultivate, those inbred sentiments which are the faithful guardians, the active monitors of our duty, the true supporters of all liberal and manly morals. We have not been drawn and trussed, in order that we may be filled, like stuffed birds in a museum, with chaff and rags, and paltry, blurred shreds of paper about the rights of man. We preserve the whole of our feelings still native and entire, unsophisticated by pedantry and infidelity. We have real hearts of flesh and blood beating in our bosoms. We fear God; we look up with awe to kings, with affection to Parliaments, with duty to magistrates, with reverence to priests, and with respect to nobility.[94] Why? Because, when such ideas are brought before our minds, it is natural to be so affected; because all other feelings are false and spurious, and tend to corrupt our minds, to vitiate our primary morals, to render us unfit for rational liberty, and, by teaching us a servile, licentious, and abandoned insolence, to be our low sport for a few holidays, to make us perfectly fit for and justly deserving of slavery through the whole course of our lives.

I almost dare to say that not one in a hundred of us shares in the "triumph" of the Revolution Society. If the king and queen of France and their children were to fall into our hands during the fiercest of wars (and I hope such an event never happens, I hope for no such hostility), they would be welcomed with a very different kind of triumphant entry into London. We have previously had a king of France in that situation: you’ve read how he was treated by the victor on the battlefield and how he was later received in England. Four hundred years have passed, but I believe we haven’t changed much since then. Thanks to our stubborn resistance to change and the cold indifference of our national character, we still carry the legacy of our ancestors. We have not, as I see it, lost the generosity and dignity of the fourteenth century; nor have we degraded ourselves into savages. We are not followers of Rousseau; we are not disciples of Voltaire; Helvetius has made no headway among us. Atheists are not our preachers; lunatics are not our lawmakers. We know that we have made no breakthroughs, and we believe that no breakthroughs are to be made in morality—or many in the fundamental principles of government, nor in the concepts of liberty, which were clearly understood long before we were born and will still be understood after the grave has covered our pride and the silent tomb has imposed its law on our incessant chatter. In England, we haven’t yet been completely stripped of our natural instincts: we still feel within us, and we cherish and nurture, those deep-rooted sentiments that are the true guardians, the active guides of our duty, and the genuine supporters of all noble and manly morals. We haven’t been drawn and tied up just to be stuffed, like taxidermy birds in a museum, with nonsense and scraps of paper about human rights. We retain all our feelings, still natural and intact, unsophisticated by pedantry and skepticism. We have real hearts of flesh and blood beating in our chests. We fear God; we look up to kings with respect, to Parliaments with affection, to magistrates with a sense of duty, to priests with reverence, and to nobility with respect. Why? Because, when such ideas come to mind, it is natural to feel this way; because all other feelings are false and counterfeit, and tend to corrupt our minds, distort our fundamental morals, make us unfit for true liberty, and, by teaching us a servile, reckless, and disrespectful arrogance, prepare us to be justly deserving of slavery throughout our lives.

You see, Sir, that in this enlightened age I am bold enough to confess that we are generally men of untaught feelings: that, instead of casting away all our old prejudices, we cherish them to a very considerable degree; and, to take more shame to ourselves, we cherish them because they are prejudices; and the longer they have lasted, and the more generally they have prevailed, the more we cherish them. We are afraid to put men to live and trade each on his own private stock of reason; because we suspect that the stock in each man is small, and that the individuals would do better to avail themselves of the general bank and capital of nations and of ages. Many of our men of speculation, instead of exploding general prejudices, employ their sagacity to discover the latent wisdom which prevails in them. If they find what they seek, (and they seldom fail,) they think it more wise to continue the prejudice, with the reason involved, than to cast away the coat of prejudice, and to leave nothing but the naked reason; because prejudice, with its reason, has a motive to give action to that reason, and an affection which will give it permanence. Prejudice is of ready application in the emergency; it previously engages the mind in a steady course of wisdom and virtue, and does not leave the man hesitating in the moment of decision, skeptical, puzzled, and unresolved. Prejudice renders a man's virtue his habit, and not a series of unconnected acts. Through just prejudice, his duty becomes a part of his nature.

You see, Sir, in this enlightened age, I’m bold enough to admit that we are mostly people of unrefined emotions: instead of discarding our old biases, we hold onto them quite fiercely; and, to our shame, we value them specifically because they are biases. The longer they’ve persisted and the more common they are, the more we cling to them. We hesitate to let individuals live and trade based on their own personal reasoning; we worry that each person's reasoning is limited, and that people would be better off relying on the collective knowledge and resources of nations and generations. Many of our thinkers, rather than challenging widespread biases, use their insight to uncover the hidden wisdom behind them. If they find what they’re looking for (which they usually do), they believe it’s wiser to uphold the bias, along with its reasoning, than to discard the bias and only rely on bare reasoning; because bias, along with its reasoning, provides a motivation to act upon that reasoning, and an emotional attachment that gives it permanence. Bias is readily applicable in emergencies; it keeps the mind engaged in a steady path of wisdom and virtue, and prevents a person from hesitating during critical decisions, feeling skeptical, confused, and uncertain. Bias turns a person's virtue into a habit rather than a collection of disconnected acts. Through appropriate bias, their duty becomes part of who they are.

Your literary men, and your politicians, and so do the whole clan of the enlightened among us, essentially differ in these points. They have no respect for the wisdom of others; but they pay it off by a very full measure of confidence in their own. With them it is a sufficient motive to destroy an old scheme of things, because it is an old one. As to the new, they are in no sort of fear with regard to the duration of a building run up in haste; because duration is no object to those who think little or nothing has been done before their time, and who place all their hopes in discovery. They conceive, very systematically, that all things which give perpetuity are mischievous, and therefore they are at inexpiable war with all establishments. They think that government may vary like modes of dress, and with as little ill effect; that there needs no principle of attachment, except a sense of present conveniency, to any constitution of the state. They always speak as if they were of opinion that there is a singular species of compact between them and their magistrates, which binds the magistrate, but which has nothing reciprocal in it, but that the majesty of the people has a right to dissolve it without any reason but its will. Their attachment to their country itself is only so far as it agrees with some of their fleeting projects: it begins and ends with that scheme of polity which falls in with their momentary opinion.

Your writers, politicians, and all the so-called enlightened people among us essentially differ in a few key ways. They have no respect for the wisdom of others; instead, they hold an overwhelming confidence in their own. For them, it's enough motivation to dismantle an old system just because it's old. When it comes to the new, they aren't worried at all about how long a hastily built structure will last; because to those who believe little has been achieved before their time, duration doesn’t matter, and they place all their hopes in discovery. They systematically believe that anything designed to last permanently is harmful, and that’s why they are in a relentless conflict with all established systems. They think government can change like fashion, and with as little negative impact; that there’s no need for any principle of loyalty to any political system except for a sense of immediate convenience. They always talk as if they believe there’s a unique agreement between them and their leaders, which binds the leaders but has no reciprocal obligation, other than that the majesty of the people has the right to dissolve it for any reason based solely on their will. Their loyalty to their country extends only as far as it aligns with some of their passing projects: it begins and ends with whatever political scheme aligns with their current beliefs.

These doctrines, or rather sentiments, seem prevalent with your new statesmen. But they are wholly different from those on which we have always acted in this country.

These beliefs, or rather feelings, seem common among your new politicians. But they are completely different from those we've always operated on in this country.

I hear it is sometimes given out in France, that what is doing among you is after the example of England. I beg leave to affirm that scarcely anything done with you has originated from the practice or the prevalent opinions of this people, either in the act or in the spirit of the proceeding. Let me add, that we are as unwilling to learn these lessons from France as we are sure that we never taught them to that nation. The cabals here who take a sort of share in your transactions as yet consist of but a handful of people. If, unfortunately, by their intrigues, their sermons, their publications, and by a confidence derived from an expected union with the counsels and forces of the French nation, they should draw considerable numbers into their faction, and in consequence should seriously attempt anything here in imitation of what has been done with you, the event, I dare venture to prophesy, will be, that, with some trouble to their country, they will soon accomplish their own destruction. This people refused to change their law in remote ages from respect to the infallibility of Popes, and they will not now alter it from a pious implicit faith in the dogmatism of philosophers,—though the former was armed with the anathema and crusade, and though the latter should act with the libel and the lamp-iron.

I hear that it’s sometimes said in France that what is happening among you is based on what’s happening in England. I’d like to assert that hardly anything you’re doing has come from the practices or beliefs of this people, either in actions or in the spirit behind them. Let me also add that we are as unwilling to learn these lessons from France as we are certain that we never taught them to that nation. The groups here that are trying to influence your actions consist of only a small number of people. If, unfortunately, their schemes, sermons, publications, and confidence from an expected alliance with the French nation should attract a significant following to their cause, and as a result, they seriously try to replicate what has been done with you, I dare say that the outcome will be that, with some trouble for their country, they will quickly bring about their own downfall. This people refused to change their laws in ancient times out of respect for the infallibility of Popes, and they will not change them now out of a blind faith in the doctrines of philosophers — even though the former had the power of excommunication and crusades, and the latter may speak with slander and threats.

Formerly your affairs were your own concern only. We felt for them as men; but we kept aloof from them, because we were not citizens of France. But when we see the model held up to ourselves, we must feel as Englishmen, and, feeling, we must provide as Englishmen. Your affairs, in spite of us, are made a part of our interest,—so far at least as to keep at a distance your panacea or your plague. If it be a panacea, we do not want it: we know the consequences of unnecessary physic. If it be a plague, it is such a plague that the precautions of the most severe quarantine ought to be established against it.

Before, your issues were only your own. We cared about them as people, but we stayed away from them because we were not citizens of France. However, when we see the example set before us, we have to feel as Englishmen, and with that feeling, we must act as Englishmen. Your matters, whether you like it or not, have become part of our concern—at least enough to keep your cure or your disaster at arm's length. If it's a cure, we don’t want it; we know the risks of taking unnecessary medicine. If it's a disaster, it's such a disaster that the strictest quarantine measures should be put in place against it.

I hear on all hands, that a cabal, calling itself philosophic, receives the glory of many of the late proceedings, and that their opinions and systems are the true actuating spirit of the whole of them. I have heard of no party in England, literary or political, at any time, known by such a description. It is not with you composed of those men, is it? whom the vulgar, in their blunt, homely style, commonly call Atheists and Infidels? If it be, I admit that we, too, have had writers of that description, who made some noise in their day. At present they repose in lasting oblivion. Who, born within the last forty years, has read one word of Collins, and Toland, and Tindal, and Chubb, and Morgan, and that whole race who called themselves Freethinkers? Who now reads Bolingbroke? Who ever read him through? Ask the booksellers of London what is become of all these lights of the world. In as few years their few successors will go to the family vault of "all the Capulets." But whatever they were, or are, with us they were and are wholly unconnected individuals. With us they kept the common nature of their kind, and were not gregarious. They never acted in corps, nor were known as a faction in the state, nor presumed to influence in that name or character, or for the purposes of such a faction, on any of our public concerns. Whether they ought so to exist, and so be permitted to act, is another question. As such cabals have not existed in England, so neither has the spirit of them had any influence in establishing the original frame of our Constitution, or in any one of the several reparations and improvements it has undergone. The whole has been done under the auspices, and is confirmed by the sanctions, of religion and piety. The whole has emanated from the simplicity of our national character, and from a sort of native plainness and directness of understanding, which for a long time characterized those men who have successively obtained authority among us. This disposition still remains,—at least in the great body of the people.

I hear everywhere that a group calling itself philosophical is claiming credit for many recent events, and that their beliefs and systems are what truly drive all of it. I've never heard of any literary or political party in England described like that at any time. It's not you guys composed of those individuals whom most people, in their straightforward way, call Atheists and Infidels, is it? If so, I acknowledge that we, too, have had writers like that who made some noise in their time. Now, they rest in lasting obscurity. Who born in the last forty years has read even a word from Collins, Toland, Tindal, Chubb, Morgan, or that entire group who called themselves Freethinkers? Who reads Bolingbroke now? Who has ever read him from start to finish? Ask the booksellers in London what has happened to all these supposed lights of the world. In just a few years, their few successors will join the family vault of "all the Capulets." But whatever they were or are, they have always been completely unconnected individuals with us. They had the common nature of their kind and were not a united group. They never acted together, were not recognized as a faction in the state, and never claimed to influence our public affairs in that name or character. Whether they should exist and be allowed to act is a different question. Since such groups haven’t existed in England, neither has their spirit influenced the founding of our Constitution or any of the various repairs and improvements it has undergone. Everything has been done under the guidance and is confirmed by the principles of religion and piety. All of it has come from the simplicity of our national character and from a kind of inherent straightforwardness and clarity of understanding that for a long time distinguished those who have held authority among us. This tendency still exists—at least within the majority of the people.

We know, and, what is better, we feel inwardly, that religion is the basis of civil society, and the source of all good, and of all comfort.[95] In England we are so convinced of this, that there is no rust of superstition, with which the accumulated absurdity of the human mind might have crusted it over in the course of ages, that ninety-nine in a hundred of the people of England would not prefer to impiety. We shall never be such fools as to call in an enemy to the substance of any system to remove its corruptions, to supply its defects, or to perfect its construction. If our religious tenets should ever want a further elucidation, we shall not call on Atheism to explain them. We shall not light up our temple from that unhallowed fire. It will be illuminated with other lights. It will be perfumed with other incense than the infectious stuff which is imported by the smugglers of adulterated metaphysics. If our ecclesiastical establishment should want a revision, it is not avarice or rapacity, public or private, that we shall employ for the audit or receipt or application of its consecrated revenue. Violently condemning neither the Greek nor the Armenian, nor, since heats are subsided, the Roman system of religion, we prefer the Protestant: not because we think it has less of the Christian religion in it, but because, in our judgment, it has more. We are Protestants, not from indifference, but from zeal.

We know, and even more importantly, we feel deeply that religion is the foundation of civil society and the source of all goodness and comfort. [95] In England, we are so convinced of this that no amount of superstition, which the accumulated nonsense of humanity might have thickened over the years, would lead ninety-nine out of a hundred people in England to choose to be irreligious. We would never be foolish enough to invite an enemy of any system to fix its problems, address its shortcomings, or improve its structure. If our religious beliefs ever need more clarity, we won’t turn to Atheism for an explanation. We won't light our temple with that unholy fire. It will be illuminated by other lights. It will be scented with other incense than the tainted stuff brought in by the smugglers of distorted philosophy. If our church establishment needs reviewing, it certainly won't be greed or selfishness, whether public or private, that will govern the handling of its sacred funds. While we don’t harshly criticize the Greek, Armenian, or, now that tensions have settled, the Roman systems of religion, we prefer the Protestant faith—not because we believe it contains less of Christianity, but because we think it embodies more. We are Protestants, not out of indifference, but out of passion.

We know, and it is our pride to know, that man is by his constitution a religious animal; that atheism is against, not only our reason, but our instincts; and that it cannot prevail long. But if, in the moment of riot, and in a drunken delirium from the hot spirit drawn out of the alembic of hell, which in France is now so furiously boiling, we should uncover our nakedness, by throwing off that Christian religion which has hitherto been our boast and comfort, and one great source of civilization amongst us, and among many other nations, we are apprehensive (being well aware that the mind will not endure a void) that some uncouth, pernicious, and degrading superstition might take place of it.

We know, and we're proud to know, that humans are inherently religious beings; that atheism goes against not just our reason, but our instincts as well; and that it can't last for long. However, if in a moment of chaos, fueled by the strong drink poured from the depths of hell, which is currently boiling over in France, we were to expose our vulnerability by rejecting the Christian faith that has been our pride and comfort, and a major source of civilization for us and many other nations, we fear (understanding that the mind can't tolerate emptiness) that some strange, harmful, and degrading superstition might take its place.

For that reason, before we take from our establishment the natural, human means of estimation, and give it up to contempt, as you have done, and in doing it have incurred the penalties you well deserve to suffer, we desire that some other may be presented to us in the place of it. We shall then form our judgment.

For that reason, before we dismiss the natural, human way of judging and give it up to scorn, like you have, and in doing so face the consequences you rightfully deserve, we ask that another option be presented to us instead. We will then make our decision.

On these ideas, instead of quarrelling with establishments, as some do, who have made a philosophy and a religion of their hostility to such institutions, we cleave closely to them. We are resolved to keep an established church, an established monarchy, an established aristocracy, and an established democracy, each in the degree it exists, and in no greater. I shall show you presently how much of each of these we possess.

On these ideas, rather than arguing with institutions, like some do who have turned their resentment towards them into a philosophy and religion, we stick closely to them. We’re committed to maintaining an established church, an established monarchy, an established aristocracy, and an established democracy, each to the extent that it exists, and not more. I will soon show you how much of each of these we have.

It has been the misfortune (not, as these gentlemen think it, the glory) of this age, that everything is to be discussed, as if the Constitution of our country were to be always a subject rather of altercation than enjoyment. For this reason, as well as for the satisfaction of those among you (if any such you have among you) who may wish to profit of examples, I venture to trouble you with a few thoughts upon each of these establishments. I do not think they were unwise in ancient Rome, who, when they wished to new-model their laws, sent commissioners to examine the best-constituted republics within their reach.

It has been the unfortunate situation (not, as these gentlemen believe, the glory) of our time that everything is up for debate, as if the Constitution of our country should always be a topic of conflict rather than enjoyment. For this reason, as well as to satisfy those among you (if any such people exist) who may want to learn from examples, I’m going to share a few thoughts on each of these institutions. I don't think those in ancient Rome were foolish when they wanted to redesign their laws by sending commissioners to study the best-run republics they could find.


First I beg leave to speak of our Church Establishment, which is the first of our prejudices,—not a prejudice destitute of reason, but involving in it profound and extensive wisdom. I speak of it first. It is first, and last, and midst in our minds. For, taking ground on that religious system of which we are now in possession, we continue to act on the early received and uniformly continued sense of mankind. That sense not only, like a wise architect, hath built up the august fabric of states, but, like a provident proprietor, to preserve the structure from profanation and ruin, as a sacred temple, purged from all the impurities of fraud and violence and injustice and tyranny, hath solemnly and forever consecrated the commonwealth, and all that officiate in it. This consecration is made, that all who administer in the government of men, in which they stand in the person of God Himself, should have high and worthy notions of their function and destination; that their hope should be full of immortality; that they should not look to the paltry pelf of the moment, nor to the temporary and transient praise of the vulgar, but to a solid, permanent existence, in the permanent part of their nature, and to a permanent fame and glory, in the example they leave as a rich inheritance to the world.

First, I want to discuss our Church Establishment, which is the first of our biases—not a bias without reason, but one that holds deep and wide wisdom. I mention it first because it is the first, last, and main thing on our minds. Grounded in the religious system we currently hold, we act on the early _____ received and consistently upheld understanding of humanity. That understanding has not only, like a skilled architect, built the grand structure of our states, but, like a diligent owner, has worked to protect the structure from desecration and decay, treating it as a sacred space, free from the impurities of fraud, violence, injustice, and tyranny, and has solemnly and forever consecrated the commonwealth and everyone who serves in it. This consecration ensures that all who govern, representing God Himself, hold noble and worthy ideas about their role and purpose; that their hopes are filled with the promise of immortality; that they do not chase after the insignificant rewards of the moment or the fleeting praise of the masses, but instead aspire for a true, lasting existence, recognizing the enduring nature of their essence, and seek a lasting legacy and glory through the example they set as a valuable inheritance for the world.

Such sublime principles ought to be infused into persons of exalted situations, and religious establishments provided that may continually revive and enforce them. Every sort of moral, every sort of civil, every sort of politic institution, aiding the rational and natural ties that connect the human understanding and affections to the divine, are not more than necessary, in order to build up that wonderful structure, Man,—whose prerogative it is, to be in a great degree a creature of his own making, and who, when made as he ought to be made, is destined to hold no trivial place in the creation. But whenever man is put over men, as the better nature ought ever to preside, in that case more particularly he should as nearly as possible be approximated to his perfection.

Such noble principles should be instilled in people of high status and in religious institutions that can consistently revive and promote them. Every type of moral, civil, and political institution that supports the rational and natural connections between human understanding, feelings, and the divine is essential for building that remarkable structure, Man—who has the unique ability to largely shape his own existence, and when developed as he should be, is meant to hold a significant place in creation. However, when one person is placed in authority over others, as a better nature should always lead, he should be as close to his ideal self as possible.

The consecration of the state by a state religious establishment is necessary also to operate with a wholesome awe upon free citizens; because, in order to secure their freedom, they must enjoy some determinate portion of power. To them, therefore, a religion connected with the state, and with their duty towards it, becomes even more necessary than in such societies where the people, by the terms of their subjection, are confined to private sentiments, and the management of their own family concerns. All persons possessing any portion of power ought to be strongly and awfully impressed with an idea that they act in trust, and that they are to account for their conduct in that trust to the one great Master, Author, and Founder of society.

The state's endorsement by a religious institution is important for instilling a healthy respect among free citizens; to maintain their freedom, they need to hold a definite amount of power. For these citizens, a religion tied to the state and their responsibilities towards it becomes even more crucial than in societies where people, due to their subservience, are limited to personal beliefs and managing their family matters. Everyone with any degree of power should be profoundly aware that they are acting in trust and will need to answer for their actions in that trust to the one ultimate Master, Creator, and Builder of society.

This principle ought even to be more strongly impressed upon the minds of those who compose the collective sovereignty than upon those of single princes. Without instruments, these princes can do nothing. Whoever uses instruments, in finding helps, finds also impediments. Their power is therefore by no means complete; nor are they safe in extreme abuse. Such persons, however elevated by flattery, arrogance, and self-opinion, must be sensible, that, whether covered or not by positive law, in some way or other they are accountable even here for the abuse of their trust. If they are not cut off by a rebellion of their people, they may be strangled by the very janissaries kept for their security against all other rebellion. Thus we have seen the king of France sold by his soldiers for an increase of pay. But where popular authority is absolute and unrestrained, the people have an infinitely greater, because a far better founded, confidence in their own power. They are themselves in a great measure their own instruments. They are nearer to their objects. Besides, they are less under responsibility to one of the greatest controlling powers on earth, the sense of fame and estimation. The share of infamy that is likely to fall to the lot of each individual in public acts is small indeed: the operation of opinion being in the inverse ratio to the number of those who abuse power. Their own approbation of their own acts has to them the appearance of a public judgment in their favor. A perfect democracy is therefore the most shameless thing in the world. As it is the most shameless, it is also the most fearless. No man apprehends in his person that he can be made subject to punishment. Certainly the people at large never ought: for, as all punishments are for example towards the conservation of the people at large, the people at large can never become the subject of punishment by any human hand.[96] It is therefore of infinite importance that they should not be suffered to imagine that their will, any more than that of kings, is the standard of right and wrong. They ought to be persuaded that they are full as little entitled, and far less qualified, with safety to themselves, to use any arbitrary power whatsoever; that therefore they are not, under a false show of liberty, but in truth to exercise an unnatural, inverted domination, tyrannically to exact from those who officiate in the state, not an entire devotion to their interest, which is their right, but an abject submission to their occasional will: extinguishing thereby, in all those who serve them, all moral principle, all sense of dignity, all use of judgment, and all consistency of character; whilst by the very same process they give themselves up a proper, a suitable, but a most contemptible prey to the servile ambition of popular sycophants or courtly flatterers.

This principle should be even more strongly emphasized for those who make up the collective authority than for individual leaders. Without tools, these leaders can achieve nothing. Whoever uses tools, in seeking help, also encounters obstacles. Their power is, therefore, far from complete; nor are they safe from extreme misuse. Those who are elevated by flattery, arrogance, and self-importance must realize that, whether backed by positive law or not, they are somehow accountable here for misusing their trust. If they aren't overthrown by a rebellion from their people, they could be betrayed by the very guards hired to protect them from other rebellions. We've seen the king of France sold out by his soldiers for a pay raise. However, when the people have absolute and unrestricted power, they have a much greater and better-founded confidence in their own strength. They are, to a large extent, their own tools. They are closer to their goals. Additionally, they are less bound by one of the greatest controlling forces on earth — public opinion and reputation. The amount of shame likely to fall on any individual for public actions is quite minimal; the effects of opinion diminish as the number of power abusers increases. Their self-approval of their actions feels like public support to them. A true democracy is therefore the most shameless thing imaginable. Being the most shameless, it is also the most fearless. No one fears punishment for themselves. Certainly, the general population should never fear it: as all punishments serve as examples for the preservation of the general public, they can never be subject to punishment by any human hand. It is therefore crucial that they do not think their will, any more than that of kings, is the measure of right and wrong. They should be convinced that they are just as unqualified, and far less safe, to wield any arbitrary power; thus, they are not exercising a genuine freedom but are instead enacting an unnatural, inverted dominance, tyrannically demanding not full loyalty to their interests—which is their right—but complete submission to their occasional whims. This makes them strip all those who serve them of moral principles, dignity, judgment, and consistency. In the same way, they become a proper, suitable, but utterly contemptible target for the servile ambitions of popular sycophants or courtly flatterers.

When the people have emptied themselves of all the lust of selfish will, which without religion it is utterly impossible they ever should,—when they are conscious that they exercise, and exercise perhaps in a higher link of the order of delegation, the power which to be legitimate must be according to that eternal, immutable law in which will and reason are the same,—they will be more careful how they place power in base and incapable hands. In their nomination to office, they will not appoint to the exercise of authority as to a pitiful job, but as to a holy function; not according to their sordid, selfish interest, nor to their wanton caprice, nor to their arbitrary will; but they will confer that power (which any man may well tremble to give or to receive) on those only in whom they may discern that predominant proportion of active virtue and wisdom, taken together and fitted to the charge, such as in the great and inevitable mixed mass of human imperfections and infirmities is to be found.

When people let go of all the selfish desires that come without religion, which is really impossible without it, they will realize that they hold power that must be legitimate according to that eternal, unchanging law where will and reason are aligned. They will be more careful about putting power in unworthy and incapable hands. When nominating someone for office, they won't treat the authority like a trivial job, but as a sacred duty; they won’t act based on their greedy self-interests, arbitrary whims, or random choices. They will only give that power—something that anyone might justifiably fear giving or receiving—to those who show a strong combination of active virtue and wisdom, suitable for the responsibility, amidst the inevitable imperfections and weaknesses of humanity.

When they are habitually convinced that no evil can be acceptable, either in the act or the permission, to Him whose essence is good, they will be better able to extirpate out of the minds of all magistrates, civil, ecclesiastical, or military, anything that bears the least resemblance to a proud and lawless domination.

When they are consistently convinced that no evil can be acceptable, whether in action or in allowance, to Him whose nature is good, they will be better equipped to remove from the minds of all authorities, whether civil, religious, or military, anything that resembles prideful and unlawful control.

But one of the first and most leading principles on which the commonwealth and the laws are consecrated is lest the temporary possessors and life-renters in it, unmindful of what they have received from their ancestors, or of what is due to their posterity, should act as if they were the entire masters; that they should not think it amongst their rights to cut off the entail or commit waste on the inheritance, by destroying at their pleasure the whole original fabric of their society: hazarding to leave to those who come after them a ruin instead of an habitation,—and teaching these successors as little to respect their contrivances as they had themselves respected the institutions of their forefathers. By this unprincipled facility of changing the state as often and as much and in as many ways as there are floating fancies or fashions, the whole chain and continuity of the commonwealth would be broken; no one generation could link with the other; men would become little better than the flies of a summer.

But one of the first and most important principles on which the government and the laws stand is to prevent temporary holders and life tenants from disregarding what they have received from their ancestors or what is owed to future generations. They shouldn't act as if they are the sole owners; they shouldn't believe they have the right to sever the inheritance or waste it by destroying the entire foundation of their society at will. This reckless behavior risks leaving future generations with ruins instead of a home, teaching them to value their creations as little as they valued the institutions established by their ancestors. If changes to the system could be made as frequently and in as many ways as current trends or whims, the entire continuity and chain of the commonwealth would be broken; no generation would have a connection to the next, and people would become little more than ephemeral creatures.

And first of all, the science of jurisprudence, the pride of the human intellect, which, with all its defects, redundancies, and errors, is the collected reason of ages, combining the principles of original justice with the infinite variety of human concerns, as a heap of old exploded errors, would be no longer studied. Personal self-sufficiency and arrogance (the certain attendants upon all those who have never experienced a wisdom greater than their own) would usurp the tribunal. Of course no certain laws, establishing invariable grounds of hope and fear, would keep the actions of men in a certain course, or direct them to a certain end. Nothing stable in the modes of holding property or exercising function could form a solid ground on which any parent could speculate in the education of his offspring, or in a choice for their future establishment in the world. No principles would be early worked into the habits. As soon as the most able instructor had completed his laborious course of institution, instead of sending forth his pupil accomplished in a virtuous discipline fitted to procure him attention and respect in his place in society, he would find everything altered, and that he had turned out a poor creature to the contempt and derision of the world, ignorant of the true grounds of estimation. Who would insure a tender and delicate sense of honor to beat almost with the first pulses of the heart, when no man could know what would be the test of honor in a nation continually varying the standard of its coin? No part of life would retain its acquisitions. Barbarism with regard to science and literature, unskilfulness with regard to arts and manufactures, would infallibly succeed to the want of a steady education and settled principle; and thus the commonwealth itself would in a few generations crumble away, be disconnected into the dust and powder of individuality, and at length dispersed to all the winds of heaven.

And first, the study of law, the pride of human intellect, which, despite its flaws, redundancies, and mistakes, represents the collective wisdom of ages, merging the principles of original justice with the endless variety of human interests, like a pile of old, discredited errors, would cease to be pursued. Personal independence and arrogance (common traits of those who have never known a wisdom beyond their own) would take over the courts. Naturally, there would be no consistent laws providing unchanging grounds for hope and fear to guide people's actions in a specific direction or toward a particular outcome. Nothing stable regarding how to hold property or perform duties could offer a solid basis for any parent to plan their children's education or future paths in life. No principles would be ingrained into habits. As soon as the best teacher finished their demanding curriculum, instead of sending out a student equipped with the virtuous skills needed to gain attention and respect in society, they would find everything changed, and that they had produced a failure, subject to the scorn and ridicule of the world, clueless about the true standards of value. Who could guarantee a sensitive and refined sense of honor that would start beating with the first heartbeats, when no one could know what the standard of honor would be in a nation constantly changing the yardstick? No part of life would hold onto its gains. A regression in science and literature, lack of skill in arts and crafts, would surely follow the absence of stable education and fixed principles; and thus, the very society itself would, in just a few generations, disintegrate, scattering into the dust of individualism, ultimately blown away by the winds of fate.

To avoid, therefore, the evils of inconstancy and versatility, ten thousand times worse than those of obstinacy and the blindest prejudice, we have consecrated the state, that no man should approach to look into its defects or corruptions but with due caution; that he should never dream of beginning its reformation by its subversion; that he should approach to the faults of the state as to the wounds of a father, with pious awe and trembling solicitude. By this wise prejudice we are taught to look with horror on those children of their country who are prompt rashly to hack that aged parent in pieces and put him into the kettle of magicians, in hopes that by their poisonous weeds and wild incantations they may regenerate the paternal constitution and renovate their father's life.

To avoid the problems of inconsistency and unpredictability—things far worse than stubbornness and extreme bias—we have dedicated ourselves to the state. No one should examine its flaws or corruption without caution; they should never think about starting its reform by tearing it down. When addressing the state's faults, they should do so with the same care and respect as one would for a parent's wounds, with reverence and heartfelt concern. This wise mindset teaches us to look with horror at those citizens who hastily want to chop up that aged parent and throw them into the pot of sorcerers, hoping that through their toxic plants and wild spells, they can restore the family's constitution and revive their father's life.

Society is, indeed, a contract. Subordinate contracts for objects of mere occasional interest may be dissolved at pleasure; but the state ought not to be considered as nothing better than a partnership agreement in a trade of pepper and coffee, calico or tobacco, or some other such low concern, to be taken up for a little temporary interest, and to be dissolved by the fancy of the parties. It is to be looked on with other reverence; because it is not a partnership in things subservient only to the gross animal existence of a temporary and perishable nature. It is a partnership in all science, a partnership in all art, a partnership in every virtue and in all perfection. As the ends of such a partnership cannot be obtained in many generations, it becomes a partnership not only between those who are living, but between those who are living, those who are dead, and those who are to be born. Each contract of each particular state is but a clause in the great primeval contract of eternal society, linking the lower with the higher natures, connecting the visible and invisible world, according to a fixed compact sanctioned by the inviolable oath which holds all physical and all moral natures each in their appointed place. This law is not subject to the will of those who, by an obligation above them, and infinitely superior, are bound to submit their will to that law. The municipal corporations of that universal kingdom are not morally at liberty, at their pleasure, and on their speculations of a contingent improvement, wholly to separate and tear asunder the bands of their subordinate community, and to dissolve it into an unsocial, uncivil, unconnected chaos of elementary principles. It is the first and supreme necessity only, a necessity that is not chosen, but chooses, a necessity paramount to deliberation, that admits no discussion and demands no evidence, which alone can justify a resort to anarchy. This necessity is no exception to the rule; because this necessity itself is a part, too, of that moral and physical disposition of things to which man must be obedient by consent or force: but if that which is only submission to necessity should be made the object of choice, the law is broken, Nature is disobeyed, and the rebellious are outlawed, cast forth, and exiled, from this world of reason, and order, and peace, and virtue, and fruitful penitence, into the antagonist world of madness, discord, vice, confusion, and unavailing sorrow.

Society is indeed a contract. Minor agreements for things of temporary interest can be ended whenever people want; however, the state shouldn’t be treated like just a business partnership involving pepper, coffee, calico, or tobacco—something taken on for short-term gain and easily dissolved at will. It should be viewed with greater respect, as it’s not just a partnership in things that satisfy our basic, fleeting needs. It’s a partnership in all knowledge, all art, every virtue, and all perfection. Since the goals of such a partnership often take many generations to achieve, it becomes a partnership that includes not just those alive today, but also those who have passed away and those yet to be born. Each agreement of each specific state is just a part of the larger, ancient contract of eternal society, connecting lower and higher natures, and linking the visible and invisible worlds based on a fixed agreement upheld by a sacred oath that keeps all physical and moral natures in their rightful place. This law doesn’t answer to the desires of those bound by a higher obligation and infinitely greater responsibility to abide by it. The local governments in that universal kingdom aren’t free to casually break apart the bonds of their communities based on speculation about potential improvements, turning it into a chaotic, disconnected mess of basic principles. This necessity is the foremost and ultimate requirement—one that isn’t chosen, but rather chooses, a necessity that takes precedence over deliberation, allows no debate, and needs no proof, which can only justify a move toward anarchy. This necessity is not an exception to the rule; instead, it’s also part of the moral and physical order that people must obey, either by choice or by force. If what is merely submitting to necessity is treated as an option, the law is violated, Nature is disobeyed, and those who rebel are cast out, exiled from this world of reason, order, peace, virtue, and fruitful repentance into a chaotic realm of madness, discord, vice, confusion, and unproductive sorrow.

These, my dear Sir, are, were, and, I think, long will be, the sentiments of not the least learned and reflecting part of this kingdom. They who are included in this description form their opinions on such grounds as such persons ought to form them. The less inquiring receive them from an authority which those whom Providence dooms to live on trust need not be ashamed to rely on. These two sorts of men move in the same direction, though in a different place. They both move with the order of the universe. They all know or feel this great ancient truth:—"Quod illi principi et præpotenti Deo qui omnem hunc mundum regit nihil eorum quæ quidem fiant in terris acceptius quam concilia et coetus hominum jure sociati quæ civitates appellantur." They take this tenet of the head and heart, not from the great name which it immediately bears, nor from the greater from whence it is derived, but from that which alone can give true weight and sanction to any learned opinion, the common nature and common relation of men. Persuaded that all things ought to be done with reference, and referring all to the point of reference to which all should be directed, they think themselves bound, not only as individuals in the sanctuary of the heart, or as congregated in that personal capacity, to renew the memory of their high origin and cast, but also in their corporate character to perform their national homage to the Institutor and Author and Protector of civil society, without which civil society man could not by any possibility arrive at the perfection of which his nature is capable, nor even make a remote and faint approach to it. They conceive that He who gave our nature to be perfected by our virtue willed also the necessary means of its perfection: He willed, therefore, the state: He willed its connection with the source and original archetype of all perfection. They who are convinced of this His will, which is the law of laws and the sovereign of sovereigns, cannot think it reprehensible that this our corporate fealty and homage, that this our recognition of a signiory paramount, I had almost said this oblation of the state itself, as a worthy offering on the high altar of universal praise, should be performed, as all public, solemn acts are performed, in buildings, in music, in decoration, in speech, in the dignity of persons, according to the customs of mankind, taught by their nature,—that is, with modest splendor, with unassuming state, with mild majesty and sober pomp. For those purposes they think some part of the wealth of the country is as usefully employed as it can be in fomenting the luxury of individuals. It is the public ornament. It is the public consolation. It nourishes the public hope. The poorest man finds his own importance and dignity in it, whilst the wealth and pride of individuals at every moment makes the man of humble rank and fortune sensible of his inferiority, and degrades and vilifies his condition. It is for the man in humble life, and to raise his nature, and to put him in mind of a state in which the privileges of opulence will cease, when he will be equal by nature, and may be more than equal by virtue, that this portion of the general wealth of his country is employed and sanctified.

These, my dear Sir, are, were, and I believe will continue to be, the views of at least the more educated and reflective individuals in this kingdom. Those who fit this description form their opinions based on the principles they should rely on. The less questioning accept them from an authority that those who are destined to rely on it need not hesitate to trust. These two types of people move in the same direction, albeit from different places. They both align with the order of the universe. They all understand or sense this important ancient truth:—"Quod illi principi et præpotenti Deo qui omnem hunc mundum regit nihil eorum quæ quidem fiant in terris acceptius quam concilia et coetus hominum jure sociati quæ civitates appellantur." They hold this belief in both mind and heart, not just because of the great figure it represents, nor from the greater source from it is derived, but from what alone can provide true weight and authority to any learned opinion: the shared nature and common relations of mankind. Believing that all actions should reference a higher point of consideration, they feel obligated, not just as individuals in their private lives, or as united in that personal capacity, to remember their noble origin and character, but also in their collective identity to pay their national respect to the Creator and Sustainer of civil society, without which humanity could never hope to reach the potential of which it is capable, nor even begin to approach it. They believe that He who designed our nature to be perfected through our virtues also intended the necessary means for this perfection: thus, He intended the state itself and its connection to the source and original model of all perfection. Those who recognize this divine will, which is the ultimate law and authority, cannot find fault with our collective loyalty and respect, our acknowledgment of a higher authority, or this offering of the state itself, as a valuable tribute on the altar of universal praise, being performed like all public, solemn acts are, in buildings, through music, with decor, in speeches, by dignified individuals, following the customs of humanity, as taught by nature—namely, with modest elegance, unpretentious dignity, mild majesty, and sober pageantry. For these purposes, they believe that a portion of the nation’s wealth can be as beneficially used as it could be in indulging individual luxury. It is the public adornment. It is the public comfort. It nurtures collective hope. Even the poorest person finds a sense of importance and dignity in it, while the wealth and pride of individuals constantly remind the humble of their inferiority, degrading and belittling their status. This portion of the general wealth of society is dedicated to uplifting those of humble means, reminding them of a state where the privileges of wealth will fade, and where they will be equal by nature, and might be even more than equal by virtue.

I assure you I do not aim at singularity. I give you opinions which have been accepted amongst us, from very early times to this moment, with a continued and general approbation, and which, indeed, are so worked into my mind that I am unable to distinguish what I have learned from others from the results of my own meditation.

I promise you I’m not trying to be different. I share thoughts that have been accepted by us for a long time, and that continue to be widely approved. These ideas are so ingrained in my mind that I can’t tell what I’ve learned from others apart from what I’ve thought about myself.

It is on some such principles that the majority of the people of England, far from thinking a religious national establishment unlawful, hardly think it lawful to be without one. In France you are wholly mistaken, if you do not believe us above all other things attached to it, and beyond all other nations; and when this people has acted unwisely and unjustifiably in its favor, (as in some instances they have done, most certainly,) in their very errors you will at least discover their zeal.

It’s based on some of these principles that most people in England don’t consider a national religious establishment to be illegal; they hardly think it’s lawful to be without one. In France, you’re completely wrong if you don’t believe that we are more attached to it than anything else, and more than any other nation; and when our people have acted foolishly and unfairly in its favor, (as they certainly have in some cases,) you can at least see their enthusiasm in those very mistakes.

This principle runs through the whole system of their polity. They do not consider their Church establishment as convenient, but as essential to their state: not as a thing heterogeneous and separable,—something added for accommodation,—what they may either keep up or lay aside, according to their temporary ideas of convenience. They consider it as the foundation of their whole Constitution, with which, and with every part of which, it holds an indissoluble union. Church and State are ideas inseparable in their minds, and scarcely is the one ever mentioned without mentioning the other.

This principle is fundamental to the entire structure of their government. They don’t view their Church as just useful, but as crucial to their state: not as something separate and optional—something they can choose to maintain or discard based on their momentary needs. They see it as the foundation of their entire Constitution, and it's deeply connected with every part of it. In their minds, Church and State are inseparable, and it's rare to mention one without referring to the other.

Our education is so formed as to confirm and fix this impression. Our education is in a manner wholly in the hands of ecclesiastics, and in all stages from infancy to manhood. Even when our youth, leaving schools and universities, enter that most important period of life which begins to link experience and study together, and when with that view they visit other countries, instead of old domestics whom we have seen as governors to principal men from other parts, three fourths of those who go abroad with our young nobility and gentlemen are ecclesiastics: not as austere masters, nor as mere followers; but as friends and companions of a graver character, and not seldom persons as well born as themselves. With them, as relations, they most commonly keep up a close connection through life. By this connection we conceive that we attach our gentlemen to the Church; and we liberalize the Church by an intercourse with the leading characters of the country.

Our education is designed to reinforce and solidify this impression. It's largely controlled by church officials at every stage, from childhood to adulthood. Even when our young people leave schools and universities and enter that crucial phase of life that starts to blend experience with learning, and when they travel to other countries for that purpose, three-quarters of those who accompany our young nobles and gentlemen are church officials. They don't just act as strict teachers or mere followers; they serve as friends and companions of a more serious nature, often coming from good families themselves. They tend to maintain a close bond throughout their lives. Through this connection, we believe we tie our gentlemen to the Church and simultaneously modernize the Church by engaging with the prominent figures of the country.

So tenacious are we of the old ecclesiastical modes and fashions of institution, that very little alteration has been made in them since the fourteenth or fifteenth century: adhering in this particular, as in all things else, to our old settled maxim, never entirely nor at once to depart from antiquity. We found these old institutions, on the whole, favorable to morality and discipline; and we thought they were susceptible of amendment, without altering the ground. We thought that they were capable of receiving and meliorating, and above all of preserving, the accessions of science and literature, as the order of Providence should successively produce them. And after all, with this Gothic and monkish education, (for such it is in the groundwork,) we may put in our claim to as ample and as early a share in all the improvements in science, in arts, and in literature, which have illuminated and adorned the modern world, as any other nation in Europe: we think one main cause of this improvement was our not despising the patrimony of knowledge which was left us by our forefathers.

We are so attached to the old church traditions and practices that very little has changed since the fourteenth or fifteenth century. We stick to our long-standing belief, in everything, that we should never fully or quickly abandon the past. We found these old institutions, overall, to be supportive of morality and discipline; we believed they could be improved without fundamentally changing their essence. We thought they could adapt and improve, and above all, preserve the advancements in science and literature as they emerge over time. Despite this Gothic and monastic education, which forms the foundation, we can claim as much and as early a stake in all the progress in science, arts, and literature that has illuminated and enriched the modern world as any other nation in Europe. We believe one major reason for this progress is that we did not overlook the treasure of knowledge left to us by our ancestors.

It is from our attachment to a Church establishment, that the English nation did not think it wise to intrust that great fundamental interest of the whole to what they trust no part of their civil or military public service,—that is, to the unsteady and precarious contribution of individuals. They go further. They certainly never have suffered, and never will suffer, the fixed estate of the Church to be converted into a pension, to depend on the Treasury, and to be delayed, withheld, or perhaps to be extinguished by fiscal difficulties: which difficulties may sometimes be pretended for political purposes, and are in fact often brought on by the extravagance, negligence, and rapacity of politicians. The people of England think that they have constitutional motives, as well as religious, against any project of turning their independent clergy into ecclesiastical pensioners of state. They tremble for their liberty, from the influence of a clergy dependent on the crown; they tremble for the public tranquillity, from the disorders of a factious clergy, if it were made to depend upon any other than the crown. They therefore made their Church, like their king and their nobility, independent.

It’s because of our connection to a Church establishment that the English people don’t think it’s a good idea to trust something so crucial to just individual contributions, which are as unreliable as they are for any part of their civil or military public service. They go even further. They have certainly never allowed, and will never allow, the established Church to be turned into a pension reliant on the Treasury, subject to delays, cuts, or possibly even eliminated due to financial issues: issues that may sometimes be feigned for political gain and are often caused by the wastefulness, negligence, and greed of politicians. The people of England believe they have both constitutional and religious reasons to oppose any plan that would turn their independent clergy into state-funded pensioners. They worry for their freedom if the clergy relies on the crown; they fear for public peace from the chaos of a partisan clergy if it were dependent on anyone other than the crown. Thus, they made their Church, just like their king and their nobility, independent.

From the united considerations of religion and constitutional policy, from their opinion of a duty to make a sure provision for the consolation of the feeble and the instruction of the ignorant, they have incorporated and identified the estate of the Church with the mass of private property, of which the state is not the proprietor, either for use or dominion, but the guardian only and the regulator. They have ordained that the provision of this establishment might be as stable as the earth on which it stands, and should not fluctuate with the Euripus of funds and actions.

From a combined view of religion and constitutional policy, and from their belief in a duty to provide ongoing support for the vulnerable and education for the unknowing, they have linked and defined the Church's estate with the large amount of private property, which the state does not own, either in use or control, but merely oversees and regulates. They have established that the funding for this institution should be as stable as the ground it stands on, and should not vary like the turbulent changes of funds and actions.

The men of England, the men, I mean, of light and leading in England, whose wisdom (if they have any) is open and direct, would be ashamed, as of a silly, deceitful trick, to profess any religion in name, which by their proceedings they appear to contemn. If by their conduct (the only language that rarely lies) they seemed to regard the great ruling principle of the moral and the natural world as a mere invention to keep the vulgar in obedience, they apprehend that by such a conduct they would defeat the politic purpose they have in view. They would find it difficult to make others believe in a system to which they manifestly gave no credit themselves. The Christian statesmen of this land would, indeed, first provide for the multitude, because it is the multitude, and is therefore, as such, the first object in the ecclesiastical institution, and in all institutions. They have been taught that the circumstance of the Gospel's being preached to the poor was one of the great tests of its true mission. They think, therefore, that those do not believe it who do not take care it should be preached to the poor. But as they know that charity is not confined to any one description, but ought to apply itself to all men who have wants, they are not deprived of a due and anxious sensation of pity to the distresses of the miserable great. They are not repelled, through a fastidious delicacy, at the stench of their arrogance and presumption, from a medicinal attention to their mental blotches and running sores. They are sensible that religious instruction is of more consequence to them than to any others: from the greatness of the temptation to which they are exposed; from the important consequences that attend their faults; from the contagion of their ill example; from the necessity of bowing down the stubborn neck of their pride and ambition to the yoke of moderation and virtue; from a consideration of the fat stupidity and gross ignorance concerning what imports men most to know, which prevails at courts, and at the head of armies, and in senates, as much as at the loom and in the field.

The men of England, the leaders and thinkers in England, whose wisdom (if they have any) is straightforward and honest, would be embarrassed, like it's a silly, deceitful trick, to openly profess any religion in name while their actions suggest otherwise. If their behavior (the only form of communication that rarely lies) implied that they viewed the fundamental principles of morality and nature as nothing more than a fabrication to keep the masses in check, they would realize that such behavior could undermine their political goals. They would struggle to convince others to believe in a system that they clearly don't endorse themselves. The Christian leaders in this country would indeed prioritize the multitude, because it is the multitude and thus the main focus in ecclesiastical and all kinds of institutions. They've been taught that the fact that the Gospel was preached to the poor was one of the key signs of its genuine mission. They believe, therefore, that those who don't ensure it's preached to the poor don't really believe in it. But since they understand that charity isn’t limited to one group, but should extend to all people in need, they maintain a proper and genuine sense of compassion for the struggles of the wealthy who suffer. They aren’t deterred by a pretentious sensitivity to the arrogance and pride of others from offering necessary attention to their mental shortcomings and issues. They realize that religious education is more important for them than for anyone else, given the significant temptations they face; the serious consequences of their mistakes; the damaging influence of their poor examples; the need to humble their pride and ambition under the burden of moderation and virtue; and a recognition of the widespread ignorance regarding what truly matters to know, which exists at courts, among military leaders, and in parliaments, just as much as in factories and fields.

The English people are satisfied, that to the great the consolations of religion are as necessary as its instructions. They, too, are among the unhappy. They feel personal pain and domestic sorrow. In these they have no privilege, but are subject to pay their full contingent to the contributions levied on mortality. They want this sovereign balm under their gnawing cares and anxieties, which, being less conversant about the limited wants of animal life, range without limit, and are diversified by infinite combinations in the wild and unbounded regions of imagination. Some charitable dole is wanting to these, our often very unhappy brethren, to fill the gloomy void that reigns in minds which have nothing on earth to hope or fear; something to relieve in the killing languor and over-labored lassitude of those who have nothing to do; something to excite an appetite to existence in the palled satiety which attends on all pleasures which may be bought, where Nature is not left to her own process, where even desire is anticipated, and therefore fruition defeated by meditated schemes and contrivances of delight, and no interval, no obstacle, is interposed between the wish and the accomplishment.

The English people believe that for the wealthy, the comforts of religion are just as important as its teachings. They, too, share in unhappiness. They experience personal pain and family sorrow. In these matters, they have no special privileges and must pay the full price of the contributions required by mortality. They seek this powerful relief from their persistent worries and anxieties, which, being less focused on the basic needs of physical life, roam freely and are varied by countless combinations in the vast and limitless realms of imagination. Some form of charitable support is needed for these, our often very unhappy fellow beings, to fill the dark void that exists in minds that have nothing on earth to hope for or fear; something to ease the crushing weariness and exhaustion of those who have nothing to do; something to spark a desire for life in the dull overindulgence that follows all pleasures that can be bought, where nature is not allowed to take its course, where even desire is anticipated, and thus fulfillment is thwarted by planned schemes and arrangements for enjoyment, with no gaps, no barriers between wish and achievement.

The people of England know how little influence the teachers of religion are likely to have with the wealthy and powerful of long standing, and how much less with the newly fortunate, if they appear in a manner no way assorted to those with whom they must associate, and over whom they must even exercise, in some cases, something like an authority. What must they think of that body of teachers, if they see it in no part above the establishment of their domestic servants? If the poverty were voluntary, there might be some difference. Strong instances of self-denial operate powerfully on our minds; and a man who has no wants has obtained great freedom and firmness, and even dignity. But as the mass of any description of men are but men, and their poverty cannot be voluntary, that disrespect which attends upon all lay poverty will not depart from the ecclesiastical. Our provident Constitution has therefore taken care that those who are to instruct presumptuous ignorance, those who are to be censors over insolent vice, should neither incur their contempt nor live upon their alms; nor will it tempt the rich to a neglect of the true medicine of their minds. For these reasons, whilst we provide first for the poor, and with a parental solicitude, we have not relegated religion (like something we were ashamed to show) to obscure municipalities or rustic villages. No! we will have her to exalt her mitred front in courts and parliaments. We will have her mixed throughout the whole mass of life, and blended with all the classes of society. The people of England will show to the haughty potentates of the world, and to their talking sophisters, that a free, a generous, an informed nation honors the high magistrates of its Church; that it will not suffer the insolence of wealth and titles, or any other species of proud pretension, to look down with scorn upon what they look up to with reverence, nor presume to trample on that acquired personal nobility which they intend always to be, and which often is, the fruit, not the reward, (for what can be the reward?) of learning, piety, and virtue. They can see, without pain or grudging, an archbishop precede a duke. They can see a bishop of Durham or a bishop of Winchester in possession of ten thousand pounds a year, and cannot conceive why it is in worse hands than estates to the like amount in the hands of this earl or that squire; although it may be true that so many dogs and horses are not kept by the former, and fed with the victuals which ought to nourish the children of the people. It is true, the whole Church revenue is not always employed, and to every shilling, in charity; nor perhaps ought it; but something is generally so employed. It is better to cherish virtue and humanity, by leaving much to free will, even with some loss to the object, than to attempt to make men mere machines and instruments of a political benevolence. The world on the whole will gain by a liberty without which virtue cannot exist.

The people of England understand how little sway religious teachers are likely to have with the old wealthy and powerful, and even less with those who have recently come into money, especially if they don’t fit in with those they need to associate with or, in some cases, hold some authority over. What must these wealthy individuals think of the teachers if they see them as being no better than their domestic servants? If the poverty were chosen, there might be some distinction. Strong examples of self-denial resonate deeply with us; a person free from wants possesses great independence, strength, and even dignity. But since most people are just that—people—and their poverty can’t be a choice, the disrespect associated with all lay poverty won’t disappear from religious figures either. Our careful Constitution has therefore ensured that those who are meant to instruct arrogant ignorance and hold accountable shameless vice won’t face contempt nor rely on charity, nor will it encourage the wealthy to neglect the true remedy for their souls. For these reasons, while we care for the poor first, with a parental concern, we haven’t pushed religion away (like something we’re ashamed of) to obscure towns or rural areas. No! We want it to assert its dignified presence in courts and parliaments. We want it to be part of every aspect of life, intertwined with all social classes. The people of England will show the arrogant rulers of the world and their persuasive speakers that a free, generous, and informed nation respects the high officials of its Church; that it won’t allow the arrogance of wealth and titles, or any other form of proud pretension, to look down with disdain on what they honor with reverence, nor presume to trample on the personal nobility they aspire to always be, and which often arises from learning, piety, and virtue, rather than being a reward (since what can truly be a reward?). They can observe, without resentment, an archbishop preceding a duke. They can see a bishop of Durham or a bishop of Winchester earning ten thousand pounds a year and won’t understand why it’s in worse hands than lands of the same value held by a certain earl or squire, even if it might be true that the former doesn't maintain as many dogs and horses fed with the resources that should nourish the people’s children. It’s true that Church revenue isn’t always used entirely for charity, nor should it necessarily be; but some of it usually is. It’s better to support virtue and humanity by allowing some resources to be governed by free will, even with some loss to the cause, than to try to transform people into mere machines and tools of political goodwill. Overall, the world will benefit from a freedom essential for the existence of virtue.

When once the commonwealth has established the estates of the Church as property, it can consistently hear nothing of the more or the less. Too much and too little are treason against property. What evil can arise from the quantity in any hand, whilst the supreme authority has the full, sovereign superintendence over this, as over any property, to prevent every species of abuse,—and whenever it notably deviates, to give to it a direction agreeable to the purposes of its institution?

When the government has established the church's assets as property, it can't really acknowledge more or less. Having too much or too little is considered a betrayal of property. What harm can come from how much someone has, as long as the highest authority maintains complete control over it, just like any other property, to prevent any kind of abuse? And whenever it strays significantly, it can guide it back to align with its intended purpose?

In England most of us conceive that it is envy and malignity towards those who are often the beginners of their own fortune, and not a love of the self-denial and mortification of the ancient Church, that makes some look askance at the distinctions and honors and revenues which, taken from no person, are set apart for virtue. The ears of the people of England are distinguishing. They hear these men speak broad. Their tongue betrays them. Their language is in the patois of fraud, in the cant and gibberish of hypocrisy. The people of England must think so, when these praters affect to carry back the clergy to that primitive evangelic poverty which in the spirit ought always to exist in them, (and in us, too, however we may like it,) but in the thing must be varied, when the relation of that body to the state is altered,—when manners, when modes of life, when indeed the whole order of human affairs, has undergone a total revolution. We shall believe those reformers to be then honest enthusiasts, not, as now we think them, cheats and deceivers, when we see them throwing their own goods into common, and submitting their own persons to the austere discipline of the early Church.

In England, most of us believe that it’s actually envy and spite towards those who often create their own success, rather than a genuine admiration for the self-denial and sacrifices of the ancient Church, that causes some people to view the distinctions, honors, and revenues meant for virtue with suspicion. The people of England are discerning. They can hear these men speak bluntly. Their speech gives them away. Their language is filled with the slang of deceit, in the jargon and nonsense of hypocrisy. The people of England must feel this way when these speakers pretend to take the clergy back to that original evangelical poverty which should always exist in their spirit (and in ours, too, whether we like it or not), but in practice must change when the relationship between that group and the state alters—when manners, lifestyles, and indeed the entire order of human affairs have undergone a total transformation. We will consider those reformers to be then honest enthusiasts, not, as we think now, fraudsters and liars, when we see them sharing their own possessions, and submitting themselves to the strict discipline of the early Church.

With these ideas rooted in their minds, the Commons of Great Britain, in the national emergencies, will never seek their resource from the confiscation of the estates of the Church and poor. Sacrilege and proscription are not among the ways and means of our Committee of Supply. The Jews in Change Alley have not yet dared to hint their hopes of a mortgage on the revenues belonging to the see of Canterbury. I am not afraid that I shall be disavowed, when I assure you that there is not one public man in this kingdom, whom you wish to quote,—no, not one, of any party or description,—who does not reprobate the dishonest, perfidious, and cruel confiscation which the National Assembly has been compelled to make of that property which it was their first duty to protect.

With these ideas in mind, the Commons of Great Britain, during national emergencies, will never look to take resources from the confiscation of the Church and the poor's estates. Robbery and exclusion are not part of our Committee of Supply's methods. The Jews in Change Alley haven't dared to suggest taking a mortgage on the revenues of the see of Canterbury. I’m confident that I won’t be contradicted when I say that there isn’t a single public figure in this country, whom you’d want to reference—not one, from any party or background—who doesn't condemn the dishonest, treacherous, and brutal confiscation that the National Assembly has been forced to carry out on the property it should have been protecting first and foremost.

It is with the exultation of a little national pride I tell you that those amongst us who have wished to pledge the societies of Paris in the cup of their abominations have been disappointed. The robbery of your Church has proved a security to the possessions of ours. It has roused the people. They see with horror and alarm that enormous and shameless act of proscription. It has opened, and will more and more open, their eyes upon the selfish enlargement of mind and the narrow liberality of sentiment of insidious men, which, commencing in close hypocrisy and fraud, have ended in open violence and rapine. At home we behold similar beginnings. We are on our guard against similar conclusions.

With a sense of national pride, I want to share that those among us who hoped to involve the societies of Paris in their disgraceful actions have been let down. The theft of your Church has actually protected our own possessions. It has awakened the public, who now view with horror and alarm that massive and shameless act of persecution. It has opened—and will continue to open—their eyes to the selfish mindset and narrow-mindedness of deceitful individuals, which started with close hypocrisy and fraud, and have escalated to open violence and looting. At home, we see similar signs. We are vigilant against similar outcomes.

I hope we shall never be so totally lost to all sense of the duties imposed upon us by the law of social union, as, upon any pretest of public service, to confiscate the goods of a single unoffending citizen. Who but a tyrant (a name expressive of everything which can vitiate and degrade human nature) could think of seizing on the property of men, unaccused, unheard, untried, by whole descriptions, by hundreds and thousands together? Who that had not lost every trace of humanity could think of casting down men of exalted rank and sacred function, some of them of an age to call at once for reverence and compassion,—of casting them down from the highest situation in the commonwealth, wherein they were maintained by their own landed property, to a state of indigence, depression, and contempt?

I hope we never lose sight of our responsibilities under the social contract to the extent that we would, under any guise of public service, take the possessions of an innocent citizen. Who but a tyrant—someone who embodies everything that corrupts and degrades human nature—could consider seizing the property of people who are unaccused, unheard, and untried, by entire groups, by the hundreds and thousands? Who, without having lost all sense of humanity, could think of bringing down people of high status and sacred duty, some deserving both respect and compassion due to their age—bringing them from the highest positions in society, where they held their own land, to a state of poverty, despair, and ridicule?

The confiscators truly have made some allowance to their victims from the scraps and fragments of their own tables, from which they have been so harshly driven, and which have been so bountifully spread for a feast to the harpies of usury. But to drive men from independence to live on alms is itself great cruelty. That which might be a tolerable condition to men in one state of life, and not habituated to other things, may, when all these circumstances are altered, be a dreadful revolution, and one to which a virtuous mind would feel pain in condemning any guilt, except that which would demand the life of the offender. But to many minds this punishment of degradation and infamy is worse than death. Undoubtedly it is an infinite aggravation of this cruel suffering, that the persons who were taught a double prejudice in favor of religion, by education, and by the place they held in the administration of its functions, are to receive the remnants of their property as alms from the profane and impious hands of those who had plundered them of all the rest,—to receive (if they are at all to receive) not from the charitable contributions of the faithful, but from the insolent tenderness of known and avowed atheism, the maintenance of religion, measured out to them on the standard of the contempt in which it is held, and for the purpose of rendering those who receive the allowance vile and of no estimation in the eyes of mankind.

The confiscators have indeed shared some scraps from their own tables with their victims, from whom they have been cruelly driven away, and who have been left to feast on what the usurers cast aside. But forcing people from independence to rely on charity is a form of great cruelty. What might be an acceptable situation for individuals in one way of life may, when circumstances change, become a terrible upheaval—one that a virtuous person would struggle to condemn, except for the most serious offenses. However, for many, the punishment of degradation and infamy is worse than death. It adds to the immense suffering that those who were raised with a strong bias towards religion, due to their upbringing and positions in its administration, are now forced to accept the remnants of their property as charity from the irreverent hands of those who robbed them of everything else. They receive not from the generous contributions of the faithful but from the disdainful pity of openly avowed atheism, which provides the maintenance of religion measured by the contempt with which it is regarded, intending to make those receiving aid appear degraded and worthless in the eyes of society.

But this act of seizure of property, it seems, is a judgment in law, and not a confiscation. They have, it seems, found out in the academies of the Palais Royal and the Jacobins, that certain men had no right to the possessions which they held under law, usage, the decisions of courts, and the accumulated prescription of a thousand years. They say that ecclesiastics are fictitious persons, creatures of the state, whom at pleasure they may destroy, and of course limit and modify in every particular; that the goods they possess are not properly theirs, but belong to the state which created the fiction; and we are therefore not to trouble ourselves with what they may suffer in their natural feelings and natural persons on account of what is done towards them in this their constructive character. Of what import is it, under what names you injure men, and deprive them of the just emoluments of a profession in which they were not only permitted, but encouraged by the state to engage, and upon the supposed certainty of which emoluments they had formed the plan of their lives, contracted debts, and led multitudes to an entire dependence upon them?

But it seems that this act of taking property is a legal judgment, not a confiscation. They’ve apparently discovered in the academies of the Palais Royal and the Jacobins that some individuals had no right to the possessions they held based on law, common practice, court decisions, and a thousand years of established precedent. They claim that clergy are fictitious entities, creations of the state, whom they can easily destroy and, of course, control and change in every way; that the goods they have don’t truly belong to them but to the state that created this fiction; and therefore, we shouldn’t concern ourselves with what they might feel or experience personally due to actions taken against them in this fictional role. What does it matter under what terms you harm people and strip them of the rightful earnings from a profession in which they were not only allowed but also encouraged by the state to participate, and upon which certainty of earnings they built their lives, incurred debts, and led many to depend on them entirely?

You do not imagine, Sir, that I am going to compliment this miserable distinction of persons with any long discussion. The arguments of tyranny are as contemptible as its force is dreadful. Had not your confiscators by their early crimes obtained a power which secures indemnity to all the crimes of which they have since been guilty, or that they can commit, it is not the syllogism of the logician, but the lash of the executioner, that would have refuted a sophistry which becomes an accomplice of theft and murder. The sophistic tyrants of Paris are loud in their declamations against the departed regal tyrants who in former ages have vexed the world. They are thus bold, because they are safe from the dungeons and iron cages of their old masters. Shall we be more tender of the tyrants of our own time, when we see them acting worse tragedies under our eyes? Shall we not use the same liberty that they do, when we can use it with the same safety, when to speak honest truth only requires a contempt of the opinions of those whose actions we abhor?

You don't think I'm going to waste time flattering this pathetic division of people with a long discussion, do you? The arguments of tyranny are as ridiculous as its brutality is terrifying. If your confiscators hadn't gained power through their early crimes, which protects them from any accountability for their subsequent misdeeds or future actions, it wouldn't be the logic of a philosopher that would expose their deceit but the whip of an executioner. The deceitful tyrants of Paris are loud in their criticism of the former kingly tyrants who troubled the world in the past. They are bold because they are safe from the dungeons and iron cages of their old masters. Should we show more leniency toward the tyrants of our own time when we see them committing even worse atrocities right in front of us? Shouldn’t we exercise the same freedom they do, especially when we can do so safely, and when speaking the honest truth simply requires us to disregard the opinions of those whose actions we detest?

This outrage on all the rights of property was at first covered with what, on the system of their conduct, was the most astonishing of all pretexts,—a regard to national faith. The enemies to property at first pretended a most tender, delicate, and scrupulous anxiety for keeping the king's engagements with the public creditor. These professors of the rights of men are so busy in teaching others, that they have not leisure to learn anything themselves; otherwise they would have known that it is to the property of the citizen, and not to the demands of the creditor of the state, that the first and original faith of civil society is pledged. The claim of the citizen is prior in time, paramount in title, superior in equity. The fortunes of individuals, whether possessed by acquisition, or by descent, or in virtue of a participation in the goods of some community, were no part of the creditor's security, expressed or implied. They never so much as entered into his head, when he made his bargain. He well knew that the public, whether represented by a monarch or by a senate, can pledge nothing but the public estate; and it can have no public estate, except in what it derives from a just and proportioned imposition upon the citizens at large. This was engaged, and nothing else could be engaged, to the public creditor. No man can mortgage his injustice as a pawn for his fidelity.

This attack on property rights was initially masked by what was, given their actions, the most surprising pretext—concern for national integrity. Those against property initially pretended to have a deep, sensitive, and rigorous worry about honoring the king’s commitments to public creditors. These advocates of individual rights are so busy lecturing others that they don’t take the time to educate themselves; otherwise, they would understand that it is the rights of citizens, not the demands of state creditors, that should take precedence in civil society. The citizen's claim is earlier in time, more significant in title, and stronger in fairness. The fortunes of individuals, whether gained through acquisition, inheritance, or community share, were never part of the creditor's security, either expressed or implied. That consideration never even crossed his mind when he made his deal. He understood that the public, whether represented by a monarchy or a senate, can only pledge the public’s resources; and it has no public resources except what it collects fairly and proportionately from its citizens as a whole. This was what was guaranteed, and nothing else could be promised to the public creditor. No one can put their wrongdoing up as collateral for their loyalty.

It is impossible to avoid some observation on the contradictions, caused by the extreme rigor and the extreme laxity of this new public faith, which influenced in this transaction, and which influenced not according to the nature of the obligation, but to the description of the persons to whom it was engaged. No acts of the old government of the kings of France are held valid in the National Assembly, except its pecuniary engagements: acts of all others of the most ambiguous legality. The rest of the acts of that royal government are considered in so odious a light that to have a claim under its authority is looked on as a sort of crime. A pension, given as a reward for service to the state, is surely as good a ground of property as any security for money advanced to the state. It is a better; for money is paid, and well paid, to obtain that service. We have, however, seen multitudes of people under this description in France, who never had been deprived of their allowances by the most arbitrary ministers in the most arbitrary times, by this assembly of the rights of men robbed without mercy. They were told, in answer to their claim to the bread earned with their blood, that their services had not been rendered to the country that now exists.

It’s impossible to ignore the contradictions brought about by the extreme strictness and extreme leniency of this new public belief, which influenced this situation, not based on the nature of the obligation but rather on the identity of the individuals involved. No actions from the former government of the kings of France are recognized as valid in the National Assembly, except for its financial commitments: all other actions are viewed with a questionable legality. The rest of the actions of that royal government are viewed so negatively that having a claim under its authority is seen as somewhat of a crime. A pension awarded for service to the state is undoubtedly as valid a basis for property as any promise for money lent to the state. It’s even better, because money is both paid and well compensated to obtain that service. However, we have seen countless individuals in France who, despite never having their allowances taken away by the most arbitrary ministers during the most arbitrary times, were mercilessly robbed of their rights by this assembly of the rights of men. They were told, in response to their claims for the sustenance earned with their sacrifices, that their services had not been rendered to the country that currently exists.

This laxity of public faith is not confined to those unfortunate persons. The Assembly, with perfect consistency, it must be owned, is engaged in a respectable deliberation how far it is bound by the treaties made with other nations under the former government; and their committee is to report which of them they ought to ratify, and which not. By this means they have put the external fidelity of this virgin state on a par with its internal.

This lack of public trust isn't limited to those unfortunate individuals. The Assembly, it must be said, is consistently engaged in a serious discussion about how far it is obligated by the treaties established with other countries under the previous government. Their committee is tasked with reporting which treaties they should ratify and which ones they should not. This way, they have aligned the external loyalty of this new state with its internal loyalty.

It is not easy to conceive upon what rational principle the royal government should not, of the two, rather have possessed the power of rewarding service and making treaties, in virtue of its prerogative, than that of pledging to creditors the revenue of the state, actual and possible. The treasure of the nation, of all things, has been the least allowed to the prerogative of the king of France, or to the prerogative of any king in Europe. To mortgage the public revenue implies the sovereign dominion, in the fullest sense, over the public purse. It goes far beyond the trust even of a temporary and occasional taxation. The acts, however, of that dangerous power (the distinctive mark of a boundless despotism) have been alone held sacred. Whence arose this preference given by a democratic assembly to a body of property deriving its title from the most critical and obnoxious of all the exertions of monarchical authority? Reason can furnish nothing to reconcile inconsistency; nor can partial favor be accounted for upon equitable principles. But the contradiction and partiality which admit no justification are not the less without an adequate cause; and that cause I do not think it difficult to discover.

It’s hard to understand why the royal government should not have the power to reward service and make treaties, given its prerogatives, rather than just having the ability to mortgage the state's revenue, both current and potential. The nation’s wealth, more than anything else, has been the least controlled by the king of France’s prerogative or by any king in Europe. Mortgaging public revenue implies total control over the public finances. It goes way beyond just managing temporary taxes. Yet, the actions associated with that dangerous power (which is a clear sign of extreme despotism) have been considered untouchable. Why did a democratic assembly prefer a type of property that stems from the most questionable and controversial uses of monarchical power? Logic can’t explain this inconsistency, and favoritism can’t be justified by fair principles. However, the contradictions and biases, which have no valid justification, still have an underlying cause, and I don’t think it’s hard to identify that cause.

By the vast debt of France a great moneyed interest has insensibly grown up, and with it a great power. By the ancient usages which prevailed in that kingdom, the general circulation of property, and in particular the mutual convertibility of land into money and of money into land, had always been a matter of difficulty. Family settlements, rather more general and more strict than they are in England, the jus retractûs, the great mass of landed property held by the crown, and, by a maxim of the French law, held unalienably, the vast estates of the ecclesiastic corporations,—all these had kept the landed and moneyed interests more separated in France, less miscible, and the owners of the two distinct species of property not so well disposed to each other as they are in this country.

Due to France's huge debt, a significant financial interest has quietly emerged, bringing with it considerable power. Historically, the general flow of property in that kingdom, especially the ability to easily convert land into cash and cash into land, has always been challenging. Family trusts have been somewhat more common and more rigid than in England, along with the jus retractûs, the large quantity of land owned by the crown, which, according to a principle of French law, cannot be sold, and the vast estates of religious organizations—all of these factors have kept land and financial interests more separated in France, less compatible, and the owners of these two different types of property less inclined to engage with each other than they are in this country.

The moneyed property was long looked on with rather an evil eye by the people. They saw it connected with their distresses, and aggravating them. It was no less envied by the old landed interests,—partly for the same reasons that rendered it obnoxious to the people, but much more so as it eclipsed, by the splendor of an ostentatious luxury, the unendowed pedigrees and naked titles of several among the nobility. Even when the nobility, which represented the more permanent landed interest, united themselves by marriage (which sometimes was the case) with the other description, the wealth which saved the family from ruin was supposed to contaminate and degrade it. Thus the enmities and heart burnings of these parties were increased even by the usual means by which discord is made to cease and quarrels are turned into friendship. In the mean time, the pride of the wealthy men, not noble, or newly noble, increased with its cause. They felt with resentment an inferiority the grounds of which they did not acknowledge. There was no measure to which they were not willing to lend themselves, in order to be revenged of the outrages of this rival pride, and to exalt their wealth to what they considered as its natural rank and estimation. They struck at the nobility through the crown and the Church. They attacked them particularly on the side on which they thought them the most vulnerable,—that is, the possessions of the Church, which, through the patronage of the crown, generally devolved upon the nobility. The bishoprics and the great commendatory abbeys were, with few exceptions, held by that order.

The wealthy property was often viewed suspiciously by the people. They saw it as linked to their troubles and making them worse. Old landowners envied it for similar reasons that made it despised by the public, but even more because its flashy luxury overshadowed the unearned titles and empty pedigrees of some nobility. Even when nobles, who represented the more established land interests, married into this other group (which sometimes happened), the wealth that saved the family from downfall was believed to taint and degrade it. This only fueled the animosities and resentments between these groups, even through the usual ways that resolve conflicts and turn enemies into friends. Meanwhile, the pride of rich men, whether they were noble or newly wealthy, grew along with their status. They felt a resentment for an inferiority they refused to acknowledge. There was no extreme they wouldn’t go to in order to take revenge on this rival pride and elevate their wealth to what they believed was its rightful place and value. They targeted the nobility through the crown and the Church. They specifically attacked them where they thought they were most vulnerable—namely, the Church's possessions, which typically passed to the nobility through royal patronage. Bishoprics and the large commendatory abbeys were generally held by that class, with few exceptions.

In this state of real, though not always perceived, warfare between the noble ancient landed interest and the new moneyed interest, the greatest, because the most applicable, strength was in the hands of the latter. The moneyed interest is in its nature more ready for any adventure, and its possessors more disposed to new enterprises of any kind. Being of a recent acquisition, it falls in more naturally with any novelties. It is therefore the kind of wealth which will be resorted to by all who wish for change.

In this ongoing battle, even if not everyone sees it, between the traditional wealthy landowners and the rising class with newly gained wealth, the most significant power lies with the latter. The wealthy are naturally more open to taking risks and are more inclined to pursue new ventures. Since their wealth is relatively fresh, it blends more easily with new ideas. Consequently, this is the type of wealth that will attract anyone seeking change.

Along with the moneyed interest, a new description of men had grown up, with whom that interest soon formed a close and marked union: I mean the political men of letters. Men of letters, fond of distinguishing themselves, are rarely averse to innovation. Since the decline of the life and greatness of Louis the Fourteenth, they were not so much cultivated either by him, or by the Regent, or the successors to the crown; nor were they engaged to the court by favors and emoluments so systematically as during the splendid period of that ostentatious and not impolitic reign. What they lost in the old court protection they endeavored to make up by joining in a sort of incorporation of their own; to which the two academies of France, and afterwards the vast undertaking of the Encyclopædia, carried on by a society of these gentlemen, did not a little contribute.

With the rise of wealthy interests, a new group of men emerged, who quickly aligned themselves with that wealth: the political intellectuals. Intellectuals, eager to stand out, are seldom opposed to change. Since the decline of the reign and greatness of Louis the Fourteenth, they were not as highly valued by him, the Regent, or subsequent monarchs; nor were they as dependent on the court for favors and rewards as they were during the extravagant and strategically savvy period of that reign. What they lost in old court patronage, they tried to regain by forming their own sort of association; the two academies of France and later the ambitious project of the Encyclopædia, driven by a group of these gentlemen, significantly contributed to this effort.

The literary cabal had some years ago formed something like a regular plan for the destruction of the Christian religion. This object they pursued with a degree of zeal which hitherto had been discovered only in the propagators of some system of piety. They were possessed with a spirit of proselytism in the most fanatical degree,—and from thence, by an easy progress, with the spirit of persecution according to their means.[97] What was not to be done towards their great end by any direct or immediate act might be wrought by a longer process through the medium of opinion. To command that opinion, the first step is to establish a dominion over those who direct it. They contrived to possess themselves, with great method and perseverance, of all the avenues to literary fame. Many of them, indeed, stood high in the ranks of literature and science. The world had done them justice, and in favor of general talents forgave the evil tendency of their peculiar principles. This was true liberality; which they returned by endeavoring to confine the reputation of sense, learning, and taste to themselves or their followers. I will venture to say that this narrow, exclusive spirit has not been less prejudicial to literature and to taste than to morals and true philosophy. These atheistical fathers have a bigotry of their own; and they have learnt to talk against monks with the spirit of a monk. But in some things they are men of the world. The resources of intrigue are called in to supply the defects of argument and wit. To this system of literary monopoly was joined an unremitting industry to blacken and discredit in every way, and by every means, all those who did not hold to their faction. To those who have observed the spirit of their conduct it has long been clear that nothing was wanted but the power of carrying the intolerance of the tongue and of the pen into a persecution which would strike at property, liberty, and life.

The literary group had several years ago developed a sort of regular plan to undermine the Christian religion. They pursued this goal with a zeal that had only been seen before in those promoting some kind of piety. They were driven by a fanatical spirit of conversion, which easily led them to the spirit of persecution as far as their resources allowed.[97] What they couldn’t accomplish directly could be achieved over time through shaping public opinion. To control that opinion, the first step is to establish dominance over those who influence it. They cleverly and persistently took over all the paths to literary recognition. Many of them, in fact, were respected figures in literature and science. The world recognized their talents and, in turn, overlooked the harmful aspects of their particular beliefs. This was genuine openness; however, they responded by trying to limit the acknowledgment of intelligence, knowledge, and taste to themselves and their supporters. I would argue that this narrow, exclusive mindset has been just as harmful to literature and taste as it has been to morals and genuine philosophy. These atheistic leaders have their own brand of bigotry, and they have learned to criticize religious figures with the attitude of a zealot. Yet, in some respects, they act like worldly individuals. They resort to intrigue to make up for their lack of logical argument and wit. Alongside this literary monopoly, there was relentless effort to tarnish and discredit anyone who disagreed with them by any means necessary. Those who have observed their behavior have long realized that what they lacked was merely the ability to turn their verbal and written intolerance into persecution that would threaten property, freedom, and life.

The desultory and faint persecution carried on against them, more from compliance with form and decency than with serious resentment, neither weakened their strength nor relaxed their efforts. The issue of the whole was, that, what with opposition, and what with success, a violent and malignant zeal, of a kind hitherto unknown in the world, had taken an entire possession of their minds, and rendered their whole conversation, which otherwise would have been pleasing and instructive, perfectly disgusting. A spirit of cabal, intrigue, and proselytism pervaded all their thoughts, words, and actions. And as controversial zeal soon turns its thoughts on force, they began to insinuate themselves into a correspondence with foreign princes,—in hopes, through their authority, which at first they flattered, they might bring about the changes they had in view. To them it was indifferent whether these changes were to be accomplished by the thunderbolt of despotism or by the earthquake of popular commotion. The correspondence between this cabal and the late king of Prussia will throw no small light upon the spirit of all their proceedings.[98] For the same purpose for which they intrigued with princes, they cultivated, in a distinguished manner, the moneyed interest of France; and partly through the means furnished by those whose peculiar offices gave them the most extensive and certain means of communication, they carefully occupied all the avenues to opinion.

The scattered and slight persecution they faced, driven more by a need to maintain appearances than by genuine anger, neither diminished their strength nor slowed their efforts. Ultimately, between the challenges and their achievements, an intense and harmful passion, previously unseen in the world, completely took over their minds, turning their conversations—which could have been enjoyable and enlightening—into something utterly unpleasant. A mindset of conspiracy, scheming, and conversion filled all their thoughts, words, and actions. And since their controversial enthusiasm soon shifted to thoughts of force, they began to subtly connect with foreign rulers—hoping that, by flattering their authority, they could achieve the changes they desired. They didn’t care whether these changes were brought about by the ruler's oppressive power or by a public uprising. The correspondence between this group and the late king of Prussia will shed considerable light on the nature of all their actions. For the same reasons they sought alliances with princes, they also strategically engaged with the wealthy interests in France; and, through the channels provided by those whose roles offered them the broadest and most reliable means of communication, they diligently worked to control all paths to public opinion.

Writers, especially when they act in a body and with one direction, have great influence on the public mind; the alliance, therefore, of these writers with the moneyed interest[99] had no small effect in removing the popular odium and envy which attended that species of wealth. These writers, like the propagators of all novelties, pretended to a great zeal for the poor and the lower orders, whilst in their satires they rendered hateful, by every exaggeration, the faults of courts, of nobility, and of priesthood. They became a sort of demagogues. They served as a link to unite, in favor of one object, obnoxious wealth to restless and desperate poverty.

Writers, especially when they come together with a common purpose, have a significant impact on public opinion; thus, the partnership of these writers with wealthy interests had a notable effect in diminishing the negative feelings and jealousy that surrounded that kind of wealth. These writers, like those who promote new ideas, claimed to care deeply for the poor and lower classes, while in their satire, they exaggerated and vilified the shortcomings of the courts, nobility, and clergy. They turned into a kind of demagogues. They acted as a connection to unite, for a single cause, the disdained wealth with the restless and desperate poverty.

As these two kinds of men appear principal leaders in all the late transactions, their junction and politics will serve to account, not upon any principles of law or of policy, but as a cause, for the general fury with which all the landed property of ecclesiastical corporations has been attacked, and the great care which, contrary to their pretended principles, has been taken of a moneyed interest originating from the authority of the crown. All the envy against wealth and power was artificially directed against other descriptions of riches. On what other principle than that which I have stated can we account for an appearance so extraordinary and unnatural as that of the ecclesiastical possessions, which had stood so many successions of ages and shocks of civil violences, and were guarded at once by justice and by prejudice, being applied to the payment of debts comparatively recent, invidious, and contracted by a decried and subverted government?

As these two types of men emerge as key leaders in all the recent events, their alliance and politics will explain not based on any legal or policy principles, but as a cause, for the widespread outrage with which all the land owned by religious organizations has been attacked, and the great care that, contrary to their claimed principles, has been taken to protect a financial interest stemming from the authority of the crown. All the jealousy towards wealth and power was deliberately redirected against different types of riches. What other explanation could there be for such an extraordinary and unnatural situation as that of the religious properties, which had endured many generations and disturbances of civil violence, and were protected by both justice and bias, being used to pay off debts that are comparatively recent, controversial, and incurred by a discredited and overthrown government?

Was the public estate a sufficient stake for the public debts? Assume that it was not, and that a loss must be incurred somewhere. When the only estate lawfully possessed, and which the contracting parties had in contemplation at the time in which their bargain was made, happens to fail, who, according to the principles of natural and legal equity, ought to be the sufferer? Certainly it ought to be either the party who trusted, or the party who persuaded him to trust, or both; and not third parties who had no concern with the transaction. Upon any insolvency, they ought to suffer who were weak enough to lend upon bad security, or they who fraudulently held out a security that was not valid. Laws are acquainted with no other rules of decision. But by the new institute of the rights of men, the only persons who in equity ought to suffer are the only persons who are to be saved harmless: those are to answer the debt who neither were lenders nor borrowers, mortgagers nor mortgagees.

Was the public estate a sufficient asset to cover the public debts? Let's say it wasn’t, and that a loss has to happen somewhere. When the only estate that was legally owned, and which the parties had in mind when making their agreement, ends up failing, who, based on the principles of fairness and justice, should bear the loss? It should be either the party who placed their trust, or the party who convinced them to trust, or both; not unrelated third parties who had nothing to do with the deal. In cases of insolvency, those who were foolish enough to lend based on bad security, or those who misleadingly offered a security that wasn’t valid, should take the hit. The law recognizes no other rules for making decisions. However, under the new guidelines of people's rights, the only individuals who should be held responsible in fairness are the ones who are to be kept unharmed: those who will be liable for the debt yet were neither the lenders nor the borrowers, neither the mortgagers nor the mortgagees.

What had the clergy to do with these transactions? What had they to do with any public engagement further than the extent of their own debt? To that, to be sure, their estates were bound to the last acre. Nothing can lead more to the true spirit of the Assembly, which sits for public confiscation with its new equity and its new morality, than an attention to their proceeding with regard to this debt of the clergy. The body of confiscators, true to that moneyed interest for which they were false to every other, have found the clergy competent to incur a legal debt. Of course they declared them legally entitled to the property which their power of incurring the debt and mortgaging the estate implied: recognizing the rights of those persecuted citizens in the very act in which they were thus grossly violated.

What did the clergy have to do with these transactions? What was their involvement in any public matters beyond their own debt? To that, their estates were indeed tied to the very last acre. Nothing reveals the true spirit of the Assembly, which meets for public confiscation with its new standards of fairness and morality, more than looking at how they handled the clergy's debt. The group of confiscators, loyal to that financial interest for which they betrayed every other principle, deemed the clergy capable of incurring a legal debt. As a result, they declared them legally entitled to the property that their ability to incur the debt and mortgage the estate implied, acknowledging the rights of those persecuted citizens in the very act that so grossly violated them.

If, as I said, any persons are to mate good deficiencies to the public creditor, besides the public at large, they must be those who managed the agreement. Why, therefore, are not the estates of all the comptrollers-general confiscated?[100] Why not those of the long succession of ministers, financiers, and bankers who have been enriched whilst the nation was impoverished by their dealings and their counsels? Why is not the estate of M. Laborde declared forfeited rather than of the Archbishop of Paris, who has had nothing to do in the creation or in the jobbing of the public funds? Or, if you must confiscate old landed estates in favor of the money-jobbers, why is the penalty confined to one description? I do not know whether the expenses of the Duke de Choiseul have left anything of the infinite sums which he had derived from the bounty of his master, during the transactions of a reign which contributed largely, by every species of prodigality in war and peace, to the present debt of France. If any such remains, why is not this confiscated? I remember to have been in Paris during the time of the old government. I was there just after the Duke d'Aiguillon had been snatched (as it was generally thought) from the block by the hand of a protecting despotism. He was a minister, and had some concern in the affairs of that prodigal period. Why do I not see his estate delivered up to the municipalities in which it is situated? The noble family of Noailles have long been servants (meritorious servants I admit) to the crown of France, and have had of course some share in its bounties. Why do I hear nothing of the application of their estates to the public debt? Why is the estate of the Duke de Rochefoucault more sacred than that of the Cardinal de Rochefoucault? The former is, I doubt not, a worthy person; and (if it were not a sort of profaneness to talk of the use, as affecting the title to property) he makes a good use of his revenues; but it is no disrespect to him to say, what authentic information well warrants me in saying, that the use made of a property equally valid, by his brother,[101] the Cardinal Archbishop of Rouen, was far more laudable and far more public-spirited. Can one hear of the proscription of such persons, and the confiscation of their effects, without indignation, and horror? He is not a man who does not feel such emotions on such occasions. He does not deserve the name of a free man who will not express them.

If, as I said, certain people are to make up for the public debt, in addition to the general public, those individuals must be the ones who oversaw the agreements. So, why aren't the estates of all the comptrollers-general seized? Why not those of the long line of ministers, financiers, and bankers who got wealthy while the country suffered due to their actions and advice? Why is M. Laborde's estate not forfeited instead of that of the Archbishop of Paris, who had nothing to do with the creation or manipulation of the public funds? Or, if we have to confiscate old estates for the benefit of the money dealers, why is the punishment only applied to one group? I’m not sure if the expenses of the Duke de Choiseul have left anything from the vast sums he gained from his master's generosity, during a reign that heavily contributed, through every sort of wastefulness in war and peace, to France's current debt. If any such money remains, why isn't it seized? I remember being in Paris during the old government, just after the Duke d'Aiguillon was, as many believed, saved from execution by a protective despot. He was a minister and had some involvement in that extravagant period. Why do I not see his estate handed over to the municipalities where it is located? The noble family of Noailles has long served (and I admit, served well) the crown of France and has naturally benefited from its rewards. Why do I hear nothing about their estates being used to pay off the national debt? Why is the estate of the Duke de Rochefoucault considered more untouchable than that of Cardinal de Rochefoucault? I have no doubt that the Duke is a good person, and he uses his income well; however, it is not disrespectful to point out that the way his brother, the Cardinal Archbishop of Rouen, utilized his estate was much more commendable and public-spirited. Can anyone listen to the exclusion of such individuals and the seizure of their possessions without feeling anger and horror? Anyone who can stay indifferent in such situations does not deserve to be called a free person.

Few barbarous conquerors have ever made so terrible a revolution in property. None of the heads of the Roman factions, when they established crudelem illam hastam in all their auctions of rapine, have ever set up to sale the goods of the conquered citizen to such an enormous amount. It must be allowed in favor of those tyrants of antiquity, that what was done by them could hardly be said to be done in cold blood. Their passions were inflamed, their tempers soured, their understandings confused with the spirit of revenge, with the innumerable reciprocated and recent inflictions and retaliations of blood and rapine. They were driven beyond all bounds of moderation by the apprehension of the return of power with the return of property to the families of those they had injured beyond all hope of forgiveness.

Few brutal conquerors have ever created such a horrific shift in property. None of the leaders of the Roman factions, when they established crudelem illam hastam in all their auctions of plunder, have ever sold the goods of the conquered citizens for such a vast amount. We must concede, in favor of those ancient tyrants, that their actions could hardly be described as done in cold blood. Their passions were heated, their tempers frayed, their minds clouded by revenge, fueled by countless cycles of violence and retribution. They were driven beyond every limit of moderation by the fear that power would return along with property to the families of those they had wronged beyond any hope of forgiveness.

These Roman confiscators, who were yet only in the elements of tyranny, and were not instructed in the rights of men to exercise all sorts of cruelties on each other without provocation, thought it necessary to spread a sort of color over their injustice. They considered the vanquished party as composed of traitors, who had borne arms, or otherwise had acted with hostility, against the commonwealth. They regarded them as persons who had forfeited their property by their crimes. With you, in your improved state of the human mind, there was no such formality. You seized upon five millions sterling of annual rent, and turned forty or fifty thousand human creatures out of their houses, because "such was your pleasure." The tyrant Harry the Eighth of England, as he was not better enlightened than the Roman Mariuses and Syllas, and had not studied in your new schools, did not know what an effectual instrument of despotism was to be found in that grand magazine of offensive weapons, the rights of men. When he resolved to rob the abbeys, as the club of the Jacobins have robbed all the ecclesiastics, he began by setting on foot a commission to examine into the crimes and abuses which prevailed in those communities. As it might be expected, his commission reported truths, exaggerations, and falsehoods. But truly or falsely, it reported abuses and offences. However, as abuses might be corrected, as every crime of persons does not infer a forfeiture with regard to communities, and as property, in that dark age, was not discovered to be a creature of prejudice, all those abuses (and there were enough of them) were hardly thought sufficient ground for such a confiscation as it was for his purposes to make. He therefore procured the formal surrender of these estates. All these operose proceedings were adopted by one of the most decided tyrants in the rolls of history, as necessary preliminaries, before he could venture, by bribing the members of his two servile Houses with a share of the spoil, and holding out to them an eternal immunity from taxation, to demand a confirmation of his iniquitous proceedings by an act of Parliament. Had fate reserved him to our times, four technical terms would have done his business, and saved him all this trouble; he needed nothing more than one short form of incantation:—"Philosophy, Light, Liberality, the Rights of Men."

These Roman confiscators, who were just beginning to embrace tyranny and didn't understand people's rights to unleash all kinds of cruelty on one another without cause, felt it was important to cover up their wrongdoing. They viewed the defeated group as traitors who had taken up arms or acted hostilely against the state. They thought of them as individuals who had lost their property because of their crimes. In your more advanced understanding of human nature, there was no such need for pretense. You took five million pounds of annual income and kicked forty or fifty thousand people out of their homes simply because "you felt like it." The tyrant Henry the Eighth of England, who was no better informed than the Roman Mariuses and Syllas and hadn’t learned from your modern ideals, didn't realize how powerful a tool of oppression could be found in the concept of human rights. When he decided to plunder the monasteries, just like the Jacobins pillaged all the clergy, he started by launching a commission to investigate the crimes and abuses within those communities. As expected, his commission reported a mix of truths, exaggerations, and lies. But whether true or false, it reported abuses and offenses. However, since abuses could be fixed and not every crime committed by individuals meant that entire communities forfeited their rights, and because property at that time was not seen as a product of bias, all these abuses (and there were plenty) were hardly enough justification for the level of confiscation he intended. He then arranged for the formal handover of these estates. All these complicated actions were taken by one of the most notorious tyrants in history as necessary steps before he could bribe the members of his two submissive Houses with a share of the loot and promise them permanent tax relief to get an act of Parliament to validate his wrongful acts. Had fate kept him around in modern times, four technical terms would have done the trick and spared him all this hassle; he would have needed only one short phrase:—"Philosophy, Light, Liberality, the Rights of Men."

I can say nothing in praise of those acts of tyranny, which no voice has hitherto ever commended under any of their false colors; yet in these false colors an homage was paid by despotism to justice. The power which was above all fear and all remorse was not set above all shame. Whilst shame keeps its watch, virtue is not wholly extinguished in the heart, nor will moderation be utterly exiled from the minds of tyrants.

I can't say anything positive about those acts of tyranny, which no one has ever praised in any of their false representations; yet in these misleading portrayals, despotism paid tribute to justice. The power that was above all fear and all guilt was not free from all shame. As long as shame exists, virtue is not completely gone from the heart, and moderation won't be completely driven out of the minds of tyrants.

I believe every honest man sympathizes in his reflections with our political poet on that occasion, and will pray to avert the omen, whenever these acts of rapacious despotism present themselves to his view or his imagination:—

I believe every honest person can relate to our political poet's thoughts during that time and will hope to avoid the bad omen whenever these acts of greedy tyranny come to mind or are visible to them:—

"Hope no storm like this" Embrace our time, where rain needs to change!
Tell me, my Muse, what terrible, serious offense,
What crime could anger any Christian king? To such a rage? Was it luxury or lust? Was he really that moderate, that pure, that fair?
Were these their crimes? They were his own, even more so:
"But being wealthy is a crime for someone who is poor."[102]

This same wealth, which is at all times treason and lèze-nation to indigent and rapacious despotism, under all modes of polity, was your temptation to violate property, law, and religion, united in one object. But was the state of France so wretched and undone, that no other resource but rapine remained to preserve its existence? On this point I wish to receive some information. When the States met, was the condition of the finances of France such, that, after economizing, on principles of justice and mercy, through all departments, no fair repartition of burdens upon all the orders could possibly restore them? If such an equal imposition would have been sufficient, you well know it might easily have been made. M. Necker, in the budget which he laid before the orders assembled at Versailles, made a detailed exposition of the state of the French nation.[103]

This same wealth, which is always a betrayal and a crime against the nation for both the poor and greedy despots, regardless of the type of government, was your temptation to violate property, law, and religion, all in one go. But was France in such a dire state that no resource other than plunder was left to sustain its existence? On this point, I would like to get some clarity. When the States convened, was France's financial situation so dire that, after making cuts based on principles of fairness and compassion throughout all departments, there was no reasonable way to distribute the burdens across all classes to restore them? If such a fair distribution had been enough, as you know, it could have easily been implemented. M. Necker, in the budget he presented to the assembled orders at Versailles, provided a detailed overview of the state of the French nation.[103]

If we give credit to him, it was not necessary to have recourse to any new impositions whatsoever, to put the receipts of France on a balance with its expenses. He stated the permanent charges of all descriptions, including the interest of a new loan of four hundred millions, at 531,444,000 livres; the fixed revenue at 475,294,000: making the deficiency 56,150,000, or short of 2,200,000 l. sterling. But to balance it, he brought forward savings and improvements of revenue (considered as entirely certain) to rather more than the amount of that deficiency; and he concludes with these emphatical words (p. 39):—"Quel pays, Messieurs, que celui, où, sans impôts et avec de simples objets inaperçus, on peut faire disparoître un déficit qui a fait tant de bruit en Europe!" As to the reimbursement, the sinking of debt, and the other great objects of public credit and political arrangement indicated in Monsieur Necker's speech, no doubt could be entertained but that a very moderate and proportioned assessment on the citizens without distinction would have provided for all of them to the fullest extent of their demand.

If we give him credit, there was no need to impose any new taxes to balance France's income with its expenses. He reported the ongoing charges of all kinds, including the interest on a new loan of four hundred million, at 531,444,000 livres; the fixed revenue at 475,294,000, resulting in a shortfall of 56,150,000, or 2,200,000 l sterling. To make up for this, he proposed savings and revenue improvements (considered completely certain) that exceeded the amount of the deficit; and he concluded with these emphatic words (p. 39):—"What a country, gentlemen, where, without taxes and with just some unnoticed items, one can eliminate a deficit that has caused so much noise in Europe!" Regarding repayment, the reduction of debt, and other significant public credit and political issues mentioned in Monsieur Necker's speech, there could be no doubt that a very moderate and fair tax on citizens without distinction would have fully covered all their needs.

If this representation of M. Necker was false, then the Assembly are in the highest degree culpable for having forced the king to accept as his minister, and, since the king's deposition, for having employed as their minister, a man who had been capable of abusing so notoriously the confidence of his master and their own: in a matter, too, of the highest moment, and directly appertaining to his particular office. But if the representation was exact, (as, having always, along with you, conceived a high degree of respect for M. Necker, I make no doubt it was,) then what can be said in favor of those who, instead of moderate, reasonable, and general contribution, have in cold blood, and impelled by no necessity, had recourse to a partial and cruel confiscation?

If this depiction of M. Necker is false, then the Assembly is extremely guilty for forcing the king to accept him as his minister, and, since the king's removal, for employing him as their minister, a man who clearly took advantage of the trust of both his master and them: especially in a matter that is highly important and directly related to his specific role. But if the depiction is accurate, (as I, along with you, have always held a great deal of respect for M. Necker, and I have no doubt it was,) then what can be said in defense of those who, instead of opting for moderate, reasonable, and fair contributions, have methodically, and without any necessity, resorted to a harsh and unfair confiscation?

Was that contribution refused on a pretext of privilege, either on the part of the clergy, or on that of the nobility? No, certainly. As to the clergy, they even ran before the wishes of the third order. Previous to the meeting of the States, they had in all their instructions expressly directed their deputies to renounce every immunity which put them upon a footing distinct from the condition of their fellow-subjects. In this renunciation the clergy were even more explicit than the nobility.

Was that contribution denied under the excuse of privilege, either by the clergy or the nobility? No, definitely not. As for the clergy, they even went ahead of what the third estate wanted. Before the States met, they had clearly instructed their representatives to give up any immunity that set them apart from their fellow citizens. In this renunciation, the clergy were even more specific than the nobility.

But let us suppose that the deficiency had remained at the fifty-six millions, (or 2,200,000 l. sterling,) as at first stated by M. Necker. Let us allow that all the resources he opposed to that deficiency were impudent and groundless fictions, and that the Assembly (or their lords of articles[104] at the Jacobins) were from thence justified in laying the whole burden of that deficiency on the clergy,—yet allowing all this, a necessity of 2,200,000 l. sterling will not support a confiscation to the amount of five millions. The imposition of 2,200,000 l. on the clergy, as partial, would have been oppressive and unjust, but it would not have been altogether ruinous to those on whom it was imposed; and therefore it would not have answered the real purpose of the managers.

But let's imagine that the shortfall stayed at fifty-six million (or 2,200,000 l. sterling), as initially mentioned by M. Necker. Let's assume that all the resources he proposed to cover that shortfall were blatant and unfounded lies, and that the Assembly (or their lords of articles[104] at the Jacobins) were justified in placing the entire burden of that shortfall on the clergy. Even so, a need of 2,200,000 l. sterling wouldn't justify a confiscation totaling five million. A tax of 2,200,000 l. on the clergy, while partial, would have been harsh and unfair, but it wouldn’t have completely devastated those it affected; hence, it wouldn’t have fulfilled the true goals of the leaders.

Perhaps persons unacquainted with the state of France, on hearing the clergy and the noblesse were privileged in point of taxation, may be led to imagine, that, previous to the Revolution, these bodies had contributed nothing to the state. This is a great mistake. They certainly did not contribute equally with each other, nor either of them equally with the commons. They both, however, contributed largely. Neither nobility nor clergy enjoyed any exemption from the excise on consumable commodities, from duties of custom, or from any of the other numerous indirect impositions, which in France, as well as here, make so very large a proportion of all payments to the public. The noblesse paid the capitation. They paid also a land-tax, called the twentieth penny, to the height sometimes of three, sometimes of four shillings in the pound: both of them direct impositions, of no light nature, and no trivial produce. The clergy of the provinces annexed by conquest to France (which in extent make about an eighth part of the whole, but in wealth a much larger proportion) paid likewise to the capitation and the twentieth penny, at the rate paid by the nobility. The clergy in the old provinces did not pay the capitation; but they had redeemed themselves at the expense of about twenty-four millions, or a little more than a million sterling. They were exempted from the twentieths: but then they made free gifts; they contracted debts for the state; and they were subject to some other charges, the whole computed at about a thirteenth part of their clear income. They ought to have paid annually about forty thousand pounds more, to put them on a par with the contribution of the nobility.

Perhaps people unfamiliar with the state of France might think that since the clergy and nobility were exempt from certain taxes, they didn’t contribute anything to the state before the Revolution. This is a big misconception. They certainly didn’t contribute equally to each other, nor did they contribute equally to the commons. However, both groups made significant contributions. Neither the nobility nor the clergy were exempt from the excise on consumable goods, customs duties, or any of the other numerous indirect taxes that, in France as well as here, make up a large portion of all public payments. The nobility paid the capitation tax and also a land tax, known as the twentieth penny, which could be as much as three or four shillings on the pound—both of these are direct taxes that are not negligible and generate considerable revenue. The clergy in regions annexed by conquest to France (which make up about one-eighth of the total area but represent a much larger share of wealth) also paid the capitation and the twentieth penny at the same rate as the nobility. The clergy in the older provinces didn’t pay the capitation but had bought their exemption at a cost of about twenty-four million francs, or just over a million pounds. They were exempt from the twentieths but made voluntary contributions, took on state debts, and were subject to some other charges, which added up to about a thirteenth of their net income. They should have contributed about forty thousand pounds more each year to match the nobility’s contributions.

When the terrors of this tremendous proscription hung over the clergy, they made an offer of a contribution, through the Archbishop of Aix, which, for its extravagance, ought not to have been accepted. But it was evidently and obviously more advantageous to the public creditor than anything which could rationally be promised by the confiscation. Why was it not accepted? The reason is plain:—There was no desire that the Church should be brought to serve the State. The service of the State was made a pretext to destroy the Church. In their way to the destruction of the Church they would not scruple to destroy their country: and they have destroyed it. One great end in the project would have been defeated, if the plan of extortion had been adopted in lieu of the scheme of confiscation. The new landed interest connected with the new republic, and connected with it for its very being, could not have been created. This was among the reasons why that extravagant ransom was not accepted.

When the threats of this severe crackdown were looming over the clergy, they made a proposal for a contribution through the Archbishop of Aix, which, due to its absurdity, should not have been accepted. However, it was clearly more beneficial to the public creditor than anything that could reasonably be promised through confiscation. So, why wasn’t it accepted? The answer is obvious: there was no intention for the Church to serve the State. The service of the State was merely an excuse to undermine the Church. In their attempt to destroy the Church, they were willing to ruin their own country: and they did. One major goal of the plan would have been thwarted if the extortion strategy had been preferred over confiscation. The new land interest linked to the new republic, essential for its existence, could not have been established. This was one of the reasons why that outrageous ransom was not accepted.

The madness of the project of confiscation, on the plan that was first pretended, soon became apparent. To bring this unwieldy mass of landed property, enlarged by the confiscation of all the vast landed domain of the crown, at once into market was obviously to defeat the profits proposed by the confiscation, by depreciating the value of those lands, and indeed of all the landed estates throughout France. Such a sudden diversion of all its circulating money from trade to land must be an additional mischief. What step was taken? Did the Assembly, on becoming sensible of the inevitable ill effects of their projected sale, revert to the offers of the clergy? No distress could oblige them to travel in a course which was disgraced by any appearance of justice. Giving over all hopes from a general immediate sale, another project seems to have succeeded. They proposed to take stock in exchange for the Church lands. In that project great difficulties arose in equalizing the objects to be exchanged. Other obstacles also presented themselves, which threw them back again upon some project of sale. The municipalities had taken an alarm. They would not hear of transferring the whole plunder of the kingdom to the stockholders in Paris. Many of those municipalities had been (upon system) reduced to the most deplorable indigence. Money was nowhere to be seen. They were therefore led to the point that was so ardently desired. They panted for a currency of any kind which might revive their perishing industry. The municipalities were, then, to be admitted to a share in the spoil, which evidently rendered the first scheme (if ever it had been seriously entertained) altogether impracticable. Public exigencies pressed upon all sides. The Minister of Finance reiterated his call for supply with, a most urgent, anxious, and boding voice. Thus pressed on all sides, instead of the first plan of converting their bankers into bishops and abbots, instead of paying the old debt, they contracted a new debt, at three per cent, creating a new paper currency, founded on an eventual sale of the Church lands. They issued this paper currency to satisfy in the first instance chiefly the demands made upon them by the bank of discount, the great machine or paper-mill of their fictitious wealth.

The insanity of the confiscation project, based on its initial claims, quickly became clear. Trying to flood the market with this massive amount of land, additionally boosted by seizing all the crown’s extensive properties, would obviously undermine the profits expected from the confiscation by lowering the value of those lands and all the estates across France. Such a sudden shift of all available cash from trade to land would only cause more harm. What action was taken? Did the Assembly, realizing the unavoidable negative impacts of their proposed sale, reconsider the clergy's offers? No amount of distress could force them to consider a path that was tainted by any hint of fairness. Abandoning all hopes for an immediate blanket sale, another plan seemed to take shape. They suggested exchanging stocks for Church lands. This plan faced significant challenges in balancing the items to be traded. Other obstacles also emerged, pushing them back toward some version of a sale. The municipalities had been alarmed. They refused to allow the entire loot of the kingdom to go to the stockholders in Paris. Many of these municipalities had been (as a policy) reduced to dire poverty. Money was nowhere to be found. They were therefore driven to the very point they desperately desired. They craved any form of currency that could revive their dying industries. Consequently, the municipalities were to be included in the spoils, which clearly made the initial scheme (if it had ever been seriously considered) completely unfeasible. Public demands were pressing from all sides. The Minister of Finance repeatedly urged for supplies with a voice that was extremely urgent, anxious, and foreboding. Thus, under pressure from all sides, rather than sticking to the original plan of turning their bankers into bishops and abbots, or paying off the old debt, they took on new debt at three percent, creating a new paper currency based on a potential sale of the Church lands. They issued this paper currency primarily to meet the initial demands made on them by the bank of discount, the main engine of their fictitious wealth.

The spoil of the Church was now become the only resource of all their operations in finance, the vital principle of all their politics, the sole security for the existence of their power. It was necessary, by all, even the most violent means, to put every individual on the same bottom, and to bind the nation in one guilty interest to uphold this act, and the authority of those by whom it was done. In order to force the most reluctant into a participation of their pillage, they rendered their paper circulation compulsory in all payments. Those who consider the general tendency of their schemes to this one object as a centre, and a centre from which afterwards all their measures radiate, will not think that I dwell too long upon this part of the proceedings of the National Assembly.

The spoils of the Church had become the only source for all their financial operations, the driving force behind their politics, and the only security for their power. It was essential, by any means necessary, to make everyone complicit and to bind the nation to this unethical interest to support this act and the authority of those who executed it. To force even the most unwilling into sharing their loot, they made their paper currency mandatory for all payments. Those who examine the overall goal of their plans as a focal point, from which all their actions stem, will not think I’m focusing too much on this part of the National Assembly’s actions.

To cut off all appearance of connection between the crown and public justice, and to bring the whole under implicit obedience to the dictators in Paris, the old independent judicature of the Parliaments, with all its merits and all its faults, was wholly abolished. Whilst the Parliaments existed, it was evident that the people might some time or other come to resort to them, and rally under the standard of their ancient laws. It became, however, a matter of consideration, that the magistrates and officers in the courts now abolished had purchased their places at a very high rate, for which, as well as for the duty they performed, they received but a very low return of interest. Simple confiscation is a boon only for the clergy: to the lawyers some appearances of equity are to be observed; and they are to receive compensation to an immense amount. Their compensation becomes part of the national debt, for the liquidation of which there is the one exhaustless fund. The lawyers are to obtain their compensation in the new Church paper, which is to march with the new principles of judicature and legislature. The dismissed magistrates are to take their share of martyrdom with the ecclesiastics, or to receive their own property from such a fund and in such a manner as all those who have been seasoned with the ancient principles of jurisprudence, and had been the sworn guardians of property, must look upon with horror. Even the clergy are to receive their miserable allowance out of the depreciated paper, which is stamped with the indelible character of sacrilege, and with the symbols of their own ruin, or they must starve. So violent an outrage upon credit, property, and liberty, as this compulsory paper currency, has seldom been exhibited by the alliance of bankruptcy and tyranny, at any time, or in any nation.

To completely sever any appearance of connection between the crown and public justice, and to bring everything under blind obedience to the leaders in Paris, the formerly independent court system of the Parliaments, with all its strengths and weaknesses, was completely abolished. While the Parliaments were still around, it was clear that the people could eventually turn to them and unite under the banner of their ancient laws. However, it became a topic of discussion that the judges and officials in the now-dismantled courts had paid a hefty price for their positions, and for their duties, they received very little in return. Simple confiscation benefits only the clergy; the lawyers require some semblance of fairness, and they are to receive significant compensation. This compensation will add to the national debt, which only has one endless source for its repayment. The lawyers are set to be compensated with new Church paper, which will align with the new judicial and legislative principles. The dismissed judges will either share in their suffering with the clergy or recover their own property from such a fund in a way that all those steeped in the old legal traditions, who had been the sworn protectors of property, should look upon with horror. Even the clergy will receive their meager payments from the devalued paper, which bears the unmistakable mark of sacrilege and the symbols of their own downfall, or they will face starvation. Such a violent attack on credit, property, and freedom, as this forced paper currency, has rarely been seen from the alliance of bankruptcy and tyranny, at any time, or in any nation.

In the course of all these operations, at length comes out the grand arcanum,—that in reality, and in a fair sense, the lands of the Church (so far as anything certain can be gathered from their proceedings) are not to be sold at all. By the late resolutions of the National Assembly, they are, indeed, to be delivered to the highest bidder. But it is to be observed, that a certain portion only of the purchase-money is to be laid down. A period of twelve years is to be given for the payment of the rest. The philosophic purchasers are therefore, on payment of a sort of fine, to be put instantly into possession of the estate. It becomes in some respects a sort of gift to them,—to be held on the feudal tenure of zeal to the new establishment. This project is evidently to let in a body of purchasers without money. The consequence will be, that these purchasers, or rather grantees, will pay, not only from the rents as they accrue, which might as well be received by the state, but from the spoil of the materials of buildings, from waste in woods, and from whatever money, by hands habituated to the gripings of usury, they can wring from the miserable peasant. He is to be delivered over to the mercenary and arbitrary discretion of men who will be stimulated to every species of extortion by the growing demands on the growing profits of an estate held under the precarious settlement of a new political system.

During all these operations, it finally emerges the major secret—that, in reality, and in a reasonable sense, the Church's lands (as much as we can understand from their actions) are not to be sold at all. According to the recent decisions of the National Assembly, they are indeed to be auctioned off to the highest bidder. However, it's important to note that only a portion of the purchase price needs to be paid upfront. A period of twelve years will be allowed for the payment of the remainder. Therefore, the philosophical buyers, by paying a sort of fee, will gain immediate possession of the property. In some ways, it becomes a kind of gift for them—to be held on the feudal condition of loyalty to the new establishment. This plan is clearly designed to bring in buyers without any money. The result will be that these buyers, or rather beneficiaries, will pay not only from the rents as they come in, which could just as well be collected by the state, but also by taking apart the materials of the buildings, through depletion of forests, and from whatever money they can extract from the struggling peasant, whose fate will be handed over to the greedy and ruthless discretion of people who will be driven to all kinds of exploitation by the increasing demands on the rising profits of an estate held under the unstable framework of a new political system.

When all the frauds, impostures, violences, rapines, burnings, murders, confiscations, compulsory paper currencies, and every description of tyranny and cruelty employed to bring about and to uphold this Revolution have their natural effect, that is, to shock the moral sentiments of all virtuous and sober minds, the abettors of this philosophic system immediately strain their throats in a declamation against the old monarchical government of France. When they have rendered that deposed power sufficiently black, they then proceed in argument, as if all those who disapprove of their new abuses must of course be partisans of the old,—that those who reprobate their crude and violent schemes of liberty ought to be treated as advocates for servitude. I admit that their necessities do compel them to this base and contemptible fraud. Nothing can reconcile men to their proceedings and projects but the supposition that there is no third option between them and some tyranny as odious as can be furnished by the records of history or by the invention of poets. This prattling of theirs hardly deserves the name of sophistry. It is nothing but plain impudence. Have these gentlemen never heard, in the whole circle of the worlds of theory and practice, of anything between the despotism of the monarch and the despotism of the multitude? Have they never heard of a monarchy directed by laws, controlled and balanced by the great hereditary wealth and hereditary dignity of a nation, and both again controlled by a judicious check from the reason and feeling of the people at large, acting by a suitable and permanent organ? Is it, then, impossible that a man may be found who, without criminal ill intention or pitiable absurdity, shall prefer such a mixed and tempered government to either of the extremes,—and who may repute that nation to be destitute of all wisdom and of all virtue, which, having in its choice to obtain such a government with ease, or rather to confirm it when actually possessed, thought proper to commit a thousand crimes, and to subject their country to a thousand evils, in order to avoid it? Is it, then, a truth so universally acknowledged, that a pure democracy is the only tolerable form into which human society can be thrown, that a man is not permitted to hesitate about its merits, without the suspicion of being a friend to tyranny, that is, of being a foe to mankind?

When all the frauds, scams, violence, thefts, arson, murders, confiscations, forced paper money, and every kind of tyranny and cruelty used to create and maintain this Revolution take their toll, shocking the moral feelings of all decent and reasonable people, the supporters of this philosophical system immediately raise their voices in a rant against the old monarchical government of France. Once they’ve painted that fallen power as evil enough, they argue as if anyone who disagrees with their new abuses must automatically be a supporter of the old regime—claiming that those who criticize their harsh and reckless ideas of freedom should be treated as advocates for oppression. I admit that they are forced into this despicable and contemptible deceit. Nothing can make people accept their actions and plans except the belief that there’s no alternative between them and some tyranny as dreadful as any found in history or created by poets. Their chatter hardly qualifies as clever argument. It's just plain audacity. Have these individuals never heard, in all their theories and practices, of anything between the despotism of a monarch and the despotism of the masses? Have they never heard of a monarchy governed by laws, checked and balanced by the significant hereditary wealth and status of a nation, which is also controlled by the reason and feelings of the people at large, acting through a stable and effective medium? Is it really impossible that someone could prefer such a mixed and balanced government to either extreme—who might consider a nation devoid of all wisdom and virtue that, having the opportunity to obtain such a government easily, or rather to confirm it once already in place, chose to commit countless crimes and subject their country to countless evils just to avoid it? Is it then a truth so commonly accepted that a pure democracy is the only acceptable form of human society, that a person is not allowed to question its merits without being suspected of supporting tyranny, which means being against humanity?

I do not know under what description to class the present ruling authority in France. It affects to be a pure democracy, though I think it in a direct train of becoming shortly a mischievous and ignoble oligarchy. But for the present I admit it to be a contrivance of the nature and effect of what it pretends to. I reprobate no form of government merely upon abstract principles. There may be situations in which the purely democratic form will become necessary. There may be some (very few, and very particularly circumstanced) where it would be clearly desirable. This I do not take to be the case of France, or of any other great country. Until now, we have seen no examples of considerable democracies. The ancients were better acquainted with them. Not being wholly unread in the authors who had seen the most of those constitutions, and who best understood them, I cannot help concurring with their opinion, that an absolute democracy no more than absolute monarchy is to be reckoned among the legitimate forms of government. They think it rather the corruption and degeneracy than the sound constitution of a republic. If I recollect rightly, Aristotle observes, that a democracy has many striking points of resemblance with a tyranny.[105] Of this I am certain, that in a democracy the majority of the citizens is capable of exercising the most cruel oppressions upon the minority, whenever strong divisions prevail in that kind of polity, as they often must,—and that oppression of the minority will extend to far greater numbers, and will be carried on with much greater fury, than can almost ever be apprehended from the dominion of a single sceptre. In such a popular persecution, individual sufferers are in a much more deplorable condition than in any other. Under a cruel prince they have the balmy compassion of mankind to assuage the smart of their wounds, they have the plaudits of the people to animate their generous constancy under their sufferings: but those who are subjected to wrong under multitudes are deprived of all external consolation; they seem deserted by mankind, overpowered by a conspiracy of their whole species.

I’m not sure how to classify the current ruling power in France. It claims to be a pure democracy, but I believe it's on the verge of turning into a harmful and dishonorable oligarchy. For now, though, I acknowledge it as something that resembles what it claims to be. I don’t condemn any form of government solely based on abstract ideas. There might be situations where a purely democratic system is necessary. There could be a few very specific cases where it would be clearly beneficial. However, I don’t think that applies to France or any other major country. So far, we haven’t seen any significant democracies. The ancients had more experience with them. Having read the works of those who extensively studied such systems and understood them well, I can't help but agree with their view that absolute democracy is just as illegitimate as absolute monarchy. They regarded it more as a corruption and decline than a healthy form of a republic. If I remember correctly, Aristotle pointed out that a democracy shares many alarming similarities with tyranny. What I am certain of is that in a democracy, the majority can impose cruel oppression on the minority whenever there are strong divisions within that system, which often happens. This oppression of the minority can affect an even larger number of people and can be carried out with much more intensity than what we might typically expect from a single ruler. In such a popular persecution, individual victims are in a far worse situation than in any other system. Under a cruel ruler, they have the sympathy of humanity to ease their pain, and they can find strength in the support of the people during their suffering. But those who suffer injustices at the hands of the majority find themselves devoid of any external comfort; they feel abandoned by society, overwhelmed by the collective will of their entire species.

But admitting democracy not to have that inevitable tendency to party tyranny which I suppose it to have, and admitting it to possess as much good in it when unmixed as I am sure it possesses when compounded with other forms; does monarchy, on its part, contain nothing at all to recommend it? I do not often quote Bolingbroke, nor have his works in general left any permanent impression on my mind. He is a presumptuous and a superficial writer. But he has one observation which in my opinion is not without depth and solidity. He says that he prefers a monarchy to other governments, because you can better ingraft any description of republic on a monarchy than anything of monarchy upon the republican forms. I think him perfectly in the right. The fact is so historically, and it agrees well with the speculation.

But even if we accept that democracy doesn’t inevitably lead to party tyranny, as I believe it does, and even if we see it as having some inherent good when it's pure, just like I’m sure it has when mixed with other systems; does monarchy, on the other hand, have nothing to recommend it? I don’t usually quote Bolingbroke, and his works haven’t left a lasting impression on me. He’s a bit arrogant and superficial in his writing. However, he does make one point that I think has some depth and validity. He claims that he prefers a monarchy over other types of government because you can more easily integrate any form of republic into a monarchy than you can incorporate monarchy into republican systems. I think he’s absolutely right. Historically, this is true, and it aligns well with the theory.

I know how easy a topic it is to dwell on the faults of departed greatness. By a revolution in the state, the fawning sycophant of yesterday is converted into the austere critic of the present hour. But steady, independent minds, when they have an object of so serious a concern to mankind as government under their contemplation, will disdain to assume the part of satirists and declaimers. They will judge of human institutions as they do of human characters. They will sort out the good from the evil, which is mixed in mortal institutions as it is in mortal men.

I understand how tempting it is to focus on the flaws of those who have passed. When the political landscape shifts, yesterday's flattering yes-man can quickly become today's harsh critic. However, thoughtful, independent thinkers, when faced with something as important to humanity as government, won't take on the role of mockers or loud speakers. Instead, they will evaluate human systems just like they assess human nature. They will distinguish the good from the bad, which is intertwined in both our institutions and in people.

Your government in France, though usually, and I think justly, reputed the best of the unqualified or ill-qualified monarchies, was still full of abuses. These abuses accumulated in a length of time, as they must accumulate in every monarchy not under the constant inspection of a popular representative. I am no stranger to the faults and defects of the subverted government of France; and I think I am not inclined by nature or policy to make a panegyric upon anything which is a just and natural object of censure. But the question is not now of the vices of that monarchy, but of its existence. Is it, then, true, that the French government was such as to be incapable or undeserving of reform, so that it was of absolute necessity the whole fabric should be at once pulled down, and the area cleared for the erection of a theoretic, experimental edifice in its place? All France was of a different opinion in the beginning of the year 1789. The instructions to the representatives to the States-General, from every district in that kingdom, were filled with projects for the reformation of that government, without the remotest suggestion of a design to destroy it. Had such a design been then even insinuated, I believe there would have been but one voice, and that voice for rejecting it with scorn and horror. Men have been sometimes led by degrees, sometimes hurried, into things of which, if they could have seen the whole together, they never would have permitted the most remote approach. When those instructions were given, there was no question but that abuses existed, and that they demanded a reform: nor is there now. In the interval between the instructions and the Revolution things changed their shape; and in consequence of that change, the true question at present is, whether those who would have reformed or those who have destroyed are in the right.

Your government in France, while often considered the best among poorly qualified monarchies—and I believe justly so—was still rife with abuses. These abuses built up over time, as they do in any monarchy that isn’t monitored by a popular representative. I'm well aware of the faults and shortcomings of the overturned French government, and I’m not naturally inclined to praise something that rightly deserves criticism. However, the issue at hand is not the failings of that monarchy but its survival. Is it really true that the French government was beyond reform and unworthy of improvement, requiring a complete teardown to make way for a theoretical, experimental new system? At the beginning of 1789, all of France thought differently. The instructions sent to the representatives at the States-General from every district were filled with ideas for reforming the government, with no hint of a plan to destroy it. If such a plan had even been suggested, I believe there would have been unanimous opposition, met with disdain and horror. People can sometimes be gradually led into situations that, if seen in their entirety, they would have never allowed even the slightest approach. When those instructions were issued, it was clear that abuses existed that needed reform, and that remains true today. In the time between those instructions and the Revolution, things shifted, and now the crucial question is whether those who sought reform or those who caused destruction are in the right.

To hear some men speak of the late monarchy of France, you would imagine that they were talking of Persia bleeding under the ferocious sword of Thamas Kouli Khân,—or at least describing the barbarous anarchic despotism of Turkey, where the finest countries in the most genial climates in the world are wasted by peace more than any countries have been worried by war, where arts are unknown, where manufactures languish, where science is extinguished, where agriculture decays, where the human race itself melts away and perishes under the eye of the observer. Was this the case of France? I have no way of determining the question but by a reference to facts. Facts do not support this resemblance. Along with much evil, there is some good in monarchy itself; and some corrective to its evil from religion, from laws, from manners, from opinions, the French monarchy must have received, which rendered it (though by no means a free, and therefore by no means a good constitution) a despotism rather in appearance than in reality.

To listen to some men talk about the last monarchy in France, you'd think they were discussing Persia suffering under the brutal rule of Thamas Kouli Khân—or at least describing the savage, chaotic dictatorship of Turkey, where the most beautiful lands in the best climates are harmed more by peace than any other country has been by war. In Turkey, the arts are non-existent, manufacturing is struggling, science has been extinguished, agriculture is in decline, and the human race itself is slowly fading away right before our eyes. Was this the situation in France? I can only answer that question by looking at the facts. The facts don’t support this comparison. Despite many problems, monarchy itself has some positives; and the French monarchy must have had some checks on its negative aspects from religion, laws, social customs, and public opinion, which made it (although definitely not a free system, and therefore not a good one) more of a despotism in appearance than in reality.

Among the standards upon which the effects of government on any country are to be estimated, I must consider the state of its population as not the least certain. No country in which population flourishes, and is in progressive improvement, can be under a very mischievous government. About sixty years ago, the Intendants of the Generalities of France made, with other matters, a report of the population of their several districts. I have not the books, which are very voluminous, by me, nor do I know where to procure them, (I am obliged to speak by memory, and therefore the less positively,) but I think the population of France was by them, even at that period, estimated at twenty-two millions of souls. At the end of the last century it had been generally calculated at eighteen. On either of these estimations, France was not ill-peopled. M. Necker, who is an authority for his own time at least equal to the Intendants for theirs, reckons, and upon apparently sure principles, the people of France, in the year 1780, at twenty-four millions six hundred and seventy thousand. But was this the probable ultimate term under the old establishment? Dr. Price is of opinion that the growth of population in France was by no means at its acme in that year. I certainly defer to Dr. Price's authority a good deal more in these speculations than I do in his general politics. This gentleman, taking ground on M. Necker's data, is very confident that since the period of that minister's calculation the French population has increased rapidly,—so rapidly, that in the year 1789 he will not consent to rate the people of that kingdom at a lower number than thirty millions. After abating much (and much I think ought to be abated) from the sanguine calculation of Dr. Price, I have no doubt that the population of France did increase considerably during this latter period: but supposing that it increased to nothing more than will be sufficient to complete the twenty-four millions six hundred and seventy thousand to twenty-five millions, still a population of twenty-five millions, and that in an increasing progress, on a space of about twenty-seven thousand square leagues, is immense. It is, for instance, a good deal more than the proportionable population of this island, or even than that of England, the best peopled part of the United Kingdom.

Among the standards used to evaluate the effects of government on any country, I consider the state of its population to be quite significant. No country with a thriving and improving population can have a *very* harmful government. About sixty years ago, the officials of the Generalities of France reported on the population of their various districts. I don’t have the very large books with me, nor do I know where to get them, so I have to rely on my memory, which is why I might not be completely certain. However, I believe that even back then, they estimated France’s population at around twenty-two million people. At the end of the last century, it was generally estimated at eighteen million. By either estimate, France was not underpopulated. M. Necker, who is a reliable authority for his time, estimated the population of France in 1780 at twenty-four million six hundred and seventy thousand. But was this the maximum under the previous regime? Dr. Price believes that the population growth in France was not at its peak that year. I certainly trust Dr. Price's expertise on these matters more than I do his general political views. He bases his argument on M. Necker’s data and is quite confident that since the time of that minister’s estimate, the French population has grown rapidly—so rapidly that in 1789, he insists the population cannot be less than thirty million. Even after adjusting his optimistic estimate (and I believe quite a bit should be adjusted), I have no doubt that France’s population increased significantly during that time. But even if it only rose to complete the twenty-four million six hundred and seventy thousand to twenty-five million, a population of twenty-five million, which is still increasing, over about twenty-seven thousand square leagues, is huge. For example, it is much larger than the proportional population of this island, or even of England, the most densely populated part of the United Kingdom.

It is not universally true that France is a fertile country. Considerable tracts of it are barren, and labor under other natural disadvantages. In the portions of that territory where things are more favorable, as far as I am able to discover, the numbers of the people correspond to the indulgence of Nature.[106] The Generality of Lisle, (this I admit is the strongest example,) upon an extent of four hundred and four leagues and a half, about ten years ago contained seven hundred and thirty-four thousand six hundred souls, which is one thousand seven hundred and seventy-two inhabitants to each square league. The middle term for the rest of France is about nine hundred inhabitants to the same admeasurement.

It’s not true for everyone that France is a fertile country. Large areas of it are unproductive and have other natural drawbacks. In the parts of the country where conditions are better, as far as I can tell, the population aligns with the generosity of Nature.[106] The Generality of Lisle, which I admit is the best example, had about seven hundred thirty-four thousand six hundred people living in a region of four hundred and four and a half leagues around ten years ago. That’s one thousand seven hundred seventy-two people for each square league. The average for the rest of France is about nine hundred people per the same measurement.

I do not attribute this population to the deposed government; because I do not like to compliment the contrivances of men with what is due in a great degree to the bounty of Providence. But that decried government could not have obstructed, most probably it favored, the operation of those causes, (whatever they were,) whether of Nature in the soil, or habits of industry among the people, which has produced so large a number of the species throughout that whole kingdom, and exhibited in some particular places such prodigies of population. I never will suppose that fabric of a state to be the worst of all political institutions which by experience is found to contain a principle favorable (however latent it may be) to the increase of mankind.

I don’t think this population can be credited to the overthrown government; I prefer not to credit human efforts for what largely comes from the generosity of Providence. However, that criticized government probably didn’t hinder, and likely supported, the factors (whatever they might be), whether from the soil’s natural qualities or the people's industrious habits, that have led to such a large population throughout the entire kingdom, and have shown remarkable population growth in certain areas. I will never believe that any state structure is the worst political system if it is found, through experience, to contain a principle that, even if hidden, supports the growth of humanity.

The wealth of a country is another, and no contemptible standard, by which we may judge whether, on the whole, a government be protecting or destructive. France far exceeds England in the multitude of her people; but I apprehend that her comparative wealth is much inferior to ours,—that it is not so equal in the distribution, nor so ready in the circulation. I believe the difference in the form of the two governments to be amongst the causes of this advantage on the side of England: I speak of England, not of the whole British dominions,—which, if compared with those of France, will in some degree weaken the comparative rate of wealth upon our side. But that wealth, which will not endure a comparison with the riches of England, may constitute a very respectable degree of opulence. M. Necker's book, published in 1785,[107] contains an accurate and interesting collection of facts relative to public economy and to political arithmetic; and his speculations on the subject are in general wise and liberal. In that work he gives an idea of the state of France, very remote from the portrait of a country whose government was a perfect grievance, an absolute evil, admitting no cure but through the violent and uncertain remedy of a total revolution. He affirms, that from the year 1726 to the year 1784 there was coined at the mint of France, in the species of gold and silver, to the amount of about one hundred millions of pounds sterling.[108]

The wealth of a country is another, and not insignificant, standard by which we can evaluate whether a government is protective or destructive. France has a much larger population than England; however, I believe that its wealth is comparatively much less than ours—it’s not as evenly distributed or as easily circulated. I think the difference in the structure of the two governments contributes to this advantage for England: I’m referring to England specifically, not the entirety of the British territories—which, if compared with France, somewhat diminishes the comparative wealth on our side. But even wealth that doesn’t compare to England's riches can still represent a respectable level of prosperity. M. Necker’s book, published in 1785, contains a precise and intriguing collection of facts related to public economy and political arithmetic, and his ideas on the subject are generally wise and progressive. In that work, he presents a view of France that is far removed from the image of a country whose government was entirely oppressive, an absolute evil that could only be fixed by the violent and uncertain remedy of a total revolution. He states that from 1726 to 1784, about one hundred million pounds sterling was minted in gold and silver in France.

It is impossible that M. Necker should be mistaken in the amount of the bullion which has been coined in the mint. It is a matter of official record. The reasonings of this able financier concerning the quantity of gold and silver which remained for circulation, when he wrote in 1785, that is, about four years before the deposition and imprisonment of the French king, are not of equal certainty; but they are laid on grounds so apparently solid, that it is not easy to refuse a considerable degree of assent to his calculation. He calculates the numéraire, or what we call specie, then actually existing in France, at about eighty-eight millions of the same English money. A great accumulation of wealth for one country, large as that country is! M. Necker was so far from considering this influx of wealth as likely to cease, when he wrote in 1785, that he presumes upon a future annual increase of two per cent upon the money brought into France during the periods from which he computed.

It’s impossible for M. Necker to be wrong about the amount of bullion that has been minted. It's a matter of official record. His insights as a skilled financier regarding the quantity of gold and silver available for circulation when he wrote in 1785, which was about four years before the deposition and imprisonment of the French king, aren't as certain; however, they are based on such solid grounds that it's hard to outright disagree with his calculations. He estimates the numéraire, or what we call specie, that was actually in circulation in France at around eighty-eight million of the same English currency. That’s a significant accumulation of wealth for one country, especially one as large as France! M. Necker was far from thinking that this influx of wealth would stop when he wrote in 1785; he even assumed a future annual increase of two percent on the money brought into France during the periods he calculated.

Some adequate cause must have originally introduced all the money coined at its mint into that kingdom; and some cause as operative must have kept at home, or returned into its bosom, such a vast flood of treasure as M. Necker calculates to remain for domestic circulation. Suppose any reasonable deductions from M. Necker's computation, the remainder must still amount to an immense sum. Causes thus powerful to acquire and to retain cannot be found in discouraged industry, insecure property, and a positively destructive government. Indeed, when I consider the face of the kingdom of France, the multitude and opulence of her cities, the useful magnificence of her spacious high-roads and bridges, the opportunity of her artificial canals and navigations opening the conveniences of maritime communication through a solid continent of so immense an extent,—when I turn my eyes to the stupendous works of her ports and harbors, and to her whole naval apparatus, whether for war or trade,—when I bring before my view the number of her fortifications, constructed with so bold and masterly a skill, and made and maintained at so prodigious a charge, presenting an armed front and impenetrable barrier to her enemies upon every side,—when I recollect how very small a part of that extensive region is without cultivation, and to what complete perfection the culture of many of the best productions of the earth have been brought in France,—when I reflect on the excellence of her manufactures and fabrics, second to none but ours, and in some particulars not second,—when I contemplate the grand foundations of charity, public and private,—when I survey the state of all the arts that beautify and polish life,—when I reckon the men she has bled for extending her fame in war, her able statesmen, the multitude of her profound lawyers and theologians, her philosophers, her critics, her historians and antiquaries, her poets and her orators, sacred and profane,—I behold in all this something which awes and commands the imagination, which checks the mind on the brink of precipitate and indiscriminate censure, and which demands that we should very seriously examine what and how great are the latent vices that could authorize us at once to level so spacious a fabric with the ground. I do not recognize in this view of things the despotism of Turkey. Nor do I discern the character of a government that has been on the whole so oppressive, or so corrupt, or so negligent, as to be utterly unfit for all reformation. I must think such a government well deserved to have its excellences heightened, its faults corrected, and its capacities improved into a British Constitution.

Some reasonable explanation must have initially introduced all the money minted in that kingdom; and some equally effective reason must have kept or returned such a vast amount of wealth as M. Necker estimates to still be in domestic circulation. Even if we make some reasonable deductions from M. Necker's calculations, the remaining amount must still be huge. Such powerful reasons for acquiring and retaining wealth can’t be attributed to discouraged labor, insecure property, and an overtly destructive government. Indeed, when I look at the landscape of France, the numerous and wealthy cities, the impressive quality of her wide roads and bridges, the potential of her artificial canals and navigation systems enhancing maritime communication across such a vast continent,—when I focus on the monumental work of her ports and harbors, and her entire naval setup, whether for war or trade,—when I consider the number of her fortifications, built with bold and masterful skill, made and maintained at such a tremendous cost, presenting an armed front and impenetrable barrier to her enemies on every side,—when I remember how very little of that vast region is uncultivated, and how completely the cultivation of many of the best products of the earth has been perfected in France,—when I reflect on the excellence of her industries and goods, second to none but ours, and in some areas unmatched,—when I think about the significant foundations of charity, both public and private,—when I survey the state of all the arts that enhance and refine life,—when I count the people she has sacrificed to expand her reputation in war, her skilled statesmen, the multitude of her brilliant lawyers and theologians, her philosophers, critics, historians and archaeologists, her poets and orators, both sacred and secular,—I see in all this something that inspires awe and commands attention, which makes us pause before jumping to hasty and sweeping judgments, and which demands that we carefully examine what and how significant the underlying issues could be that might justify tearing down such a grand structure. I do not see the tyranny of Turkey in this perspective. Nor do I perceive the character of a government that has, overall, been so oppressive, corrupt, or negligent as to be completely unfit for any reform. I believe such a government deserves to enhance its strengths, correct its faults, and improve its capacities to align with a British Constitution.

Whoever has examined into the proceedings of that deposed government for several years back cannot fail to have observed, amidst the inconstancy and fluctuation natural to courts, an earnest endeavor towards the prosperity and improvement of the country; he must admit that it had long been employed, in some instances wholly to remove, in many considerably to correct, the abusive practices and usages that had prevailed in the state,—and that even the unlimited power of the sovereign over the persons of his subjects, inconsistent, as undoubtedly it was, with law and liberty, had yet been every day growing more mitigated in the exercise. So far from refusing itself to reformation, that government was open, with a censurable degree of facility, to all sorts of projects and projectors on the subject. Rather too much countenance was given to the spirit of innovation, which soon was turned against those who fostered it, and ended in their ruin. It is but cold, and no very flattering justice to that fallen monarchy, to say, that, for many years, it trespassed more by levity and want of judgment in several of its schemes than from any defect in diligence or in public spirit. To compare the government of France for the last fifteen or sixteen years with wise and well-constituted establishments during that, or during any period, is not to act with fairness. But if in point of prodigality in the expenditure of money, or in point of rigor in the exercise of power, it be compared with any of the former reigns, I believe candid judges will give little credit to the good intentions of those who dwell perpetually on the donations to favorites, or on the expenses of the court, or on the horrors of the Bastile, in the reign of Louis the Sixteenth.[109]

Whoever has looked into the actions of that deposed government over the past few years must have noticed, amid the natural inconsistency and changes typical in courts, a sincere effort to promote the prosperity and development of the country; they have to acknowledge that it had long been working, in some cases entirely to eliminate, and in many others significantly to improve, the abusive practices and customs that had existed in the state,—and that even the absolute power of the sovereign over the lives of his subjects, which was undoubtedly inconsistent with law and liberty, had been gradually exercised in a milder way over time. Far from resisting reform, that government was open, to a regrettable extent, to all kinds of projects and innovators on the topic. It gave a little too much support to the spirit of change, which soon turned against those who encouraged it, leading to their downfall. It's rather unfair and unflattering to say of that fallen monarchy that, for many years, it failed more due to carelessness and poor judgment in some of its plans than from any lack of effort or public spirit. Comparing the government of France over the last fifteen or sixteen years with wise and well-structured governments from that time or any other is not a just comparison. However, if we compare it in terms of excess spending or the strict exercise of power with any of the previous reigns, I believe impartial judges will have doubts about the good intentions of those who constantly focus on the gifts to favorites, the court's expenses, or the horrors of the Bastille during the reign of Louis the Sixteenth.[109]

Whether the system, if it deserves such a name, now built on the ruins of that ancient monarchy, will be able to give a better account of the population and wealth of the country which it has taken under its care, is a matter very doubtful. Instead of improving by the change, I apprehend that a long series of years must be told, before it can recover in any degree the effects of this philosophic Revolution, and before the nation can be replaced on its former footing. If Dr. Price should think fit, a few years hence, to favor us with an estimate of the population of France, he will hardly be able to make up his tale of thirty millions of souls, as computed in 1789, or the Assembly's computation of twenty-six millions of that year, or even M. Necker's twenty-five millions in 1780. I hear that there are considerable emigrations from France,—and that many, quitting that voluptuous climate, and that seductive Circean liberty, have taken refuge in the frozen regions and under the British despotism of Canada.

Whether the system, if it can even be called that, which has emerged from the remnants of the ancient monarchy, will actually provide a more accurate account of the population and wealth of the country it now oversees is highly uncertain. Instead of improving through this change, I fear that it will take many years before the nation can recover even slightly from the impacts of this philosophical Revolution, and before it can return to its previous state. If Dr. Price chooses to provide us with an estimate of the population of France in a few years, he will likely struggle to reach the thirty million figure estimated in 1789, the Assembly's estimate of twenty-six million from that year, or even M. Necker's twenty-five million from 1780. I've heard there are significant emigrations from France, and that many people, leaving that appealing climate and its enticing freedoms, have found refuge in the cold regions and under the British rule of Canada.

In the present disappearance of coin, no person could think it the same country in which the present minister of the finances has been able to discover fourscore millions sterling in specie. From its general aspect one would conclude that it had been for some time past under the special direction of the learned academicians of Laputa and Balnibarbi.[110] Already the population of Paris has so declined, that M. Necker stated to the National Assembly the provision to be made for its subsistence at a fifth less than what had formerly been found requisite.[111] It is said (and I have never heard it contradicted) that a hundred thousand people are out of employment in that city, though it is become the seat of the imprisoned court and National Assembly. Nothing, I am credibly informed, can exceed the shocking and disgusting spectacle of mendicancy displayed in that capital. Indeed, the votes of the National Assembly leave no doubt of the fact. They have lately appointed a standing committee of mendicancy. They are contriving at once a vigorous police on this subject, and, for the first time, the imposition of a tax to maintain the poor, for whoso present relief great sums appear on the face of the public accounts of the year.[112] In the mean time the leaders of the legislative clubs and coffee-houses are intoxicated with admiration at their own wisdom and ability. They speak with the most sovereign contempt of the rest of the world. They toll the people, to comfort them in the rags with which they have clothed them, that they are a nation of philosophers; and sometimes, by all the arts of quackish parade, by show, tumult, and bustle, sometimes by the alarms of plots and invasions, they attempt to drown the cries of indigence, and to divert the eyes of the observer from the ruin and wretchedness of the state. A brave people will certainly prefer liberty accompanied with a virtuous poverty to a depraved and wealthy servitude. But before the price of comfort and opulence is paid, one ought to be pretty sure it is real liberty which is purchased, and that she is to be purchased at no other price. I shall always, however, consider that liberty as very equivocal in her appearance, which has not wisdom and justice for her companions, and does not lead prosperity and plenty in her train.

In today's world of disappearing currency, no one would recognize it as the same country where the current finance minister has managed to find eighty million pounds in cash. From what you see, you’d think it has been under the control of the learned scholars from Laputa and Balnibarbi for some time.[110] The population of Paris has dropped so much that Mr. Necker informed the National Assembly that provisions for its sustenance are being estimated at a fifth less than what was previously considered necessary. [111] It is said (and I've never heard anyone dispute it) that a hundred thousand people are unemployed in that city, even though it has become the center for the trapped court and the National Assembly. I have credible information that the distressing and repulsive sight of begging in that capital is beyond anything else. Indeed, the votes from the National Assembly make it clear. They recently set up a standing committee on begging. They are developing a strict policy on this issue and, for the first time, introducing a tax to support the poor, as substantial amounts are evident in the public accounts for the year.[112] Meanwhile, the leaders of the legislative clubs and coffeehouses are drunk on their own self-importance. They speak with utter disdain for the rest of the world. They tell the people, trying to comfort them in their rags, that they are a nation of philosophers; and sometimes, through all sorts of flashy displays—chaos, noise, and commotion, and at times through fear of plots and invasions—they try to drown out the cries of the needy and distract observers from the ruin and misery of the state. A brave people will surely choose freedom alongside a noble poverty over a corrupt and wealthy servitude. But before paying the price for comfort and wealth, you should be very certain that the freedom you’re buying is genuine, and that it comes at no other cost. I will always see freedom as questionable if it does not have wisdom and justice as its companions, and does not bring prosperity and abundance with it.

The advocates for this Revolution, not satisfied with exaggerating the vices of their ancient government, strike at the fame of their country itself, by painting almost all that could have attracted the attention of strangers, I mean their nobility and their clergy, as objects of horror. If this were only a libel, there had not been much in it. But it has practical consequences. Had your nobility and gentry, who formed the great body of your landed men and the whole of your military officers, resembled those of Germany, at the period when the Hanse towns were necessitated to confederate against the nobles in defence of their property,—had they been like the Orsini and Vitelli in Italy, who used to sally from their fortified dens to rob the trader and traveller,—had they been such as the Mamelukes in Egypt, or the Nayres on the coast of Malabar,—I do admit that too critical an inquiry might not be advisable into the means of freeing the world from such a nuisance. The statues of Equity and Mercy might be veiled for a moment. The tenderest minds, confounded with the dreadful exigence in which morality submits to the suspension of its own rules in favor of its own principles, might turn aside whilst fraud and violence were accomplishing the destruction of a pretended nobility, which disgraced, whilst it persecuted, human nature. The persons most abhorrent from blood and treason and arbitrary confiscation might remain silent spectators of this civil war between the vices.

The supporters of this Revolution, not content with exaggerating the faults of their old government, attack the reputation of their country by depicting almost everything that could have captivated outsiders—namely, their nobility and clergy—as horror stories. If this were just slander, it wouldn’t be a big deal. But it has real consequences. If your nobility and gentry, who made up most of your landowners and all your military officers, had been like those in Germany when the Hanse towns had to band together against the nobles to protect their property,—if they had been like the Orsini and Vitelli in Italy, who would come out from their fortified homes to rob traders and travelers,—if they had been similar to the Mamelukes in Egypt, or the Nayres on the Malabar coast,—I can agree that a too detailed inquiry might not be wise when looking for ways to rid the world of such a nuisance. The statues of Equity and Mercy might be temporarily covered. The most sensitive individuals, faced with the terrible situation where morality has to set aside its own rules in favor of its principles, might look away while deception and violence were leading to the downfall of a so-called nobility that brought shame while it oppressed human nature. Those who are most against bloodshed, treason, and arbitrary confiscation might choose to remain silent witnesses to this civil war among the vices.

But did the privileged nobility who met under the king's precept at Versailles in 1789, or their constituents, deserve to be looked on as the Nayres or Mamelukes of this age, or as the Orsini and Vitelli of ancient times? If I had then asked the question, I should have passed for a madman. What have they since done, that they were to be driven into exile, that their persons should be hunted about, mangled, and tortured, their families dispersed, their houses laid in ashes, and that their order should be abolished, and the memory of it, if possible, extinguished, by ordaining them to change the very names by which they were usually known? Read their instructions to their representatives. They breathe the spirit of liberty as warmly, and they recommend reformation as strongly, as any other order. Their privileges relative to contribution were voluntarily surrendered; as the king, from the beginning, surrendered all pretence to a right of taxation. Upon a free constitution there was but one opinion in France. The absolute monarchy was at an end. It breathed its last without a groan, without struggle, without convulsion. All the struggle, all the dissension, arose afterwards, upon the preference of a despotic democracy to a government of reciprocal control. The triumph of the victorious party was over the principles of a British Constitution.

But did the privileged nobles who gathered under the king's orders at Versailles in 1789, or their supporters, deserve to be seen as the Nayres or Mamelukes of this time, or as the Orsini and Vitelli of ancient history? If I had asked that question back then, people would have thought I was crazy. What have they done since then that warranted their exile, that led to them being pursued, tortured, and mutilated, their families scattered, their homes burned down, and their class abolished, with any memory of it being erased, even to the point of forcing them to change the names by which they were commonly known? Read their instructions to their representatives. They express the spirit of liberty as passionately and advocate for reform as strongly as any other group. Their privileges regarding taxes were willingly given up; the king, from the outset, renounced any claim to tax authority. There was only one view on a free constitution in France. The absolute monarchy was finished. It ended quietly, without a groan, struggle, or upheaval. All the conflict and disagreement emerged later, over the choice between a tyrannical democracy and a system of checks and balances. The victorious party triumphed over the principles of the British Constitution.

I have observed the affectation which for many years past has prevailed in Paris, even to a degree perfectly childish, of idolizing the memory of your Henry the Fourth. If anything could put any one out of humor with that ornament to the kingly character, it would be this overdone style of insidious panegyric. The persons who have worked this engine the most busily are those who have ended their panegyrics in dethroning his successor and descendant: a man as good-natured, at the least, as Henry the Fourth; altogether as fond of his people; and who has done infinitely more to correct the ancient vices of the state than that great monarch did, or we are sure he ever meant to do. Well it is for his panegyrists that they have not him to deal with! For Henry of Navarre was a resolute, active, and politic prince. He possessed, indeed, great humanity and mildness, but an humanity and mildness that never stood in the way of his interests. He never sought to be loved without putting himself first in a condition to be feared. He used soft language with determined conduct. He asserted and maintained his authority in the gross, and distributed his acts of concession only in the detail. Ho spent the income of his prerogative nobly, but he took care not to break in upon the capital,—never abandoning for a moment any of the claims which he made under the fundamental laws, nor sparing to shed the blood of those who opposed him, often in the field, sometimes upon the scaffold. Because he knew how to make his virtues respected by the ungrateful, he has merited the praises of those whom, if they had lived in his time, he would have shut up in the Bastile, and brought to punishment along with the regicides whom he hanged after he had famished Paris into a surrender.

I have noticed the pretentiousness that has plagued Paris for many years, to a completely childish extent, of idolizing the memory of your Henry the Fourth. If anything could make someone dislike that royal figure, it would be this exaggerated style of insidious praise. The people who have promoted this hype the most are those who have ended their accolades by undermining his successor and descendant: a man just as good-natured, at the very least, as Henry the Fourth; just as fond of his people; and who has done far more to correct the old vices of the state than that great monarch ever did, or likely intended to do. It’s fortunate for his admirers that they don’t have to deal with him! For Henry of Navarre was a determined, active, and strategic ruler. He had significant humanity and gentleness, but his humanity and gentleness never got in the way of his interests. He never sought to be loved without first placing himself in a position to be feared. He spoke kindly but acted decisively. He asserted and upheld his authority boldly, and only made concessions in specific instances. He spent the income from his royal prerogative generously, but he made sure not to touch the principal—never once abandoning any of his rights under the fundamental laws, nor hesitating to shed blood against those who opposed him, sometimes in battle, sometimes on the scaffold. Because he knew how to earn respect for his virtues from the ungrateful, he has deserved the praises of those whom, had they lived in his time, he would have locked up in the Bastille and punished alongside the regicides he executed after starving Paris into surrender.

If these panegyrists are in earnest in their admiration of Henry the Fourth, they must remember that they cannot think more highly of him than he did of the noblesse of France,—whose virtue, honor, courage, patriotism, and loyalty were his constant theme.

If these admirers are genuinely enthusiastic about Henry the Fourth, they need to keep in mind that they can't think more highly of him than he thought of the nobility of France—whose virtue, honor, courage, patriotism, and loyalty were his consistent topics.

But the nobility of France are degenerated since the days of Henry the Fourth.—This is possible; but it is more than I can believe to be true in any great degree. I do not pretend to know France as correctly as some others; but I have endeavored through my whole life to make myself acquainted with human nature,—otherwise I should be unfit to take even my humble part in the service of mankind. In that study I could not pass by a vast portion of our nature as it appeared modified in a country but twenty-four miles from the shore of this island. On my best observation, compared with my best inquiries, I found your nobility for the greater part composed of men of a high spirit, and of a delicate sense of honor, both with regard to themselves individually, and with regard to their whole corps, over whom they kept, beyond what is common in other countries, a censorial eye. They were tolerably well bred; very officious, humane, and hospitable; in their conversation frank and open; with a good military tone; and reasonably tinctured with literature, particularly of the authors in their own language. Many had pretensions far above this description. I speak of those who were generally met with.

But the nobility of France has declined since the days of Henry the Fourth. This might

As to their behavior to the inferior classes, they appeared to me to comport themselves towards them with good-nature, and with something more nearly approaching to familiarity than is generally practised with us in the intercourse between the higher and lower ranks of life. To strike any person, even in the most abject condition, was a thing in a manner unknown, and would be highly disgraceful. Instances of other ill-treatment of the humble part of the community were rare; and as to attacks made upon the property or the personal liberty of the commons, I never heard of any whatsoever from them,—nor, whilst the laws were in vigor under the ancient government, would such tyranny in subjects have been permitted. As men of landed estates, I had no fault to find with their conduct, though much to reprehend, and much to wish changed, in many of the old tenures. Where the letting of their land was by rent, I could not discover that their agreements with their farmers were oppressive; nor when they were in partnership with the farmer, as often was the case, have I heard that they had taken the lion's share. The proportions seemed not inequitable. There might be exceptions; but certainly they were exceptions only. I have no reason to believe that in these respects the landed noblesse of France were worse than the landed gentry of this country,—certainly in no respect more vexatious than the landholders, not noble, of their own nation. In cities the nobility had no manner of power; in the country very little. You know, Sir, that much of the civil government, and the police in the most essential parts, was not in the hands of that nobility which presents itself first to our consideration. The revenue, the system and collection of which were the most grievous parts of the French government, was not administered by the men of the sword; nor were they answerable for the vices of its principle, or the vexations, where any such existed, in its management.

Regarding their treatment of the lower classes, they seemed to interact with them in a friendly way, showing more familiarity than what we typically see between the upper and lower classes. Hitting anyone, even those in the lowest positions, was almost unheard of and would be considered very shameful. Cases of mistreatment towards the less fortunate were uncommon; as for attacks on the property or personal freedom of common people, I never heard of any from them. Under the old government, such tyranny against subjects would not have been allowed. As landowners, I found no fault with their behavior, though there were many aspects of the old tenures that I would criticize and wish to see changed. When their land was rented out, I didn’t see any evidence that their agreements with farmers were unfair; nor did I hear that, when they partnered with farmers, they took advantage of them. The distribution seemed fair, although exceptions might have existed, they were surely rare. I have no reason to believe that the landed nobility of France acted worse than the landed gentry here—certainly not in a more annoying way than the non-noble landholders of their own country. In cities, the nobility had no real power; in the countryside, very little. You know, Sir, that much of the civil government and essential police functions were not controlled by that nobility which we first consider. The revenue system, which was one of the most burdensome aspects of the French government, wasn’t managed by the military nobility, nor were they responsible for its faults or any annoyances in its administration.

Denying, as I am well warranted to do, that the nobility had any considerable share in the oppression of the people, in cases in which real oppression existed, I am ready to admit that they were not without considerable faults and errors. A foolish imitation of the worst part of the manners of England, which impaired their natural character, without substituting in its place what perhaps they meant to copy, has certainly rendered them worse than formerly they were. Habitual dissoluteness of manners, continued beyond the pardonable period of life, was more common amongst them than it is with us; and it reigned with the less hope of remedy, though possibly with something of less mischief, by being covered with more exterior decorum. They countenanced too much that licentious philosophy which has helped to bring on their ruin. There was another error amongst them more fatal. Those of the commons who approached to or exceeded many of the nobility in point of wealth were not fully admitted to the rank and estimation which wealth, in reason and good policy, ought to bestow in every country,—though I think not equally with that of other nobility. The two kinds of aristocracy were too punctiliously kept asunder: less so, however, than in Germany and some other nations.

Denying, as I rightfully can, that the nobility played a significant role in the oppression of the people when real oppression occurred, I admit they had their fair share of faults and mistakes. Their foolish imitation of the worst aspects of English manners tarnished their natural character without successfully replacing it with what they likely intended to emulate, making them worse than they used to be. A persistent disregard for proper conduct, extending beyond an acceptable age, was more common among them than it is today, existing with less chance of correction, although it might have caused slightly less harm thanks to a facade of outward decorum. They supported too much of the reckless philosophy that contributed to their downfall. There was another mistake among them that was even more damaging. Those commoners who matched or surpassed many members of the nobility in wealth were not fully recognized with the rank and respect that wealth should rightfully grant in any country—though I believe it shouldn't have been equal to that of the nobility. The two types of aristocracy were kept too distinctly separate; however, not as much as in Germany and some other nations.

This separation, as I have already taken the liberty of suggesting to you, I conceive to be one principal cause of the destruction of the old nobility. The military, particularly, was too exclusively reserved for men of family. But, after all, this was an error of opinion, which a conflicting opinion would have rectified. A permanent Assembly, in which the commons had their share of power, would soon abolish whatever was too invidious and insulting in these distinctions; and even the faults in the morals of the nobility would have been probably corrected, by the greater varieties of occupation and pursuit to which a constitution by orders would have given rise.

This separation, as I have already suggested to you, seems to be a major reason for the downfall of the old nobility. The military, in particular, was mainly reserved for those of noble birth. However, this was ultimately a mistaken belief that an opposing viewpoint could have corrected. A permanent Assembly where the common people had a share of power would soon eliminate any distinctions that were overly contentious and offensive; and even the moral failings of the nobility could have likely been addressed by the wider range of occupations and pursuits that a system of different social classes would have created.

All this violent cry against the nobility I take to be a mere work of art. To be honored and even privileged by the laws, opinions, and inveterate usages of our country, growing out of the prejudice of ages, has nothing to provoke horror and indignation in any man. Even to be too tenacious of those privileges is not absolutely a crime. The strong struggle in every individual to preserve possession of what he has found to belong to him, and to distinguish him, is one of the securities against injustice and despotism implanted in our nature. It operates as an instinct to secure property, and to preserve communities in a settled state. What is there to shock in this? Nobility is a graceful ornament to the civil order. It is the Corinthian capital of polished society. "Omnes boni nobilitati semper favemus," was the saying of a wise and good man. It is, indeed, one sign of a liberal and benevolent mind to incline to it with some sort of partial propensity. He feels no ennobling principle in his own heart, who wishes to level all the artificial institutions which have been adopted for giving a body to opinion and permanence to fugitive esteem. It is a sour, malignant, envious disposition, without taste for the reality, or for any image or representation of virtue, that sees with joy the unmerited fall of what had long nourished in splendor and in honor. I do not like to see anything destroyed, any void produced in society, any ruin on the face of the land. It was therefore with no disappointment or dissatisfaction that my inquiries and observations did not present to me any incorrigible vices in the noblesse of France, or any abuse which could not be removed by a reform very short of abolition. Your noblesse did not deserve punishment; but to degrade is to punish.

All this violent outcry against the nobility seems to me like a mere work of art. Being honored and even privileged by the laws, opinions, and long-standing traditions of our country, stemming from age-old prejudices, isn’t something that should provoke horror or outrage in anyone. Even being overly attached to those privileges isn’t necessarily a crime. The strong instinct in every individual to hold on to what they believe belongs to them and to stand out is one of the safeguards against injustice and tyranny that is part of our nature. It functions like an instinct to protect property and to keep communities stable. What’s so shocking about that? Nobility is a graceful addition to civil society. It’s the Corinthian capital of refined culture. “Omnes boni nobilitati semper favemus,” was the saying of a wise and good man. It is, in fact, a sign of a generous and kind mind to feel some sort of preference for it. Anyone who wishes to tear down all the artificial structures that have been created to give shape to opinions and permanence to fleeting esteem shows no sense of nobility in their own heart. It’s a bitter, malicious, envious attitude, lacking appreciation for real virtue or any representation of it, that takes joy in the undeserved downfall of what has long thrived in splendor and honor. I dislike seeing anything destroyed, any void created in society, or any ruin across the land. So, I wasn’t disappointed or dissatisfied when my inquiries and observations didn’t reveal any irredeemable flaws among the French nobility or any abuses that couldn’t be fixed with reforms well short of abolition. Your nobility didn’t deserve punishment; to degrade is to punish.

It was with the same satisfaction I found that the result of my inquiry concerning your clergy was not dissimilar. It is no soothing news to my ears, that great bodies of men are incurably corrupt. It is not with much credulity I listen to any, when they speak evil of those whom they are going to plunder. I rather suspect that vices are feigned or exaggerated, when profit is looked for in their punishment. An enemy is a bad witness; a robber is a worse. Vices and abuses there were undoubtedly in that order, and must be. It was an old establishment, and not frequently revised. But I saw no crimes in the individuals that merited confiscation of their substance, nor those cruel insults and degradations, and that unnatural persecution, which have been substituted in the place of meliorating regulation.

I felt the same relief when I found that the results of my inquiry about your clergy were similar. It's not comforting to hear that large groups of people are hopelessly corrupt. I don't easily believe what anyone says when they speak badly of those they plan to exploit. I tend to think that their faults are exaggerated or made up when there's a profit to gain from punishing them. An enemy makes a poor witness; a thief makes an even worse one. There were indeed faults and abuses present, and there probably had to be, as it was an old institution that wasn't frequently updated. However, I didn't see any crimes in the individuals that justified taking away their possessions or subjecting them to cruel insults and degradations, or that unnatural persecution, which has replaced reasonable regulation.

If there had been any just cause for this new religions persecution, the atheistic libellers, who act as trumpeters to animate the populace to plunder, do not love anybody so much as not to dwell with complacence on the vices of the existing clergy. This they have not done. They find themselves obliged to rake into the histories of former ages (which they have ransacked with a malignant and profligate industry) for every instance of oppression and persecution which has been made by that body or in its favor, in order to justify, upon very iniquitous because very illogical principles of retaliation, their own persecutions and their own cruelties. After destroying all other genealogies and family distinctions, they invent a sort of pedigree of crimes. It is not very just to chastise men for the offences of their natural ancestors; but to take the fiction of ancestry in a corporate succession, as a ground for punishing men who have no relation to guilty acts, except in names and general descriptions, is a sort of refinement in injustice belonging to the philosophy of this enlightened age. The Assembly punishes men, many, if not most, of whom abhor the violent conduct of ecclesiastics in former times as much as their present persecutors can do, and who would be as loud and as strong in the expression of that sense, if they were not well aware of the purposes for which all this declamation is employed.

If there had been any valid reason for this new persecution of religions, the godless critics, who incite the public to loot, aren't so fond of anyone that they don't take pleasure in highlighting the flaws of the current clergy. They haven't done this. They feel compelled to dig through the histories of past ages (which they have searched with a spiteful and reckless effort) for every instance of oppression and persecution committed by that group or in its favor, in order to justify their own persecutions and cruelties based on very unfair and illogical principles of revenge. After dismantling all other lineages and family distinctions, they create a twisted genealogy of crimes. It's not really fair to punish people for the sins of their ancestors; but to use the idea of collective ancestry as a reason to punish individuals who are not connected to any wrongdoing except in name and broad descriptions is a form of injustice that fits the philosophy of this so-called enlightened age. The Assembly punishes many individuals, if not most, who detest the violent actions of church leaders in the past just as much as their current oppressors do, and who would express that sentiment loudly and strongly if they weren't fully aware of the motives behind all this rhetoric.

Corporate bodies are immortal for the good of the members, but not for their punishment. Nations themselves are such corporations. As well might we in England think of waging inexpiable war upon all Frenchmen for the evils which they have brought upon us in the several periods of our mutual hostilities. You might, on your part, think yourselves justified in falling upon all Englishmen on account of the unparalleled calamities brought upon the people of France by the unjust invasions of our Henrys and our Edwards. Indeed, we should be mutually justified in this exterminatory war upon each other, full as much as you are in the unprovoked persecution of your present countrymen, on account of the conduct of men of the same name in other times.

Corporate entities exist indefinitely for the benefit of their members, but not for their punishment. Nations themselves are similar organizations. It would be just as unreasonable for us in England to think about waging an endless war against all French people for the wrongs they have inflicted on us during our past conflicts. You might think you’re justified in attacking all English people because of the immense suffering caused to the people of France by the unjust invasions of our Henrys and Edwards. In fact, we could both feel justified in waging an extermination war against each other just as much as you do in unjustly persecuting your fellow countrymen for the actions of people with the same name in different times.

We do not draw the moral lessons we might from history. On the contrary, without care it may be used to vitiate our minds and to destroy our happiness. In history a great volume is unrolled for our instruction, drawing the materials of future wisdom from the past errors and infirmities of mankind. It may, in the perversion, serve for a magazine, furnishing offensive and defensive weapons for parties in Church and State, and supplying the means of keeping alive or reviving dissensions and animosities, and adding fuel to civil fury. History consists, for the greater part, of the miseries brought upon the world by pride, ambition, avarice, revenge, lust, sedition, hypocrisy, ungoverned zeal, and all the train of disorderly appetites, which shake the public with the same

We often miss the important lessons we can learn from history. In fact, if we're not careful, history can warp our minds and ruin our happiness. History lays out a vast amount of information for us to learn from, taking insights for future wisdom from the mistakes and weaknesses of humanity in the past. However, if misused, it can serve as a resource for fueling arguments within religious and political groups, keeping conflicts and resentments alive, and intensifying civil unrest. Much of history is filled with the suffering caused by pride, ambition, greed, revenge, lust, rebellion, hypocrisy, uncontrolled zeal, and all the chaotic desires that disturb society with similar consequences.

"troublesome storms that toss
The private state makes life bitter."

These vices are the causes of those storms. Religion, morals, laws, prerogatives, privileges, liberties, rights of men, are the pretexts. The pretexts are always found in some specious appearance of a real good. You would not secure men from tyranny and sedition by rooting out of the mind the principles to which these fraudulent pretexts apply? If you did, you would root out everything that is valuable in the human breast. As these are the pretexts, so the ordinary actors and instruments in great public evils are kings, priests, magistrates, senates, parliaments, national assemblies, judges, and captains. You would not cure the evil by resolving that there should be no more monarchs, nor ministers of state, nor of the Gospel,—no interpreters of law, no general officers, no public councils. You might change the names: the things in some shape must remain. A certain quantum of power must always exist in the community, in some hands, and under some appellation. Wise men will apply their remedies to vices, not to names,—to the causes of evil, which are permanent, not to the occasional organs by which they act, and the transitory modes in which they appear. Otherwise you will be wise historically, a fool in practice. Seldom have two ages the same fashion in their pretexts, and the same modes of mischief. Wickedness is a little more inventive. Whilst you are discussing fashion, the fashion is gone by. The very same vice assumes a new body. The spirit transmigrates; and, far from losing its principle of life by the change of its appearance, it is renovated in its new organs with the fresh vigor of a juvenile activity. It walks abroad, it continues its ravages, whilst you are gibbeting the carcass or demolishing the tomb. You are terrifying yourselves with ghosts and apparitions, whilst your house is the haunt of robbers. It is thus with all those who, attending only to the shell and husk of history, think they are waging war with intolerance, pride, and cruelty, whilst, under color of abhorring the ill principles of antiquated parties, they are authorizing and feeding the same odious vices in different factions, and perhaps in worse.

These vices are the causes of those storms. Religion, morals, laws, privileges, rights of men are the pretexts. The pretexts are always found in some deceptive appearance of a real good. Would you really protect people from tyranny and unrest by eliminating the beliefs that these misleading pretexts rely on? If you did, you would wipe out everything valuable in the human spirit. Just as these are the pretexts, the usual players and tools in significant public wrongdoings are kings, priests, judges, senates, parliaments, national assemblies, judges, and military leaders. You wouldn't fix the problem by deciding there should be no more monarchs, ministers of state, or religious leaders—no interpreters of the law, no military officials, no public councils. You might change the titles, but the reality in some form must persist. A certain amount of power will always exist in the community, in some hands, and under some name. Wise people will address the vices, not the names—the underlying causes of evil that are permanent, rather than the temporary instruments through which they operate, and the fleeting ways they manifest. Otherwise, you'll be historically informed but practically foolish. Rarely do two eras share the same style in their pretexts and ways of doing harm. Wickedness is a bit more creative. While you're debating style, the style has already passed. The same vice takes on a new form. The spirit shifts; and rather than losing its life force with the change in appearance, it becomes revitalized in its new forms with the fresh energy of youthful activity. It continues to roam, wreaking havoc while you are busy displaying the remains or tearing down the grave. You are scaring yourselves with ghosts and visions while your home is overrun by thieves. This is how it is with all those who, focusing only on the surface and outer layers of history, think they are fighting against intolerance, pride, and cruelty, while, under the guise of rejecting the harmful principles of outdated groups, they are legitimizing and nurturing the same hateful vices in different factions, possibly in even worse forms.

Your citizens of Paris formerly had lent themselves as the ready instruments to slaughter the followers of Calvin, at the infamous massacre of St. Bartholomew. What should we say to those who could think of retaliating on the Parisians of this day the abominations and horrors of that time? They are, indeed, brought to abhor that massacre. Ferocious as they are, it is not difficult to make them dislike it, because the politicians and fashionable teachers have no interest in giving their passions exactly the same direction. Still, however, they find it their interest to keep the same savage dispositions alive. It was but the other day that they caused this very massacre to be acted on the stage for the diversion of the descendants of those who committed it. In this tragic farce they produced the Cardinal of Lorraine in his robes of function, ordering general slaughter. Was this spectacle intended to make the Parisians abhor persecution and loathe the effusion of blood? No: it was to teach them to persecute their own pastors; it was to excite them, by raising a disgust and horror of their clergy, to an alacrity in hunting down to destruction an order which, if it ought to exist at all, ought to exist not only in safety, but in reverence. It was to stimulate their cannibal appetites (which one would think had been gorged sufficiently) by variety and seasoning,—and to quicken them to an alertness in new murders and massacres, if it should suit the purpose of the Guises of the day. An Assembly in which sat a multitude of priests and prelates was obliged to suffer this indignity at its door. The author was not sent to the galleys, nor the players to the house of correction. Not long after this exhibition, those players came forward to the Assembly to claim the rites of that very religion which they had dared to expose, and to show their prostituted faces in the senate, whilst the Archbishop of Paris, whose function was known to his people only by his prayers and benedictions, and his wealth only by alms, is forced to abandon his house, and to fly from his flock, (as from ravenous wolves,) because, truly, in the sixteenth century, the Cardinal of Lorraine was a rebel and a murderer.[113]

Your citizens of Paris used to be quick to join in the slaughter of Calvin's followers during the infamous St. Bartholomew’s Day Massacre. What should we say to those who contemplate punishing today’s Parisians for the horrendous acts of that time? They have indeed come to detest that massacre. As fierce as they are, it's not hard for them to dislike it, because politicians and trendy educators have no interest in stirring their emotions in the same way. Still, they find it beneficial to keep their savage instincts alive. Just the other day, they staged that very massacre for the entertainment of the descendants of those who committed it. In this tragic farce, they portrayed the Cardinal of Lorraine in his official robes, commanding mass slaughter. Was this spectacle meant to make Parisians hate persecution and detest bloodshed? No; it was meant to encourage them to persecute their own pastors. It aimed to incite them by instilling a disgust and hatred for their clergy, pushing them to eagerly hunt down and destroy a group that, if it had to exist at all, should at least be safe and respected. It was to awaken their cannibalistic cravings (which one would think had been satisfied already) by providing variety and seasoning—and to prompt them to quickly engage in new murders and massacres if it suited the interests of the Guises of the day. An Assembly filled with many priests and prelates had to endure this humiliation at its doors. The author wasn’t punished, nor were the actors sent to jail. Shortly after this performance, those actors approached the Assembly to seek the privileges of the very religion they had dared to mock, showing their disgraced faces in the senate, while the Archbishop of Paris, known to his people only through his prayers and blessings, and his wealth only through charity, was forced to flee his home and escape from his flock (like from ravenous wolves) because, truly, in the sixteenth century, the Cardinal of Lorraine was a rebel and a murderer.[113]

Such is the effect of the perversion of history by those who, for the same nefarious purposes, have perverted every other part of learning. But those who will stand upon that elevation of reason which places centuries under our eye and brings things to the true point of comparison, which obscures little names and effaces the colors of little parties, and to which nothing can ascend but the spirit and moral quality of human actions, will say to the teachers of the Palais Royal,—The Cardinal of Lorraine was the murderer of the sixteenth century; you have the glory of being the murderers in the eighteenth; and this is the only difference between you. But history in the nineteenth century, better understood and better employed, will, I trust, teach a civilized posterity to abhor the misdeeds of both these barbarous ages. It will teach future priests and magistrates not to retaliate upon the speculative and inactive atheists of future times the enormities committed by the present practical zealots and furious fanatics of that wretched error, which, in its quiescent state, is more than punished, whenever it is embraced. It will teach posterity not to make war upon either religion or philosophy for the abuse which the hypocrites of both have made of the two most valuable blessings conferred upon us by the bounty of the universal Patron, who in all things eminently favors and protects the race of man.

Such is the impact of distorting history by those who have twisted every other area of learning for the same selfish reasons. But those who elevate themselves to a level of reason that allows them to see centuries clearly and compare things accurately, removing the shadows of small names and diminishing the conflicts of minor groups, will say to the teachers of the Palais Royal, — The Cardinal of Lorraine was the murderer of the sixteenth century; you share the distinction of being the murderers of the eighteenth; and that's the only difference between you. However, history in the nineteenth century, better understood and utilized, will hopefully teach future generations to reject the wrongdoings of both these brutal eras. It will instruct future priests and officials not to take out their frustrations on the thoughtful and passive atheists of the future for the atrocities committed by today’s active zealots and violent fanatics, whose terrible error is, in its dormant state, more than compensated whenever it is accepted. It will teach future generations not to wage war against either religion or philosophy for the misuse that the hypocrites of both have made of the two most precious gifts granted to us by the generosity of the universal Creator, who in all things notably supports and protects humanity.

If your clergy, or any clergy, should show themselves vicious beyond the fair bounds allowed to human infirmity, and to those professional faults which can hardly be separated from professional virtues, though their vices never can countenance the exercise of oppression, I do admit that they would naturally have the effect of abating very much of our indignation against the tyrants who exceed measure and justice in their punishment. I can allow in clergymen, through all their divisions, some tenaciousness of their own opinion, some overflowings of zeal for its propagation, some predilection to their own state and office, some attachment to the interest of their own corps, some preference to those who Us ten with docility to their doctrines beyond those who scorn and deride them. I allow all this, because I am a man who have to deal with men, and who would not, through a violence of toleration, run into the greatest of all intolerance. I must bear with infirmities, until they fester into crimes.

If your clergy, or any clergy, act in a way that's way off the mark compared to the acceptable limits of human flaws, and the professional mistakes that are hard to separate from the professional qualities, even though their wrongdoings can never justify any abuse of power, I acknowledge that this behavior might really reduce our anger towards the tyrants who go too far in their punishments. I can accept that clergymen, regardless of their different factions, might hold strong opinions, have a passionate desire to spread their beliefs, show a bias towards their own position and role, stick up for their own group's interests, and favor those who follow their teachings more obediently over those who mock and ridicule them. I accept all of this because I'm a person dealing with other people and I wouldn't want to become the worst kind of intolerant by being overly permissive. I need to put up with flaws until they turn into serious wrongs.

Undoubtedly, the natural progress of the passions, from frailty to vice, ought to be prevented by a watchful eye and a firm hand. But is it true that the body of your clergy had passed those limits of a just allowance? Prom the general style of your late publications of all sorts, one would be led to believe that your clergy in France were a sort of monsters: an horrible composition of superstition, ignorance, sloth, fraud, avarice, and tyranny. But is this true? Is it true that the lapse of time, the cessation of conflicting interests, the woful experience of the evils resulting from party rage, have had no sort of influence gradually to meliorate their minds? Is it true that they were daily renewing invasions on the civil power, troubling the domestic quiet of their country, and rendering the operations of its government feeble and precarious? Is it true that the clergy of our times have pressed down the laity with an iron hand, and were in all places lighting up the fires of a savage persecution? Did they by every fraud endeavor to increase their estates? Did they use to exceed the due demands on estates that were their own? Or, rigidly screwing up right into wrong, did they convert a legal claim into a vexatious extortion? When not possessed of power, were they filled with the vices of those who envy it? Were they inflamed with a violent, litigious spirit of controversy? Goaded on with the ambition of intellectual sovereignty, were they ready to fly in the face of all magistracy, to fire churches, to massacre the priests of other descriptions, to pull down altars, and to make their way over the ruins of subverted governments to an empire of doctrine, sometimes flattering, sometimes forcing, the consciences of men from the jurisdiction of public institutions into a submission to their personal authority, beginning with a claim of liberty and ending with an abuse of power?

Without a doubt, the natural evolution of passions, from weakness to wrongdoing, should be kept in check by a careful eye and a strong hand. But is it really true that your clergy have gone beyond the limits of what is acceptable? From the general tone of your recent publications of all kinds, one might think that your clergy in France are some sort of monsters: a horrible mix of superstition, ignorance, laziness, deceit, greed, and oppression. But is that really true? Has the passage of time, the end of conflicting interests, and the unfortunate lessons learned from the harms of factionalism not had any effect on gradually improving their minds? Is it true that they continuously invade civil authority, disrupt the peace of their country, and make the operations of its government weak and unstable? Is it true that the clergy of today have kept the laity under an iron grip, instigating fierce persecution everywhere? Did they try to expand their wealth through every deceitful means? Did they go beyond what was reasonable regarding their own estates? Or, by twisting rights into wrongs, did they turn a legal claim into a burdensome extortion? When they lacked power, were they consumed by the vices of those who envy it? Were they driven by a fierce, litigious spirit of conflict? Spurred on by the desire for intellectual dominance, were they willing to confront all forms of authority, burn churches, slaughter priests of other faiths, tear down altars, and build their empire over the ruins of fallen governments, sometimes flattering and sometimes forcing people's consciences away from public institutions to submit to their personal authority, starting with a claim of freedom and ending with an abuse of power?

These, or some of these, were the vices objected, and not wholly without foundation, to several of the churchmen of former times, who belonged to the two great parties which then divided and distracted Europe.

These, or some of these, were the flaws pointed out, and not without some basis, regarding several church leaders from the past, who were part of the two major factions that divided and troubled Europe at that time.

If there was in France, as in other countries there visibly is, a great abatement, rather than any increase of these vices, instead of loading the present clergy with the crimes of other men and the odious character of other times, in common equity they ought to be praised, encouraged, and supported, in their departure from a spirit which disgraced their predecessors, and for having assumed a temper of mind and manners more suitable to their sacred function.

If there was in France, as there clearly is in other countries, a significant reduction, rather than an increase, of these vices, instead of blaming the current clergy for the wrongdoings of others and the unpleasant traits of the past, they should, in fairness, be praised, encouraged, and supported for moving away from the behaviors that embarrassed their predecessors and for adopting attitudes and conduct that are more fitting for their sacred role.

When my occasions took me into France, towards the close of the late reign, the clergy, under all their forms, engaged a considerable part of my curiosity. So far from finding (except from one set of men, not then very numerous, though very active) the complaints and discontents against that body which some publications had given me reason to expect, I perceived little or no public or private uneasiness on their account. On further examination, I found the clergy, in general, persons of moderate minds and decorous manners: I include the seculars, and the regulars of both sexes. I had not the good fortune to know a great many of the parochial clergy: but in general I received a perfectly good account of their morals, and of their attention to their duties. With some of the higher clergy I had a personal acquaintance, and of the rest in that class a very good means of information. They were almost all of them persons of noble birth. They resembled others of their own rank; and where there was any difference, it was in their favor. They were more fully educated than the military noblesse,—so as by no means to disgrace their profession by ignorance, or by want of fitness for the exercise of their authority. They seemed to me, beyond the clerical character, liberal and open, with the hearts of gentlemen and men of honor, neither insolent nor servile in their manners and conduct. They seemed to me rather a superior class,—a set of men amongst whom you would not be surprised to find a Fénelon. I saw among the clergy in Paris (many of the description are not to be met with anywhere) men of great learning and candor; and I had reason to believe that this description was not confined to Paris. What I found in other places I know was accidental, and therefore to be presumed a fair sample. I spent a few days in a provincial town, where, in the absence of the bishop, I passed my evenings with three clergymen, his vicars-general, persons who would have done honor to any church. They were all well-informed; two of them of deep, general, and extensive erudition, ancient and modern, Oriental and Western,—particularly in their own profession. They had a more extensive knowledge of our English divines than I expected; and they entered into the genius of those writers with a critical accuracy. One of these gentlemen is since dead: the Abbé Morangis. I pay this tribute without reluctance to the memory of that noble, reverend, learned, and excellent person; and I should do the same with equal cheerfulness to the merits of the others, who I believe are still living, if I did not fear to hurt those whom I am unable to serve.

When I visited France towards the end of the previous reign, the clergy, in all their forms, captured a significant part of my curiosity. Contrary to what I had expected from certain publications, which suggested there was widespread discontent with them, I found little to no public or private dissatisfaction regarding their presence. Upon closer examination, I saw that, in general, the clergy were moderate-minded individuals with decent behavior, including both secular clergy and regulars of all genders. I didn’t get the chance to meet many parish clergy, but overall, I heard good things about their morals and commitment to their duties. I had personal connections with some higher-ranking clergy and had reliable sources of information about others in that category. Most of them came from noble backgrounds and shared similarities with other people of their rank; in cases where there were differences, they favored the clergy. They were better educated than the military nobility, ensuring that they wouldn't bring shame to their role through ignorance or unfitness for their responsibilities. Beyond being clerics, they struck me as liberal and open-minded, embodying the virtues of gentlemen and honorable men, neither arrogant nor submissive in their behavior. They appeared to be a distinguished group, someone you wouldn’t be shocked to find a Fénelon among. In Paris, I encountered many clergymen—many of whom you wouldn't find elsewhere—who were highly knowledgeable and candid. I also had reason to believe this wasn't just a Parisian phenomenon. The experiences I had in other locations seemed coincidental, suggesting a fair representation. I spent a few days in a provincial town, where, in the bishop's absence, I spent my evenings with three clergymen, his vicars-general, who would bring honor to any church. They were all well-informed, with two of them possessing deep, extensive knowledge of ancient and modern literature, both Eastern and Western, particularly relating to their profession. They had a broader understanding of our English theologians than I had anticipated, and they analyzed those authors with impressive discernment. One of these gentlemen, the Abbé Morangis, has since passed away. I pay this tribute without hesitation to the memory of that noble, reverent, learned, and outstanding individual, and I would gladly do the same for the others, whom I believe are still alive, if I were not concerned about hurting those I cannot assist.

Some of these ecclesiastics of rank are, by all titles, persons deserving of general respect. They are deserving of gratitude from me, and from many English. If this letter should ever come into their hands, I hope they will believe there are those of our nation who feel for their unmerited fall, and for the cruel confiscation of their fortunes, with no common sensibility. What I say of them is a testimony, as far as one feeble voice can go, which I owe to truth. Whenever the question of this unnatural persecution is concerned, I will pay it. No one shall prevent me from being just and grateful. The time is fitted for the duty; and it is particularly becoming to show our justice and gratitude, when those who have deserved well of us and of mankind are laboring under popular obloquy and the persecutions of oppressive power.

Some of these high-ranking church leaders truly deserve everyone's respect. They have my gratitude, and that of many English people. If this letter ever reaches them, I hope they understand that there are members of our nation who genuinely sympathize with their unjust downfall and the harsh loss of their assets, with deep feelings. What I say about them is a testament, as far as one weak voice can express, that I owe to the truth. Whenever the topic of this unnatural persecution comes up, I will speak out. No one will stop me from being fair and thankful. The time is right for this duty; it’s especially important to show our fairness and gratitude when those who have done well for us and for humanity are suffering under public shame and the oppression of powerful forces.

You had before your Revolution about a hundred and twenty bishops. A few of them were men of eminent sanctity, and charity without limit. When we talk of the heroic, of course we talk of rare virtue. I believe the instances of eminent depravity may be as rare amongst them as those of transcendent goodness. Examples of avarice and of licentiousness may be picked out, I do not question it, by those who delight in the investigation which leads to such discoveries. A man as old as I am will not be astonished that several, in every description, do not lead that perfect life of self-denial, with regard to wealth or to pleasure, which is wished for by all, by some expected, but by none exacted with more rigor than by those who are the most attentive to their own interests or the most indulgent to their own passions. When I was in France, I am certain that the number of vicious prelates was not great. Certain individuals among them, not distinguishable for the regularity of their lives, made some amends for their want of the severe virtues in their possession of the liberal, and wore endowed with qualities which made them useful in the Church and State. I am told, that, with few exceptions, Louis the Sixteenth had been more attentive to character, in his promotions to that rank, than his immediate predecessor; and I believe (as some spirit of reform has prevailed through the whole reign) that it may be true. But the present ruling power has shown a disposition only to plunder the Church. It has punished all prelates: which is to favor the vicious, at least in point of reputation. It has made a degrading pensionary establishment, to which no man of liberal ideas or liberal condition will destine his children. It must settle into the lowest classes of the people. As with you the inferior clergy are not numerous enough for their duties, as these duties are beyond measure minute and toilsome, as you have left no middle classes of clergy at their ease, in future nothing of science or erudition can exist in the Gallican Church. To complete the project, without the least attention to the rights of patrons, the Assembly has provided in future an elective clergy: an arrangement which will drive out of the clerical profession all men of sobriety, all who can pretend to independence in their function or their conduct,—and which will throw the whole direction of the public mind into the hands of a set of licentious, bold, crafty, factious, flattering wretches, of such condition and such habits of life as will make their contemptible pensions (in comparison of which the stipend of an exciseman is lucrative and honorable) an object of low and illiberal intrigue. Those officers whom they still call bishops are to be elected to a provision comparatively mean, through the same arts, (that is, electioneering arts,) by men of all religious tenets that are known or can be invented. The new lawgivers have not ascertained anything whatsoever concerning their qualifications, relative either to doctrine or to morals, no more than they have done with regard to the subordinate clergy; nor does it appear but that both the higher and the lower may, at their discretion, practise or preach any mode of religion or irreligion that they please. I do not yet see what the jurisdiction of bishops over their subordinates is to be, or whether they are to have any jurisdiction at all.

You had around one hundred and twenty bishops before your Revolution. A few of them were truly holy and incredibly charitable. When we talk about heroism, we obviously mean something that’s rare. I believe instances of serious wrongdoing among them might be as infrequent as those of outstanding goodness. Sure, you can find examples of greed and immorality if you’re looking for them, especially from those who enjoy uncovering such things. A man my age isn’t surprised that some, in every group, don’t live that ideal life of self-denial regarding wealth or pleasure that everyone desires, some expect, but none demand more strictly than those most focused on their own interests or indulgent about their own desires. When I was in France, I’m sure the number of corrupt bishops wasn’t significant. Some individuals among them, not known for how they lived, made up for their lack of strict virtues with their liberal qualities and had traits that made them useful in both the Church and the State. I’ve heard that, with few exceptions, Louis the Sixteenth took more care regarding character when promoting to that rank than his immediate predecessor; and I believe (since some reform spirit has influenced his entire reign) that might be true. But the current ruling power seems only interested in exploiting the Church. It has punished all bishops: which benefits the corrupt, at least in terms of reputation. It has created a degrading pension system, to which no one with progressive ideas or means will send their children. It will have to cater to the lower classes of society. Just like you, the lower clergy aren’t numerous enough for their duties, since those tasks are excessively minute and laborious, and you’ve left no middle class of clergy that can take it easy, so in the future, nothing of learning or scholarship can exist in the Gallican Church. To top it off, without any regard for the rights of patrons, the Assembly has established an elective clergy: a setup that will drive out all sober individuals, anyone who might claim independence in their role or actions—and it will entrust the entire control of public opinion to a group of reckless, bold, cunning, factional, flattering individuals, whose status and lifestyle will reduce their meager pensions (compared to which the salary of a tax collector seems generous and respectable) to an object of petty and disgraceful intrigue. Those officials still called bishops will be elected to a relatively insignificant position through the same methods (i.e., electioneering tactics) by people of all known or fabricated religious beliefs. The new lawmakers haven’t specified anything at all regarding their qualifications, either in doctrine or morals, just like they haven’t for the lower clergy; nor does it seem that both the higher and the lower could, at their discretion, practice or preach any form of religion or irreligion they choose. I still don’t see what the authority of bishops over their subordinates will be, or if they will have any authority at all.

In short, Sir, it seems to me that this new ecclesiastical establishment is intended only to be temporary, and preparatory to the utter abolition, under any of its forms, of the Christian religion, whenever the minds of men are prepared for this last stroke against it by the accomplishment of the plan for bringing its ministers into universal contempt. They who will not believe that the philosophical fanatics who guide in these matters have long entertained such a design are utterly ignorant of their character and proceedings. These enthusiasts do not scruple to avow their opinion, that a state can subsist without any religion better than with one, and that they are able to supply the place of any good which may be in it by a project of their own,—namely, by a sort of education they have imagined, founded in a knowledge of the physical wants of men, progressively carried to an enlightened self-interest, which, when well understood, they tell us, will identify with an interest more enlarged and public. The scheme of this education has been long known. Of late they distinguish it (as they have got an entirely new nomenclature of technical terms) by the name of a Civic Education.

In short, Sir, it seems to me that this new church setup is meant to be just temporary, paving the way for the complete removal of Christianity in all its forms, as soon as people are ready for this final blow against it by making its leaders widely despised. Those who don’t believe that the philosophical radicals driving these changes have held this plan for a long time clearly don't understand their motives and actions. These zealots openly state that a state can exist without any religion just as well as with one, and that they can replace any good found in religion with their own scheme — specifically, a type of education they've come up with, based on understanding people's basic needs and gradually leading to enlightened self-interest, which, once understood, they claim will align with a broader public interest. This educational plan has been known for a while. Recently, they have begun to refer to it (having created a completely new set of technical terms) as Civic Education.

I hope their partisans in England (to whom I rather attribute very inconsiderate conduct than the ultimate object in this detestable design) will succeed neither in the pillage of the ecclesiastics nor in the introduction of a principle of popular election to our bishoprics and parochial cures. This, in the present condition of the world, would be the last corruption of the Church, the utter ruin of the clerical character, the most dangerous shock that the state ever received through a misunderstood arrangement of religion. I know well enough that the bishoprics and cures, under kingly and seigniorial patronage, as now they are in England, and as they have been lately in France, are sometimes acquired by unworthy methods; but the other mode of ecclesiastical canvass subjects them infinitely more surely and more generally to all the evil arts of low ambition, which, operating on and through greater numbers, will produce mischief in proportion.

I hope their supporters in England (whom I see as acting thoughtlessly rather than with a clear goal in this awful scheme) will fail in looting the church officials or bringing a system of popular elections to our bishoprics and local parishes. In today's world, that would be the final degradation of the Church, the complete downfall of the clergy, and the most significant threat the state has ever faced due to a misapplied approach to religion. I’m well aware that bishoprics and parishes, under royal and noble patronage, like they currently are in England and were recently in France, are sometimes obtained through dishonorable means; however, the alternative method of church campaigning opens them up even more certainly and broadly to all the dishonest tactics of petty ambition, which, spreading through larger groups, will cause damage in proportion.

Those of you who have robbed the clergy think that they shall easily reconcile their conduct to all Protestant nations, because the clergy whom they have thus plundered, degraded, and given over to mockery and scorn, are of the Roman Catholic, that is, of their own pretended persuasion. I have no doubt that some miserable bigots will be found here as well as elsewhere, who hate sects and parties different from their own more than they love the substance of religion, and who are more angry with those who differ from them in their particular plans and systems than displeased with those who attack the foundation of our common hope. These men will write and speak on the subject in the manner that is to be expected from their temper and character. Burnet says, that, when he was in France, in the year 1683, "the method which carried over the men of the finest parts to Popery was this: they brought themselves to doubt of the whole Christian religion: when that was once done, it seemed a more indifferent thing of what side or form they continued outwardly." If this was then the ecclesiastic policy of France, it is what they have since but too much reason to repent of. They preferred atheism to a form of religion not agreeable to their ideas. They succeeded in destroying that form; and atheism has succeeded in destroying them. I can readily give credit to Burnet's story; because I have observed too much of a similar spirit (for a little of it is "much too much") amongst ourselves. The humor, however, is not general.

Those of you who have robbed the clergy think they can easily justify their actions to all Protestant nations because the clergy they’ve plundered, degraded, and subjected to mockery are Roman Catholic, meaning they’re of their own supposed persuasion. I have no doubt that some miserable bigots will be found here as well as elsewhere, who hate different sects and parties more than they love the essence of religion, and who are more angry with those who disagree with them on their specific plans and systems than they are with those who attack the foundation of our shared hope. These men will write and talk about the topic in a way that reflects their temper and character. Burnet says that when he was in France in 1683, "the method which carried over the men of the finest parts to Popery was this: they brought themselves to doubt of the whole Christian religion: when that was once done, it seemed a more indifferent thing of what side or form they continued outwardly." If this was then the ecclesiastical policy of France, it's something they have since had plenty of reason to regret. They chose atheism over a form of religion that didn’t fit their ideas. They succeeded in destroying that form; and atheism has succeeded in destroying them. I can easily believe Burnet's account because I've seen too much of a similar spirit (for a little of it is "much too much") among us. However, this attitude isn’t widespread.

The teachers who reformed our religion in England bore no sort of resemblance to your present reforming doctors in Paris. Perhaps they were (like those whom they opposed) rather more than could be wished under the influence of a party spirit; but they were most sincere believers; men of the most fervent and exalted piety; ready to die (as some of them did die) like true heroes in defence of their particular ideas of Christianity,—as they would with equal fortitude, and more cheerfully, for that stock of general truth for the branches of which they contended with their blood. These men would have disavowed with horror those wretches who claimed a fellowship with them upon no other titles than those of their having pillaged the persons with whom they maintained controversies, and their having despised the common religion, for the purity of which they exerted themselves with a zeal which unequivocally bespoke their highest reverence for the substance of that system which they wished to reform. Many of their descendants have retained the same zeal, but (as less engaged in conflict) with more moderation. They do not forget that justice and mercy are substantial parts of religion. Impious men do not recommend themselves to their communion by iniquity and cruelty towards any description of their fellow-creatures.

The teachers who changed our religion in England were nothing like your current reformers in Paris. They may have been (like those they stood against) somewhat influenced by party spirit, but they were genuinely sincere believers; men filled with deep and elevated piety; ready to die (as some of them did) like true heroes for their specific beliefs about Christianity—just as they would face death with equal courage, and even more willingly, for the fundamental truths they fought for with their blood. These men would have been horrified by those scoundrels who sought to align themselves with them based solely on their acts of plundering their opponents and their disdain for the common faith, the purity of which they worked tirelessly to uphold, clearly demonstrating their great respect for the core principles of the system they aimed to reform. Many of their descendants maintain the same passion today, but (being less involved in conflict) with more moderation. They remember that justice and mercy are essential parts of religion. Improper individuals cannot gain acceptance among them through wrongdoing and cruelty towards any of their fellow beings.

We hear these new teachers continually boasting of their spirit of toleration. That those persons should tolerate all opinions, who think none to be of estimation, is a matter of small merit. Equal neglect is not impartial kindness. The species of benevolence which arises from contempt is no true charity. There are in England abundance of men who tolerate in the true spirit of toleration. They think the dogmas of religion, though in different degrees, are all of moment, and that amongst them there is, as amongst all things of value, a just ground of preference. They favor, therefore, and they tolerate. They tolerate, not because they despise opinions, but because they respect justice. They would reverently and affectionately protect all religions, because they love and venerate the great principle upon which they all agree, and the great object to which they are all directed. They begin more and more plainly to discern that we have all a common cause, as against a common enemy. They will not be so misled by the spirit of faction as not to distinguish what is done in favor of their subdivision from those acts of hostility which, through some particular description, are aimed at the whole corps in which they themselves, under another denomination, are included. It is impossible for me to say what may be the character of every description of men amongst us. But I speak for the greater part; and for them, I must tell you, that sacrilege is no part of their doctrine of good works; that, so far from calling you into their fellowship on such title, if your professors are admitted to their communion, they must carefully conceal their doctrine of the lawfulness of the proscription of innocent men, and that they must make restitution of all stolen goods whatsoever. Till then they are none of ours.

We keep hearing these new teachers bragging about their tolerance. It's not very impressive that those who regard all opinions as worthless think they should tolerate them. Ignoring everything isn't the same as being fair. The kind of goodwill that comes from having no regard for opinions isn’t true kindness. In England, there are plenty of people who genuinely embody the spirit of tolerance. They believe that the ideas of religion, even if they vary in importance, all matter, and that like all valuable things, they can be prioritized. They support and tolerate, not because they look down on opinions, but because they value fairness. They would respectfully and lovingly protect all religions because they admire the fundamental principle they all share and the ultimate goal they are all striving toward. They are starting to clearly see that we have a shared cause against a common enemy. They won’t be misled by divisiveness to confuse what benefits their specific group with acts of aggression targeted at the entire community of which they’re a part under a different label. I can’t speak for everyone among us, but I represent the majority, and for them, I must say that sacrilege isn’t part of their beliefs about good actions; far from inviting you into their community on such grounds, if your members join theirs, they must hide their beliefs about the legitimacy of excluding innocent people and must return everything that has been stolen. Until then, they are not with us.

You may suppose that we do not approve your confiscation of the revenues of bishops, and deans, and chapters, and parochial clergy possessing independent estates arising from land, because we have the same sort of establishment in England. That objection, you will say, cannot hold as to the confiscation of the goods of monks and nuns, and the abolition of their order. It is true that this particular part of your general confiscation does not affect England, as a precedent in point; but the reason applies, and it goes a great way. The Long Parliament confiscated the lands of deans and chapters in England on the same ideas upon which your Assembly set to sale the lands of the monastic orders. But it is in the principle of injustice that the danger lies, and not in the description of persons on whom it is first exercised. I see, in a country very near us, a course of policy pursued, which sets justice, the common concern of mankind, at defiance. With the National Assembly of France possession is nothing, law and usage are nothing. I see the National Assembly openly reprobate the doctrine of prescription, which one of the greatest of their own lawyers[114] tells us, with great truth, is a part of the law of Nature. He tells us that the positive ascertainment of its limits, and its security from invasion, were among the causes for which civil society itself has been instituted. If prescription be once shaken, no species of property is secure, when it once becomes an object large enough to tempt the cupidity of indigent power. I see a practice perfectly correspondent to their contempt of this great fundamental part of natural law. I see the confiscators begin with bishops, and chapters, and monasteries; but I do not see them end there. I see the princes of the blood, who, by the oldest usages of that kingdom, held large landed estates, (hardly with the compliment of a debate,) deprived of their possessions, and, in lieu of their stable, independent property, reduced to the hope of some precarious charitable pension at the pleasure of an Assembly, which of course will pay little regard to the rights of pensioners at pleasure, when it despises those of legal proprietors. Flushed with the insolence of their first inglorious victories, and pressed by the distresses caused by their lust of unhallowed lucre, disappointed, but not discouraged, they have at length ventured completely to subvert all property of all descriptions throughout the extent of a great kingdom. They have compelled all men, in all transactions of commerce, in the disposal of lands, in civil dealing, and through the whole communion of life, to accept, as perfect payment and good and lawful tender, the symbols of their speculations on a projected sale of their plunder. What vestiges of liberty or property have they left? The tenant-right of a cabbage-garden, a year's interest in a hovel, the good-will of an ale-house or a baker's shop, the very shadow of a constructive property, are more ceremoniously treated in our Parliament than with you the oldest and most valuable landed possessions, in the hands of the most respectable personages, or than the whole body of the moneyed and commercial interest of your country. We entertain a high opinion of the legislative authority; but we have never dreamt that Parliaments had any right whatever to violate property, to overrule prescription, or to force a currency of their own fiction in the place of that which is real, and recognized by the law of nations. But you, who began with refusing to submit to the most moderate restraints, have ended by establishing an unheard-of despotism. I find the ground upon which your confiscators go is this: that, indeed, their proceedings could not be supported in a court of justice, but that the rules of prescription cannot bind a legislative assembly.[115] So that this legislative assembly of a free nation sits, not for the security, but for the destruction of property,—and not of property only, but of every rule and maxim which can give it stability, and of those instruments which can alone give it circulation.

You might think that we disapprove of your confiscation of the income from bishops, deans, chapters, and local clergy who have their own estates from land, just because we have a similar system in England. You might argue that this objection doesn't apply to your confiscation of the belongings of monks and nuns or the dissolution of their orders. While it's true that this specific part of your broader confiscation doesn't directly impact England, the underlying reason still holds true and carries significant weight. The Long Parliament confiscated the lands of deans and chapters in England based on similar principles that your Assembly used to sell off the lands of monastic orders. However, the real danger lies in the principle of injustice itself, rather than the specific groups it targets first. I observe a nearby country pursuing a policy that defies justice, which should be a common concern for all people. With the National Assembly of France, possession means nothing, and law and custom mean nothing. I see the National Assembly openly rejecting the idea of prescription, which one of their finest lawyers accurately describes as a fundamental part of natural law. He argues that clearly defining its boundaries and ensuring protection from violation are among the main reasons civil society was established. If prescription is undermined, no type of property is safe, especially when it becomes something that draws the greed of needy power. I notice a practice that corresponds perfectly with their disregard for this essential aspect of natural law. The confiscators start with bishops, chapters, and monasteries; I don't see them stopping there. I see royal relatives, who, according to the longstanding customs of that kingdom, owned substantial properties, stripped of their possessions without much debate, reduced to hoping for some uncertain charitable pension at the discretion of an Assembly that will naturally ignore the rights of pensioners when it disregards the rights of legal owners. Energized by the arrogance of their initial unheroic victories and driven by the hardships caused by their greed for ill-gotten gains, they have eventually dared to completely overthrow all types of property across a vast kingdom. They have forced everyone, in all commercial transactions, in land dealings, in civil interactions, and throughout everyday life, to accept, as complete payment and legitimate tender, the symbols of their schemes on a planned sale of their plunder. What remnants of liberty or property remain? The tenant's right to a vegetable garden, a year’s interest in a dilapidated house, the goodwill of a pub or bakery, even the mere notion of constructive property, are treated with more respect in our Parliament than your oldest and most valuable land holdings in the hands of the most esteemed individuals, or even the entire financial and commercial interests of your country. We hold the legislative authority in high regard; however, we've never thought that Parliaments had any right to violate property, override prescription, or impose their fabricated currency in place of that which is real and recognized by international law. Yet you, who started by refusing to accept even the most reasonable limits, have ended up establishing an unprecedented tyranny. The basis of your confiscators’ actions is this: that their actions wouldn't hold up in a court of law, but that the rules of prescription cannot bind a legislative assembly. So, this legislative assembly of a free nation exists not for the protection, but for the destruction of property—and not just property, but of every rule and principle that can provide it with stability, as well as the means that can ensure its circulation.

When the Anabaptists of Munster, in the sixteenth century, had filled Germany with confusion, by their system of levelling, and their wild opinions concerning property, to what country in Europe did not the progress of their fury furnish just cause of alarm? Of all things, wisdom is the most terrified with epidemical fanaticism, because of all enemies it is that against which she is the least able to furnish any kind of resource. We cannot be ignorant of the spirit of atheistical fanaticism, that is inspired by a multitude of writings dispersed with incredible assiduity and expense, and by sermons delivered in all the streets and places of public resort in Paris. These writings and sermons have filled the populace with a black and savage atrocity of mind, which supersedes in them the common feelings of Nature, as well as all sentiments of morality and religion; insomuch that these wretches are induced to bear with a sullen patience the intolerable distresses brought upon them by the violent convulsions and permutations that have been made in property.[116] The spirit of proselytism attends this spirit of fanaticism. They have societies to cabal and correspond at home and abroad for the propagation of their tenets. The republic of Berne, one of the happiest, the most prosperous, and the best-governed countries upon earth, is one of the great objects at the destruction of which they aim. I am told they have in some measure succeeded in sowing there the seeds of discontent. They are busy throughout Germany. Spain and Italy have not been untried. England is not left out of the comprehensive scheme of their malignant charity: and in England we find those who stretch out their arms to them, who recommend their example from more than one pulpit, and who choose, in more than one periodical meeting, publicly to correspond with them, to applaud them, and to hold them up as objects for imitation; who receive from them tokens of confraternity, and standards consecrated amidst their rites and mysteries;[117] who suggest to them leagues of perpetual amity, at the very time when the power to which our Constitution has exclusively delegated the federative capacity of this kingdom may find it expedient to make war upon them.

When the Anabaptists of Munster stirred up chaos in Germany during the sixteenth century with their ideas of equality and extreme views on property, which country in Europe was not alarmed by the spread of their madness? Among all things, wisdom is most frightened by widespread fanaticism because it is the one enemy against which it can offer the least defense. We cannot ignore the spirit of atheistic fanaticism fueled by numerous writings spread with incredible effort and expense, along with sermons delivered in every street and public space in Paris. These writings and sermons have filled the people with a dark and savage mindset that overrides their natural feelings and any sense of morality or religion, leading these unfortunate souls to endure with grim patience the unbearable hardships caused by the violent upheavals in property.[116] This spirit of fanaticism is accompanied by a drive to convert others. They have groups that plot and communicate both domestically and internationally to spread their beliefs. The republic of Berne, one of the happiest, most prosperous, and best-governed places on Earth, is one of their main targets for destruction. I’ve heard they have somewhat succeeded in planting the seeds of discontent there. They are active throughout Germany. Spain and Italy have not been spared. England isn’t excluded from their grand plan of wicked outreach: there we find people reaching out to them, praising their example from multiple pulpits, and choosing to connect with them publicly in various meetings, applauding them and holding them up as role models. They receive tokens of brotherhood and flags blessed during their rituals and mysteries;[117] they even suggest alliances of everlasting friendship, while the authority to which our Constitution has exclusively granted the power of federation in this kingdom may find it necessary to go to war against them.

It is not the confiscation of our Church property from this example in France that I dread, though I think this would be no trifling evil. The great source of my solicitude is, lest it should ever be considered in England as the policy of a state to seek a resource in confiscations of any kind, or that any one description of citizens should be brought to regard any of the others as their proper prey.[118] Nations are wading deeper and deeper into an ocean of boundless debt. Public debts, which at first were a security to governments, by interesting many in the public tranquillity, are likely in their excess to become the means of their subversion. If governments provide for these debts by heavy impositions, they perish by becoming odious to the people. If they do not provide for them, they will be undone by the efforts of the most dangerous of all parties: I mean an extensive, discontented moneyed interest, injured and not destroyed. The men who compose this interest look for their security, in the first instance, to the fidelity of government; in the second, to its power. If they find the old governments effete, worn out, and with their springs relaxed, so as not to be of sufficient vigor for their purposes, they may seek new ones that shall be possessed of more energy; and this energy will be derived, not from an acquisition of resources, but from a contempt of justice. Revolutions are favorable to confiscation; and it is impossible to know under what obnoxious names the next confiscations will be authorized. I am sure that the principles predominant in France extend to very many persons, and descriptions of persons, in all countries, who think their innoxious indolence their security. This kind of innocence in proprietors may be argued into inutility; and inutility into an unfitness for their estates. Many parts of Europe are in open disorder. In many others there is a hollow murmuring under ground; a confused movement is felt, that threatens a general earthquake in the political world. Already confederacies and correspondences of the most extraordinary nature are forming in several countries.[119] In such a state of things we ought to hold ourselves upon our guard. In all mutations (if mutations must be) the circumstance which will serve most to blunt the edge of their mischief, and to promote what good may be in them, is, that they should find us with our minds tenacious of justice and tender of property.

It’s not the seizure of our Church property from this example in France that worries me, even though that would be a serious issue. What really concerns me is the possibility that it might be seen in England as acceptable for the state to look for solutions in confiscations of any kind, or that any group of citizens might see others as fair game. Nations are sinking deeper into overwhelming debt. Public debts, which initially provided security to governments by getting many invested in public stability, are likely to lead to their downfall due to their excess. If governments handle these debts with heavy taxes, they risk becoming hated by the people. If they don’t address them, they will be undermined by a very dangerous group: a vast, dissatisfied financial interest that feels wronged but not destroyed. The people in this group look for security first in the government’s commitment, and second in its power. If they see the existing governments as ineffective, exhausted, and unable to meet their needs, they might search for new ones that have more strength; and this strength may come not from legitimate means but from a disregard for justice. Revolutions often lead to confiscation, and it’s hard to predict what unjust labels the next confiscations will carry. I’m confident that the attitudes prevailing in France resonate with many individuals and groups in all countries who mistakenly believe their inactivity secures their safety. This notion of innocence among property owners can be interpreted as uselessness, and that uselessness as unfitness for their property. Many regions in Europe are openly chaotic. In many others, there is a quiet unrest brewing; a jumbled movement is stirring, threatening a widespread political upheaval. Unusual alliances and connections are already forming in several countries. In such times, we need to remain vigilant. In all changes (if changes are inevitable), the key factor that can soften their harmful effects and encourage whatever good may come from them is that they encounter us holding firmly to justice and being sensitive to property rights.

But it will be argued, that this confiscation in France ought not to alarm other nations. They say it is not made from wanton rapacity; that it is a great measure of national policy, adopted to remove an extensive, inveterate, superstitious mischief.—It is with the greatest difficulty that I am able to separate policy from justice. Justice is itself the great standing policy of civil society; and any eminent departure from it, under any circumstances, lies under the suspicion of being no policy at all.

But it will be argued that this confiscation in France shouldn't alarm other nations. They say it isn't driven by mere greed; that it's a significant measure of national policy aimed at eliminating a widespread, deep-rooted, superstitious problem. It’s extremely difficult for me to separate policy from justice. Justice is inherently the main guiding principle of civil society, and any major departure from it, under any circumstances, raises suspicions that it isn't really policy at all.

When men are encouraged to go into a certain mode of life by the existing laws, and protected in that mode as in a lawful occupation,—when they have accommodated all their ideas and all their habits to it,—when the law had long made their adherence to its rules a ground of reputation, and their departure from them a ground of disgrace and even of penalty,—I am sure it is unjust in legislature, by an arbitrary act, to offer a sudden violence to their minds and their feelings, forcibly to degrade them from their state and condition, and to stigmatize with shame and infamy that character and those customs which before had been made the measure of their happiness and honor. If to this be added an expulsion from their habitations and a confiscation of all their goods, I am not sagacious enough to discover how this despotic sport made of the feelings, consciences, prejudices, and properties of men can be discriminated from the rankest tyranny.

When people are encouraged to live a certain way by the laws in place, and are protected in that lifestyle as if it were a legitimate job—when they have adjusted all their beliefs and habits to fit it—and when the law has long made their adherence to its rules a mark of reputation, while breaking them leads to disgrace and penalties—I believe it is unfair for the legislature, through a reckless action, to suddenly disrupt their thoughts and feelings, forcibly lower them from their position, and label the character and customs that once represented their happiness and honor with shame and infamy. If this is followed by being kicked out of their homes and having all their belongings taken away, I can't see how such a cruel treatment of people's feelings, beliefs, biases, and properties can be distinguished from the worst kind of tyranny.

If the injustice of the course pursued in France be clear, the policy of the measure, that is, the public benefit to be expected from it, ought to be at least as evident, and at least as important. To a man who acts under the influence of no passion, who has nothing in view in his projects but the public good, a great difference will immediately strike him, between what policy would dictate on the original introduction of such institutions, and on a question of their total abolition, where they have cast their roots wide and deep, and where, by long habit, things more valuable than themselves are so adapted to them, and in a manner interwoven with them, that the one cannot be destroyed without notably impairing the other. He might be embarrassed, if the case were really such as sophisters represent it in their paltry style of debating. But in this, as in most questions of state, there is a middle. There is something else than the mere alternative of absolute destruction or unreformed existence. Spartam nactus es; hanc exorna. This is, in my opinion, a rule of profound sense, and ought never to depart from the mind of an honest reformer. I cannot conceive how any man can have brought himself to that pitch of presumption, to consider his country as nothing but carte blanche, upon which he may scribble whatever he pleases. A man full of warm, speculative benevolence may wish his society otherwise constituted than he finds it; but a good patriot, and a true politician, always considers how he shall make the most of the existing materials of his country. A disposition to preserve, and an ability to improve, taken together, would be my standard of a statesman. Everything else is vulgar in the conception, perilous in the execution.

If the injustice of what's happening in France is clear, then the policy behind it—the public benefit expected from it—should be just as obvious and important. To someone who acts without passion and solely for the public good, a significant difference will immediately stand out between what policy would suggest for originally establishing such institutions and for completely abolishing them, especially where they have grown strong roots and where, due to long-standing habits, things more valuable than the institutions themselves are so intertwined with them that you can't destroy one without significantly harming the other. He might be confused if the situation were truly as sophists portray it in their shallow debate style. But, as in many state matters, there is a middle ground. There's more than just the choice between complete destruction or unchanged existence. Spartam nactus es; hanc exorna. I believe this is a sensible principle and should always guide the thoughts of a sincere reformer. I can’t understand how anyone could reach the level of arrogance to view their country as just a carte blanche on which they can scribble whatever they want. A person full of warm, idealistic benevolence might wish for their society to be different from what it is, but a good patriot and true politician always considers how to make the most of the existing resources in their country. A tendency to preserve, coupled with the ability to improve, would be my ideal for a statesman. Everything else is simplistic in thought and dangerous to carry out.

There are moments in the fortune of states, when particular men are called to make improvements by great mental exertion. In those moments, even when they seem to enjoy the confidence of their prince and country, and to be invested with full authority, they have not always apt instruments. A politician, to do great things, looks for a power, what our workmen call a purchase; and if he finds that power, in politics as in mechanics, he cannot be at a loss to apply it. In the monastic institutions, in my opinion, was found a great power for the mechanism of politic benevolence. There were revenues with a public direction; there were men wholly set apart and dedicated to public purposes, without any other than public ties and public principles,—men without the possibility of converting the estate of the community into a private fortune,—men denied to self-interests, whose avarice is for some community,—men to whom personal poverty is honor, and implicit obedience stands in the place of freedom. In vain shall a man look to the possibility of making such things when he wants them. The winds blow as they list. These institutions are the products of enthusiasm; they are the instruments of wisdom. Wisdom cannot create materials; they are the gifts of Nature or of chance; her pride is in the use. The perennial existence of bodies corporate and their fortunes are things particularly suited to a man who has long views,—who meditates designs that require time in fashioning, and which propose duration when they are accomplished. He is not deserving to rank high, or even to be mentioned in the order of great statesmen, who, having obtained the command and direction of such a power as existed in the wealth, the discipline, and the habits of such corporations as those which you have rashly destroyed, cannot find any way of converting it to the great and lasting benefit of his country. On the view of this subject, a thousand uses suggest themselves to a contriving mind. To destroy any power growing wild from the rank productive force of the human mind is almost tantamount, in the moral world, to the destruction of the apparently active properties of bodies in the material. It would be like the attempt to destroy (if it were in our competence to destroy) the expansive force of fixed air in nitre, or the power of steam, or of electricity, or of magnetism. These energies always existed in Nature, and they were always discernible. They seemed, some of them unserviceable, some noxious, some no better than a sport to children,—until contemplative ability, combining with practic skill, tamed their wild nature, subdued them to use, and rendered them at once the most powerful and the most tractable agents, in subservience to the great views and designs of men. Did fifty thousand persons, whose mental and whose bodily labor you might direct, and so many hundred thousand a year of a revenue, which was neither lazy nor superstitious, appear too big for your abilities to wield? Had you no way of using the men, but by converting monks into pensioners? Had you no way of turning the revenue to account, but through the improvident resource of a spendthrift sale? If you were thus destitute of mental funds, the proceeding is in its natural course. Your politicians do not understand their trade; and therefore they sell their tools.

There are times in the fortunes of states when certain individuals are called to drive improvements through significant mental effort. In those moments, even if they seem to have the confidence of their ruler and nation and are granted full authority, they don't always have the right tools. A politician, to achieve great things, looks for a **power**, what our workers refer to as a **purchase**; and if he finds that power, whether in politics or mechanics, he won't struggle to apply it. In my view, the monastic institutions provided a significant **power** for the machinery of political goodwill. They had revenues directed toward public interests; there were individuals completely devoted to public purposes, bound by public ties and principles—people who couldn’t turn community resources into personal wealth—individuals free of selfish interests, whose greed was for the community—people for whom personal poverty is a badge of honor, and blind obedience replaces freedom. It is futile for anyone to expect to create such things when they are needed. The winds blow as they wish. These institutions are born of passion; they are instruments of wisdom. Wisdom cannot create resources; those are the gifts of Nature or chance; her pride lies in their use. The enduring existence of corporate bodies and their fortunes especially suits someone with long-term vision—who considers plans that take time to develop and that aim for longevity when achieved. He does not deserve to be highly ranked, or even mentioned among great statesmen, who, after gaining control over the power that existed in the wealth, discipline, and habits of those corporations you carelessly destroyed, fails to find any way to utilize it for the lasting benefit of his country. From this perspective, a thousand possibilities arise for a creative mind. Destroying any power that grows haphazardly from the vast potential of the human mind is almost equivalent, in the moral realm, to destroying the seemingly active properties of materials in the physical world. It would be like trying to eliminate (if we were capable of doing so) the expanding force of fixed air in saltpeter, or the power of steam, electricity, or magnetism. These forces always existed in Nature and were always recognizable. They appeared, some unhelpful, some harmful, some no better than child's play—until thoughtful ability, combined with practical skill, tamed their wild nature, subdued them for use, and made them both powerful and manageable agents, in service to humanity's grand goals. Did fifty thousand people, whose mental and physical labor you could direct, and such a sizable annual revenue, which was neither idle nor superstitious, seem too overwhelming for you to handle? Did you have no way to utilize these people except by turning monks into pensioners? Could you think of no way to make use of the revenue except through the reckless method of a wasteful sale? If you were indeed lacking in mental resources, then the outcome is as it should be. Your politicians do not know their craft; therefore, they sell their tools.

But the institutions savor of superstition in their very principle; and they nourish it by a permanent and standing influence.—This I do not mean to dispute; but this ought not to hinder you from deriving from superstition itself any resources which may thence be furnished for the public advantage. You derive benefits from many dispositions and many passions of the human mind which are of as doubtful a color, in the moral eye, as superstition itself. It was your business to correct and mitigate everything which was noxious in this passion, as in all the passions. But is superstition the greatest of all possible vices? In its possible excess I think it becomes a very great evil. It is, however, a moral subject, and of course admits of all degrees and all modifications. Superstition is the religion of feeble minds; and they must be tolerated in an intermixture of it, in some trifling or some enthusiastic shape or other, else you will deprive weak minds of a resource found necessary to the strongest. The body of all true religion consists, to be sure, in obedience to the will of the Sovereign of the world, in a confidence in His declarations, and in imitation of His perfections. The rest is our own. It may be prejudicial to the great end,—it may be auxiliary. Wise men, who, as such, are not admirers, (not admirers at least of the munera terræ,) are not violently attached to these things, nor do they violently hate them. Wisdom is not the most severe corrector of folly. They are the rival follies which mutually wage so unrelenting a war, and which make so cruel a use of their advantages, as they can happen to engage the immoderate vulgar, on the one side or the other, in their quarrels. Prudence would be neuter; but if, in the contention between fond attachment and fierce antipathy concerning things in their nature not made to produce such heats, a prudent man were obliged to make a choice of what errors and excesses of enthusiasm he would condemn or bear, perhaps he would think the superstition which builds to be more tolerable than that which demolishes,—that which adorns a country, than that which deforms it,—that which endows, than that which plunders,—that which disposes to mistaken beneficence, than that which stimulates to real injustice,—that which leads a man to refuse to himself lawful pleasures, than that which snatches from others the scanty subsistence of their self-denial. Such, I think, is very nearly the state of the question between the ancient founders of monkish superstition and the superstition of the pretended philosophers of the hour.

But the institutions are rooted in superstition at their core, and they maintain it through a lasting and ongoing influence. While I don't intend to dispute that, it shouldn't stop you from using superstition in any way that can benefit the public good. You gain advantages from many human traits and emotions that are just as questionable, morally speaking, as superstition itself. Your role is to correct and temper everything harmful in this passion, as with all passions. But is superstition really the worst vice? In its most extreme forms, I believe it can indeed be very harmful. That said, it's a moral issue and can have varying degrees and changes. Superstition is the belief of weaker minds, and we must allow some blend of it—whether minor or overly enthusiastic—else we risk denying weaker minds a resource that even the strongest feel is necessary. The essence of true religion lies in obeying the will of the Sovereign of the universe, having confidence in His word, and striving to emulate His qualities. The rest is our own creation. It can either hinder the ultimate goal or support it. Wise people, who aren’t fans—at least not of the "gifts of the earth"—aren't excessively drawn to these things, nor do they passionately detest them. Wisdom isn't the toughest critic of folly. It’s the competing foolishness that carries out a relentless battle, cruelly exploiting any advantage they manage to sway the excessive masses toward in their disputes. Prudence would remain neutral; however, if a sensible person had to choose which errors and excesses of enthusiasm to reject or tolerate in the ongoing struggle between blind devotion and fierce aversion to things that shouldn’t provoke such strong emotions, they might find the superstition that builds to be more acceptable than the one that tears down—what beautifies a place rather than what disfigures it—what enriches, rather than what plunders—what inspires misguided generosity, rather than what incites real injustice—what leads a person to deny themselves lawful pleasures, rather than what takes away from others the little they have through self-denial. This, I think, closely resembles the debate between the original founders of religious superstition and the so-called philosophers of today.

For the present I postpone all consideration of the supposed public profit of the sale, which, however, I conceive to be perfectly delusive. I shall here only consider it as a transfer of property. On the policy of that transfer I shall trouble you with a few thoughts.

For now, I'm putting aside any thoughts about the supposed public benefit of the sale, which I believe is truly misleading. I'll focus here on it as a transfer of ownership. I’ll share a few thoughts on the policy of that transfer.

In every prosperous community something more is produced than goes to the immediate support of the producer. This surplus forms the income of the landed capitalist. It will be spent by a proprietor who does not labor. But this idleness is itself the spring of labor, this repose the spur to industry. The only concern for the state is, that the capital taken in rent from the land should be returned again to the industry from whence it came, and that its expenditure should be with the least possible detriment to the morals of those who expend it and to those of the people to whom it is returned.

In every thriving community, more is created than what's needed for the producer's immediate support. This surplus becomes the income of the landowner. It will be spent by someone who doesn’t work. But this idleness actually drives labor, and this rest inspires productivity. The main concern for the state is that the rent taken from the land should be reinvested back into the industry that generated it, and that its spending should harm the morals of those who spend it and those of the people who receive it as little as possible.

In all the views of receipt, expenditure, and personal employment, a sober legislator would carefully compare the possessor whom he was recommended to expel with the stranger who was proposed to fill his place. Before the inconveniences are incurred which must attend all violent revolutions in property through extensive confiscation, we ought to have some rational assurance that the purchasers of the confiscated property will be in a considerable degree more laborious, more virtuous, more sober, less disposed to extort an unreasonable proportion of the gains of the laborer, or to consume on themselves a larger share than is fit for the measure of an individual,—or that they should be qualified to dispense the surplus in a more steady and equal mode, so as to answer the purposes of a politic expenditure, than the old possessors, call those possessors bishops, or canons, or commendatory abbots, or monks, or what you please. The monks are lazy. Be it so. Suppose them no otherwise employed than by singing in the choir. They are as usefully employed as those who neither sing nor say,—as usefully even as those who sing upon the stage. They are as usefully employed as if they worked from dawn to dark in the innumerable servile, degrading, unseemly, unmanly, and often most unwholesome and pestiferous occupations to which by the social economy so many wretches are inevitably doomed. If it were not generally pernicious to disturb the natural course of things, and to impede in any degree the great wheel of circulation which is turned by the strangely directed labor of these unhappy people, I should be infinitely more inclined forcibly to rescue them from their miserable industry than violently to disturb the tranquil repose of monastic quietude. Humanity, and perhaps policy, might better justify me in the one than in the other. It is a subject on which I have often reflected, and never reflected without feeling from it. I am sure that no consideration, except the necessity of submitting to the yoke of luxury and the despotism of fancy, who in their own imperious way will distribute the surplus product of the soil, can justify the toleration of such trades and employments in a well-regulated state. But for this purpose of distribution, it seems to me that the idle expenses of monks are quite as well directed as the idle expenses of us lay loiterers.

In considering receipts, expenses, and personal employment, a sensible lawmaker would take a careful look at the person he's being asked to remove and the outsider who is suggested to take over. Before we incur the problems that come with radical changes in property through massive confiscation, we should have a solid reason to believe that the buyers of the confiscated property will work harder, be more virtuous, more responsible, less inclined to take an unfair share of the worker's earnings, or to indulge in a larger portion than what’s appropriate for an individual. Alternatively, they should be capable of managing the surplus in a more consistent and fair manner for the purposes of a wise expenditure than the previous owners, whether those owners are bishops, canons, commendatory abbots, monks, or anyone else you might choose. The monks are often seen as lazy. Fine. Let’s assume their only task is singing in the choir. They’re as productive as those who don’t sing or speak at all—just as useful as those performing on stage. They’re as useful as if they spent every day laboring in the countless degrading, unseemly, and often harmful jobs that many unfortunate people are forced into by society. If disturbing the natural order didn’t generally lead to harm and disrupt the larger system of circulation driven by the oddly managed labor of these unfortunate individuals, I would much prefer to save them from their miserable work than to disrupt the peaceful tranquility of monastic life. Humanity, and perhaps practicality, might better support my reasoning in the first scenario over the latter. This is a topic I’ve thought about often and deeply feel about. I’m convinced that no reasoning, except for the need to yield to the burden of luxury and the control of whim—who dictate how the surplus products of the land are shared—can justify tolerating such trades and jobs in a well-organized society. However, regarding this distribution, it seems that the monks’ unnecessary expenses are just as well spent as those of us ordinary idlers.

When the advantages of the possession and of the project are on a par, there is no motive for a change. But in the present case, perhaps, they are not upon a par, and the difference is in favor of the possession. It does not appear to me that the expenses of those whom you are going to expel do in fact take a course so directly and so generally leading to vitiate and degrade and render miserable those through whom they pass as the expenses of those favorites whom you are intruding into their houses. Why should the expenditure of a great landed property, which is a dispersion of the surplus product of the soil, appear intolerable to you or to me, when it takes its course through the accumulation of vast libraries, which are the history of the force and weakness of the human mind,—through great collections of ancient records, medals, and coins, which attest and explain laws and customs,—through paintings and statues, that, by imitating Nature, seem to extend the limits of creation,—through grand monuments of the dead, which continue the regards and connections of life beyond the grave,—through collections of the specimens of Nature, which become a representative assembly of all the classes and families of the world, that by disposition facilitate, and by exciting curiosity open, the avenues to science? If by great permanent establishments all these objects of expense are better secured from the inconstant sport of personal caprice and personal extravagance, are they worse than if the same tastes prevailed in scattered individuals? Does not the sweat of the mason and carpenter, who toil in order to partake the sweat of the peasant, flow as pleasantly and as salubriously in the construction and repair of the majestic edifices of religion as in the painted booths and sordid sties of vice and luxury? as honorably and as profitably in repairing those sacred works which grow hoary with innumerable years as on the momentary receptacles of transient voluptuousness,—in opera-houses, and brothels, and gaming-houses, and club-houses, and obelisks in the Champ de Mars? Is the surplus product of the olive and the vine worse employed in the frugal sustenance of persons whom the fictions of a pious imagination raise to dignity by construing in the service of God than in pampering the innumerable multitude of those who are degraded by being made useless domestics, subservient to the pride of man? Are the decorations of temples an expenditure less worthy a wise man than ribbons, and laces, and national cockades, and petit maisons, and petit soupers, and all the innumerable fopperies and follies in which opulence sports away the burden of its superfluity?

When the benefits of owning something and the project are equal, there’s no reason to change. But in this case, they might not be equal, and the advantage leans toward ownership. It doesn’t seem to me that the costs associated with the people you're about to remove actually lead to degrading and ruining the lives of others as much as the costs of the favorites you’re bringing into their homes. Why should the spending of a large estate, which spreads the surplus from the land, seem unbearable to you or me when it goes towards building vast libraries that preserve the history of human thought—through extensive collections of ancient documents, medals, and coins that help explain laws and customs—through art that, by mimicking nature, expands the boundaries of creativity—through grand monuments that honor the dead and keep connections to life beyond death—through collections of natural specimens that serve as a representative assembly of all classes and families of the world, facilitating understanding and sparking curiosity about science? If these expenses are better protected from personal whims and extravagance through significant establishments, are they any less valuable than if the same interests were spread among many individuals? Doesn’t the labor of the mason and carpenter, who work to share in the efforts of the peasant, seem just as rewarding and beneficial in constructing and maintaining the grand buildings of worship as it does in the painted booths and dismal places of vice and luxury? Are they any less honorable or profitable when repairing those sacred sites that age gracefully over countless years compared to temporary venues for fleeting pleasures like opera houses, brothels, gaming establishments, and social clubs? Is the surplus from olives and grapes used less wisely in the modest support of those whom the imagination of faith elevates by interpreting their service to God than in indulging the countless individuals who are reduced to useless servants for the pride of others? Are the adornments of temples less worthy of a wise person’s expenditure than ribbons, laces, national pins, fancy houses, lavish dinners, and all the countless absurdities and indulgences with which the wealthy squander their excess?

We tolerate even these,—not from love of them, but for fear of worse. We tolerate them, because property and liberty, to a degree, require that toleration. But why proscribe the other, and surely, in every point of view, the more laudable use of estates? Why, through the violation of all property, through an outrage upon every principle of liberty, forcibly carry them from the better to the worse?

We put up with even these—not because we like them, but out of fear of something worse. We accept them because our property and freedom, to some extent, demand that acceptance. But why ban the other, which is clearly the more admirable use of resources? Why, by violating all property rights and going against every principle of freedom, forcefully push them from the better to the worse?

This comparison between the new individuals and the old corps is made upon a supposition that no reform could be made in the latter. But, in a question of reformation, I always consider corporate bodies, whether sole or consisting of many, to be much more susceptible of a public direction, by the power of the state, in the use of their property, and in the regulation of modes and habits of life in their members, than private citizens ever can be, or perhaps ought to be; and this seems to me a very material consideration for those who undertake anything which merits the name of a politic enterprise.—So far as to the estates of monasteries.

This comparison between the new individuals and the old institutions assumes that no changes could be made to the latter. However, when it comes to reform, I believe that organizations, whether they are single entities or made up of many people, are much more open to public oversight by the state concerning how they use their property and how they regulate the lives of their members, than private citizens ever can be, or perhaps should be. This is an important point for anyone involved in what can be considered a political effort. —Regarding the properties of monasteries.

With regard to the estates possessed by bishops and canons and commendatory abbots, I cannot find out for what reason some landed estates may not be held otherwise than by inheritance. Can any philosophic spoiler undertake to demonstrate the positive or the comparative evil of having a certain, and that, too, a large, portion of landed property passing in succession through persons whose title to it is, always in theory and often in fact, an eminent degree of piety, morals, and learning; a property which by its destination, in their turn, and on the score of merit, gives to the noblest families renovation and support, to the lowest the means of dignity and elevation; a property, the tenure of which is the performance of some duty, (whatever value you may choose to set upon that duty,) and the character of whose proprietors demands at least an exterior decorum and gravity of manners,—who are to exercise a generous, but temperate hospitality,—part of whose income they are to consider as a trust for charity,—and who, even when they fail in their trust, when they slide from their character, and degenerate into a mere common secular nobleman or gentleman, are in no respect worse than those who may succeed them in their forfeited possessions? Is it better that estates should be held by those who have no duty than by those who have one? by those whose character and destination point to virtues than by those who have no rule and direction in the expenditure of their estates but their own will and appetite? Nor are these estates held altogether in the character or with the evils supposed inherent in mortmain. They pass from hand to hand with a more rapid circulation than any other. No excess is good, and therefore too great a proportion of landed property may be held officially for life; but it does not seem to me of material injury to any common wealth that there should exist some estates that have a chance of being acquired by other means than the previous acquisition of money.

Regarding the properties owned by bishops, canons, and commendatory abbots, I can’t understand why some lands can only be passed down through inheritance. Can anyone make a convincing case for the advantages or disadvantages of having a sizable amount of land changing hands among individuals whose claim to it is, both in theory and often in practice, grounded in a high level of piety, morals, and knowledge? This land, by its nature, provides renowned families with renewal and support, while offering those with less the opportunity for dignity and advancement; the tenure of which is tied to fulfilling certain duties (regardless of how much value you assign to those duties), and where the character of the owners at least demands a certain level of decorum and seriousness. They are expected to practice gracious, but restrained hospitality, consider part of their income as a charitable trust, and even when they fail in these responsibilities, when they slip into becoming just another ordinary noble or gentleman, they are no worse than those who inherit their lost estates. Is it preferable for properties to be held by those who have no obligations rather than by those who do? By individuals whose roles and responsibilities lead them towards virtues instead of those who follow only their own whims and desires? Moreover, these estates aren’t completely burdened by the supposed issues of mortmain. They change hands with a speed that exceeds that of any other type of property. While excessive possession is never beneficial, and thus too much property should be held officially for life, I don’t think it harms the common good if there are some estates that can be obtained through means other than just having money.


This letter is grown to a great length, though it is, indeed, short with regard to the infinite extent of the subject. Various avocations have from time to time called my mind from the subject. I was not sorry to give myself leisure to observe whether in the proceedings of the National Assembly I might not find reasons to change or to qualify some of my first sentiments. Everything has confirmed me more strongly in my first opinions. It was my original purpose to take a view of the principles of the National Assembly with regard to the great and fundamental establishments, and to compare the whole of what you have substituted in the place of what you have destroyed with the several members of our British Constitution. But this plan is of greater extent than at first I computed, and I find that you have little desire to take the advantage of any examples. At present I must content myself with some remarks upon your establishments, reserving for another time what I proposed to say concerning the spirit of our British monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy, as practically they exist.

This letter has become quite lengthy, even though it remains brief compared to the vastness of the topic. Various distractions have occasionally pulled my attention away from it. I wasn't unhappy to take some time to see if the actions of the National Assembly would give me reasons to change or soften some of my initial views. Instead, everything has only strengthened my original opinions. I initially intended to explore the principles of the National Assembly regarding the major and fundamental institutions and compare everything you've replaced with what you have dismantled to the different parts of our British Constitution. However, this plan is broader than I initially thought, and I see that you have little interest in drawing from any examples. For now, I must settle for some comments on your institutions, saving for another time what I intended to say about the nature of our British monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy as they actually exist.

I have taken a view of what has been done by the governing power in France. I have certainly spoke of it with freedom. Those whose principle it is to despise the ancient, permanent sense of mankind, and to set up a scheme of society on new principles, must naturally expect that such of us who think better of the judgment of the human race than, of theirs should consider both them and their devices as men and schemes upon their trial. They must take it for granted that we attend much to their reason, but not at all to their authority. They have not one of the great influencing prejudices of mankind in their favor. They avow their hostility to opinion. Of course they must expect no support from that influence, which, with every other authority, they have deposed from the seat of its jurisdiction.

I have taken a look at what the governing power in France has done. I’ve certainly spoken about it freely. Those who choose to disregard the timeless understanding of humanity and create a new society based on different principles should naturally expect that those of us who have a higher regard for human judgment than for theirs will see both them and their ideas as being put to the test. They should assume that we pay attention to their reasoning, but not at all to their authority. They don’t have any of the major influential biases of humanity on their side. They openly reject public opinion. Therefore, they should expect no support from the influence that they have ousted from its rightful place of power.

I can never consider this Assembly as anything else than a voluntary association of men who have availed themselves of circumstances to seize upon the power of the state. They have not the sanction and authority of the character under which they first met. They have assumed another of a very different nature, and have completely altered and inverted all the relations in which they originally stood. They do not hold the authority they exercise under any constitutional law of the state. They have departed from the instructions of the people by whom they were sent; which instructions, as the Assembly did not act in virtue of any ancient usage or settled law, were the sole source of their authority. The most considerable of their acts have not been done by great majorities; and in this sort of near divisions, which carry only the constructive authority of the whole, strangers will consider reasons as well as resolutions.

I can't see this Assembly as anything other than a voluntary group of people who have taken advantage of circumstances to grab hold of state power. They don't have the backing and legitimacy they had when they first came together. They've taken on a completely different role and have changed all the relationships that existed initially. They don't have the authority they claim under any constitutional law of the state. They've strayed from the instructions given by the people who sent them; those instructions, since the Assembly didn't act based on any long-standing tradition or established law, were their only source of authority. Most of their significant actions weren't decided by large majorities; and in these close votes, which only have the implied authority of the whole group, outside observers will consider arguments as well as decisions.

If they had set up this new, experimental government as a necessary substitute for an expelled tyranny, mankind would anticipate the time of prescription, which through long usage mellows into legality governments that were violent in their commencement. All those who have affections which lead them to the conservation of civil order would recognize, even in its cradle, the child as legitimate, which has been produced from those principles of cogent expediency to which all just governments owe their birth, and on which they justify their continuance. But they will be late and reluctant in giving any sort of countenance to the operations of a power which has derived its birth from no law and no necessity, but which, on the contrary, has had its origin in those vices and sinister practices by which the social union is often disturbed and sometimes destroyed. This Assembly has hardly a year's prescription. We have their own word for it that they have made a revolution. To make a revolution is a measure which, primâ fronte, requires an apology. To make a revolution is to subvert the ancient state of our country; and no common reasons are called for to justify so violent a proceeding. The sense of mankind authorizes us to examine into the mode of acquiring new power, and to criticize on the use that is made of it, with less awe and reverence than that which is usually conceded to a settled and recognized authority.

If they had established this new, experimental government as a necessary replacement for a removed tyranny, people would expect that over time, through long use, such governments would transition into legality, even if they started out violently. Everyone who cares about maintaining civil order would recognize, even in its early stages, this new entity as legitimate, born from the solid principles of practical need that all just governments owe their existence to and on which they justify their survival. However, they will be slow and hesitant to support any actions from a power that has arisen without any law or necessity, but instead from the vices and harmful practices that often disrupt and sometimes destroy social unity. This Assembly has barely been around for a year. They themselves admit they have made a revolution. Starting a revolution is something that, at first glance, demands justification. To create a revolution means to overturn our country's established order; thus, significant reasons are needed to justify such a drastic action. Society gives us the right to scrutinize how new power is gained and to critique how it is used, with less respect and reverence than is typically shown to an established and recognized authority.

In obtaining and securing their power, the Assembly proceeds upon principles the most opposite from those which appear to direct them in the use of it. An observation on this difference will let us into the true spirit of their conduct. Everything which they have done, or continue to do, in order to obtain and keep their power, is by the most common arts. They proceed exactly as their ancestors of ambition have done before them. Trace them through all their artifices, frauds, and violences, you can find nothing at all that is new. They follow precedents and examples with the punctilious exactness of a pleader. They never depart an iota from the authentic formulas of tyranny and usurpation. But in all the regulations relative to the public good the spirit has been the very reverse of this. There they commit the whole to the mercy of untried speculations; they abandon the dearest interests of the public to those loose theories to which none of them would choose to trust the slightest of his private concerns. They make this difference, because in their desire of obtaining and securing power they are thoroughly in earnest; there they travel in the beaten road. The public interests, because about them they have no real solicitude, they abandon wholly to chance: I say to chance, because their schemes have nothing in experience to prove their tendency beneficial.

In gaining and holding their power, the Assembly operates on principles that are completely different from those guiding them in how they use it. Noticing this difference reveals the true nature of their actions. Everything they have done or continue to do to obtain and maintain their power follows the oldest tricks in the book. They act just like their ambitious ancestors did before them. If you trace their manipulations, deceit, and violence, you won’t find anything new. They adhere to precedents and examples with the meticulousness of a lawyer. They never stray even a bit from the established methods of tyranny and usurpation. However, when it comes to regulations related to the public good, their approach is the exact opposite. They leave everything to the mercy of untested theories; they risk the most cherished interests of the public on ideas they wouldn't trust with even the smallest aspect of their personal affairs. They make this distinction because they are completely serious about obtaining and securing power; they stick to the tried-and-true path. But in regard to public interests, since they have no real concern for them, they leave everything to chance: I say chance, because their plans lack any practical experience to show that they will be beneficial.

We must always see with a pity not unmixed with respect the errors of those who are timid and doubtful of themselves with regard to points wherein the happiness of mankind is concerned. But in these gentlemen there is nothing of the tender parental solicitude which fears to cut up the infant for the sake of an experiment. In the vastness of their promises and the confidence of their predictions they far outdo all the boasting of empirics. The arrogance of their pretensions in a manner provokes and challenges us to an inquiry into their foundation.

We should always view with a mix of pity and respect the mistakes of those who are timid and unsure about themselves, especially when it comes to issues that affect human happiness. However, these gentlemen don't possess the caring concern of a parent afraid to dissect an infant for the sake of a test. In the grand scale of their promises and the certainty of their forecasts, they surpass all the bragging of those who rely solely on experience. The boldness of their claims essentially provokes us to investigate their basis.

I am convinced that there are men of considerable parts among the popular leaders in the National Assembly. Some of them display eloquence in their speeches and their writings. This cannot be without powerful and cultivated talents. But eloquence may exist without a proportionable degree of wisdom. When I speak of ability, I am obliged to distinguish. What they have done towards the support of their system bespeaks no ordinary men. In the system itself, taken as the scheme of a republic constructed for procuring the prosperity and security of the citizen, and for promoting the strength and grandeur of the state, I confess myself unable to find out anything which displays, in a single instance, the work of a comprehensive and disposing mind, or even the provisions of a vulgar prudence. Their purpose everywhere seems to have been to evade and slip aside from difficulty. This it has been the glory of the great masters in all the arts to confront, and to overcome,—and when they had overcome the first difficulty, to turn it into an instrument for new conquests over new difficulties: thus to enable them to extend the empire of their science, and even to push forward, beyond the reach of their original thoughts, the landmarks of the human understanding itself. Difficulty is a severe instructor, set over us by the supreme ordinance of a parental Guardian and Legislator, who knows us better than we know ourselves, as He loves us better too. Pater ipse colendi haud facilem esse viam voluit. He that wrestles with us strengthens our nerves and sharpens our skill. Our antagonist is our helper. This amicable conflict with difficulty obliges us to an intimate acquaintance with our object, and compels us to consider it in all its relations. It will not suffer us to be superficial. It is the want of nerves of understanding for such a task, it is the degenerate fondness for tricking short-outs and little fallacious facilities, that has in so many parts of the world created governments with arbitrary powers. They have created the late arbitrary monarchy of France. They have created the arbitrary republic of Paris. With them defects in wisdom are to be supplied by the plenitude of force. They get nothing by it. Commencing their labors on a principle of sloth, they have the common fortune of slothful men. The difficulties, which they rather had eluded than escaped, meet them again in their course; they multiply and thicken on them; they are involved, through a labyrinth of confused detail, in an industry without limit and without direction; and in conclusion, the whole of their work becomes feeble, vicious, and insecure.

I believe there are some really talented men among the popular leaders in the National Assembly. A few of them are quite eloquent in their speeches and writings, which indicates they have strong and refined skills. However, eloquence doesn’t necessarily mean they have a comparable level of wisdom. When I talk about ability, I have to differentiate. Their efforts to support their system show they are not ordinary men. Yet, when I look at the system itself—a republic meant to ensure the prosperity and security of its citizens and promote the strength and greatness of the state—I honestly can’t find anything that reflects true comprehensive thinking or even basic common sense. Their approach seems to be to avoid and sidestep challenges. The true masters of every discipline have always faced these challenges head-on and overcome them. Once they tackle the first difficulty, they turn it into a stepping stone for further challenges, thus expanding the boundaries of their field and pushing the limits of human understanding itself. Difficulty is a tough teacher, appointed by a wise Guardian and Legislator who knows us better than we know ourselves, and loves us deeply. He wants the path to mastery to be challenging. Those who struggle with difficulties strengthen their skills and enhance their abilities. Our challenges become our helpers. This friendly battle with difficulties forces us to deeply understand our subject and consider all its aspects. It doesn’t allow us to be superficial. It’s a lack of understanding and an unhealthy desire for easy shortcuts that has led to arbitrary governments in many parts of the world. They have contributed to the recent arbitrary monarchy in France and the arbitrary republic in Paris. In those cases, flaws in wisdom are compensated by an excess of force. But that strategy yields nothing. Starting their work from a place of laziness, they meet the fate of lazy individuals. The challenges they tried to avoid come back to confront them; they accumulate and overwhelm them, trapping them in a maze of chaotic details, resulting in aimless and boundless work. Ultimately, their efforts become weak, flawed, and unstable.

It is this inability to wrestle with difficulty which has obliged the arbitrary Assembly of France to commence their schemes of reform with abolition and total destruction.[120] But is it in destroying and pulling down that skill is displayed? Your mob can do this as well at least as your assemblies. The shallowest understanding, the rudest hand, is more than equal to that task. Rage and frenzy will pull down more in half an hour than prudence, deliberation, and foresight can build up in a hundred years. The errors and defects of old establishments are visible and palpable. It calls for little ability to point them out; and where absolute power is given, it requires but a word wholly to abolish the vice and the establishment together. The same lazy, but restless disposition, which loves sloth and hates quiet, directs these politicians, when they come to work for supplying the place of what they have destroyed. To make everything the reverse of what they have seen is quite as easy as to destroy. No difficulties occur in what has never been tried. Criticism is almost baffled in discovering the defects of what has not existed; and eager enthusiasm and cheating hope have all the wide field of imagination, in which they may expatiate with little or no opposition.

It’s this inability to deal with challenges that has forced the arbitrary Assembly of France to start their reform plans with outright abolition and complete destruction.[120] But is skill really shown in destroying and tearing things down? Your mob can do that just as well as your assemblies. Even the simplest understanding and the roughest hands can handle that job. Anger and chaos can tear down more in half an hour than wisdom, careful thought, and foresight can build in a hundred years. The mistakes and flaws of old systems are obvious and clear. It doesn’t take much talent to point them out; and where absolute power exists, it only takes a word to completely eliminate both the problem and the system. The same lazy yet restless attitude that favors inactivity and dislikes calm drives these politicians when they try to replace what they've destroyed. Making everything the opposite of what they’ve seen is just as easy as destroying it. There are no difficulties with what has never been attempted. Criticism struggles to find faults in what hasn’t existed; and eager excitement and deceptive hope have the entire realm of imagination to explore with little to no challenge.

At once to preserve and to reform is quite another thing. When the useful parts of an old establishment are kept, and what is superadded is to be fitted to what is retained, a vigorous mind, steady, persevering attention, various powers of comparison and combination, and the resources of an understanding fruitful in expedients are to be exercised; they are to be exercised in a continued conflict with the combined force of opposite vices, with the obstinacy that rejects all improvement, and the levity that is fatigued and disgusted with everything of which it is in possession. But you may object,—"A process of this kind is slow. It is not fit for an Assembly which glories in performing in a few months the work of ages. Such a mode of reforming, possibly, might take up many years." Without question it might; and it ought. It is one of the excellences of a method in which time is amongst the assistants, that its operation is slow, and in some cases almost imperceptible. If circumspection and caution are a part of wisdom, when we work only upon inanimate matter, surely they become a part of duty too, when the subject of our demolition and construction is not brick and timber, but sentient beings, by the sudden alteration of whose state, condition, and habits, multitudes may be rendered miserable. But it seems as if it were the prevalent opinion in Paris, that an unfeeling heart and an undoubting confidence are the sole qualifications for a perfect legislator. Far different are my ideas of that high office. The true lawgiver ought to have a heart full of sensibility. He ought to love and respect his kind, and to fear himself. It may be allowed to his temperament to catch his ultimate object with an intuitive glance; but his movements towards it ought to be deliberate. Political arrangement, as it is a work for social ends, is to be only wrought by social means. There mind must conspire with mind. Time is required to produce that union of minds which alone can produce all the good we aim at. Our patience will achieve more than our force. If I might venture to appeal to what is so much out of fashion in Paris,—I mean to experience,—I should tell you, that in my course I have known, and, according to my measure, have coöperated with great men; and I have never yet seen any plan which has not been mended by the observations of those who were much inferior in understanding to the person who took the lead in the business. By a slow, but well-sustained progress, the effect of each step is watched; the good or ill success of the first gives light to us in the second; and so, from light to light, we are conducted with safety through the whole series. We see that the parts of the system do not clash. The evils latent in the most promising contrivances are provided for as they arise. One advantage is as little as possible sacrificed to another. We compensate, we reconcile, we balance. We are enabled to unite into a consistent whole the various anomalies and contending principles that are found in the minds and affairs of men. From hence arises, not an excellence in simplicity, but one far superior, an excellence in composition. Where the great interests of mankind are concerned through a long succession of generations, that succession ought to be admitted into some share in the councils which are so deeply to affect them. If justice requires this, the work itself requires the aid of more minds than one age can furnish. It is from this view of things that the best legislators have been often satisfied with the establishment of some sure, solid, and ruling principle in government,—a power like that which some of the philosophers have called a plastic Nature; and having fixed the principle, they have left it afterwards to its own operation.

Preserving and reforming at the same time is a different challenge altogether. When the useful aspects of an old system are kept and new elements are added in harmony with what remains, it requires a sharp mind, steady and patient focus, a range of comparative and combinatory skills, and a creative understanding to find practical solutions. This effort involves an ongoing struggle against strong opposing flaws, against stubbornness that refuses any change, and against the indifference that grows tired and disillusioned with everything it has. You might argue, "This kind of process takes too long. It's not suitable for an assembly that prides itself on achieving in just a few months what would typically take ages." It certainly could take many years, and it should. One of the strengths of a method that includes time as a partner is that its impact can be gradual, sometimes almost unnoticed. If being careful and thoughtful is part of wisdom when dealing with lifeless matter, it certainly becomes a duty when we’re dealing with living beings, where sudden changes to their condition and habits can lead to suffering for many. However, it seems to be a common belief in Paris that a cold heart and blind confidence are the only traits a perfect lawmaker needs. My vision of such a high position is very different. The true lawmaker should be compassionate. They should care for and respect humanity and hold a healthy fear of themselves. While they might intuitively grasp their ultimate goal, their actions toward it should be considered and deliberate. Since political organization aims for social goals, it must be achieved through social methods. Minds must align. It takes time to create that unity of thought necessary to attain the good we seek. Our patience can achieve more than our strength. If I may reference something that’s gone out of style in Paris—experience—I would say that throughout my journey I have observed and, to some extent, collaborated with great individuals, and I have never encountered a plan that wasn’t improved by insights from those who had much less understanding than the leaders. Through a steady, though slow, progression, we can monitor the effects of each step; the success or failure of the first informs us for the next, guiding us with increasing clarity safely through the entire process. We see that the components of the system don’t conflict. Issues hidden in seemingly promising methods are addressed as they arise. One advantage is minimized as little as possible for the sake of another. We negotiate, we mediate, we find balance. We can integrate the various contradictions and competing principles found in human thoughts and actions into a coherent whole. This leads to not just a simplicity that is excellent, but to something far superior—an excellence in composition. When the significant interests of humanity span many generations, that succession should be included in the discussions that will greatly impact them. If justice calls for this, then the task itself needs the insights of more minds than one generation can provide. This perspective explains why the best lawmakers have often been content to establish some firm, solid, and guiding principle of governance—something akin to what some philosophers have called a "plastic Nature"; they set the principle in place and then allow it to operate on its own.

To proceed in this manner, that is, to proceed with a presiding principle and a prolific energy, is with me the criterion of profound wisdom. What your politicians think the marks of a bold, hardy genius are only proofs of a deplorable want of ability. By their violent haste, and their defiance of the process of Nature, they are delivered over blindly to every projector and adventurer, to every alchemist and empiric. They despair of turning to account anything that is common. Diet is nothing in their system of remedy. The worst of it is, that this their despair of curing common distempers by regular methods arises not only from defect of comprehension, but, I fear, from some malignity of disposition. Your legislators seem to have taken their opinions of all professions, ranks, and offices from the declamations and buffooneries of satirists,—who would themselves be astonished, if they were held to the letter of their own descriptions. By listening only to these, your leaders regard all things only on the side of their vices and faults, and view those vices and faults under every color of exaggeration. It is undoubtedly true, though it may seem paradoxical,—but, in general, those who are habitually employed in finding and displaying faults are unqualified for the work of reformation; because their minds are not only unfurnished with patterns of the fair and good, but by habit they come to take no delight in the contemplation of those things. By hating vices too much, they come to love men too little. It is therefore not wonderful that they should be indisposed and unable to serve them. From hence arises the complexional disposition of some of your guides to pull everything in pieces. At this malicious game they display the whole of their quadrimanous activity. As to the rest, the paradoxes of eloquent writers, brought forth purely as a sport of fancy, to try their talents, to rouse attention, and excite surprise, are taken up by these gentlemen, not in the spirit of the original authors, as means of cultivating their taste and improving their style: these paradoxes become with them serious grounds of action, upon which they proceed in regulating the most important concerns of the state. Cicero ludicrously describes Cato as endeavoring to act in the commonwealth upon the school paradoxes which exercised the wits of the junior students in the Stoic philosophy. If this was true of Cato, these gentlemen copy after him in the manner of some persons who lived about his time,—pede nudo Catonem. Mr. Hume told me that he had from Rousseau himself the secret of his principles of composition. That acute, though eccentric observer, had perceived, that, to strike and interest the public, the marvellous must be produced; that the marvellous of the heathen mythology had long since lost its effects; that giants, magicians, fairies, and heroes of romance, which succeeded, had exhausted the portion of credulity which belonged to their age; that now nothing was left to a writer but that species of the marvellous, which might still be produced, and with as great an effect as ever, though in another way,—that is, the marvellous in life, in manners, in characters, and in extraordinary situations, giving rise to new and unlooked-for strokes in politics and morals. I believe, that, were Rousseau alive, and in one of his lucid intervals, he would be shocked at the practical frenzy of his scholars, who in their paradoxes are servile imitators, and even in their incredulity discover an implicit faith.

To move forward like this—meaning to act with a guiding principle and a strong energy—is my definition of true wisdom. What your politicians see as signs of a bold, fearless genius are actually clear indicators of a serious lack of ability. Their reckless rush and disregard for the natural process lead them blindly to every schemer and adventurer, every quack and charlatan. They have given up on making use of anything ordinary. In their view, diet is irrelevant for their system of remedies. The worst part is that their hopelessness about treating common ailments through standard methods stems not only from a failure to understand but, I fear, from some malice in their character. Your lawmakers seem to base their views on all professions, classes, and positions on the rants and mockeries of satirists—who would themselves be shocked if they were judged by their own descriptions. By only listening to these voices, your leaders see everything through the lens of its faults and vices, exaggerating those flaws at every turn. It’s certainly true, though it might seem surprising, that those who are constantly focused on finding and showcasing faults are unsuitable for the job of reforming things; their minds lack examples of what is beautiful and good, and over time they come to take no pleasure in contemplating those ideals. By hating vices too much, they end up loving people too little. So, it’s no wonder they feel unwilling and unable to help them. This gives rise to the tendency among some of your leaders to tear everything apart. In this malicious game, they show off all their energy. As for the rest, the paradoxes created by eloquent writers purely for fun, to test their skills and capture attention, are taken up by these gentlemen, not in the spirit of the original authors as a means to refine their taste and improve their writing style. Instead, those paradoxes become serious foundations for actions that influence their handling of major state matters. Cicero humorously portrays Cato as trying to run the government following the school paradoxes that challenged the minds of young students in Stoic philosophy. If this was true of Cato, these gentlemen imitate him like some people did in his time—pede nudo Catonem. Mr. Hume mentioned to me that he got the secret of Rousseau's composition principles straight from him. That sharp, though unconventional thinker, realized that to engage and interest the public, something extraordinary must be presented; that the wonders of ancient mythology had long lost their impact; that giants, magicians, fairies, and romance heroes had exhausted the public's capacity for belief; that now, a writer has left to them only that type of wonder which can still be created—with as great an effect as before, but in a different way—namely, the marvels in life, in manners, in character, and in unusual situations, which can lead to new and unexpected developments in politics and morals. I believe that if Rousseau were alive today and had one of his clear moments, he would be appalled by the practical craziness of his students, who, in their paradoxes, are merely imitating him and even in their disbelief show an implicit faith.

Men who undertake considerable things, even in a regular way, ought to give us ground to presume ability. But the physician of the state, who, not satisfied with the cure of distempers, undertakes to regenerate constitutions, ought to show uncommon powers. Some very unusual appearances of wisdom ought to display themselves on the face of the designs of those who appeal to no practice and who copy after no model. Has any such been manifested? I shall take a view (it shall for the subject be a very short one) of what the Assembly has done, with regard, first, to the constitution of the legislature; in the next place, to that of the executive power; then to that of the judicature; afterwards to the model of the army; and conclude with the system of finance: to see whether we can discover in any part of their schemes the portentous ability which may justify these bold undertakers in the superiority which they assume over mankind.

Men who take on significant responsibilities, even in a consistent manner, should give us a reason to believe they have the capability. However, the person in charge of the state, who, not content with simply fixing problems, aims to transform the entire system, should demonstrate exceptional skills. Some very remarkable signs of wisdom should be evident in the plans of those who don’t follow established practices and who create their own models. Has any such evidence been shown? I will take a brief look at what the Assembly has done, starting with the structure of the legislature; next, the structure of the executive branch; then, the judiciary; followed by the organization of the military; and finally, the financial system: to see if we can find any part of their proposals that shows the extraordinary ability which might justify their claim to superiority over others.

It is in the model of the sovereign and presiding part of this new republic that we should expect their grand display. Here they were to prove their title to their proud demands. For the plan itself at large, and for the reasons on which it is grounded, I refer to the journals of the Assembly of the 29th of September, 1789, and to the subsequent proceedings which have made any alterations in the plan. So far as in a matter somewhat confused I can see light, the system remains substantially as it has been originally framed. My few remarks will be such as regard its spirit, its tendency, and its fitness for framing a popular commonwealth, which they profess theirs to be, suited to the ends for which any commonwealth, and particularly such a commonwealth, is made. At the same time I mean to consider its consistency with itself and its own principles.

It is in the model of the ruling and leading part of this new republic that we should expect their grand display. Here, they were to prove their right to their lofty demands. For the overall plan and the reasons it’s based on, I refer you to the Assembly's records from September 29, 1789, and the following actions that have made any changes to the plan. As far as I can see through what is somewhat confusing, the system basically remains as it was originally designed. My comments will focus on its spirit, its direction, and how suitable it is for creating a popular government, which they claim theirs to be, appropriate for the purposes any government, and especially such a government, is established. At the same time, I will also consider its consistency with itself and its own principles.

Old establishments are tried by their effects. If the people are happy, united, wealthy, and powerful, we presume the rest. We conclude that to be good from whence good is derived. In old establishments various correctives have been found for their aberrations from theory. Indeed, they are the results of various necessities and expediences. They are not often constructed after any theory: theories are rather drawn from them. In them we often see the end best obtained, where the means seem not perfectly reconcilable to what we may fancy was the original scheme. The means taught by experience may be better suited to political ends than those contrived in the original project. They again react upon the primitive constitution, and sometimes improve the design itself, from which they seem to have departed. I think all this might be curiously exemplified in the British Constitution. At worst, the errors and deviations of every kind in reckoning are found and computed, and the ship proceeds in her course. This is the case of old establishments; but in a new and merely theoretic system, it is expected that every contrivance shall appear, on the face of it, to answer its ends, especially where the projectors are no way embarrassed with an endeavor to accommodate the new building to an old one, either in the walls or on the foundations.

Old systems are judged by their results. If the people are happy, united, wealthy, and powerful, we assume the rest is positive. We conclude that goodness comes from good outcomes. In old systems, different solutions have been discovered for their deviations from theory. In fact, they typically arise from various necessities and practical situations. They aren't usually built on a specific theory; instead, theories are often developed from them. We often find that the best outcomes are achieved even when the methods don’t seem fully aligned with what we might think was the original plan. The methods learned through experience may be better suited to political goals than those imagined in the initial design. These methods can also influence the original structure, sometimes enhancing the original concept from which they seemed to have diverged. I believe all this can be interestingly illustrated in the British Constitution. At the very least, the mistakes and variations in calculations are identified and accounted for, allowing the system to continue on its path. This applies to old systems; however, in a new, purely theoretical system, it is expected that every element clearly serves its purpose, especially when those creating it aren't hindered by trying to adapt the new structure to an old one, whether it be the walls or the foundations.

The French builders, clearing away as mere rubbish whatever they found, and, like their ornamental gardeners, forming everything into an exact level, propose to rest the whole local and general legislature on three bases of three different kinds,—one geometrical, one arithmetical, and the third financial; the first of which they call the basis of territory; the second, the basis of population; and the third, the basis of contribution. For the accomplishment of the first of these purposes, they divide the area of their country into eighty-three pieces, regularly square, of eighteen leagues by eighteen. These large divisions are called Departments. These they portion, proceeding by square measurement, into seventeen hundred and twenty districts, called Communes. These again they subdivide, still proceeding by square measurement, into smaller districts, called Cantons, making in all 6,400.

The French builders, dismissing everything they found as mere junk, and like their decorative gardeners, leveling everything out precisely, aim to base the entire local and national legislature on three foundations of different types—one geometrical, one arithmetical, and the third financial. They refer to the first as the basis of territory; the second as the basis of population; and the third as the basis of contribution. To achieve the first goal, they divide their country's area into eighty-three square sections, each eighteen leagues by eighteen. These large divisions are called Departments. They then further divide these into about seventeen hundred and twenty districts, referred to as Communes. These are again subdivided, continuing with square measurements, into smaller districts called Cantons, totaling 6,400.

At first view this geometrical basis of theirs presents not much to admire or to blame. It calls for no great legislative talents. Nothing more than an accurate land-surveyor, with his chain, sight, and theodolite, is requisite for such a plan as this. In the old divisions of the country, various accidents at times, and the ebb and flow of various properties and jurisdictions, settled their bounds. These bounds were not made upon any fixed system, undoubtedly. They were subject to some inconveniences; but they were inconveniences for which use had found remedies, and habit had supplied accommodation and patience. In this new pavement of square within square, and this organization and semi-organization, made on the system of Empedocles and Buffon, and not upon any politic principle, it is impossible that innumerable local inconveniences, to which men are not habituated, must not arise. But these I pass over, because it requires an accurate knowledge of the country, which I do not possess, to specify them.

At first glance, their geometrical approach doesn’t seem particularly impressive or flawed. It doesn’t require any exceptional legislative skills—just a skilled land surveyor with a measuring chain, sight levels, and a theodolite is enough to carry out a plan like this. In the past divisions of the country, various circumstances and the shifting nature of properties and jurisdictions defined their boundaries. These boundaries weren’t established on any fixed system, for sure. They had some drawbacks, but these were inconveniences that practical use had addressed, and over time, people had learned to adapt and be patient. With this new layout of squares within squares, and this system of organization and semi-organization, based on the ideas of Empedocles and Buffon rather than any political reasoning, it’s inevitable that many local issues will arise—which people are not used to dealing with. However, I’ll skip over these because identifying them requires a detailed understanding of the area that I don’t have.

When these state surveyors came to take a view of their work of measurement, they soon found that in politics the most fallacious of all things was geometrical demonstration. They had then recourse to another basis (or rather buttress) to support the building, which tottered on that false foundation. It was evident that the goodness of the soil, the number of the people, their wealth, and the largeness of their contribution, made such infinite variations between square and square as to render mensuration a ridiculous standard of power in the commonwealth, and equality in geometry the most unequal of all measures in the distribution of men. However, they could not give it up,—but, dividing their political and civil representation into three parts, they allotted one of those parts to the square measurement, without a single fact or calculation to ascertain whether this territorial proportion of representation was fairly assigned, and ought upon any principle really to be a third. Having, however, given to geometry this portion, (of a third for her dower,) out of compliment, I suppose, to that sublime science, they left the other two to be scuffled for between the other parts, population and contribution.

When the state surveyors came to assess their measurement work, they quickly realized that in politics, the most misleading thing was geometric proof. They then turned to another foundation to support the shaky structure built on that false base. It was clear that the quality of the land, the population size, their wealth, and the size of their contributions created such vast differences between areas that using area measurement as a standard for power in the government was absurd, and the concept of equality in geometry was the most unequal measure when it came to distributing people. However, they couldn’t let go of the idea. Instead, they split their political and civil representation into three parts and assigned one of those parts to geometric measurement, without a single fact or calculation to determine whether this allocation was fair or made sense as a third. After assigning this portion to geometry (as a third for its contribution), out of respect, I suppose, for that noble science, they left the remaining two parts to be contested between population and contribution.

When they came to provide for population, they were not able to proceed quite so smoothly as they had done in the field of their geometry. Here their arithmetic came to bear upon their juridical metaphysics. Had they stuck to their metaphysic principles, the arithmetical process would be simple indeed. Men, with them, are strictly equal, and are entitled to equal rights in their own government. Each head, on this system, would have its vote, and every man would vote directly for the person who was to represent him in the legislature. "But soft,—by regular degrees, not yet." This metaphysic principle, to which law, custom, usage, policy, reason, were to yield, is to yield itself to their pleasure. There must be many degrees, and some stages, before the representative can come in contact with his constituent. Indeed, as we shall soon see, these two persons are to have no sort of communion with each other. First, the voters in the Canton, who compose what they call primary assemblies, are to have a qualification. What! a qualification on the indefeasible rights of men? Yes; but it shall be a very small qualification. Our injustice shall be very little oppressive: only the local valuation of three days' labor paid to the public. Why, this is not much, I readily admit, for anything but the utter subversion of your equalizing principle. As a qualification it might as well be let alone; for it answers no one purpose for which qualifications are established; and, on your ideas, it excludes from a vote the man of all others whose natural equality stands the most in need of protection and defence: I mean the man who has nothing else but his natural equality to guard him. You order him to buy the right which you before told him Nature had given to him gratuitously at his birth, and of which no authority on earth could lawfully deprive him. With regard to the person who cannot come up to your market, a tyrannous aristocracy, as against him, is established at the very outset, by you who pretend to be its sworn foe.

When they tried to provide for the population, things didn't go as smoothly as in their geometry work. Here, their math collided with their legal philosophy. If they had stuck to their philosophical principles, the mathematical process would have been straightforward. In their view, all people are equal and deserve equal rights in their governance. Each individual would get a vote, and everyone would vote directly for their representative in the legislature. "But wait—let's take it step by step, not just yet." This philosophical principle, which laws, customs, practices, and reason were supposed to obey, is bending to their will. There have to be multiple steps and stages before a representative engages with their voters. In fact, as we'll soon see, these two parties won't have any real connection with each other. First, the voters in the Canton, who make up what they call primary assemblies, must meet a qualification. What? A qualification on the undeniable rights of people? Yes, but it will be a very minimal qualification. Our injustice will be minimally oppressive: just the local value of three days' labor paid to the public. Honestly, this isn't much, I freely admit, for anything other than completely undermining your equal rights principle. As a qualification, it might as well not exist; it serves no real purpose for which qualifications are meant; and, based on your ideas, it excludes from voting the person who most desperately needs protection for their natural equality: the person who has nothing but that equality to defend them. You're telling them to purchase the right that you previously stated Nature gave them for free at birth, and from which no authority on earth can justly take away. For those who can't meet your requirements, a tyrannical elite is established right from the start by you, who claim to be its greatest enemy.

The gradation proceeds. These primary assemblies of the Canton elect deputies to the Commune,—one for every two hundred qualified inhabitants. Here is the first medium put between the primary elector and the representative legislator; and here a new turnpike is fixed for taxing the rights of men with a second qualification: for none can be elected into the Commune who does not pay the amount of ten days' labor. Nor have we yet done. There is still to be another gradation.[121] These Communes, chosen by the Canton, choose to the Department; and the deputies of the Department choose their deputies to the National Assembly. Here is a third barrier of a senseless qualification. Every deputy to the National Assembly must pay, in direct contribution, to the value of a mark of silver. Of all these qualifying barriers we must think alike: that they are impotent to secure independence, strong only to destroy the rights of men.

The gradation continues. These primary assemblies of the Canton elect representatives to the Commune,—one for every two hundred qualified residents. This is the first layer placed between the primary voter and the legislative representative; and here a new requirement is established for restricting the rights of individuals based on a second qualification: only those who can pay the equivalent of ten days' labor can be elected to the Commune. But we’re not finished yet. There’s still another layer to add.[121] These Communes, elected by the Canton, select representatives to the Department; and the deputies from the Department choose their delegates to the National Assembly. This is a third barrier of a pointless qualification. Every deputy to the National Assembly must pay, as a direct contribution, the value of a mark of silver. When it comes to all these qualifying barriers, we must agree: they do not ensure independence, but are only effective in undermining the rights of individuals.

In all this process, which in its fundamental elements affects to consider only population, upon a principle of natural right, there is a manifest attention to property,—which, however just and reasonable on other schemes, is on theirs perfectly unsupportable.

In this entire process, which fundamentally focuses only on population based on a principle of natural rights, there is a clear emphasis on property—which, while fair and sensible in other contexts, is completely unsustainable in theirs.

When they come to their third basis, that of Contribution, we find that they have more completely lost sight of the rights of men. This last basis rests entirely on property. A principle totally different from the equality of men, and utterly irreconcilable to it, is thereby admitted: but no sooner is this principle admitted than (as usual) it is subverted; and it is not subverted (as we shall presently see) to approximate the inequality of riches to the level of Nature. The additional share in the third portion of representation (a portion reserved exclusively for the higher contribution) is made to regard the district only, and not the individuals in it who pay. It is easy to perceive, by the course of their reasonings, how much they were embarrassed by their contradictory ideas of the rights of men and the privileges of riches. The Committee of Constitution do as good as admit that they are wholly irreconcilable. "The relation with regard to the contributions is without doubt null, (say they,) when the question is on the balance of the political rights as between individual and individual; without which personal equality would be destroyed, and an aristocracy of the rich would be established. But this inconvenience entirely disappears, when the proportional relation of the contribution is only considered in the great masses, and is solely between province and province; it serves in that case only to form a just reciprocal proportion between the cities, without affecting the personal rights of the citizens."

When they arrive at their third basis, which is Contribution, it's clear that they have completely lost sight of people's rights. This last basis relies entirely on property. This principle is fundamentally different from the equality of individuals and is completely incompatible with it. However, as soon as this principle is acknowledged, it is (as usual) undermined; and it is not undermined (as we will soon see) to align the inequality of wealth with the natural order. The extra share in the third portion of representation (a portion reserved exclusively for higher contributions) focuses only on the district and not on the individuals within it who are paying. By following their reasoning, it's easy to see how much they struggled with their conflicting ideas about people's rights and the privileges of wealth. The Committee of Constitution pretty much admits that these ideas are irreconcilable. "The relationship regarding contributions is undoubtedly null, (they say,) when it comes to balancing political rights between individuals; without which personal equality would be destroyed, and an aristocracy of the rich would be formed. But this issue completely disappears when the proportional relationship of contributions is only considered among the great masses and applies solely between provinces; in that case, it merely creates a fair reciprocal ratio between cities, without impacting the personal rights of citizens."

Here the principle of contribution, as taken between man and man, is reprobated as null, and destructive to equality,—and as pernicious, too, because it leads to the establishment of an aristocracy of the rich. However, it must not be abandoned. And the way of getting rid of the difficulty is to establish the inequality as between department and department, leaving all the individuals in each department upon an exact par. Observe, that this parity between individuals had been before destroyed, when the qualifications within the departments were settled; nor does it seem a matter of great importance whether the equality of men be injured by masses or individually. An individual is not of the same importance in a mass represented by a few as in a mass represented by many. It would be too much to tell a man jealous of his equality, that the elector has the same franchise who votes for three members as he who votes for ten.

Here, the idea of contribution between individuals is criticized as null and harmful to equality, as it also fosters the creation of an aristocracy of the rich. However, it shouldn’t be completely discarded. The solution to this issue is to create inequality between different departments while keeping all individuals within each department on an equal footing. Note that this equality among individuals was already disrupted when the qualifications within the departments were set; it doesn't seem to matter much whether equality among people is compromised by groups or individuals. A single person doesn’t hold the same significance in a group represented by a few as they do in a group represented by many. It would be unfair to tell someone concerned about their equality that the voter who elects three members has the same voting rights as the one who elects ten.

Now take it in the other point of view, and let us suppose their principle of representation according to contribution, that is according to riches, to be well imagined, and to be a necessary basis for their republic. In this their third basis they assume that riches ought to be respected, and that justice and policy require that they should entitle men, in some mode or other, to a larger share in the administration of public affairs; it is now to be seen how the Assembly provides for the preëminence, or even for the security of the rich, by conferring, in virtue of their opulence, that larger measure of power to their district which is denied to them personally. I readily admit (indeed, I should lay it down as a fundamental principle) that in a republican government, which has a democratic basis, the rich do require an additional security above what is necessary to them in monarchies. They are subject to envy, and through envy to oppression. On the present scheme it is impossible to divine what advantage they derive from the aristocratic preference upon which the unequal representation of the masses is founded. The rich cannot feel it, either as a support to dignity or as security to fortune: for the aristocratic mass is generated from purely democratic principles; and the prevalence given to it in the general representation has no sort of reference to or connection with the persons upon account of whose property this superiority of the mass is established. If the contrivers of this scheme meant any sort of favor to the rich, in consequence of their contribution, they ought to have conferred the privilege either on the individual rich, or on some class formed of rich persons (as historians represent Servius Tullius to have done in the early constitution of Rome); because the contest between the rich and the poor is not a struggle between corporation and corporation, but a contest between men and men,—a competition, not between districts, but between descriptions. It would answer its purpose better, if the scheme were inverted: that the votes of the masses were rendered equal, and that the votes within each mass were proportioned to property.

Now let’s look at it from another angle and suppose their idea of representation based on contributions, meaning based on wealth, is well-founded and necessary for their republic. In this third principle, they assume that wealth should be respected and that fairness and policy require it to grant individuals, in one way or another, greater participation in public affairs. It’s now worth examining how the Assembly ensures the dominance, or even the security, of the wealthy by giving them more power in their district because of their wealth, which is denied to them personally. I fully acknowledge (in fact, I would establish it as a fundamental principle) that in a republican government with a democratic foundation, the wealthy need extra security compared to what is necessary in monarchies. They are vulnerable to envy, and through that envy, potential oppression. Under the current arrangement, it’s unclear what benefit they gain from the aristocratic preference that underlies the unequal representation of the masses. The wealthy cannot perceive it as a boost to their dignity or security for their wealth, since the aristocratic class is formed entirely from democratic principles; the emphasis on it in the overall representation has no real connection to the individuals whose wealth establishes this superiority of the class. If the creators of this system intended to favor the wealthy due to their contributions, they should have granted the privilege either to individual wealthy persons or to a specific class of wealthy individuals (as historians say Servius Tullius did in the early constitution of Rome); because the conflict between the rich and the poor is not a battle between organizations but a struggle between individuals—it's a competition not between districts, but between types of people. It would make more sense if the plan were reversed: making the votes of the masses equal while proportioning the votes within each group according to wealth.

Let us suppose one man in a district (it is an easy supposition) to contribute as much as a hundred of his neighbors. Against these he has but one vote. If there were but one representative for the mass, his poor neighbors would outvote him by an hundred to one for that single representative. Bad enough! But amends are to be made him. How? The district, in virtue of his wealth, is to choose, say ten members instead of one: that is to say, by paying a very large contribution he has the happiness of being outvoted, an hundred to one, by the poor, for ten representatives, instead of being outvoted exactly in the same proportion for a single member. In truth, instead of benefiting by this superior quantity of representation, the rich man is subjected to an additional hardship. The increase of representation within his province sets up nine persons more, and as many more than nine as there may be democratic candidates, to cabal and intrigue and to flatter the people at his expense and to his oppression. An interest is by this means held out to multitudes of the inferior sort, in obtaining a salary of eighteen livres a day, (to them a vast object,) besides the pleasure of a residence in Paris, and their share in the government of the kingdom. The more the objects of ambition are multiplied and become democratic, just in that proportion the rich are endangered.

Let's say one person in a community (which is easy to imagine) contributes as much as a hundred of his neighbors. He only gets one vote against them. If there were just one representative for the whole group, his less wealthy neighbors would outvote him one hundred to one for that single representative. That's bad enough! But there's supposed to be a fix for him. How? Because of his wealth, the district gets to elect, let's say, ten representatives instead of just one: meaning by making a huge contribution, he gets the pleasure of being outvoted one hundred to one by the poor for ten representatives, rather than being outvoted in the same ratio for just one. In reality, instead of gaining from this increased representation, the wealthy individual faces even more challenges. The rise in representatives in his area creates nine more people—and even more depending on how many democratic candidates there are—who will scheme, plot, and flatter the public at his expense and to his detriment. This way, many from the lower class are incentivized to secure a salary of eighteen livres a day (which is a significant amount for them), along with the perk of living in Paris and having a stake in the country's governance. The more ambitions become widespread and democratic, the more the rich are at risk.

Thus it must fare between the poor and the rich in the province deemed aristocratic, which in its internal relation is the very reverse of that character. In its external relation, that is, in its relation to the other provinces, I cannot see how the unequal representation which is given to masses on account of wealth becomes the means of preserving the equipoise and the tranquillity of the commonwealth. For, if it be one of the objects to secure the weak from being crushed by the strong, (as in all society undoubtedly it is,) how are the smaller and poorer of these masses to be saved from the tyranny of the more wealthy? Is it by adding to the wealthy further and more systematical means of oppressing them? When we come to a balance of representation between corporate bodies, provincial interests, emulations, and jealousies are full as likely to arise among them as among individuals; and their divisions are likely to produce a much hotter spirit of dissension, and something leading much more nearly to a war.

It has to be about how the poor and the rich interact in the province considered aristocratic, which ironically is the opposite of that idea in its internal dynamics. Externally, in relation to other provinces, I can’t see how the unfair representation based on wealth helps maintain balance and peace in society. If one of the goals is to protect the vulnerable from being dominated by the powerful—something every society aims for—how are the smaller and poorer groups supposed to avoid being oppressed by the wealthier ones? Is it by providing the rich with more organized ways to control them? When we talk about balancing representation among corporations, provincial interests, rivalries, and animosities can emerge just as easily as they do among individuals; and their divisions are likely to spark much more intense conflicts and lead much closer to war.

I see that these aristocratic masses are made upon what is called the principle of direct contribution. Nothing can be a more unequal standard than this. The indirect contribution, that which arises from duties on consumption, is in truth a better standard, and follows and discovers wealth more naturally than this of direct contribution. It is difficult, indeed, to fix a standard of local preference on account of the one, or of the other, or of both, because some provinces may pay the more of either or of both on account of causes not intrinsic, but originating from those very districts over whom they have obtained a preference in consequence of their ostensible contribution. If the masses were independent, sovereign bodies, who were to provide for a federative treasury by distinct contingents, and that the revenue had not (as it has) many impositions running through the whole, which affect men individually, and not corporately, and which, by their nature, confound all territorial limits, something might be said for the basis of contribution as founded on masses. But, of all things, this representation, to be measured by contribution, is the most difficult to settle upon principles of equity in a country which considers its districts as members of a whole. For a great city, such as Bordeaux or Paris, appears to pay a vast body of duties, almost out of all assignable proportion to other places, and its mass is considered accordingly. But are these cities the true contributors in that proportion? No. The consumers of the commodities imported into Bordeaux, who are scattered through all France, pay the import duties of Bordeaux. The produce of the vintage in Guienne and Languedoc give to that city the means of its contribution growing out of an export commerce. The landholders who spend their estates in Paris, and are thereby the creators of that city, contribute for Paris from the provinces out of which their revenues arise. Very nearly the same arguments will apply to the representative share given on account of direct contribution: because the direct contribution must be assessed on wealth, real or presumed; and that local wealth will itself arise from causes not local, and which therefore in equity ought not to produce a local preference.

I see that these aristocratic masses are based on what is called the principle of direct contribution. Nothing could be a more unequal standard than this. The indirect contribution, which comes from consumption taxes, is actually a better standard, and it more naturally tracks and reveals wealth than direct contribution does. It is indeed challenging to establish a standard of local preference based on either one, or both, because some regions may pay more of either or both due to factors that are not inherent but stem from the very districts that have gained a preference because of their apparent contribution. If the masses were independent, sovereign entities that provided for a federal treasury with distinct contributions, and if the revenue didn’t have, as it does, many taxes that apply to individuals and not to groups, which by their nature blur all territorial boundaries, then there could be a case for measuring contribution based on masses. However, above all, this representation, when measured by contribution, is the hardest to determine on fair principles in a country that views its districts as parts of a whole. For a major city, like Bordeaux or Paris, seems to pay a tremendous amount of taxes, far out of proportion to other places, and its size is considered accordingly. But are these cities actually the true contributors in that proportion? No. The consumers of the goods imported into Bordeaux, who spread across all of France, pay the import taxes of Bordeaux. The produce from the vineyards in Guienne and Languedoc provides that city the means for its contribution arising from export commerce. The landowners who spend their wealth in Paris, thus contributing to the city's development, contribute to Paris from the provinces where their incomes come from. Very similar reasoning applies to the representative share allocated based on direct contribution: because the direct contribution must be calculated based on wealth, whether real or assumed; and that local wealth will itself arise from non-local causes, which therefore, in fairness, should not create a local preference.

It is very remarkable, that, in this fundamental regulation which settles the representation of the mass upon the direct contribution, they have not yet settled how that direct contribution shall be laid, and how apportioned. Perhaps there is some latent policy towards the continuance of the present Assembly in this strange procedure. However, until they do this, they can have no certain constitution. It must depend at last upon the system of taxation, and must vary with every variation in that system. As they have contrived matters, their taxation does not so much depend on their constitution as their constitution on their taxation. This must introduce great confusion among the masses; as the variable qualification for votes within the district must, if ever real contested elections take place, cause infinite internal controversies.

It's quite surprising that in this essential rule that determines how the public is represented based on direct contributions, they still haven't figured out how that direct contribution will be assessed and distributed. There might be some hidden agenda related to keeping the current Assembly going behind this unusual process. However, until they address this, they won't have a stable constitution. Ultimately, it will rely on the tax system and change with every adjustment to that system. As things stand, their taxation relies more on their constitution than the other way around. This could lead to significant confusion among the public since the changing requirements for voting in the

To compare together the three bases, not on their political reason, but on the ideas on which the Assembly works, and to try its consistency with itself, we cannot avoid observing that the principle which the committee call the basis of population does not begin to operate from the same point with the two other principles, called the bases of territory and of contribution, which are both of an aristocratic nature. The consequence is, that, where all three begin to operate together, there is the most absurd inequality produced by the operation of the former on the two latter principles. Every canton contains four square leagues, and is estimated to contain, on the average, 4,000 inhabitants, or 680 voters in the primary assemblies, which vary in numbers with the population of the canton, and send one deputy to the commune for every 200 voters. Nine cantons make a commune.

To compare the three bases, not by their political rationale, but by the ideas that guide the Assembly, and to evaluate their internal consistency, we should note that the principle the committee refers to as the basis of population doesn’t start functioning from the same point as the other two principles, known as the bases of territory and contribution, which both have an aristocratic nature. As a result, where all three principles function together, the initial principle produces a highly absurd inequality in relation to the other two. Each canton covers four square leagues and is estimated to have an average population of 4,000 inhabitants, or 680 voters in the primary assemblies, which fluctuate in number based on the canton’s population, and each sends one deputy to the commune for every 200 voters. Nine cantons make up a commune.

Now let us take a canton containing a seaport town of trade, or a great manufacturing town. Let us suppose the population of this canton to be 12,700 inhabitants, or 2,193 voters, forming three primary assemblies, and sending ten deputies to the commune.

Now let's consider a region with a busy trading seaport or a major manufacturing city. Suppose the population of this region is 12,700 residents, or 2,193 voters, making up three local assemblies and sending ten representatives to the community.

Oppose to this one canton two others of the remaining eight in the same commune. These we may suppose to have their fair population, of 4,000 inhabitants, and 680 voters each, or 8,000 inhabitants and 1,360 voters, both together. These will form only two primary assemblies, and send only six deputies to the commune.

Opposed to this one district are two other districts of the remaining eight in the same municipality. We can assume that each has a fair population of 4,000 residents and 680 voters, totaling 8,000 residents and 1,360 voters combined. These will only form two primary assemblies and will send only six representatives to the municipality.

When the assembly of the commune comes to vote on the basis of territory, which principle is first admitted to operate in that assembly, the single canton, which has half the territory of the other two, will have ten voices to six in the election of three deputies to the assembly of the department, chosen on the express ground of a representation of territory. This inequality, striking as it is, will be yet highly aggravated, if we suppose, as we fairly may, the several other cantons of the commune to fall proportionally short of the average population, as much as the principal canton exceeds it.

When the assembly of the commune comes to vote based on territory, the principle that is first accepted in that assembly is the single canton. This canton, which has half the territory of the other two, will have ten votes compared to six in the election of three deputies to the department assembly, chosen specifically to represent territory. This inequality, though notable, will become even more pronounced if we assume, as we can reasonably do, that the other cantons of the commune fall proportionately short of the average population, just as the principal canton exceeds it.

Now as to the basis of contribution, which also is a principle admitted first to operate in the assembly of the commune. Let us again take one canton, such as is stated above. If the whole of the direct contributions paid by a great trading or manufacturing town be divided equally among the inhabitants, each individual will be found to pay much more than an individual living in the country according to the same average. The whole paid by the inhabitants of the former will be more than the whole paid by the inhabitants of the latter,—we may fairly assume one third more. Then the 12,700 inhabitants, or 2,193 voters of the canton, will pay as much as 19,050 inhabitants, or 3,289 voters of the other cantons, which are nearly the estimated proportion of inhabitants and voters of five other cantons. Now the 2,193 voters will, as I before said, send only ten deputies to the assembly; the 3,289 voters will send sixteen. Thus, for an equal share in the contribution of the whole commune, there will be a difference of sixteen voices to ten in voting for deputies to be chosen on the principle of representing the general contribution of the whole commune.

Now regarding the basis of contribution, which is a principle initially applied in the assembly of the commune. Let's take one canton, as mentioned earlier. If we divide the total direct contributions paid by a large trading or manufacturing city equally among its residents, each person would pay significantly more than someone living in the countryside based on the same average. The total contribution from the city’s residents will exceed that of the rural residents—let's reasonably assume it's about one third more. Therefore, the 12,700 residents, or 2,193 voters of the canton, will contribute as much as 19,050 residents, or 3,289 voters from the other cantons, which closely matches the estimated population and voter ratio of five other cantons. As I mentioned earlier, the 2,193 voters will only send ten deputies to the assembly; the 3,289 voters will send sixteen. So, for an equal share in the contributions of the whole commune, there will be a difference of sixteen votes to ten when electing deputies based on the principle of representing the overall contributions of the entire commune.

By the same mode of computation, we shall find 15,875 inhabitants, or 2,741 voters of the other cantons, who pay one sixth LESS to the contribution of the whole commune, will have three voices MORE than the 12,700 inhabitants, or 2,193 voters of the one canton.

By using the same method of calculation, we will find 15,875 residents, or 2,741 voters from the other cantons, who pay one sixth LESS towards the overall commune, will have three more votes than the 12,700 residents, or 2,193 voters from the one canton.

Such is the fantastical and unjust inequality between mass and mass, in this curious repartition of the rights of representation arising out of territory and contribution. The qualifications which these confer are in truth negative qualifications, that give a right in an inverse proportion to the possession of them.

Such is the strange and unfair inequality between groups in this odd distribution of representation rights based on territory and contribution. The qualifications that these provide are actually negative qualifications, granting rights in a way that inversely relates to how much one possesses.

In this whole contrivance of the three bases, consider it in any light you please, I do not see a variety of objects reconciled in one consistent whole, but several contradictory principles reluctantly and irreconcilably brought and held together by your philosophers, like wild beasts shut up in a cage, to claw and bite each other to their mutual destruction.

In this entire setup of the three bases, no matter how you look at it, I don't see different elements fitting together into a unified whole, but rather several conflicting principles that are awkwardly and irreconcilably forced together by your philosophers, like wild animals trapped in a cage, clawing and biting each other to their mutual destruction.

I am afraid I have gone too far into their way of considering the formation of a Constitution. They have much, but bad, metaphysics,—much, but bad, geometry,—much, but false, proportionate arithmetic; but if it were all as exact as metaphysics, geometry, and arithmetic ought to be, and if their schemes were perfectly consistent in all their parts, it would make only a more fair and sightly vision. It is remarkable, that, in a great arrangement of mankind, not one reference whatsoever is to be found to anything moral or anything politic,—nothing that relates to the concerns, the actions, the passions, the interests of men. Hominem non sapiunt.

I'm afraid I've gotten too deep into how they think about creating a Constitution. They have a lot of ideas, but they're not good—lots of poor metaphysics, flawed geometry, and incorrect arithmetic. Even if it were all as precise as metaphysics, geometry, and arithmetic should be, and if their plans were completely consistent in every part, it would just create a more visually appealing picture. It's striking that in such a large arrangement of people, there’s no reference at all to anything moral or political—nothing about the concerns, actions, passions, or interests of people. Hominem non sapiunt.

You see I only consider this Constitution as electoral, and leading by steps to the National Assembly. I do not enter into the internal government of the departments, and their genealogy through the communes and cantons. These local governments are, in the original plan, to be as nearly as possible composed in the same manner and on the same principles with the elective assemblies. They are each of them bodies perfectly compact and rounded in themselves.

You see, I only view this Constitution as a way to elect representatives and lead us to the National Assembly. I’m not getting into the internal workings of the departments and their connections through the municipalities and districts. These local governments are meant to be formed as closely as possible in the same way and based on the same principles as the elected assemblies. Each of them is a complete and unified entity on its own.

You cannot but perceive in this scheme, that it has a direct and immediate tendency to sever France into a variety of republics, and to render them totally independent of each other, without any direct constitutional means of coherence, connection, or subordination, except what may be derived from their acquiescence in the determinations of the general congress of the ambassadors from each independent republic. Such in reality is the National Assembly; and such governments, I admit, do exist in the world, though, in forms infinitely more suitable to the local and habitual circumstances of their people. But such associations, rather than bodies politic, have generally been the effect of necessity, not choice; and I believe the present French power is the very first body of citizens who, having obtained full authority to do with their country what they pleased, have chosen to dissever it in this barbarous manner.

You can’t help but see in this plan that it aims to split France into multiple republics, making them completely independent from one another, with no real constitutional way to stay connected or subordinate, except for whatever agreement they might reach through the general congress of ambassadors from each independent republic. That’s basically what the National Assembly is; I acknowledge that such governments do exist in the world, but often in forms that are much better suited to the local and habitual needs of their people. However, these kinds of associations, more than true political bodies, have usually come about from necessity rather than choice. I believe the current French government is the first group of citizens who, having gained full power to manage their country as they wish, have chosen to split it apart in this brutal way.

It is impossible not to observe, that, in the spirit of this geometrical distribution and arithmetical arrangement, these pretended citizens treat France exactly like a country of conquest. Acting as conquerors, they have imitated the policy of the harshest of that harsh race. The policy of such barbarous victors, who contemn a subdued people, and insult their feelings, has ever been, as much as in them lay, to destroy all vestiges of the ancient country, in religion, in polity, in laws, and in manners; to confound all territorial limits; to produce a general poverty; to put up their properties to auction; to crush their princes, nobles, and pontiffs; to lay low everything which had lifted its head above the level, or which could serve to combine or rally, in their distresses, the disbanded people, under the standard of old opinion. They have made France free in the manner in which those sincere friends to the rights of mankind, the Romans, freed Greece, Macedon, and other nations. They destroyed the bonds of their union, under color of providing for the independence of each of their cities.

It's hard not to notice that, in line with this geometric distribution and arithmetic arrangement, these so-called citizens treat France like a conquered land. Acting like conquerors, they've adopted the tactics of the harshest members of that brutal race. The approach of these barbaric victors, who look down on a subdued people and mock their feelings, has always been to wipe out any trace of the ancient country—in religion, government, laws, and customs. They aim to erase all territorial boundaries, create widespread poverty, auction off their properties, and dismantle their princes, nobles, and religious leaders. They seek to bring down anything that stands out or could help unite the scattered people under the banner of past beliefs. They’ve made France “free” just like those genuine advocates for human rights, the Romans, freed Greece, Macedon, and other nations by breaking the ties that held them together, all while claiming to ensure each city’s independence.

When the members who compose these new bodies of cantons, communes, and departments, arrangements purposely produced through the medium of confusion, begin to act, they will find themselves in a great measure strangers to one another. The electors and elected throughout, especially in the rural cantons, will be frequently without any civil habitudes or connections, or any of that natural discipline which is the soul of a true republic. Magistrates and collectors of revenue are now no longer acquainted with their districts, bishops with their dioceses, or curates with their parishes. These new colonies of the rights of men bear a strong resemblance to that sort of military colonies which Tacitus has observed upon in the declining policy of Rome. In better and wiser days (whatever course they took with foreign nations) they were careful to make the elements of a methodical subordination and settlement to be coeval, and even to lay the foundations of discipline in the military.[122] But when all the good arts had fallen into ruin, they proceeded, as your Assembly does, upon the equality of men, and with as little judgment, and as little care for those things which make a republic tolerable or durable. But in this, as well as almost every instance, your new commonwealth is born and bred and fed in those corruptions which mark degenerated and worn-out republics. Your child comes into the world with the symptoms of death; the facies Hippocratica forms the character of its physiognomy and the prognostic of its fate.

When the members of these new groups of cantons, communes, and departments, created intentionally through confusion, start to take action, they'll find they're mostly strangers to one another. The voters and those elected, especially in the rural cantons, often lack any social habits or connections, or that natural discipline which is essential for a true republic. Magistrates and tax collectors are no longer familiar with their districts, bishops with their dioceses, or curates with their parishes. These new colonies of human rights closely resemble the kind of military colonies that Tacitus noted in the declining era of Rome. In better and wiser times (regardless of how they dealt with foreign nations), they took care to establish elements of organized hierarchy and settlement simultaneously and even laid the groundwork for discipline in the military.[122] But when all the good practices fell apart, they acted, like your Assembly does, based on the equality of men, with as little judgment and concern for the things that make a republic sustainable or enduring. In this, as in almost every case, your new commonwealth is born, raised, and sustained in the corruptions that characterize decayed and worn-out republics. Your child enters the world showing signs of death; the facies Hippocratica shapes its appearance and signals its fate.

The legislators who framed the ancient republics knew that their business was too arduous to be accomplished with no better apparatus than the metaphysics of an undergraduate and the mathematics and arithmetic of an exciseman. They had to do with men, and they were obliged to study human nature. They had to do with citizens, and they were obliged to study the effects of those habits which are communicated by the circumstances of civil life. They were sensible that the operation of this second nature on the first produced a new combination,—and thence arose many diversities amongst men, according to their birth, their education, their professions, the periods of their lives, their residence in towns or in the country, their several ways of acquiring and of fixing property, and according to the quality of the property itself, all which rendered them, as it were, so many different species of animals. From hence they thought themselves obliged to dispose their citizens into such classes, and to place them in such situations in the state, as their peculiar habits might qualify them to fill, and to allot to them such appropriated privileges as might secure to them what their specific occasions required, and which might furnish to each description such force as might protect it in the conflict caused by the diversity of interests that must exist, and must contend, in all complex society: for the legislator would have been ashamed that the coarse husbandman should well know how to assort and to use his sheep, horses, and oxen, and should have enough of common sense not to abstract and equalize them all into animals, without providing for each kind an appropriate food, care, and employment,—whilst he, the economist, disposer, and shepherd of his own kindred, subliming himself into an airy metaphysician, was resolved to know nothing of his flocks but as men in general. It is for this reason that Montesquieu observed, very justly, that, in their classification of the citizens, the great legislators of antiquity made the greatest display of their powers, and even soared above themselves. It is here that your modern legislators have gone deep into the negative series, and sunk even below their own nothing. As the first sort of legislators attended to the different kinds of citizens, and combined them into one commonwealth, the others, the metaphysical and alchemistical legislators, have taken the directly contrary course. They have attempted to confound all sorts of citizens, as well as they could, into one homogeneous mass; and then they divided this their amalgama into a number of incoherent republics. They reduce men to loose counters, merely for the sake of simple telling, and not to figures, whose power is to arise from their place in the table. The elements of their own metaphysics might have taught them better lessons. The troll of their categorical table might have informed them that there was something else in the intellectual world besides substance and quantity. They might learn from the catechism of metaphysics that there were eight heads more,[123] in every complex deliberation, which they have never thought of; though these, of all the ten, are the subject on which the skill of man can operate anything at all.

The lawmakers who created the ancient republics understood that their task was too challenging to be tackled with nothing more than the philosophy of a college student and the math skills of a tax collector. They were dealing with people and had to study human nature. They were working with citizens and needed to understand the impact of the habits shaped by civil life. They realized that this second nature interacting with the first created new combinations, leading to many differences among people based on their birth, education, professions, life stages, living in cities or rural areas, their methods of acquiring and securing property, and the characteristics of the property itself, making them, in essence, so many different types of beings. Thus, they felt compelled to organize their citizens into classes and place them in roles within the state that their unique habits would allow them to fulfill, assigning specific privileges to ensure they had what they needed, while also providing each group with enough strength to protect themselves in the conflicts arising from the diverse interests present in any complex society. It would be embarrassing for the legislator to know that a simple farmer could skillfully categorize and manage his sheep, horses, and oxen, and have enough common sense not to treat them all the same, providing each kind with appropriate food, care, and tasks, while he, the economist, planner, and caretaker of his own people, loftily decided to regard them merely as humans in generalized terms. This is why Montesquieu rightly noted that in classifying citizens, the great lawmakers of antiquity showcased their abilities and even exceeded expectations. In contrast, contemporary lawmakers have dug deep into negativity, sinking even below their own minimalism. While the first group of lawmakers focused on the different types of citizens and unified them into a commonwealth, the latter, the metaphysical and alchemical legislators, have taken the opposite approach. They have tried to merge all types of citizens into one homogeneous mass, and then split this mix into several disconnected republics. They reduce people to mere numbers for the sake of counting, rather than recognizing them as entities whose power stems from their position within a system. Their own metaphysical principles might have taught them better. The framework of their categorical structure might have shown them that there are more elements in the intellectual realm than just substance and quantity. They could learn from the basics of metaphysics that there are eight additional components, in every complex decision-making process, which they have completely overlooked, even though these, of all ten, are the subjects where human skill can have any impact at all.

So far from this able disposition of some of the old republican legislators, which follows with a solicitous accuracy the moral conditions and propensities of men, they have levelled and crushed together all the orders which they found, even under the coarse, unartificial arrangement of the monarchy, in which mode of government the classing of the citizens is not of so much importance as in a republic. It is true, however, that every such classification, if properly ordered, is good in all forms of government, and composes a strong barrier against the excesses of despotism, as well as it is the necessary means of giving effect and permanence to a republic. For want of something of this kind, if the present project of a republic should fail, all securities to a moderated freedom fail along with it, all the indirect restraints which mitigate despotism are removed; insomuch that, if monarchy should ever again obtain an entire ascendency in France, under this or any other dynasty, it will probably be, if not voluntarily tempered, at setting out, by the wise and virtuous counsels of the prince, the most completely arbitrary power that has ever appeared on earth. This is to play a most desperate game.

So far from the careful approach of some of the old republican lawmakers, who accurately consider the moral conditions and tendencies of people, they have leveled and crushed together all the social classes they found, even under the rough and basic structure of the monarchy, where the classification of citizens isn’t as crucial as it is in a republic. However, it is true that any proper classification is beneficial in all forms of government and serves as a strong barrier against the excesses of tyranny, as well as being essential for ensuring the effectiveness and longevity of a republic. Without something like this, if the current republican project fails, all safeguards for moderate freedom will vanish alongside it, and all the indirect checks that lessen tyranny will be gone; so much so that, if monarchy were to regain complete control in France, whether under this dynasty or another, it would likely emerge, unless voluntarily moderated by the wise and virtuous guidance of the ruler, as the most arbitrary power ever seen on earth. This is playing a very risky game.

The confusion which attends on all such proceedings they even declare to be one of their objects, and they hope to secure their Constitution by a terror of a return of those evils which attended their making it. "By this," say they, "its destruction will become difficult to authority, which cannot break it up without the entire disorganization of the whole state." They presume, that, if this authority should ever come to the same degree of power that they have acquired, it would make a more moderate and chastised use of it, and would piously tremble entirely to disorganize the state in the savage manner that they have done. They expect from the virtues of returning despotism the security which is to be enjoyed by the offspring of their popular vices.

The confusion that comes with all these actions is something they even say is one of their goals, and they hope to protect their Constitution by instilling fear of a return to the problems that arose when it was created. "Because of this," they argue, "it will become hard for authority to destroy it, as they cannot dismantle it without completely destabilizing the entire state." They believe that if this authority ever gains the same level of power they have, it would use that power more moderately and carefully, and would fearfully avoid disrupting the state in the brutal way they have done. They expect to gain security from the qualities of returning tyranny, which they think will be enjoyed by the products of their popular wrongs.

I wish, Sir, that you and my readers would give an attentive perusal to the work of M. de Calonne on this subject. It is, indeed, not only an eloquent, but an able and instructive performance. I confine myself to what he says relative to the Constitution of the new state, and to the condition of the revenue. As to the disputes of this minister with his rivals, I do not wish to pronounce upon them. As little do I mean to hazard any opinion concerning his ways and means, financial or political, for taking his country out of its present disgraceful and deplorable situation of servitude, anarchy, bankruptcy, and beggary. I cannot speculate quite so sanguinely as he does: but he is a Frenchman, and has a closer duty relative to those objects, and better means of judging of them, than I can have. I wish that the formal avowal which he refers to, made by one of the principal leaders in the Assembly, concerning the tendency of their scheme to bring France not only from a monarchy to a republic, but from a republic to a mere confederacy, may be very particularly attended to. It adds new force to my observations: and, indeed, M. de Calonne's work supplies my deficiencies by many new and striking arguments on most of the subjects of this letter.[124]

I wish, Sir, that you and my readers would take a careful look at M. de Calonne's work on this topic. It is not only eloquent but also insightful and informative. I will focus on what he says about the Constitution of the new state and the state of the revenue. I'm not going to comment on the disputes between this minister and his opponents, nor do I intend to express any views on his financial or political strategies for pulling his country out of its current shameful and miserable situation of oppression, chaos, bankruptcy, and poverty. I'm not as optimistic as he is, but he is French and has a closer responsibility regarding these issues and better insight into them than I do. I hope that the official acknowledgment he mentions, made by one of the main leaders in the Assembly about their plan leading France not just from a monarchy to a republic but from a republic to a mere confederation, is given special attention. It reinforces my points: and indeed, M. de Calonne's work fills my gaps with many new and compelling arguments on most topics in this letter.[124]

It is this resolution to break their country into separate republics which has driven them into the greatest number of their difficulties and contradictions. If it were not for this, all the questions of exact equality, and these balances, never to be settled, of individual rights, population, and contribution, would be wholly useless. The representation, though derived from parts, would be a duty which equally regarded the whole. Each deputy to the Assembly would be the representative of France, and of all its descriptions, of the many and of the few, of the rich and of the poor, of the great districts and of the small. All these districts would themselves be subordinate to some standing authority, existing independently of them,—an authority in which their representation, and everything that belongs to it, originated, and to which it was pointed. This standing, unalterable, fundamental government would make, and it is the only thing which could make, that territory truly and properly a whole. With us, when we elect popular representatives, we send them to a council in which each man individually is a subject, and submitted to a government complete in all its ordinary functions. With you the elective Assembly is the sovereign, and the sole sovereign; all the members are therefore integral parts of this sole sovereignty. But with us it is totally different. With us the representative, separated from the other parts, can have no action and no existence. The government is the point of reference of the several members and districts of our representation. This is the centre of our unity. This government of reference is a trustee for the whole, and not for the parts. So is the other branch of our public council: I mean the House of Lords. With us the King and the Lords are several and joint securities for the equality of each district, each province, each city. When did you hear in Great Britain of any province suffering from the inequality of its representation? what district from having no representation at all? Not only our monarchy and our peerage secure the equality on which our unity depends, but it is the spirit of the House of Commons itself. The very inequality of representation, which is so foolishly complained of, is perhaps the very thing which prevents us from thinking or acting as members for districts. Cornwall elects as many members as all Scotland. But is Cornwall better taken care of than Scotland? Few trouble their heads about any of your bases, out of some giddy clubs. Most of those who wish for any change, upon any plausible grounds, desire it on different ideas.

It’s this decision to split their country into separate republics that has led to the majority of their challenges and contradictions. Without this, all the debates about exact equality, and the never-ending balances of individual rights, population, and contributions, would be entirely pointless. The representation, although originating from different parts, would serve a duty that concerns the whole nation. Each representative in the Assembly would be an ambassador for France, representing everyone—the many and the few, the rich and the poor, the large regions and the small ones. All these areas would be subject to a consistent authority that exists independently of them—an authority from which their representation and everything tied to it originated, and to which it is directed. This stable, unchanging, fundamental government would create, and it’s the only thing that could create, a truly unified territory. When we elect representatives, we send them to a council where each person is an individual subject under a government that operates fully in its usual capacities. In your case, the elected Assembly is the supreme authority, and the only authority; therefore, all members are essential parts of this sole sovereignty. But for us, it’s entirely different. Here, the representative, separated from the other parts, cannot act or exist on their own. The government serves as the point of reference for the various members and districts of our representation. This is the core of our unity. This reference government acts as a trustee for the whole, not for the individual parts. The same goes for the other branch of our public council: I mean the House of Lords. Here, the King and the Lords are both separate and joint guarantors of equality for each district, province, and city. When have you ever heard in Great Britain of a province suffering from unequal representation? Or a district lacking any representation at all? Not only do our monarchy and peerage ensure the equality that maintains our unity, but it’s also the core spirit of the House of Commons. The very inequality of representation, which is so mindlessly criticized, may actually be what prevents us from thinking or acting solely on behalf of specific districts. Cornwall elects as many members as all of Scotland combined. But is Cornwall better represented than Scotland? Few people concern themselves with your arguments from some reckless clubs. Most who seek change for any reason have different ideas in mind.

Your new Constitution is the very reverse of ours in its principle; and I am astonished how any persons could dream of holding out anything done in it as an example for Great Britain. With you there is little, or rather no, connection between the last representative and the first constituent. The member who goes to the National Assembly is not chosen by the people, nor accountable to them. There are three elections before he is chosen; two sets of magistracy intervene between him and the primary assembly, so as to render him, as I have said, an ambassador of a state, and not the representative of the people within a state. By this the whole spirit of the election is changed; nor can any corrective your Constitution-mongers have devised render him anything else than what he is. The very attempt to do it would inevitably introduce a confusion, if possible, more horrid than the present. There is no way to make a connection between the original constituent and the representative, but by the circuitous means which may lead the candidate to apply in the first instance to the primary electors, in order that by their authoritative instructions (and something more perhaps) these primary electors may force the two succeeding bodies of electors to make a choice agreeable to their wishes. But this would plainly subvert the whole scheme. It would be to plunge them back into that tumult and confusion of popular election, which, by their interposed gradation of elections, they mean to avoid, and at length to risk the whole fortune of the state with those who have the least knowledge of it and the least interest in it. This is a perpetual dilemma, into which they are thrown by the vicious, weak, and contradictory principles they have chosen. Unless the people break up and level this gradation, it is plain that they do not at all substantially elect to the Assembly; indeed, they elect as little in appearance as reality.

Your new Constitution is completely different from ours in principle, and I’m amazed that anyone could think anything done under it could serve as a model for Great Britain. In your system, there’s little, or rather no, connection between the last representative and the first voter. The member who goes to the National Assembly isn’t chosen by the people nor accountable to them. There are three elections before he gets chosen; two sets of officials come between him and the primary assembly, making him, as I said, an ambassador of a state rather than the representative of the people within that state. This changes the entire spirit of the election, and no correction your Constitution-makers devise can transform him into anything else. Even trying to do so would likely create a confusion more terrible than what exists now. There is no way to connect the original voters to the representative except through these indirect methods that might lead the candidate to first appeal to the primary voters, so that with their authoritative instructions (and maybe something more), these primary voters might pressure the two subsequent groups of electors to make a choice that matches their wishes. But this would clearly undermine the entire system. It would throw them back into the chaos and confusion of popular elections, which, by having multiple layers of elections, they aim to avoid—ultimately risking the entire fate of the state with those who have the least knowledge of it and the least interest in it. This is a constant dilemma caused by the flawed, weak, and contradictory principles they’ve chosen. Unless the people dismantle and level this hierarchy, it’s clear they aren’t truly electing to the Assembly; in fact, they have as little say in appearance as in reality.

What is it we all seek for in an election? To answer its real purposes, you must first possess the means of knowing the fitness of your man; and then you must retain some hold upon him by personal obligation or dependence. For what end are these primary electors complimented, or rather mocked, with a choice? They can never know anything of the qualities of him that is to serve them, nor has he any obligation whatsoever to them. Of all the powers unfit to be delegated by those who have any real means of judging, that most peculiarly unfit is what relates to a personal choice. In case of abuse, that body of primary electors never can call the representative to an account for his conduct. He is too far removed from them in the chain of representation. If he acts improperly at the end of his two years' lease, it does not concern him for two years more. By the new French Constitution the best and the wisest representatives go equally with the worst into this Limbus Patrum. Their bottoms are supposed foul, and they must go into dock to be refitted. Every man who has served in an Assembly is ineligible for two years after. Just as these magistrates begin to learn their trade, like chimney-sweepers, they are disqualified for exercising it. Superficial, new, petulant acquisition, and interrupted, dronish, broken, ill recollection, is to be the destined character of all your future governors. Your Constitution has too much of jealousy to have much of sense in it. You consider the breach of trust in the representative so principally that you do not at all regard the question of his fitness to execute it.

What do we all want in an election? To understand its true purposes, you first need to know how to evaluate the suitability of your candidate; then, you must have some connection to him through personal obligation or dependence. Why are these primary voters given a choice, only to be disillusioned? They can never know the qualities of the person meant to serve them, and that person has no real obligation to them. Of all the powers that should not be handed over by those who have any real means of judgment, the ability to make a personal choice is especially unfit. In case of misconduct, those primary voters can never hold the representative accountable for his actions. He is too far removed from them in the representation chain. If he behaves poorly at the end of his two-year term, it won’t affect him for another two years. According to the new French Constitution, the best and the brightest representatives are treated the same as the worst, as if they all belong in Limbus Patrum. They are presumed to have failed and must go into a sort of timeout to be “refitted.” Anyone who has served in an Assembly can’t run for two years afterward. Just as these officials start to learn their jobs, like chimney sweeps, they are disqualified from continuing in their roles. What you'll get is a group of your future leaders who have superficial knowledge, are easily distracted, have broken and poor recollections. Your Constitution is too focused on jealousy to have much sense. You emphasize the breach of trust by the representative so much that you overlook whether he is actually fit to fulfill his duties.

This purgatory interval is not unfavorable to a faithless representative, who may be as good a canvasser as he was a bad governor. In this time he may cabal himself into a superiority over the wisest and most virtuous. As, in the end, all the members of this elective Constitution are equally fugitive, and exist only for the election, they may be no longer the same persons who had chosen him, to whom he is to be responsible when he solicits for a renewal of his trust. To call all the secondary electors of the commune to account is ridiculous, impracticable, and unjust: they may themselves have been deceived in their choice, as the third set of electors, those of the department, may be in theirs. In your elections responsibility cannot exist.

This waiting period isn’t a bad situation for a representative who lacks faith, and he might be just as effective at campaigning as he was ineffective as a governor. During this time, he could maneuver his way into thinking he’s superior to the smartest and most virtuous people. Since, in the end, all members of this elected body are temporary and exist only for the election, they might not even be the same people who chose him, and he will be accountable to those who he seeks to convince to renew his position. Holding all the secondary voters of the commune accountable is silly, impractical, and unfair: they could have been misled in their choice, just like the third group of voters, those of the department, could have been in theirs. In your elections, accountability simply doesn’t exist.

Finding no sort of principle of coherence with each other in the nature and constitution of the several new republics of France, I considered what cement the legislators had provided for them from any extraneous materials. Their confederations, their spectacles, their civic feasts, and their enthusiasm I take no notice of; they are nothing but mere tricks; but tracing their policy through their actions, I think I can distinguish the arrangements by which they propose to hold these republics together. The first is the confiscation, with the compulsory paper currency annexed to it; the second is the supreme power of the city of Paris; the third is the general army of the state. Of this last I shall reserve what I have to say, until I come to consider the army as an head by itself.

Finding no real principle of coherence among the various new republics of France, I thought about what external forces the lawmakers had used to hold them together. Their alliances, their spectacles, their civic celebrations, and their enthusiasm don’t interest me; they’re just superficial tricks. However, by analyzing their policies through their actions, I believe I can identify the strategies they intend to use to keep these republics unified. The first is the confiscation, along with the mandatory paper currency associated with it; the second is the supreme authority of the city of Paris; the third is the national army. I'll save what I have to say about the army for when I discuss it as a separate topic.

As to the operation of the first (the confiscation and paper currency) merely as a cement, I cannot deny that these, the one depending on the other, may for some time compose some sort of cement, if their madness and folly in the management, and in the tempering of the parts together, does not produce a repulsion in the very outset. But allowing to the scheme some coherence and some duration, it appears to me, that, if, after a while, the confiscation should not be found sufficient to support the paper coinage, (as I am morally certain it will not,) then, instead of cementing, it will add infinitely to the dissociation, distraction, and confusion of these confederate republics, both with relation to each other and to the several parts within themselves. But if the confiscation should so far succeed as to sink the paper currency, the cement is gone with the circulation. In the mean time its binding force will be very uncertain, and it will straiten or relax with every variation in the credit of the paper.

Regarding the first operation (the confiscation and paper currency) simply as a unifying force, I can't deny that these two, relying on each other, might for a while act as a kind of glue, unless their madness and foolishness in managing and combining the elements leads to immediate rejection. However, if the plan has some degree of coherence and lasts a bit, I believe that if, over time, the confiscation fails to adequately support the paper currency (which I'm pretty sure it will), instead of uniting, it will only increase the division, distraction, and chaos among these united republics, both in their relations to one another and within their individual parts. But if the confiscation were to succeed enough to devalue the paper currency, the glue will disappear along with the currency's circulation. In the meantime, its ability to hold together will be very unpredictable, tightening or loosening with every fluctuation in the currency's credit.

One thing only is certain in this scheme, which is an effect seemingly collateral, but direct, I have no doubt, in the minds of those who conduct this business; that is, its effect in producing an oligarchy in every one of the republics. A paper circulation, not founded on any real money deposited or engaged for, amounting already to four-and-forty millions of English money, and this currency by force substituted in the place of the coin of the kingdom, becoming thereby the substance of its revenue, as well as the medium of all its commercial and civil intercourse, must put the whole of what power, authority, and influence is left, in any form whatsoever it may assume, into the hands of the managers and conductors of this circulation.

One thing is clear in this plan, which has a seemingly indirect but definitely direct effect, I believe, on the people running this operation; that is, it leads to an oligarchy in all of the republics. A paper currency, not backed by any real money held or pledged, amounting to forty-four million pounds, and this currency forcibly replacing the kingdom's coin, thereby becoming its revenue as well as the means for all commercial and social transactions, must concentrate the remaining power, authority, and influence in any form it may take, into the hands of those managing and overseeing this currency.

In England we feel the influence of the Bank, though it is only the centre of a voluntary dealing. He knows little, indeed, of the influence of money upon mankind, who does not see the force of the management of a moneyed concern which is so much more extensive, and in its nature so much more depending on the managers, than any of ours. But this is not merely a money concern. There is another member in the system inseparably connected with this money management. It consists in the means of drawing out at discretion portions of the confiscated lands for sale, and carrying on a process of continual transmutation of paper into land and land into paper. When we follow this process in its effects, we may conceive something of the intensity of the force with which this system must operate. By this means the spirit of money-jobbing and speculation goes into the mass of land itself, and incorporates with it. By this kind of operation, that species of property becomes, as it were, volatilized; it assumes an unnatural and monstrous activity, and thereby throws into the hands of the several managers, principal and subordinate, Parisian and provincial, all the representative of money, and perhaps a full tenth part of all the land in France, which has now acquired the worst and most pernicious part of the evil of a paper circulation, the greatest possible uncertainty in its value. They have reversed the Latonian kindness to the landed property of Delos. They have sent theirs to be blown about, like the light fragments of a wreck, oras et littora circum.

In England, we feel the impact of the Bank, even though it’s just the center of voluntary transactions. Anyone who doesn’t recognize how money influences people doesn't understand the extensive reach of managing a financial enterprise, which is far broader and more reliant on its managers than anything we have. But this isn't just about money. There's another component in the system that’s inextricably linked to this financial management. It involves the ability to selectively sell portions of confiscated land, leading to a constant cycle of turning paper into land and land into paper. When we observe the effects of this process, we can get a sense of the intense power this system wields. This way, the mentality of money trading and speculation seeps into the land itself and becomes part of it. Through this kind of operation, property seems to become almost gaseous; it takes on an unnatural, chaotic energy, putting all the money’s representatives—both major and minor, urban and rural—into the hands of a few, commanding perhaps a full tenth of all the land in France. This land has now taken on the worst aspects of a paper currency system, marked by extreme uncertainty in its value. They’ve distorted the kind-hearted treatment of the land in Delos, sending theirs adrift like scattered debris from a shipwreck, oras et littora circum.

The new dealers, being all habitually adventurers, and without any fixed habits or local predilections, will purchase to job out again, as the market of paper or of money or of land shall present an advantage. For though a holy bishop thinks that agriculture will derive great advantages from the "enlightened" usurers who are to purchase the Church confiscations, I, who am not a good, but an old farmer, with great humility beg leave to tell his late Lordship that usury is not a tutor of agriculture; and if the word "enlightened" be understood according to the new dictionary, as it always is in your new schools, I cannot conceive how a man's not believing in God can teach him to cultivate the earth with the least of any additional skill or encouragement. "Diis immortalibus sero," said an old Roman, when he held one handle of the plough, whilst Death held the other. Though you were to join in the commission all the directors of the two Academies to the directors of the Caisse d'Escompte, an old experienced peasant is worth them all. I have got more information upon a curious and interesting branch of husbandry, in one short conversation with an old Carthusian monk, than I have derived from all the bank directors that I have ever conversed with. However, there is no cause for apprehension from the meddling of money-dealers with rural economy. These gentlemen are too wise in their generation. At first, perhaps, their tender and susceptible imaginations may be captivated with the innocent and unprofitable delights of a pastoral life; but in a little time they will find that agriculture is a trade much more laborious and much less lucrative than that which they had left. After making its panegyric, they will turn their backs on it, like their great precursor and prototype. They may, like him, begin by singing, "Beatus ille"—but what will be the end?

The new dealers, being habitual adventurers with no fixed routines or local preferences, will buy to resell again when the market for paper, money, or land offers an advantage. Although a holy bishop believes that agriculture will greatly benefit from the "enlightened" usurers who will buy the Church's confiscated wealth, I, who may not be a good farmer but am an experienced one, humbly ask his Lordship to consider that usury is not a teacher of agriculture. If the term "enlightened" is understood according to the modern definitions used in today's schools, I can't see how someone who doesn't believe in God can effectively cultivate the land with any added skill or support. "Diis immortalibus sero," said an ancient Roman, as he held one handle of the plow while Death held the other. Even if you appointed all the directors from both Academies to work with the directors of the Caisse d'Escompte, an experienced old farmer is worth more than all of them combined. I've gained more knowledge about an intriguing aspect of farming in one brief conversation with an old Carthusian monk than I've ever gotten from all the bank directors I've spoken with. Nonetheless, there's no reason to worry about money dealers interfering with agriculture. These gentlemen are too clever for that. Initially, their sensitive imaginations might be charmed by the simple and unprofitable joys of pastoral life, but soon enough they will realize that farming is a much tougher and less profitable business than what they left behind. After praising it, they will turn away from it, just like their great predecessor and model. They might start by singing, "Beatus ille"—but what will be the outcome?

Hæc ubi locutus lender Alphius,
Jam jam future country, Reallocated money in Idus,
Asks to set for the Calends.

They will cultivate the Caisse d'Église, under the sacred auspices of this prelate, with much more profit than its vineyards and its corn-fields. They will employ their talents according to their habits and their interests. They will not follow the plough, whilst they can direct treasuries and govern provinces.

They will develop the Caisse d'Église under the respected guidance of this bishop, gaining much more from it than from their vineyards and grain fields. They will use their skills based on their customs and interests. They won't be farming when they can manage finances and govern regions.

Your legislators, in everything new, are the very first who have founded a commonwealth upon gaming, and infused this spirit into it as its vital breath. The great object in these politics is to metamorphose France from a great kingdom into one great play-table,—to turn its inhabitants into a nation of gamesters,—to make speculation as extensive as life,—to mix it with all its concerns,—and to divert the whole of the hopes and fears of the people from their usual channels into the impulses, passions, and superstitions of those who live on chances. They loudly proclaim their opinion, that this their present system of a republic cannot possibly exist without this kind of gaming fund, and that the very thread of its life is spun out of the staple of these speculations. The old gaming in funds was mischievous enough, undoubtedly; but it was so only to individuals. Even when it had its greatest extent, in the Mississippi and South Sea, it affected but few, comparatively; where it extends further, as in lotteries, the spirit has but a single object. But where the law, which in most circumstances forbids, and in none countenances gaming, is itself debauched, so as to reverse its nature and policy, and expressly to force the subject to this destructive table, by bringing the spirit and symbols of gaming into the minutest matters, and engaging everybody in it, and in everything, a more dreadful epidemic distemper of that kind is spread than yet has appeared in the world. With you a man can neither earn nor buy his dinner without a speculation. What he receives in the morning will not have the same value at night. What he is compelled to take as pay for an old debt will not be received as the same, when he comes to pay a debt contracted by himself; nor will it be the same, when by prompt payment he would avoid contracting any debt at all. Industry must wither away. Economy must be driven from your country. Careful provision will have no existence. Who will labor without knowing the amount of his pay? Who will study to increase what none can estimate? Who will accumulate, when he does not know the value of what he saves? If you abstract it from its uses in gaming, to accumulate your paper wealth would be, not the providence of a man, but the distempered instinct of a jackdaw.

Your lawmakers are the first to build a society based on gambling, making it the essence of their system. The main goal of this political game is to transform France from a powerful kingdom into one giant gambling table—to turn its people into a nation of gamblers—to make speculation as widespread as life itself—to integrate it with all aspects of life—and to redirect all the hopes and fears of the public into the whims, passions, and superstitions of those who thrive on chance. They loudly assert that their current republican system cannot survive without this gambling fund and that its very existence depends on these speculations. The old gambling practices were certainly harmful, but mostly just to individuals. Even at its peak, like during the Mississippi and South Sea bubbles, it affected relatively few people; where it spread further, like with lotteries, it primarily had a singular focus. However, when the law, which typically forbids gambling and never endorses it, gets corrupted enough to turn against its own purpose and actively pushes people toward this harmful gamble, bringing the essence and signs of gambling into even the smallest transactions and involving everyone in it, a more terrifying outbreak of this issue spreads than has ever been seen before. In your world, a man can neither earn nor buy his meal without speculation. What he gets in the morning won’t hold the same value by evening. What he must accept as payment for an old debt won’t be considered equal when he goes to settle a debt he incurred himself; nor will it be the same when making an immediate payment to avoid getting into debt at all. Hard work will fade away. Savings will vanish from your nation. Thoughtful planning will cease to exist. Who will work without knowing how much they'll be paid? Who will strive to increase what nobody can evaluate? Who will save when they don’t know the worth of what they’re saving? If you remove the gambling aspect from it, amassing your paper wealth becomes not the foresight of a man, but the reckless instinct of a magpie.

The truly melancholy part of the policy of systematically making a nation of gamesters is this,—that, though all are forced to play, few can understand the game, and fewer still are in a condition to avail themselves of that knowledge. The many must be the dupes of the few who conduct the machine of these speculations. What effect it must have on the country-people is visible. The townsman can calculate from day to day; not so the inhabitant of the country. When the peasant first brings his corn to market, the magistrate in the towns obliges him to take the assignat at par; when he goes to the shop with this money, he finds it seven per cent the worse for crossing the way. This market he will not readily resort to again. The towns-people will be inflamed; they will force the country-people to bring their corn. Resistance will begin, and the murders of Paris and St. Denis may be renewed through all France.

The really sad part of the policy that turns everyone into gamblers is this: while everyone is forced to play, very few can actually understand the game, and even fewer are able to benefit from that knowledge. Most people will just be taken advantage of by the few who run these speculative schemes. The impact on rural communities is clear. City dwellers can keep track of things day by day; the same isn't true for those in the countryside. When a farmer first takes his grain to market, the town officials make him accept the assignat at its face value; but when he goes to the store with that money, he finds it is worth seven percent less just for crossing the street. He won’t want to come back to that market again. The city folks will get worked up; they’ll pressure the farmers to bring their grain. Resistance will start, and the violence seen in Paris and St. Denis could reignite all across France.

What signifies the empty compliment paid to the country, by giving it, perhaps, more than its share in the theory of your representation? Where have you placed the real power over moneyed and landed circulation? Where have you placed the means of raising and falling the value of every man's freehold? Those whose operations can take from or add ten per cent to the possessions of every man in France must be the masters of every man in France. The whole of the power obtained by this Revolution will settle in the towns among the burghers, and the moneyed directors who lead them. The landed gentleman, the yeoman, and the peasant have, none of them, habits or inclinations or experience which can lead them to any share in this the sole source of power and influence now left in France. The very nature of a country life, the very nature of landed property, in all the occupations and all the pleasures they afford, render combination and arrangement (the sole way of procuring and exerting influence) in a manner impossible amongst country-people. Combine them by all the art you can, and all the industry, they are always dissolving into individuality. Anything in the nature of incorporation is almost impracticable amongst them. Hope, fear, alarm, jealousy, the ephemerous tale that does its business and dies in a day, all these things, which are the reins and spurs by which leaders check or urge the minds of followers, are not easily employed, or hardly at all, amongst scattered people. They assemble, they arm, they act, with the utmost difficulty, and at the greatest charge. Their efforts, if ever they can be commenced, cannot be sustained. They cannot proceed systematically. If the country-gentlemen attempt an influence through the mere income of their property, what is it to that of those who have ten times their income to sell, and who can ruin their property by bringing their plunder to meet it at market? If the landed man wishes to mortgage, he falls the value of his land and raises the value of assignats. He augments the power of his enemy by the very means he must take to contend with him. The country-gentleman, therefore, the officer by sea and land, the man of liberal views and habits, attached to no profession, will be as completely excluded from the government of his country as if he were legislatively proscribed. It is obvious, that, in the towns, all the things which conspire against the country-gentleman combine in favor of the money manager and director. In towns combination is natural. The habits of burghers, their occupations, their diversion, their business, their idleness, continually bring them into mutual contact. Their virtues and their vices are sociable; they are always in garrison; and they come embodied and half-disciplined into the hands of those who mean to form them for civil or military action.

What does it mean to give an empty compliment to the country by perhaps attributing more power in your representation than it deserves? Where have you put the real power over financial and land transactions? Where have you positioned the ability to raise and lower the value of everyone’s property? Those whose actions can impact the possessions of every individual in France by ten percent must be in control of everyone in France. The entire power gained from this Revolution will settle among the towns with the merchants and the financial leaders guiding them. The landowners, farmers, and peasants do not have the habits, interests, or experience to participate in this, the only remaining source of power and influence in France. The nature of rural life and land ownership, along with the activities and pleasures they offer, makes it nearly impossible for country folk to come together and exert influence. No matter how hard you try to rally them, they always dissolve into individuals. Any form of organization is almost unattainable among them. Emotions like hope, fear, anxiety, jealousy, and the fleeting gossip that makes its rounds for a day—these are the tools leaders use to guide their followers but are hard to harness among scattered people. They gather, they arm themselves, and take action with great difficulty and expense. Their efforts, if they can even begin, cannot be maintained. They cannot act in a coordinated way. If the landowners try to gain influence through the income from their properties, how does that compare to those who have ten times more income to sell and can destroy their property by flooding the market with their spoils? If a landowner wants to mortgage, he reduces the value of his land and increases the value of assignats. He strengthens his adversary by the very means he must use to fight back. Thus, the country gentleman, the officer both on land and sea, and the person with progressive views, detached from any profession, will be completely excluded from governing his own country as if he were legally banned. Clearly, in the towns, everything that works against the country gentleman comes together in support of the financial manager and director. In towns, collaboration is instinctive. The routines of merchants, their work, their leisure, their business, and their idleness constantly bring them into contact with one another. Their strengths and weaknesses are social; they are always together, and they come together as a group, somewhat trained, into the hands of those who plan to organize them for civil or military purposes.

All these considerations leave no doubt on my mind, that, if this monster of a Constitution can continue, France will be wholly governed by the agitators in corporations, by societies in the towns, formed of directors in assignats, and trustees for the sale of Church lands, attorneys, agents, money-jobbers, speculators, and adventurers, composing an ignoble oligarchy, founded on the destruction of the crown, the Church, the nobility, and the people. Here end all the deceitful dreams and visions of the equality and rights of men. In "the Serbonian bog" of this base oligarchy they are all absorbed, sunk, and lost forever.

All these thoughts leave no doubt in my mind that if this terrible Constitution continues, France will be completely controlled by the agitators in corporations, by societies in the towns made up of directors with paper money and trustees for selling Church lands, lawyers, agents, money dealers, speculators, and opportunists, forming a disgraceful oligarchy, built on the destruction of the crown, the Church, the nobility, and the people. Here end all the deceptive dreams and visions of equality and human rights. In "the Serbonian bog" of this corrupt oligarchy, they are all absorbed, sunk, and lost forever.

Though human eyes cannot trace them, one would be tempted to think some great offences in France must cry to Heaven, which has thought fit to punish it with a subjection to a vile and inglorious domination, in which no comfort or compensation is to be found in any even of those false splendors which, playing about other tyrannies, prevent mankind from feeling themselves dishonored even whilst they are oppressed. I must confess I am touched with a sorrow mixed with some indignation, at the conduct of a few men, once of great rank, and still of great character, who, deluded with specious names, have engaged in a business too deep for the line of their understanding to fathom,—who have lent their fair reputation and the authority of their high-sounding names to the designs of men with whom they could not be acquainted, and have thereby made their very virtues operate to the ruin of their country.

Though we can't see them, it’s hard not to think that some serious wrongs in France must be calling out for justice, which has chosen to punish it with a shameful and unremarkable rule, where there’s no comfort or reward even in the false glories that surround other tyrannies, keeping people from feeling dishonored while they’re being oppressed. I have to admit I feel a mix of sadness and indignation at the actions of a few men, once of high status and still respected, who, misled by appealing names, have gotten involved in something too complex for them to fully grasp—who have put their good reputation and the weight of their impressive names behind the schemes of people they hardly know, and have thus turned their own virtues into tools for the destruction of their country.

So far as to the first cementing principle.

So far as to the first key principle.

The second material of cement for their new republic is the superiority of the city of Paris; and this, I admit, is strongly connected with the other cementing principle of paper circulation and confiscation. It is in this part of the project we must look for the cause of the destruction of all the old bounds of provinces and jurisdictions, ecclesiastical and secular, and the dissolution of all ancient combinations of things, as well as the formation of so many small unconnected republics. The power of the city of Paris is evidently one great spring of all their politics. It is through the power of Paris, now become the centre and focus of jobbing, that the leaders of this faction direct, or rather command, the whole legislative and the whole executive government. Everything, therefore, must be done which can confirm the authority of that city over the other republics. Paris is compact; she has an enormous strength, wholly disproportioned to the force of any of the square republics; and this strength is collected and condensed within a narrow compass. Paris has a natural and easy connection of its parts, which will not be affected by any scheme of a geometrical constitution; nor does it much signify whether its proportion of representation be more or less, since it has the whole draught of fishes in its drag-net. The other divisions of the kingdom, being hackled and torn to pieces, and separated from all their habitual means and even principles of union, cannot, for some time at least, confederate against her. Nothing was to be left in all the subordinate members, but weakness, disconnection, and confusion. To confirm this part of the plan, the Assembly has lately come to a resolution that no two of their republics shall have the same commander-in-chief.

The second building block of their new republic is the dominance of the city of Paris, which I acknowledge is closely tied to the other uniting principle of paper circulation and confiscation. In this aspect of the project, we have to seek the reason for the destruction of all the old boundaries of provinces and jurisdictions, both church and state, and the breakdown of all ancient alliances, as well as the rise of so many small, disconnected republics. The power of Paris is clearly a major driving force behind their politics. It is through Paris's influence, now established as the center of deal-making, that the leaders of this group control, or rather dominate, the entire legislative and executive government. Therefore, everything possible must be done to reinforce that city's authority over the other republics. Paris is cohesive; it possesses an immense strength that dwarfs the power of any of the smaller republics, and this strength is concentrated within a small area. Paris has a natural and seamless connection among its parts, which won’t be disrupted by any geometrical arrangement; nor does it matter much if its representation is greater or lesser, since it captures all the resources in its net. The other parts of the country, being fragmented and cut off from their usual means and even principles of unity, cannot, at least for the time being, come together to oppose it. Nothing should be left in all the subordinate regions but weakness, disconnection, and chaos. To solidify this part of the plan, the Assembly has recently decided that no two of their republics can have the same commander-in-chief.

To a person who takes a view of the whole, the strength of Paris, thus formed, will appear a system of general weakness. It is boasted that the geometrical policy has been adopted, that all local ideas should be sunk, and that the people should be no longer Gascons, Picards, Bretons, Normans,—but Frenchmen, with one country, one heart, and one Assembly. But, instead of being all Frenchmen, the greater likelihood is that the inhabitants of that region will shortly have no country. No man ever was attached by a sense of pride, partiality, or real affection, to a description of square measurement. He never will glory in belonging to the chequer No. 71, or to any other badge-ticket. We begin our public affections in our families. No cold relation is a zealous citizen. We pass on to our neighborhoods, and our habitual provincial connections. These are inns and resting-places. Such divisions of our country as have been formed by habit, and not by a sudden jerk of authority, were so many little images of the great country, in which the heart found something which it could fill. The love to the whole is not extinguished by this subordinate partiality. Perhaps it is a sort of elemental training to those higher and more large regards by which alone men come to be affected, as with their own concern, in the prosperity of a kingdom so extensive as that of France. In that general territory itself, as in the old name of Provinces, the citizens are interested from old prejudices and unreasoned habits, and not on account of the geometric properties of its figure. The power and preëminence of Paris does certainly press down and hold these republics together as long as it lasts: but, for the reasons I have already given you, I think it can not last very long.

To someone who sees the bigger picture, the strength of Paris, as it stands, looks like a system of overall weakness. People boast about adopting a geometric approach, claiming all local identities should be erased, and that the citizens should no longer be Gascons, Picards, Bretons, or Normans—but just Frenchmen, with one country, one heart, and one Assembly. However, instead of everyone being just French, it’s more likely that the residents of that area will soon have no country at all. No one feels pride, attachment, or genuine affection for a square unit of measurement. No one will take pride in being part of the square No. 71, or any other label. We start our public loyalties with our families. A distant relative doesn’t make a passionate citizen. We then connect with our neighborhoods and the local community we are used to. These are like inns and resting spots. The divisions of our country that have developed through habit, rather than a sudden imposition of authority, are like small mirrors of the larger country, where our hearts find something to relate to. Our love for the whole isn’t dampened by these smaller attachments. Perhaps these smaller connections serve as a foundational training for the broader concerns that allow people to genuinely care for the welfare of a vast nation like France. Within that expansive territory, as indicated by the old names of Provinces, citizens feel connected through longstanding biases and unthinking habits, rather than because of the geometric shape of the land. The power and prominence of Paris certainly holds these republics together as long as it endures; however, for the reasons I've already mentioned, I don’t believe it can last much longer.

Passing from the civil creating and the civil cementing principles of this Constitution to the National Assembly, which is to appear and act as sovereign, we see a body in its constitution with every possible power and no possible external control. We see a body without fundamental laws, without established maxims, without respected rules of proceeding, which nothing can keep firm to any system whatsoever. Their idea of their powers is always taken at the utmost stretch of legislative competency, and their examples for common cases from the exceptions of the most urgent necessity. The future is to be in most respects like the present Assembly; but, by the mode of the new elections and the tendency of the new circulations, it will be purged of the small degree of internal control existing in a minority chosen originally from various interests, and preserving something of their spirit. If possible, the next Assembly must be worse than the present. The present, by destroying and altering everything, will leave to their successors apparently nothing popular to do. They will be roused by emulation and example to enterprises the boldest and the most absurd. To suppose such an Assembly sitting in perfect quietude is ridiculous.

Transitioning from the principles that shape and support this Constitution to the National Assembly, which is supposed to operate as the ultimate authority, we see a group that has every conceivable power and no external checks. This body exists without fundamental laws, established principles, or respected procedures, meaning nothing can anchor it to any consistent system. Their interpretation of their powers is always at the extreme limits of legislative authority, taking their examples from urgent exceptions rather than standard cases. The future will largely resemble the current Assembly, but with the new election process and changing dynamics, it will likely lose even the minimal internal control provided by a diverse minority initially selected from various interests, which retained some original spirit. If anything, the next Assembly will probably be worse than the current one. The present Assembly, by dismantling and changing everything, will leave its successors seemingly with nothing popular to address. They will be inspired by ambition and precedent to pursue the boldest and most outrageous ventures. It’s absurd to imagine such an Assembly remaining completely calm.

Your all-sufficient legislators, in their hurry to do everything at once, have forgot one thing that seems essential, and which, I believe, never has been before, in the theory or the practice, omitted by any projector of a republic. They have forgot to constitute a senate, or something of that nature and character. Never, before this time, was heard of a body politic composed of one legislative and active assembly, and its executive officers, without such a council: without something to which foreign states might connect themselves,—something to which, in the ordinary detail of government, the people could look up,—something which might give a bias and steadiness, and preserve something like consistency in the proceedings of state. Such a body kings generally have as a council. A monarchy may exist without it; but it seems to be in the very essence of a republican government. It holds a sort of middle place between the supreme power exercised by the people, or immediately delegated from them, and the mere executive. Of this there are no traces in your Constitution; and in providing nothing of this kind, your Solons and Numas have, as much as in anything else, discovered a sovereign incapacity.

Your all-powerful lawmakers, in their rush to do everything at once, have overlooked one crucial thing that seems essential and, I believe, has never been omitted before by anyone trying to create a republic. They have forgotten to establish a senate or something similar. Never before has there been a political body made up of a single legislative and active assembly, along with its executive officers, without such a council: without something for foreign nations to associate with—something that, in the day-to-day running of government, the people could look up to—something that could provide guidance and stability, and keep a level of consistency in state proceedings. Monarchs usually have such a council. A monarchy can exist without it; however, it seems to be an essential part of a republican government. It serves as a sort of middle ground between the supreme power exercised by the people, or directly delegated from them, and the mere executive. There are no signs of this in your Constitution; and by not providing anything of this sort, your Solons and Numas have, as much as in anything else, shown a fundamental incapacity.

Let us now turn our eyes to what they have done towards the formation of an executive power. For this they have chosen a degraded king. This their first executive officer is to be a machine, without any sort of deliberative discretion in any one act of his function. At best, he is but a channel to convey to the National Assembly such matter as may import that body to know. If he had been made the exclusive channel, the power would not have been without its importance, though infinitely perilous to those who would choose to exercise it. But public intelligence and statement of facts may pass to the Assembly with equal authenticity through any other conveyance. As to the means, therefore, of giving a direction to measures by the statement of an authorized reporter, this office of intelligence is as nothing.

Let’s look at what they’ve done to create an executive power. They’ve appointed a powerless king. This first executive officer will act like a machine, without any real decision-making ability in any of his duties. At best, he’s just a way to pass along information to the National Assembly that it needs to know. If he were the only way to communicate, it would matter more, even though it would be extremely risky for those who wanted to use that power. However, public information and facts can still reach the Assembly just as effectively through other means. So, when it comes to directing actions based on information from an authorized reporter, this role of relaying information is essentially meaningless.

To consider the French scheme of an executive officer, in its two natural divisions of civil and political.—In the first it must be observed, that, according to the new Constitution, the higher parts of judicature, in either of its lines, are not in the king. The king of France is not the fountain of justice. The judges, neither the original nor the appellate, are of his nomination. He neither proposes the candidates nor has a negative on the choice. He is not even the public prosecutor. He serves only as a notary, to authenticate the choice made of the judges in the several districts. By his officers he is to execute their sentence. When we look into the true nature of his authority, he appears to be nothing more than a chief of bumbailiffs, sergeants-at-mace, catchpoles, jailers, and hangmen. It is impossible to place anything called royalty in a more degrading point of view. A thousand times better it had been for the dignity of this unhappy prince, that he had nothing at all to do with the administration of justice, deprived as he is of all that is venerable and all that is consolatory in that function, without power of originating any process, without a power of suspension, mitigation, or pardon. Everything in justice that is vile and odious is thrown upon him. It was not for nothing that the Assembly has been at such pains to remove the stigma from certain offices, when they were resolved to place the person who had lately been their king in a situation but one degree above the executioner, and in an office nearly of the same quality. It is not in Nature, that, situated as the king of the French now is, he can respect himself or can be respected by others.

To look at the French system of an executive officer, with its two main divisions of civil and political. In the first, it’s important to note that, according to the new Constitution, the highest levels of the judiciary are not connected to the king. The king of France is not the source of justice. The judges, both original and appellate, are not appointed by him. He doesn’t propose candidates or have a say in the selection process. He isn’t even the public prosecutor. His role is merely to sign off on the selection of judges in various districts. He is to carry out their sentences through his officers. When we examine his true authority, he seems to be nothing more than the head of bailiffs, sergeants, catchpoles, jailers, and executioners. It’s impossible to depict any form of royalty in a more humiliating light. It would have been far better for the dignity of this unfortunate prince if he had no involvement in the administration of justice, stripped of everything noble and comforting in that role, without the ability to initiate any legal proceedings, nor to suspend, ease, or grant pardons. All that is contemptible and detestable in justice is attributed to him. The Assembly worked hard to remove the disgrace from certain positions, yet they placed the person who was recently their king in a role just slightly above that of an executioner, and in a position of nearly the same nature. Given the current situation of the king of the French, it’s impossible for him to hold any respect for himself or be respected by others.

View this new executive officer on the side of his political capacity, as he acts under the orders of the National Assembly. To execute laws is a royal office; to execute orders is not to be a king. However, a political executive magistracy, though merely such, is a great trust. It is a trust, indeed, that has much depending upon its faithful and diligent performance, both in the person presiding in it and in all its subordinates. Means of performing this duty ought to be given by regulation; and dispositions towards it ought to be infused by the circumstances attendant on the trust. It ought to be environed with dignity, authority, and consideration, and it ought to lead to glory. The office of execution is an office of exertion. It is not from impotence we are to expect the tasks of power. What sort of person is a king to command executory service, who has no means whatsoever to reward it:—not in a permanent office; not in a grant of land; no, not in a pension of fifty pounds a year; not in the vainest and most trivial title? In France the king is no more the fountain of honor than he is the fountain of justice. All rewards, all distinctions, are in other hands. Those who serve the king can be actuated by no natural motive but fear,—by a fear of everything except their master. His functions of internal coercion are as odious as those which he exercises in the department of justice. If relief is to be given to any municipality, the Assembly gives it. If troops are to be sent to reduce them to obedience to the Assembly, the king is to execute the order; and upon every occasion he is to be spattered over with the blood of his people. He has no negative; yet his name and authority is used to enforce every harsh decree. Nay, he must concur in the butchery of those who shall attempt to free him from his imprisonment, or show the slightest attachment to his person or to his ancient authority.

Consider this new executive officer in terms of his political role, as he follows the directives of the National Assembly. Enforcing laws is a royal duty; carrying out orders doesn’t equate to being a king. However, holding a political executive position, even if it’s just that, is a significant responsibility. It’s a responsibility that relies heavily on the faithful and diligent execution by both the person in charge and all their subordinates. There should be guidelines for performing this duty, and the surrounding circumstances should inspire the right attitude toward it. It should be surrounded by dignity, authority, and respect, and it should lead to honor. The role of execution is one of effort. It’s not from weakness that we should expect acts of power. What kind of king can expect to command effective service if he has no means to reward it—neither a permanent position, land grants, nor even a meager pension of fifty pounds a year; not even the most trivial title? In France, the king is neither the source of honor nor justice. All rewards and distinctions lie in other hands. Those who serve the king can only be driven by fear—fear of everything except their master. His role of internal enforcement is as detestable as his functions in justice. If any aid is to be given to a municipality, it’s the Assembly that provides it. If troops are to be sent to force obedience to the Assembly, the king must carry out the order; and he will always bear the burden of his people's blood. He has no veto power; yet his name and authority is used to support every harsh decree. Indeed, he must consent to the slaughter of those who attempt to liberate him from his confinement or show any loyalty to him or his former authority.

Executive magistracy ought to be constituted in such a manner that those who compose it should be disposed to love and to venerate those whom they are bound to obey. A purposed neglect, or, what is worse, a literal, but perverse and malignant obedience, must be the ruin of the wisest counsels. In vain will the law attempt to anticipate or to follow such studied neglects and fraudulent attentions. To make them act zealously is not in the competence of law. Kings, even such as are truly kings, may and ought to bear the freedom of subjects that are obnoxious to them. They may, too, without derogating from themselves, bear even the authority of such persons, if it promotes their service. Louis the Thirteenth mortally hated the Cardinal de Richelieu; but his support of that minister against his rivals was the source of all the glory of his reign, and the solid foundation of his throne itself. Louis the Fourteenth, when come to the throne, did not love the Cardinal Mazarin; but for his interests he preserved him in power. When old, he detested Louvois; but for years, whilst he faithfully served his greatness, he endured his person. When George the Second took Mr. Pitt, who certainly was not agreeable to him, into his councils, he did nothing which could humble a wise sovereign. But these ministers, who were chosen by affairs, not by affections, acted in the name of and in trust for kings, and not as their avowed constitutional and ostensible masters. I think it impossible that any king, when he has recovered his first terrors, can cordially infuse vivacity and vigor into measures which he knows to be dictated by those who, he must be persuaded, are in the highest degree ill affected to his person. Will any ministers, who serve such a king (or whatever he may be called) with but a decent appearance of respect, cordially obey the orders of those whom but the other day in his name they had committed to the Bastile? will they obey the orders of those whom, whilst they were exercising despotic justice upon them, they conceived they were treating with lenity, and for whom in a prison they thought they had provided an asylum? If you expect such obedience, amongst your other innovations and regenerations, you ought to make a revolution in Nature, and provide a new constitution, for the human mind: otherwise your supreme government cannot harmonize with its executory system. There are cases in which we cannot take up with names and abstractions. You may call half a dozen leading individuals, whom we have reason to fear and hate, the nation. It makes no other difference than to make us fear and hate them the more. If it had been thought justifiable and expedient to make such a revolution by such means and through such persons as you have made yours, it would have been more wise to have completed the business of the fifth and sixth of October. The new executive officer would then owe his situation to those who are his creators as well as his masters; and he might be bound in interest, in the society of crime, and (if in crimes there could be virtues) in gratitude, to serve those who had promoted him to a place of great lucre and great sensual indulgence,—and of something more: for more he must have received from those who certainly would not have limited an aggrandized creature as they have done a submitting antagonist.

The executive authority should be set up in a way that encourages those in power to respect and care for those they are meant to serve. Any intentional neglect, or worse, a twisted and harmful compliance, will undermine the best ideas. The law can't effectively deal with such deliberate neglects and deceitful attentions. It's not the law's job to force them to act with enthusiasm. Even true kings should tolerate the freedom of subjects they find troublesome, and they can also respect the authority of those individuals if it benefits their rule. Louis the Thirteenth despised Cardinal de Richelieu, yet backing him against rivals was crucial to the success of his reign and the stability of his throne. Similarly, Louis the Fourteenth did not have affection for Cardinal Mazarin at the start of his reign, but he kept him in power because it served his interests. In his later years, he grew to dislike Louvois, yet he tolerated him for years as he served his needs. When George the Second brought Mr. Pitt—who was certainly not his favorite—into his cabinet, he did nothing to diminish his status as a wise ruler. However, these ministers, chosen for their skills rather than personal affections, acted on behalf of the king and not as his openly recognized superiors. I find it hard to believe that any king, once he regains his confidence, can genuinely energize policies that he knows are pushed by those he believes dislike him intensely. Will any ministers, who serve such a king (or whatever name you want to call him) while maintaining a semblance of respect, truly follow the commands of those they had just locked away in the Bastille in his name? Will they heed the orders of those they thought they were treating leniently while enforcing harsh justice? If you expect this kind of loyalty, amid your other changes and reforms, then you would need to radically change human nature and create a new constitution for the human mind; otherwise, your ultimate authority will clash with its execution. There are situations where we can't rely on names and concepts alone. You might label a few leading figures, whom we justifiably fear and dislike, as the nation. This only serves to heighten our fear and hatred. If it were seen as reasonable and beneficial to initiate such a change through the means and people you've employed, it would have been wiser to finish the work of October fifth and sixth. The new executive would then owe his position to those who created and controlled him; he might be tied by self-interest, by a bond of wrongdoing, and perhaps (if virtues can exist within crimes) by gratitude to those who elevated him to a place of wealth and indulgence— and likely more, as those who backed him would not have restricted a favored individual like they have a submissive opponent.

A king circumstanced as the present, if he is totally stupefied by his misfortunes, so as to think it not the necessity, but the premium and privilege of life, to eat and sleep, without any regard to glory, can never be fit for the office. If he feels as men commonly feel, he must he sensible that an office so circumstanced is one in which he can obtain no fame or reputation. He has no generous interest that can excite him to action. At best, his conduct will be passive and defensive. To inferior people such an office might be matter of honor. But to be raised to it and to descend to it are different things, and suggest different sentiments. Does he really name the ministers? They will have a sympathy with him. Are they forced upon him? The whole business between them and the nominal king will be mutual counteraction. In all other countries the office of ministers of state is of the highest dignity. In France it is full of peril, and incapable of glory. Rivals, however, they will have in their nothingness, whilst shallow ambition exists in the world, or the desire of a miserable salary is an incentive to short-sighted avarice. Those competitors of the ministers are enabled by your Constitution to attack them in their vital parts, whilst they have not the means of repelling their charges in any other than the degrading character of culprits. The ministers of state in Prance are the only persons in that country who are incapable of a share in the national councils. What ministers! What councils! What a nation!—But they are responsible. It is a poor service that is to be had from responsibility. The elevation of mind to be derived from fear will never make a nation glorious. Responsibility prevents crimes. It makes all attempts against the laws dangerous. But for a principle of active and zealous service, none but idiots could think of it. Is the conduct of a war to be trusted to a man who may abhor its principle,—who, in every step he may take to render it successful, confirms the power of those by whom he is oppressed? Will foreign states seriously treat with him who has no prerogative of peace or war,—no, not so much as in a single vote by himself or his ministers, or by any one whom he can possibly influence? A state of contempt is not a state for a prince: better get rid of him at once.

A king in the situation we're looking at, who is completely overwhelmed by his misfortunes and thinks it's just a privilege of life to eat and sleep without caring about glory, will never be fit for the role. If he feels like most people do, he must realize that such a position offers no chance for fame or a good reputation. He won't have any noble interest to motivate him to take action. At best, his behavior will be passive and defensive. For lesser people, such a position might be an honor. But being elevated to it and then falling to it feel different and bring about different emotions. Does he *really* appoint the ministers? They will share his perspective. Are they forced upon him? Then the whole relationship between them and the nominal king will just be one of constant opposition. In all other countries, the role of state ministers is of the highest dignity. In France, it's filled with danger and lacks glory. However, they will still have rivals in their lack of significance, as long as shallow ambition exists in the world or the desire for a pitiful salary drives greedy individuals. These competitors can attack the ministers directly, while the ministers have no means to fend off the accusations apart from the humiliating position of being viewed as criminals. The state ministers in France are the only people in the country who are unable to participate in the national discussions. What kind of ministers! What kind of councils! What kind of nation!—But they are held accountable. It's a poor service that comes from responsibility. The mindset born from fear will never make a nation great. Accountability might prevent crimes and make any attempts against the laws risky. But for anyone who openly and energetically serves, only fools would consider it. Should the conduct of a war be entrusted to someone who may detest it—who, with every action he takes to ensure its success, strengthens the power of those who oppress him? Will foreign states take him seriously when he possesses no authority over peace or war—not even a single vote for himself or his ministers, or anyone he could possibly influence? A state of humiliation is not suitable for a prince: it’s better to remove him altogether.

I know it will be said that these humors in the court and executive government will continue only through this generation, and that the king has been brought to declare the dauphin shall be educated in a conformity to his situation. If he is made to conform to his situation, he will have no education at all. His training must be worse even than that of an arbitrary monarch. If he reads,—whether he reads or not, some good or evil genius will tell him his ancestors were kings. Thenceforward his object must be to assert himself and to avenge his parents. This you will say is not his duty. That may be; but it is Nature; and whilst you pique Nature against you, you do unwisely to trust to duty. In this futile scheme of polity, the state nurses in its bosom, for the present, a source of weakness, perplexity, counteraction, inefficiency, and decay; and it prepares the means of its final ruin. In short, I see nothing in the executive force (I cannot call it authority) that has even an appearance of vigor, or that has the smallest degree of just correspondence or symmetry or amicable relation with the supreme power, either as it now exists, or as it is planned for the future government.

I know people will say that the issues in the court and government will only last for this generation, and that the king has decided the dauphin will be raised in line with his position. But if he is raised to fit his position, he won’t get any real education at all. His upbringing will be even worse than that of an absolute monarch. If he learns to read—whether he actually reads or not, some good or evil influence will tell him that his ancestors were kings. From then on, his goal will be to assert himself and to avenge his parents. You might say that’s not his responsibility. That may be true, but it is human nature; and while you push against nature, it’s unwise to rely on duty. In this pointless political scheme, the state currently harbors a source of weakness, confusion, resistance, inefficiency, and deterioration, and it sets itself up for ultimate ruin. In short, I see nothing in the executive power (I can't even call it authority) that shows any signs of strength or has the slightest semblance of balance, order, or friendly connection with the supreme power, whether as it stands now or as it is meant to be for the future government.

You have settled, by an economy as perverted as the policy, two[125] establishments of government,—one real, one fictitious: both maintained at a vast expense; but the fictitious at, I think, the greatest. Such a machine as the latter is not worth the grease of its wheels. The expense is exorbitant; and neither the show nor the use deserve the tenth part of the charge.—Oh! but I don't do justice to the talents of the legislators: I don't allow, as I ought to do, for necessity. Their scheme of executive force was not their choice. This pageant must be kept. The people would not consent to part with it.—Right: I understand you. You do, in spite of your grand theories, to which you would have heaven and earth to bend, you do know how to conform yourselves to the nature and circumstances of things. But when you were obliged to conform thus far to circumstances, you ought to have carried your submission farther, and to have made, what you were obliged to take, a proper instrument, and useful to its end. That was in your power. For instance, among many others, it was in your power to leave to your king the right of peace and war.—What! to leave to the executive magistrate the most dangerous of all prerogatives?—I know none more dangerous; nor any one more necessary to be so trusted. I do not say that this prerogative ought to be trusted to your king, unless he enjoyed other auxiliary trusts along with it, which he does not now hold. But, if he did possess them, hazardous as they are undoubtedly, advantages would arise from such a Constitution, more than compensating the risk. There is no other way of keeping the several potentates of Europe from intriguing distinctly and personally with the members of your Assembly, from intermeddling in all your concerns, and fomenting, in the heart of your country, the most pernicious of all factions,—factions in the interest and under the direction of foreign powers. From that worst of evils, thank God, we are still free. Your skill, if you had any, would be well employed to find out indirect correctives and controls upon this perilous trust. If you did not like those which in England we have chosen, your leaders might have exerted their abilities in contriving better. If it were necessary to exemplify the consequences of such an executive government as yours, in the management of great affairs, I should refer you to the late reports of M. de Montmorin to the National Assembly, and all the other proceedings relative to the differences between Great Britain and Spain. It would be treating your understanding with disrespect to point them out to you.

You have established, through a twisted economy like the policy itself, two government systems—one real, one fake: both maintained at a huge cost; but I believe the fake one costs the most. That kind of setup isn't worth the grease needed for its wheels. The expense is outrageous, and neither the display nor the function is worth a fraction of the cost. —Oh! But I’m not giving credit to the lawmakers: I’m not considering, as I should, the necessity. Their plan for executive power wasn’t their decision. This spectacle has to be maintained. The people wouldn’t agree to get rid of it.—Right: I get you. Despite your grand theories that you want everyone to bow to, you do know how to adapt to the reality and circumstances. But when you had to adapt to some extent, you should have gone further and made what you had to accept a proper tool and useful for its purpose. You had the power to do that. For example, among many others, you could have left your king the right to declare peace and war.—What! Give the executive the most dangerous of all powers?—I don’t know a power more dangerous, or one that needs to be trusted more. I’m not saying this power should be given to your king unless he had other supportive powers along with it, which he currently doesn’t. But if he did possess them, as risky as they undoubtedly are, the benefits of such a Constitution would outweigh the risks. There’s no other way to keep the various rulers of Europe from directly engaging with your Assembly members, meddling in all your affairs, and stirring up the most harmful factions—factions for the interests and guidance of foreign powers. Thank God we are still free from that worst of evils. Your skills, if you had any, would be better used finding indirect controls and corrections for this risky trust. If you didn’t like those we’ve chosen in England, your leaders could have used their talents to come up with better options. If you needed an example of the effects of an executive government like yours on handling significant issues, I’d point you to the recent reports from M. de Montmorin to the National Assembly and the other discussions regarding the conflicts between Great Britain and Spain. It would be disrespectful to your understanding to even point those out to you.

I hear that the persons who are called ministers have signified an intention of resigning their places. I am rather astonished that they have not resigned long since. For the universe I would not have stood in the situation in which they have been for this last twelvemonth. They wished well, I take it for granted, to the Revolution. Let this fact be as it may, they could not, placed as they were upon an eminence, though an eminence of humiliation, but be the first to see collectively, and to feel each in his own department, the evils which have been produced by that Revolution. In every step which they took, or forbore to take, they must have felt the degraded situation of their country, and their utter incapacity of serving it. They are in a species of subordinate servitude in which no men before them were ever seen. Without confidence from their sovereign on whom they were forced, or from the Assembly who forced them upon him, all the noble functions of their office are executed by committees of the Assembly, without any regard whatsoever to their personal or their official authority. They are to execute, without power; they are to be responsible, without discretion; they are to deliberate, without choice. In their puzzled situation, under two sovereigns, over neither of whom they have any influence, they must act in such a manner as (in effect, whatever they may intend) sometimes to betray the one, sometimes the other, and always to betray themselves. Such has been their situation; such must be the situation of those who succeed them. I have much respect, and many good wishes, for M. Necker. I am obliged to him for attentions. I thought, when his enemies had driven him from Versailles, that his exile was a subject of most serious congratulation. Sed multæ urbes et publica vota vicerunt. He is now sitting on the ruins of the finances and of the monarchy of France.

I hear that the people called ministers have expressed their intention to resign. I'm pretty shocked they haven't done it already. I wouldn't want to be in the position they've been in for the past year for anything in the world. I assume they supported the Revolution. Regardless of that, being on a pedestal, even one of humiliation, they couldn't help but be the first to see collectively, and feel individually in their roles, the problems caused by that Revolution. With every decision they made or didn’t make, they must have felt the degraded state of their country and their complete inability to serve it. They are in a kind of subordinate servitude that no one has ever experienced before. Without the confidence of the sovereign they were forced to serve, or from the Assembly that pushed them onto him, all the important functions of their role are carried out by committees of the Assembly, ignoring their personal and official authority. They are to carry out orders, without power; to be accountable, without discretion; to deliberate, without choice. In their confusing situation, under two authorities, neither of whom they can influence, they must act in ways that, regardless of their intentions, sometimes betray one, sometimes the other, and always betray themselves. That has been their situation, and that will be the situation of those who follow them. I have a lot of respect and good wishes for M. Necker. I'm thankful for his kindness. When his enemies pushed him out of Versailles, I thought his exile was something to seriously celebrate. Sed multæ urbes et publica vota vicerunt. He is now sitting amid the ruins of France's finances and monarchy.

A great deal more might be observed on the strange constitution of the executory part of the new government; but fatigue must give bounds to the discussion of subjects which in themselves have hardly any limits.

A lot more could be said about the unusual structure of the executive branch of the new government, but exhaustion has to limit the conversation on topics that really have no boundaries.

As little genius and talent am I able to perceive in the plan of judicature formed by the National Assembly. According to their invariable course, the framers of your Constitution have begun with the utter abolition of the parliaments. These venerable bodies, like the rest of the old government, stood in need of reform, even though there should be no change made in the monarchy. They required several more alterations to adapt them to the system of a free Constitution. But they had particulars in their constitution, and those not a few, which deserved approbation from the wise. They possessed one fundamental excellence: they were independent. The most doubtful circumstance attendant on their office, that of its being vendible, contributed, however, to this independency of character. They held for life. Indeed, they may be said to have held by inheritance. Appointed by the monarch, they were considered as nearly out of his power. The most determined exertions of that authority against them only showed their radical independence. They composed permanent bodies politic, constituted to resist arbitrary innovation; and from that corporate constitution, and from most of their forms, they were well calculated to afford both certainty and stability to the laws. They had been a safe asylum to secure these laws, in all the revolutions of humor and opinion. They had saved that sacred deposit of the country during the reigns of arbitrary princes and the struggles of arbitrary factions. They kept alive the memory and record of the Constitution. They were the great security to private property; which might be said (when personal liberty had no existence) to be, in fact, as well guarded in France as in any other country. Whatever is supreme in a state ought to have, as much as possible, ifs judicial authority so constituted as not only not to depend upon it, but in some sort to balance it. It ought to give a security to its justice against its power. It ought to make its judicature, as it were, something exterior to the state.

I see very little genius or talent in the judicial plan created by the National Assembly. True to their usual approach, the creators of your Constitution have started by completely eliminating the parliaments. These respected institutions, like the rest of the old government, needed reform, even if there was no change in the monarchy. They required several adjustments to fit the system of a free Constitution. However, they did have certain aspects in their structure, and not a few, that deserved praise from the wise. They had one key strength: they were independent. The most questionable aspect of their role, that it could be bought and sold, oddly contributed to this independence. They served for life. In fact, they could be said to hold their positions by inheritance. Appointed by the monarch, they were viewed as largely out of his control. The most forceful actions of that authority against them only demonstrated their fundamental independence. They formed permanent political bodies designed to resist arbitrary changes; and due to their corporate structure and many of their procedures, they were well-positioned to provide both certainty and stability to the laws. They had been a safe haven to protect these laws throughout all shifts in opinion and sentiment. They preserved that sacred trust of the country during the reigns of absolute rulers and the conflicts of oppressive factions. They kept alive the memory and record of the Constitution. They were a major safeguard for private property, which could be said (when personal liberty was nonexistent) to be as well protected in France as in any other country. Whatever is supreme in a state should have its judicial authority structured in such a way that it does not depend on it and, in some way, balances it. It should provide security for its justice against its power. It should make its judiciary something external to the state.

Those parliaments had furnished, not the best certainly, but some considerable corrective to the excesses and vices of the monarchy. Such an independent judicature was ten times more necessary when a democracy became the absolute power of the country. In that Constitution, elective, temporary, local judges, such as you have contrived, exercising their dependent functions in a narrow society, must be the worst of all tribunals. In them it will be vain to look for any appearance of justice towards strangers, towards the obnoxious rich, towards the minority of routed parties, towards all those who in the election have supported unsuccessful candidates. It will be impossible to keep the new tribunals clear of the worst spirit of faction. All contrivances by ballot we know experimentally to be vain and childish to prevent a discovery of inclinations. Where they may the best answer the purposes of concealment, they answer to produce suspicion, and this is a still more mischievous cause of partiality.

Those parliaments provided, not the best certainly, but some significant correction to the excesses and vices of the monarchy. Such an independent judiciary was even more essential when a democracy held absolute power in the country. In that Constitution, elected, temporary, local judges, like those you’ve created, performing their dependent roles in a small community, must be the worst kind of courts. It will be pointless to search for any sign of justice for outsiders, for the disliked wealthy, for the minority of defeated parties, for all those who supported unsuccessful candidates in the election. It will be impossible to keep the new courts free from the worst spirit of faction. We know from experience that any ballot measures to conceal preferences are pointless and naive. Where they might best serve the purpose of hiding true intentions, they instead lead to suspicion, which is an even more harmful source of bias.

If the parliaments had been preserved, instead of being dissolved at so ruinous a change to the nation, they might have served in this new commonwealth, perhaps not precisely the same, (I do not mean an exact parallel,) but near the same purposes as the court and senate of Areopagus did in Athens: that is, as one of the balances and correctives to the evils of a light and unjust democracy. Every one knows that this tribunal was the great stay of that state; every one knows with what care it was upheld, and with what a religious awe it was consecrated. The parliaments were not wholly free from faction, I admit; but this evil was exterior and accidental, and not so much the vice of their constitution itself as it must be in your new contrivance of sexennial elective judicatories. Several English commend the abolition of the old tribunals, as supposing that they determined everything by bribery and corruption. But they have stood the test of monarchic and republican scrutiny. The court was well disposed to prove corruption on those bodies, when they were dissolved in 1771; those who have again dissolved them would have done the same, if they could; but both inquisitions having failed, I conclude that gross pecuniary corruption must have been rather rare amongst them.

If the parliaments had been maintained instead of being dissolved during such a disastrous change for the nation, they might have played a role in this new commonwealth, perhaps not exactly the same (I don't mean a perfect comparison), but serving quite similar purposes as the court and senate of Areopagus did in Athens: that is, as a balance and check against the issues of a shallow and unjust democracy. Everyone knows this tribunal was a crucial support for that state; everyone knows how carefully it was upheld and how it was respected almost religiously. I admit the parliaments weren't completely free from faction, but that issue was external and accidental, not a flaw in their very structure, unlike in your new setup of six-year elected judicatories. Many English people praise the abolition of the old tribunals, believing they operated entirely through bribery and corruption. However, they have withstood both monarchic and republican scrutiny. The court was eager to uncover corruption in those bodies when they were dissolved in 1771; those who dissolved them again would have done the same if they could, but since both inquiries failed, I conclude that blatant financial corruption must have been quite rare among them.

It would have been prudent, along with the parliaments, to preserve their ancient power of registering, and of remonstrating at least upon, all the decrees of the National Assembly, as they did upon those which passed in the time of the monarchy. It would be a means of squaring the occasional decrees of a democracy to some principles of general jurisprudence. The vice of the ancient democracies, and one cause of their ruin, was, that they ruled, as you do, by occasional decrees, psephismata. This practice soon broke in upon the tenor and consistency of the laws; it abated the respect of the people towards them, and totally destroyed them in the end.

It would have been smart, along with the parliaments, to keep their old power of recording and at least voicing objections to all the decisions made by the National Assembly, just like they did during the monarchy. This would help align the occasional decisions of a democracy with some basic principles of law. A major flaw of the ancient democracies, which contributed to their downfall, was that they governed, like you do, through occasional decisions, psephismata. This approach quickly undermined the stability and consistency of the laws; it diminished the people's respect for them and ultimately led to their complete destruction.

Your vesting the power of remonstrance, which, in the time of the monarchy, existed in the Parliament of Paris, in your principal executive officer, whom, in spite of common sense, you persevere in calling king, is the height of absurdity. You ought never to suffer remonstrance from him who is to execute. This is to understand neither council nor execution, neither authority nor obedience. The person whom you call king ought not to have this power, or he ought to have more.

Your giving the power of protest, which used to exist in the Parliament of Paris during the monarchy, to your main executive officer, whom you stubbornly continue to call king despite common sense, is completely absurd. You should never allow the person who is supposed to execute the law to have the power to protest against it. This shows a lack of understanding of both advising and executing, of authority and obedience. The person you call king shouldn’t have this power, or he should have much more.

Your present arrangement is strictly judicial. Instead of imitating your monarchy, and seating your judges on a bench of independence, your object is to reduce them to the most blind obedience. As you have changed all things, you have invented new principles of order. You first appoint judges, who, I suppose, are to determine according to law, and then you let them know, that, at some time or other, you intend to give them some law by which they are to determine. Any studies which they have made (if any they have made) are to be useless to them. But to supply these studies, they are to be sworn to obey all the rules, orders, and instructions which from time to time they are to receive from the National Assembly. These if they submit to, they leave no ground of law to the subject. They become complete and most dangerous instruments in the hands of the governing power, which, in the midst of a cause, or on the prospect of it, may wholly change the rule of decision. If these orders of the National Assembly come to be contrary to the will of the people who locally choose those judges, such confusion must happen as is terrible to think of. For the judges owe their place to the local authority, and the commands they are sworn to obey come from those who have no share in their appointment. In the mean time they have the example of the court of Châtelet to encourage and guide them in the exercise of their functions. That court is to try criminals sent to it by the National Assembly, or brought before it by other courses of delation. They sit under a guard to save their own lives. They know not by what law they judge, nor under what authority they act, nor by what tenure they hold. It is thought that they are sometimes obliged to condemn at peril of their lives. This is not perhaps certain, nor can it be ascertained; but when they acquit, we know they have seen the persons whom they discharge, with perfect impunity to the actors, hanged at the door of their court.

Your current system is purely judicial. Instead of copying your monarchy and putting your judges on a bench of independence, your goal is to force them into blind obedience. As you've changed everything, you've created new principles of order. First, you appoint judges who are supposed to decide based on law, and then you inform them that, at some point, you plan to provide them with laws they should follow. Any studies they might have done (if they have done any) will be useless to them. To replace their studies, they must swear to obey all the rules, orders, and instructions they receive from the National Assembly over time. If they comply, they leave no legal basis for the individual. They become complete and dangerous tools in the hands of those in power, who can completely alter the rules of decision amid a case or just before it. If these orders from the National Assembly contradict the wishes of the people who elected those judges, it could lead to a situation that's frightening to consider. The judges owe their positions to the local authority, while the rules they must follow come from people who had no role in their selection. Meanwhile, they look to the court of Châtelet for guidance and inspiration in their duties. That court examines criminals sent to it by the National Assembly or those brought before it through other means. They operate under guard to protect their own lives. They have no idea what law they are judging under, what authority they are acting with, or how they maintain their positions. It is believed that they are sometimes pressured to convict, or risk their own lives. This may not be totally certain, nor can it be asverified; but when they acquit, it's evident they have seen those they free, with complete safety for themselves, hanged at the entrance of their court.

The Assembly, indeed, promises that they will form a body of law, which shall be short, simple, clear, and so forth. That is, by their short laws, they will leave much to the discretion of the judge, whilst they have exploded the authority of all the learning which could make judicial discretion (a thing perilous at best) deserving the appellation of a sound discretion.

The Assembly genuinely promises to create a set of laws that will be brief, straightforward, and clear. In other words, their concise laws will allow judges to have a lot of discretion, while they have dismissed the value of the knowledge that could make judicial discretion—something risky at best—worthy of being called a sound discretion.

It is curious to observe, that the administrative bodies are carefully exempted from the jurisdiction of these new tribunals. That is, those persons are exempted from the power of the laws who ought to be the most entirely submitted to them. Those who execute public pecuniary trusts ought of all men to be the most strictly held to their duty. One would have thought that it must have been among your earliest cares, if you did not mean that those administrative bodies should be real, sovereign, independent states, to form an awful tribunal, like your late parliaments, or like our King's Bench, where all corporate officers might obtain protection in the legal exercise of their functions, and would find coercion, if they trespassed against their legal duty. But the cause of the exemption is plain. These administrative bodies are the great instruments of the present leaders in their progress through democracy to oligarchy. They must therefore be put above the law. It will be said that the legal tribunals which you have made are unfit to coerce them. They are, undoubtedly. They are unfit for any rational purpose. It will be said, too, that the administrative bodies will be accountable to the general Assembly. This, I fear, is talking without much consideration of the nature of that Assembly or of these corporations. However, to be subject to the pleasure of that Assembly is not to be subject to law, either for protection or for constraint.

It’s interesting to see that the administrative bodies are intentionally kept out of the reach of these new courts. In other words, the people who should be most accountable to the law are the ones being exempted. Those in charge of managing public funds should definitely be the most responsible for their duties. You might think that one of your top priorities would be to create a serious court, like your previous parliaments or our King’s Bench, where all corporate officials could get legal protection while performing their roles and face consequences if they violated their legal responsibilities. But the reason for this exemption is clear. These administrative bodies are key tools for the current leaders as they transition from democracy to oligarchy. Therefore, they need to be placed above the law. It might be argued that the legal courts you’ve established aren’t fit to hold them accountable. That’s true—they're not suitable for any reasonable purpose. It might also be said that the administrative bodies will be answerable to the General Assembly. Unfortunately, this seems to overlook the reality of that Assembly and these corporations. However, being subject to the whims of that Assembly does not mean being subject to the law, whether for protection or restraint.

This establishment of judges as yet wants something to its completion. It is to be crowned by a new tribunal. This is to be a grand state judicature; and it is to judge of crimes committed against the nation, that is, against the power of the Assembly. It seems as if they had something in their view of the nature of the high court of justice erected in England during the time of the great usurpation. As they have not yet finished this part of the scheme, it is impossible to form a direct judgment upon it. However, if great care is not taken to form it in a spirit very different from that which has guided them in their proceedings relative to state offences, this tribunal, subservient to their inquisition, the Committee of Research, will extinguish the last sparks of liberty in France, and settle the most dreadful and arbitrary tyranny ever known in any nation. If they wish to give to this tribunal any appearance of liberty and justice, they must not evoke from or send to it the causes relative to their own members, at their pleasure. They must also remove the seat of that tribunal out of the republic of Paris.[126]

This establishment of judges still needs something to be complete. It will be topped off by a new court, which will serve as a major state judiciary to judge crimes against the nation, specifically against the Assembly's authority. It seems like they are envisioning something similar to the high court of justice that was established in England during the time of the major usurpation. Since they haven't finished this aspect of the plan yet, it's impossible to form a clear opinion on it. However, if they don't take great care to create it with a spirit very different from how they have handled matters related to state offenses, this court, which will be controlled by their inquisition, the Committee of Research, will snuff out the last remnants of liberty in France and impose the most terrible and arbitrary tyranny ever seen in any nation. If they want this court to seem like it embodies liberty and justice, they should not bring or send cases involving their own members at will. They also need to move the court out of the republic of Paris.[126]

Has more wisdom been displayed in the constitution of your army than what is discoverable in your plan of judicature? The able arrangement of this part is the more difficult, and requires the greater skill and attention, not only as a great concern in itself, but as it is the third cementing principle in the new body of republics which you call the French nation. Truly, it is not easy to divine what that army may become at last. You have voted a very large one, and on good appointments, at least fully equal to your apparent means of payment. But what is the principle of its discipline? or whom is it to obey? You have got the wolf by the ears, and I wish you joy of the happy position in which you have chosen to place yourselves, and in which you are well circumstanced for a free deliberation relatively to that army, or to anything else.

Has there been more wisdom shown in your army's structure than in your legal plan? The effective organization of this aspect is more challenging and requires greater skill and attention, not just because it's a major issue in itself, but also because it's the third essential principle in the new framework of republics that you refer to as the French nation. Honestly, it's hard to predict what that army might eventually turn into. You've voted for a very large one, and with good appointments, at least matching your obvious means of payment. But what governs its discipline? Who does it answer to? You've got the wolf by the ears, and I wish you luck with the fortunate position you've chosen for yourselves, where you are well-placed for open discussions about that army or anything else.

The minister and secretary of state for the War Department is M. de La Tour du Pin. This gentleman, like his colleagues in administration, is a most zealous assertor of the Revolution, and a sanguine admirer of the new Constitution which originated in that event. His statement of facts relative to the military of France is important, not only from his official and personal authority, but because it displays very clearly the actual condition of the army in France, and because it throws light on the principles upon which the Assembly proceeds in the administration of this critical object. It may enable us to form some judgment how far it may be expedient in this country to imitate the martial policy of France.

The minister and secretary of state for the War Department is M. de La Tour du Pin. This man, like his fellow administrators, is a passionate supporter of the Revolution and a strong admirer of the new Constitution that resulted from it. His account of the military situation in France is significant, not only because of his official and personal credibility but also because it clearly shows the current state of the army in France and sheds light on the principles guiding the Assembly in managing this critical issue. It might help us evaluate how advisable it is for our country to adopt the military policies of France.

M. de La Tour du Pin, on the fourth of last June, comes to give an account of the state of his department, as it exists under the auspices of the National Assembly. No man knows it so well; no man can express it better. Addressing himself to the National Assembly, he says,—

M. de La Tour du Pin, on June 4th of last year, comes to report on the state of his department, as it currently stands under the guidance of the National Assembly. No one understands it better; no one can explain it more clearly. Speaking to the National Assembly, he says,—

"His Majesty has this day sent me to apprise you of the multiplied disorders of which every day he receives the most distressing intelligence. The army [le corps militaire] threatens to fall into the most turbulent anarchy. Entire regiments have dared to violate at once the respect due to the laws, to the king, to the order established by your decrees, and to the oaths which they have taken with the most awful solemnity. Compelled by my duty to give you information of these excesses, my heart bleeds, when I consider who they are that have committed them. Those against whom it is not in my power to withhold the most grievous complaints are a part of that very soldiery which to this day have been so full of honor and loyalty, and with whom for fifty years I have lived the comrade and the friend.

"His Majesty has today sent me to inform you of the many troubles he hears about every day that cause him great distress. The army [le corps militaire] is threatening to descend into chaotic anarchy. Entire regiments have boldly disrespected the laws, the king, the order established by your decrees, and the oaths they took with utmost seriousness. It pains me to report these excesses, especially when I think about who is responsible for them. Those I am compelled to bring the most severe complaints against are part of the very military that has long been proud and loyal, and with whom I have shared camaraderie and friendship for fifty years."

"What incomprehensible spirit of delirium and delusion has all at once led them astray? Whilst you are indefatigable in establishing uniformity in the empire and moulding the whole into one coherent and consistent body, whilst the French are taught by you at once the respect which the laws owe to the rights of man and that which the citizens owe to the laws, the administration of the army presents nothing but disturbance and confusion. I see in more than one corps the bonds of discipline relaxed or broken,—the most unheard-of pretensions avowed directly and without any disguise,—the ordinances without force,—the chiefs without authority,—the military chest and the colors carried off,—the authority of the king himself [risum teneatis] proudly defied,—the officers despised, degraded, threatened, driven away, and some of them prisoners in the midst of their corps, dragging on a precarious life in the bosom of disgust and humiliation. To fill up the measure of all these horrors, the commandants of places have had their throats out under the eyes and almost in the arms of their own soldiers.

"What confusing spirit of madness and illusion has suddenly led them astray? While you tirelessly work to create uniformity in the empire and shape everything into one coherent and consistent entity, while the French are simultaneously taught by you to respect both the rights of man and the duties citizens have to the laws, the army's administration is nothing but chaos and disorder. I see in more than one corps the bonds of discipline weakened or broken—the most outrageous demands openly declared without any disguise—the orders ineffective—the leaders lacking authority—the military funds and colors stolen—the authority of the king himself [risum teneatis] boldly challenged—the officers disrespected, degraded, threatened, driven away, and some even imprisoned among their own corps, living a precarious existence steeped in disgust and humiliation. To top it all off, the commanders of various places have been executed right before the eyes and almost in the arms of their own soldiers."

"These evils are great; but they are not the worst consequences which may be produced by such military insurrections. Sooner or later they may menace the nation itself. The nature of things requires that the army should never act but as an instrument. The moment that, erecting itself into a deliberate body, it shall act according to its own resolutions, the government, be it what it may, will immediately degenerate into a military democracy: a species of political monster which has always ended by devouring those who have produced it.

"These problems are serious; however, they are not the worst outcomes that can arise from military uprisings. Eventually, they could pose a threat to the nation itself. The nature of things requires that the army should only act as an instrument. The moment it establishes itself as an independent body and starts acting on its own decisions, the government, whatever it is, will quickly turn into a military democracy: a kind of political monster that has always ended up consuming those who created it."

"After all this, who must not be alarmed at the irregular consultations and turbulent committees formed in some regiments by the common soldiers and non-commissioned officers, without the knowledge, or even in contempt of the authority, of their superiors?—although the presence and concurrence of those superiors could give no authority to such monstrous democratic assemblies [comices]."

"After all this, who wouldn't be concerned about the unusual meetings and chaotic committees formed in some regiments by the regular soldiers and non-commissioned officers, without the knowledge, or even in defiance of the authority, of their superiors?—even though the presence and agreement of those superiors wouldn't give any legitimacy to such outrageous democratic gatherings [comices]."

It is not necessary to add much to this finished picture,—finished as far as its canvas admits, but, as I apprehend, not taking in the whole of the nature and complexity of the disorders of this military democracy, which, the minister at war truly and wisely observes, wherever it exists, must be the true constitution of the state, by whatever formal appellation it may pass. For, though he informs the Assembly that the more considerable part of the army have not cast off their obedience, but are still attached to their duty, yet those travellers who have seen the corps whose conduct is the best rather observe in them the absence of mutiny than the existence of discipline.

It’s unnecessary to add much to this completed image—complete as far as the canvas allows—but, as I understand, it doesn't capture the full nature and complexity of the issues within this military democracy. The minister of war rightly points out that wherever it exists, it must be the true foundation of the state, regardless of what formal name it goes by. Although he tells the Assembly that most of the army hasn’t abandoned their loyalty and still holds onto their duties, those who have observed the units with the best conduct notice more a lack of mutiny than actual discipline in them.

I cannot help pausing here for a moment, to reflect upon the expressions of surprise which this minister has let fall relative to the excesses he relates. To him the departure of the troops from their ancient principles of loyalty and honor seems quite inconceivable. Surely those to whom he addresses himself know the causes of it but too well. They know the doctrines which they have preached, the decrees which they have passed, the practices which they have countenanced. The soldiers remember the sixth of October. They recollect the French guards. They have not forgot the taking of the king's castles in Paris and at Marseilles. That the governors in both places were murdered with impunity is a fact that has not passed out of their minds. They do not abandon the principles, laid down so ostentatiously and laboriously, of the equality of men. They cannot shut their eyes to the degradation of the whole noblesse of France, and the suppression of the very idea of a gentleman. The total abolition of titles and distinctions is not lost upon them. But M. du Pin is astonished at their disloyalty, when the doctors of the Assembly have taught them at the same time the respect due to laws. It is easy to judge which of the two sorts of lessons men with arms in their hands are likely to learn. As to the authority of the king, we may collect from the minister himself (if any argument on that head were not quite superfluous) that it is not of more consideration with these troops than it is with everybody else. "The king," says he, "has over and over again repeated his orders to put a stop to these excesses; but in so terrible a crisis, your [the Assembly's] concurrence is become indispensably necessary to prevent the evils which menace the state. You unite to the force of the legislative power that of opinion, still more important." To be sure, the army can have no opinion of the power or authority of the king. Perhaps the soldier has by this time learned, that the Assembly itself does not enjoy a much greater degree of liberty than that royal figure.

I can't help but pause here for a moment to think about the surprise this minister has expressed regarding the excesses he talks about. To him, the troops abandoning their long-standing principles of loyalty and honor seems unimaginable. Surely, the people he's speaking to are well aware of the reasons behind it. They know the ideas they've preached, the laws they've enacted, and the actions they've supported. The soldiers remember October 6th. They recall the French guards. They haven't forgotten the seizure of the king's castles in Paris and Marseille. The fact that the governors in both places were murdered with no consequences is still fresh in their minds. They won't abandon the principles of equality that have been so proudly and painstakingly laid out. They can't ignore the downfall of the entire French nobility and the erasure of the idea of a gentleman. The complete removal of titles and distinctions isn’t lost on them. Yet, M. du Pin is shocked by their disloyalty when the Assembly's leaders have taught them to respect the law. It’s easy to see which of the two lessons soldiers are likely to take to heart. As for the king's authority, we can discern from the minister himself (if additional argument on that point weren’t unnecessary) that it holds no more weight with these troops than it does with anyone else. "The king," he says, "has repeatedly ordered to put a stop to these excesses; but in such a terrible crisis, your [the Assembly's] cooperation is absolutely essential to prevent the threats to the state. You combine the legislative power with that of opinion, which is even more crucial." Clearly, the army doesn’t have any respect for the king’s power or authority. Perhaps the soldiers have by now realized that the Assembly itself doesn't possess much more freedom than that royal figure.

It is now to be seen what has been proposed in this exigency, one of the greatest that can happen in a state. The minister requests the Assembly to array itself in all its terrors, and to call forth all its majesty. He desires that the grave and severe principles announced by them may give vigor to the king's proclamation. After this we should have looked for courts civil and martial, breaking of some corps, decimating of others, and all the terrible means which necessity has employed in such cases to arrest the progress of the most terrible of all evils; particularly, one might expect that a serious inquiry would be made into the murder of commandants in the view of their soldiers. Not one word of all this, or of anything like it. After they had been told that the soldiery trampled upon the decrees of the Assembly promulgated by the king, the Assembly pass new decrees, and they authorize the king to make new proclamations. After the secretary at war had stated that the regiments had paid no regard to oaths, prêtés avec la plus imposante solennité, they propose—what? More oaths. They renew decrees and proclamations as they experience their insufficiency, and they multiply oaths in proportion as they weaken in the minds of men the sanctions of religion. I hope that handy abridgments of the excellent sermons of Voltaire, D'Alembert, Diderot, and Helvétius, on the Immortality of the Soul, on a Particular Superintending Providence, and on a Future State of Rewards and Punishments, are sent down to the soldiers along with their civic oaths. Of this I have no doubt; as I understand that a certain description of reading makes no inconsiderable part of their military exercises, and that they are full as well supplied with the ammunition of pamphlets as of cartridges.

It is now to be seen what has been proposed in this urgent situation, one of the greatest that can occur in a state. The minister asks the Assembly to present itself in all its seriousness and to assert its authority. He wishes that the serious and stern principles they have stated may strengthen the king's proclamation. After this, we would expect to see civil and military courts established, some groups disbanded, others punished, and all the harsh measures that necessity has employed in such cases to stop the spread of the worst of all evils; particularly, one might think a serious investigation would be made into the murders of commanders in front of their soldiers. Yet not a single word about this, or anything similar. After being informed that the soldiers ignored the decrees of the Assembly decreed by the king, the Assembly passes new decrees, and they authorize the king to issue new proclamations. After the war secretary indicated that the regiments had disregarded their oaths, made with the utmost solemnity, what do they propose? More oaths. They repeat decrees and proclamations as they recognize their inadequacy and multiply oaths as they weaken the influence of religious sanctions in people's minds. I hope that concise summaries of the excellent sermons of Voltaire, D'Alembert, Diderot, and Helvétius, on the Immortality of the Soul, on a Specific Supervising Providence, and on a Future State of Rewards and Punishments, are sent to the soldiers along with their civic oaths. I have no doubt about this; I understand that a certain kind of reading makes up a significant part of their military training, and they are just as well equipped with pamphlets as they are with cartridges.

To prevent the mischiefs arising from conspiracies, irregular consultations, seditious committees, and monstrous democratic assemblies [comitia, comices] of the soldiers, and all the disorders arising from idleness, luxury, dissipation, and insubordination, I believe the most astonishing means have been used that ever occurred to men, even in all the inventions of this prolific age. It is no less than this:—The king has promulgated in circular letters to all the regiments his direct authority and encouragement, that the several corps should join themselves with the clubs and confederations in the several municipalities, and mix with them in their feasts and civic entertainments! This jolly discipline, it seems, is to soften the ferocity of their minds, to reconcile them to their bottle companions of other descriptions, and to merge particular conspiracies in more general associations.[127] That this remedy would be pleasing to the soldiers, as they are described by M. de La Tour du Pin, I can readily believe,—and that, however mutinous otherwise, they will dutifully submit themselves to these royal proclamations. But I should question whether all this civic swearing, clubbing, and feasting would dispose them, more than at present they are disposed, to an obedience to their officers, or teach them better to submit to the austere rules of military discipline. It will make them admirable citizens after the French mode, but not quite so good soldiers after any mode. A doubt might well arise, whether the conversations at these good tables would fit them a great deal the better for the character of mere instruments, which this veteran officer and statesman justly observes the nature of things always requires an army to be.

To prevent the troubles that come from conspiracies, irregular meetings, rebellious groups, and wild democratic gatherings [comitia, comices] of the soldiers, as well as all the chaos resulting from laziness, indulgence, wastrel behavior, and defiance, I believe the most astonishing measures have been taken that anyone has ever thought of, even in this inventive age. It's nothing less than this: The king has sent circular letters to all the regiments declaring his direct authority and encouragement for the different units to join the clubs and organizations in the various towns and participate in their celebrations and community events! This cheerful approach is meant to soften their harsh attitudes, bring them together with their drinking buddies of different backgrounds, and merge specific conspiracies into broader alliances.[127] I can easily believe that this remedy would be appealing to the soldiers, as described by M. de La Tour du Pin, and that, despite their rebellious tendencies, they will comply with these royal proclamations. However, I question whether all this civic swearing, clubbing, and feasting will encourage them to be more obedient to their officers or teach them to better follow the strict rules of military discipline. It will make them great citizens in the French sense, but not necessarily better soldiers in any sense. One could wonder if the conversations at these friendly gatherings would really prepare them better to be mere instruments, as this experienced officer and statesman rightly notes is what the nature of things always demands of an army.

Concerning the likelihood of this improvement in discipline by the free conversation of the soldiers with the municipal festive societies, which is thus officially encouraged by royal authority and sanction, we may judge by the state of the municipalities themselves, furnished to us by the war minister in this very speech. He conceives good hopes of the success of his endeavors towards restoring order for the present from the good disposition of certain regiments; but he finds something cloudy with regard to the future. As to preventing the return of confusion, "for this the administration" (says he) "cannot be answerable to you, as long as they see the municipalities arrogate to themselves an authority over the troops which your institutions have reserved wholly to the monarch. You have fixed the limits of the military authority and the municipal authority. You have bounded the action which you have permitted to the latter over the former to the right of requisition; but never did the letter or the spirit of your decrees authorize the commons in these municipalities to break the officers, to try them, to give orders to the soldiers, to drive them from the posts committed to their guard, to stop them in their marches ordered by the king, or, in a word, to enslave the troops to the caprice of each of the cities or even market-towns through which they are to pass."

Regarding the possibility of improving discipline through open conversations between the soldiers and the local festive organizations, which is officially supported by royal authority, we can assess this by looking at the state of the municipalities as outlined by the war minister in this speech. He has good reasons to be optimistic about maintaining order for now, thanks to the positive attitude of certain regiments; however, he sees some uncertainties about the future. In terms of preventing chaos from returning, “the administration” (as he says) “cannot guarantee this to you as long as they see the municipalities claiming authority over the troops, which your institutions have reserved entirely for the monarch. You have established the boundaries of military authority and municipal authority. You’ve limited the actions you allowed the latter to take over the former to the right of requisition; however, neither the letter nor the spirit of your decrees gave the common people in these municipalities the power to break officers, put them on trial, give orders to soldiers, remove them from their posts, disrupt marches ordered by the king, or, in short, subject the troops to the whims of each city or even smaller towns they pass through.”

Such is the character and disposition of the municipal society which is to reclaim the soldiery, to bring them back to the true principles of military subordination, and to lender them machines in the hands of the supreme power of the country! Such are the distempers of the French troops! Such is their cure! As the army is, so is the navy. The municipalities supersede the orders of the Assembly, and the seamen in their turn supersede the orders of the municipalities. From my heart I pity the condition of a respectable servant of the public, like this war minister, obliged in his old age to pledge the Assembly in their civic cups, and to enter with a hoary head into all the fantastic vagaries of these juvenile politicians. Such schemes are not like propositions coming from a man of fifty years' wear and tear amongst mankind. They seem rather such as ought to be expected from those grand compounders in politics who shorten the road to their degrees in the state, and have a certain inward fanatical assurance and illumination upon all subjects,—upon the credit of which, one of their doctors has thought fit, with great applause, and greater success, to caution the Assembly not to attend to old men, or to any persons who value themselves upon their experience. I suppose all the ministers of state must qualify, and take this test,—wholly abjuring the errors and heresies of experience and observation. Every man has his own relish; but I think, if I could not attain to the wisdom, I would at least preserve something of the stiff and peremptory dignity of age. These gentlemen deal in regeneration: but at any price I should hardly yield my rigid fibres to be regenerated by them,—nor begin, in my grand climacteric, to squall in their new accents, or to stammer, in my second cradle, the elemental sounds of their barbarous metaphysics.[128] Si isti mihi largiantur ut repuerascam, et in eorum cunis vagiam, valde recusem!

Such is the nature and mindset of the local society that aims to reform the military, to bring them back to the true principles of military discipline, and to make them tools of the country’s supreme authority! Such are the problems with the French troops! Such is their solution! As the army is, so is the navy. The municipalities override the orders of the Assembly, and the sailors, in turn, override the orders from the municipalities. I genuinely feel sorry for a respected public servant like this war minister, who, in his old age, has to toast the Assembly at their civic gatherings and engage with the childish whims of these young politicians. These plans do not seem to come from someone who has spent fifty years navigating the complexities of life. They appear to be the kind of ideas expected from those who seek quick advancement in politics and possess a sort of misguided confidence on every topic—on which one of their scholars has notably warned the Assembly, to much applause and even more success, not to pay attention to old men or anyone who prides themselves on their experience. I suppose all government ministers must pass this test—completely rejecting the mistakes and misconceptions that come from experience and observation. Everyone has their own taste; but I believe that if I couldn’t achieve wisdom, I would at least maintain some of the unyielding dignity that comes with age. These gentlemen are about renewal: yet I would hardly allow my firm beliefs to be reformed by them—nor would I begin, in my twilight years, to wail in their new jargon or to stumble, in my second childhood, through the basic sounds of their crude philosophy. Si isti mihi largiantur ut repuerascam, et in eorum cunis vagiam, valde recusem!

The imbecility of any part of the puerile and pedantic system which they call a Constitution cannot be laid open without discovering the utter insufficiency and mischief of every other part with which it comes in contact, or that bears any the remotest relation to it. You cannot propose a remedy for the incompetence of the crown, without displaying the debility of the Assembly. You cannot deliberate on the confusion of the army of the state, without disclosing the worse disorders of the armed municipalities. The military lays open the civil, and the civil betrays the military anarchy. I wish everybody carefully to peruse the eloquent speech (such it is) of Mons. de La Tour du Pin. He attributes the salvation of the municipalities to the good behavior of some of the troops. These troops are to preserve the well-disposed part of the municipalities, which is confessed to be the weakest, from the pillage of the worst disposed, which is the strongest. But the municipalities affect a sovereignty, and will command those troops which are necessary for their protection. Indeed, they must command them or court them. The municipalities, by the necessity of their situation, and by the republican powers they have obtained, must, with relation to the military, be the masters, or the servants, or the confederates, or each successively, or they must make a jumble of all together, according to circumstances. What government is there to coerce the army but the municipality, or the municipality but the army? To preserve concord where authority is extinguished, at the hazard of all consequences, the Assembly attempts to cure the distempers by the distempers themselves; and they hope to preserve themselves from a purely military democracy by giving it a debauched interest in the municipal.

The stupidity of any part of the childish and boring system they call a Constitution can’t be exposed without revealing the complete inadequacy and harm of every other part that interacts with it or is even slightly related to it. You can't suggest a solution for the incompetence of the crown without highlighting the weakness of the Assembly. You can't discuss the chaos in the state army without uncovering the even worse issues in the armed local governments. The military reveals the civil disorder, and the civil chaos betrays the military. I really want everyone to carefully read the impressive speech (it truly is) by Mons. de La Tour du Pin. He claims that the salvation of the local governments relies on the good conduct of some troops. These troops are meant to protect the part of the municipalities that is acknowledged as the weakest from the looting of the worst elements, which are the strongest. However, the municipalities act like they are sovereign and will command the troops needed for their protection. In fact, they must either command them or win them over. Given their situation and the republican powers they have gained, the municipalities must, in relation to the military, be the leaders, the followers, or the partners, or alternate among all these roles based on the circumstances. What government can control the army other than the municipality, or the municipality without the army? To maintain peace where authority has faded, the Assembly tries to fix issues with the very issues themselves; they hope to protect themselves from a purely military democracy by giving it a corrupt interest in the local government.

If the soldiers once come to mix for any time in the municipal clubs, cabals, and confederacies, an elective attraction will draw them to the lowest and most desperate part. With them will be their habits, affections, and sympathies. The military conspiracies which are to be remedied by civic confederacies, the rebellious municipalities which are to be rendered obedient by furnishing them with the means of seducing the very armies of the state that are to keep them in order,—all these chimeras of a monstrous and portentous policy must aggravate the confusion from which they have arisen. There must be blood. The want of common judgment manifested in the construction of all their descriptions of forces, and in all their kinds of civil and judicial authorities, will make it flow. Disorders may be quieted in one time and in one part. They will break out in others; because the evil is radical and intrinsic. All these schemes of mixing mutinous soldiers with seditious citizens must weaken still more and more the military connection of soldiers with their officers, as well as add military and mutinous audacity to turbulent artificers and peasants. To secure a real army, the officer should be first and last in the eye of the soldier,—first and last in his attention, observance, and esteem. Officers, it seems, there are to be, whose chief qualification must be temper and patience. They are to manage their troops by electioneering arts. They must bear themselves as candidates, not as commanders. But as by such means power may be occasionally in their hands, the authority by which they are to be nominated becomes of high importance.

If the soldiers start hanging out in local clubs, groups, and alliances, they'll be drawn to the lowest and most desperate elements. Along with them will come their habits, feelings, and sympathies. The military plots meant to be handled by civic groups, the rebellious towns expected to follow rules by giving them the power to sway the very armies that keep them in check—these bizarre and alarming strategies will only worsen the chaos from which they stem. There will be bloodshed. The lack of common sense reflected in how they organize all their different forces and in all their civil and judicial authorities will make it happen. Problems may be settled in one place and time, but they'll break out elsewhere because the root of the issue is deep and inherent. All these plans to mix rebellious soldiers with rebellious citizens will further weaken the bond between soldiers and their officers, while also inciting more boldness in unruly workers and peasants. To build a real army, the officer should be at the forefront of the soldier's mind—first and foremost in his attention, respect, and admiration. It seems there will be officers whose main qualifications will be temperament and patience. They are expected to manage their troops using political tactics. They must act like candidates, not commanders. However, since such methods might occasionally place power in their hands, the way they are appointed becomes extremely important.

What you may do finally does not appear: nor is it of much moment, whilst the strange and contradictory relation between your army and all the parts of your republic, as well as the puzzled relation of those parts to each other and to the whole, remain as they are. You seem to have given the provisional nomination of the officers, in the first instance, to the king, with a reserve of approbation by the National Assembly. Men who have an interest to pursue are extremely sagacious in discovering the true seat of power. They must soon perceive that those who can negative indefinitely in reality appoint. The officers must therefore look to their intrigues in the Assembly as the sole certain road to promotion. Still, however, by your new Constitution, they must begin their solicitation at court. This double negotiation for military rank seems to me a contrivance, as well adapted as if it were studied for no other end, to promote faction in the Assembly itself relative to this vast military patronage,—and then to poison the corps of officers with factions of a nature still more dangerous to the safety of government, upon any bottom on which it can be placed, and destructive in the end to the efficacy of the army itself. Those officers who lose the promotions intended for them by the crown must become of a faction opposite to that of the Assembly which has rejected their claims, and must nourish discontents in the heart of the army against the ruling powers. Those officers, on the other hand, who, by carrying their point through an interest in the Assembly, feel themselves to be at best only second in the good-will of the crown, though first in that of the Assembly, must slight an authority which would not advance and could not retard their promotion. If, to avoid these evils, you will have no other rule for command or promotion than seniority, you will have an army of formality; at the same time it will become more independent and more of a military republic. Not they, but the king is the machine. A king is not to be deposed by halves. If he is not everything in the command of an army, he is nothing. What is the effect of a power placed nominally at the head of the army, who to that army is no object of gratitude or of fear? Such a cipher is not fit for the administration of an object of all things the most delicate, the supreme command of military men. They must be constrained (and their inclinations lead them to what their necessities require) by a real, vigorous, effective, decided, personal authority. The authority of the Assembly itself suffers by passing through such a debilitating channel as they have chosen. The army will not long look to an Assembly acting through the organ of false show and palpable imposition. They will not seriously yield obedience to a prisoner. They will either despise a pageant, or they will pity a captive king. This relation of your army to the crown will, if I am not greatly mistaken, become a serious dilemma in your politics.

What you can ultimately do doesn’t seem clear, and it’s not that important as long as the strange and conflicting relationship between your army and all parts of your republic, as well as the confusing connections between those parts themselves and the whole, stay the same. It looks like you’ve initially given the king provisional authority to appoint officers, with a requirement for approval from the National Assembly. People with their own agendas are very good at figuring out where real power lies. They will quickly notice that those who can indefinitely reject appointments essentially hold the power to decide. Therefore, the officers will have to rely on their maneuvering in the Assembly as the only certain way to advance. However, with your new Constitution, they must start their lobbying at court. This dual process for military rank seems to be designed, as if intentionally, to encourage factions within the Assembly regarding this significant military patronage—and it could ultimately create divisions among the officers themselves, which would be even more dangerous for the stability of the government and ultimately undermine the effectiveness of the army. Officers who miss out on promotions that should have been granted by the crown will likely become part of a faction opposed to the Assembly that denied their requests, fostering discontent within the army against those in power. On the flip side, officers who manage to secure their positions through alliances in the Assembly will realize they are at best a secondary priority for the king, even if they are favored in the Assembly. They may disregard an authority that can't support or hinder their promotions. If you want to avoid these issues by only using seniority as the measure for command or promotion, you'll end up with a military that is merely formal, while also becoming more independent and resembling a military republic. It’s not the officers who are in control, but the king. A king cannot be partially deposed. If he isn’t fully in command of the army, he effectively has no power. What good is a power that nominally leads the army but is neither respected nor feared by the troops? Such a figure isn’t suitable for managing something as sensitive as the supreme command of military personnel. The officers must be obliged (and they will naturally lean toward fulfilling what they need) by a real, strong, effective, decisive, personal authority. The Assembly’s own authority suffers by going through such a weakening channel as the one they have chosen. The army won't stick around for long with an Assembly that operates through a façade and blatant deception. They won’t truly obey someone who’s merely a figurehead. They will either scorn a performance or feel pity for a captive king. This dynamic between your army and the crown will, I believe, create a serious dilemma in your politics.

It is besides to be considered, whether an Assembly like yours, even supposing that it was in possession of another sort of organ, through which its orders were to pass, is fit for promoting the obedience and discipline of an army. It is known that armies have hitherto yielded a very precarious and uncertain obedience to any senate or popular authority; and they will least of all yield it to an Assembly which is to have only a continuance of two years. The officers must totally lose the characteristic disposition of military men, if they see with perfect submission and due admiration the dominion of pleaders,—especially when they find that they have a new court to pay to an endless succession of those pleaders, whose military policy, and the genius of whose command, (if they should have any,) must be as uncertain as their duration is transient. In the weakness of one kind of authority, and in the fluctuation of all, the officers of an army will remain for some time mutinous and full of faction, until some popular general, who understands the art of conciliating the soldiery, and who possesses the true spirit of command, shall draw the eyes of all men upon himself. Armies will obey him on his personal account. There is no other way of securing military obedience in this state of things. But the moment in which that event shall happen, the person who really commands the army is your master,—the master (that is little) of your king, the master of your Assembly, the master of your whole republic.

It’s important to consider whether an Assembly like yours, even if it had a different means of passing its orders, is capable of ensuring the obedience and discipline of an army. History shows that armies have often given inconsistent and unreliable obedience to any senate or popular authority; they are even less likely to obey an Assembly that only lasts for two years. The officers would have to completely abandon their military mindset if they were to flawlessly accept and admire the control of advocates—especially when they realize they’ll have to report to an endless series of these advocates, whose military strategies and leadership qualities, if they even have any, will be as unpredictable as their temporary positions. With one type of authority weakened and all others in flux, the officers of an army will likely remain rebellious and divided until a popular general emerges, someone who knows how to win over the soldiers and who has the true essence of leadership, capturing everyone's attention. Armies will follow him for his personal qualities. There’s no other way to ensure military obedience in this situation. But once that moment arrives, the person who truly leads the army becomes your master—the master of your king, the master of your Assembly, the master of your entire republic.

How came the Assembly by their present power over the army? Chiefly, to be sure, by debauching the soldiers from their officers. They have begun by a most terrible operation. They have touched the central point about which the particles that compose armies are at repose. They have destroyed the principle of obedience in the great, essential, critical link between the officer and the soldier, just where the chain of military subordination commences, and on which the whole of that system, depends. The soldier is told he is a citizen, and has the rights of man and citizen. The right of a man, he is told, is, to be his own governor, and to be ruled only by those to whom he delegates that self-government. It is very natural he should think that he ought most of all to have his choice where he is to yield the greatest degree of obedience. He will therefore, in all probability, systematically do what he does at present occasionally: that is, he will exercise at least a negative in the choice of his officers. At present the officers are known at best to be only permissive, and on their good behavior. In fact, there have been many instances in which they have been cashiered by their corps. Here is a second negative on the choice of the king: a negative as effectual, at least, as the other of the Assembly. The soldiers know already that it has been a question, not ill received in the National Assembly, whether they ought not to have the direct choice of their officers, or some proportion of them. When such matters are in deliberation, it is no extravagant supposition that they will incline to the opinion most favorable to their pretensions. They will not bear to be deemed the army of an imprisoned king, whilst another army in the same country, with whom too they are to feast and confederate, is to be considered as the free army of a free Constitution. They will cast their eyes on the other and more permanent army: I mean the municipal. That corps, they well know, does actually elect its own officers. They may not be able to discern the grounds of distinction on which they are not to elect a Marquis de La Fayette (or what is his new name?) of their own. If this election of a commander-in-chief be a part of the rights of men, why not of theirs? They see elective justices of peace, elective judges, elective curates, elective bishops, elective municipalities, and elective commanders of the Parisian army. Why should they alone be excluded? Are the brave troops of France the only men in that nation who are not the fit judges of military merit, and of the qualifications necessary for a commander-in-chief? Are they paid by the state, and do they therefore lose the rights of men? They are a part of that nation themselves, and contribute to that pay. And is not the king, is not the National Assembly, and are not all who elect the National Assembly, likewise paid? Instead of seeing all these forfeit their rights by their receiving a salary, they perceive that in all these cases a salary is given for the exercise of those rights. All your resolutions, all your proceedings, all your debates, all the works of your doctors in religion and politics, have industriously been put into their hands; and you expect that they will apply to their own case just as much of your doctrines and examples as suits your pleasure.

How did the Assembly gain their current power over the army? Mainly, by persuading the soldiers to turn against their officers. They started with a truly drastic move. They’ve hit the core principle that keeps armies functioning. They’ve undermined the essential bond of obedience between officers and soldiers, which is where military hierarchy begins and the entire system relies. Soldiers are told they are citizens and have the rights of a person and a citizen. They’re informed that their right as individuals is to govern themselves and to be led only by those they choose to delegate that self-governance to. Naturally, they might believe they should have the most say in who they obey the most. Therefore, they’ll likely do systematically what they currently do only occasionally: that is, they will at least make a negative choice about who their officers are. Right now, the officers are viewed as merely permissive and dependent on their good conduct. In fact, there have been numerous occasions where officers have been dismissed by their regiments. This represents a second avenue for soldiers to oppose the king’s choice, just as effective as the Assembly’s. Soldiers are already aware that there has been discussion in the National Assembly about whether they shouldn’t have the direct choice of their officers, or at least a portion of them. When such topics are up for debate, it’s not unreasonable to assume they’ll lean toward the opinion that most supports their interests. They refuse to be seen as the army of a trapped king while another army in the same country, with whom they are supposed to join and ally, is viewed as the free army of a free Constitution. They will look to the established municipal army, which they know actually elects its own officers. They might not grasp the reasoning behind why they can’t elect their own leader like a Marquis de La Fayette (or whatever his new name is). If electing a commander-in-chief is a fundamental right, why shouldn’t it apply to them? They see justices of the peace, judges, curates, bishops, local councils, and commanders of the Parisian army all being elected. Why should they be the only ones excluded? Are the brave troops of France the only ones in that nation who are not qualified to judge military capability and what’s needed in a commander-in-chief? Are they paid by the state, and do they then forfeit their rights? They are part of that nation and contribute to that pay. And is not the king, is not the National Assembly, and isn’t everyone who elects the National Assembly also compensated? Instead of seeing everyone else lose their rights because they receive a salary, they recognize that in these cases, a salary is given in exchange for exercising those rights. All your resolutions, all your actions, all your debates, and all the works of your scholars in religion and politics have been handed to them, and you expect them to apply to their situation only the doctrines and examples that suit your interests.

Everything depends upon the army in such a government as yours; for you have industriously destroyed all the opinions and prejudices, and, as far as in you lay, all the instincts which support government. Therefore the moment any difference arises between your National Assembly and any part of the nation, you must have recourse to force. Nothing else is left to you,—or rather, you have left nothing else to yourselves. You see, by the report of your war minister, that the distribution of the army is in a great measure made with a view of internal coercion.[129] You must rule by an army; and you have infused into that army by which you rule, as well as into the whole body of the nation, principles which after a time must disable you in the use you resolve to make of it. The king is to call out troops to act against his people, when the world has been told, and the assertion is still ringing in our ears, that troops ought not to fire on citizens. The colonies assert to themselves an independent constitution and a free trade. They must be constrained by troops. In what chapter of your code of the rights of men are they able to read that it is a part of the rights of men to have their commerce monopolized and restrained for the benefit of others? As the colonists rise on you, the negroes rise on them. Troops again,—massacre, torture, hanging! These are your rights of men! These are the fruits of metaphysic declarations wantonly made and shamefully retracted! It was but the other day that the farmers of land in one of your provinces refused to pay some sorts of rents to the lord of the soil. In consequence of this, you decree that the country-people shall pay all rents and dues, except those which as grievances you have abolished; and if they refuse, then you order the king to march troops against them. You lay down metaphysic propositions which infer universal consequences, and then you attempt to limit logic by despotism. The leaders of the present system tell them of their rights, as men, to take fortresses, to murder guards, to seize on kings without the least appearance of authority even from the Assembly, whilst, as the sovereign legislative body, that Assembly was sitting in the name of the nation; and yet these leaders presume to order out the troops which have acted in these very disorders, to coerce those who shall judge on the principles and follow the examples which have been guarantied by their own approbation.

Everything depends on the military in a government like yours; you have systematically dismantled all the beliefs and biases that support governance, and, as much as you could, you’ve stripped away the instincts that uphold it. So, whenever a conflict arises between your National Assembly and any part of the nation, you have no choice but to resort to force. You have left yourselves with no other option. Your war minister’s report shows that the army’s deployment is largely focused on internal control.[129] You rule with an army, and you've instilled in that army, as well as in the entire nation, principles that over time will impair your ability to use them as you intend. The king is supposed to call out troops to act against his people when the world has been informed that troops should not fire on citizens. The colonies claim their own independent constitution and free trade. They need to be subdued by force. In what part of your declaration of human rights can they read that it is a part of those rights to have their trade monopolized and restricted for the benefit of others? As the colonists rise against you, the enslaved rise against them. More troops—massacres, torture, hangings! These are your human rights! These are the results of philosophical claims made recklessly and then shamefully retracted! Just recently, in one of your provinces, farmers refused to pay certain rents to the landowner. As a result, you declare that the rural people must pay all rents and dues except those you've declared grievances; and if they refuse, you instruct the king to send troops against them. You lay down philosophical principles that imply broad consequences and then try to restrict logic with tyranny. The leaders of the current system tell them about their rights as human beings to take fortresses, to kill guards, and to seize kings without any legitimate authority even from the Assembly, while that Assembly, as the sovereign legislative body, is convening in the name of the nation. Yet, these leaders have the audacity to deploy the troops that have participated in these very disturbances to control those who would assess the principles and follow the examples that have been endorsed by their own approval.

The leaders teach the people to abhor and reject all feodality as the barbarism of tyranny; and they tell them afterwards how much of that barbarous tyranny they are to bear with patience. As they are prodigal of light with regard to grievances, so the people find them sparing in the extreme with regard to redress. They know that not only certain quit-rents and personal duties, which you have permitted them to redeem, (but have furnished no money for the redemption,) are as nothing to those burdens for which you have made no provision at all; they know that almost the whole system of landed property in its origin is feudal,—that it is the distribution of the possessions of the original proprietors made by a barbarous conqueror to his barbarous instruments,—and that the most grievous effects of the conquest axe the land-rents of every kind, as without question they are.

The leaders teach the people to hate and reject all forms of feudalism as the cruelty of tyranny; then they later tell them how much of that cruel tyranny they should endure with patience. While they are very open about grievances, the people find them incredibly unhelpful when it comes to solutions. They understand that not just the specific quit-rents and personal duties, which you've allowed them to pay off (but haven't provided any money for), are insignificant compared to the burdens you've made no plans to address at all; they realize that nearly the entire system of land ownership is originally feudal—that it stems from a brutal conqueror distributing the land of the original owners to his brutal followers—and that the most severe impacts of the conquest are the land rents of all types, without a doubt they are.

The peasants, in all probability, are the descendants of these ancient proprietors, Romans or Gauls. But if they fail, in any degree, in the titles which they make on the principles of antiquaries and lawyers, they retreat into the citadel of the rights of men. There they find that men are equal; and the earth, the kind and equal mother of all, ought not to be monopolized to foster the pride and luxury of any men, who by nature are no better than themselves, and who, if they do not labor for their bread, are worse. They find, that, by the laws of Nature, the occupant and subduer of the soil is the true proprietor,—that there is no prescription against Nature,—and that the agreements (where any there are) which have been made with the landlords during the time of slavery are only the effect of duresse and force,—and that, when the people reëntered into the rights of men, those agreements were made as void as everything else which had been settled under the prevalence of the old feudal and aristocratic tyranny. They will tell you that they see no difference between an idler with a hat and a national cockade and an idler in a cowl or in a rochet. If you ground the title to rents on succession and prescription, they tell you from the speech of M. Camus, published by the National Assembly for their information, that things ill begun cannot avail themselves of prescription,—that the title of those lords was vicious in its origin,—and that force is at least as bad as fraud. As to the title by succession, they will tell you that the succession of those who have cultivated the soil is the true pedigree of property, and not rotten parchments and silly substitutions,—that the lords have enjoyed their usurpation too long,—and that, if they allow to these lay monks any charitable pension, they ought to be thankful to the bounty of the true proprietor, who is so generous towards a false claimant to his goods.

The peasants are likely the descendants of those ancient landowners, whether Romans or Gauls. However, if they have any shortcomings in the claims they make based on the principles of historians and lawyers, they fall back on the fundamental rights of humans. They understand that all people are equal, and the earth, which is a kind and equal mother to everyone, shouldn't be hoarded to support the pride and luxury of any individuals who are, by nature, no better than they are—and those who don't work for their sustenance are even worse. They realize that, according to the laws of Nature, the person who occupies and cultivates the land is the true owner; there are no claims against Nature—and any agreements made with landlords during the times of servitude were born out of coercion and force. When people reclaim their human rights, those agreements become as invalid as everything else that was arranged under the old feudal and aristocratic oppression. They would argue that there's no difference between a slacker wearing a top hat and a national insignia and a slacker in a robe or a clerical garment. If you base the claim to rents on inheritance and long-standing ownership, they'll remind you, from a speech by M. Camus published by the National Assembly for their reference, that illegitimate beginnings can't claim established rights—that the claim of those lords is fundamentally flawed—and that force is at least as bad as deceit. Regarding inheritance, they'll assert that the true lineage of property belongs to those who have worked the land, not to worthless documents and ridiculous substitutions—that the lords have held onto their wrongful claims for too long—and that if they grant any charitable pension to these lay monks, they should be grateful to the real owner, who is so generous towards a false claimant to his possessions.

When the peasants give you back that coin of sophistic reason on which you have set your image and superscription, you cry it down as base money, and tell them you will pay for the future with French guards and dragoons and hussars. You hold up, to chastise them, the second-hand authority of a king, who is only the instrument of destroying, without any power of protecting either the people or his own person. Through him, it seems, you will make yourselves obeyed. They answer,—"You have taught us that there are no gentlemen; and which of your principles teach us to bow to kings whom we have not elected? We know, without your teaching, that lands were given for the support of feudal dignities, feudal titles, and feudal offices. When you took down the cause as a grievance, why should the more grievous effect remain? As there are now no hereditary honors and no distinguished families, why are we taxed to maintain what you tell us ought not to exist? You have sent down our old aristocratic landlords in no other character and with no other title but that of exactors under your authority. Have you endeavored to make these your rent-gatherers respectable to us? No. You have sent them to us with their arms reversed, their shields broken, their impresses defaced,—and so displumed, degraded, and metamorphosed, such unfeathered two-legged things, that we no longer know them. They are strangers to us. They do not even go by the names of our ancient lords. Physically they may be the same men,—though we are not quite sure of that, on your new philosophic doctrines of personal identity. In all other respects they are totally changed. We do not see why we have not as good a right to refuse them their rents as you have to abrogate all their honors, titles, and distinctions. This we have never commissioned you to do; and it is one instance among many, indeed, of your assumption of undelegated power. We see the burghers of Paris, through their clubs, their mobs, and their national guards, directing you at their pleasure, and giving that as law to you, which, under your authority, is transmitted as law to us. Through you, these burghers dispose of the lives and fortunes of us all. Why should not you attend as much to the desires of the laborious husbandman with regard to our rent, by which we are affected in the most serious manner, as you do to the demands of these insolent burghers relative to distinctions and titles of honor, by which neither they nor we are affected at all? But we find you pay more regard to their fancies than to our necessities. Is it among the rights of man to pay tribute to his equals? Before this measure of yours we might have thought we were not perfectly equal; we might have entertained some old, habitual, unmeaning prepossession in favor of those landlords; but we cannot conceive with what other view than that of destroying all respect to them you could have made the law that degrades them. You have forbidden us to treat them with any of the old formalities of respect; and now you send troops to sabre and to bayonet us into a submission to fear and force which you did not suffer us to yield to the mild authority of opinion."

When the peasants return the coin of fake reasoning that you've stamped with your image and inscription, you dismiss it as worthless money, claiming you'll pay for the future with French guards, dragoons, and hussars. You raise the outdated authority of a king to punish them, who is just a tool for destruction, lacking any power to protect either the people or himself. Through him, you believe you can make yourselves obeyed. They respond, “You’ve taught us that there are no gentlemen; what makes your principles justify bowing to kings we haven’t chosen? We understand, without your teaching, that lands were given to support feudal dignities, titles, and offices. When you removed the cause as a grievance, why should the more serious effect remain? Since there are no hereditary honors or distinguished families anymore, why should we be taxed to support what you claim shouldn’t exist? You’ve reduced our former aristocratic landlords to nothing more than tax collectors under your authority. Did you try to make these rent-collectors respectable to us? No. You’ve sent them to us defeated, their shields broken, their insignias worn down—so stripped of status and dignity that we no longer recognize them. They are strangers to us. They don’t even go by the names of our ancient lords. Physically, they might be the same men—although we're not entirely sure about that with your new philosophical ideas about personal identity. In every other way, they are completely changed. We don’t see why we shouldn’t refuse to pay them their rents as you have removed all their honors, titles, and distinctions. We never gave you the authority to do this; and it’s just one example among many of your grasping for power that you don’t actually have. We see the merchants of Paris, through their clubs, mobs, and national guards, controlling you at their whim, and giving that as law to you, which, under your authority, is handed down as law to us. Through you, these merchants dictate the lives and fortunes of all of us. So why don’t you pay as much attention to the demands of the hardworking farmers about our rent, which seriously affects us, as you do to the claims of these arrogant merchants about distinctions and titles of honor, which don’t matter to either them or us? But we see you listen more to their whims than to our needs. Is it one of man's rights to pay tribute to his peers? Before your actions, we might have thought we weren’t completely equal; we might have held on to some outdated, meaningless loyalty to those landlords; but we can’t understand why you would have made the law that humiliates them, if not to destroy any respect we had for them. You’ve forbidden us from treating them with any of the old courtesies; and now you send troops to intimidate us into submission to fear and force, which you didn’t allow us to yield to the gentle authority of opinion."

The ground of some of these arguments is horrid and ridiculous to all rational ears; but to the politicians of metaphysics, who have opened schools for sophistry, and made establishments for anarchy, it is solid and conclusive. It is obvious, that, on a mere consideration of the right, the leaders in the Assembly would not in the least have scrupled to abrogate the rents along with the titles and family ensigns. It would be only to follow up the principle of their reasonings, and to complete the analogy of their conduct. But they had newly possessed themselves of a great body of landed property by confiscation. They had this commodity at market; and the market would have been wholly destroyed, if they were to permit the husbandmen to riot in the speculations with which they so freely intoxicated themselves. The only security which property enjoys in any one of its descriptions is from the interests of their rapacity with regard to some other. They have left nothing but their own arbitrary pleasure to determine what property is to be protected and what subverted.

Some of these arguments are terrible and absurd to any reasonable person; but to the politicians of metaphysics, who have set up schools for deceit and created systems for chaos, they seem solid and convincing. It's clear that, if we only consider what is right, the leaders in the Assembly wouldn't hesitate to abolish rents along with titles and family symbols. They would merely be following through on their reasoning and completing the pattern of their actions. However, they had just taken control of a large amount of land through confiscation. They had this asset on the market; and the market would have been completely disrupted if they allowed the farmers to indulge in the fantasies they were so eagerly intoxicated by. The only protection that property has in any form comes from competing interests regarding other people's greed. They've left nothing but their own whims to decide which properties are to be protected and which ones are to be taken away.

Neither have they left any principle by which any of their municipalities can be bound to obedience,—or even conscientiously obliged not to separate from the whole, to become independent, or to connect itself with some other state. The people of Lyons, it seems, have refused lately to pay taxes. Why should they not? What lawful authority is there left to exact them? The king imposed some of them. The old States, methodized by orders, settled the more ancient. They may say to the Assembly,—"Who are you, that are not our kings, nor the States we have elected, nor sit on the principles on which we have elected you? And who are we, that, when we see the gabelles which you have ordered to be paid wholly shaken off, when we see the act of disobedience afterwards ratified by yourselves, who are we, that we are not to judge what taxes we ought or ought not to pay, and are not to avail ourselves of the same powers the validity of which you have approved in others?" To this the answer is, "We will send troops." The last reason of kings is always the first with your Assembly. This military aid may serve for a time, whilst the impression of the increase of pay remains, and the vanity of being umpires in all disputes is flattered. But this weapon will snap short, unfaithful to the hand that employs it. The Assembly keep a school, where, systematically, and with unremitting perseverance, they teach principles and form regulations destructive to all spirit of subordination, civil and military,—and then they expect that they shall hold in obedience an anarchic people by an anarchic army.

They haven't established any principle that would require their municipalities to follow orders—or even to feel morally obligated not to separate from the whole, become independent, or join another state. Recently, the people of Lyons have refused to pay taxes. Why shouldn't they? What legal authority remains to collect them? The king imposed some. The old States, organized by orders, settled the more ancient ones. They could question the Assembly, saying, “Who are you, since you are neither our kings, nor the elected States, nor do you act on the principles for which we elected you? And who are we, that when we see the gabelles you ordered to be paid completely disregarded, when we see the act of disobedience afterwards approved by you, who are we to not decide what taxes we should or shouldn't pay, and not use the same powers whose validity you recognized in others?” The reply is, “We will send troops.” The last resort of kings is always the first for your Assembly. This military support may work for a while, as long as the increase in pay is felt, and the pride of being referees in all disputes is stroked. But this weapon will fail, unfaithful to its wielder. The Assembly runs a system where they consistently teach principles and create regulations that undermine all spirit of obedience, both civil and military—and then they expect to maintain control over a chaotic populace with a chaotic army.

The municipal army, which, according to their new policy, is to balance this national army, if considered in itself only, is of a constitution much more simple, and in every respect less exceptionable. It is a mere democratic body, unconnected with the crown or the kingdom, armed and trained and officered at the pleasure of the districts to which the corps severally belong; and the personal service of the individuals who compose, or the fine in lieu of personal service, are directed by the same authority.[130] Nothing is more uniform. If, however, considered in any relation to the crown, to the National Assembly, to the public tribunals, or to the other army, or considered in a view to any coherence or connection between its parts, it seems a monster, and can hardly fail to terminate its perplexed movements in some great national calamity. It is a worse preservative of a general constitution than the systasis of Crete, or the confederation of Poland, or any other ill-devised corrective which has yet been imagined, in the necessities produced by an ill-constructed system of government.

The municipal army, which, according to their new policy, is meant to balance the national army, is, when viewed on its own, much simpler in structure and generally less objectionable. It is simply a democratic entity, not connected to the crown or the kingdom, armed, trained, and led at the discretion of the districts to which the individual units belong; the personal service of its members, or the fines in lieu of service, are managed by the same authority.[130] There’s nothing more consistent. However, when viewed in relation to the crown, the National Assembly, public courts, or the other army, or in terms of the coherence among its parts, it appears as a chaotic entity, likely to end in significant national disaster. It serves as a poorer safeguard for a general constitution than either the Cretan system or the Polish confederation, or any other poorly thought-out corrective that has been proposed due to the challenges posed by a poorly designed government system.


Having concluded my few remarks on the constitution of the supreme power, the executive, the judicature, the military, and on the reciprocal relation of all these establishments, I shall say something of the ability showed by your legislators with regard to the revenue.

Having finished my brief comments on the structure of the supreme power, the executive, the judiciary, the military, and the relationships among these institutions, I will now discuss the competence demonstrated by your lawmakers concerning revenue.

In their proceedings relative to this object, if possible, still fewer traces appear of political judgment or financial resource. When the States met, it seemed to be the great object to improve the system of revenue, to enlarge its collection, to cleanse it of oppression and vexation, and to establish it on the most solid footing. Great were the expectations entertained on that head throughout Europe. It was by this grand arrangement that France was to stand or fall; and this became, in my opinion very properly, the test by which the skill and patriotism of those who ruled in that Assembly would be tried. The revenue of the state is the state. In effect, all depends upon it, whether for support or for reformation. The dignity of every occupation wholly depends upon the quantity and the kind of virtue that may be exerted in it. As all great qualities of the mind which operate in public, and are not merely suffering and passive, require force for their display, I had almost said for their unequivocal existence, the revenue, which is the spring of all power, becomes in its administration the sphere of every active virtue. Public virtue, being of a nature magnificent and splendid, instituted for great things, and conversant about great concerns, requires abundant scope and room, and cannot spread and grow under confinement, and in circumstances straitened, narrow, and sordid. Through the revenue alone the body politic can act in its true genius and character; and therefore it will display just as much of its collective virtue, and as much of that virtue which may characterize those who move it, and are, as it were, its life and guiding principle, as it is possessed of a just revenue. For from hence not only magnanimity, and liberality, and beneficence, and fortitude, and providence, and the tutelary protection of all good arts derive their food, and the growth of their organs, but continence, and self-denial, and labor, and vigilance, and frugality, and whatever else there is in which the mind shows itself above the appetite, are nowhere more in their proper element than in the provision and distribution of the public wealth. It is therefore not without reason that the science of speculative and practical finance, which must take to its aid so many auxiliary branches of knowledge, stands high in the estimation not only of the ordinary sort, but of the wisest and best men; and as this science has grown with the progress of its object, the prosperity and improvement of nations has generally increased with the increase of their revenues; and they will both continue to grow and flourish as long as the balance between what is left to strengthen the efforts of individuals and what is collected for the common efforts of the state bear to each other a due reciprocal proportion, and are kept in a close correspondence and communication. And perhaps it may be owing to the greatness of revenues, and to the urgency of state necessities, that old abuses in the constitution of finances are discovered, and their true nature and rational theory comes to be more perfectly understood; insomuch that a smaller revenue might have been more distressing in one period than a far greater is found to be in another, the proportionate wealth even remaining the same. In this state of things, the French Assembly found something in their revenues to preserve, to secure, and wisely to administer, as well as to abrogate and alter. Though their proud assumption might justify the severest tests, yet, in trying their abilities on their financial proceedings, I would only consider what is the plain, obvious duty of a common finance minister, and try them upon that, and not upon models of ideal perfection.

In their discussions about this issue, there were even fewer signs of political insight or financial savvy. When the States convened, their main goal seemed to be improving the tax system, expanding its collection, removing oppression and harassment, and ensuring it was built on a solid foundation. There were high hopes regarding this matter across Europe. This grand plan was posited as essential for France's success or failure; thus, it seemed entirely fair to assess the skill and patriotism of those in the Assembly based on this. The state's revenue is synonymous with the state itself. Ultimately, everything hinges on it, whether for support or reform. The value of any profession relies completely on the level and type of integrity that may be displayed in it. Since all great qualities of the mind, which function in public and are not merely passive, require energy to manifest—indeed, I might say for their clear existence—the revenue, being the source of all power, becomes the arena for every active virtue in its management. Public virtue, which is inherently grand and noble, designed for significant endeavors and engaged in critical matters, needs ample space and opportunity to thrive; it cannot expand and flourish in cramped, narrow, and dismal conditions. Through revenue alone can the political body act in its true spirit and identity; therefore, it will reveal as much of its collective virtue and the qualities that characterize those who drive it—who are, in a sense, its essence and guiding force—as it has a fair revenue. For here not only do nobility, generosity, kindness, courage, foresight, and the protective care of all positive endeavors find their sustenance and growth, but also self-control, temperance, hard work, diligence, frugality, and any other trait where the mind demonstrates superiority over desire are best expressed in the management and distribution of public wealth. It's reasonable, then, that the field of both theoretical and practical finance, which requires the support of various other knowledge areas, is highly regarded not just by average people but also by the wisest and most commendable individuals. As this field has developed alongside its objectives, the prosperity and enhancement of nations have generally risen with their increasing revenues; and both will continue to grow and thrive as long as there’s a proper balance between what individuals retain to support their efforts and what is gathered for the collective initiatives of the state, maintaining a close connection and communication. Perhaps the increased revenues and the pressing needs of the state reveal longstanding issues in financial systems, clarifying their true nature and sensible principles; so much so that a smaller revenue might have been more troublesome at one time than a much larger one may be at another, even if their proportional wealth stays the same. In this context, the French Assembly found something valuable in their revenues that needed preservation, security, and wise management, along with elements that required abolition and change. Although their lofty ambitions could justify strict evaluations, when assessing their capabilities regarding financial matters, I would only consider the basic, apparent responsibilities of a typical finance minister and judge them based on that, rather than on standards of ideal perfection.

The objects of a financier are, then, to secure an ample revenue; to impose it with judgment and equality; to employ it economically; and when necessity obliges him to make use of credit, to secure its foundations in that instance, and forever, by the clearness and candor of his proceedings, the exactness of his calculations, and the solidity of his funds. On these heads we may take a short and distinct view of the merits and abilities of those in the National Assembly who have taken to themselves the management of this arduous concern.

The goals of a financier are to ensure a good income, manage it wisely and fairly, use it efficiently, and when they need to rely on credit, to make sure that it is based on transparency and honesty in their actions, accuracy in their calculations, and reliability in their funds. With this in mind, we can take a brief and clear look at the skills and qualifications of those in the National Assembly who have taken on the challenge of this important responsibility.

Far from any increase of revenue in their hands, I find, by a report of M. Vernier, from the Committee of Finances, of the second of August last, that the amount of the national revenue, as compared with its produce before the Revolution, was diminished by the sum of two hundred millions, or eight millions sterling, of the annual income,—considerably more than one third of the whole.

Far from seeing any increase in revenue, I found in a report by M. Vernier from the Committee of Finances, dated August 2nd of last year, that the national revenue, compared to its earnings before the Revolution, had decreased by two hundred million, or eight million pounds, in annual income—more than one third of the total.

If this be the result of great ability, never surely was ability displayed in a more distinguished manner or with so powerful an effect. No common folly, no vulgar incapacity, no ordinary official negligence, even no official crime, no corruption, no peculation, hardly any direct hostility, which we have seen in the modern world, could in so short a time have made so complete an overthrow of the finances, and, with them, of the strength of a great kingdom.—Cedo quî vestram rempublicam tantam amisistis tam cito?

If this is the outcome of great talent, then surely no talent has ever been shown in such an impressive way or had such a significant impact. No typical foolishness, no common incompetence, no usual lack of attention from officials, not even official wrongdoing, corruption, theft, or hardly any open hostility that we've seen in the modern world, could have caused such a total collapse of the finances, and, along with it, the power of a great kingdom in so short a time.—Cedo quî vestram rempublicam tantam amisistis tam cito?

The sophisters and declaimers, as soon as the Assembly met, began with decrying the ancient constitution of the revenue in many of its most essential branches, such as the public monopoly of salt. They charged it, as truly as unwisely, with being ill-contrived, oppressive, and partial. This representation they were not satisfied to make use of in speeches preliminary to some plan of reform; they declared it in a solemn resolution or public sentence, as it were judicially passed upon it; and this they dispersed throughout the nation. At the time they passed the decree, with the same gravity they ordered the same absurd, oppressive, and partial tax to be paid, until they could find a revenue to replace it. The consequence was inevitable. The provinces which had been always exempted from this salt monopoly, some of whom were charged with other contributions, perhaps equivalent, were totally disinclined to bear any part of the burden, which by an equal distribution was to redeem the others. As to the Assembly, occupied as it was with the declaration and violation of the rights of men, and with their arrangements for general confusion, it had neither leisure nor capacity to contrive, nor authority to enforce, any plan of any kind relative to the replacing the tax, or equalizing it, or compensating the provinces, or for conducting their minds to any scheme of accommodation with the other districts which were to be relieved. The people of the salt provinces, impatient under taxes damned by the authority which had directed their payment, very soon found their patience exhausted. They thought themselves as skilful in demolishing as the Assembly could be. They relieved themselves by throwing off the whole burden. Animated by this example, each district, or part of a district, judging of its own grievance by its own feeling, and of its remedy by its own opinion, did as it pleased with other taxes.

As soon as the Assembly gathered, the speakers and debaters started criticizing the ancient system of revenue, particularly the public salt monopoly. They accused it, rightly but unwise, of being poorly designed, oppressive, and biased. They didn't just use this argument in speeches leading up to some reform plan; they issued a formal resolution, almost like a legal ruling, and spread it throughout the country. At the time they enacted this decree, they seriously mandated the same ridiculous, oppressive, and unfair tax to be paid until they could find a replacement revenue source. The outcome was predictable. The provinces that had always been exempt from this salt monopoly, some of which had other contributions that might have been similar, were completely unwilling to share in the burden that was meant to lighten the load for others. Meanwhile, the Assembly, preoccupied with declaring and violating people's rights and with their plans for widespread chaos, had neither the time nor capacity to devise or enforce any strategy to replace the tax, distribute it more fairly, compensate the provinces, or guide people's thoughts toward any kind of agreement with the other regions that were supposed to be relieved. The people in the salt-producing provinces, frustrated by taxes that were condemned by the very authority that mandated their payment, quickly ran out of patience. They believed they were just as capable of dismantling the system as the Assembly. They freed themselves by discarding the entire burden. Inspired by this example, each district, or part of a district, evaluated its own grievances based on its own experiences and sought remedies according to its own views, managing their other taxes as they wished.

We are next to see how they have conducted themselves in contriving equal impositions, proportioned to the means of the citizens, and the least likely to lean heavy on the active capital employed in the generation of that private wealth from whence the public fortune must be derived. By suffering the several districts, and several of the individuals in each district, to judge of what part of the old revenue they might withhold, instead of better principles of equality, a new inequality was introduced of the most oppressive kind. Payments were regulated by dispositions. The parts of the kingdom which were the most submissive, the most orderly, or the most affectionate to the commonwealth, bore the whole burden of the state. Nothing turns out to be so oppressive and unjust as a feeble government. To fill up all the deficiencies in the old impositions, and the new deficiencies of every kind which were to be expected, what remained to a state without authority? The National Assembly called for a voluntary benevolence,—for a fourth part of the income of all the citizens, to be estimated on the honor of those who were to pay. They obtained something more than could be rationally calculated, but what was far indeed from answerable to their real necessities, and much less to their fond expectations. Rational people could have hoped for little from this their tax in the disguise of a benevolence,—tax weak, ineffective, and unequal,—a tax by which luxury, avarice, and selfishness were screened, and the load thrown upon productive capital, upon integrity, generosity, and public spirit,—a tax of regulation upon virtue. At length the mask is thrown off, and they are now trying means (with little success) of exacting their benevolence by force.

We are about to examine how they managed to create equal taxes that were based on citizens' means and were least likely to heavily burden the active capital used to generate the private wealth that should support public fortune. By allowing different areas and individuals within those areas to decide what part of the old revenue they could withhold, instead of using better principles of fairness, a new and harsh inequality was created. Payments were determined by individual preferences. The regions of the country that were the most compliant, orderly, or loyal to the common good ended up shouldering the entire burden of the state. Nothing is as oppressive and unfair as a weak government. To cover the gaps in the old taxes and the new expected shortages, what could a state without authority do? The National Assembly requested a voluntary contribution—one-fourth of the income from all citizens, to be calculated based on the honor of those who would pay. They received more than could have been reasonably expected, but it was far from meeting their actual needs and much less than their hopeful expectations. Rational people could have expected little from this tax disguised as a goodwill gesture—a weak, ineffective, and unfair tax that shielded luxury, greed, and selfishness while placing the burden on productive capital, integrity, generosity, and public spirit—a tax that regulated virtue. In the end, the disguise was removed, and they are now attempting (with little success) to force contributions.

This benevolence, the rickety offspring of weakness, was to be supported by another resource, the twin brother of the same prolific imbecility. The patriotic donations were to make good the failure of the patriotic contribution. John Doe was to become security for Richard Roe. By this scheme they took things of much price from the giver, comparatively of small value to the receiver; they ruined several trades; they pillaged the crown of its ornaments, the churches of their plate, and the people of their personal decorations. The invention of those juvenile pretenders to liberty was in reality nothing more than a servile imitation of one of the poorest resources of doting despotism. They took an old, huge, full-bottomed periwig out of the wardrobe of the antiquated frippery of Louis the Fourteenth, to cover the premature baldness of the National Assembly. They produced this old-fashioned formal folly, though it had been so abundantly exposed in the Memoirs of the Duke de Saint-Simon,—if to reasonable men it had wanted any arguments to display its mischief and insufficiency. A device of the same kind was tried in my memory by Louis the Fifteenth, but it answered at no time. However, the necessities of ruinous wars were some excuse for desperate projects. The deliberations of calamity are rarely wise. But here was a season for disposition and providence. It was in a time of profound peace, then enjoyed for five years, and promising a much longer continuance, that they had recourse to this desperate trifling. They were sure to lose more reputation by sporting, in their serious situation, with these toys and playthings of finance, which have filled half their journals, than could possibly be compensated by the poor temporary supply which they afforded. It seemed as if those who adopted such projects were wholly ignorant of their circumstances, or wholly unequal to their necessities. Whatever virtue may be in these devices, it is obvious that neither the patriotic gifts nor the patriotic contribution can ever be resorted to again. The resources of public folly are soon exhausted. The whole, indeed, of their scheme of revenue is to make, by any artifice, an appearance of a full reservoir for the hour, whilst at the same time they cut off the springs and living fountains of perennial supply. The account not long since furnished by M. Necker was meant, without question, to be favorable. He gives a flattering view of the means of getting through the year; but he expresses, as it is natural he should, some apprehension for that which was to succeed. On this last prognostic, instead of entering into the grounds of this apprehension, in order, by a proper foresight, to prevent the prognosticated evil, M. Necker receives a sort of friendly reprimand from the President of the Assembly.

This kindness, a shaky result of weakness, was meant to be backed by another resource, the twin of the same foolishness. The patriotic donations were supposed to make up for the failure of the patriotic contributions. John Doe was to guarantee for Richard Roe. With this scheme, they took valuable things from the giver that were of relatively little worth to the receiver; they ruined several businesses; they stripped the crown of its jewels, the churches of their silver, and the people of their personal belongings. The creation of these young pretenders to freedom was really just a servile imitation of one of the poorest strategies of foolish tyranny. They took an old, oversized, full-bottomed wig from the outdated wardrobe of Louis the Fourteenth to hide the premature baldness of the National Assembly. They showcased this outdated formal foolishness, even though it had already been widely criticized in the Memoirs of the Duke de Saint-Simon—if reasonable people needed any proof of its harmfulness and inadequacy. A similar maneuver was attempted in my lifetime by Louis the Fifteenth, but it never succeeded. However, the demands of devastating wars were somewhat of an excuse for desperate plans. The discussions during times of disaster are rarely wise. But this was a moment for careful planning and provision. It was during a time of deep peace, which had lasted for five years and promised to last much longer, that they resorted to this desperate nonsense. They were bound to lose more credibility by playing around, in their serious situation, with these financial toys and trinkets that had filled half their reports, than could be compensated by the meager temporary relief they provided. It seemed as though those who supported such plans were completely unaware of their circumstances or completely unfit for their needs. Whatever merit these ideas might have, it's clear that neither the patriotic gifts nor the patriotic contributions can ever be relied upon again. The resources of public foolishness run out quickly. The entirety of their revenue scheme is to create, by any trick, the appearance of a full tank for the moment, while simultaneously cutting off the sources and living streams of continuous supply. The report recently provided by M. Necker was clearly intended to be favorable. He gives an optimistic view of the means to get through the year; however, he expresses, as is natural, some concern for what comes next. Instead of addressing the basis for this concern in order to prevent the predicted misfortune through proper foresight, M. Necker receives a kind of friendly reprimand from the President of the Assembly.

As to their other schemes of taxation, it is impossible to say anything of them with certainty, because they have not yet had their operation; but nobody is so sanguine as to imagine they will fill up any perceptible part of the wide gaping breach which their incapacity has made in their revenues. At present the state of their treasury sinks every day more and more in cash, and swells more and more in fictitious representation. When so little within or without is now found but paper, the representative not of opulence, but of want, the creature not of credit, but of power, they imagine that our flourishing state in England is owing to that bank-paper, and not the bank-paper to the flourishing condition of our commerce, to the solidity of our credit, and to the total exclusion of all idea of power from any part of the transaction. They forget that in England not one shilling of paper money of any description is received but of choice,—that the whole has had its origin in cash actually deposited,—and that it is convertible at pleasure, in an instant, and without the smallest loss, into cash again. Our paper is of value in commerce, because in law it is of none. It is powerful on 'Change, because in Westminster Hall it is impotent. In payment of a debt of twenty shillings a creditor may refuse all the paper of the Bank of England. Nor is there amongst us a single public security, of any quality or nature whatsoever, that is enforced by authority. In fact, it might be easily shown that our paper wealth, instead of lessening the real coin, has a tendency to increase it,—instead of being a substitute for money, it only facilitates its entry, its exit, and its circulation,—that it is the symbol of prosperity, and not the badge of distress. Never was a scarcity of cash and an exuberance of paper a subject of complaint in this nation.

As for their other tax plans, it's hard to say anything definite because they haven't been put into action yet. However, nobody really believes they will significantly close the huge gap their incompetence has created in revenues. Right now, their treasury declines more each day in actual cash and increases daily in fake representation. When there's hardly anything but paper around—representing not wealth, but need, and not credit, but authority—they mistakenly think that our thriving situation in England is due to that bank paper, rather than the bank paper being a result of our vibrant commerce, strong credit, and the complete absence of any notion of power in the transactions. They overlook that in England, no one accepts any form of paper money unless they choose to—it's all based on actual cash deposits—and it can immediately and effortlessly be converted back to cash without any loss. Our paper holds value in commerce because, legally, it doesn’t. It’s strong in trading because it’s weak in court. A creditor can refuse all Bank of England paper when it comes time to pay a debt of twenty shillings. There isn't a single public security among us, regardless of type, that is enforced by authority. In fact, it can be easily argued that our paper wealth, instead of reducing real coin, actually tends to increase it. Rather than replacing money, it simply makes it easier to enter, exit, and circulate. It represents prosperity, not distress. There has never been a complaint in this nation about a cash shortage alongside an abundance of paper.

Well! but a lessening of prodigal expenses, and the economy which has been introduced by the virtuous and sapient Assembly, make amends for the losses sustained in the receipt of revenue. In this at least they have fulfilled the duty of a financier.—Have those who say so looked at the expenses of the National Assembly itself? of the municipalities? of the city of Paris? of the increased pay of the two armies? of the new police? of the new judicatures? Have they even carefully compared the present pension-list with the former? These politicians have been cruel, not economical. Comparing the expenses of the former prodigal government and its relation to the then revenues with the expenses of this new system as opposed to the state of its new treasury, I believe the present will be found beyond all comparison more chargeable.[131]

Well! But cutting back on excessive spending and the budget management introduced by the wise and virtuous Assembly makes up for the revenue losses suffered. At least in this regard, they have done their job as financial managers. Have those who claim this really looked at the expenses of the National Assembly itself? The municipalities? The city of Paris? The increased pay for both armies? The new police force? The new courts? Have they even compared the current pension list with the previous one? These politicians have been harsh, not frugal. When comparing the expenses of the old extravagant government and its relation to the revenues at that time with the expenses of this new system against the state of its current treasury, I believe the present situation will be found to be much more costly.[131]

It remains only to consider the proofs of financial ability furnished by the present French managers when they are to raise supplies on credit. Here I am a little at a stand; for credit, properly speaking, they have none. The credit of the ancient government was not, indeed, the best; but they could always, on some terms, command money, not only at home, but from most of the countries of Europe where a surplus capital was accumulated; and the credit of that government was improving daily. The establishment of a system of liberty would of course be supposed to give it new strength: and so it would actually have done, if a system of liberty had been established. What offers has their government of pretended liberty had from Holland, from Hamburg, from Switzerland, from Genoa, from England, for a dealing in their paper? Why should these nations of commerce and economy enter into any pecuniary dealings with a people who attempt to reverse the very nature of things,—amongst whom they see the debtor prescribing at the point of the bayonet the medium of his solvency to the creditor, discharging one of his engagements with another, turning his very penury into his resource, and paying his interest with his rags?

It only remains to look at the evidence of financial ability provided by the current French managers when they want to secure supplies on credit. I'm a bit stuck here because, to be honest, they really don’t have any credit. The credit of the old government wasn't great, but they could still usually get money, not just locally, but from most European countries with excess capital; and their credit was actually getting better every day. The establishment of a system of liberty would presumably strengthen it: and it truly would have, if such a system had been put in place. What offers has their so-called liberty government received from Holland, Hamburg, Switzerland, Genoa, or England for dealing with their paper? Why would these commercial nations get involved in any financial dealings with people who are trying to turn everything upside down—where they see a debtor forcing the terms of payment on the creditor at gunpoint, settling one obligation with another, turning their hardship into a resource, and paying their interest with scraps?

Their fanatical confidence in the omnipotence of Church plunder has induced these philosophers to overlook all care of the public estate, just as the dream of the philosopher's stone induces dupes, under the more plausible delusion of the hermetic art, to neglect all rational means of improving their fortunes. With these philosophic financiers, this universal medicine made of Church mummy is to cure all the evils of the state. These gentlemen perhaps do not believe a great deal in the miracles of piety; but it cannot be questioned that they have an undoubting faith in the prodigies of sacrilege. Is there a debt which presses them? Issue assignats. Are compensations to be made or a maintenance decreed to those whom they have robbed of their freehold in their office or expelled from their profession? Assignats. Is a fleet to be fitted out? Assignats. If sixteen millions sterling of these assignats forced on the people leave the wants of the state as urgent as ever, Issue, says one, thirty millions sterling of assignats,—says another, Issue fourscore millions more of assignats. The only difference among their financial factions is on the greater or the lesser quantity of assignats to be imposed on the public sufferance. They are all professors of assignats. Even those whose natural good sense and knowledge of commerce, not obliterated by philosophy, furnish decisive arguments against this delusion, conclude their arguments by proposing the emission of assignats. I suppose they must talk of assignats, as no other language would be understood. All experience of their inefficacy does not in the least discourage them. Are the old assignats depreciated at market? What is the remedy? Issue new assignats.—Mais si maladia opiniatria non vult se garire, quid illi facere? Assignare; postea assignare; ensuita assignare. The word is a trifle altered. The Latin of your present doctors may be better than that of your old comedy; their wisdom and the variety of their resources are the same. They have not more notes in their song than the cuckoo; though, far from the softness of that harbinger of summer and plenty, their voice is as harsh and as ominous as that of the raven.

Their blind faith in the Church's ability to take from others has led these thinkers to ignore any responsibility for the public good, just as the quest for the philosopher's stone lures people into neglecting sensible ways to improve their lives. For these financial philosophers, this supposed miracle made from Church relics is meant to fix all the problems facing the state. These gentlemen might not fully believe in the miracles of faith; however, they definitely have unwavering faith in the wonders of theft. Are they facing a pressing debt? Just issue assignats. Are they supposed to make reparations or provide support to those they've stripped of their property or forced out of their jobs? Assignats. Is a fleet being prepared? Assignats. If sixteen million pounds worth of these assignats thrust upon the people still leave the state's needs unaddressed, one says to issue thirty million pounds of assignats, while another suggests issuing eighty million more of assignats. The only difference among their financial groups is about how many assignats to burden the public with. They all advocate for assignats. Even those whose common sense and understanding of commerce, not clouded by philosophical nonsense, provide strong arguments against this fantasy, end their points by suggesting the release of assignats. I guess they have to talk about assignats, as nothing else would make sense. All the past failures of these assignats do nothing to deter them. Are the old assignats losing value in the market? What's the solution? Issue new assignats. — But if this chronic illness refuses to be cured, what do they do? Assign more; then assign again; next, assign again. The term has only slightly changed. The Latin from today's doctors may be better than that of your old comedies; their wisdom and range of options are the same. They have no more variations in their tune than the cuckoo; though, far from the gentle voice of that herald of summer and abundance, their sound is as grating and foreboding as that of a raven.

Who but the most desperate adventurers in philosophy and finance could at all have thought of destroying the settled revenue of the state, the sole security for the public credit, in the hope of rebuilding it with the materials of confiscated property? If, however, an excessive zeal for the state should have led a pious and venerable prelate (by anticipation a father of the Church[132]) to pillage his own order, and, for the good of the Church and people, to take upon himself the place of grand financier of confiscation and comptroller-general of sacrilege, he and his coadjutors were, in my opinion, bound to show, by their subsequent conduct, that they knew something of the office they assumed. When they had resolved to appropriate to the fisc a certain portion of the landed property of their conquered country, it was their business to render their bank a real fund of credit,—as far as such a bank was capable of becoming so.

Who but the most desperate adventurers in philosophy and finance would ever consider destroying the established revenue of the state, the only security for public credit, in hopes of rebuilding it with confiscated property? Yet, if an excessive passion for the state drove a devout and respected church leader (in anticipation, a father of the Church[132]) to raid his own order and assume the role of chief financier of confiscation and general controller of sacrilege for the benefit of the Church and the people, he and his supporters were, in my opinion, obligated to demonstrate through their actions that they understood the responsibilities of the position they took on. Once they decided to allocate a portion of the land from their conquered territories to the treasury, it was their responsibility to turn their bank into a true credit fund—as much as such a bank could actually become one.

To establish a current circulating credit upon any land-bank, under any circumstances whatsoever, has hitherto proved difficult at the very least. The attempt has commonly ended in bankruptcy. But when the Assembly were led, through a contempt of moral, to a defiance of economical principles, it might at least have been expected that nothing would be omitted on their part to lessen this difficulty, to prevent any aggravation of this bankruptcy. It might be expected, that, to render your land-bank tolerable, every means would be adopted that could display openness and candor in the statement of the security, everything which could aid the recovery of the demand. To take things in their most favorable point of view, your condition was that of a man of a large landed estate which he wished to dispose of for the discharge of a debt and the supply of certain services. Not being able instantly to sell, you wished to mortgage. What would a man of fair intentions and a commonly clear understanding do in such circumstances? Ought he not first to ascertain the gross value of the estate, the charges of its management and disposition, the incumbrances perpetual and temporary of all kinds that affect it,—then, striking a net surplus, to calculate the just value of the security? When that surplus (the only security to the creditor) had been clearly ascertained, and properly vested in the hands of trustees, then he would indicate the parcels to be sold, and the time and conditions of sale; after this he would admit the public creditor, if he chose it, to subscribe his stock into this new fund,—or he might receive proposals for an assignat from those who would advance money to purchase this species of security. This would be to proceed like men of business, methodically and rationally, and on the only principles of public and private credit that have an existence. The dealer would then know exactly what he purchased; and the only doubt which could hang upon his mind would be the dread of the resumption of the spoil, which one day might be made (perhaps with an addition of punishment) from the sacrilegious gripe of those execrable wretches who could become purchasers at the auction of their innocent fellow-citizens.

Establishing a current circulating credit on any land bank, under any circumstances, has proven to be quite challenging, to say the least. Attempts have often ended in bankruptcy. However, when the Assembly was driven, out of a disregard for morals, to defy economic principles, it should have been expected that they would do everything possible to lessen this difficulty and prevent any further aggravation of the bankruptcy. It would be reasonable to expect that, to make your land bank viable, every effort would be made to ensure transparency and honesty in the presentation of the security, and everything that could assist in recovering the demand. To view it in the best light, your situation resembles that of a person with a large estate who wants to sell it to pay off a debt and cover specific expenses. Unable to sell immediately, you want to mortgage it. What would a fair-minded person with a clear understanding do in this situation? Shouldn't he first determine the total value of the estate, the costs of managing and selling it, and identify all the ongoing and temporary burdens affecting it—then, after calculating a net surplus, determine the true value of the security? Once that surplus (the only security for the creditor) is clearly established and properly entrusted to trustees, he would then specify the parcels to be sold, along with the timing and conditions of the sale; after that, he would allow any public creditor who is interested to subscribe their stock into this new fund—or they could submit proposals for an assignat from those willing to advance money to buy this type of security. This would be a methodical and rational approach, operating on the only principles of public and private credit that actually exist. The buyer would then know exactly what he is purchasing; and the only uncertainty in his mind would come from the fear of having the property taken back, possibly with additional penalties, from the hands of those __________ execrable wretches who could become buyers at the auction of their innocent fellow-citizens.

An open, and exact statement of the clear value of the property, and of the time, the circumstances, and the place of sale, were all necessary, to efface as much as possible the stigma that has hitherto been branded on every kind of land-bank. It became necessary on another principle,—that is, on account of a pledge of faith previously given on that subject, that their future fidelity in a slippery concern might be established by their adherence to their first engagement. When they had finally determined on a state resource from Church booty, they came, on the fourteenth of April, 1790, to a solemn resolution on the subject, and pledged themselves to their country, "that, in the statement of the public charges for each year, there should be brought to account a sum sufficient for defraying the expenses of the R.C.A. religion, the support of the ministers at the altars, the relief of the poor, the pensions to the ecclesiastics, secular as well as regular, of the one and of the other sex, in order that the estates and goods which are at the disposal of the nation may be disengaged of all charges, and employed by the representatives, or the legislative body, to the great and most pressing exigencies of the state." They further engaged, on the same day, that the sum necessary for the year 1791 should be forthwith determined.

An open and clear statement of the property's true value, along with the time, circumstances, and location of the sale, was essential to mitigate the negative perception associated with land banks. It was also important because of a promise made earlier regarding this issue; their credibility in a precarious matter depended on their commitment to their original promise. After deciding on a state resource derived from Church assets, they came to a formal resolution on April 14, 1790, pledging to their country that "in the report of public expenses for each year, a sufficient amount would be accounted for covering the costs of the R.C.A. religion, the support of ministers at the altars, assistance for the poor, and pensions for both secular and regular clergy, of all genders, so that the estates and assets available to the nation may be free from all charges and utilized by the representatives or the legislative body for the critical and most urgent needs of the state." They also committed, on the same day, to immediately determine the amount required for the year 1791.

In this resolution they admit it their duty to show distinctly the expense of the above objects, which, by other resolutions, they had before engaged should be first in the order of provision. They admit that they ought to show the estate clear and disengaged of all charges, and that they should show it immediately. Have they done this immediately, or at any time? Have they ever furnished a rent-roll of the immovable estate, or given in an inventory of the movable effects, which they confiscate to their assignats? In what manner they can fulfil their engagements of holding out to public service "an estate disengaged of all charges," without authenticating the value of the estate or the quantum of the charges, I leave it to their English admirers to explain. Instantly upon this assurance, and previously to any one step towards making it good, they issue, on the credit of so handsome a declaration, sixteen millions sterling of their paper. This was manly. Who, after this masterly stroke, can doubt of their abilities in finance?—But then, before any other emission of these financial indulgences, they took care at least to make good their original promise.—If such estimate, either of the value of the estate or the amount of the incumbrances, has been made, it has escaped me. I never heard of it.

In this resolution, they acknowledge their responsibility to clearly show the costs of the above items, which, in previous resolutions, they committed to prioritizing. They recognize that they should present the estate free of any charges and that they need to do this right away. Have they done this promptly, or at any time? Have they ever provided a rent-roll of the real estate, or supplied an inventory of the movable assets they have seized for their assignats? It’s up to their English supporters to explain how they can meet their promise of providing "an estate free of all charges" without verifying the estate's value or the amount of the charges. Immediately following this assurance, and before taking any steps to fulfill it, they issued, based on such a bold declaration, sixteen million pounds of their paper currency. That was impressive. Who, after this clever move, can doubt their financial skills?—But then, before any further release of these financial indulgences, they made sure to fulfill their original promise. If any estimate of the estate's value or the total amount of the encumbrances has been made, I haven’t seen it. I’ve never heard of it.

At length they have spoken out, and they have made a full discovery of their abominable fraud in holding out the Church lands as a security for any debts or any service whatsoever. They rob only to enable them to cheat; but in a very short time they defeat the ends both of the robbery and the fraud, by making out accounts for other purposes, which blow up their whole apparatus of force and of deception. I am obliged to M. de Calonne for his reference to the document which proves this extraordinary fact: it had by some means escaped me. Indeed, it was not necessary to make out my assertion as to the breach of faith on the declaration of the fourteenth of April, 1790. By a report of their committee it now appears that the charge of keeping up the reduced ecclesiastical establishments, and other expenses attendant on religion, and maintaining the religious of both sexes, retained or pensioned, and the other concomitant expenses of the same nature, which they have brought upon themselves by this convulsion in property, exceeds the income of the estates acquired by it in the enormous sum of two millions sterling annually,—besides a debt of seven millions and upwards. These are the calculating powers of imposture! This is the finance of philosophy! This is the result of all the delusions held out to engage a miserable people in rebellion, murder, and sacrilege, and to make them prompt and zealous instruments in the ruin of their country! Never did a state, in any case, enrich itself by the confiscations of the citizens. This new experiment has succeeded like all the rest. Every honest mind, every true lover of liberty and humanity, must rejoice to find that injustice is not always good policy, nor rapine the high-road to riches. I subjoin with pleasure, in a note, the able and spirited observations of M. de Calonne on this subject.[133]

At last, they’ve spoken up, revealing their outrageous fraud of using Church lands as collateral for any debts or services. They steal just to cheat; however, they quickly undermine both the theft and the fraud by creating accounts for other reasons, which exposes their entire scheme of force and deception. I thank M. de Calonne for pointing me to the document that proves this shocking fact: it had somehow slipped my mind. In fact, it wasn't necessary to back up my claim about the breach of faith regarding the declaration of April 14, 1790. According to their committee's report, it now shows that the costs of maintaining the reduced church institutions, and other religious expenses, including the support of both male and female clergy, whether retained or pensioned, alongside similar expenses they incurred due to this upheaval in property, exceed the income from the estates acquired during this time by a staggering two million pounds annually—on top of a debt of over seven million. These are the calculating powers of deceit! This is the philosophy of finance! This is the outcome of all the lies used to entangle a suffering people in rebellion, murder, and sacrilege, turning them into eager participants in the destruction of their country! Never has a state benefited from the confiscation of its citizens’ property. This new experiment has fared like all the others. Every honest person, every true lover of liberty and humanity, should be glad to see that injustice isn’t always smart policy, nor is plunder a path to wealth. I am happy to include, in a note, the insightful and forceful comments of M. de Calonne on this matter.[133]

In order to persuade the world of the bottomless resource of ecclesiastical confiscation, the Assembly have proceeded to other confiscations of estates in offices, which could not be done with any common color without being compensated out of this grand confiscation of landed property. They have thrown upon this fund, which was to show a surplus disengaged of all charges, a new charge, namely, the compensation to the whole body of the disbanded judicature, and of all suppressed offices and estates: a charge which I cannot ascertain, but which unquestionably amounts to many French millions. Another of the new charges is an annuity of four hundred and eighty thousand pounds sterling, to be paid (if they choose to keep faith) by daily payments, for the interest of the first assignats. Have they ever given themselves the trouble to state fairly the expense of the management of the Church lands in the hands of the municipalities, to whose care, skill, and diligence, and that of their legion of unknown under-agents, they have chosen to commit the charge of the forfeited estates, and the consequence of which had been so ably pointed out by the Bishop of Nancy?

To convince the world of the endless resource from church property confiscations, the Assembly has moved on to confiscating estates linked to positions, which couldn't be done fairly without compensating through this major land confiscation. They've added a new expense to this fund, which was supposed to be free of all charges, specifically the compensation for the entire disbanded judiciary and all the abolished offices and estates: an expense I can't specify, but it certainly amounts to millions in French currency. Another new charge is an annuity of four hundred eighty thousand pounds sterling, to be paid (if they decide to honor their commitments) through daily payments for the interest of the initial assignats. Have they ever taken the time to accurately assess the costs of managing the Church lands now in the hands of municipalities, which they entrusted to the care, skill, and diligence of countless unknown underlings, and the issues that the Bishop of Nancy had clearly pointed out?

But it is unnecessary to dwell on these obvious heads of incumbrance. Have they made out any clear state of the grand incumbrance of all, I mean the whole of the general and municipal establishments of all sorts, and compared it with the regular income by revenue? Every deficiency in these becomes a charge on the confiscated estate, before the creditor can plant his cabbages on an acre of Church property. There is no other prop than this confiscation to keep the whole state from tumbling to the ground. In this situation they have purposely covered all, that they ought industriously to have cleared, with a thick fog; and then, blindfold themselves, like bulls that shut their eyes when they push, they drive, by the point of the bayonets, their slaves, blindfolded indeed no worse than their lords, to take their fictions for currencies, and to swallow down paper pills by thirty-four millions sterling at a dose. Then they proudly lay in their claim to a future credit, on failure of all their past engagements, and at a time when (if in such a matter anything can be clear) it is clear that the surplus estates will never answer even the first of their mortgages,—I mean that of the four hundred millions (or sixteen millions sterling) of assignats. In all this procedure I can discern neither the solid sense of plain dealing nor the subtle dexterity of ingenious fraud. The objections within the Assembly to pulling up the flood-gates for this inundation of fraud are unanswered; but they are thoroughly refuted by an hundred thousand financiers in the street. These are the numbers by which the metaphysic arithmeticians compute. These are the grand calculations on which a philosophical public credit is founded in France. They cannot raise supplies; but they can raise mobs. Let them rejoice in the applauses of the club at Dundee for their wisdom and patriotism in having thus applied the plunder of the citizens to the service of the state. I hear of no address upon this subject from the directors of the Bank of England,—though their approbation would be of a little more weight in the scale of credit than that of the club at Dundee. But to do justice to the club, I believe the gentlemen who compose it to be wiser than they appear,—that they will be less liberal of their money than of their addresses, and that they would not give a dog's ear of their most rumpled and ragged Scotch paper for twenty of your fairest assignats.

But there's no need to focus on these obvious burdens. Have they figured out the full extent of the major burden, meaning all the general and local establishments, and compared it to the regular income from taxes? Any shortfall in these falls on the confiscated land before the creditor can even think about planting crops on Church property. This confiscation is the only support keeping the entire state from collapsing. In this situation, they have intentionally obscured everything they should have clarified, shrouding it in a thick fog; then, blindfolded like bulls that close their eyes when they charge, they push their blindfolded followers with bayonets to accept their fabrications as currency and swallow down paper money in doses of thirty-four million pounds. Then they confidently lay claim to future credit despite failing to meet all their past obligations, at a time when it’s clear that the surplus estates won’t even cover the first of their loans—specifically, the four hundred million (or sixteen million pounds) of assignats. In all this, I see neither straightforward honesty nor clever deceit. The objections within the Assembly to opening the floodgates for this wave of fraud go unanswered, yet they are convincingly refuted by a hundred thousand financiers out in the streets. These are the figures that metaphysical accountants compute. These are the major calculations upon which a rational public credit in France is built. They can't raise funds, but they can raise mobs. Let them enjoy the praise from the club in Dundee for their wisdom and patriotism in using this plunder from the citizens for the state's benefit. I haven't heard of any statement on this issue from the directors of the Bank of England—although their endorsement would weigh a bit more in terms of credit than that of the club in Dundee. However, to be fair to the club, I believe the members to be wiser than they seem—that they would be less generous with their money than with their statements, and that they wouldn't give a farthing of their poorest and most tattered Scottish paper for twenty of your finest assignats.

Early in this year the Assembly issued paper to the amount of sixteen millions sterling. What must have been the state into which the Assembly has brought your affairs, that the relief afforded by so vast a supply has been hardly perceptible? This paper also felt an almost immediate depreciation of five per cent, which in a little time came to about seven. The effect of these assignats on the receipt of the revenue is remarkable. M. Necker found that the collectors of the revenue, who received in coin, paid the treasury in assignats. The collectors made seven per cent by thus receiving in money, and accounting in depreciated paper. It was not very difficult to foresee that this must be inevitable. It was, however, not the less embarrassing. M. Necker was obliged (I believe, for a considerable part, in the market of London) to buy gold and silver for the mint, which amounted to about twelve thousand pounds above the value of the commodity gained. That minister was of opinion, that, whatever their secret nutritive virtue might be, the state could not live upon assignats alone,—that some real silver was necessary, particularly for the satisfaction of those who, having iron in their hands, were not likely to distinguish themselves for patience, when they should perceive, that, whilst an increase of pay was held out to them in real money, it was again to be fraudulently drawn back by depreciated paper. The minister, in this very natural distress, applied to the Assembly, that they should order the collectors to pay in specie what in specie they had received. It could not escape him, that, if the Treasury paid three per cent for the use of a currency which should be returned seven per cent worse than the minister issued it, such a dealing could not very greatly tend to enrich the public. The Assembly took no notice of his recommendation. They were in this dilemma: If they continued to receive the assignats, cash must become an alien to their Treasury; if the Treasury should refuse those paper amulets, or should discountenance them in any degree, they must destroy the credit of their sole resource. They seem, then, to have made their option, and to have given some sort of credit to their paper by taking it themselves; at the same time, in their speeches, they made a sort of swaggering declaration, something, I rather think, above legislative competence,—that is, that there is no difference in value between metallic money and their assignats. This was a good, stout, proof article of faith, pronounced under an anathema by the venerable fathers of this philosophic synod. Credat who will,—certainly not Judæus Apella.

Early this year, the Assembly issued paper money totaling sixteen million pounds. What must the state of your affairs be that the relief from such a massive supply has hardly been noticeable? This paper also experienced an almost immediate depreciation of five percent, which soon rose to about seven. The impact of these notes on revenue collection is striking. M. Necker discovered that revenue collectors, who received cash, were paying the treasury with these notes. The collectors made seven percent by accepting cash and reporting it in devalued paper. It wasn't hard to predict that this would happen. Still, it was quite problematic. M. Necker had to buy gold and silver for the mint, which cost about twelve thousand pounds more than the actual value of the material acquired. That minister believed that, regardless of their hidden value, the state could not only rely on these notes; real silver was essential, especially to satisfy those who, armed with weapons, wouldn't be inclined to wait patiently when they saw that, while a pay increase was promised in real money, it would again be deceitfully withheld through devalued paper. In this very understandable situation, the minister approached the Assembly, asking them to direct collectors to pay in cash for what they had received in cash. He noticed that if the Treasury paid three percent for using currency that was returned seven percent worse than it was issued, such a practice wouldn't significantly benefit the public. The Assembly ignored his suggestion. They found themselves in a bind: if they continued to accept the notes, cash would vanish from their Treasury; if the Treasury refused these paper "amulets" or discouraged them in any way, they would undermine the credibility of their only resource. They seemed to have made their choice, giving some level of credibility to their notes by accepting them themselves; at the same time, in their speeches, they made a bold declaration, which I believe exceeds their legislative authority—that there is no difference in value between real money and their notes. This served as a strong statement of faith, pronounced under a curse by the respected members of this philosophical assembly. Let whoever will believe it—certainly not Judæus Apella.

A noble indignation rises in the minds of your popular leaders, on hearing the magic-lantern in their show of finance compared to the fraudulent exhibitions of Mr. Law. They cannot bear to hear the sands of his Mississippi compared with the rock of the Church, on which they build their system. Pray let them suppress this glorious spirit, until they show to the world what piece of solid ground there is for their assignats, which they have not preoccupied by other charges. They do injustice to that great mother fraud, to compare it with their degenerate imitation. It is not true that Law built solely on a speculation concerning the Mississippi. He added the East India trade; he added the African trade; he added the farms of all the farmed revenue of France. All these together unquestionably could not support the structure which the public enthusiasm, not he, chose to build upon these bases. But these were, however, in comparison, generous delusions. They supposed, and they aimed at, an increase of the commerce of France. They opened to it the whole range of the two hemispheres. They did not think of feeding France from its own substance. A grand imagination found in this flight of commerce something to captivate. It was wherewithal to dazzle the eye of an eagle. It was not made to entice the smell of a mole, nuzzling and burying himself in his mother earth, as yours is. Men were not then quite shrunk from their natural dimensions by a degrading and sordid philosophy, and fitted for low and vulgar deceptions. Above all, remember, that, in imposing on the imagination, the then managers of the system made a compliment to the freedom of men. In their fraud there was no mixture of force. This was reserved to our time, to quench the little glimmerings of reason which might break in upon the solid darkness of this enlightened age.

A noble anger rises in the minds of your popular leaders when they hear their financial schemes compared to the fraudulent shows of Mr. Law. They can't stand to hear the sands of his Mississippi compared to the solid foundation of the Church, which supports their system. Please let them hold back this proud spirit until they can show the world what solid ground there is for their currency, which they haven't already burdened with other debts. They do a disservice to that great original fraud by comparing it to their poor imitation. It's not true that Law built purely on speculation about the Mississippi. He included the East India trade; he included the African trade; he included all the taxes from France's agricultural revenue. All these together definitely couldn't support the structure built upon these bases, a structure chosen by public enthusiasm, not him. However, these were generous illusions in comparison. They believed and aimed for an increase in France's commerce. They opened the entire world to it across two hemispheres. They didn’t just think about feeding France from its own resources. There was a grand imagination behind this leap in commerce that captivated people. It was something to dazzle the eye of an eagle. It wasn’t meant to attract the smell of a mole, burrowing into the earth, as yours is. People hadn’t completely shrunk from their natural heights due to a degrading and materialistic philosophy that made them fit for low and petty deceptions. Above all, remember that when it came to firing up the imagination, the managers of the system at that time paid homage to human freedom. In their fraud, there was no mix of force. That was left for our time, to snuff out the small sparks of reason that might break through the thick darkness of this enlightened age.

On recollection, I have said nothing of a scheme of finance which may be urged in favor of the abilities of these gentlemen, and which has been introduced with great pomp, though not yet finally adopted in the National Assembly. It comes with something solid in aid of the credit of the paper circulation; and much has been said of its utility and its elegance. I mean the project for coining into money the bells of the suppressed churches. This is their alchemy. There are some follies which baffle argument, which go beyond ridicule, and which excite no feeling in us but disgust; and therefore I say no more upon it.

Looking back, I haven't mentioned a financial scheme that supports the abilities of these gentlemen, which has been presented with a lot of fanfare but hasn't yet been officially accepted in the National Assembly. It offers something tangible to strengthen the credibility of the paper currency, and there's been a lot of talk about its usefulness and appeal. I'm referring to the idea of turning the bells from the closed churches into currency. This is their version of alchemy. Some absurdities are beyond argument, surpass ridicule, and only evoke feelings of disgust; so I won't say anything more about it.

It is as little worth remarking any farther upon all their drawing and re-drawing, on their circulation for putting off the evil day, on the play between the Treasury and the Caisse d'Escompte, and on all these old, exploded contrivances of mercantile fraud, now exalted into policy of state. The revenue will not be trifled with. The prattling about the rights of men will not be accepted in payment of a biscuit or a pound of gunpowder. Here, then, the metaphysicians descend from their airy speculations, and faithfully follow examples. What examples? The examples of bankrupts. But defeated, baffled, disgraced, when their breath, their strength, their inventions, their fancies desert them, their confidence still maintains its ground. In the manifest failure of their abilities, they take credit for their benevolence. When the revenue disappears in their hands, they have the presumption, in some of their late proceedings, to value themselves on the relief given to the people. They did not relieve the people. If they entertained such intentions, why did they order the obnoxious taxes to be paid? The people relieved themselves, in spite of the Assembly.

It's hardly worth commenting any further on all their drawing and re-drawing, on their schemes to delay the inevitable, on the back-and-forth between the Treasury and the Caisse d'Escompte, and on all these outdated and discredited tactics of financial deceit, now elevated to state policy. Revenue is not something to be toyed with. Talk about people's rights won't be accepted as payment for a biscuit or a pound of gunpowder. So here, the thinkers come down from their lofty ideas and look to real-life examples. What examples? The examples of bankrupts. But even when defeated, frustrated, and humiliated, when their energy, their strength, their inventions, and their ideas abandon them, their confidence still holds strong. In the clear failure of their abilities, they take credit for their supposed goodwill. When the revenue disappears in their hands, they have the nerve, in some of their recent actions, to pat themselves on the back for the aid given to the people. They did not help the people. If they had any genuine intentions, why did they impose the unpopular taxes to be paid? The people helped themselves, despite the Assembly.

But waiving all discussion on the parties who may claim the merit of this fallacious relief, has there been, in effect, any relief to the people in any form? M. Bailly, one of the grand agents of paper circulation, lets you into the nature of this relief. His speech to the National Assembly contained a high and labored panegyric on the inhabitants of Paris, for the constancy and unbroken resolution with which they have borne their distress and misery. A fine picture of public felicity! What! great courage and unconquerable firmness of mind to endure benefits and sustain redress? One would think, from the speech of this learned lord mayor, that the Parisians, for this twelvemonth past, had been suffering the straits of some dreadful blockade,—that Henry the Fourth had been stopping up the avenues to their supply, and Sully thundering with his ordnance at the gates of Paris,—when in reality they are besieged by no other enemies than their own madness and folly, their own credulity and perverseness. But M. Bailly will sooner thaw the eternal ice of his Atlantic regions than restore the central heat to Paris, whilst it remains "smitten with the cold, dry, petrific mace" of a false and unfeeling philosophy. Some time after this speech, that is, on the thirteenth of last August, the same magistrate, giving an account of his government at the bar of the same Assembly, expresses himself as follows:—"In the month of July, 1789," (the period of everlasting commemoration,) "the finances of the city of Paris were yet in good order; the expenditure was counterbalanced by the receipt, and she had at that time a million [forty thousand pounds sterling] in bank. The expenses which she has been constrained to incur, subsequent to the Revolution, amount to 2,500,000 livres. From these expenses, and the great falling off in the product of the free gifts, not only a momentary, but a total, want of money has taken place." This is the Paris upon whose nourishment, in the course of the last year, such immense sums, drawn from the vitals of all France, have been expended. As long as Paris stands in the place of ancient Rome, so long she will be maintained by the subject provinces. It is an evil inevitably attendant on the dominion of sovereign democratic republics. As it happened in Rome, it may survive that republican domination which gave rise to it. In that case despotism itself must submit to the vices of popularity. Rome, under her emperors, united the evils of both systems; and this unnatural combination was one great cause of her ruin.

But putting aside any debate about who deserves credit for this misguided relief, has there actually been any real help for the people in any form? M. Bailly, one of the main figures behind the paper currency system, reveals the true nature of this relief. His speech to the National Assembly included a lengthy praise of the people of Paris for their steadfastness and unyielding determination in the face of their struggles and suffering. What a lovely image of public happiness! What? Great bravery and unbreakable will to endure what they consider to be benefits and support? One might think, from this learned mayor’s speech, that the Parisians have been enduring a terrible blockade for the past year—that Henry the Fourth had blocked their supply routes and Sully was bombarding their gates—when, in reality, the only enemies they face are their own madness and foolishness, their own gullibility and stubbornness. Yet M. Bailly will thaw the eternal ice of his Atlantic regions faster than he will restore the warmth to Paris, as long as it remains "smitten with the cold, dry, petrifying mace" of a false and unfeeling philosophy. Some time after this speech, on August 13 of last year, the same official, reporting on his administration to the same Assembly, stated: “In July 1789” (a date for the history books), “the finances of the city of Paris were still in good order; the expenses were balanced by income, and at that time she had a million [forty thousand pounds sterling] in the bank. The costs she has been forced to incur, after the Revolution, amount to 2,500,000 livres. Because of these expenses, and the significant decrease in the revenue from free gifts, there is not only a temporary but a total shortage of funds.” This is the Paris that, over the past year, has consumed such enormous sums taken from the very heart of all France. As long as Paris continues to play the role of ancient Rome, she will be supported by her subject provinces. This is an unavoidable consequence of the rule of sovereign democratic republics. Just as in Rome, it may outlast the republican rule that brought it about. In that case, tyranny itself must bow to the flaws of popularity. Rome, under her emperors, combined the worst of both systems; and this unnatural mix was a major reason for her downfall.

To tell the people that they are relieved by the dilapidation of their public estate is a cruel and insolent imposition. Statesmen, before they valued themselves on the relief given to the people by the destruction of their revenue, ought first to have carefully attended to the solution of this problem:—Whether it be more advantageous to the people to pay considerably and to gain in proportion, or to gain little or nothing and to be disburdened of all contribution? My mind is made up to decide in favor of the first proposition. Experience is with me, and, I believe, the best opinions also. To keep a balance between the power of acquisition on the part of the subject and the demands he is to answer on the part of the state is the fundamental part of the skill of a true politician. The means of acquisition are prior in time and in arrangement. Good order is the foundation of all good things. To be enabled to acquire, the people, without being servile, must be tractable and obedient. The magistrate must have his reverence, the laws their authority. The body of the people must not find the principles of natural subordination by art rooted out of their minds. They must respect that property of which they cannot partake. They must labor to obtain what by labor can be obtained; and when they find, as they commonly do, the success disproportioned to the endeavor, they must be taught their consolation in the final proportions of eternal justice. Of this consolation whoever deprives them deadens their industry, and strikes at the root of all acquisition as of all conservation. He that does this is the cruel oppressor, the merciless enemy of the poor and wretched; at the same time that by his wicked speculations he exposes the fruits of successful industry and the accumulations of fortune to the plunder of the negligent, the disappointed, and the unprosperous.

Telling people that they’re better off because their public services are in ruins is a cruel and arrogant lie. Before officials take pride in saying they’re helping the people by cutting their funding, they should first seriously consider this question: Is it better for people to pay a lot and gain something in return, or to pay little or nothing and get nothing back? I’m convinced it’s better to pay and receive. Experience, and I believe sound opinions, support my view. Balancing how much people can earn with what the state demands from them is the essence of being a good politician. The means of earning should come first, both in time and structure. Good organization is the foundation of all good things. To be able to earn, people must be willing and compliant without being servile. The magistrate needs respect, and the laws need authority. The community must not lose the understanding of natural hierarchies. They should respect property they can’t own. They must work to achieve what can be gained through effort, and when they often see the results don't match their hard work, they need to learn to find comfort in the ultimate fairness of justice. Whoever takes away that comfort drains their motivation and attacks the basis of both earning and preserving wealth. That person is a harsh oppressor, a ruthless enemy of the poor and suffering, while their greedy actions put the rewards of hard work and the fruits of success at risk from those who are careless, disappointed, or struggling.

Too many of the financiers by profession are apt to see nothing in revenue but banks, and circulations, and annuities on lives, and tontines, and perpetual rents, and all the small wares of the shop. In a settled order of the state, these things are not to be slighted, nor is the skill in them to be held of trivial estimation. They are good, but then only good when they assume the effects of that settled order, and are built upon it. But when men think that these beggarly contrivances may supply a resource for the evils which result from breaking up the foundations of public order, and from causing or suffering the principles of property to be subverted, they will, in the ruin of their country, leave a melancholy and lasting monument of the effect of preposterous politics, and presumptuous, short-sighted, narrow-minded wisdom.

Too many people in finance tend to see revenue only as banks, cash flows, life annuities, tontines, perpetual rents, and other small transactions. In a stable society, these things shouldn’t be ignored, nor should the skill in managing them be considered trivial. They are beneficial, but only when they reflect the stability of that society and are built upon it. However, when individuals believe that these meager schemes can address the problems that arise from undermining public order and disrupting property rights, they will, in the downfall of their nation, leave behind a sad and lasting reminder of the consequences of misguided policies and short-sighted thinking.

The effects of the incapacity shown by the popular leaders in all the great members of the commonwealth are to be covered with the "all-atoning name" of Liberty. In some people I see great liberty, indeed; in many, if not in the most, an oppressive, degrading servitude. But what is liberty without wisdom and without virtue? It is the greatest of all possible evils; for it is folly, vice, and madness, without tuition or restraint. Those who know what virtuous liberty is cannot bear to see it disgraced by incapable heads, on account of their having high-sounding words in their mouths. Grand, swelling sentiments of liberty I am sure I do not despise. They warm the heart; they enlarge and liberalize our minds; they animate our courage in a time of conflict. Old as I am, I read the fine raptures of Lucan and Corneille with pleasure. Neither do I wholly condemn the little arts and devices of popularity. They facilitate the carrying of many points of moment; they keep the people together; they refresh the mind in its exertions; and they diffuse occasional gayety over the severe brow of moral freedom. Every politician ought to sacrifice to the Graces, and to join compliance with reason. But in such an undertaking as that in France all these subsidiary sentiments and artifices are of little avail. To make a government requires no great prudence. Settle the seat of power, teach obedience, and the work is done. To give freedom is still more easy. It is not necessary to guide; it only requires to let go the rein. But to form a free government, that is, to temper together these opposite elements of liberty and restraint in one consistent work, requires much thought, deep reflection, a sagacious, powerful, and combining mind. This I do not find in those who take the lead in the National Assembly. Perhaps they are not so miserably deficient as they appear. I rather believe it. It would put them below the common level of human understanding. But when the leaders choose to make themselves bidders at an auction of popularity, their talents, in the construction of the state, will be of no service. They will become flatterers instead of legislators,—the instruments, not the guides of the people. If any of them should happen to propose a scheme of liberty soberly limited, and defined with proper qualifications, he will be immediately outbid by his competitors, who will produce something more splendidly popular. Suspicions will be raised of his fidelity to his cause. Moderation will be stigmatized as the virtue of cowards, and compromise as the prudence of traitors,—until, in hopes of preserving the credit which may enable him to temper and moderate on some occasions, the popular leader is obliged to become active in propagating doctrines and establishing powers that will afterwards defeat any sober purpose at which he ultimately might have aimed.

The effects of the incompetence displayed by popular leaders across all major parts of the commonwealth are disguised with the so-called "all-atoning name" of Liberty. Some people truly embody great liberty; for many, if not most, it’s just an oppressive, degrading servitude. But what is liberty without wisdom and virtue? It's the worst kind of evil because it leads to foolishness, vice, and madness without guidance or limits. Those who understand what virtuous liberty means cannot stand to see it tarnished by inept leaders simply because they use impressive language. I definitely don’t dismiss grand, lofty ideas of liberty. They inspire us, expand our minds, and fuel our courage during tough times. Even at my age, I still enjoy reading the passionate works of Lucan and Corneille. I don't completely disapprove of the little tricks and tactics used to gain popularity either. They help push important issues forward, keep the people united, energize our minds in their efforts, and bring some lightness to the serious nature of moral freedom. Every politician should pay attention to the subtleties and balance reasoning with appeal. But in a situation like that in France, all these minor sentiments and strategies don’t have much impact. Creating a government doesn’t require much wisdom. Establish the seat of power, teach obedience, and the job is done. Granting freedom is even easier. It doesn’t require guidance; just let loose. However, establishing a free government—that is, blending together these opposing forces of liberty and restraint into a cohesive structure—demands considerable thought, deep reflection, and a keen, powerful, and synthesizing mind. I don’t see that in those leading the National Assembly. They may not be as utterly deficient as they seem, and I actually believe that. It would place them below the average level of human understanding. But when leaders choose to participate in a popularity contest, their skills in building the state become useless. They end up as flatterers instead of legislators—servants, not leaders of the people. If any of them proposes a plan for liberty that’s carefully limited and properly qualified, they’ll quickly be outdone by rivals offering something more spectacularly appealing. Doubts about their loyalty to their cause will arise. Moderation will be labeled as cowardice, and compromise as treachery—even as, in hopes of maintaining a reputation that allows them to temper and moderate at times, the popular leader ends up actively promoting ideas and establishing powers that will ultimately thwart any sensible goals they might have aimed for.


But am I so unreasonable as to see nothing at all that deserves commendation in the indefatigable labors of this Assembly? I do not deny, that, among an infinite number of acts of violence and folly, some good may have been done. They who destroy everything certainly will remove some grievance. They who make everything new have a chance that they may establish something beneficial. To give them credit for what they have done in virtue of the authority they have usurped, or to excuse them in the crimes by which that authority has been acquired, it must appear that the same things could not have been accomplished without producing such a revolution. Most assuredly they might; because almost every one of the regulations made by them, which is not very equivocal, was either in the cession of the king, voluntarily made at the meeting of the States, or in the concurrent instructions to the orders. Some usages have been abolished on just grounds; but they were such, that, if they had stood as they were to all eternity, they would little detract from the happiness and prosperity of any state. The improvements of the National Assembly are superficial, their errors fundamental.

But am I really so unreasonable as to see nothing worthwhile in the tireless efforts of this Assembly? I don’t deny that, amid countless acts of violence and foolishness, some good may have been achieved. Those who tear everything down will certainly eliminate some issues. Those who create something new have a shot at establishing something beneficial. To give them credit for what they’ve done with the authority they’ve taken for themselves, or to excuse them for the wrongs committed to gain that authority, it has to be clear that the same outcomes couldn’t have been achieved without causing such a revolution. They absolutely could have been; because almost all of the regulations they’ve created, which aren’t very ambiguous, were either part of the king’s concession, which he voluntarily made during the meeting of the States, or in the agreed instructions to the orders. Some practices have been abolished for good reasons; however, they were such that, if they had remained unchanged forever, they wouldn’t significantly detract from the happiness and prosperity of any state. The changes made by the National Assembly are superficial, while their mistakes are fundamental.

Whatever they are, I wish my countrymen rather to recommend to our neighbors the example of the British Constitution than to take models from them for the improvement of our own. In the former they have got an invaluable treasure. They are not, I think, without some causes of apprehension and complaint; but these they do not owe to their Constitution, but to their own conduct. I think our happy situation owing to our Constitution,—but owing to the whole of it, and not to any part singly,—owing in a great measure to what we have left standing in our several reviews and reformations, as well as to what we have altered or superadded. Our people will find employment enough for a truly patriotic, free, and independent spirit, in guarding what they possess from violation. I would not exclude alteration neither; but even when I changed, it should be to preserve. I should be led to my remedy by a great grievance. In what I did, I should follow the example of our ancestors. I would make the reparation as nearly as possible in the style of the building. A politic caution, a guarded circumspection, a moral rather than a complexional timidity, were among the ruling principles of our forefathers in their most decided conduct. Not being illuminated with the light of which the gentlemen of France tell us they have got so abundant a, share, they acted under a strong impression of the ignorance and fallibility of mankind. He that had made them thus fallible rewarded them for having in their conduct attended to their nature. Let us imitate their caution, if we wish to deserve their fortune or to retain their bequests. Let us add, if we please, but let us preserve what they have left; and standing on the firm ground of the British Constitution, let us be satisfied to admire, rather than attempt to follow in their desperate flights, the aëronauts of France.

Whatever they are, I wish my fellow countrymen would recommend the British Constitution as an example to our neighbors rather than taking inspiration from them to improve our own. The British have something truly valuable. While they do have reasons to feel worried and complain, those issues aren't caused by their Constitution but rather by their own actions. I believe our fortunate situation comes from our Constitution — from all of it, not just one part — and largely from what we've kept in our various reviews and reforms, as well as from what we've changed or added. Our people will have plenty to do in a genuinely patriotic, free, and independent spirit by protecting what they have from being violated. I wouldn’t rule out changes either; but when I do change something, it should be to preserve what is important. Any modifications I make should come from significant grievances. In my actions, I’d follow the examples set by our ancestors. I would aim to make adjustments in a way that aligns with the original structure. A wise caution, careful consideration, and a moral rather than anxious timidity were key principles for our forefathers in their most decisive actions. Lacking the enlightenment that the gentlemen of France claim to possess so abundantly, they acted with a strong awareness of human ignorance and fallibility. Those who made them fallible rewarded them for having acted according to their human nature. Let’s emulate their caution if we want to earn their fortune or maintain their legacy. Let’s add improvements if we want, but let’s preserve what they have left; and standing firmly on the British Constitution, let’s be content to admire rather than trying to follow the reckless pursuits of the French aeronauts.

I have told you candidly my sentiments. I think they are not likely to alter yours. I do not know that they ought. You are young; you cannot guide, but must follow, the fortune of your country. But hereafter they may be of some use to you, in some future form which your commonwealth may take. In the present it can hardly remain; but before its final settlement, it may be obliged to pass, as one of our poets says, "through great varieties of untried being," and in all its transmigrations to be purified by fire and blood.

I’ve honestly shared my feelings with you. I don’t think they’ll change how you feel. I’m not sure they should. You’re young; you can’t lead, but you have to follow the fate of your country. But later, they might be helpful to you in some future form that your nation might take. Right now, it’s unlikely to stay the same; however, before it reaches a final resolution, it might have to go through, as one of our poets puts it, "many varied and untested experiences," and in all its transformations, it will be cleansed by fire and blood.

I have little to recommend my opinions but long observation and much impartiality. They come from one who has been no tool of power, no flatterer of greatness, and who in his last acts does not wish to belie the tenor of his life. They come from one almost the whole of whose public exertion has been a struggle for the liberty of others,—from one in whose breast no anger durable or vehement has ever been kindled but by what he considered as tyranny, and who snatches from his share in the endeavors which are used by good men to discredit opulent oppression the hours he has employed on your affairs, and who in so doing persuades himself he has not departed from his usual office. They come from one who desires honors, distinctions, and emoluments but little, and who expects them not at all,—who has no contempt for fame, and no fear of obloquy,—who shuns contention, though he will hazard an opinion; from one who wishes to preserve consistency, but who would preserve consistency by varying his means to secure the unity of his end,—and, when the equipoise of the vessel in which he sails may be endangered by overloading it upon one side, is desirous of carrying the small weight of his reasons to that which may preserve its equipoise.

I don’t have much to support my opinions other than long observation and a fair perspective. They come from someone who has never been a tool of power, never a flatterer of those in high places, and who, in his final actions, doesn’t want to contradict the essence of his life. They come from someone whose entire public effort has been a fight for the freedom of others—a person whose heart has never been ignited with lasting or intense anger except for what he views as tyranny. He takes time away from his own pursuits to contribute to the efforts that good people make against wealthy oppression, believing that in doing so, he hasn’t strayed from his usual role. They come from someone who desires honors, distinctions, and rewards very little, and expects them not at all—someone who doesn’t despise fame and isn’t afraid of criticism—who avoids conflict, even though he will express his opinion; from someone who wants to maintain consistency but is willing to change his approach to ensure the unity of his goals—and when the balance of the vessel he sails may be threatened by overload on one side, seeks to adjust the small weight of his reasoning to restore its stability.

FOOTNOTES:

[77] Ps. cxlix.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Ps. 149.

[78] Discourse on the Love of our Country, Nov. 4, 1789, by Dr. Richard Price, 3d edition, p. 17 and 18.

[78] A Talk About the Love of Our Country, Nov. 4, 1789, by Dr. Richard Price, 3rd edition, p. 17 and 18.

[79] "Those who dislike that mode of worship which is prescribed by public authority ought, if they can find no worship out of the Church which they approve, to set up a separate worship for themselves; and by doing this, and giving an example of a rational and manly worship, men of weight from their rank and literature may do the greatest service to society and the world."—P. 18, Dr. Price's Sermon.

[79] "Those who don't appreciate the method of worship mandated by the government should, if they can't find any worship outside of the Church that they agree with, set up their own separate worship. By doing this and demonstrating a rational and dignified way of worship, individuals of significance based on their status and education can provide the greatest benefit to society and the world."—P. 18, Dr. Price's Sermon.

[80] P. 34, Discourse on the Love of our Country, by Dr. Price.

[80] P. 34, Discourse on the Love of Our Country, by Dr. Price.

[81] 1st Mary, sess. 3, ch. 1.

[81] 1st Mary, sess. 3, ch. 1.

[82] "That King James the Second, having endeavored to subvert the Constitution of the kingdom, by breaking the original contract between king and people, and, by the advice of Jesuits and other wicked persons, having violated the fundamental laws, and having withdrawn himself out of the kingdom, hath abdicated the government, and the throne is thereby vacant."

[82] "King James the Second, by trying to undermine the Constitution of the kingdom and breaking the original agreement between the king and the people, along with the influence of Jesuits and other corrupt individuals, has violated the fundamental laws and has withdrawn himself from the kingdom, thereby abdicating the government, which leaves the throne vacant."

[83] P. 23, 23, 24.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ pp. 23-24.

[84] See Blackstone's Magna Charta, printed at Oxford, 1759.

[84] Check out Blackstone's Magna Charta, published in Oxford, 1759.

[85] 1 W. and M.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 1 W. and M.

[86] Ecclesiasticus, chap, xxxviii. ver. 24, 25. "The wisdom of a learned man cometh by opportunity of leisure: and he that hath little business shall become wise. How can he get wisdom that holdeth the plough, and that glorieth in the goad; that driveth oxen, and is occupied in their labors, and whose talk is of bullocks?"

[86] Ecclesiasticus, chap, xxxviii. ver. 24, 25. "The wisdom of a knowledgeable person comes from having free time: someone with little to do will become wise. How can someone gain wisdom if they are busy plowing, taking pride in their tools, driving oxen, and focused on their work, whose conversations revolve around cattle?"

Ver. 27. "So every carpenter and workmaster, that laboreth night and day," &c.

Ver. 27. "So every carpenter and craftsman, who works night and day," &c.

Ver. 33. "They shall not be sought for in public counsel, nor sit high in the congregation: they shall not sit on the judge's seat, nor understand the sentence of judgment: they cannot declare justice and judgment, and they shall not be found where parables are spoken."

Ver. 33. "They won’t be consulted in public matters, nor take prominent positions in the community: they won’t sit in judgment, nor grasp the meaning of rulings: they can’t declare justice and fairness, and they won’t be found where stories with deeper meanings are told."

Ver. 34. "But they will maintain the state of the world."

Ver. 34. "But they will uphold the condition of the world."

I do not determine whether this book be canonical, as the Gallican Church (till lately) has considered it, or apocryphal, as here it is taken. I am sure it contains a great deal of sense and truth.

I don't judge whether this book is considered canonical, as the Gallican Church (until recently) has viewed it, or apocryphal, as it is regarded here. I know it holds a lot of sense and truth.

[87] Discourse on the Love of our Country, 3rd edit p. 39.

[87] Discussion on the Love of Our Country, 3rd ed. p. 39.

[88] Another of these reverend gentlemen, who was witness to some of the spectacles which Paris has lately exhibited, expresses himself thus:—"A king dragged in submissive triumph by his conquering subjects is one of those appearances of grandeur which seldom rise in the prospect of human affairs, and which, during the remainder of my life, I shall think of with wonder and gratification." These gentlemen agree marvellously in their feelings.

[88] Another one of these respected individuals, who witnessed some of the events recently seen in Paris, expressed himself like this:—"A king being led in humble triumph by his victorious subjects is one of those displays of greatness that rarely occurs in human history, and which, for the rest of my life, I will remember with amazement and satisfaction." These individuals share their sentiments remarkably.

[89] State Trials, Vol. II. p. 360, 363.

[89] State Trials, Vol. II. p. 360, 363.

[90] 6th of October, 1789.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ October 6, 1789.

[91] "Tous les Évêques à la lanterne!"

[91] "All the Bishops to the light!"

[92] It is proper here to refer to a letter written upon this subject by an eyewitness. That eyewitness was one of the most honest, intelligent, and eloquent members of the National Assembly, one of the most active and zealous reformers of the state. He was obliged to secede from the Assembly; and he afterwards became a voluntary exile, on account of the horrors of this pious triumph, and the dispositions of men, who, profiting of crimes, if not causing them, have taken the lead in public affairs.

[92] It's important to mention a letter written about this topic by someone who saw it firsthand. This person was one of the most honest, intelligent, and articulate members of the National Assembly, and one of the most committed and passionate reformers in the country. He had to leave the Assembly, and later became a voluntary exile due to the horrors of this so-called righteous victory and the attitudes of those who, whether by committing crimes or benefiting from them, have taken charge of public affairs.

Extract of M. de Lally Tollendal's Second Letter to a Friend.

Extract of M. de Lally Tollendal's Second Letter to a Friend.

"Parlons du parti que j'ai pris; il est bien justifé dans ma conscience.—Ni cette ville coupable, ni cette assemblée plus coupable encore, ne méritoient que je me justifie; mais j'ai à cœur que vous, et les personnes qui pensent comme vous, ne me condamnent pas.—Ma santé, je vous jure, me rendoit mes fonctions impossibles; mais même en les mettant de côté il a été au-dessus de mes forces de supporter plus longtems l'horreur que me causoit ce sang,—ces têtes,—cette reine presque egorgée,—ce roi, amené esclave, entrant à Paris au milieu de ses assassins, et précédé des têtes de ses malheureux gardes,—ces perfides janissaires, ces assassins, ces femmes cannibales,—ce cri de TOUS LES ÉVÊQUES À LA LANTERNE, dans le moment où le roi entre sa capitale avec deux évêques de son conseil dans sa voiture,—un coup de fusil, que j'ai vu tirer dans un des carrosses de la reine,—M. Bailly appellant cela un beau jour,—l'assemblée ayant déclaré froidement le matin, qu'il n'étoit pas de sa dignité d'aller toute entière environner le roi,—M. Mirabeau disant impunément dans cette assemblée, que le vaisseau de l'état, loin d'être arrêté dans sa course, s'élanceroit avec plus de rapidité que jamais vers sa régénération,—M. Barnave, riant avec lui, quand des flots de sang couloient autour de nous,—le vertueux Mounier[A] échappant par miracle à vingt assassins, qui avoient voulu faire de sa tête un trophée de plus: Voilà ce qui me fit jurer de ne plus mettre le pied dans cette caverne d'Antropophages [The National Assembly], où je n'avois plus de force d'élever la voix, où depuis six semaines je l'avois élevée en vain.

"Let's talk about the stance I've taken; it's well justified in my conscience. Neither this guilty city nor this even guiltier assembly deserved my justification; however, I care that you and those who think like you do not condemn me. My health, I swear, made my duties impossible; but even setting that aside, it has been beyond my strength to endure any longer the horror caused by this blood—these heads—this queen almost slashed—this king, brought in as a slave, entering Paris amidst his assassins, preceded by the heads of his unfortunate guards—those treacherous janissaries, those murderers, those cannibal women—this cry of ALL THE BISHOPS TO THE LANTERN, just as the king enters his capital with two bishops from his council in his carriage— a gunshot that I saw fired from one of the queen's carriages—Mr. Bailly calling it a beautiful day—the assembly having calmly declared in the morning that it was not dignified to surround the king in full—Mr. Mirabeau shamelessly saying in this assembly that the vessel of the state, far from being halted in its course, would surge forward faster than ever towards its regeneration—Mr. Barnave laughing with him while rivers of blood flowed around us—the virtuous Mounier[A] escaping by miracle from twenty assassins who wanted to make his head another trophy: This is what made me swear never again to set foot in this cavern of cannibals [The National Assembly], where I had no more strength to raise my voice, having raised it in vain for six weeks."

"Moi, Mounier, et tous les honnêtes gens, ont pensé que le dernier effort à faire pour le bien étoit d'en sortir. Aucune idée de crainte ne s'est approchée de moi. Je rougirois de m'en défendre. J'avois encore reçû sur la route de la part de ce peuple, moins coupable que ceux qui l'ont enivré de fureur, des acclamations, et des applaudissements, dont d'autres auroient été flattés, et qui m'ont fait frémir. C'est à l'indignation, c'est à l'horreur, c'est aux convulsions physiques, que le seul aspect du sang me fait éprouver que j'ai cédé. On brave une seule mort; on la brave plusieurs fois, quand elle peut être utile. Mais aucune puissance sous le ciel, mais aucune opinion publique ou privée n'ont le droit de me condamner à souffrir inutilement mille supplices par minute, et à périr de désespoir, de rage, au milieu des triomphes, du crime que je n'ai pu arrêter. Ils me proscriront, ils confisqueront mes biens. Je labourerai la terre, et je ne les verrai plus. Voilà ma justification. Vous pourrez la lire, la montrer, la laisser copier; tant pis pour ceux qui ne la comprendront pas; ce ne sera alors moi qui auroit eu tort de la leur donner."

"Me, Mounier, and all decent people believed that the final effort for the greater good was to leave it behind. I felt no fear whatsoever. I would be embarrassed to defend myself against it. Still, along the way, I received cheers and applause from this people, less guilty than those who have intoxicated them with fury, which would have flattered others and made me shudder. It is to indignation, horror, and physical convulsions that the mere sight of blood makes me yield. One can mock death once; one mocks it multiple times when it can be useful. But no power under heaven, nor any public or private opinion, has the right to condemn me to suffer a thousand tortures per minute and to die of despair and rage amidst the triumphs and the crime that I could not stop. They will banish me and confiscate my belongings. I will work the land, and I will not see them again. That is my justification. You can read it, show it, let it be copied; too bad for those who don’t understand it; it will not be me who was wrong for giving it to them."

This military man had not so good nerves as the peaceable gentlemen of the Old Jewry.—See Mons. Mounier's narrative of these transactions: a man also of honor and virtue and talents, and therefore a fugitive.

This soldier didn't have the same composure as the calm gentlemen of the Old Jewry.—See Mons. Mounier's account of these events: a man of honor, virtue, and talent, and for that reason, a fugitive.

[A] N.B.M. Mounier was then speaker of the National Assembly. He has since been obliged to live in exile, though one of the firmest assertors of liberty.

[A] N.B.M. Mounier was the speaker of the National Assembly at that time. He has since been forced into exile, despite being one of the strongest advocates for freedom.

[93] See the fate of Bailly and Condorcet, supposed to be here particularly alluded to. Compare the circumstances of the trial and execution of the former with this prediction.

[93] Look at what happened to Bailly and Condorcet, which is supposedly mentioned here. Compare the details of the trial and execution of the former with this prediction.

[94] The English are, I conceive, misrepresented in a letter published in one of the papers, by a gentleman thought to be a Dissenting minister. When writing to Dr. Price of the spirit which prevails at Paris, he says,—"The spirit of the people in this place has abolished all the proud distinctions which the king and nobles had usurped in their minds: whether they talk of the king, the noble, or the priest, their whole language is that of the most enlightened and liberal amongst the English." If this gentleman means to confine the terms enlightened and liberal to one set of men in England, it may be true. It is not generally so.

[94] I think the English are misrepresented in a letter published in one of the papers by a gentleman believed to be a dissenting minister. While writing to Dr. Price about the spirit that exists in Paris, he states, “The spirit of the people here has eliminated all the proud distinctions that the king and nobles had claimed in their minds: whether they discuss the king, the noble, or the priest, their entire way of speaking reflects the most enlightened and liberal among the English.” If this gentleman intends to limit the terms enlightened and liberal to a specific group of people in England, that might be accurate. But it isn’t generally the case.

[95] Sit igitur hoc ab initio persuasum civibus, dominos esse omnium rerum ac moderatores deos; eaque, quæ gerantur, eorum geri vi, ditione, ac numine; eosdemque optime de genere hominum mereri; et qualis quisque sit, quid agat, quid in se admittat, qua mente, qua pietate colat religiones intueri: piorum et impiorum habere rationem. His enim rebus imbutæ mentes haud sane abhorrebunt ab utili et a vera sententia.—Cic. de Legibus, l. 2.

[95] So let it be understood from the very beginning by the citizens that the gods are the masters and rulers of all things; and that whatever happens is done through their power, authority, and divine will; and they certainly deserve the best from humankind; and how each person is, what actions they take, what they allow within themselves, and with what mindset and piety they observe the religions to consider the distinction between the righteous and the wicked. For with these ideas in mind, their thoughts will not stray far from what is useful and the true principles. —Cic. de Legibus, l. 2.

[96] Quicquid multis peccatur inultum.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Whatever is wrong goes unpunished.

[97] This (down to the end of the first sentence in the next paragraph) and some other parts, here and there, were inserted, on his reading the manuscript, by my lost son.

[97] This (up to the end of the first sentence in the next paragraph) along with a few other sections, placed here and there, were added by my late son after he read the manuscript.

[98] I do not choose to shock the feeling of the moral reader with any quotation of their vulgar, base, and profane language.

[98] I don't want to offend the moral reader by quoting their crude, low, and disrespectful language.

[99] Their connection with Turgot and almost all the people of the finance.

[99] Their relationship with Turgot and nearly everyone involved in finance.

[100] All have been confiscated in their turn.

[100] They have all been taken away in their turn.

[101] Not his brother, nor any near relation; but this mistake does not affect the argument.

[101] Not his brother, nor any close relative; but this mistake doesn't change the argument.

[102] The rest of the passage is this:—

[102] The rest of the passage is this:—

"Who, after using up the riches of his crown,
Condemns their luxury to satisfy his own. And yet this action, to cover up the shame Of sacrilege, must carry the name of Devotion.
No crime is so bold that it wouldn't be understood. A real, or at least a seemingly good. Who doesn't fear doing wrong, yet is afraid of the name, And free from guilt, is a slave to popularity.
In this way, he both protects and undermines the Church: But princes' swords are sharper than their words. And so he makes amends for the past ages,
Their charity destroys, while their faith protects.
Then did Religion in a cozy space,
In empty, light thoughts, stay; And like the block, remained unmoved: but ours,
Too active, like the stork that feeds. Is there no temperate region that can be known? Between their cold zone and our hot zone? Could we not wake up from that sluggish dream,
But to be even more restless? And for that laziness, there was no concern,
But to be thrown into a calenture?
Can knowledge be limitless, or must it progress? So far, to make us long for ignorance,
And instead, we feel our way through the darkness,
Then, led by a misguided guide, to make mistakes during the day? Who looks at these gloomy piles, but would ask Which brutal invader raided the land? But when he hears that neither a Goth nor a Turk brought This emptiness, yet a Christian king,
When all that's left is the name of zeal
Between our best actions and their worst,
What does he believe our wrongdoing would save,
When do the effects of our devotions happen?
Cooper's Hill, by Sir JOHN DENHAM.

[103] Rapport de Mons. le Directeur-Général des Finances, fait par Ordre du Roi à Versailles. Mai 5, 1789.

[103] Report from Mr. the Director-General of Finances, made by Order of the King in Versailles. May 5, 1789.

[104] In the Constitution of Scotland, during the Stuart reigns, a committee sat for preparing bills; and none could pass, but those previously approved by them. This committee was called Lords of Articles.

[104] In the Constitution of Scotland, during the Stuart reigns, a committee met to prepare bills; and none could be passed unless they were previously approved by this committee. This committee was known as the Lords of Articles.

[105] When I wrote this I quoted from memory, after many years had elapsed from my reading the passage. A learned friend has found it and it is as follows:—

[105] When I wrote this, I quoted from memory after many years had passed since I read the passage. A knowledgeable friend has located it, and it is as follows:—

τὸ ἠ̂θος τὸ αὐτό, καὶ ἄμφω δεσποτικὰ τω̂ν βελτιόνων, καὶ τὰ ψηφίσματα ὥσπερ ἐκει̂ τὰ ἐπιτάγματα, καὶ ὁ δημαγωγὸς καὶ ὁ κόλαξ οἱ αὐτοὶ καὶ ἀνάλογον. καὶ μάλιστα δ' ἑκάτεροι παρ' ἑκατέροις ἰσχύουσιν, οἱ μὲν κόλακες παρὰ τοι̂ς τυράννοις, οἱ δὲ δημαγωγοὶ παρὰ τοι̂ς δήμοις τοι̂ς τοιούτοις.

τὸ ἠθος τὸ αὐτό, καὶ ἄμφω δεσποτικὰ τω̂ν βελτιόνων, καὶ τὰ ψηφίσματα ὥσπερ ἐκει̂ τὰ ἐπιτάγματα, καὶ ὁ δημαγωγὸς καὶ ὁ κόλαξ οἱ αὐτοὶ καὶ ἀνάλογον. καὶ μάλιστα δ' ἑκάτεροι παρ' ἑκατέροις ἰσχύουσιν, οἱ μὲν κόλακες παρὰ τοι̂ς τυράννοις, οἱ δὲ δημαγωγοὶ παρὰ τοι̂ς δήμοις τοι̂ς τοιούτοις.

"The ethical character is the same: both exercise despotism over the better class of citizens; and decrees are in the one what ordinances and arrêts are in the other: the demagogue, too, and the court favorite, are not unfrequently the same identical men, and always bear a close analogy; and these have the principal power, each in their respective forms of government, favorites with the absolute monarch, and demagogues with a people such as I have described."—Arist. Politic. lib. iv. cap. 4.

"The ethical character is the same: both exert control over the more virtuous citizens; and decrees in one are like ordinances and rulings in the other. The demagogue and the court favorite are often the same people and always show a strong resemblance; they hold the main power, each in their own type of government—favorites with the absolute monarch and demagogues with a public like the one I've described."—Arist. Politic. lib. iv. cap. 4.

[106] De l'Administration des Finances de la France, par Mons. Necker, Vol. I. p. 288.

[106] On the Administration of Finance in France, by Mr. Necker, Volume I, p. 288.

[107] De l'Administration des Finances de la France, par M. Necker.

[107] On the Administration of the Finances of France, by M. Necker.

[108] Vol. III. chap. 8 and chap. 9.

[108] Vol. III. chap. 8 and chap. 9.

[109] The world is obliged to M. de Calonne for the pains he has taken to refute the scandalous exaggerations relative to some of the royal expenses, and to detect the fallacious account given of pensions, for the wicked purpose of provoking the populace to all sorts of crimes.

[109] The world owes a debt of gratitude to M. de Calonne for the effort he has made to counter the outrageous exaggerations about certain royal expenses and to expose the misleading narrative presented about pensions, which was maliciously intended to incite the public to commit various crimes.

[110] See Gulliver's Travels for the idea of countries governed by philosophers.

[110] Check out Gulliver's Travels for the concept of countries ruled by philosophers.

[111] M. de Calonne states the falling off of the population of Paris as far more considerable; and it may be so, since the period of M. Necker's calculation.

[111] M. de Calonne claims that the decline in the population of Paris is much more significant; and it could be true, given the time that has passed since M. Necker's calculations.

[112]
Livres. £ s. d.
Travaux de charité pour subvenir au manque de travail à Paris et dans les provinces 3,866,920 161,121 13 4
Destruction de vagabondage et de la mendicité 1,671,417 69,642 7 6
Primes pour l'importation de grains 5,671,907 235,329 9 2
Dépenses relatives aux subsistances, déduction fait des reconvrements qui out en lieu 39,871,790 1,661,324 11 8
Total 51,082,034 2,128,418 1 8

When I sent this book to the press, I entertained some doubt concerning the nature and extent of the last article in the above accounts, which is only under a general head, without any detail. Since then I have seen M. de Calonne's work. I must think it a great loss to me that I had not that advantage earlier. M. de Calonne thinks this article to be on account of general subsistence; but as he is not able to comprehend how so great a loss as upwards of 1,661,000l. sterling could be sustained on the difference between the price and the sale of grain, he seems to attribute this enormous head of charge to secret expenses of the Revolution. I cannot say anything positively on that subject. The reader is capable of judging, by the aggregate of these immense charges, on the state and condition of France, and the system of public economy adopted in that nation. These articles of account produced no inquiry or discussion in the National Assembly.

When I sent this book to the publisher, I had some doubts about the nature and extent of the last item in the accounts above, which is only mentioned broadly without any details. Since then, I've come across M. de Calonne's work. I really regret not having had that insight earlier. M. de Calonne believes this item refers to general support for living, but he can't understand how such a massive loss of over 1,661,000l. sterling could happen just from the price difference in grain sales, so he seems to think this huge expense is due to hidden costs from the Revolution. I can't say anything definitive on that topic. The reader can judge for themselves, based on the total of these enormous charges, the state and condition of France, and the public economic system in place in that country. These accounting items didn't lead to any inquiries or discussions in the National Assembly.

[113] This is on a supposition of the truth of this story; but he was not in France at the time. One name serves as well as another.

[113] This assumes that the story is true; however, he wasn't in France at that time. Any name works just as well.

[114] Domat.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Domat.

[115] Speech of M. Camus, published by order of the National Assembly.

[115] Speech by M. Camus, released by the National Assembly.

[116] Whether the following description is strictly true I know not; but it is what the publishers would have pass for true, in order to animate others. In a letter from Toul, given in one of their papers, is the following passage concerning the people of that district:—"Dans la Révolution actuelle, ils ont résisté à toutes les séductions du bigotisme, aux persécutions et aux tracasseries des ennemis de la Révolution. Oubliant leurs plus grands intérêts pour rendre hommage aux vues d'ordre général qui out déterminé l'Assemblée Nationale, ils voient, sans se plaindre, supprimer cette foule d'établissemens ecclésiastiques par lesquels ils subsistoient; et même, en perdant leur siège épiscopal, la seule de toutes ces ressources qui pouvoit, on plutôt qui devoit, en toute équité, leur être conservée, condamnés à la plus effrayante misère sans avoir été ni pu être entendus, ils ne murmurent point, ils restent fidèles aux principes du plus pur patriotisme; ils sont encore prêts à verser leur sang pour le maintien de la constitution, qui va réduire leur ville à la plus déplorable nullité."—These people are not supposed to have endured those sufferings and injustices in a struggle for liberty, for the same account states truly that they have been always free; their patience in beggary and ruin, and their suffering, without remonstrance, the most flagrant and confessed injustice, if strictly true, can be nothing but the effect of this dire fanaticism. A great multitude all over France is in the same condition and the same temper.

[116] I’m not sure if the following description is completely accurate, but it’s what the publishers want people to believe to inspire others. In a letter from Toul, published in one of their papers, there’s this passage about the people in that area:—"During the current Revolution, they have resisted all the temptations of bigotry, the persecutions and hassles from the enemies of the Revolution. Forgetting their own best interests to honor the broader objectives set by the National Assembly, they accept, without complaint, the elimination of the many ecclesiastical establishments that helped them survive; and even losing their episcopal seat, the only resource that could—and should, in all fairness—be preserved for them, condemned to the most terrifying poverty without being heard or able to be heard, they do not complain, they remain loyal to the principles of the truest patriotism; they are still ready to shed their blood to uphold the constitution, which will reduce their city to the most deplorable insignificance."—These people are not thought to have endured these sufferings and injustices in a fight for freedom, as the same account rightly says they have always been free; their patience in poverty and devastation, and their tolerance of the most blatant and acknowledged injustice, if entirely true, can only be seen as the result of this terrible fanaticism. A large number of people throughout France are in the same situation and share the same mindset.

[117] See the proceedings of the confederation at Nantes.

[117] Check out the discussions of the confederation in Nantes.

[118] "Si plures sunt ii quibus improbe datum est, quam illi quibus injuste ademptum est, idcirco plus etiam valent? Non enim numero hæc judicantur, sed pondere. Quam autem habet æquitatem, ut agrum multis annis, aut etiam sæculis ante possessum, qui nullum habuit habeat, qui autem habuit amittat? Ac, propter hoc injuriæ genus, Lacedæmonii Lysandrum Ephorum expulerunt; Agin regem (quod nunquam antea apud eos acciderat) necaverunt; exque eo tempore tantæ discordiæ secutæ sunt, ut et tyranni exsisterent, et optimates exterminarentur, et preclarissime constituta respublica dilaberetur. Nec vero solum ipsa cecidit, sed etiam reliquam Græciam evertit contagionibus malorum, quæ a Lacedæmoniis profectæ manarunt latius."—After speaking of the conduct of the model of true patriots, Aratus of Sicyon, which was in a very different spirit, he says,—"Sic par est agere cum civibus; non (ut bis jam vidimus) hastam in foro ponere et bona civium voci subjicere præconis. At ille Græcus (id quod fuit sapientis et præstantis viri) omnibus consulendum esse putavit: eaque est summa ratio et sapientia boni civis, commoda civium non divellere, sed omnes eadem æquitate continere."—Cic. Off. 1. 2.

[118] "If there are more people who have been wronged than those who have been unjustly deprived, does that make their claims any stronger? It's not about the numbers but the weight of the situation. How is it fair that someone who has possessed land for many years, or even for centuries, should lose it to someone who has never possessed it? Because of this type of injustice, the Spartans expelled Lysander from power; they even killed Agis, which had never happened before among them. From that time on, such great discord followed that tyrants emerged, the nobility was exterminated, and the highly regarded republic fell apart. Moreover, not only did it collapse itself, but it also caused chaos throughout the rest of Greece, spreading the evils that originated from the Spartans."—After discussing the conduct of the true patriots, like Aratus of Sicyon, who acted in a very different spirit, he says,—"This is how one should behave with fellow citizens; not (as we have already seen twice) by placing a spear in the forum and subjecting the property of citizens to the voice of a herald. That Greek (which was the mark of a wise and distinguished man) believed that everyone should be consulted: and this is the essence of a good citizen's wisdom, to not tear apart the well-being of citizens, but to maintain equality for all."—Cic. Off. 1. 2.

[119] See two books entitled, "Einige Originalschriften des Illuminatenordens,"—"System und Folgen des Illuminatenordens." München, 1787.

[119] See two books titled, "Some Original Writings of the Illuminati Order,"—"System and Consequences of the Illuminati Order." Munich, 1787.

[120] A leading member of the Assembly, M. Rabaut de St. Étienne, has expressed the principle of all their proceedings as clearly as possible; nothing can be more simple:—"Tous les établissemens en France couronnent le malheur du peuple: pour le rendre heureux, il faut le renouveler, changer ses idées, changer ses loix, changer ses mœurs, ... changer les hommes, changer les choses, changer ses mots, ... tout détruire; oui, tout détruire; puisque tout est à récréer."—This gentleman was chosen president in an assembly not sitting at Quinze-Vingt or the Petites Maisons, and composed of persons giving themselves out to be rational beings; but neither his ideas, language, or conduct differ in the smallest degree from the discourses, opinions, and actions of those, within and without the Assembly, who direct the operations of the machine now at work in France.

[120] A prominent member of the Assembly, M. Rabaut de St. Étienne, has articulated the main principle behind all their actions as clearly as possible; it’s very straightforward:—"All the institutions in France contribute to the people's suffering: to make them happy, we need to renew everything, change their ideas, change their laws, change their customs, ... change the people, change the things, change their words, ... destroy everything; yes, destroy everything; because everything needs to be recreated."—This individual was elected president in a forum not held at Quinze-Vingt or the Petites Maisons, and made up of people who claim to be rational beings; yet neither his ideas, language, nor behavior differ at all from the speeches, opinions, and actions of those, both inside and outside the Assembly, who steer the operations of the machinery currently at work in France.

[121] The Assembly, in executing the plan of their committee, made some alterations. They have struck out one stage in these gradations; this removes a part of the objection; but the main objection, namely, that in their scheme the first constituent voter has no connection with the representative legislator, remains in all its force. There are other alterations, some possibly for the better, some certainly for the worse: but to the author the merit or demerit of these smaller alterations appears to be of no moment, where the scheme itself is fundamentally vicious and absurd.

[121] The Assembly, while carrying out the plan of their committee, made some changes. They removed one stage in these steps, which addresses part of the concern; however, the main issue—that the first constituent voter has no connection with the representative legislator—still stands strong. There are other changes, some possibly improvements and some definitely drawbacks: but to the author, the worth or flaws of these minor changes seem insignificant when the overall scheme is fundamentally flawed and ridiculous.

[122] "Non, ut olim, universæ legiones deducebantur, cum tribunis, et centurionibus, et sui cujusque ordinis militibus, ut consensu et caritate rempublicam efficerent; sed ignoti inter se, diversis manipulis, sine rectore, sine affectibus mutuis, quasi ex alio genere mortalium repente in unum collecti, numerus magis quam colonia."—Tac. Annal. lib. 14, sect. 27.—All this will be still more applicable to the unconnected, rotatory, biennial national assemblies, in this absurd and senseless constitution.

[122] "No longer were all the legions brought together, with their tribunes, centurions, and soldiers from each rank, to unite in harmony and dedication for the good of the state; instead, they were unknown to each other, coming from different units, without a leader, lacking mutual feelings, as if suddenly gathered from a different kind of humanity, more of a number than a community."—Tac. Annal. lib. 14, sect. 27.—All of this is even more relevant to the disconnected, rotating, biennial national assemblies, in this absurd and nonsensical system.

[123] Qualitas, Relatio, Actio, Passio, Ubi, Quando, Situs, Habitus.

[123] Quality, Relation, Action, Passion, Where, When, Location, Condition.

[124] See l'État de la France, p. 363.

[124] See the State of France, p. 363.

[125] In reality three, to reckon the provincial republican establishments.

[125] In reality, there are three if you count the provincial republican establishments.

[126] For further elucidations upon the subject of all these judicatures and of the Committee of Research, see M. de Calonne's work.

[126] For more information on the topic of all these courts and the Committee of Research, check out M. de Calonne's book.

[127] "Comme sa Majesté a reconnu, non un système d'associations particulières, mais une réunion de volontés de tous les François pour la liberté et la prospérité communes, ainsi pour le maintien de l'ordre publique, il a pensé qu'il convenoit que chaque régiment prît part à ces fêtes civiques pour multiplier les rapports, et resserrer les liens d'union entre les citoyens et les troupes."—Lest I should not be credited, I insert the words authorizing the troops to feast with the popular confederacies.

[127] "As His Majesty recognized not just a system of individual associations, but a collective will of all French people for shared freedom and prosperity, as well as for maintaining public order, he thought it was appropriate for each regiment to participate in these civic celebrations to strengthen connections and tighten the bonds of unity between citizens and the troops."—To ensure I am credible, I include the words that authorize the troops to celebrate with the popular coalitions.

[128] This war minister has since quitted the school and resigned his office.

[128] The war minister has since left the school and stepped down from his position.

[129] Courrier François, 30 July, 1790. Assemblée Nationale, Numero 210.

[129] Courier François, July 30, 1790. National Assembly, Number 210.

[130] I see by M. Necker's account, that the national guards of Paris have received, over and above the money levied within their own city, about 145,000l. sterling out of the public treasure. Whether this be an actual payment for the nine months of their existence, or an estimate of their yearly charge, I do not clearly perceive. It is of no great importance, as certainly they may take whatever they please.

[130] According to M. Necker's report, the national guards of Paris have received, in addition to the money raised within their own city, about £145,000 from the public treasury. I’m not sure if this is a payment for the nine months they’ve been active or just an estimate of their annual costs. It's not very important, as they can take whatever they want.

[131] The reader will observe that I have but lightly touched (my plan demanded nothing more) on the condition of the French finances as connected with the demands upon them. If I had intended to do otherwise, the materials in my hands for such a task are not altogether perfect. On this subject I refer the reader to M. de Calonne's work, and the tremendous display that he has made of the havoc and devastation in the public estate, and in all the affairs of France, caused by the presumptuous good intentions of ignorance and incapacity. Such effects those causes will always produce. Looking over that account with a pretty strict eye, and, with perhaps too much rigor, deducting everything which may be placed to the account of a financier out of place, who might be supposed by his enemies desirous of making the most of his cause, I believe it will be found that a more salutary lesson of caution against the daring spirit of innovators than what has been supplied at the expense of France never was at any time furnished to mankind.

[131] The reader will notice that I have only briefly mentioned (my plan required nothing more) the state of French finances in relation to their obligations. If I had meant to delve deeper, the information I have isn't entirely sufficient for that task. For this topic, I direct the reader to M. de Calonne's work, which presents a striking account of the damage and destruction in public resources and all affairs of France, brought about by misguided good intentions driven by ignorance and incompetence. Such outcomes will always arise from those causes. Upon reviewing that account closely, and perhaps a bit too harshly discounting anything that could be attributed to a misplaced financier trying to defend himself, I believe it will be evident that a more significant warning about the risks of reckless innovation than what has been learned at France's expense has never been offered to humanity.

[132] La Bruyère of Bossuet.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ La Bruyère of Bossuet.

[133] "Ce n'est point à l'assemblée entière que je m'adresse ici; je ne parle qu'à ceux qui l'égarent, en lui cachant sous des gazes séduisantes le but où ils l'entraînent. C'est à eux que je dis: Votre objet, vous n'en disconviendrez pas, c'est d'ôter tout espoir au clergé, et de consommer sa ruine; c'est-là, en ne vous soupçonnant d'aucune combinaison de cupidité, d'aucun regard sur le jeu des effets publics, c'est-là ce qu'on doit croire que vous avez en vue dans la terrible opération que vous proposez; c'est ce qui doit en être le fruit. Mais le peuple qui vous y intéressez, quel avantage peut-il y trouver? En vous servant sans cesse de lui, que faites-vous pour lui? Rien, absolument rien; et, au contraire, vous faites ce qui ne conduit qu'à l'accabler de nouvelles charges. Vous avez rejeté, à son préjudice, une offre de 400 millions, dont l'acceptation pouvoit devenir un moyen de soulagement en sa faveur; et à cette ressource, aussi profitable que légitime, vous avez substitué une injustice ruineuse, qui, de votre propre aveu, charge le trésor public, et par consequent le peuple, d'un surcroît de dépense annuelle de 50 millions an moins, et d'un remboursement de 150 millions.

[133] "I'm not addressing the whole assembly here; I'm speaking only to those who mislead it by hiding their true intentions behind attractive façades. To you, I say: Your goal, which you can't deny, is to take away all hope from the clergy and to ensure its downfall. This is what should be understood as your aim in the terrible plan you're proposing; this is what will be the outcome. But the people you're involving in this, what benefit can they derive? By constantly using them, what are you doing for them? Nothing, absolutely nothing; on the contrary, you're only adding to their burdens. You've rejected a 400 million offer that could have become a means of relief for them, and instead of this beneficial and legitimate resource, you’ve imposed a destructive injustice that, by your own admission, adds an extra annual expense of 50 million to the public treasury, which ultimately falls on the people, along with a repayment of 150 million."

"Malheureux peuple! voilà ce que vous vaut en dernier résultat l'expropriation de l'Église, et la dureté des décrets taxateurs du traitement des ministres d'une religion bienfaisante; et désormais ils scront à votre charge: leurs charités soulageoient les pauvres; et vous allez être imposés pour subvenir à leur entretien!"—De l'État de la France, p. 81. See also p. 92, and the following pages.

"Unfortunate people! This is what the removal of the Church and the harsh laws taxing the pay of ministers of a helpful religion has led to; from now on, you will bear their burden: their charities used to help the poor; and now you are going to be taxed to support their upkeep!"—De l'État de la France, p. 81. See also p. 92, and the following pages.

END OF VOL. III.




        
        
    
Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!