This is a modern-English version of Meno, originally written by Plato.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
MENO
by Plato
Translated by Benjamin Jowett
Contents
|
INTRODUCTION.
This Dialogue begins abruptly with a question of Meno, who asks, 'whether virtue can be taught.' Socrates replies that he does not as yet know what virtue is, and has never known anyone who did. 'Then he cannot have met Gorgias when he was at Athens.' Yes, Socrates had met him, but he has a bad memory, and has forgotten what Gorgias said. Will Meno tell him his own notion, which is probably not very different from that of Gorgias? 'O yes—nothing easier: there is the virtue of a man, of a woman, of an old man, and of a child; there is a virtue of every age and state of life, all of which may be easily described.'
This Dialogue starts suddenly with Meno asking, 'Can virtue be taught?' Socrates responds that he doesn't really know what virtue is and has never met anyone who does. 'Then he must not have met Gorgias when he was in Athens.' Yes, Socrates met him, but he has a poor memory and has forgotten what Gorgias said. Will Meno share his own idea, which is probably not much different from Gorgias's? 'Oh yes—it's easy: there’s the virtue of a man, of a woman, of an old man, and of a child; there’s a virtue for every age and stage of life, all of which can be easily described.'
Socrates reminds Meno that this is only an enumeration of the virtues and not a definition of the notion which is common to them all. In a second attempt Meno defines virtue to be 'the power of command.' But to this, again, exceptions are taken. For there must be a virtue of those who obey, as well as of those who command; and the power of command must be justly or not unjustly exercised. Meno is very ready to admit that justice is virtue: 'Would you say virtue or a virtue, for there are other virtues, such as courage, temperance, and the like; just as round is a figure, and black and white are colours, and yet there are other figures and other colours. Let Meno take the examples of figure and colour, and try to define them.' Meno confesses his inability, and after a process of interrogation, in which Socrates explains to him the nature of a 'simile in multis,' Socrates himself defines figure as 'the accompaniment of colour.' But some one may object that he does not know the meaning of the word 'colour;' and if he is a candid friend, and not a mere disputant, Socrates is willing to furnish him with a simpler and more philosophical definition, into which no disputed word is allowed to intrude: 'Figure is the limit of form.' Meno imperiously insists that he must still have a definition of colour. Some raillery follows; and at length Socrates is induced to reply, 'that colour is the effluence of form, sensible, and in due proportion to the sight.' This definition is exactly suited to the taste of Meno, who welcomes the familiar language of Gorgias and Empedocles. Socrates is of opinion that the more abstract or dialectical definition of figure is far better.
Socrates points out to Meno that he’s only listing the virtues and not actually defining what they all have in common. In his second attempt, Meno defines virtue as 'the power to command.' However, there are exceptions to this definition. There has to be a virtue for those who obey, just as there is for those who command; and the power to command needs to be exercised justly or, at the very least, not unjustly. Meno readily agrees that justice is a virtue: 'Would you say virtue or a virtue? There are other virtues, like courage, temperance, and so on; just as round is a shape, and black and white are colors, yet there are other shapes and colors too. Let Meno use the examples of shape and color and try to define them.' Meno admits he can’t, and after a back-and-forth, where Socrates explains the concept of a 'simile in multis,' Socrates defines shape as 'the accompaniment of color.' However, someone might argue that they don’t know what 'color' means; and if they are a genuine friend and not just someone who likes to argue, Socrates is happy to provide a simpler and more philosophical definition that avoids any contested terms: 'Shape is the limit of form.' Meno stubbornly insists that he still needs a definition of color. Some playful banter ensues, and eventually, Socrates concedes that 'color is the effluence of form, perceptible, and in proper proportion to sight.' This definition suits Meno just fine, as it echoes the familiar style of Gorgias and Empedocles. Socrates believes that the more abstract or dialectical definition of shape is much better.
Now that Meno has been made to understand the nature of a general definition, he answers in the spirit of a Greek gentleman, and in the words of a poet, 'that virtue is to delight in things honourable, and to have the power of getting them.' This is a nearer approximation than he has yet made to a complete definition, and, regarded as a piece of proverbial or popular morality, is not far from the truth. But the objection is urged, 'that the honourable is the good,' and as every one equally desires the good, the point of the definition is contained in the words, 'the power of getting them.' 'And they must be got justly or with justice.' The definition will then stand thus: 'Virtue is the power of getting good with justice.' But justice is a part of virtue, and therefore virtue is the getting of good with a part of virtue. The definition repeats the word defined.
Now that Meno understands what a general definition is, he responds like a true Greek gentleman, quoting a poet: 'Virtue is taking delight in honorable things and having the ability to acquire them.' This is a closer attempt at a complete definition than he has made so far, and considered as a piece of popular wisdom, it’s not far off from the truth. However, the objection is raised that 'the honorable is the good,' and since everyone equally desires the good, the core of the definition lies in the phrase 'the ability to acquire them.' 'And they must be acquired justly or with justice.' Therefore, the definition would be: 'Virtue is the ability to acquire good with justice.' But since justice is a part of virtue, this means virtue is the acquiring of good with a component of virtue. The definition ends up repeating the word it’s trying to define.
Meno complains that the conversation of Socrates has the effect of a torpedo's shock upon him. When he talks with other persons he has plenty to say about virtue; in the presence of Socrates, his thoughts desert him. Socrates replies that he is only the cause of perplexity in others, because he is himself perplexed. He proposes to continue the enquiry. But how, asks Meno, can he enquire either into what he knows or into what he does not know? This is a sophistical puzzle, which, as Socrates remarks, saves a great deal of trouble to him who accepts it. But the puzzle has a real difficulty latent under it, to which Socrates will endeavour to find a reply. The difficulty is the origin of knowledge:—
Meno complains that talking to Socrates feels like being shocked by a torpedo. When he chats with others, he has a lot to say about virtue; but in Socrates' presence, he can't seem to think straight. Socrates responds that he just confuses others because he himself is confused. He suggests they keep exploring the topic. But Meno asks, how can he explore either what he knows or what he doesn’t know? This is a tricky question that, as Socrates points out, makes things easier for whoever accepts it. However, there's a real challenge hidden within it, which Socrates will try to address. The challenge is about where knowledge comes from:—
He has heard from priests and priestesses, and from the poet Pindar, of an immortal soul which is born again and again in successive periods of existence, returning into this world when she has paid the penalty of ancient crime, and, having wandered over all places of the upper and under world, and seen and known all things at one time or other, is by association out of one thing capable of recovering all. For nature is of one kindred; and every soul has a seed or germ which may be developed into all knowledge. The existence of this latent knowledge is further proved by the interrogation of one of Meno's slaves, who, in the skilful hands of Socrates, is made to acknowledge some elementary relations of geometrical figures. The theorem that the square of the diagonal is double the square of the side—that famous discovery of primitive mathematics, in honour of which the legendary Pythagoras is said to have sacrificed a hecatomb—is elicited from him. The first step in the process of teaching has made him conscious of his own ignorance. He has had the 'torpedo's shock' given him, and is the better for the operation. But whence had the uneducated man this knowledge? He had never learnt geometry in this world; nor was it born with him; he must therefore have had it when he was not a man. And as he always either was or was not a man, he must have always had it. (Compare Phaedo.)
He has heard from priests and priestesses, and from the poet Pindar, about an immortal soul that is reborn again and again through different stages of existence. This soul returns to the world after paying for ancient wrongdoings, and after traveling through all places of the upper and underworld, having seen and learned everything at some point, can recover all knowledge through association. Nature is fundamentally connected, and every soul has a seed or potential that can be developed into complete knowledge. The existence of this hidden knowledge is further demonstrated by asking one of Meno's slaves, who in the skillful hands of Socrates, recognizes some basic relationships of geometric figures. The theorem stating that the square of the diagonal is twice the square of the side—that famous discovery of early mathematics, in honor of which the legendary Pythagoras is said to have sacrificed a great number of animals—is revealed by him. The first step in the teaching process has made him aware of his own ignorance. He has experienced the 'shock of the torpedo' and is better for it. But where did this knowledge come from for someone who isn't educated? He never learned geometry in this life; nor was he born with it; he must have had it before he became a man. And since he has always been either a man or not, he must have always possessed it. (Compare Phaedo.)
After Socrates has given this specimen of the true nature of teaching, the original question of the teachableness of virtue is renewed. Again he professes a desire to know 'what virtue is' first. But he is willing to argue the question, as mathematicians say, under an hypothesis. He will assume that if virtue is knowledge, then virtue can be taught. (This was the stage of the argument at which the Protagoras concluded.)
After Socrates presents this example of what teaching really is, the original question about whether virtue can be taught comes up again. He again expresses a desire to understand 'what virtue is' first. However, he is open to discussing the issue, as mathematicians might say, under a hypothesis. He will assume that if virtue is knowledge, then it can be taught. (This is where Protagoras ended his argument.)
Socrates has no difficulty in showing that virtue is a good, and that goods, whether of body or mind, must be under the direction of knowledge. Upon the assumption just made, then, virtue is teachable. But where are the teachers? There are none to be found. This is extremely discouraging. Virtue is no sooner discovered to be teachable, than the discovery follows that it is not taught. Virtue, therefore, is and is not teachable.
Socrates easily demonstrates that virtue is good and that all kinds of goods, whether related to the body or the mind, need to be guided by knowledge. Based on this assumption, virtue can be taught. But where are the teachers? They are nowhere to be found. This is very disheartening. As soon as we realize that virtue can be taught, we also realize that it isn’t being taught. Therefore, virtue is both teachable and not teachable.
In this dilemma an appeal is made to Anytus, a respectable and well-to-do citizen of the old school, and a family friend of Meno, who happens to be present. He is asked 'whether Meno shall go to the Sophists and be taught.' The suggestion throws him into a rage. 'To whom, then, shall Meno go?' asks Socrates. To any Athenian gentleman—to the great Athenian statesmen of past times. Socrates replies here, as elsewhere (Laches, Prot.), that Themistocles, Pericles, and other great men, had sons to whom they would surely, if they could have done so, have imparted their own political wisdom; but no one ever heard that these sons of theirs were remarkable for anything except riding and wrestling and similar accomplishments. Anytus is angry at the imputation which is cast on his favourite statesmen, and on a class to which he supposes himself to belong; he breaks off with a significant hint. The mention of another opportunity of talking with him, and the suggestion that Meno may do the Athenian people a service by pacifying him, are evident allusions to the trial of Socrates.
In this situation, Anytus, a respected and well-off old-school citizen and a family friend of Meno, is called upon since he happens to be present. He is asked whether Meno should go to the Sophists to get an education. This suggestion makes him furious. Socrates then asks, "Who should Meno go to?" The answer is any Athenian gentleman—historical Athenian leaders from the past. Socrates points out, as he has before (Laches, Prot.), that Themistocles, Pericles, and other notable figures had sons whom they surely would have shared their political wisdom with if they could. But no one ever heard of these sons being exceptional in anything other than skills like riding, wrestling, and similar activities. Anytus is upset by the implication against his favorite leaders and the group he believes he represents, and he cuts off the conversation with a pointed hint. The mention of another chance to speak with him and the idea that Meno could help calm him down hints at the trial of Socrates.
Socrates returns to the consideration of the question 'whether virtue is teachable,' which was denied on the ground that there are no teachers of it: (for the Sophists are bad teachers, and the rest of the world do not profess to teach). But there is another point which we failed to observe, and in which Gorgias has never instructed Meno, nor Prodicus Socrates. This is the nature of right opinion. For virtue may be under the guidance of right opinion as well as of knowledge; and right opinion is for practical purposes as good as knowledge, but is incapable of being taught, and is also liable, like the images of Daedalus, to 'walk off,' because not bound by the tie of the cause. This is the sort of instinct which is possessed by statesmen, who are not wise or knowing persons, but only inspired or divine. The higher virtue, which is identical with knowledge, is an ideal only. If the statesman had this knowledge, and could teach what he knew, he would be like Tiresias in the world below,—'he alone has wisdom, but the rest flit like shadows.'
Socrates revisits the question of whether virtue can be taught, which was previously rejected because there aren't any real teachers of it: (the Sophists are poor educators, and most others don’t claim to teach). However, there's another aspect we missed, and neither Gorgias nor Prodicus has explained it to Meno or Socrates. This concerns the nature of correct opinion. Virtue can come from correct opinion just as much as from knowledge; correct opinion is just as useful for practical purposes as knowledge, but it can't be taught and is also prone to 'walking away,' like Daedalus's creations, because it isn't connected by the cause. This kind of instinct is found in statesmen, who aren’t necessarily wise or knowledgeable, but rather inspired or divinely guided. The highest form of virtue, which is the same as knowledge, is merely an ideal. If a statesman possessed that knowledge and could teach what they understood, they would be like Tiresias in the underworld—“he alone has wisdom, while the others drift like shadows.”
This Dialogue is an attempt to answer the question, Can virtue be taught? No one would either ask or answer such a question in modern times. But in the age of Socrates it was only by an effort that the mind could rise to a general notion of virtue as distinct from the particular virtues of courage, liberality, and the like. And when a hazy conception of this ideal was attained, it was only by a further effort that the question of the teachableness of virtue could be resolved.
This Dialogue tries to answer the question, Can virtue be taught? Nowadays, no one would even ask or answer a question like that. But back in Socrates’ time, it took real effort for people to grasp a broad idea of virtue, separate from specific virtues like courage and generosity. And even when they managed to form a vague understanding of this ideal, it required additional effort to address the question of whether virtue can be taught.
The answer which is given by Plato is paradoxical enough, and seems rather intended to stimulate than to satisfy enquiry. Virtue is knowledge, and therefore virtue can be taught. But virtue is not taught, and therefore in this higher and ideal sense there is no virtue and no knowledge. The teaching of the Sophists is confessedly inadequate, and Meno, who is their pupil, is ignorant of the very nature of general terms. He can only produce out of their armoury the sophism, 'that you can neither enquire into what you know nor into what you do not know;' to which Socrates replies by his theory of reminiscence.
The answer given by Plato is pretty paradoxical and seems more meant to provoke thought than to provide a clear answer. Virtue is knowledge, which means that virtue can be taught. But since virtue isn't actually taught, in this higher and ideal sense, there’s no real virtue and no real knowledge. The teachings of the Sophists are clearly insufficient, and Meno, who is one of their students, doesn't even understand the basic nature of general concepts. He can only pull from their resources the argument, 'that you can’t inquire into what you know or what you don’t know;' to which Socrates responds with his theory of recollection.
To the doctrine that virtue is knowledge, Plato has been constantly tending in the previous Dialogues. But the new truth is no sooner found than it vanishes away. 'If there is knowledge, there must be teachers; and where are the teachers?' There is no knowledge in the higher sense of systematic, connected, reasoned knowledge, such as may one day be attained, and such as Plato himself seems to see in some far off vision of a single science. And there are no teachers in the higher sense of the word; that is to say, no real teachers who will arouse the spirit of enquiry in their pupils, and not merely instruct them in rhetoric or impart to them ready-made information for a fee of 'one' or of 'fifty drachms.' Plato is desirous of deepening the notion of education, and therefore he asserts the paradox that there are no educators. This paradox, though different in form, is not really different from the remark which is often made in modern times by those who would depreciate either the methods of education commonly employed, or the standard attained—that 'there is no true education among us.'
Plato has been consistently leaning towards the idea that virtue is knowledge in his earlier dialogues. However, as soon as this new truth is discovered, it slips away. “If there’s knowledge, there need to be teachers; but where are the teachers?” There’s no knowledge in the more advanced sense of systematic, interconnected, reasoned knowledge that might someday be achieved, and which Plato himself seems to envision in a distant glimpse of a singular science. Moreover, there are no true teachers in the deeper sense of the term; that is, there are no real educators who will ignite the spirit of inquiry in their students, rather than just teach them rhetoric or provide them with prepared information for a fee of ‘one’ or ‘fifty drachms.’ Plato wants to expand the concept of education, which is why he makes the paradoxical claim that there are no real educators. This paradox, though different in its expression, is not fundamentally different from the common remark made in modern times by those who criticize either the educational methods typically used or the level of achievement reached— that “there’s no real education among us.”
There remains still a possibility which must not be overlooked. Even if there be no true knowledge, as is proved by 'the wretched state of education,' there may be right opinion, which is a sort of guessing or divination resting on no knowledge of causes, and incommunicable to others. This is the gift which our statesmen have, as is proved by the circumstance that they are unable to impart their knowledge to their sons. Those who are possessed of it cannot be said to be men of science or philosophers, but they are inspired and divine.
There is still a possibility that shouldn't be ignored. Even if there isn't any real knowledge, as shown by "the awful state of education," there might be a right opinion that comes from a kind of guessing or intuition that doesn't rely on an understanding of causes and can't be shared with others. This is the ability that our politicians have, as demonstrated by their failure to pass on their knowledge to their children. Those who have this ability can't be considered scientists or philosophers; instead, they are inspired and seem almost godlike.
There may be some trace of irony in this curious passage, which forms the concluding portion of the Dialogue. But Plato certainly does not mean to intimate that the supernatural or divine is the true basis of human life. To him knowledge, if only attainable in this world, is of all things the most divine. Yet, like other philosophers, he is willing to admit that 'probability is the guide of life (Butler's Analogy.);' and he is at the same time desirous of contrasting the wisdom which governs the world with a higher wisdom. There are many instincts, judgments, and anticipations of the human mind which cannot be reduced to rule, and of which the grounds cannot always be given in words. A person may have some skill or latent experience which he is able to use himself and is yet unable to teach others, because he has no principles, and is incapable of collecting or arranging his ideas. He has practice, but not theory; art, but not science. This is a true fact of psychology, which is recognized by Plato in this passage. But he is far from saying, as some have imagined, that inspiration or divine grace is to be regarded as higher than knowledge. He would not have preferred the poet or man of action to the philosopher, or the virtue of custom to the virtue based upon ideas.
There might be some hint of irony in this interesting section, which makes up the final part of the Dialogue. However, Plato definitely does not mean to suggest that the supernatural or divine is the true foundation of human existence. To him, knowledge—if it can only be gained in this world—is the most divine thing of all. Yet, like other philosophers, he accepts that 'probability is the guide of life (Butler's Analogy);' and he also wants to contrast the wisdom that governs the world with a higher kind of wisdom. There are many instincts, judgments, and anticipations of the human mind that can’t be neatly categorized, and whose foundations can’t always be expressed in words. A person might have some skill or instinctive experience that they can apply themselves, but can't teach others because they lack principles and can't organize their thoughts. They have practice but no theory; art but no science. This is a real psychological truth, which Plato acknowledges in this passage. But he is far from claiming, as some have thought, that inspiration or divine grace should be seen as superior to knowledge. He wouldn’t have favored the poet or the doer over the philosopher, or the virtue of habit over the virtue grounded in ideas.
Also here, as in the Ion and Phaedrus, Plato appears to acknowledge an unreasoning element in the higher nature of man. The philosopher only has knowledge, and yet the statesman and the poet are inspired. There may be a sort of irony in regarding in this way the gifts of genius. But there is no reason to suppose that he is deriding them, any more than he is deriding the phenomena of love or of enthusiasm in the Symposium, or of oracles in the Apology, or of divine intimations when he is speaking of the daemonium of Socrates. He recognizes the lower form of right opinion, as well as the higher one of science, in the spirit of one who desires to include in his philosophy every aspect of human life; just as he recognizes the existence of popular opinion as a fact, and the Sophists as the expression of it.
Also here, like in the Ion and Phaedrus, Plato seems to recognize an irrational aspect in the higher nature of humans. The philosopher has knowledge, but the statesman and the poet are inspired. There might be some irony in viewing the gifts of genius this way. However, there’s no reason to think he’s mocking them, any more than he mocks the experiences of love or enthusiasm in the Symposium, or the oracles in the Apology, or divine insights when he talks about Socrates' daemonium. He acknowledges the lower form of right opinion, as well as the higher one of knowledge, in a way that aims to encompass all aspects of human life; just as he accepts the existence of public opinion as a reality, and the Sophists as its representation.
This Dialogue contains the first intimation of the doctrine of reminiscence and of the immortality of the soul. The proof is very slight, even slighter than in the Phaedo and Republic. Because men had abstract ideas in a previous state, they must have always had them, and their souls therefore must have always existed. For they must always have been either men or not men. The fallacy of the latter words is transparent. And Socrates himself appears to be conscious of their weakness; for he adds immediately afterwards, 'I have said some things of which I am not altogether confident.' (Compare Phaedo.) It may be observed, however, that the fanciful notion of pre-existence is combined with a true but partial view of the origin and unity of knowledge, and of the association of ideas. Knowledge is prior to any particular knowledge, and exists not in the previous state of the individual, but of the race. It is potential, not actual, and can only be appropriated by strenuous exertion.
This Dialogue introduces the idea of reminiscence and the immortality of the soul. The evidence is quite weak, even weaker than in the Phaedo and Republic. Because humans had abstract ideas in a previous state, they must have always had them, meaning their souls must have always existed. They must have always been either human or not human. The flaw in the latter statement is obvious. Socrates himself seems aware of this weakness; he immediately adds, "I have said some things of which I am not altogether confident." (Compare Phaedo.) However, it can be noted that the imaginative idea of pre-existence is combined with a true but limited understanding of the origin and unity of knowledge, as well as the connection between ideas. Knowledge exists before any specific knowledge and is part of the collective human experience, not the individual. It is potential, not actual, and can only be realized through determined effort.
The idealism of Plato is here presented in a less developed form than in the Phaedo and Phaedrus. Nothing is said of the pre-existence of ideas of justice, temperance, and the like. Nor is Socrates positive of anything but the duty of enquiry. The doctrine of reminiscence too is explained more in accordance with fact and experience as arising out of the affinities of nature (ate tes thuseos oles suggenous ouses). Modern philosophy says that all things in nature are dependent on one another; the ancient philosopher had the same truth latent in his mind when he affirmed that out of one thing all the rest may be recovered. The subjective was converted by him into an objective; the mental phenomenon of the association of ideas (compare Phaedo) became a real chain of existences. The germs of two valuable principles of education may also be gathered from the 'words of priests and priestesses:' (1) that true knowledge is a knowledge of causes (compare Aristotle's theory of episteme); and (2) that the process of learning consists not in what is brought to the learner, but in what is drawn out of him.
Plato's idealism is presented here in a simpler way than in the Phaedo and Phaedrus. There’s no mention of the pre-existence of ideas like justice or temperance. Socrates only emphasizes the importance of inquiry. The idea of recollection is explained more in line with facts and experiences, highlighting natural connections. Modern philosophy states that everything in nature relies on one another; the ancient philosopher had a similar insight when he claimed that from one thing, everything else can be understood. He transformed the subjective into the objective; the mental process of connecting ideas became a tangible link of existences. Two important educational principles can also be drawn from the 'words of priests and priestesses:' (1) that true knowledge involves understanding causes (similar to Aristotle's theory of episteme); and (2) that learning is not about what the teacher provides to the student, but about what is revealed from within the learner.
Some lesser points of the dialogue may be noted, such as (1) the acute observation that Meno prefers the familiar definition, which is embellished with poetical language, to the better and truer one; or (2) the shrewd reflection, which may admit of an application to modern as well as to ancient teachers, that the Sophists having made large fortunes; this must surely be a criterion of their powers of teaching, for that no man could get a living by shoemaking who was not a good shoemaker; or (3) the remark conveyed, almost in a word, that the verbal sceptic is saved the labour of thought and enquiry (ouden dei to toiouto zeteseos). Characteristic also of the temper of the Socratic enquiry is, (4) the proposal to discuss the teachableness of virtue under an hypothesis, after the manner of the mathematicians; and (5) the repetition of the favourite doctrine which occurs so frequently in the earlier and more Socratic Dialogues, and gives a colour to all of them—that mankind only desire evil through ignorance; (6) the experiment of eliciting from the slave-boy the mathematical truth which is latent in him, and (7) the remark that he is all the better for knowing his ignorance.
Some lesser points of the dialogue can be noted, such as (1) the sharp observation that Meno prefers the familiar definition, which is dressed up in poetic language, to the better and more accurate one; or (2) the insightful reflection, which can apply to both modern and ancient teachers, that the Sophists have made large fortunes; this must surely be a sign of their teaching abilities, since no one could make a living as a shoemaker unless they were a skilled one; or (3) the almost one-word remark that the verbal skeptic is spared the effort of thought and inquiry (ouden dei to toiouto zeteseos). Also characteristic of the spirit of Socratic inquiry is (4) the suggestion to discuss whether virtue can be taught under a hypothesis, like mathematicians do; and (5) the repetition of the favorite doctrine that appears so often in the earlier and more Socratic Dialogues, which shapes them all—that people only desire evil out of ignorance; (6) the experiment of drawing out the mathematical truth that is hidden within the slave-boy, and (7) the observation that he is better off for knowing his ignorance.
The character of Meno, like that of Critias, has no relation to the actual circumstances of his life. Plato is silent about his treachery to the ten thousand Greeks, which Xenophon has recorded, as he is also silent about the crimes of Critias. He is a Thessalian Alcibiades, rich and luxurious—a spoilt child of fortune, and is described as the hereditary friend of the great king. Like Alcibiades he is inspired with an ardent desire of knowledge, and is equally willing to learn of Socrates and of the Sophists. He may be regarded as standing in the same relation to Gorgias as Hippocrates in the Protagoras to the other great Sophist. He is the sophisticated youth on whom Socrates tries his cross-examining powers, just as in the Charmides, the Lysis, and the Euthydemus, ingenuous boyhood is made the subject of a similar experiment. He is treated by Socrates in a half-playful manner suited to his character; at the same time he appears not quite to understand the process to which he is being subjected. For he is exhibited as ignorant of the very elements of dialectics, in which the Sophists have failed to instruct their disciple. His definition of virtue as 'the power and desire of attaining things honourable,' like the first definition of justice in the Republic, is taken from a poet. His answers have a sophistical ring, and at the same time show the sophistical incapacity to grasp a general notion.
The character of Meno, like Critias, isn’t really connected to the actual events of his life. Plato doesn’t mention his betrayal of the ten thousand Greeks, which Xenophon noted, nor does he speak of Critias's crimes. He’s like a Thessalian Alcibiades—wealthy and extravagant—essentially a spoiled child of fortune, and he’s described as a long-time friend of the great king. Like Alcibiades, he has a strong desire for knowledge and is eager to learn from both Socrates and the Sophists. He can be seen as being in a similar position to Gorgias as Hippocrates is to the other great Sophist in the Protagoras. He’s the cultured young man who becomes the subject of Socrates's cross-examination, just like the innocent young boys in the Charmides, Lysis, and Euthydemus. Socrates treats him in a playful way that fits his personality, but he also seems not to fully grasp the process he’s going through. Meno is shown as lacking the basic elements of dialectics, which the Sophists failed to teach him. His definition of virtue as “the power and desire to achieve honorable things,” similar to the initial definition of justice in the Republic, is borrowed from a poet. His responses sound sophistical and reveal his inability to understand a general concept.
Anytus is the type of the narrow-minded man of the world, who is indignant at innovation, and equally detests the popular teacher and the true philosopher. He seems, like Aristophanes, to regard the new opinions, whether of Socrates or the Sophists, as fatal to Athenian greatness. He is of the same class as Callicles in the Gorgias, but of a different variety; the immoral and sophistical doctrines of Callicles are not attributed to him. The moderation with which he is described is remarkable, if he be the accuser of Socrates, as is apparently indicated by his parting words. Perhaps Plato may have been desirous of showing that the accusation of Socrates was not to be attributed to badness or malevolence, but rather to a tendency in men's minds. Or he may have been regardless of the historical truth of the characters of his dialogue, as in the case of Meno and Critias. Like Chaerephon (Apol.) the real Anytus was a democrat, and had joined Thrasybulus in the conflict with the thirty.
Anytus represents the typical narrow-minded person who is upset about new ideas and equally dislikes both popular teachers and true philosophers. He seems, like Aristophanes, to view new opinions—whether from Socrates or the Sophists—as a threat to Athenian greatness. He is similar to Callicles in the Gorgias but differs in that he doesn't embrace the immoral and clever tactics of Callicles. The way he is portrayed with moderation is striking, especially if he is indeed the one accusing Socrates, as his final words suggest. Perhaps Plato wanted to show that the accusation against Socrates stemmed not from malice but rather from a common mindset. Or he might not have cared about the historical accuracy of the characters in his dialogue, like in the cases of Meno and Critias. Like Chaerephon (Apol.), the real Anytus was a democrat and had sided with Thrasybulus in the battle against the thirty.
The Protagoras arrived at a sort of hypothetical conclusion, that if 'virtue is knowledge, it can be taught.' In the Euthydemus, Socrates himself offered an example of the manner in which the true teacher may draw out the mind of youth; this was in contrast to the quibbling follies of the Sophists. In the Meno the subject is more developed; the foundations of the enquiry are laid deeper, and the nature of knowledge is more distinctly explained. There is a progression by antagonism of two opposite aspects of philosophy. But at the moment when we approach nearest, the truth doubles upon us and passes out of our reach. We seem to find that the ideal of knowledge is irreconcilable with experience. In human life there is indeed the profession of knowledge, but right opinion is our actual guide. There is another sort of progress from the general notions of Socrates, who asked simply, 'what is friendship?' 'what is temperance?' 'what is courage?' as in the Lysis, Charmides, Laches, to the transcendentalism of Plato, who, in the second stage of his philosophy, sought to find the nature of knowledge in a prior and future state of existence.
The Protagoras comes to a sort of hypothetical conclusion that if 'virtue is knowledge, it can be taught.' In the Euthydemus, Socrates gives an example of how a true teacher can bring out the mind of youth, contrasting with the silly arguments of the Sophists. In the Meno, the topic is explored further; the foundations of the inquiry are dug deeper, and the nature of knowledge is explained more clearly. There's a progression through the conflict between two opposing views of philosophy. But just when we seem to get closest to the truth, it slips away from us. We realize that the ideal of knowledge doesn’t quite match up with experience. In human life, we may claim to have knowledge, but it's actually right opinion that guides us. There's also another kind of progress from Socrates' general ideas, as he simply asked, 'what is friendship?', 'what is temperance?', 'what is courage?' in the Lysis, Charmides, and Laches, to Plato's transcendentalism, who, in the next phase of his philosophy, tried to understand the nature of knowledge in a past and future state of existence.
The difficulty in framing general notions which has appeared in this and in all the previous Dialogues recurs in the Gorgias and Theaetetus as well as in the Republic. In the Gorgias too the statesmen reappear, but in stronger opposition to the philosopher. They are no longer allowed to have a divine insight, but, though acknowledged to have been clever men and good speakers, are denounced as 'blind leaders of the blind.' The doctrine of the immortality of the soul is also carried further, being made the foundation not only of a theory of knowledge, but of a doctrine of rewards and punishments. In the Republic the relation of knowledge to virtue is described in a manner more consistent with modern distinctions. The existence of the virtues without the possession of knowledge in the higher or philosophical sense is admitted to be possible. Right opinion is again introduced in the Theaetetus as an account of knowledge, but is rejected on the ground that it is irrational (as here, because it is not bound by the tie of the cause), and also because the conception of false opinion is given up as hopeless. The doctrines of Plato are necessarily different at different times of his life, as new distinctions are realized, or new stages of thought attained by him. We are not therefore justified, in order to take away the appearance of inconsistency, in attributing to him hidden meanings or remote allusions.
The challenge of defining general concepts, which has come up in this and all previous dialogues, also appears in the Gorgias and Theaetetus, as well as in the Republic. In the Gorgias, the politicians return, but this time they are more strongly opposed to the philosopher. They are no longer seen as having a divine insight; while they are recognized as clever and skilled speakers, they are criticized as 'blind leaders of the blind.' The idea of the immortality of the soul is further developed, becoming the basis for not only a theory of knowledge but also a framework for understanding rewards and punishments. In the Republic, the relationship between knowledge and virtue is explained in a way that's more aligned with modern distinctions. It's acknowledged that virtues can exist without the kind of higher, philosophical knowledge. Right opinion is brought up again in the Theaetetus as a description of knowledge, but it's dismissed as irrational (in this case, because it lacks a causal connection), and the notion of false opinion is given up as unworkable. Plato’s ideas necessarily change at different points in his life as he realizes new distinctions or reaches new levels of thought. Therefore, we can't justify attributing hidden meanings or distant references to him just to avoid seeming inconsistent.
There are no external criteria by which we can determine the date of the Meno. There is no reason to suppose that any of the Dialogues of Plato were written before the death of Socrates; the Meno, which appears to be one of the earliest of them, is proved to have been of a later date by the allusion of Anytus.
There are no outside standards we can use to figure out when the Meno was written. There's no reason to think that any of Plato's Dialogues were created before Socrates died; the Meno, which seems to be one of the earliest, is shown to be from a later time because of the reference to Anytus.
We cannot argue that Plato was more likely to have written, as he has done, of Meno before than after his miserable death; for we have already seen, in the examples of Charmides and Critias, that the characters in Plato are very far from resembling the same characters in history. The repulsive picture which is given of him in the Anabasis of Xenophon, where he also appears as the friend of Aristippus 'and a fair youth having lovers,' has no other trait of likeness to the Meno of Plato.
We can't argue that Plato was more likely to have written about Meno before his unfortunate death rather than after. As we've already seen with Charmides and Critias, the characters in Plato's works don't closely resemble their historical counterparts. The unflattering portrayal of him in Xenophon's Anabasis, where he shows up as Aristippus's friend and a handsome young man with lovers, shares no other similarities with Plato's Meno.
The place of the Meno in the series is doubtfully indicated by internal evidence. The main character of the Dialogue is Socrates; but to the 'general definitions' of Socrates is added the Platonic doctrine of reminiscence. The problems of virtue and knowledge have been discussed in the Lysis, Laches, Charmides, and Protagoras; the puzzle about knowing and learning has already appeared in the Euthydemus. The doctrines of immortality and pre-existence are carried further in the Phaedrus and Phaedo; the distinction between opinion and knowledge is more fully developed in the Theaetetus. The lessons of Prodicus, whom he facetiously calls his master, are still running in the mind of Socrates. Unlike the later Platonic Dialogues, the Meno arrives at no conclusion. Hence we are led to place the Dialogue at some point of time later than the Protagoras, and earlier than the Phaedrus and Gorgias. The place which is assigned to it in this work is due mainly to the desire to bring together in a single volume all the Dialogues which contain allusions to the trial and death of Socrates.
The placement of the Meno in the series is uncertain based on the internal evidence. The main character of the Dialogue is Socrates; however, his 'general definitions' are complemented by the Platonic idea of reminiscence. The issues of virtue and knowledge have been explored in the Lysis, Laches, Charmides, and Protagoras; the question of knowing and learning has already come up in the Euthydemus. The concepts of immortality and pre-existence are further developed in the Phaedrus and Phaedo; the distinction between opinion and knowledge is more thoroughly discussed in the Theaetetus. The teachings of Prodicus, whom he playfully refers to as his master, are still fresh in Socrates' mind. Unlike the later Platonic Dialogues, the Meno does not reach a conclusion. Therefore, we are inclined to place the Dialogue sometime after the Protagoras and before the Phaedrus and Gorgias. Its position in this collection is primarily due to the goal of gathering all the Dialogues that reference the trial and death of Socrates in one volume.
ON THE IDEAS OF PLATO.
Plato's doctrine of ideas has attained an imaginary clearness and definiteness which is not to be found in his own writings. The popular account of them is partly derived from one or two passages in his Dialogues interpreted without regard to their poetical environment. It is due also to the misunderstanding of him by the Aristotelian school; and the erroneous notion has been further narrowed and has become fixed by the realism of the schoolmen. This popular view of the Platonic ideas may be summed up in some such formula as the following: 'Truth consists not in particulars, but in universals, which have a place in the mind of God, or in some far-off heaven. These were revealed to men in a former state of existence, and are recovered by reminiscence (anamnesis) or association from sensible things. The sensible things are not realities, but shadows only, in relation to the truth.' These unmeaning propositions are hardly suspected to be a caricature of a great theory of knowledge, which Plato in various ways and under many figures of speech is seeking to unfold. Poetry has been converted into dogma; and it is not remarked that the Platonic ideas are to be found only in about a third of Plato's writings and are not confined to him. The forms which they assume are numerous, and if taken literally, inconsistent with one another. At one time we are in the clouds of mythology, at another among the abstractions of mathematics or metaphysics; we pass imperceptibly from one to the other. Reason and fancy are mingled in the same passage. The ideas are sometimes described as many, coextensive with the universals of sense and also with the first principles of ethics; or again they are absorbed into the single idea of good, and subordinated to it. They are not more certain than facts, but they are equally certain (Phaedo). They are both personal and impersonal. They are abstract terms: they are also the causes of things; and they are even transformed into the demons or spirits by whose help God made the world. And the idea of good (Republic) may without violence be converted into the Supreme Being, who 'because He was good' created all things (Tim.).
Plato's theory of ideas has taken on a supposed clarity and definiteness that isn’t actually present in his own works. The common understanding of them comes partly from a couple of passages in his Dialogues, interpreted without considering their poetic context. It's also influenced by how the Aristotelian school misunderstood him, and this flawed view has been further limited and solidified by the realism of medieval philosophers. This popular interpretation of Platonic ideas could be summarized as follows: 'Truth lies not in specific details but in universals, which exist in the mind of God or in some distant heaven. These were revealed to humans in a previous existence and are retrieved through reminiscence (anamnesis) or connection to tangible things. The tangible things are not real but only shadows in comparison to the truth.' These meaningless statements are rarely recognized as a distortion of a significant theory of knowledge that Plato, through various means and figures of speech, attempts to explain. Poetry has been turned into dogma; and it’s overlooked that the Platonic ideas appear in only about a third of Plato's writings and aren’t exclusive to him. They take on many forms, and if interpreted literally, they conflict with each other. Sometimes we find ourselves in the realm of mythology, while at other times we’re dealing with mathematical or metaphysical abstractions; we shift seamlessly from one to the other. Reason and imagination blend within the same sections. The ideas are sometimes described as numerous, encompassing the universals of sensory experience as well as the fundamental principles of ethics; at other times, they are integrated into the single idea of the good and placed beneath it. They are just as certain as facts, but equally uncertain (Phaedo). They can be both personal and impersonal. They are abstract concepts, but they are also the sources of things; and they can even be turned into the demons or spirits that helped God create the world. The idea of good (Republic) can, without strain, be seen as the Supreme Being, who 'because He was good' created everything (Tim.).
It would be a mistake to try and reconcile these differing modes of thought. They are not to be regarded seriously as having a distinct meaning. They are parables, prophecies, myths, symbols, revelations, aspirations after an unknown world. They derive their origin from a deep religious and contemplative feeling, and also from an observation of curious mental phenomena. They gather up the elements of the previous philosophies, which they put together in a new form. Their great diversity shows the tentative character of early endeavours to think. They have not yet settled down into a single system. Plato uses them, though he also criticises them; he acknowledges that both he and others are always talking about them, especially about the Idea of Good; and that they are not peculiar to himself (Phaedo; Republic; Soph.). But in his later writings he seems to have laid aside the old forms of them. As he proceeds he makes for himself new modes of expression more akin to the Aristotelian logic.
It would be a mistake to try to reconcile these different ways of thinking. They shouldn't be taken too seriously as having distinct meanings. They are parables, prophecies, myths, symbols, revelations, and aspirations for an unknown world. They originate from a deep sense of religion and contemplation, as well as from an observation of interesting mental phenomena. They collect elements from previous philosophies and rearrange them into a new form. Their great variety reflects the experimental nature of early thinking. They haven't settled into a single system yet. Plato uses them, even while critiquing them; he recognizes that both he and others are constantly discussing them, especially the Idea of Good, and that they aren't unique to him (Phaedo; Republic; Soph.). However, in his later writings, he seems to have moved away from these old forms. As he continues, he develops new ways of expressing ideas that are more aligned with Aristotelian logic.
Yet amid all these varieties and incongruities, there is a common meaning or spirit which pervades his writings, both those in which he treats of the ideas and those in which he is silent about them. This is the spirit of idealism, which in the history of philosophy has had many names and taken many forms, and has in a measure influenced those who seemed to be most averse to it. It has often been charged with inconsistency and fancifulness, and yet has had an elevating effect on human nature, and has exercised a wonderful charm and interest over a few spirits who have been lost in the thought of it. It has been banished again and again, but has always returned. It has attempted to leave the earth and soar heavenwards, but soon has found that only in experience could any solid foundation of knowledge be laid. It has degenerated into pantheism, but has again emerged. No other knowledge has given an equal stimulus to the mind. It is the science of sciences, which are also ideas, and under either aspect require to be defined. They can only be thought of in due proportion when conceived in relation to one another. They are the glasses through which the kingdoms of science are seen, but at a distance. All the greatest minds, except when living in an age of reaction against them, have unconsciously fallen under their power.
Yet among all these differences and contradictions, there’s a common meaning or essence that runs through his writings, whether he discusses the ideas or remains silent about them. This is the essence of idealism, which throughout the history of philosophy has been known by many names and taken on many forms, influencing even those who seemed most opposed to it. It’s often been criticized for being inconsistent and fanciful, yet it has inspired an uplifting effect on human nature and has captivated a handful of minds who have immersed themselves in it. It has been rejected time and again but always makes a comeback. It has tried to escape the earthly realm and reach for the heavens, only to realize that a solid foundation of knowledge can only be established through experience. It has devolved into pantheism yet emerged once more. No other form of knowledge has provided as much motivation for the mind. It is the science of sciences, which are also ideas, and both aspects need to be clearly defined. They can only be understood in proper proportion when considered in relation to one another. They are the lenses through which the realms of science are viewed, albeit from a distance. All the greatest minds, except when living in a time of reaction against them, have unknowingly fallen under their influence.
The account of the Platonic ideas in the Meno is the simplest and clearest, and we shall best illustrate their nature by giving this first and then comparing the manner in which they are described elsewhere, e.g. in the Phaedrus, Phaedo, Republic; to which may be added the criticism of them in the Parmenides, the personal form which is attributed to them in the Timaeus, the logical character which they assume in the Sophist and Philebus, and the allusion to them in the Laws. In the Cratylus they dawn upon him with the freshness of a newly-discovered thought.
The description of Platonic ideas in the Meno is the simplest and clearest, and we can best explain their nature by starting with this first account and then comparing how they are described in other works, like the Phaedrus, Phaedo, and Republic. We can also include the critique of them in the Parmenides, the personal traits assigned to them in the Timaeus, the logical aspects they take on in the Sophist and Philebus, and the reference to them in the Laws. In the Cratylus, they appear to him like a fresh, newly discovered idea.
The Meno goes back to a former state of existence, in which men did and suffered good and evil, and received the reward or punishment of them until their sin was purged away and they were allowed to return to earth. This is a tradition of the olden time, to which priests and poets bear witness. The souls of men returning to earth bring back a latent memory of ideas, which were known to them in a former state. The recollection is awakened into life and consciousness by the sight of the things which resemble them on earth. The soul evidently possesses such innate ideas before she has had time to acquire them. This is proved by an experiment tried on one of Meno's slaves, from whom Socrates elicits truths of arithmetic and geometry, which he had never learned in this world. He must therefore have brought them with him from another.
The Meno refers to a past state of existence where people experienced good and bad, facing rewards or punishments until their sins were cleansed, allowing them to return to Earth. This is an ancient tradition supported by priests and poets. When souls come back to Earth, they carry a hidden memory of ideas they knew before. This memory is activated by encountering similar things on Earth. Clearly, the soul has these innate ideas even before actively learning them. This is demonstrated through an experiment with one of Meno's slaves, where Socrates draws out truths about arithmetic and geometry that the slave has never studied in this life. Therefore, he must have brought those ideas from another existence.
The notion of a previous state of existence is found in the verses of Empedocles and in the fragments of Heracleitus. It was the natural answer to two questions, 'Whence came the soul? What is the origin of evil?' and prevailed far and wide in the east. It found its way into Hellas probably through the medium of Orphic and Pythagorean rites and mysteries. It was easier to think of a former than of a future life, because such a life has really existed for the race though not for the individual, and all men come into the world, if not 'trailing clouds of glory,' at any rate able to enter into the inheritance of the past. In the Phaedrus, as well as in the Meno, it is this former rather than a future life on which Plato is disposed to dwell. There the Gods, and men following in their train, go forth to contemplate the heavens, and are borne round in the revolutions of them. There they see the divine forms of justice, temperance, and the like, in their unchangeable beauty, but not without an effort more than human. The soul of man is likened to a charioteer and two steeds, one mortal, the other immortal. The charioteer and the mortal steed are in fierce conflict; at length the animal principle is finally overpowered, though not extinguished, by the combined energies of the passionate and rational elements. This is one of those passages in Plato which, partaking both of a philosophical and poetical character, is necessarily indistinct and inconsistent. The magnificent figure under which the nature of the soul is described has not much to do with the popular doctrine of the ideas. Yet there is one little trait in the description which shows that they are present to Plato's mind, namely, the remark that the soul, which had seen truths in the form of the universal, cannot again return to the nature of an animal.
The idea of a past state of existence is found in the writings of Empedocles and the fragments of Heraclitus. It naturally answered two questions: "Where did the soul come from? What is the source of evil?" This concept spread widely in the East. It likely made its way into Greece through Orphic and Pythagorean rituals and mysteries. It was easier to think of a previous life than a future one because a previous life has actually existed for humanity, even if not for individuals, and everyone enters the world, even if not "trailing clouds of glory," at least capable of tapping into the legacy of the past. In both the Phaedrus and the Meno, Plato focuses more on this former life rather than a future one. There, the gods, along with men following them, go out to observe the heavens, and they are carried around in their cycles. They behold the divine forms of justice, temperance, and similar qualities in their unchanging beauty, but this requires more than human effort. The human soul is compared to a charioteer with two horses, one mortal and the other immortal. The charioteer and the mortal horse are in intense conflict; eventually, the animal instinct is ultimately subdued, although not completely eliminated, by the combined forces of the passionate and rational aspects. This is one of those passages in Plato that, having both philosophical and poetic elements, is necessarily vague and inconsistent. The grand image used to describe the nature of the soul doesn’t closely align with the popular understanding of the ideas. However, there is one small detail in the description that indicates Plato has these ideas in mind: the notion that the soul, having perceived truths in their universal form, cannot revert back to being like an animal.
In the Phaedo, as in the Meno, the origin of ideas is sought for in a previous state of existence. There was no time when they could have been acquired in this life, and therefore they must have been recovered from another. The process of recovery is no other than the ordinary law of association, by which in daily life the sight of one thing or person recalls another to our minds, and by which in scientific enquiry from any part of knowledge we may be led on to infer the whole. It is also argued that ideas, or rather ideals, must be derived from a previous state of existence because they are more perfect than the sensible forms of them which are given by experience. But in the Phaedo the doctrine of ideas is subordinate to the proof of the immortality of the soul. 'If the soul existed in a previous state, then it will exist in a future state, for a law of alternation pervades all things.' And, 'If the ideas exist, then the soul exists; if not, not.' It is to be observed, both in the Meno and the Phaedo, that Socrates expresses himself with diffidence. He speaks in the Phaedo of the words with which he has comforted himself and his friends, and will not be too confident that the description which he has given of the soul and her mansions is exactly true, but he 'ventures to think that something of the kind is true.' And in the Meno, after dwelling upon the immortality of the soul, he adds, 'Of some things which I have said I am not altogether confident' (compare Apology; Gorgias). From this class of uncertainties he exempts the difference between truth and appearance, of which he is absolutely convinced.
In the Phaedo, just like in the Meno, the origin of ideas is traced back to a previous state of existence. There was never a time when they could have been acquired in this life, so they must have been retrieved from another. This process of retrieval is simply the normal law of association, where seeing one thing or person prompts us to remember another, and through scientific inquiry, we can infer the whole from any part of knowledge. It's also argued that ideas, or rather ideals, must come from a prior existence because they are more perfect than the tangible forms we experience. However, in the Phaedo, the concept of ideas is secondary to proving the immortality of the soul. "If the soul existed in a previous state, then it will exist in a future state, as a law of alternation governs everything." And, "If ideas exist, then the soul exists; if not, then it doesn't." It's worth noting that in both the Meno and the Phaedo, Socrates speaks with uncertainty. In the Phaedo, he mentions the thoughts that have comforted him and his friends, and he doesn’t want to be too sure that his description of the soul and its realms is completely accurate, but he "dares to believe that something like it is true." In the Meno, after discussing the immortality of the soul, he adds, "About some things I have said, I'm not entirely confident" (compare Apology; Gorgias). He does, however, exclude the difference between truth and appearance from these uncertainties, of which he is absolutely certain.
In the Republic the ideas are spoken of in two ways, which though not contradictory are different. In the tenth book they are represented as the genera or general ideas under which individuals having a common name are contained. For example, there is the bed which the carpenter makes, the picture of the bed which is drawn by the painter, the bed existing in nature of which God is the author. Of the latter all visible beds are only the shadows or reflections. This and similar illustrations or explanations are put forth, not for their own sake, or as an exposition of Plato's theory of ideas, but with a view of showing that poetry and the mimetic arts are concerned with an inferior part of the soul and a lower kind of knowledge. On the other hand, in the 6th and 7th books of the Republic we reach the highest and most perfect conception, which Plato is able to attain, of the nature of knowledge. The ideas are now finally seen to be one as well as many, causes as well as ideas, and to have a unity which is the idea of good and the cause of all the rest. They seem, however, to have lost their first aspect of universals under which individuals are contained, and to have been converted into forms of another kind, which are inconsistently regarded from the one side as images or ideals of justice, temperance, holiness and the like; from the other as hypotheses, or mathematical truths or principles.
In the Republic, the ideas are discussed in two ways that, while not contradictory, are different. In the tenth book, they are described as the general concepts that group together individuals with a common name. For example, there's the bed made by the carpenter, the painting of the bed created by the artist, and the ideal bed in nature, of which God is the creator. All actual beds are merely shadows or reflections of this ideal. These examples are presented not for their own sake or as an explanation of Plato's theory of ideas, but to show that poetry and the mimetic arts deal with a lower part of the soul and a lesser kind of knowledge. Conversely, in the 6th and 7th books of the Republic, we encounter the highest and most complete understanding that Plato can achieve about the nature of knowledge. The ideas are finally recognized as both one and many, as causes as well as concepts, unified by the idea of the good, which is the source of everything else. However, they seem to have lost their initial identity as universals grouping individuals and have transitioned into another kind of form, inconsistently viewed from one side as images or ideals of justice, temperance, holiness, etc., and from the other as hypotheses or mathematical truths and principles.
In the Timaeus, which in the series of Plato's works immediately follows the Republic, though probably written some time afterwards, no mention occurs of the doctrine of ideas. Geometrical forms and arithmetical ratios furnish the laws according to which the world is created. But though the conception of the ideas as genera or species is forgotten or laid aside, the distinction of the visible and intellectual is as firmly maintained as ever. The IDEA of good likewise disappears and is superseded by the conception of a personal God, who works according to a final cause or principle of goodness which he himself is. No doubt is expressed by Plato, either in the Timaeus or in any other dialogue, of the truths which he conceives to be the first and highest. It is not the existence of God or the idea of good which he approaches in a tentative or hesitating manner, but the investigations of physiology. These he regards, not seriously, as a part of philosophy, but as an innocent recreation (Tim.).
In the Timaeus, which comes right after the Republic in Plato's works, even though it was likely written later, there’s no mention of the theory of ideas. Instead, geometric shapes and arithmetic ratios provide the laws that govern the creation of the world. Although the idea of forms as categories or types is overlooked or set aside, the distinction between the visible and the intellectual remains as strong as ever. The IDEA of good also disappears and is replaced by the idea of a personal God, who acts according to a final cause or principle of goodness that he embodies. Plato expresses no doubt, either in the Timaeus or in any other dialogue, about the truths he believes to be the most fundamental and important. He does not approach the existence of God or the idea of good tentatively or uncertainly; rather, it is the study of physiology that he views not seriously as part of philosophy, but as a light-hearted pastime (Tim.).
Passing on to the Parmenides, we find in that dialogue not an exposition or defence of the doctrine of ideas, but an assault upon them, which is put into the mouth of the veteran Parmenides, and might be ascribed to Aristotle himself, or to one of his disciples. The doctrine which is assailed takes two or three forms, but fails in any of them to escape the dialectical difficulties which are urged against it. It is admitted that there are ideas of all things, but the manner in which individuals partake of them, whether of the whole or of the part, and in which they become like them, or how ideas can be either within or without the sphere of human knowledge, or how the human and divine can have any relation to each other, is held to be incapable of explanation. And yet, if there are no universal ideas, what becomes of philosophy? (Parmenides.) In the Sophist the theory of ideas is spoken of as a doctrine held not by Plato, but by another sect of philosophers, called 'the Friends of Ideas,' probably the Megarians, who were very distinct from him, if not opposed to him (Sophist). Nor in what may be termed Plato's abridgement of the history of philosophy (Soph.), is any mention made such as we find in the first book of Aristotle's Metaphysics, of the derivation of such a theory or of any part of it from the Pythagoreans, the Eleatics, the Heracleiteans, or even from Socrates. In the Philebus, probably one of the latest of the Platonic Dialogues, the conception of a personal or semi-personal deity expressed under the figure of mind, the king of all, who is also the cause, is retained. The one and many of the Phaedrus and Theaetetus is still working in the mind of Plato, and the correlation of ideas, not of 'all with all,' but of 'some with some,' is asserted and explained. But they are spoken of in a different manner, and are not supposed to be recovered from a former state of existence. The metaphysical conception of truth passes into a psychological one, which is continued in the Laws, and is the final form of the Platonic philosophy, so far as can be gathered from his own writings (see especially Laws). In the Laws he harps once more on the old string, and returns to general notions:—these he acknowledges to be many, and yet he insists that they are also one. The guardian must be made to recognize the truth, for which he has contended long ago in the Protagoras, that the virtues are four, but they are also in some sense one (Laws; compare Protagoras).
Moving on to the Parmenides, we see that this dialogue doesn't explain or defend the theory of ideas; rather, it criticizes them, voiced by the seasoned Parmenides. This critique could be attributed to Aristotle himself or one of his followers. The theory under attack takes on two or three forms, but none manage to avoid the logical challenges presented against it. It's acknowledged that there are ideas for everything, but the way individuals relate to them—whether through the whole or the part—and how they become similar to them, or how ideas can exist either within or outside the realm of human understanding, or how the human and the divine connect, is deemed impossible to clarify. And yet, if there are no universal ideas, what happens to philosophy? (Parmenides.) In the Sophist, the theory of ideas is described as a belief not held by Plato, but by another group of philosophers called 'the Friends of Ideas,' likely the Megarians, who were quite different from him, if not outright opposed (Sophist). Moreover, in what could be called Plato's summary of philosophical history (Soph.), there’s no mention of the origins of this theory or any part of it deriving from the Pythagoreans, the Eleatics, the Heracleiteans, or even Socrates, as we find in the first book of Aristotle's Metaphysics. In the Philebus, probably one of the last of Plato's dialogues, he maintains the idea of a personal or semi-personal god represented as the mind, the ruler of all, and also the source. The concept of the one and the many from the Phaedrus and Theaetetus still occupies Plato's thoughts, and the relationship of ideas, not of 'all with all,' but 'some with some,' is affirmed and clarified. However, they're discussed differently and aren’t thought to be rediscovered from a previous state of existence. The metaphysical idea of truth shifts into a psychological one, which continues into the Laws, representing the final form of Platonic philosophy, as far as can be inferred from his own writings (see especially Laws). In the Laws, he revisits the familiar theme and reiterates general concepts: he recognizes that these are numerous, yet he insists they are also one. The guardian must come to understand the truth he argued for long ago in the Protagoras, that while virtues are four, they are also unified in some sense (Laws; compare Protagoras).
So various, and if regarded on the surface only, inconsistent, are the statements of Plato respecting the doctrine of ideas. If we attempted to harmonize or to combine them, we should make out of them, not a system, but the caricature of a system. They are the ever-varying expression of Plato's Idealism. The terms used in them are in their substance and general meaning the same, although they seem to be different. They pass from the subject to the object, from earth (diesseits) to heaven (jenseits) without regard to the gulf which later theology and philosophy have made between them. They are also intended to supplement or explain each other. They relate to a subject of which Plato himself would have said that 'he was not confident of the precise form of his own statements, but was strong in the belief that something of the kind was true.' It is the spirit, not the letter, in which they agree—the spirit which places the divine above the human, the spiritual above the material, the one above the many, the mind before the body.
The statements of Plato about the doctrine of ideas are so varied and, if looked at from a surface level, seem inconsistent. If we tried to bring them together or create a harmony between them, we wouldn’t end up with a coherent system, but rather a distorted version of one. They represent the constantly changing expression of Plato's Idealism. The terms he uses convey the same underlying substance and general meaning, even though they might seem different. They move from the subject to the object, from this world to the next, without acknowledging the divide that later theology and philosophy have created between the two. These statements also aim to complement or reinforce each other. They deal with a topic about which Plato himself would have said that he wasn’t sure of the exact wording of his own statements, but firmly believed that something like it was true. It is the spirit, not the specifics, that they agree on—the spirit that elevates the divine above the human, the spiritual above the material, the one above the many, and the mind above the body.
The stream of ancient philosophy in the Alexandrian and Roman times widens into a lake or sea, and then disappears underground to reappear after many ages in a distant land. It begins to flow again under new conditions, at first confined between high and narrow banks, but finally spreading over the continent of Europe. It is and is not the same with ancient philosophy. There is a great deal in modern philosophy which is inspired by ancient. There is much in ancient philosophy which was 'born out of due time; and before men were capable of understanding it. To the fathers of modern philosophy, their own thoughts appeared to be new and original, but they carried with them an echo or shadow of the past, coming back by recollection from an elder world. Of this the enquirers of the seventeenth century, who to themselves appeared to be working out independently the enquiry into all truth, were unconscious. They stood in a new relation to theology and natural philosophy, and for a time maintained towards both an attitude of reserve and separation. Yet the similarities between modern and ancient thought are greater far than the differences. All philosophy, even that part of it which is said to be based upon experience, is really ideal; and ideas are not only derived from facts, but they are also prior to them and extend far beyond them, just as the mind is prior to the senses.
The stream of ancient philosophy during the Alexandrian and Roman eras expands into a lake or sea, then sinks underground only to resurface many ages later in a far-off land. It begins to flow again under new circumstances, initially confined between steep and narrow banks, but ultimately spreading across Europe. It is both a continuation and a departure from ancient philosophy. A lot of modern philosophy is influenced by the ancient. Much of ancient philosophy was 'born before its time' and was beyond what people could grasp. To the founders of modern philosophy, their own ideas felt fresh and original, but they also carried an echo of the past, recalling an earlier world. Those who explored these ideas in the seventeenth century believed they were independently discovering all truth, unaware that they were revisiting older concepts. They formed a new relationship with theology and natural philosophy and temporarily kept a distance from both. However, the similarities between modern and ancient thought greatly outweigh the differences. All philosophy, even the portions claimed to be grounded in experience, is fundamentally ideal; ideas not only come from facts but also precede them and reach far beyond them, just as the mind precedes the senses.
Early Greek speculation culminates in the ideas of Plato, or rather in the single idea of good. His followers, and perhaps he himself, having arrived at this elevation, instead of going forwards went backwards from philosophy to psychology, from ideas to numbers. But what we perceive to be the real meaning of them, an explanation of the nature and origin of knowledge, will always continue to be one of the first problems of philosophy.
Early Greek thought peaks in the ideas of Plato, or more accurately, in the single idea of the good. His followers, and perhaps he himself, having reached this height, instead of moving forward, regressed from philosophy to psychology, from ideas to numbers. However, what we understand to be the true meaning of these concepts—an explanation of the nature and origin of knowledge—will always remain one of the primary problems of philosophy.
Plato also left behind him a most potent instrument, the forms of logic—arms ready for use, but not yet taken out of their armoury. They were the late birth of the early Greek philosophy, and were the only part of it which has had an uninterrupted hold on the mind of Europe. Philosophies come and go; but the detection of fallacies, the framing of definitions, the invention of methods still continue to be the main elements of the reasoning process.
Plato also left behind a powerful tool, the forms of logic—ready for use, but not yet taken out of their arsenal. They were a late development of early Greek philosophy and were the only part of it that has consistently influenced the thinking of Europe. Philosophies come and go, but identifying fallacies, creating definitions, and developing methods continue to be the core elements of the reasoning process.
Modern philosophy, like ancient, begins with very simple conceptions. It is almost wholly a reflection on self. It might be described as a quickening into life of old words and notions latent in the semi-barbarous Latin, and putting a new meaning into them. Unlike ancient philosophy, it has been unaffected by impressions derived from outward nature: it arose within the limits of the mind itself. From the time of Descartes to Hume and Kant it has had little or nothing to do with facts of science. On the other hand, the ancient and mediaeval logic retained a continuous influence over it, and a form like that of mathematics was easily impressed upon it; the principle of ancient philosophy which is most apparent in it is scepticism; we must doubt nearly every traditional or received notion, that we may hold fast one or two. The being of God in a personal or impersonal form was a mental necessity to the first thinkers of modern times: from this alone all other ideas could be deduced. There had been an obscure presentiment of 'cognito, ergo sum' more than 2000 years previously. The Eleatic notion that being and thought were the same was revived in a new form by Descartes. But now it gave birth to consciousness and self-reflection: it awakened the 'ego' in human nature. The mind naked and abstract has no other certainty but the conviction of its own existence. 'I think, therefore I am;' and this thought is God thinking in me, who has also communicated to the reason of man his own attributes of thought and extension—these are truly imparted to him because God is true (compare Republic). It has been often remarked that Descartes, having begun by dismissing all presuppositions, introduces several: he passes almost at once from scepticism to dogmatism. It is more important for the illustration of Plato to observe that he, like Plato, insists that God is true and incapable of deception (Republic)—that he proceeds from general ideas, that many elements of mathematics may be found in him. A certain influence of mathematics both on the form and substance of their philosophy is discernible in both of them. After making the greatest opposition between thought and extension, Descartes, like Plato, supposes them to be reunited for a time, not in their own nature but by a special divine act (compare Phaedrus), and he also supposes all the parts of the human body to meet in the pineal gland, that alone affording a principle of unity in the material frame of man. It is characteristic of the first period of modern philosophy, that having begun (like the Presocratics) with a few general notions, Descartes first falls absolutely under their influence, and then quickly discards them. At the same time he is less able to observe facts, because they are too much magnified by the glasses through which they are seen. The common logic says 'the greater the extension, the less the comprehension,' and we may put the same thought in another way and say of abstract or general ideas, that the greater the abstraction of them, the less are they capable of being applied to particular and concrete natures.
Modern philosophy, like ancient philosophy, starts with very basic ideas. It's mostly an exploration of the self. It can be seen as reviving old words and concepts found in the somewhat crude Latin and assigning new meanings to them. Unlike ancient philosophy, it hasn’t been influenced much by the outside world; it developed within the confines of the mind itself. From Descartes to Hume and Kant, it hasn’t really engaged with scientific facts. On the other hand, ancient and medieval logic consistently influenced it, and it easily took on a mathematical form; the principle that stands out from ancient philosophy is skepticism—we need to doubt almost every traditional idea to hold on to one or two. The existence of God, whether personal or impersonal, was a mental necessity for the earliest modern thinkers: it served as the foundation from which all other ideas could be derived. There was a vague premonition of 'cogito, ergo sum' more than 2000 years earlier. The Eleatic idea that being and thought are the same was reimagined by Descartes. But this time, it gave rise to consciousness and self-reflection; it awakened the 'ego' within human nature. The mind, stripped down and abstract, has no certainty other than the belief in its own existence. 'I think, therefore I am;' and this thought represents God thinking through me, who has also shared his own attributes of thought and extension with human reason—these are genuinely given because God is truth (see Republic). It has often been noted that Descartes, after rejecting all assumptions, introduces several of his own: he quickly shifts from skepticism to dogmatism. For understanding Plato, it’s crucial to note he, like Plato, asserts that God is true and cannot deceive (Republic)—that he works from general ideas and that many elements of mathematics can be found within him. There’s a discernible influence of mathematics on both the form and substance of their philosophies. After establishing a deep division between thought and extension, Descartes, similar to Plato, hypothesizes that they reunite for a time, not in their own nature but through a special divine act (see Phaedrus), and he also suggests all parts of the human body converge in the pineal gland, which alone provides a principle of unity in the human material frame. The early phase of modern philosophy is characterized by starting (much like the Presocratics) with a few broad ideas; Descartes initially falls completely under their influence before quickly abandoning them. At the same time, he struggles to observe facts because they are magnified too much by the lenses through which they are viewed. Common logic states that 'the greater the extension, the less the comprehension,' and we can express this idea differently regarding abstract or general concepts: the greater their abstraction, the less effectively they can be applied to specific and concrete entities.
Not very different from Descartes in his relation to ancient philosophy is his successor Spinoza, who lived in the following generation. The system of Spinoza is less personal and also less dualistic than that of Descartes. In this respect the difference between them is like that between Xenophanes and Parmenides. The teaching of Spinoza might be described generally as the Jewish religion reduced to an abstraction and taking the form of the Eleatic philosophy. Like Parmenides, he is overpowered and intoxicated with the idea of Being or God. The greatness of both philosophies consists in the immensity of a thought which excludes all other thoughts; their weakness is the necessary separation of this thought from actual existence and from practical life. In neither of them is there any clear opposition between the inward and outward world. The substance of Spinoza has two attributes, which alone are cognizable by man, thought and extension; these are in extreme opposition to one another, and also in inseparable identity. They may be regarded as the two aspects or expressions under which God or substance is unfolded to man. Here a step is made beyond the limits of the Eleatic philosophy. The famous theorem of Spinoza, 'Omnis determinatio est negatio,' is already contained in the 'negation is relation' of Plato's Sophist. The grand description of the philosopher in Republic VI, as the spectator of all time and all existence, may be paralleled with another famous expression of Spinoza, 'Contemplatio rerum sub specie eternitatis.' According to Spinoza finite objects are unreal, for they are conditioned by what is alien to them, and by one another. Human beings are included in the number of them. Hence there is no reality in human action and no place for right and wrong. Individuality is accident. The boasted freedom of the will is only a consciousness of necessity. Truth, he says, is the direction of the reason towards the infinite, in which all things repose; and herein lies the secret of man's well-being. In the exaltation of the reason or intellect, in the denial of the voluntariness of evil (Timaeus; Laws) Spinoza approaches nearer to Plato than in his conception of an infinite substance. As Socrates said that virtue is knowledge, so Spinoza would have maintained that knowledge alone is good, and what contributes to knowledge useful. Both are equally far from any real experience or observation of nature. And the same difficulty is found in both when we seek to apply their ideas to life and practice. There is a gulf fixed between the infinite substance and finite objects or individuals of Spinoza, just as there is between the ideas of Plato and the world of sense.
Not very different from Descartes in his relationship to ancient philosophy is his successor Spinoza, who lived in the next generation. Spinoza's system is less personal and also less dualistic than Descartes'. In this respect, the difference between them is similar to that between Xenophanes and Parmenides. Spinoza's teachings can be generally described as the Jewish religion turned into an abstraction, taking the form of Eleatic philosophy. Like Parmenides, he is overwhelmed and fascinated by the concept of Being or God. The greatness of both philosophies lies in the vastness of a thought that excludes all others; their weakness is the inevitable separation of this thought from actual existence and practical life. In neither philosophy is there a clear distinction between the inner and outer world. Spinoza's substance has two attributes, which are the only ones understandable to humans: thought and extension; these are in extreme opposition to each other, yet also inseparably connected. They can be seen as the two aspects or expressions through which God or substance is revealed to humanity. Here, a step is taken beyond the limits of Eleatic philosophy. The famous theorem by Spinoza, 'Omnis determinatio est negatio,' is already present in Plato's Sophist with 'negation is relation.' The grand portrayal of the philosopher in Republic VI, as the observer of all time and existence, can be compared with another well-known phrase by Spinoza, 'Contemplatio rerum sub specie eternitatis.' According to Spinoza, finite objects are unreal, as they are conditioned by external factors and by each other. Human beings are among these finite objects. Therefore, there is no reality in human action and no place for right and wrong. Individuality is merely accidental. The claimed freedom of the will is just an awareness of necessity. Truth, he claims, is the direction of reason towards the infinite, where all things reside; and within this lies the secret to human well-being. In the elevation of reason or intellect, and in the denial of the voluntariness of evil (Timaeus; Laws), Spinoza comes closer to Plato than he does in his idea of an infinite substance. As Socrates argued that virtue is knowledge, Spinoza would assert that knowledge itself is good, and anything that contributes to knowledge is useful. Both philosophies are equally distant from any genuine experience or observation of nature. The same challenge exists for both when we try to apply their ideas to life and practice. There is a fixed gap between Spinoza's infinite substance and finite objects or individuals, just as there is between Plato's ideas and the sensory world.
Removed from Spinoza by less than a generation is the philosopher Leibnitz, who after deepening and intensifying the opposition between mind and matter, reunites them by his preconcerted harmony (compare again Phaedrus). To him all the particles of matter are living beings which reflect on one another, and in the least of them the whole is contained. Here we catch a reminiscence both of the omoiomere, or similar particles of Anaxagoras, and of the world-animal of the Timaeus.
Separated from Spinoza by just a generation is the philosopher Leibniz, who, after exploring and intensifying the conflict between mind and matter, brings them back together through his idea of pre-established harmony (see also Phaedrus). To him, all particles of matter are living beings that interact with one another, and even the smallest of them contains the whole. Here, we can see a reference to both the omoiomere, or similar particles, of Anaxagoras, and the world-animal concept from the Timaeus.
In Bacon and Locke we have another development in which the mind of man is supposed to receive knowledge by a new method and to work by observation and experience. But we may remark that it is the idea of experience, rather than experience itself, with which the mind is filled. It is a symbol of knowledge rather than the reality which is vouchsafed to us. The Organon of Bacon is not much nearer to actual facts than the Organon of Aristotle or the Platonic idea of good. Many of the old rags and ribbons which defaced the garment of philosophy have been stripped off, but some of them still adhere. A crude conception of the ideas of Plato survives in the 'forms' of Bacon. And on the other hand, there are many passages of Plato in which the importance of the investigation of facts is as much insisted upon as by Bacon. Both are almost equally superior to the illusions of language, and are constantly crying out against them, as against other idols.
In Bacon and Locke, we see a shift where the human mind is thought to gain knowledge through a new approach based on observation and experience. However, we should note that it's the idea of experience, rather than actual experience, that fills the mind. It's more of a representation of knowledge than the reality that is granted to us. Bacon's Organon isn't significantly closer to real facts than Aristotle's Organon or Plato's concept of the good. Many outdated notions that marred the field of philosophy have been removed, yet some still remain. A basic version of Plato's ideas can still be seen in Bacon's "forms." Conversely, there are numerous passages in Plato that emphasize the significance of investigating facts just as strongly as Bacon does. Both thinkers are nearly equally critical of the misconceptions created by language and repeatedly speak out against these and other false beliefs.
Locke cannot be truly regarded as the author of sensationalism any more than of idealism. His system is based upon experience, but with him experience includes reflection as well as sense. His analysis and construction of ideas has no foundation in fact; it is only the dialectic of the mind 'talking to herself.' The philosophy of Berkeley is but the transposition of two words. For objects of sense he would substitute sensations. He imagines himself to have changed the relation of the human mind towards God and nature; they remain the same as before, though he has drawn the imaginary line by which they are divided at a different point. He has annihilated the outward world, but it instantly reappears governed by the same laws and described under the same names.
Locke can't really be seen as the author of sensationalism any more than of idealism. His system is based on experience, but for him, experience includes both reflection and sensory input. His analysis and construction of ideas have no real foundation; it's just the mind's dialectic 'talking to itself.' Berkeley's philosophy is simply a shift of two words. He would replace objects of sense with sensations. He believes he has altered the relationship between the human mind, God, and nature; yet, they remain unchanged, even though he has drawn an imaginary line to separate them at a different spot. He has erased the external world, but it quickly reappears, still governed by the same laws and referred to by the same names.
A like remark applies to David Hume, of whose philosophy the central principle is the denial of the relation of cause and effect. He would deprive men of a familiar term which they can ill afford to lose; but he seems not to have observed that this alteration is merely verbal and does not in any degree affect the nature of things. Still less did he remark that he was arguing from the necessary imperfection of language against the most certain facts. And here, again, we may find a parallel with the ancients. He goes beyond facts in his scepticism, as they did in their idealism. Like the ancient Sophists, he relegates the more important principles of ethics to custom and probability. But crude and unmeaning as this philosophy is, it exercised a great influence on his successors, not unlike that which Locke exercised upon Berkeley and Berkeley upon Hume himself. All three were both sceptical and ideal in almost equal degrees. Neither they nor their predecessors had any true conception of language or of the history of philosophy. Hume's paradox has been forgotten by the world, and did not any more than the scepticism of the ancients require to be seriously refuted. Like some other philosophical paradoxes, it would have been better left to die out. It certainly could not be refuted by a philosophy such as Kant's, in which, no less than in the previously mentioned systems, the history of the human mind and the nature of language are almost wholly ignored, and the certainty of objective knowledge is transferred to the subject; while absolute truth is reduced to a figment, more abstract and narrow than Plato's ideas, of 'thing in itself,' to which, if we reason strictly, no predicate can be applied.
A similar comment applies to David Hume, whose philosophy centers on denying the relationship between cause and effect. He would strip people of a familiar concept that they can hardly afford to lose; yet, he seems not to realize that this change is merely a matter of words and doesn’t affect the nature of reality at all. Even more, he failed to notice that he was arguing against well-established facts using the inherent limitations of language. Once again, we can see a parallel with the ancients. He extends his skepticism beyond facts, just as they did with their idealism. Like the ancient Sophists, he assigns the more significant principles of ethics to customary practice and probability. But as crude and pointless as this philosophy is, it had a considerable impact on his followers, much like Locke influenced Berkeley and Berkeley influenced Hume himself. All three were skeptical and idealistic to nearly the same degree. Neither they nor their predecessors had a proper understanding of language or the history of philosophy. Hume's paradox has faded from memory, and like the skepticism of the ancients, it didn’t really need a serious rebuttal. Like some other philosophical paradoxes, it would have been better left to fade away. It certainly couldn't be countered by a philosophy like Kant's, in which, just like in the systems mentioned earlier, the history of human thought and the essence of language are largely overlooked, and the certainty of objective knowledge is shifted to the subject; meanwhile, absolute truth is reduced to a more abstract and limited concept than Plato's ideas of the 'thing in itself,’ to which, if we reason carefully, no predicate can truly apply.
The question which Plato has raised respecting the origin and nature of ideas belongs to the infancy of philosophy; in modern times it would no longer be asked. Their origin is only their history, so far as we know it; there can be no other. We may trace them in language, in philosophy, in mythology, in poetry, but we cannot argue a priori about them. We may attempt to shake them off, but they are always returning, and in every sphere of science and human action are tending to go beyond facts. They are thought to be innate, because they have been familiar to us all our lives, and we can no longer dismiss them from our mind. Many of them express relations of terms to which nothing exactly or nothing at all in rerum natura corresponds. We are not such free agents in the use of them as we sometimes imagine. Fixed ideas have taken the most complete possession of some thinkers who have been most determined to renounce them, and have been vehemently affirmed when they could be least explained and were incapable of proof. The world has often been led away by a word to which no distinct meaning could be attached. Abstractions such as 'authority,' 'equality,' 'utility,' 'liberty,' 'pleasure,' 'experience,' 'consciousness,' 'chance,' 'substance,' 'matter,' 'atom,' and a heap of other metaphysical and theological terms, are the source of quite as much error and illusion and have as little relation to actual facts as the ideas of Plato. Few students of theology or philosophy have sufficiently reflected how quickly the bloom of a philosophy passes away; or how hard it is for one age to understand the writings of another; or how nice a judgment is required of those who are seeking to express the philosophy of one age in the terms of another. The 'eternal truths' of which metaphysicians speak have hardly ever lasted more than a generation. In our own day schools or systems of philosophy which have once been famous have died before the founders of them. We are still, as in Plato's age, groping about for a new method more comprehensive than any of those which now prevail; and also more permanent. And we seem to see at a distance the promise of such a method, which can hardly be any other than the method of idealized experience, having roots which strike far down into the history of philosophy. It is a method which does not divorce the present from the past, or the part from the whole, or the abstract from the concrete, or theory from fact, or the divine from the human, or one science from another, but labours to connect them. Along such a road we have proceeded a few steps, sufficient, perhaps, to make us reflect on the want of method which prevails in our own day. In another age, all the branches of knowledge, whether relating to God or man or nature, will become the knowledge of 'the revelation of a single science' (Symp.), and all things, like the stars in heaven, will shed their light upon one another.
The question Plato raised about the origin and nature of ideas is among the earliest issues in philosophy; in modern times, it wouldn’t even be asked. Their origin is just their history, as we know it; there’s no other explanation. We can trace them in language, philosophy, mythology, and poetry, but we can’t debate them based on prior reasoning. We might try to set them aside, but they always come back and, in every area of science and human activity, they tend to go beyond mere facts. They seem to be innate because they’ve been part of our lives for so long, and we can’t just dismiss them. Many of them represent relationships between terms that don’t correspond to anything exact or even anything at all in reality. We aren’t as free to use them as we sometimes think. Fixed ideas have completely taken over some thinkers who have been most determined to reject them, and these ideas are often strongly asserted when they’re at their least explainable and when there’s no proof for them. The world has frequently been misled by a word to which no clear meaning could be attached. Abstract concepts like 'authority,' 'equality,' 'utility,' 'liberty,' 'pleasure,' 'experience,' 'consciousness,' 'chance,' 'substance,' 'matter,' 'atom,' and many other metaphysical and theological terms lead to just as much error and confusion and have as little connection to real facts as Plato's ideas. Few theology or philosophy students have really considered how quickly the appeal of a philosophy fades, how difficult it is for one generation to understand the works of another, or how careful one must be when trying to express the philosophy of one time using the vocabulary of another. The 'eternal truths' that metaphysicians talk about rarely last longer than a generation. In our time, schools or systems of philosophy that were once renowned have faded away even before their founders have passed. We are still, like in Plato's time, searching for a new method that is more comprehensive than the existing ones and also more lasting. We seem to glimpse the potential of such a method, which will likely be based on an idealized experience with deep roots in the history of philosophy. This method doesn’t separate the present from the past, or the part from the whole, or the abstract from the concrete, or theory from fact, or the divine from the human, or one science from another, but tries to connect them. We’ve made a few steps along this path, enough to reflect on the lack of method that exists today. In another era, all branches of knowledge, whether about God, humanity, or nature, will come together as the knowledge of 'the revelation of a single science,' and everything, like the stars in the sky, will illuminate each other.
MENO
PERSONS OF THE DIALOGUE: Meno, Socrates, A Slave of Meno (Boy), Anytus.
PERSONS OF THE DIALOGUE: Meno, Socrates, A Slave of Meno (Boy), Anytus.
MENO: Can you tell me, Socrates, whether virtue is acquired by teaching or by practice; or if neither by teaching nor by practice, then whether it comes to man by nature, or in what other way?
MENO: Can you tell me, Socrates, if virtue is learned through teaching or through practice? Or if it's not learned that way, does it come to a person by nature, or is there some other way it happens?
SOCRATES: O Meno, there was a time when the Thessalians were famous among the other Hellenes only for their riches and their riding; but now, if I am not mistaken, they are equally famous for their wisdom, especially at Larisa, which is the native city of your friend Aristippus. And this is Gorgias' doing; for when he came there, the flower of the Aleuadae, among them your admirer Aristippus, and the other chiefs of the Thessalians, fell in love with his wisdom. And he has taught you the habit of answering questions in a grand and bold style, which becomes those who know, and is the style in which he himself answers all comers; and any Hellene who likes may ask him anything. How different is our lot! my dear Meno. Here at Athens there is a dearth of the commodity, and all wisdom seems to have emigrated from us to you. I am certain that if you were to ask any Athenian whether virtue was natural or acquired, he would laugh in your face, and say: 'Stranger, you have far too good an opinion of me, if you think that I can answer your question. For I literally do not know what virtue is, and much less whether it is acquired by teaching or not.' And I myself, Meno, living as I do in this region of poverty, am as poor as the rest of the world; and I confess with shame that I know literally nothing about virtue; and when I do not know the 'quid' of anything how can I know the 'quale'? How, if I knew nothing at all of Meno, could I tell if he was fair, or the opposite of fair; rich and noble, or the reverse of rich and noble? Do you think that I could?
SOCRATES: Oh Meno, there was a time when the Thessalians were known among the other Greeks mainly for their wealth and their horse riding; but now, if I'm not mistaken, they are just as famous for their wisdom, especially in Larisa, which is the hometown of your friend Aristippus. This is due to Gorgias; when he arrived there, the best of the Aleuadae, including your admirer Aristippus and other leaders of the Thessalians, became enamored with his wisdom. He has taught you to respond to questions in a grand and bold way, which suits those who are knowledgeable, and it’s the way he himself answers anyone who asks him something. Any Greek who wants can ask him anything. How different is our situation! My dear Meno. Here in Athens, we lack that kind of thinking, and it seems all wisdom has moved from us to you. I’m sure that if you asked any Athenian whether virtue is natural or learned, he would laugh at you and say: 'Stranger, you think way too highly of me if you believe I could answer your question. I literally don’t know what virtue is, and even less whether it’s learned through teaching.' And I myself, Meno, living as I do in this area of lack, am just as clueless as everyone else; and I admit with shame that I know absolutely nothing about virtue; and if I don’t know the 'what' of something, how can I know the 'how'? How could I tell if Meno was beautiful or the opposite, rich and noble, or the opposite of rich and noble? Do you think I could?
MENO: No, indeed. But are you in earnest, Socrates, in saying that you do not know what virtue is? And am I to carry back this report of you to Thessaly?
MENO: No, really. But are you serious, Socrates, when you say you don't know what virtue is? Am I supposed to take this back to Thessaly?
SOCRATES: Not only that, my dear boy, but you may say further that I have never known of any one else who did, in my judgment.
SOCRATES: Not only that, my dear boy, but you could also say that, in my opinion, I have never known anyone else who did.
MENO: Then you have never met Gorgias when he was at Athens?
MENO: So you've never met Gorgias when he was in Athens?
SOCRATES: Yes, I have.
SOCRATES: Yeah, I have.
MENO: And did you not think that he knew?
MENO: And didn't you think that he knew?
SOCRATES: I have not a good memory, Meno, and therefore I cannot now tell what I thought of him at the time. And I dare say that he did know, and that you know what he said: please, therefore, to remind me of what he said; or, if you would rather, tell me your own view; for I suspect that you and he think much alike.
SOCRATES: I don't have a great memory, Meno, so I can't recall what I thought of him back then. I'm sure he knew, and you probably remember what he said too. So please remind me of his words; or if you prefer, share your thoughts instead, because I have a feeling that you and he share similar views.
MENO: Very true.
So true.
SOCRATES: Then as he is not here, never mind him, and do you tell me: By the gods, Meno, be generous, and tell me what you say that virtue is; for I shall be truly delighted to find that I have been mistaken, and that you and Gorgias do really have this knowledge; although I have been just saying that I have never found anybody who had.
SOCRATES: Since he’s not here, forget about him. Just tell me this: By the gods, Meno, be generous and share your thoughts on what virtue is. I would be truly happy to discover that I've been wrong and that you and Gorgias actually possess this knowledge, even though I've just said that I've never encountered anyone who does.
MENO: There will be no difficulty, Socrates, in answering your question. Let us take first the virtue of a man—he should know how to administer the state, and in the administration of it to benefit his friends and harm his enemies; and he must also be careful not to suffer harm himself. A woman's virtue, if you wish to know about that, may also be easily described: her duty is to order her house, and keep what is indoors, and obey her husband. Every age, every condition of life, young or old, male or female, bond or free, has a different virtue: there are virtues numberless, and no lack of definitions of them; for virtue is relative to the actions and ages of each of us in all that we do. And the same may be said of vice, Socrates (Compare Arist. Pol.).
MENO: It won’t be hard, Socrates, to answer your question. Let’s start with a man’s virtue—he should know how to run the state, making sure to benefit his friends and harm his enemies; he also needs to be careful not to get harmed himself. A woman’s virtue, if you’re curious about that, can also be simply described: her role is to manage her household, take care of what’s inside, and obey her husband. Every age and every situation in life—whether young or old, male or female, enslaved or free—has its own kind of virtue: there are countless virtues and plenty of definitions for them; virtue is relative to our actions and ages in everything we do. The same goes for vice, Socrates (Compare Arist. Pol.).
SOCRATES: How fortunate I am, Meno! When I ask you for one virtue, you present me with a swarm of them (Compare Theaet.), which are in your keeping. Suppose that I carry on the figure of the swarm, and ask of you, What is the nature of the bee? and you answer that there are many kinds of bees, and I reply: But do bees differ as bees, because there are many and different kinds of them; or are they not rather to be distinguished by some other quality, as for example beauty, size, or shape? How would you answer me?
SOCRATES: How lucky I am, Meno! When I ask you for one virtue, you give me a whole bunch of them (Compare Theaet.), which you have. Let’s stick with the idea of the swarm, and if I ask you, What is the nature of the bee? and you respond by saying there are many types of bees, I would then ask: Do bees differ from one another just because there are many and various kinds, or are they actually distinguished by some other quality, like beauty, size, or shape? How would you respond?
MENO: I should answer that bees do not differ from one another, as bees.
MENO: I think I should say that bees are all the same, as bees.
SOCRATES: And if I went on to say: That is what I desire to know, Meno; tell me what is the quality in which they do not differ, but are all alike;—would you be able to answer?
SOCRATES: And if I continued to say: That's what I want to know, Meno; tell me what is the quality in which they don't differ but are all the same;—would you be able to answer?
MENO: I should.
I should.
SOCRATES: And so of the virtues, however many and different they may be, they have all a common nature which makes them virtues; and on this he who would answer the question, 'What is virtue?' would do well to have his eye fixed: Do you understand?
SOCRATES: So, all the virtues, no matter how many or different they are, share a common essence that makes them virtues. The person who wants to answer the question, 'What is virtue?' should really focus on this. Do you get it?
MENO: I am beginning to understand; but I do not as yet take hold of the question as I could wish.
MENO: I'm starting to get it; but I still don't fully grasp the question like I want to.
SOCRATES: When you say, Meno, that there is one virtue of a man, another of a woman, another of a child, and so on, does this apply only to virtue, or would you say the same of health, and size, and strength? Or is the nature of health always the same, whether in man or woman?
SOCRATES: When you say, Meno, that there’s one type of virtue for a man, another for a woman, and another for a child, does this only apply to virtue, or would you say the same for health, size, and strength? Or is the essence of health always the same, regardless of whether it’s in a man or a woman?
MENO: I should say that health is the same, both in man and woman.
MENO: I should say that health is the same for both men and women.
SOCRATES: And is not this true of size and strength? If a woman is strong, she will be strong by reason of the same form and of the same strength subsisting in her which there is in the man. I mean to say that strength, as strength, whether of man or woman, is the same. Is there any difference?
SOCRATES: Isn't this also true for size and strength? If a woman is strong, it’s because she has the same form and strength as a man. What I'm saying is that strength, in itself, whether in a man or a woman, is the same. Is there any difference?
MENO: I think not.
I don't think so.
SOCRATES: And will not virtue, as virtue, be the same, whether in a child or in a grown-up person, in a woman or in a man?
SOCRATES: And won't virtue, as virtue, be the same, whether in a child or an adult, in a woman or a man?
MENO: I cannot help feeling, Socrates, that this case is different from the others.
MENO: I can’t shake the feeling, Socrates, that this situation is different from the others.
SOCRATES: But why? Were you not saying that the virtue of a man was to order a state, and the virtue of a woman was to order a house?
SOCRATES: But why? Weren't you saying that a man's virtue is to manage a state, while a woman's virtue is to manage a household?
MENO: I did say so.
I really did say that.
SOCRATES: And can either house or state or anything be well ordered without temperance and without justice?
SOCRATES: Can any home or community, or anything really, be well-organized without self-control and justice?
MENO: Certainly not.
Definitely not.
SOCRATES: Then they who order a state or a house temperately or justly order them with temperance and justice?
SOCRATES: So, those who manage a state or a household wisely or fairly do so with wisdom and fairness?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: Then both men and women, if they are to be good men and women, must have the same virtues of temperance and justice?
SOCRATES: So both men and women, if they're going to be good people, must share the same virtues of self-control and fairness?
MENO: True.
MENO: For sure.
SOCRATES: And can either a young man or an elder one be good, if they are intemperate and unjust?
SOCRATES: Can a young person or an older person be good if they are lacking in self-control and unjust?
MENO: They cannot.
They can't.
SOCRATES: They must be temperate and just?
SOCRATES: So they should be moderate and fair?
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yep.
SOCRATES: Then all men are good in the same way, and by participation in the same virtues?
SOCRATES: So, are all people good in the same way, sharing the same virtues?
MENO: Such is the inference.
MENO: That's the conclusion.
SOCRATES: And they surely would not have been good in the same way, unless their virtue had been the same?
SOCRATES: They definitely wouldn't have been good in the same way unless their virtue was the same?
MENO: They would not.
They won't.
SOCRATES: Then now that the sameness of all virtue has been proven, try and remember what you and Gorgias say that virtue is.
SOCRATES: Now that we’ve established that all virtues are the same, try to recall what you and Gorgias say virtue is.
MENO: Will you have one definition of them all?
MENO: Will you have just one definition for all of them?
SOCRATES: That is what I am seeking.
SOCRATES: That's what I'm looking for.
MENO: If you want to have one definition of them all, I know not what to say, but that virtue is the power of governing mankind.
MENO: If you want a single definition for everything, I can’t say much except that virtue is the ability to lead humanity.
SOCRATES: And does this definition of virtue include all virtue? Is virtue the same in a child and in a slave, Meno? Can the child govern his father, or the slave his master; and would he who governed be any longer a slave?
SOCRATES: So, does this definition of virtue cover all of virtue? Is virtue the same in a child as it is in a slave, Meno? Can a child govern his father, or a slave his master? And would someone who governs still be considered a slave?
MENO: I think not, Socrates.
MENO: I don't think so, Socrates.
SOCRATES: No, indeed; there would be small reason in that. Yet once more, fair friend; according to you, virtue is 'the power of governing;' but do you not add 'justly and not unjustly'?
SOCRATES: No, definitely not; that wouldn't make much sense. Once again, my dear friend, you say that virtue is 'the ability to govern;' but don't you also say 'justly and not unjustly'?
MENO: Yes, Socrates; I agree there; for justice is virtue.
MENO: Yes, Socrates; I agree with you on that; justice is a form of virtue.
SOCRATES: Would you say 'virtue,' Meno, or 'a virtue'?
SOCRATES: Would you say 'virtue,' Meno, or 'a virtue'?
MENO: What do you mean?
MENO: What do you mean?
SOCRATES: I mean as I might say about anything; that a round, for example, is 'a figure' and not simply 'figure,' and I should adopt this mode of speaking, because there are other figures.
SOCRATES: What I mean is similar to anything else; for instance, a round is 'a figure' and not just 'figure,' and I use this way of speaking because there are other types of figures.
MENO: Quite right; and that is just what I am saying about virtue—that there are other virtues as well as justice.
MENO: Exactly; and that’s exactly what I’m saying about virtue—that there are other virtues besides justice.
SOCRATES: What are they? tell me the names of them, as I would tell you the names of the other figures if you asked me.
SOCRATES: What are they? Tell me their names, just like I would share the names of the other figures if you asked me.
MENO: Courage and temperance and wisdom and magnanimity are virtues; and there are many others.
MENO: Courage, self-control, wisdom, and generosity are virtues; and there are many others.
SOCRATES: Yes, Meno; and again we are in the same case: in searching after one virtue we have found many, though not in the same way as before; but we have been unable to find the common virtue which runs through them all.
SOCRATES: Yes, Meno; once again we find ourselves in the same situation: in trying to capture one virtue, we’ve discovered many, though not in the same way as before; yet we still can’t identify the common virtue that connects them all.
MENO: Why, Socrates, even now I am not able to follow you in the attempt to get at one common notion of virtue as of other things.
MENO: Why, Socrates, even now I can’t keep up with your effort to find a single definition of virtue like we do for other things.
SOCRATES: No wonder; but I will try to get nearer if I can, for you know that all things have a common notion. Suppose now that some one asked you the question which I asked before: Meno, he would say, what is figure? And if you answered 'roundness,' he would reply to you, in my way of speaking, by asking whether you would say that roundness is 'figure' or 'a figure;' and you would answer 'a figure.'
SOCRATES: No surprise there; but I’ll try to get closer if I can, since you know that everything has a shared concept. Now, imagine someone asked you the same question I asked before: Meno, they would say, what is a figure? And if you said 'roundness,' they would respond, in my way of putting it, by asking whether you would consider roundness to be 'figure' or 'a figure;' and you would reply 'a figure.'
MENO: Certainly.
Absolutely.
SOCRATES: And for this reason—that there are other figures?
SOCRATES: Is that why there are other figures?
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And if he proceeded to ask, What other figures are there? you would have told him.
SOCRATES: And if he went on to ask, What other figures are there? you would have told him.
MENO: I should.
I should.
SOCRATES: And if he similarly asked what colour is, and you answered whiteness, and the questioner rejoined, Would you say that whiteness is colour or a colour? you would reply, A colour, because there are other colours as well.
SOCRATES: And if he asked what color is, and you answered whiteness, and the questioner responded, Would you say that whiteness is color or a color? you would reply, A color, because there are other colors too.
MENO: I should.
I definitely should.
SOCRATES: And if he had said, Tell me what they are?—you would have told him of other colours which are colours just as much as whiteness.
SOCRATES: And if he had asked, "What are they?"—you would have told him about other colors that are just as much colors as whiteness is.
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yep.
SOCRATES: And suppose that he were to pursue the matter in my way, he would say: Ever and anon we are landed in particulars, but this is not what I want; tell me then, since you call them by a common name, and say that they are all figures, even when opposed to one another, what is that common nature which you designate as figure—which contains straight as well as round, and is no more one than the other—that would be your mode of speaking?
SOCRATES: If he were to look at things my way, he would say: We often get caught up in specifics, but that’s not what I’m after; so tell me this: since you refer to them with a common term and say they’re all figures, even though they’re different from one another, what is that common nature you call figure—which includes both straight and round, and is neither one more than the other? That would be your way of expressing it?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And in speaking thus, you do not mean to say that the round is round any more than straight, or the straight any more straight than round?
SOCRATES: So when you say this, you don’t mean to suggest that round is any more round than straight, or that straight is any more straight than round?
MENO: Certainly not.
Definitely not.
SOCRATES: You only assert that the round figure is not more a figure than the straight, or the straight than the round?
SOCRATES: Are you really saying that a round shape isn't any more of a shape than a straight one, or a straight shape isn't any more of a shape than a round one?
MENO: Very true.
So true.
SOCRATES: To what then do we give the name of figure? Try and answer. Suppose that when a person asked you this question either about figure or colour, you were to reply, Man, I do not understand what you want, or know what you are saying; he would look rather astonished and say: Do you not understand that I am looking for the 'simile in multis'? And then he might put the question in another form: Meno, he might say, what is that 'simile in multis' which you call figure, and which includes not only round and straight figures, but all? Could you not answer that question, Meno? I wish that you would try; the attempt will be good practice with a view to the answer about virtue.
SOCRATES: So, what do we actually mean when we say "figure"? Give it a shot. Imagine someone asks you about either figure or color, and you respond, "Man, I don’t get what you’re asking or what you mean." That person would probably look surprised and say, "Don’t you realize I’m looking for the 'simile in multis'?" Then they might rephrase the question: "Meno, what is that 'simile in multis' that you refer to as figure, which includes not just round and straight figures, but all figures?" Can you answer that, Meno? I really hope you try; it’ll be good practice for the answer about virtue.
MENO: I would rather that you should answer, Socrates.
MENO: I’d prefer if you answered, Socrates.
SOCRATES: Shall I indulge you?
SOCRATES: Should I indulge you?
MENO: By all means.
For sure.
SOCRATES: And then you will tell me about virtue?
SOCRATES: So, you're going to tell me about virtue?
MENO: I will.
Sure thing.
SOCRATES: Then I must do my best, for there is a prize to be won.
SOCRATES: Then I have to give it my all, because there's a reward to be earned.
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: Well, I will try and explain to you what figure is. What do you say to this answer?—Figure is the only thing which always follows colour. Will you be satisfied with it, as I am sure that I should be, if you would let me have a similar definition of virtue?
SOCRATES: Alright, I’ll try to explain what figure means. How do you feel about this answer?—Figure is the only thing that always comes after color. Would you be okay with that? I know I would be if you could give me a similar definition of virtue.
MENO: But, Socrates, it is such a simple answer.
MENO: But, Socrates, it's such a straightforward answer.
SOCRATES: Why simple?
SOCRATES: Why is it simple?
MENO: Because, according to you, figure is that which always follows colour.
MENO: Because, according to you, shape is something that always comes after color.
(SOCRATES: Granted.)
(SOCRATES: Agreed.)
MENO: But if a person were to say that he does not know what colour is, any more than what figure is—what sort of answer would you have given him?
MENO: But if someone were to say that they don't know what color is, just like they don't know what shape is—what kind of answer would you give them?
SOCRATES: I should have told him the truth. And if he were a philosopher of the eristic and antagonistic sort, I should say to him: You have my answer, and if I am wrong, your business is to take up the argument and refute me. But if we were friends, and were talking as you and I are now, I should reply in a milder strain and more in the dialectician's vein; that is to say, I should not only speak the truth, but I should make use of premises which the person interrogated would be willing to admit. And this is the way in which I shall endeavour to approach you. You will acknowledge, will you not, that there is such a thing as an end, or termination, or extremity?—all which words I use in the same sense, although I am aware that Prodicus might draw distinctions about them: but still you, I am sure, would speak of a thing as ended or terminated—that is all which I am saying—not anything very difficult.
SOCRATES: I should have told him the truth. And if he were the kind of philosopher who's all about argument and conflict, I'd say to him: You've got my answer, and if I'm wrong, it's your job to take the argument and prove me wrong. But if we were friends, talking like we are now, I'd respond in a gentler way and more in line with what a dialectician would do; that is to say, I wouldn't just state the truth, but I'd use premises that the person I'm talking to would be willing to accept. And that's how I plan to approach you. You'll agree, won't you, that there is such a thing as an end, or conclusion, or limit?—I use all these terms in the same way, although I know Prodicus might make distinctions about them. But still, I'm sure you would refer to something as having ended or concluded—that's all I'm saying—not anything very complicated.
MENO: Yes, I should; and I believe that I understand your meaning.
MENO: Yes, I should, and I think I get what you're saying.
SOCRATES: And you would speak of a surface and also of a solid, as for example in geometry.
SOCRATES: So, you would talk about a surface and also about a solid, like in geometry, for instance.
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: Well then, you are now in a condition to understand my definition of figure. I define figure to be that in which the solid ends; or, more concisely, the limit of solid.
SOCRATES: So now, you’re in a position to grasp my definition of figure. I define figure as that which signifies the end of a solid; or, to put it more simply, the boundary of a solid.
MENO: And now, Socrates, what is colour?
MENO: So, Socrates, what is color?
SOCRATES: You are outrageous, Meno, in thus plaguing a poor old man to give you an answer, when you will not take the trouble of remembering what is Gorgias' definition of virtue.
SOCRATES: You're unbelievable, Meno, putting a poor old man through this just to get an answer when you won't even bother to remember Gorgias' definition of virtue.
MENO: When you have told me what I ask, I will tell you, Socrates.
MENO: Once you answer my question, I’ll share my thoughts with you, Socrates.
SOCRATES: A man who was blindfolded has only to hear you talking, and he would know that you are a fair creature and have still many lovers.
SOCRATES: A man who's blindfolded just needs to hear you speak, and he'll know that you're an attractive person and have plenty of admirers.
MENO: Why do you think so?
MENO: Why do you think that?
SOCRATES: Why, because you always speak in imperatives: like all beauties when they are in their prime, you are tyrannical; and also, as I suspect, you have found out that I have weakness for the fair, and therefore to humour you I must answer.
SOCRATES: Well, it's because you always talk in commands: like all beauties when they're at their best, you're overbearing; and also, I think you've realized that I have a weakness for attractive people, so to please you, I have to respond.
MENO: Please do.
MENO: Go ahead.
SOCRATES: Would you like me to answer you after the manner of Gorgias, which is familiar to you?
SOCRATES: Do you want me to respond like Gorgias, as you're used to?
MENO: I should like nothing better.
I totally agree.
SOCRATES: Do not he and you and Empedocles say that there are certain effluences of existence?
SOCRATES: Don't he, you, and Empedocles say that there are certain outflows of existence?
MENO: Certainly.
Definitely.
SOCRATES: And passages into which and through which the effluences pass?
SOCRATES: And what about the passages that the effluences go into and through?
MENO: Exactly.
MENO: Exactly.
SOCRATES: And some of the effluences fit into the passages, and some of them are too small or too large?
SOCRATES: So, some of the substances fit into the openings, while others are either too small or too large?
MENO: True.
MENO: Facts.
SOCRATES: And there is such a thing as sight?
SOCRATES: So, does sight really exist?
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And now, as Pindar says, 'read my meaning:'—colour is an effluence of form, commensurate with sight, and palpable to sense.
SOCRATES: And now, as Pindar says, 'understand what I mean:'—color is a result of form, to be measured by sight, and noticeable to the senses.
MENO: That, Socrates, appears to me to be an admirable answer.
MENO: That seems like a fantastic answer, Socrates.
SOCRATES: Why, yes, because it happens to be one which you have been in the habit of hearing: and your wit will have discovered, I suspect, that you may explain in the same way the nature of sound and smell, and of many other similar phenomena.
SOCRATES: Well, yes, because it's something you've gotten used to hearing: and I think you've realized that you can explain the nature of sound and smell, along with many other similar things, in the same way.
MENO: Quite true.
Totally true.
SOCRATES: The answer, Meno, was in the orthodox solemn vein, and therefore was more acceptable to you than the other answer about figure.
SOCRATES: The answer, Meno, was in the traditional serious style, and so it was more acceptable to you than the other answer about the figure.
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And yet, O son of Alexidemus, I cannot help thinking that the other was the better; and I am sure that you would be of the same opinion, if you would only stay and be initiated, and were not compelled, as you said yesterday, to go away before the mysteries.
SOCRATES: And yet, oh son of Alexidemus, I can’t help but think that the other was better; and I’m sure you would agree if you just stayed and got initiated instead of having to leave before the mysteries, like you mentioned yesterday.
MENO: But I will stay, Socrates, if you will give me many such answers.
MENO: But I'll stick around, Socrates, if you keep giving me answers like that.
SOCRATES: Well then, for my own sake as well as for yours, I will do my very best; but I am afraid that I shall not be able to give you very many as good: and now, in your turn, you are to fulfil your promise, and tell me what virtue is in the universal; and do not make a singular into a plural, as the facetious say of those who break a thing, but deliver virtue to me whole and sound, and not broken into a number of pieces: I have given you the pattern.
SOCRATES: Alright then, for both our sakes, I’ll do my best; but I’m afraid I won’t be able to give you very many that are just as good. Now it’s your turn to keep your promise and tell me what virtue is in general. And don’t turn something singular into plural, as the jokers say about those who break something; instead, present virtue to me complete and intact, not shattered into pieces. I’ve given you the example.
MENO: Well then, Socrates, virtue, as I take it, is when he, who desires the honourable, is able to provide it for himself; so the poet says, and I say too—
MENO: Well then, Socrates, I believe that virtue is when someone who wants to do what’s right can actually achieve it for themselves; that's what the poet says, and I agree—
'Virtue is the desire of things honourable and the power of attaining them.'
'Virtue is the desire for noble things and the ability to achieve them.'
SOCRATES: And does he who desires the honourable also desire the good?
SOCRATES: Does someone who wants what's honorable also want what's good?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: Then are there some who desire the evil and others who desire the good? Do not all men, my dear sir, desire good?
SOCRATES: So, are there some people who want to do bad things and others who want to do good things? Don’t all people, my dear sir, want what’s good?
MENO: I think not.
I don't think so.
SOCRATES: There are some who desire evil?
SOCRATES: Are there people who actually want to do evil?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: Do you mean that they think the evils which they desire, to be good; or do they know that they are evil and yet desire them?
SOCRATES: Are you saying that they believe the bad things they want are good, or do they know they are bad and still want them?
MENO: Both, I think.
MENO: I think both.
SOCRATES: And do you really imagine, Meno, that a man knows evils to be evils and desires them notwithstanding?
SOCRATES: Do you really think, Meno, that a person knows something is bad and still wants it anyway?
MENO: Certainly I do.
For sure, I do.
SOCRATES: And desire is of possession?
SOCRATES: So, desire is about wanting to have something?
MENO: Yes, of possession.
Yes, of ownership.
SOCRATES: And does he think that the evils will do good to him who possesses them, or does he know that they will do him harm?
SOCRATES: Does he believe that the evils will benefit the person who has them, or does he understand that they will cause him harm?
MENO: There are some who think that the evils will do them good, and others who know that they will do them harm.
MENO: Some people believe that bad things will benefit them, while others are aware that they will cause them harm.
SOCRATES: And, in your opinion, do those who think that they will do them good know that they are evils?
SOCRATES: So, do you think that those who believe they are doing good actually realize that they are doing evil?
MENO: Certainly not.
Definitely not.
SOCRATES: Is it not obvious that those who are ignorant of their nature do not desire them; but they desire what they suppose to be goods although they are really evils; and if they are mistaken and suppose the evils to be goods they really desire goods?
SOCRATES: Isn't it clear that those who don’t understand their true nature don’t want them; instead, they want what they think are good things, even though they’re actually bad; and if they’re wrong and think the bad things are good, then they truly want the good things?
MENO: Yes, in that case.
MENO: Yeah, in that case.
SOCRATES: Well, and do those who, as you say, desire evils, and think that evils are hurtful to the possessor of them, know that they will be hurt by them?
SOCRATES: So, do the people who, as you say, want bad things and believe that bad things are harmful to those who have them, actually realize that they'll be hurt by them?
MENO: They must know it.
They have to know it.
SOCRATES: And must they not suppose that those who are hurt are miserable in proportion to the hurt which is inflicted upon them?
SOCRATES: And shouldn't they think that those who are hurt are unhappy in proportion to the harm done to them?
MENO: How can it be otherwise?
MENO: How else could it be?
SOCRATES: But are not the miserable ill-fated?
SOCRATES: But aren't the unfortunate ones ill-fated?
MENO: Yes, indeed.
Absolutely.
SOCRATES: And does any one desire to be miserable and ill-fated?
SOCRATES: Does anyone actually want to be unhappy and unfortunate?
MENO: I should say not, Socrates.
MENO: I certainly don't think so, Socrates.
SOCRATES: But if there is no one who desires to be miserable, there is no one, Meno, who desires evil; for what is misery but the desire and possession of evil?
SOCRATES: But if no one wants to be unhappy, then no one, Meno, wants to do wrong; because what is unhappiness if not wanting and having something bad?
MENO: That appears to be the truth, Socrates, and I admit that nobody desires evil.
MENO: That seems to be true, Socrates, and I acknowledge that no one wants to do evil.
SOCRATES: And yet, were you not saying just now that virtue is the desire and power of attaining good?
SOCRATES: And yet, weren't you just saying that virtue is the desire and ability to achieve what is good?
MENO: Yes, I did say so.
MENO: Yeah, I did say that.
SOCRATES: But if this be affirmed, then the desire of good is common to all, and one man is no better than another in that respect?
SOCRATES: But if this is true, then the desire for good is shared by everyone, and one person isn't any better than another in that sense?
MENO: True.
MENO: For sure.
SOCRATES: And if one man is not better than another in desiring good, he must be better in the power of attaining it?
SOCRATES: And if one person doesn't want good more than another, they must be better at actually achieving it?
MENO: Exactly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: Then, according to your definition, virtue would appear to be the power of attaining good?
SOCRATES: So, based on your definition, virtue seems to be the ability to achieve good?
MENO: I entirely approve, Socrates, of the manner in which you now view this matter.
MENO: I completely agree with how you see this issue now, Socrates.
SOCRATES: Then let us see whether what you say is true from another point of view; for very likely you may be right:—You affirm virtue to be the power of attaining goods?
SOCRATES: Let's take a look at what you're saying from a different perspective; you might actually be right: Do you assert that virtue is the ability to achieve good things?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And the goods which you mean are such as health and wealth and the possession of gold and silver, and having office and honour in the state—those are what you would call goods?
SOCRATES: So, the things you're talking about are things like health and wealth, having gold and silver, and having a position and respect in the community—those are what you consider valuable?
MENO: Yes, I should include all those.
MENO: Yeah, I should include all of that.
SOCRATES: Then, according to Meno, who is the hereditary friend of the great king, virtue is the power of getting silver and gold; and would you add that they must be gained piously, justly, or do you deem this to be of no consequence? And is any mode of acquisition, even if unjust and dishonest, equally to be deemed virtue?
SOCRATES: So, based on what Meno says, who is the loyal friend of the great king, virtue is about being able to acquire silver and gold. Would you agree that these should be obtained in a pious and just way, or do you think that doesn’t matter? Is any method of gaining wealth, even if it's unjust or dishonest, still considered virtue?
MENO: Not virtue, Socrates, but vice.
MENO: Not virtue, Socrates, but vice.
SOCRATES: Then justice or temperance or holiness, or some other part of virtue, as would appear, must accompany the acquisition, and without them the mere acquisition of good will not be virtue.
SOCRATES: So, justice, temperance, holiness, or some other aspect of virtue, as it seems, must come along with the gaining of good, and without them, just getting good won’t count as virtue.
MENO: Why, how can there be virtue without these?
MENO: How can there be virtue without these?
SOCRATES: And the non-acquisition of gold and silver in a dishonest manner for oneself or another, or in other words the want of them, may be equally virtue?
SOCRATES: So is it possible that not acquiring gold and silver through dishonest means, for yourself or for someone else, or in other words, lacking them, might also be considered a virtue?
MENO: True.
MENO: For sure.
SOCRATES: Then the acquisition of such goods is no more virtue than the non-acquisition and want of them, but whatever is accompanied by justice or honesty is virtue, and whatever is devoid of justice is vice.
SOCRATES: So, gaining these kinds of goods is no more virtuous than not gaining them and being without them; instead, whatever is paired with justice or honesty is virtue, and whatever lacks justice is vice.
MENO: It cannot be otherwise, in my judgment.
MENO: I don't think it can be any other way, in my opinion.
SOCRATES: And were we not saying just now that justice, temperance, and the like, were each of them a part of virtue?
SOCRATES: And weren't we just saying that justice, temperance, and the like, are each a part of virtue?
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And so, Meno, this is the way in which you mock me.
SOCRATES: So, Meno, this is how you tease me.
MENO: Why do you say that, Socrates?
MENO: Why do you say that, Socrates?
SOCRATES: Why, because I asked you to deliver virtue into my hands whole and unbroken, and I gave you a pattern according to which you were to frame your answer; and you have forgotten already, and tell me that virtue is the power of attaining good justly, or with justice; and justice you acknowledge to be a part of virtue.
SOCRATES: Well, it’s because I asked you to give me a complete and intact idea of virtue, and I provided you with a model to shape your response; yet you’ve already forgotten and now claim that virtue is the ability to achieve good fairly or justly, while you acknowledge that justice is a part of virtue.
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: Then it follows from your own admissions, that virtue is doing what you do with a part of virtue; for justice and the like are said by you to be parts of virtue.
SOCRATES: So, based on what you've said, it seems that virtue involves doing what you do with a portion of virtue; since you say that justice and similar qualities are parts of virtue.
MENO: What of that?
What about that?
SOCRATES: What of that! Why, did not I ask you to tell me the nature of virtue as a whole? And you are very far from telling me this; but declare every action to be virtue which is done with a part of virtue; as though you had told me and I must already know the whole of virtue, and this too when frittered away into little pieces. And, therefore, my dear Meno, I fear that I must begin again and repeat the same question: What is virtue? for otherwise, I can only say, that every action done with a part of virtue is virtue; what else is the meaning of saying that every action done with justice is virtue? Ought I not to ask the question over again; for can any one who does not know virtue know a part of virtue?
SOCRATES: What's the point of that! Didn't I ask you to explain the nature of virtue as a whole? You're very far from doing that; instead, you claim that every action done with a bit of virtue is virtue, as if you've told me everything I need to know about virtue, even when it's broken down into tiny pieces. So, my dear Meno, I think I need to start over and ask the same question: What is virtue? Because otherwise, I can only say that every action done with a bit of virtue is virtue; what else does it mean to say that every action done with justice is virtue? Shouldn't I ask the question again? Can anyone who doesn't know what virtue is really understand a part of virtue?
MENO: No; I do not say that he can.
MENO: No; I’m not saying that he can.
SOCRATES: Do you remember how, in the example of figure, we rejected any answer given in terms which were as yet unexplained or unadmitted?
SOCRATES: Do you remember how, in the example of the figure, we dismissed any answers that were given using terms that were still unexplained or unaccepted?
MENO: Yes, Socrates; and we were quite right in doing so.
MENO: Yes, Socrates; and we were totally right to do that.
SOCRATES: But then, my friend, do not suppose that we can explain to any one the nature of virtue as a whole through some unexplained portion of virtue, or anything at all in that fashion; we should only have to ask over again the old question, What is virtue? Am I not right?
SOCRATES: But then, my friend, don’t think that we can explain the nature of virtue as a whole by using just a part of it, or anything like that; we would just have to ask the same old question, What is virtue? Am I wrong?
MENO: I believe that you are.
MENO: I believe you are.
SOCRATES: Then begin again, and answer me, What, according to you and your friend Gorgias, is the definition of virtue?
SOCRATES: So let’s start over, and tell me, what do you and your friend Gorgias believe is the definition of virtue?
MENO: O Socrates, I used to be told, before I knew you, that you were always doubting yourself and making others doubt; and now you are casting your spells over me, and I am simply getting bewitched and enchanted, and am at my wits' end. And if I may venture to make a jest upon you, you seem to me both in your appearance and in your power over others to be very like the flat torpedo fish, who torpifies those who come near him and touch him, as you have now torpified me, I think. For my soul and my tongue are really torpid, and I do not know how to answer you; and though I have been delivered of an infinite variety of speeches about virtue before now, and to many persons—and very good ones they were, as I thought—at this moment I cannot even say what virtue is. And I think that you are very wise in not voyaging and going away from home, for if you did in other places as you do in Athens, you would be cast into prison as a magician.
MENO: Oh Socrates, before I knew you, people used to tell me that you always doubted yourself and made others doubt as well; and now you’re casting your spells on me, and I’m just getting completely enchanted and confused, and I don’t know what to do. If I can make a little joke about you, you seem to me, both in how you look and in how you influence others, a lot like a flat torpedo fish, which paralyzes anyone who gets too close or touches it, just as I feel paralyzed by you right now. My mind and my tongue are really sluggish, and I can’t figure out how to respond to you; even though I’ve given countless talks about virtue before, to a lot of people—and I thought they were really good—right now I can’t even say what virtue is. I think you’re really smart for not traveling far from home, because if you acted the same way you do in Athens elsewhere, you’d probably end up in jail as a magician.
SOCRATES: You are a rogue, Meno, and had all but caught me.
SOCRATES: You're a trickster, Meno, and you almost had me there.
MENO: What do you mean, Socrates?
MENO: What do you mean, Socrates?
SOCRATES: I can tell why you made a simile about me.
SOCRATES: I understand why you compared me to something else.
MENO: Why?
MENO: Why?
SOCRATES: In order that I might make another simile about you. For I know that all pretty young gentlemen like to have pretty similes made about them—as well they may—but I shall not return the compliment. As to my being a torpedo, if the torpedo is torpid as well as the cause of torpidity in others, then indeed I am a torpedo, but not otherwise; for I perplex others, not because I am clear, but because I am utterly perplexed myself. And now I know not what virtue is, and you seem to be in the same case, although you did once perhaps know before you touched me. However, I have no objection to join with you in the enquiry.
SOCRATES: I want to create another comparison about you. I know that all attractive young men enjoy having nice comparisons made about them—as they should—but I won’t return the favor. As for me being a torpedo, if the torpedo is sluggish and also causes sluggishness in others, then I suppose I am one, but not in any other way; I confuse others not because I am clear, but because I am completely baffled myself. And now, I don’t know what virtue is, and you seem to be in the same situation, even though you might have known at one point before you interacted with me. Still, I don’t mind joining you in the search for answers.
MENO: And how will you enquire, Socrates, into that which you do not know? What will you put forth as the subject of enquiry? And if you find what you want, how will you ever know that this is the thing which you did not know?
MENO: So how will you, Socrates, investigate something you don't know? What will you focus on as your topic of inquiry? And if you do find what you're looking for, how will you know it's actually the thing you didn't know?
SOCRATES: I know, Meno, what you mean; but just see what a tiresome dispute you are introducing. You argue that a man cannot enquire either about that which he knows, or about that which he does not know; for if he knows, he has no need to enquire; and if not, he cannot; for he does not know the very subject about which he is to enquire (Compare Aristot. Post. Anal.).
SOCRATES: I get what you’re saying, Meno, but look at the annoying debate you’re bringing up. You say that a person can’t ask questions about what they know or what they don’t know; because if they know, they don’t need to ask, and if they don’t know, they can’t ask since they’re not even clear on the topic they’re supposed to be inquiring about.
MENO: Well, Socrates, and is not the argument sound?
MENO: So, Socrates, isn't the argument valid?
SOCRATES: I think not.
SOCRATES: I don't think so.
MENO: Why not?
Why not?
SOCRATES: I will tell you why: I have heard from certain wise men and women who spoke of things divine that—
SOCRATES: I'll tell you why: I've heard from some wise men and women who talked about divine matters that—
MENO: What did they say?
MENO: What did they say?
SOCRATES: They spoke of a glorious truth, as I conceive.
SOCRATES: They talked about a wonderful truth, as I see it.
MENO: What was it? and who were they?
MENO: What was it? And who were they?
SOCRATES: Some of them were priests and priestesses, who had studied how they might be able to give a reason of their profession: there have been poets also, who spoke of these things by inspiration, like Pindar, and many others who were inspired. And they say—mark, now, and see whether their words are true—they say that the soul of man is immortal, and at one time has an end, which is termed dying, and at another time is born again, but is never destroyed. And the moral is, that a man ought to live always in perfect holiness. 'For in the ninth year Persephone sends the souls of those from whom she has received the penalty of ancient crime back again from beneath into the light of the sun above, and these are they who become noble kings and mighty men and great in wisdom and are called saintly heroes in after ages.' The soul, then, as being immortal, and having been born again many times, and having seen all things that exist, whether in this world or in the world below, has knowledge of them all; and it is no wonder that she should be able to call to remembrance all that she ever knew about virtue, and about everything; for as all nature is akin, and the soul has learned all things; there is no difficulty in her eliciting or as men say learning, out of a single recollection all the rest, if a man is strenuous and does not faint; for all enquiry and all learning is but recollection. And therefore we ought not to listen to this sophistical argument about the impossibility of enquiry: for it will make us idle; and is sweet only to the sluggard; but the other saying will make us active and inquisitive. In that confiding, I will gladly enquire with you into the nature of virtue.
SOCRATES: Some of them were priests and priestesses who studied how to explain their profession. There were also poets who spoke about these things through inspiration, like Pindar, and many others who were inspired too. They say—pay attention and see if their words are true—they say that the soul of man is immortal. At one point, it ends, which is referred to as dying, and at another time, it is reborn, but it is never destroyed. The takeaway is that a person should always live in complete holiness. 'In the ninth year, Persephone sends back the souls of those who have paid the penalty for ancient crimes from below into the light of the sun above, and these are the ones who become noble kings and mighty figures and are renowned for great wisdom, known as saintly heroes in later times.' The soul, then, being immortal and having been reborn many times and having witnessed everything that exists, whether in this world or the underworld, knows all of it; it's not surprising that it can recall everything it ever knew about virtue and about everything else. Because all nature is interconnected, and the soul has learned all things, it's not difficult for it to draw out of one single memory all the others if a person is persistent and doesn't give up; because all inquiry and all learning is just recollection. Therefore, we shouldn't pay attention to this tricky argument about the impossibility of inquiry: it will make us lazy and only appeals to the idle; but the other perspective will drive us to be active and curious. With that confidence, I'm eager to explore with you the nature of virtue.
MENO: Yes, Socrates; but what do you mean by saying that we do not learn, and that what we call learning is only a process of recollection? Can you teach me how this is?
MENO: Yes, Socrates; but what do you mean when you say that we don’t actually learn, and that what we call learning is just a process of remembering? Can you explain how this works?
SOCRATES: I told you, Meno, just now that you were a rogue, and now you ask whether I can teach you, when I am saying that there is no teaching, but only recollection; and thus you imagine that you will involve me in a contradiction.
SOCRATES: I just told you, Meno, that you're being tricky, and now you want to know if I can teach you, even though I'm saying that teaching doesn't exist, only remembering; and so you think you'll catch me in a contradiction.
MENO: Indeed, Socrates, I protest that I had no such intention. I only asked the question from habit; but if you can prove to me that what you say is true, I wish that you would.
MENO: Honestly, Socrates, I swear I didn't mean to do that. I only asked the question out of habit; but if you can show me that what you're saying is true, I would really appreciate it.
SOCRATES: It will be no easy matter, but I will try to please you to the utmost of my power. Suppose that you call one of your numerous attendants, that I may demonstrate on him.
SOCRATES: It won't be easy, but I'll do my best to satisfy you. Let's say you call one of your many attendants so I can show you.
MENO: Certainly. Come hither, boy.
MENO: Sure. Come here, boy.
SOCRATES: He is Greek, and speaks Greek, does he not?
SOCRATES: He’s Greek and speaks Greek, right?
MENO: Yes, indeed; he was born in the house.
MENO: Yes, that's right; he was born in this house.
SOCRATES: Attend now to the questions which I ask him, and observe whether he learns of me or only remembers.
SOCRATES: Pay attention to the questions I ask him and see if he learns from me or just recalls what he already knows.
MENO: I will.
I will.
SOCRATES: Tell me, boy, do you know that a figure like this is a square?
SOCRATES: Tell me, kid, do you know that a shape like this is a square?
BOY: I do.
I do.
SOCRATES: And you know that a square figure has these four lines equal?
SOCRATES: And you know that a square has four equal sides?
BOY: Certainly.
Sure thing.
SOCRATES: And these lines which I have drawn through the middle of the square are also equal?
SOCRATES: Are these lines I’ve drawn through the middle of the square also equal?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: A square may be of any size?
SOCRATES: A square can be any size?
BOY: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And if one side of the figure be of two feet, and the other side be of two feet, how much will the whole be? Let me explain: if in one direction the space was of two feet, and in the other direction of one foot, the whole would be of two feet taken once?
SOCRATES: If one side of the figure is two feet, and the other side is also two feet, how much will that total? Let me clarify: if one direction is two feet and the other direction is one foot, would the total still be two feet?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: But since this side is also of two feet, there are twice two feet?
SOCRATES: But since this side is also two feet long, is there twice two feet?
BOY: There are.
There are.
SOCRATES: Then the square is of twice two feet?
SOCRATES: So the square is four square feet?
BOY: Yes.
Yeah.
SOCRATES: And how many are twice two feet? count and tell me.
SOCRATES: How many is two times two feet? Count and let me know.
BOY: Four, Socrates.
BOY: Four, Socrates.
SOCRATES: And might there not be another square twice as large as this, and having like this the lines equal?
SOCRATES: Isn't it possible that there could be another square that's twice as large as this one, with sides that are equal just like this?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And of how many feet will that be?
SOCRATES: And how many feet will that be?
BOY: Of eight feet.
BOY: Eight feet long.
SOCRATES: And now try and tell me the length of the line which forms the side of that double square: this is two feet—what will that be?
SOCRATES: Now, please tell me the length of the line that makes up the side of that double square: this is two feet—what will that be?
BOY: Clearly, Socrates, it will be double.
BOY: Clearly, Socrates, it will be double.
SOCRATES: Do you observe, Meno, that I am not teaching the boy anything, but only asking him questions; and now he fancies that he knows how long a line is necessary in order to produce a figure of eight square feet; does he not?
SOCRATES: Do you see, Meno, that I'm not teaching the boy anything, but just asking him questions? And now he thinks he knows how long a line is needed to create a figure of eight square feet; doesn’t he?
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And does he really know?
SOCRATES: So does he actually know?
MENO: Certainly not.
Definitely not.
SOCRATES: He only guesses that because the square is double, the line is double.
SOCRATES: He just assumes that because the square is double, the line is double.
MENO: True.
MENO: For sure.
SOCRATES: Observe him while he recalls the steps in regular order. (To the Boy:) Tell me, boy, do you assert that a double space comes from a double line? Remember that I am not speaking of an oblong, but of a figure equal every way, and twice the size of this—that is to say of eight feet; and I want to know whether you still say that a double square comes from double line?
SOCRATES: Watch him as he goes through the steps in the right order. (To the Boy:) Tell me, boy, do you really think that a double space comes from a double line? Just to be clear, I’m not talking about a rectangle, but a shape that is equal on all sides and twice the size of this one—that is, eight feet; and I want to know if you still believe that a double square comes from a double line?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: But does not this line become doubled if we add another such line here?
SOCRATES: But doesn’t this line double if we add another one here?
BOY: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And four such lines will make a space containing eight feet?
SOCRATES: So, four lines like that will create a space that’s eight feet?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: Let us describe such a figure: Would you not say that this is the figure of eight feet?
SOCRATES: Let's describe this figure: Wouldn't you agree that this is the figure of eight feet?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And are there not these four divisions in the figure, each of which is equal to the figure of four feet?
SOCRATES: And aren't there these four sections in the shape, each of which is equal to the shape of four feet?
BOY: True.
BOY: For sure.
SOCRATES: And is not that four times four?
SOCRATES: Isn't that four times four?
BOY: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And four times is not double?
SOCRATES: So four times isn’t double?
BOY: No, indeed.
BOY: Nope, definitely not.
SOCRATES: But how much?
SOCRATES: But how much is it?
BOY: Four times as much.
BOY: Four times more.
SOCRATES: Therefore the double line, boy, has given a space, not twice, but four times as much.
SOCRATES: So the double line, kid, has created a space, not double, but four times as much.
BOY: True.
BOY: For real.
SOCRATES: Four times four are sixteen—are they not?
SOCRATES: Four times four is sixteen, right?
BOY: Yes.
Sure.
SOCRATES: What line would give you a space of eight feet, as this gives one of sixteen feet;—do you see?
SOCRATES: What line would give you a length of eight feet, like this one gives a length of sixteen feet;—do you understand?
BOY: Yes.
BOY: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And the space of four feet is made from this half line?
SOCRATES: So, this half line makes up a space of four feet?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: Good; and is not a space of eight feet twice the size of this, and half the size of the other?
SOCRATES: Great; so isn't a space that's eight feet long twice the size of this one and half the size of the other?
BOY: Certainly.
BOY: Of course.
SOCRATES: Such a space, then, will be made out of a line greater than this one, and less than that one?
SOCRATES: So, a space like that will be created from a line that's bigger than this one and smaller than that one?
BOY: Yes; I think so.
BOY: Yeah, I think so.
SOCRATES: Very good; I like to hear you say what you think. And now tell me, is not this a line of two feet and that of four?
SOCRATES: That sounds great; I appreciate you sharing your thoughts. Now tell me, isn’t this a line of two feet and that one of four?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: Then the line which forms the side of eight feet ought to be more than this line of two feet, and less than the other of four feet?
SOCRATES: So the line that measures eight feet should be longer than this line of two feet, but shorter than the other one that measures four feet?
BOY: It ought.
BOY: It should.
SOCRATES: Try and see if you can tell me how much it will be.
SOCRATES: Give it a try and let me know how much you think it will be.
BOY: Three feet.
BOY: Three feet tall.
SOCRATES: Then if we add a half to this line of two, that will be the line of three. Here are two and there is one; and on the other side, here are two also and there is one: and that makes the figure of which you speak?
SOCRATES: So if we add a half to this line of two, we'll have the line of three. Here are two and there's one; and on the other side, there are two as well and there's one: that creates the figure you're talking about?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: But if there are three feet this way and three feet that way, the whole space will be three times three feet?
SOCRATES: But if there are three feet this way and three feet that way, the total area will be three times three feet?
BOY: That is evident.
BOY: That's obvious.
SOCRATES: And how much are three times three feet?
SOCRATES: So, what’s three times three feet?
BOY: Nine.
Boy: 9.
SOCRATES: And how much is the double of four?
SOCRATES: So, what's two times four?
BOY: Eight.
Eight.
SOCRATES: Then the figure of eight is not made out of a line of three?
SOCRATES: So, the figure eight isn't created from a line of three?
BOY: No.
No.
SOCRATES: But from what line?—tell me exactly; and if you would rather not reckon, try and show me the line.
SOCRATES: But from what line? —just tell me clearly; and if you’d rather not count, try to show me the line.
BOY: Indeed, Socrates, I do not know.
BOY: Honestly, Socrates, I have no idea.
SOCRATES: Do you see, Meno, what advances he has made in his power of recollection? He did not know at first, and he does not know now, what is the side of a figure of eight feet: but then he thought that he knew, and answered confidently as if he knew, and had no difficulty; now he has a difficulty, and neither knows nor fancies that he knows.
SOCRATES: Do you see, Meno, how far he has come in his ability to remember? He didn't know at first, and he still doesn't know, what the side of a figure is that's eight feet long: but back then he thought he knew, and answered confidently as if he did, without any struggle; now he has a problem, and he neither knows nor pretends that he knows.
MENO: True.
MENO: For sure.
SOCRATES: Is he not better off in knowing his ignorance?
SOCRATES: Isn't he better off knowing his ignorance?
MENO: I think that he is.
I think he is.
SOCRATES: If we have made him doubt, and given him the 'torpedo's shock,' have we done him any harm?
SOCRATES: If we've made him question things and given him a 'shock like a torpedo,' have we harmed him at all?
MENO: I think not.
MENO: I don't think so.
SOCRATES: We have certainly, as would seem, assisted him in some degree to the discovery of the truth; and now he will wish to remedy his ignorance, but then he would have been ready to tell all the world again and again that the double space should have a double side.
SOCRATES: It seems we have helped him a bit to uncover the truth; now he’ll want to fix his ignorance, but he’d have been eager to tell everyone over and over again that a double space should have a double side.
MENO: True.
MENO: For sure.
SOCRATES: But do you suppose that he would ever have enquired into or learned what he fancied that he knew, though he was really ignorant of it, until he had fallen into perplexity under the idea that he did not know, and had desired to know?
SOCRATES: But do you think he would have ever questioned or learned about what he believed he knew, even though he was really clueless, until he got confused by the idea that he didn’t know and wanted to find out?
MENO: I think not, Socrates.
MENO: I don't think so, Socrates.
SOCRATES: Then he was the better for the torpedo's touch?
SOCRATES: So, he benefited from the touch of the torpedo?
MENO: I think so.
I believe so.
SOCRATES: Mark now the farther development. I shall only ask him, and not teach him, and he shall share the enquiry with me: and do you watch and see if you find me telling or explaining anything to him, instead of eliciting his opinion. Tell me, boy, is not this a square of four feet which I have drawn?
SOCRATES: Now, pay attention to what happens next. I’m just going to ask him questions and not teach him anything, and he’ll join me in the quest for understanding. You should observe and see if I’m telling or explaining anything to him instead of drawing out his own thoughts. Tell me, boy, isn’t this a square that measures four feet on each side?
BOY: Yes.
Yep.
SOCRATES: And now I add another square equal to the former one?
SOCRATES: So now I’m adding another square that’s equal to the first one?
BOY: Yes.
BOY: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And a third, which is equal to either of them?
SOCRATES: So, what about a third one that is equal to either of those?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: Suppose that we fill up the vacant corner?
SOCRATES: What if we fill in the empty corner?
BOY: Very good.
Awesome.
SOCRATES: Here, then, there are four equal spaces?
SOCRATES: So, there are four equal spaces here?
BOY: Yes.
BOY: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And how many times larger is this space than this other?
SOCRATES: So, how many times bigger is this area compared to that one?
BOY: Four times.
BOY: Four times.
SOCRATES: But it ought to have been twice only, as you will remember.
SOCRATES: But it should have only happened twice, as you will recall.
BOY: True.
BOY: For sure.
SOCRATES: And does not this line, reaching from corner to corner, bisect each of these spaces?
SOCRATES: Doesn't this line, stretching from corner to corner, divide each of these areas?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And are there not here four equal lines which contain this space?
SOCRATES: Aren't there four equal lines that define this area?
BOY: There are.
There are.
SOCRATES: Look and see how much this space is.
SOCRATES: Take a look and see how big this space is.
BOY: I do not understand.
BOY: I don't get it.
SOCRATES: Has not each interior line cut off half of the four spaces?
SOCRATES: Hasn’t each inner line split half of the four spaces?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And how many spaces are there in this section?
SOCRATES: So, how many spaces are there in this section?
BOY: Four.
Four.
SOCRATES: And how many in this?
SOCRATES: So, how many are there in this?
BOY: Two.
Two.
SOCRATES: And four is how many times two?
SOCRATES: So, how many times is two in four?
BOY: Twice.
BOY: Two times.
SOCRATES: And this space is of how many feet?
SOCRATES: So, how big is this space in feet?
BOY: Of eight feet.
Eight feet long.
SOCRATES: And from what line do you get this figure?
SOCRATES: So where does this figure come from?
BOY: From this.
BOY: From this.
SOCRATES: That is, from the line which extends from corner to corner of the figure of four feet?
SOCRATES: You mean the line that goes from one corner to the opposite corner of the shape that has four sides?
BOY: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And that is the line which the learned call the diagonal. And if this is the proper name, then you, Meno's slave, are prepared to affirm that the double space is the square of the diagonal?
SOCRATES: And that’s what the experts refer to as the diagonal. If that's the correct term, then you, Meno's slave, are ready to agree that the double area is the square of the diagonal?
BOY: Certainly, Socrates.
Sure thing, Socrates.
SOCRATES: What do you say of him, Meno? Were not all these answers given out of his own head?
SOCRATES: What do you think of him, Meno? Weren't all these answers his own thoughts?
MENO: Yes, they were all his own.
MENO: Yes, they were all his.
SOCRATES: And yet, as we were just now saying, he did not know?
SOCRATES: And yet, as we just said, he didn’t know?
MENO: True.
True.
SOCRATES: But still he had in him those notions of his—had he not?
SOCRATES: But he still had those ideas of his—didn’t he?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: Then he who does not know may still have true notions of that which he does not know?
SOCRATES: So, someone who doesn't know can still have accurate ideas about what they don't know?
MENO: He has.
He's got it.
SOCRATES: And at present these notions have just been stirred up in him, as in a dream; but if he were frequently asked the same questions, in different forms, he would know as well as any one at last?
SOCRATES: Right now, these ideas have just been brought to his attention, like in a dream; but if he were asked the same questions repeatedly, in different ways, he would eventually know just as well as anyone else, right?
MENO: I dare say.
I must say.
SOCRATES: Without any one teaching him he will recover his knowledge for himself, if he is only asked questions?
SOCRATES: Without anyone teaching him, he will rediscover his knowledge on his own if he is simply asked questions?
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And this spontaneous recovery of knowledge in him is recollection?
SOCRATES: So, this natural recall of knowledge in him is what we call recollection?
MENO: True.
MENO: For sure.
SOCRATES: And this knowledge which he now has must he not either have acquired or always possessed?
SOCRATES: So, this knowledge he has now, he must have either gained it or always had it, right?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: But if he always possessed this knowledge he would always have known; or if he has acquired the knowledge he could not have acquired it in this life, unless he has been taught geometry; for he may be made to do the same with all geometry and every other branch of knowledge. Now, has any one ever taught him all this? You must know about him, if, as you say, he was born and bred in your house.
SOCRATES: But if he always had this knowledge, then he would have always known it; or if he learned it, he couldn't have done so in this life unless he was taught geometry. He could be made to do the same with all of geometry and every other area of knowledge. Now, has anyone ever taught him all this? You must know about him if, as you say, he was born and raised in your house.
MENO: And I am certain that no one ever did teach him.
MENO: And I'm sure that no one ever taught him.
SOCRATES: And yet he has the knowledge?
SOCRATES: So he really has the knowledge?
MENO: The fact, Socrates, is undeniable.
MENO: The truth is, Socrates, it's undeniable.
SOCRATES: But if he did not acquire the knowledge in this life, then he must have had and learned it at some other time?
SOCRATES: But if he didn't gain that knowledge in this life, then he must have had it and learned it at some other time?
MENO: Clearly he must.
He obviously must.
SOCRATES: Which must have been the time when he was not a man?
SOCRATES: When do you think he wasn't a man?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And if there have been always true thoughts in him, both at the time when he was and was not a man, which only need to be awakened into knowledge by putting questions to him, his soul must have always possessed this knowledge, for he always either was or was not a man?
SOCRATES: And if he has always had true thoughts, even when he was and wasn't a man, which just need to be brought to light by asking him questions, then his soul must have always had this knowledge, since he always either was or wasn’t a man?
MENO: Obviously.
Clearly.
SOCRATES: And if the truth of all things always existed in the soul, then the soul is immortal. Wherefore be of good cheer, and try to recollect what you do not know, or rather what you do not remember.
SOCRATES: If the truth of everything has always been in the soul, then the soul is immortal. So be optimistic, and try to remember what you don’t know, or more accurately, what you don’t remember.
MENO: I feel, somehow, that I like what you are saying.
MENO: I somehow feel like I agree with what you're saying.
SOCRATES: And I, Meno, like what I am saying. Some things I have said of which I am not altogether confident. But that we shall be better and braver and less helpless if we think that we ought to enquire, than we should have been if we indulged in the idle fancy that there was no knowing and no use in seeking to know what we do not know;—that is a theme upon which I am ready to fight, in word and deed, to the utmost of my power.
SOCRATES: And I, Meno, feel good about what I’m saying. There are things I’ve mentioned that I’m not entirely sure about. But I believe that we will be better, braver, and less vulnerable if we think we should seek knowledge, rather than just daydreaming that there’s nothing to know and no point in trying to learn what we don’t know;—that’s a topic I’m willing to argue about, in both words and actions, with all the strength I have.
MENO: There again, Socrates, your words seem to me excellent.
MENO: Once again, Socrates, I think your words are excellent.
SOCRATES: Then, as we are agreed that a man should enquire about that which he does not know, shall you and I make an effort to enquire together into the nature of virtue?
SOCRATES: So, since we both agree that a person should look into what they don't know, should we try to explore together what virtue really is?
MENO: By all means, Socrates. And yet I would much rather return to my original question, Whether in seeking to acquire virtue we should regard it as a thing to be taught, or as a gift of nature, or as coming to men in some other way?
MENO: Of course, Socrates. But I'd really prefer to go back to my original question: Should we see virtue as something that can be taught, a natural gift, or does it come to people in some different way?
SOCRATES: Had I the command of you as well as of myself, Meno, I would not have enquired whether virtue is given by instruction or not, until we had first ascertained 'what it is.' But as you think only of controlling me who am your slave, and never of controlling yourself,—such being your notion of freedom, I must yield to you, for you are irresistible. And therefore I have now to enquire into the qualities of a thing of which I do not as yet know the nature. At any rate, will you condescend a little, and allow the question 'Whether virtue is given by instruction, or in any other way,' to be argued upon hypothesis? As the geometrician, when he is asked whether a certain triangle is capable being inscribed in a certain circle (Or, whether a certain area is capable of being inscribed as a triangle in a certain circle.), will reply: 'I cannot tell you as yet; but I will offer a hypothesis which may assist us in forming a conclusion: If the figure be such that when you have produced a given side of it (Or, when you apply it to the given line, i.e. the diameter of the circle (autou).), the given area of the triangle falls short by an area corresponding to the part produced (Or, similar to the area so applied.), then one consequence follows, and if this is impossible then some other; and therefore I wish to assume a hypothesis before I tell you whether this triangle is capable of being inscribed in the circle':—that is a geometrical hypothesis. And we too, as we know not the nature and qualities of virtue, must ask, whether virtue is or is not taught, under a hypothesis: as thus, if virtue is of such a class of mental goods, will it be taught or not? Let the first hypothesis be that virtue is or is not knowledge,—in that case will it be taught or not? or, as we were just now saying, 'remembered'? For there is no use in disputing about the name. But is virtue taught or not? or rather, does not every one see that knowledge alone is taught?
SOCRATES: If I had control over both you and myself, Meno, I wouldn't have asked whether virtue comes from instruction until we figured out what it actually is. But since you focus solely on dominating me, your slave, and not on mastering yourself—this seems to be your idea of freedom—I have to concede, because you are hard to resist. So now, I need to look into the qualities of something whose nature is still unknown to me. Will you, at least, entertain the idea that we can discuss whether virtue is taught or acquired in another way as a hypothesis? Just like a geometer, when asked if a specific triangle can fit inside a certain circle, responds: "I can't give you a definite answer yet, but I can suggest a hypothesis that might help us draw a conclusion: If the figure is such that when you extend a certain side of it, the area of the triangle falls short by an amount corresponding to the extension, then one outcome follows; if that’s impossible, then another outcome follows. So I want to propose a hypothesis before I answer whether this triangle fits inside the circle": that’s what a geometric hypothesis looks like. Similarly, since we don't understand the nature and qualities of virtue, we should ask whether virtue can be taught, based on a hypothesis: say if virtue belongs to a category of mental goods, can it be taught or not? Let’s start by considering the first hypothesis: is virtue knowledge or isn’t it? In that case, can it be taught or not? Or, as we just mentioned, 'remembered'? Because there's no point in arguing about the terminology. But is virtue taught or not? Or doesn't everyone realize that only knowledge is teachable?
MENO: I agree.
I’m in.
SOCRATES: Then if virtue is knowledge, virtue will be taught?
SOCRATES: So, if virtue is knowledge, can virtue be taught?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: Then now we have made a quick end of this question: if virtue is of such a nature, it will be taught; and if not, not?
SOCRATES: So, we've quickly wrapped up this question: if virtue can be taught, then it has that kind of nature; if it can't, then it doesn't?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: The next question is, whether virtue is knowledge or of another species?
SOCRATES: The next question is whether virtue is knowledge or something else?
MENO: Yes, that appears to be the question which comes next in order.
MENO: Yes, that seems to be the question that comes next.
SOCRATES: Do we not say that virtue is a good?—This is a hypothesis which is not set aside.
SOCRATES: Don’t we say that virtue is good?—This is a claim that isn’t disregarded.
MENO: Certainly.
Of course.
SOCRATES: Now, if there be any sort of good which is distinct from knowledge, virtue may be that good; but if knowledge embraces all good, then we shall be right in thinking that virtue is knowledge?
SOCRATES: So, if there's a type of good that is separate from knowledge, then virtue might be that good; but if knowledge includes all good, then it makes sense to say that virtue is knowledge, right?
MENO: True.
MENO: For real.
SOCRATES: And virtue makes us good?
SOCRATES: So, virtue makes us good?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And if we are good, then we are profitable; for all good things are profitable?
SOCRATES: If we’re good, then we benefit from it; because all good things bring benefits?
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yep.
SOCRATES: Then virtue is profitable?
SOCRATES: So, is virtue beneficial?
MENO: That is the only inference.
MENO: That’s the only conclusion.
SOCRATES: Then now let us see what are the things which severally profit us. Health and strength, and beauty and wealth—these, and the like of these, we call profitable?
SOCRATES: So now let's look at what benefits us individually. Do we consider health, strength, beauty, and wealth—things like these—as beneficial?
MENO: True.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And yet these things may also sometimes do us harm: would you not think so?
SOCRATES: And yet, these things can sometimes be harmful to us, don’t you think?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And what is the guiding principle which makes them profitable or the reverse? Are they not profitable when they are rightly used, and hurtful when they are not rightly used?
SOCRATES: So what’s the main principle that makes them beneficial or not? Aren’t they beneficial when used correctly, and harmful when used incorrectly?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: Next, let us consider the goods of the soul: they are temperance, justice, courage, quickness of apprehension, memory, magnanimity, and the like?
SOCRATES: Next, let's think about the virtues of the soul: they are self-control, fairness, bravery, quick thinking, memory, nobility, and similar qualities?
MENO: Surely.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And such of these as are not knowledge, but of another sort, are sometimes profitable and sometimes hurtful; as, for example, courage wanting prudence, which is only a sort of confidence? When a man has no sense he is harmed by courage, but when he has sense he is profited?
SOCRATES: So, those things that aren’t knowledge, but are something else, can be useful or harmful; like courage without wisdom, which is just foolish confidence. When someone lacks judgment, their courage can lead to harm, but when they have good judgment, it can be beneficial.
MENO: True.
True.
SOCRATES: And the same may be said of temperance and quickness of apprehension; whatever things are learned or done with sense are profitable, but when done without sense they are hurtful?
SOCRATES: The same goes for self-control and quick understanding; anything learned or done with reason is beneficial, but when done without reason, it can be harmful.
MENO: Very true.
So true.
SOCRATES: And in general, all that the soul attempts or endures, when under the guidance of wisdom, ends in happiness; but when she is under the guidance of folly, in the opposite?
SOCRATES: Generally speaking, everything the soul tries or experiences, when guided by wisdom, results in happiness; but when it's guided by foolishness, the outcome is the opposite?
MENO: That appears to be true.
MENO: That seems to be true.
SOCRATES: If then virtue is a quality of the soul, and is admitted to be profitable, it must be wisdom or prudence, since none of the things of the soul are either profitable or hurtful in themselves, but they are all made profitable or hurtful by the addition of wisdom or of folly; and therefore if virtue is profitable, virtue must be a sort of wisdom or prudence?
SOCRATES: If virtue is a quality of the soul and is considered beneficial, it must be wisdom or good judgment because none of the aspects of the soul are inherently beneficial or harmful; they become beneficial or harmful through the presence of wisdom or foolishness. Therefore, if virtue is indeed beneficial, it must be a kind of wisdom or good judgment, right?
MENO: I quite agree.
I completely agree.
SOCRATES: And the other goods, such as wealth and the like, of which we were just now saying that they are sometimes good and sometimes evil, do not they also become profitable or hurtful, accordingly as the soul guides and uses them rightly or wrongly; just as the things of the soul herself are benefited when under the guidance of wisdom and harmed by folly?
SOCRATES: The other goods, like wealth and similar things, which we just mentioned can be good at times and bad at others—don’t they also turn out to be beneficial or harmful depending on how the soul directs and uses them, just like the aspects of the soul are improved with wisdom and damaged by foolishness?
MENO: True.
MENO: For sure.
SOCRATES: And the wise soul guides them rightly, and the foolish soul wrongly.
SOCRATES: And the wise person guides them correctly, while the foolish person guides them incorrectly.
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And is not this universally true of human nature? All other things hang upon the soul, and the things of the soul herself hang upon wisdom, if they are to be good; and so wisdom is inferred to be that which profits—and virtue, as we say, is profitable?
SOCRATES: Isn't this true for all of human nature? Everything else depends on the soul, and the matters of the soul depend on wisdom if they are to be good; therefore, we can conclude that wisdom is what benefits us—and virtue, as we say, is beneficial?
MENO: Certainly.
MENO: Of course.
SOCRATES: And thus we arrive at the conclusion that virtue is either wholly or partly wisdom?
SOCRATES: So, we come to the conclusion that virtue is either completely or partially wisdom?
MENO: I think that what you are saying, Socrates, is very true.
MENO: I believe what you're saying, Socrates, is really true.
SOCRATES: But if this is true, then the good are not by nature good?
SOCRATES: But if that's the case, then aren't the good people not good by nature?
MENO: I think not.
I don't think so.
SOCRATES: If they had been, there would assuredly have been discerners of characters among us who would have known our future great men; and on their showing we should have adopted them, and when we had got them, we should have kept them in the citadel out of the way of harm, and set a stamp upon them far rather than upon a piece of gold, in order that no one might tamper with them; and when they grew up they would have been useful to the state?
SOCRATES: If that were the case, there definitely would have been people among us who could recognize the traits of future great leaders. Based on their judgment, we would have chosen those individuals, and once we had them, we would have kept them safe in the citadel to protect them from harm, valuing them far more than a piece of gold to ensure no one could interfere with them. When they grew up, they would have been beneficial to the state.
MENO: Yes, Socrates, that would have been the right way.
MENO: Yes, Socrates, that would have been the right approach.
SOCRATES: But if the good are not by nature good, are they made good by instruction?
SOCRATES: But if good people aren't naturally good, does teaching make them good?
MENO: There appears to be no other alternative, Socrates. On the supposition that virtue is knowledge, there can be no doubt that virtue is taught.
MENO: It seems there’s no other option, Socrates. If we accept that virtue is knowledge, then it’s clear that virtue can be taught.
SOCRATES: Yes, indeed; but what if the supposition is erroneous?
SOCRATES: Yes, that's true; but what if the assumption is wrong?
MENO: I certainly thought just now that we were right.
MENO: I really thought just now that we were correct.
SOCRATES: Yes, Meno; but a principle which has any soundness should stand firm not only just now, but always.
SOCRATES: Yes, Meno; but a principle that is truly solid should remain steady not just now, but always.
MENO: Well; and why are you so slow of heart to believe that knowledge is virtue?
MENO: Well, why are you so hesitant to believe that knowledge is virtue?
SOCRATES: I will try and tell you why, Meno. I do not retract the assertion that if virtue is knowledge it may be taught; but I fear that I have some reason in doubting whether virtue is knowledge: for consider now and say whether virtue, and not only virtue but anything that is taught, must not have teachers and disciples?
SOCRATES: I’ll explain why, Meno. I still stand by the idea that if virtue is knowledge, then it can be taught; but I’m starting to have some doubts about whether virtue is actually knowledge. Think about this and let me know if you agree: Doesn’t virtue, and anything else that can be taught, need teachers and students?
MENO: Surely.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And conversely, may not the art of which neither teachers nor disciples exist be assumed to be incapable of being taught?
SOCRATES: So, can we not say that if there are no teachers or students for a certain art, it must be something that can't be taught?
MENO: True; but do you think that there are no teachers of virtue?
MENO: True; but do you think there are no teachers of virtue?
SOCRATES: I have certainly often enquired whether there were any, and taken great pains to find them, and have never succeeded; and many have assisted me in the search, and they were the persons whom I thought the most likely to know. Here at the moment when he is wanted we fortunately have sitting by us Anytus, the very person of whom we should make enquiry; to him then let us repair. In the first place, he is the son of a wealthy and wise father, Anthemion, who acquired his wealth, not by accident or gift, like Ismenias the Theban (who has recently made himself as rich as Polycrates), but by his own skill and industry, and who is a well-conditioned, modest man, not insolent, or overbearing, or annoying; moreover, this son of his has received a good education, as the Athenian people certainly appear to think, for they choose him to fill the highest offices. And these are the sort of men from whom you are likely to learn whether there are any teachers of virtue, and who they are. Please, Anytus, to help me and your friend Meno in answering our question, Who are the teachers? Consider the matter thus: If we wanted Meno to be a good physician, to whom should we send him? Should we not send him to the physicians?
SOCRATES: I've definitely asked many times if there are any teachers of virtue and have put in a lot of effort to find them, but I've never had any luck. Many people have helped me in this search, and they were the ones I thought would know best. Luckily, right now we have Anytus here with us, who is exactly the person we should ask. First of all, he is the son of a wealthy and wise father, Anthemion, who earned his wealth not by chance or gift, like Ismenias the Theban (who has recently become as rich as Polycrates), but through his own skill and hard work. Anthemion is a decent, humble man — not arrogant, overbearing, or irritating. Plus, Anytus himself has received a good education, as the people of Athens clearly believe, since they choose him for the highest positions. These are the kinds of people from whom you could probably learn if there are any teachers of virtue, and who they are. So, Anytus, please help me and your friend Meno answer our question: Who are the teachers? Think about it this way: If we wanted Meno to be a good doctor, who would we send him to? Wouldn’t we send him to the doctors?
ANYTUS: Certainly.
ANYTUS: Sure.
SOCRATES: Or if we wanted him to be a good cobbler, should we not send him to the cobblers?
SOCRATES: If we want him to be a good cobbler, shouldn't we send him to the cobblers?
ANYTUS: Yes.
ANYTUS: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And so forth?
SOCRATES: And what else?
ANYTUS: Yes.
ANYTUS: Yeah.
SOCRATES: Let me trouble you with one more question. When we say that we should be right in sending him to the physicians if we wanted him to be a physician, do we mean that we should be right in sending him to those who profess the art, rather than to those who do not, and to those who demand payment for teaching the art, and profess to teach it to any one who will come and learn? And if these were our reasons, should we not be right in sending him?
SOCRATES: Let me ask you one more question. When we say that it makes sense to send him to the doctors if we want him to become a doctor, do we mean that we should send him to those who actually practice medicine, rather than to those who don’t? And to those who charge money for teaching the craft, and claim to teach it to anyone willing to come and learn? If those are our reasons, shouldn't we be right to send him?
ANYTUS: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And might not the same be said of flute-playing, and of the other arts? Would a man who wanted to make another a flute-player refuse to send him to those who profess to teach the art for money, and be plaguing other persons to give him instruction, who are not professed teachers and who never had a single disciple in that branch of knowledge which he wishes him to acquire—would not such conduct be the height of folly?
SOCRATES: Isn’t the same true for playing the flute and other arts? Would a person who wanted to make someone else a flute player really refuse to send them to those who teach the art for a fee and instead bother others who aren't professional teachers and have never taught anyone in that area of expertise—wouldn't that be extremely foolish?
ANYTUS: Yes, by Zeus, and of ignorance too.
ANYTUS: Yes, by Zeus, and also by ignorance.
SOCRATES: Very good. And now you are in a position to advise with me about my friend Meno. He has been telling me, Anytus, that he desires to attain that kind of wisdom and virtue by which men order the state or the house, and honour their parents, and know when to receive and when to send away citizens and strangers, as a good man should. Now, to whom should he go in order that he may learn this virtue? Does not the previous argument imply clearly that we should send him to those who profess and avouch that they are the common teachers of all Hellas, and are ready to impart instruction to any one who likes, at a fixed price?
SOCRATES: Great. Now you’re ready to help me talk about my friend Meno. He’s been telling me, Anytus, that he wants to gain the kind of wisdom and virtue needed to manage a state or a household, honor his parents, and know when to welcome or dismiss citizens and strangers, as a good person should. So, where should he go to learn this virtue? Doesn’t our earlier discussion clearly suggest that we should send him to those who claim to be the common teachers of all Greece and are willing to teach anyone for a set fee?
ANYTUS: Whom do you mean, Socrates?
ANYTUS: Who are you talking about, Socrates?
SOCRATES: You surely know, do you not, Anytus, that these are the people whom mankind call Sophists?
SOCRATES: You definitely know, right, Anytus, that these are the people that everyone refers to as Sophists?
ANYTUS: By Heracles, Socrates, forbear! I only hope that no friend or kinsman or acquaintance of mine, whether citizen or stranger, will ever be so mad as to allow himself to be corrupted by them; for they are a manifest pest and corrupting influence to those who have to do with them.
ANYTUS: By Heracles, Socrates, stop! I just hope that no friend, family member, or acquaintance of mine, whether a citizen or a stranger, will ever be foolish enough to let themselves be corrupted by them; they are clearly a harmful and corrupting influence on anyone who interacts with them.
SOCRATES: What, Anytus? Of all the people who profess that they know how to do men good, do you mean to say that these are the only ones who not only do them no good, but positively corrupt those who are entrusted to them, and in return for this disservice have the face to demand money? Indeed, I cannot believe you; for I know of a single man, Protagoras, who made more out of his craft than the illustrious Pheidias, who created such noble works, or any ten other statuaries. How could that be? A mender of old shoes, or patcher up of clothes, who made the shoes or clothes worse than he received them, could not have remained thirty days undetected, and would very soon have starved; whereas during more than forty years, Protagoras was corrupting all Hellas, and sending his disciples from him worse than he received them, and he was never found out. For, if I am not mistaken, he was about seventy years old at his death, forty of which were spent in the practice of his profession; and during all that time he had a good reputation, which to this day he retains: and not only Protagoras, but many others are well spoken of; some who lived before him, and others who are still living. Now, when you say that they deceived and corrupted the youth, are they to be supposed to have corrupted them consciously or unconsciously? Can those who were deemed by many to be the wisest men of Hellas have been out of their minds?
SOCRATES: What do you mean, Anytus? Among all the people who claim to know how to help others, are you saying they are the only ones who not only fail to do any good but actively harm those they’re supposed to support, and then have the nerve to ask for money in return? I can't believe that; I know of one man, Protagoras, who made more from his work than the famous Pheidias, who created such remarkable pieces, or any ten other sculptors. How could that be? A shoemaker who ruined old shoes, or a tailor who messed up clothes worse than they were before, couldn’t last thirty days without being noticed and would quickly go hungry. Yet for over forty years, Protagoras was ruining all of Greece, sending his students away worse off than they came, and no one ever caught on. If I’m not mistaken, he was about seventy when he died, having spent forty of those years practicing his craft; and throughout that time, he maintained a good reputation, which even today he still has. Not only Protagoras, but many others have also been well-regarded; some lived before him, and others are still around. Now, when you say they deceived and harmed the youth, are we to assume they did this knowingly or unknowingly? Could those who were considered by many to be the wisest men in Greece really have been out of their minds?
ANYTUS: Out of their minds! No, Socrates; the young men who gave their money to them were out of their minds, and their relations and guardians who entrusted their youth to the care of these men were still more out of their minds, and most of all, the cities who allowed them to come in, and did not drive them out, citizen and stranger alike.
ANYTUS: They're crazy! No, Socrates; the young men who gave their money to them were crazy, and their families and guardians who handed over their youth to these men were even crazier, and most of all, the cities that let them in and didn't kick them out, both citizens and outsiders.
SOCRATES: Has any of the Sophists wronged you, Anytus? What makes you so angry with them?
SOCRATES: Has any of the Sophists done you wrong, Anytus? Why are you so angry with them?
ANYTUS: No, indeed, neither I nor any of my belongings has ever had, nor would I suffer them to have, anything to do with them.
ANYTUS: No way, neither I nor anything I own has ever had, nor would I allow them to have, anything to do with them.
SOCRATES: Then you are entirely unacquainted with them?
SOCRATES: So, you have no idea who they are?
ANYTUS: And I have no wish to be acquainted.
ANYTUS: I don’t want to get to know you.
SOCRATES: Then, my dear friend, how can you know whether a thing is good or bad of which you are wholly ignorant?
SOCRATES: So, my dear friend, how can you know if something is good or bad if you have no idea about it?
ANYTUS: Quite well; I am sure that I know what manner of men these are, whether I am acquainted with them or not.
ANYTUS: I'm pretty sure I know what kind of men these are, whether I know them personally or not.
SOCRATES: You must be a diviner, Anytus, for I really cannot make out, judging from your own words, how, if you are not acquainted with them, you know about them. But I am not enquiring of you who are the teachers who will corrupt Meno (let them be, if you please, the Sophists); I only ask you to tell him who there is in this great city who will teach him how to become eminent in the virtues which I was just now describing. He is the friend of your family, and you will oblige him.
SOCRATES: You must be a fortune teller, Anytus, because I really can’t understand how you know about them if you’re not familiar with them. But I’m not asking you who the teachers are that will corrupt Meno (let’s assume they’re the Sophists); I just want you to tell him who in this big city can teach him how to excel in the virtues I just mentioned. He’s a friend of your family, and you would be doing him a favor.
ANYTUS: Why do you not tell him yourself?
ANYTUS: Why don't you tell him yourself?
SOCRATES: I have told him whom I supposed to be the teachers of these things; but I learn from you that I am utterly at fault, and I dare say that you are right. And now I wish that you, on your part, would tell me to whom among the Athenians he should go. Whom would you name?
SOCRATES: I’ve mentioned the people I thought were teaching these things; but now I realize I was completely wrong, and I believe you’re correct. So, could you tell me who among the Athenians he should approach? Who would you recommend?
ANYTUS: Why single out individuals? Any Athenian gentleman, taken at random, if he will mind him, will do far more good to him than the Sophists.
ANYTUS: Why focus on specific individuals? Any random Athenian gentleman, if he chooses to pay attention, will do much more good for him than the Sophists.
SOCRATES: And did those gentlemen grow of themselves; and without having been taught by any one, were they nevertheless able to teach others that which they had never learned themselves?
SOCRATES: Did those gentlemen develop on their own; and without being taught by anyone, were they still able to teach others what they had never learned themselves?
ANYTUS: I imagine that they learned of the previous generation of gentlemen. Have there not been many good men in this city?
ANYTUS: I guess they heard about the previous generation of gentlemen. Haven't there been many good men in this city?
SOCRATES: Yes, certainly, Anytus; and many good statesmen also there always have been and there are still, in the city of Athens. But the question is whether they were also good teachers of their own virtue;—not whether there are, or have been, good men in this part of the world, but whether virtue can be taught, is the question which we have been discussing. Now, do we mean to say that the good men of our own and of other times knew how to impart to others that virtue which they had themselves; or is virtue a thing incapable of being communicated or imparted by one man to another? That is the question which I and Meno have been arguing. Look at the matter in your own way: Would you not admit that Themistocles was a good man?
SOCRATES: Yes, of course, Anytus; and there have always been, and still are, many good politicians in the city of Athens. But the real question is whether they were also good at teaching their own virtue—it's not just about whether there are or have been good people in this part of the world, but whether virtue can be taught. That’s what we’ve been discussing. Now, are we saying that the good people from our time and from the past knew how to pass on the virtue they had themselves, or is virtue something that can't be shared or taught from one person to another? That’s the question Meno and I have been debating. Think about it your own way: Would you not agree that Themistocles was a good man?
ANYTUS: Certainly; no man better.
ANYTUS: Definitely; no one better.
SOCRATES: And must not he then have been a good teacher, if any man ever was a good teacher, of his own virtue?
SOCRATES: And he must have been a good teacher, if anyone ever was, of his own virtue, right?
ANYTUS: Yes certainly,—if he wanted to be so.
ANYTUS: Yeah, of course—if he wanted to be.
SOCRATES: But would he not have wanted? He would, at any rate, have desired to make his own son a good man and a gentleman; he could not have been jealous of him, or have intentionally abstained from imparting to him his own virtue. Did you never hear that he made his son Cleophantus a famous horseman; and had him taught to stand upright on horseback and hurl a javelin, and to do many other marvellous things; and in anything which could be learned from a master he was well trained? Have you not heard from our elders of him?
SOCRATES: But wouldn't he have wanted that? He would have definitely wanted to raise his son to be a good man and a gentleman; he couldn't have been jealous of him or intentionally held back his own virtues. Haven't you heard about how he made his son Cleophantus an excellent horseman? He taught him to stand upright on horseback, throw a javelin, and do many other amazing things, and he received great training in anything that could be taught by a master. Haven't you heard our elders talk about him?
ANYTUS: I have.
I have.
SOCRATES: Then no one could say that his son showed any want of capacity?
SOCRATES: So, nobody could say that his son lacked ability?
ANYTUS: Very likely not.
ANYTUS: Probably not.
SOCRATES: But did any one, old or young, ever say in your hearing that Cleophantus, son of Themistocles, was a wise or good man, as his father was?
SOCRATES: But has anyone, young or old, ever said in your presence that Cleophantus, son of Themistocles, was a wise or good man like his father?
ANYTUS: I have certainly never heard any one say so.
ANYTUS: I’ve definitely never heard anyone say that.
SOCRATES: And if virtue could have been taught, would his father Themistocles have sought to train him in these minor accomplishments, and allowed him who, as you must remember, was his own son, to be no better than his neighbours in those qualities in which he himself excelled?
SOCRATES: If virtue could be taught, would his father Themistocles have tried to teach him these minor skills and let his son, as you must remember, be no better than his neighbors in the qualities where he himself stood out?
ANYTUS: Indeed, indeed, I think not.
ANYTUS: Yeah, I really don’t think so.
SOCRATES: Here was a teacher of virtue whom you admit to be among the best men of the past. Let us take another,—Aristides, the son of Lysimachus: would you not acknowledge that he was a good man?
SOCRATES: Here’s a teacher of virtue whom you recognize as one of the best people from the past. Let’s consider another—Aristides, the son of Lysimachus: would you not agree that he was a good man?
ANYTUS: To be sure I should.
I definitely should.
SOCRATES: And did not he train his son Lysimachus better than any other Athenian in all that could be done for him by the help of masters? But what has been the result? Is he a bit better than any other mortal? He is an acquaintance of yours, and you see what he is like. There is Pericles, again, magnificent in his wisdom; and he, as you are aware, had two sons, Paralus and Xanthippus.
SOCRATES: Didn't he train his son Lysimachus better than any other Athenian could with the help of teachers? But what's the outcome? Is he any better than anyone else? You know him, and you can see what he's like. Then there's Pericles, who's impressive in his wisdom; and as you know, he had two sons, Paralus and Xanthippus.
ANYTUS: I know.
ANYTUS: Got it.
SOCRATES: And you know, also, that he taught them to be unrivalled horsemen, and had them trained in music and gymnastics and all sorts of arts—in these respects they were on a level with the best—and had he no wish to make good men of them? Nay, he must have wished it. But virtue, as I suspect, could not be taught. And that you may not suppose the incompetent teachers to be only the meaner sort of Athenians and few in number, remember again that Thucydides had two sons, Melesias and Stephanus, whom, besides giving them a good education in other things, he trained in wrestling, and they were the best wrestlers in Athens: one of them he committed to the care of Xanthias, and the other of Eudorus, who had the reputation of being the most celebrated wrestlers of that day. Do you remember them?
SOCRATES: And you know that he taught them to be exceptional horse riders and had them trained in music, gymnastics, and all kinds of arts—in these areas, they were as good as the best. Didn't he want to make them good people? Of course, he must have wanted that. But I suspect that virtue couldn't be taught. And to remind you, it wasn't just the less competent teachers who were the lower-class Athenians and few in number; remember that Thucydides had two sons, Melesias and Stephanus. He not only provided them with a good education in other subjects, but he also trained them in wrestling, and they were the best wrestlers in Athens. One of them was taken care of by Xanthias, and the other by Eudorus, who were known as the most famous wrestlers of that time. Do you remember them?
ANYTUS: I have heard of them.
ANYTUS: I've heard of them.
SOCRATES: Now, can there be a doubt that Thucydides, whose children were taught things for which he had to spend money, would have taught them to be good men, which would have cost him nothing, if virtue could have been taught? Will you reply that he was a mean man, and had not many friends among the Athenians and allies? Nay, but he was of a great family, and a man of influence at Athens and in all Hellas, and, if virtue could have been taught, he would have found out some Athenian or foreigner who would have made good men of his sons, if he could not himself spare the time from cares of state. Once more, I suspect, friend Anytus, that virtue is not a thing which can be taught?
SOCRATES: Now, is there really any doubt that Thucydides, whose kids were educated in things that cost him money, would have taught them to be good people, which wouldn't have cost him anything, if virtue could actually be taught? Will you argue that he was a petty man and didn't have many friends among the Athenians and allies? Not at all, he came from a prominent family and was a man of influence in Athens and throughout Greece, and if virtue could be taught, he would have found some Athenian or outsider who could have raised his sons to be good men, even if he couldn’t take the time himself because of state affairs. Once again, I suspect, my friend Anytus, that virtue is not something that can be taught?
ANYTUS: Socrates, I think that you are too ready to speak evil of men: and, if you will take my advice, I would recommend you to be careful. Perhaps there is no city in which it is not easier to do men harm than to do them good, and this is certainly the case at Athens, as I believe that you know.
ANYTUS: Socrates, I think you’re too quick to criticize others. If I may offer some advice, it’s best to be cautious. In every city, it’s usually easier to hurt people than to help them, and I believe this is especially true in Athens, as you surely know.
SOCRATES: O Meno, think that Anytus is in a rage. And he may well be in a rage, for he thinks, in the first place, that I am defaming these gentlemen; and in the second place, he is of opinion that he is one of them himself. But some day he will know what is the meaning of defamation, and if he ever does, he will forgive me. Meanwhile I will return to you, Meno; for I suppose that there are gentlemen in your region too?
SOCRATES: Hey Meno, just think about how furious Anytus is. And he has every right to be angry because he believes I'm slandering these guys. Plus, he thinks he’s one of them. But eventually, he'll understand what slander really means, and when that happens, he might forgive me. In the meantime, let’s get back to you, Meno; I assume there are some respectable people in your area as well?
MENO: Certainly there are.
Of course there are.
SOCRATES: And are they willing to teach the young? and do they profess to be teachers? and do they agree that virtue is taught?
SOCRATES: Are they willing to teach the young? Do they claim to be teachers? And do they believe that virtue can be taught?
MENO: No indeed, Socrates, they are anything but agreed; you may hear them saying at one time that virtue can be taught, and then again the reverse.
MENO: No, Socrates, they definitely don’t agree; one moment you’ll hear them claim that virtue can be taught, and the next moment, they’ll say the opposite.
SOCRATES: Can we call those teachers who do not acknowledge the possibility of their own vocation?
SOCRATES: Can we really consider those teachers who don't recognize the possibility of their own calling?
MENO: I think not, Socrates.
MENO: I don't think so, Socrates.
SOCRATES: And what do you think of these Sophists, who are the only professors? Do they seem to you to be teachers of virtue?
SOCRATES: So, what do you think about these Sophists, who are the only ones teaching? Do you see them as teachers of virtue?
MENO: I often wonder, Socrates, that Gorgias is never heard promising to teach virtue: and when he hears others promising he only laughs at them; but he thinks that men should be taught to speak.
MENO: I often wonder, Socrates, why Gorgias never claims he can teach virtue. When he hears others making that promise, he just laughs at them, but he believes that people should be taught how to speak.
SOCRATES: Then do you not think that the Sophists are teachers?
SOCRATES: So, don’t you think the Sophists are teachers?
MENO: I cannot tell you, Socrates; like the rest of the world, I am in doubt, and sometimes I think that they are teachers and sometimes not.
MENO: I can't say, Socrates; like everyone else, I'm unsure, and sometimes I think they are teachers and sometimes I don't.
SOCRATES: And are you aware that not you only and other politicians have doubts whether virtue can be taught or not, but that Theognis the poet says the very same thing?
SOCRATES: And do you realize that it's not just you and other politicians who doubt whether virtue can be taught, but that the poet Theognis says the exact same thing?
MENO: Where does he say so?
MENO: Where does he say that?
SOCRATES: In these elegiac verses (Theog.):
SOCRATES: In these elegiac verses (Theog.):
'Eat and drink and sit with the mighty, and make yourself agreeable to them; for from the good you will learn what is good, but if you mix with the bad you will lose the intelligence which you already have.'
"Eat and drink and hang out with the powerful, and make yourself likable to them; because from the good, you'll learn what's good, but if you associate with the bad, you'll lose the wisdom you already possess."
Do you observe that here he seems to imply that virtue can be taught?
Do you notice that here he seems to suggest that virtue can be taught?
MENO: Clearly.
Clearly.
SOCRATES: But in some other verses he shifts about and says (Theog.):
SOCRATES: But in some other lines, he changes his position and says (Theog.):
'If understanding could be created and put into a man, then they' (who were able to perform this feat) 'would have obtained great rewards.'
'If understanding could be created and instilled in a person, then those who could achieve this would have received great rewards.'
And again:—
And again:—
'Never would a bad son have sprung from a good sire, for he would have heard the voice of instruction; but not by teaching will you ever make a bad man into a good one.'
'No bad son would come from a good father, because he would have listened to guidance; but you will never turn a bad person into a good one just by teaching.'
And this, as you may remark, is a contradiction of the other.
And this, as you might notice, is the opposite of the other.
MENO: Clearly.
Absolutely.
SOCRATES: And is there anything else of which the professors are affirmed not only not to be teachers of others, but to be ignorant themselves, and bad at the knowledge of that which they are professing to teach? or is there anything about which even the acknowledged 'gentlemen' are sometimes saying that 'this thing can be taught,' and sometimes the opposite? Can you say that they are teachers in any true sense whose ideas are in such confusion?
SOCRATES: Is there anything else that the professors claim they don’t teach others, but also don’t understand themselves, and are actually poor at the knowledge of what they say they teach? Or is there anything that even the so-called 'gentlemen' sometimes say can be taught, and other times say cannot? Can you really call them teachers in any meaningful way when their ideas are so confused?
MENO: I should say, certainly not.
MENO: I definitely wouldn't say that.
SOCRATES: But if neither the Sophists nor the gentlemen are teachers, clearly there can be no other teachers?
SOCRATES: But if neither the Sophists nor the gentlemen are teachers, then there can’t be any other teachers, right?
MENO: No.
No.
SOCRATES: And if there are no teachers, neither are there disciples?
SOCRATES: So, if there are no teachers, then there are no students either?
MENO: Agreed.
MENO: Sounds good.
SOCRATES: And we have admitted that a thing cannot be taught of which there are neither teachers nor disciples?
SOCRATES: So we've agreed that something can't be taught if there are no teachers or students?
MENO: We have.
We got it.
SOCRATES: And there are no teachers of virtue to be found anywhere?
SOCRATES: So, there are no teachers of virtue to be found anywhere?
MENO: There are not.
There aren't any.
SOCRATES: And if there are no teachers, neither are there scholars?
SOCRATES: So, if there are no teachers, then there are no scholars either?
MENO: That, I think, is true.
MENO: I believe that's true.
SOCRATES: Then virtue cannot be taught?
SOCRATES: So, virtue can't be taught?
MENO: Not if we are right in our view. But I cannot believe, Socrates, that there are no good men: And if there are, how did they come into existence?
MENO: That’s not true if we see it differently. But I can’t believe, Socrates, that there aren’t any good people. And if there are, how did they come to be?
SOCRATES: I am afraid, Meno, that you and I are not good for much, and that Gorgias has been as poor an educator of you as Prodicus has been of me. Certainly we shall have to look to ourselves, and try to find some one who will help in some way or other to improve us. This I say, because I observe that in the previous discussion none of us remarked that right and good action is possible to man under other guidance than that of knowledge (episteme);—and indeed if this be denied, there is no seeing how there can be any good men at all.
SOCRATES: I'm afraid, Meno, that you and I aren't really doing much good, and that Gorgias hasn't taught you any better than Prodicus has taught me. We definitely need to take responsibility for ourselves and find someone who can help us improve in some way. I say this because I noticed that in our earlier talk, none of us pointed out that a person can take the right and good actions without knowledge (episteme) guiding them; and if that's not true, then it's hard to see how anyone can be a good person at all.
MENO: How do you mean, Socrates?
MENO: What do you mean, Socrates?
SOCRATES: I mean that good men are necessarily useful or profitable. Were we not right in admitting this? It must be so.
SOCRATES: I mean that good people are definitely useful or beneficial. Were we not correct in agreeing on this? It has to be true.
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yep.
SOCRATES: And in supposing that they will be useful only if they are true guides to us of action—there we were also right?
SOCRATES: So, if we assume that they will only be helpful if they truly guide our actions—were we also right about that?
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: But when we said that a man cannot be a good guide unless he have knowledge (phrhonesis), this we were wrong.
SOCRATES: But when we said that a man cannot be a good guide unless he has knowledge, we were mistaken.
MENO: What do you mean by the word 'right'?
MENO: What do you mean by the word 'right'?
SOCRATES: I will explain. If a man knew the way to Larisa, or anywhere else, and went to the place and led others thither, would he not be a right and good guide?
SOCRATES: Let me explain. If a person knew the way to Larisa, or anywhere else, and went there while leading others along, wouldn’t he be a good and trustworthy guide?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And a person who had a right opinion about the way, but had never been and did not know, might be a good guide also, might he not?
SOCRATES: And a person who had the right opinion about the path, but had never been there and did not know it, could still be a good guide, right?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And while he has true opinion about that which the other knows, he will be just as good a guide if he thinks the truth, as he who knows the truth?
SOCRATES: So, if he has a correct opinion about what the other knows, will he be just as good a guide if he believes the truth, as the person who actually knows the truth?
MENO: Exactly.
MENO: Totally.
SOCRATES: Then true opinion is as good a guide to correct action as knowledge; and that was the point which we omitted in our speculation about the nature of virtue, when we said that knowledge only is the guide of right action; whereas there is also right opinion.
SOCRATES: So, true opinion is just as good a guide to right action as knowledge is; and that was the point we missed in our discussion about the nature of virtue, when we said that only knowledge guides right action; meanwhile, there is also right opinion.
MENO: True.
MENO: For sure.
SOCRATES: Then right opinion is not less useful than knowledge?
SOCRATES: So, isn't right opinion just as useful as knowledge?
MENO: The difference, Socrates, is only that he who has knowledge will always be right; but he who has right opinion will sometimes be right, and sometimes not.
MENO: The difference, Socrates, is that someone with knowledge will always be correct; but someone with the right opinion will be right sometimes and wrong other times.
SOCRATES: What do you mean? Can he be wrong who has right opinion, so long as he has right opinion?
SOCRATES: What do you mean? Can someone be wrong if they have the right opinion, as long as they hold that right opinion?
MENO: I admit the cogency of your argument, and therefore, Socrates, I wonder that knowledge should be preferred to right opinion—or why they should ever differ.
MENO: I see the strength of your argument, and so, Socrates, I’m curious why knowledge is considered better than correct opinion—or why they should ever be different.
SOCRATES: And shall I explain this wonder to you?
SOCRATES: Should I explain this amazing thing to you?
MENO: Do tell me.
MENO: Please share.
SOCRATES: You would not wonder if you had ever observed the images of Daedalus (Compare Euthyphro); but perhaps you have not got them in your country?
SOCRATES: You wouldn't be surprised if you had ever seen the sculptures of Daedalus (See Euthyphro); but maybe they're not found in your country?
MENO: What have they to do with the question?
MENO: What does that have to do with the question?
SOCRATES: Because they require to be fastened in order to keep them, and if they are not fastened they will play truant and run away.
SOCRATES: Because they need to be secured to hold onto them, and if they aren't secured, they'll wander off and escape.
MENO: Well, what of that?
MENO: So, what about that?
SOCRATES: I mean to say that they are not very valuable possessions if they are at liberty, for they will walk off like runaway slaves; but when fastened, they are of great value, for they are really beautiful works of art. Now this is an illustration of the nature of true opinions: while they abide with us they are beautiful and fruitful, but they run away out of the human soul, and do not remain long, and therefore they are not of much value until they are fastened by the tie of the cause; and this fastening of them, friend Meno, is recollection, as you and I have agreed to call it. But when they are bound, in the first place, they have the nature of knowledge; and, in the second place, they are abiding. And this is why knowledge is more honourable and excellent than true opinion, because fastened by a chain.
SOCRATES: What I’m saying is that these possessions aren’t very valuable if they’re free to roam, since they’ll just walk away like escapees; but when they’re secured, they’re really impressive works of art. This illustrates the nature of true opinions: while they stay with us, they’re beautiful and productive, but they can easily slip away from our minds and don’t last long, which is why they’re not very valuable unless tied to a specific reason. This tying process, my friend Meno, is what we’ve agreed to call recollection. When they’re secured, they first take on the nature of knowledge, and second, they last. That’s why knowledge is considered more honorable and superior to true opinion—because it’s bound by a chain.
MENO: What you are saying, Socrates, seems to be very like the truth.
MENO: What you're saying, Socrates, sounds really close to the truth.
SOCRATES: I too speak rather in ignorance; I only conjecture. And yet that knowledge differs from true opinion is no matter of conjecture with me. There are not many things which I profess to know, but this is most certainly one of them.
SOCRATES: I also speak mostly from a place of ignorance; I'm just guessing. Still, I definitely believe that knowledge is different from just having a true opinion. There aren't many things I claim to know, but this is definitely one of them.
MENO: Yes, Socrates; and you are quite right in saying so.
MENO: Yes, Socrates; and you're completely right to say that.
SOCRATES: And am I not also right in saying that true opinion leading the way perfects action quite as well as knowledge?
SOCRATES: Am I not correct in saying that a true opinion can guide actions just as effectively as knowledge?
MENO: There again, Socrates, I think you are right.
MENO: Once again, Socrates, I believe you’re right.
SOCRATES: Then right opinion is not a whit inferior to knowledge, or less useful in action; nor is the man who has right opinion inferior to him who has knowledge?
SOCRATES: So, having the right opinion is just as good as having knowledge, and it’s just as useful when it comes to taking action; nor is the person who has the right opinion any less valuable than the one who has knowledge?
MENO: True.
MENO: For sure.
SOCRATES: And surely the good man has been acknowledged by us to be useful?
SOCRATES: And we’ve agreed that a good person is someone who is useful, right?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: Seeing then that men become good and useful to states, not only because they have knowledge, but because they have right opinion, and that neither knowledge nor right opinion is given to man by nature or acquired by him—(do you imagine either of them to be given by nature?
SOCRATES: So, since people become good and valuable to society not just because they have knowledge but also because they have the right opinions, and since neither knowledge nor the right opinions are naturally given to people or something they acquire—(do you think either of them is given by nature?
MENO: Not I.)
Not me.)
SOCRATES: Then if they are not given by nature, neither are the good by nature good?
SOCRATES: So if these qualities aren't inherent, then the good things aren’t inherently good either?
MENO: Certainly not.
Definitely not.
SOCRATES: And nature being excluded, then came the question whether virtue is acquired by teaching?
SOCRATES: So if we set aside nature, the next question is whether virtue can be taught?
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: If virtue was wisdom (or knowledge), then, as we thought, it was taught?
SOCRATES: If virtue is wisdom (or knowledge), then, as we believed, it can be taught?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And if it was taught it was wisdom?
SOCRATES: And if it was taught, was it wisdom?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And if there were teachers, it might be taught; and if there were no teachers, not?
SOCRATES: So, if there were teachers, it could be taught; but if there were no teachers, then it couldn't, right?
MENO: True.
MENO: For real.
SOCRATES: But surely we acknowledged that there were no teachers of virtue?
SOCRATES: But we agreed that there are no teachers of virtue?
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: Then we acknowledged that it was not taught, and was not wisdom?
SOCRATES: So, we agreed that it wasn’t something that could be taught and wasn’t really wisdom?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And yet we admitted that it was a good?
SOCRATES: So, we agreed that it was good?
MENO: Yes.
Yes.
SOCRATES: And the right guide is useful and good?
SOCRATES: So, the right guide is helpful and beneficial?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: And the only right guides are knowledge and true opinion—these are the guides of man; for things which happen by chance are not under the guidance of man: but the guides of man are true opinion and knowledge.
SOCRATES: The only true guides are knowledge and genuine opinion—these are what lead us; events that occur by chance aren't really under our control. What guides us are genuine opinion and knowledge.
MENO: I think so too.
MENO: I agree.
SOCRATES: But if virtue is not taught, neither is virtue knowledge.
SOCRATES: But if virtue can't be taught, then virtue isn't knowledge either.
MENO: Clearly not.
No way.
SOCRATES: Then of two good and useful things, one, which is knowledge, has been set aside, and cannot be supposed to be our guide in political life.
SOCRATES: So, out of two good and useful things, one—knowledge—has been ignored and can't be assumed to lead us in political life.
MENO: I think not.
I don't think so.
SOCRATES: And therefore not by any wisdom, and not because they were wise, did Themistocles and those others of whom Anytus spoke govern states. This was the reason why they were unable to make others like themselves—because their virtue was not grounded on knowledge.
SOCRATES: So, it wasn’t because of any wisdom or because they were wise that Themistocles and the others Anytus mentioned governed states. This is why they couldn't make others like them—because their virtue wasn't based on knowledge.
MENO: That is probably true, Socrates.
MENO: That’s probably true, Socrates.
SOCRATES: But if not by knowledge, the only alternative which remains is that statesmen must have guided states by right opinion, which is in politics what divination is in religion; for diviners and also prophets say many things truly, but they know not what they say.
SOCRATES: But if it's not through knowledge, the only other option is that leaders must have guided the state by correct belief, which is to politics what prophecy is to religion; because both diviners and prophets say many true things, but they don't actually understand what they are saying.
MENO: So I believe.
MENO: I believe so.
SOCRATES: And may we not, Meno, truly call those men 'divine' who, having no understanding, yet succeed in many a grand deed and word?
SOCRATES: And can't we, Meno, really call those people 'divine' who, despite having no understanding, still succeed in many great actions and words?
MENO: Certainly.
Sure.
SOCRATES: Then we shall also be right in calling divine those whom we were just now speaking of as diviners and prophets, including the whole tribe of poets. Yes, and statesmen above all may be said to be divine and illumined, being inspired and possessed of God, in which condition they say many grand things, not knowing what they say.
SOCRATES: Then it makes sense to also call those we were just talking about, like diviners and prophets, divine. This includes all the poets as well. Yes, especially statesmen can be considered divine and enlightened, as they are inspired and possessed by a higher power, which leads them to say many great things without fully understanding what they're saying.
MENO: Yes.
MENO: Yeah.
SOCRATES: And the women too, Meno, call good men divine—do they not? and the Spartans, when they praise a good man, say 'that he is a divine man.'
SOCRATES: And the women too, Meno, refer to good men as divine—don’t they? And the Spartans, when they praise a good man, say 'that he is a divine man.'
MENO: And I think, Socrates, that they are right; although very likely our friend Anytus may take offence at the word.
MENO: And I believe, Socrates, that they are right; although it's quite possible our friend Anytus might be offended by the term.
SOCRATES: I do not care; as for Anytus, there will be another opportunity of talking with him. To sum up our enquiry—the result seems to be, if we are at all right in our view, that virtue is neither natural nor acquired, but an instinct given by God to the virtuous. Nor is the instinct accompanied by reason, unless there may be supposed to be among statesmen some one who is capable of educating statesmen. And if there be such an one, he may be said to be among the living what Homer says that Tiresias was among the dead, 'he alone has understanding; but the rest are flitting shades'; and he and his virtue in like manner will be a reality among shadows.
SOCRATES: I don’t really care; as for Anytus, there will be another chance to talk to him. To summarize our discussion—the conclusion seems to be, if we’re right in our perspective, that virtue is neither innate nor learned, but rather an instinct given by God to those who are virtuous. This instinct doesn’t come with reason, unless we can suppose there’s someone among politicians who is capable of educating other politicians. If such a person exists, they can be compared to what Homer says about Tiresias among the dead, ‘he alone has understanding; but the rest are just fleeting shadows’; and he and his virtue will similarly be a reality amongst shadows.
MENO: That is excellent, Socrates.
That's awesome, Socrates.
SOCRATES: Then, Meno, the conclusion is that virtue comes to the virtuous by the gift of God. But we shall never know the certain truth until, before asking how virtue is given, we enquire into the actual nature of virtue. I fear that I must go away, but do you, now that you are persuaded yourself, persuade our friend Anytus. And do not let him be so exasperated; if you can conciliate him, you will have done good service to the Athenian people.
SOCRATES: So, Meno, the conclusion is that virtue comes to the virtuous as a gift from God. But we won't really know the true answer until, before we ask how virtue is given, we explore what virtue actually is. I’m afraid I have to leave, but now that you’re convinced, convince our friend Anytus. And don’t let him get so worked up; if you can win him over, you'll have done a great service for the people of Athens.
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!