This is a modern-English version of We Philologists: Complete Works of Friedrich Nietzsche, Volume 8, originally written by Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
THE COMPLETE WORKS OF FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE
First Complete and Authorised English translation in Eighteen Volumes
EDITED BY
Dr. OSCAR LEVY
VOLUME EIGHT
THIRD EDITION
WE PHILOLOGISTS
TRANSLATED BY
J. M. KENNEDY
T. N. FOULIS
13 & 15 FREDERICK STREET
EDINBURGH · AND LONDON
1911
CONTENTS
WE PHILOLOGISTS
Fall 1874
(Published After Death)
Translated by J. M. KENNEDY
AUTHOR OF "THE QUINTESSENCE OF NIETZSCHE," "RELIGIONS AND PHILOSOPHIES OF THE EAST," &c.
The mussel is crooked inside and rough outside · it is only when we hear its deep note after blowing into it that we can begin to esteem it at its true value.—(Ind. Spruche, ed Bothlingk, 1 335)
The mussel is twisted on the inside and rough on the outside; it’s only when we blow into it and hear its deep sound that we can begin to recognize its real value.—(Ind. Spruche, ed Bothlingk, 1 335)
An ugly-looking-wind instrument · but we must first blow into it.
An unappealing wind instrument, but we have to blow into it first.
TRANSLATOR'S INTRODUCTION
The subject of education was one to which Nietzsche, especially during his residence in Basel, paid considerable attention, and his insight into it was very much deeper than that of, say, Herbert Spencer or even Johann Friedrich Herbart, the latter of whom has in late years exercised considerable influence in scholastic circles. Nietzsche clearly saw that the "philologists" (using the word chiefly in reference to the teachers of the classics in German colleges and universities) were absolutely unfitted for their high task, since they were one and all incapable of entering into the spirit of antiquity. Although at the first reading, therefore, this book may seem to be rather fragmentary, there are two main lines of thought running through it: an incisive criticism of German professors, and a number of constructive ideas as to what classical culture really should be.
The topic of education was one that Nietzsche, especially during his time in Basel, focused on a lot, and his understanding of it was much deeper than that of, say, Herbert Spencer or even Johann Friedrich Herbart, the latter of whom has recently had a significant impact in academic circles. Nietzsche clearly recognized that the "philologists" (using the term mainly to refer to teachers of the classics in German colleges and universities) were completely unqualified for their important role, as they were all unable to grasp the essence of ancient cultures. So, while this book might seem a bit disjointed at first glance, there are two main themes throughout: a sharp criticism of German professors and several constructive ideas about what classical culture should truly be.
These scattered aphorisms, indeed, are significant as showing how far Nietzsche had travelled along the road over which humanity had been travelling from remote ages, and how greatly he was imbued with the pagan spirit which he recognised in Goethe and valued in Burckhardt. Even at this early period of his life Nietzsche was convinced that Christianity was the real danger to culture; and not merely modern Christianity, but also the Alexandrian culture, the last gasp of Greek [Pg 106]antiquity, which had helped to bring Christianity about. When, in the later aphorisms of "We Philologists," Nietzsche appears to be throwing over the Greeks, it should be remembered that he does not refer to the Greeks of the era of Homer or Æschylus, or even of Aristotle, but to the much later Greeks of the era of Longinus.
These scattered sayings are important because they show how far Nietzsche had come along a path that humanity has been on for ages, and how deeply he was influenced by the pagan spirit he saw in Goethe and appreciated in Burckhardt. Even at this early stage in his life, Nietzsche believed that Christianity posed a real threat to culture; and not just modern Christianity, but also the Alexandrian culture, which was the last breath of Greek antiquity and contributed to the rise of Christianity. When Nietzsche seems to dismiss the Greeks in the later sayings of "We Philologists," it's important to remember that he’s not talking about the Greeks from the time of Homer, Aeschylus, or even Aristotle, but rather the much later Greeks from the time of Longinus.
Classical antiquity, however, was conveyed to the public through university professors and their intellectual offspring, and these professors, influenced (quite unconsciously, of course) by religious and "liberal" principles, presented to their scholars a kind of emasculated antiquity. It was only on these conditions that the State allowed the pagan teaching to be propagated in the schools; and if, where classical scholars were concerned, it was more tolerant than the Church had been, it must be borne in mind that the Church had already done all the rough work of emasculating its enemies, and had handed down to the State a body of very innocuous and harmless investigators. A totally erroneous conception of what constituted classical culture was thus brought about. Where any distinction was actually made, for example, later Greek thought was enormously over-rated, and early Greek thought equally undervalued. Aphorism 44, together with the first half-dozen or so in the book, may be taken as typical specimens of Nietzsche's protest against this state of things.
Classical antiquity was presented to the public by university professors and their students, who, influenced (though often unconsciously) by religious and "liberal" values, offered a softened version of antiquity. The State only permitted the spread of pagan teachings in schools under these conditions; while it was more tolerant than the Church had been regarding classical scholars, it's important to remember that the Church had already done the work of neutralizing its opponents, leaving the State with a group of rather harmless researchers. This led to a completely misleading understanding of what classical culture really was. When distinctions were made, later Greek thought was greatly overvalued, while early Greek thought was significantly undervalued. Aphorism 44, along with the first few in the book, can be seen as typical examples of Nietzsche's criticism of this situation.
It must be added, unfortunately, that Nietzsche's observations in this book apply as much to England as to Germany. Classical teachers here may not be rated so high as they are in Germany, but their[Pg 107] influence would appear to be equally powerful, and their theories of education and of classical antiquity equally chaotic. In England as in Germany they are "theologians in disguise." The danger of modern "values" to true culture may be readily gathered from a perusal of aphorisms that follow: and, if these aphorisms enable even one scholar in a hundred to enter more thoroughly into the spirit of a great past they will not have been penned in vain.
It should be noted, unfortunately, that Nietzsche's insights in this book apply just as much to England as they do to Germany. Classical educators here may not be held in as high regard as they are in Germany, but their[Pg 107] influence seems to be just as strong, and their approaches to education and classical history just as disorganized. In England, just like in Germany, they are "theologians in disguise." The threat posed by modern "values" to genuine culture can be easily understood from reading the following aphorisms; and if these aphorisms help even one in a hundred scholars connect more deeply with the spirit of a remarkable past, they will not have been written in vain.
J. M. KENNEDY.
J.M. Kennedy.
London, July 1911.
London, July 1911.
WE PHILOLOGISTS
I
To what a great extent men are ruled by pure hazard, and how little reason itself enters into the question, is sufficiently shown by observing how few people have any real capacity for their professions and callings, and how many square pegs there are in round holes: happy and well chosen instances are quite exceptional, like happy marriages, and even these latter are not brought about by reason. A man chooses his calling before he is fitted to exercise his faculty of choice. He does not know the number of different callings and professions that exist; he does not know himself; and then he wastes his years of activity in this calling, applies all his mind to it, and becomes experienced and practical. When, afterwards, his understanding has become fully developed, it is generally too late to start something new; for wisdom on earth has almost always had something of the weakness of old age and lack of vigour about it.
To what extent men are driven by pure chance, and how little reason actually plays a role, is clearly shown by how few people really have the skills for their jobs and how many square pegs there are in round holes: happy and well-suited matches are quite rare, like successful marriages, and even those aren’t usually built on reason. A person picks their career before they’re truly ready to make that choice. They don’t know about all the different jobs and professions out there; they don’t know themselves; and then they spend their active years in that job, committing fully to it, gaining experience and expertise. Once their understanding has matured, it’s usually too late to pivot to something new; because wisdom in this world often comes with the frailty of old age and a lack of energy.
For the most part the task is to make good, and to set to rights as well as possible, that which was bungled in the beginning. Many will come to recognise that the latter part of their life shows a purpose or design which has sprung from a primary discord: it is hard to live through it. Towards the end of his life, however, the average man has become accustomed to it—then he may make a mistake in regard[Pg 110] to the life he has lived, and praise his own stupidity: bene navigavi cum naufragium feci . he may even compose a song of thanksgiving to "Providence."
For the most part, the task is to make things right and to repair as much as possible what was messed up at the start. Many will come to realize that the latter part of their lives shows a purpose or design that has emerged from an initial conflict: it’s tough to get through. However, by the end of his life, the average person has become used to it—then he might mistake his past choices and praise his own foolishness: bene navigavi cum naufragium feci. He might even write a song of thanks to "Providence."
2
On inquiring into the origin of the philologist I find:
On looking into the origin of the philologist, I discover:
1. A young man cannot have the slightest conception of what the Greeks and Romans were.
1. A young man can’t even begin to understand what the Greeks and Romans were like.
2. He does not know whether he is fitted to investigate into them;
2. He isn't sure if he's suited to look into them;
3. And, in particular, he does not know to what extent, in view of the knowledge he may actually possess, he is fitted to be a teacher. What then enables him to decide is not the knowledge of himself or his science; but
3. And, in particular, he doesn't know to what extent, considering the knowledge he might actually have, he is suited to be a teacher. What allows him to make that decision is not his understanding of himself or his subject; but
(a) Imitation.
(a) Copying.
(b) The convenience of carrying on the kind of work which he had begun at school.
(b) The simplicity of carrying on with the kind of work he had begun in school.
(c) His intention of earning a living.
(c) His aim of earning a living.
In short, ninety-nine philologists out of a hundred should not be philologists at all.
In short, ninety-nine out of a hundred philologists shouldn't be philologists at all.
3
The more strict religions require that men shall look upon their activity simply as one means of carrying out a metaphysical scheme: an unfortunate choice of calling may then be explained as a test of the individual. Religions keep their eyes fixed only upon the salvation of the individual . whether he is a slave or a free man, a merchant or a scholar, his aim in life has nothing to do with his calling, so that a wrong choice is not such a very great piece[Pg 111] of unhappiness. Let this serve as a crumb of comfort for philologists in general; but true philologists stand in need of a better understanding: what will result from a science which is "gone in for" by ninety-nine such people? The thoroughly unfitted majority draw up the rules of the science in accordance with their own capacities and inclinations; and in this way they tyrannise over the hundredth, the only capable one among them. If they have the training of others in their hands they will train them consciously or unconsciously after their own image . what then becomes of the classicism of the Greeks and Romans?
The stricter religions require that men see their work as just a way to fulfill a larger spiritual plan: a poor choice of career might then be seen as a test for the individual. Religions focus solely on the salvation of the individual, whether he is a slave or free, a merchant or a scholar; his purpose in life is unrelated to his job, so a wrong choice isn’t such a significant source of unhappiness. Let this be a small comfort for linguists in general; however, true linguists need a deeper understanding: what will come from a field pursued by ninety-nine such individuals? The mostly unqualified majority sets the standards of the field based on their own abilities and preferences, and in doing so, they dominate the one capable person among them. If they control the training of others, they will mold them, consciously or unconsciously, in their own image. What happens then to the classicism of the Greeks and Romans?
The points to be proved are—
The points to prove are—
(a) The disparity between philologists and the ancients.
(a) The difference between linguists and ancient scholars.
(b) The inability of the philologist to train his pupils, even with the help of the ancients.
(b) The failure of the language expert to teach his students, even with guidance from the classics.
(c) The falsifying of the science by the (incapacity of the) majority, the wrong requirements held in view; the renunciation of the real aim of this science.
(c) The distortion of science by the inability of the majority, the incorrect goals in mind; the abandonment of the true purpose of this science.
4
All this affects the sources of our present philology: a sceptical and melancholy attitude. But how otherwise are philologists to be produced?
All of this impacts the sources of our current philology: a doubtful and sad attitude. But how else can we produce philologists?
The imitation of antiquity: is not this a principle which has been refuted by this time?
The imitation of the past: isn't this a principle that's been proven wrong by now?
The flight from actuality to the ancients: does not this tend to falsify our conception of antiquity?[Pg 112]
The shift from reality to the past: doesn’t this distort our understanding of ancient times?[Pg 112]
5
We are still behindhand in one type of contemplation: to understand how the greatest productions of the intellect have a dreadful and evil background . the sceptical type of contemplation. Greek antiquity is now investigated as the most beautiful example of life.
We are still lagging in one area of reflection: understanding how the greatest intellectual achievements have a dark and troubling backdrop—the skeptical kind of contemplation. Greek antiquity is now examined as the finest example of life.
As man assumes a sceptical and melancholy attitude towards his life's calling, so we must sceptically examine the highest life's calling of a nation: in order that we may understand what life is.
As people take on a skeptical and gloomy perspective about their life's purpose, we must also critically assess a nation's highest calling to understand what life really is.
6
My words of consolation apply particularly to the single tyrannised individual out of a hundred: such exceptional ones should simply treat all the unenlightened majorities as their subordinates; and they should in the same way take advantage of the prejudice, which is still widespread, in favour of classical instruction—they need many helpers. But they must have a clear perception of what their actual goal is.
My words of comfort are aimed especially at the one oppressed person out of a hundred: those extraordinary individuals should view all the ignorant majorities as their subordinates; and similarly, they should leverage the still-common bias in favor of traditional education—they need a lot of support. However, they must have a clear understanding of what their true goal is.
7
Philology as the science of antiquity does not, of course, endure for ever; its elements are not inexhaustible. What cannot be exhausted, however, is the ever-new adaptation of one's age to antiquity; the comparison of the two. If we make it our task to understand our own age better by means of antiquity, then our task will be an everlasting one.—This is the antinomy of philology: people have always endeavoured to understand antiquity by means of the[Pg 113] present—and shall the present now be understood by means of antiquity? Better: people have explained antiquity to themselves out of their own experiences; and from the amount of antiquity thus acquired they have assessed the value of their experiences. Experience, therefore, is certainly an essential prerequisite for a philologist—that is, the philologist must first of all be a man; for then only can he be productive as a philologist. It follows from this that old men are well suited to be philologists if they were not such during that portion of their life which was richest in experiences.
Philology, as the study of ancient times, obviously isn't something that lasts forever; its components aren't endless. What never runs out, though, is the continual reinterpretation of each era through the lens of antiquity; the comparison between the two. If we aim to better understand our current time by examining the past, this task will always be relevant. This is the contradiction of philology: people have consistently tried to make sense of the past using the present—and should the present now be interpreted through the past? Ideally, people have explained antiquity based on their own experiences; and from the knowledge of the past they've gathered, they've evaluated the worth of their experiences. Thus, experience is definitely a crucial requirement for a philologist—meaning, the philologist must firstly be a person; only then can they truly contribute as a philologist. This implies that older individuals are well-suited to be philologists, provided they weren't engaged in that role during the most experience-rich part of their lives.
It must be insisted, however, that it is only through a knowledge of the present that one can acquire an inclination for the study of classical antiquity. Where indeed should the impulse come from if not from this inclination? When we observe how few philologists there actually are, except those that have taken up philology as a means of livelihood, we can easily decide for ourselves what is the matter with this impulse for antiquity: it hardly exists at all, for there are no disinterested philologists.
It must be emphasized, however, that you can only develop an interest in studying classical history by understanding the present. Where else would that motivation come from if not from this interest? When we see how few philologists there really are, aside from those who pursue philology as a way to make a living, we can easily determine what the issue is with this interest in the past: it barely exists because there are no truly passionate philologists.
Our task then is to secure for philology the universally educative results which it should bring about. The means: the limitation of the number of those engaged in the philological profession (doubtful whether young men should be made acquainted with philology at all). Criticism of the philologist. The value of antiquity: it sinks with you: how deeply you must have sunk, since its value is now so little![Pg 114]
Our job now is to ensure that philology delivers the educational benefits it promises. The approach: limit the number of people in the philological field (it's questionable whether young people should even be introduced to philology). Critique of the philologist. The worth of ancient knowledge: it deteriorates with you; how far you must have fallen, since its value is now so minimal![Pg 114]
8
It is a great advantage for the true philologist that a great deal of preliminary work has been done in his science, so that he may take possession of this inheritance if he is strong enough for it—I refer to the valuation of the entire Hellenic mode of thinking. So long as philologists worked simply at details, a misunderstanding of the Greeks was the consequence. The stages of this undervaluation are · the sophists of the second century, the philologist-poets of the Renaissance, and the philologist as the teacher of the higher classes of society (Goethe, Schiller).
It’s a big advantage for today’s philologist that a lot of foundational work has already been done in this field, allowing them to build on that legacy if they’re capable of doing so—I’m talking about the assessment of the whole Hellenic way of thinking. As long as philologists focused only on the details, they misunderstood the Greeks. The phases of this undervaluation include the sophists of the second century, the philologist-poets of the Renaissance, and the philologist as an instructor for the upper classes of society (Goethe, Schiller).
Valuing is the most difficult of all.
Valuing is the hardest of them all.
In what respect is one most fitted for this valuing?
In what way is someone best suited for this evaluation?
—Not, at all events, when one is trained for philology as one is now. It should be ascertained to what extent our present means make this last object impossible.
—Not, at least, when you're trained for philology like we are now. We should determine how much our current resources make this last goal unachievable.
—Thus the philologist himself is not the aim of philology.
—So, the philologist is not the goal of philology.
9
Most men show clearly enough that they do not regard themselves as individuals: their lives indicate this. The Christian command that everyone shall steadfastly keep his eyes fixed upon his salvation, and his alone, has as its counterpart the general life of mankind, where every man lives merely as a point among other points—living not only as the result of earlier generations, but living also only with an eye to the future. There are only three forms of existence in which a man remains an individual as a philosopher, as a Saviour, and as an artist. But just let us consider how a scientific man bungles his life:[Pg 115] what has the teaching of Greek particles to do with the sense of life?—Thus we can also observe how innumerable men merely live, as it were, a preparation for a man, the philologist, for example, as a preparation for the philosopher, who in his turn knows how to utilise his ant-like work to pronounce some opinion upon the value of life. When such ant-like work is not carried out under any special direction the greater part of it is simply nonsense, and quite superfluous.
Most men clearly don't see themselves as individuals; their lives show this. The Christian command for everyone to focus solely on their own salvation contrasts with the general human experience, where each person lives as just one point among many—existing not only as a result of past generations but also with an eye on the future. There are only three ways a person remains an individual: as a philosopher, a savior, or an artist. But just think about how a scientist messes up their life: what do Greek grammar lessons have to do with the meaning of life? We can also see how countless men simply live in preparation for someone else, like a philologist preparing for a philosopher, who then uses that ant-like labor to share some thoughts on the meaning of life. When that kind of labor isn't guided in any specific way, most of it is just nonsense and completely unnecessary.
10
Besides the large number of unqualified philologists there is, on the other hand, a number of what may be called born philologists, who from some reason or other are prevented from becoming such. The greatest obstacle, however, which stands in the way of these born philologists is the bad representation of philology by the unqualified philologists.
Besides the many unqualified language experts, there are also some natural language enthusiasts who, for various reasons, can't pursue this path. The biggest challenge these natural philologists face is the poor image of the field created by the unqualified practitioners.
Leopardi is the modern ideal of a philologist: The German philologists can do nothing. (As a proof of this Voss should be studied!)
Leopardi represents the modern ideal of a philologist: The German philologists can't accomplish anything. (Voss should be studied as proof of this!)
11
Let it be considered how differently a science is propagated from the way in which any special talent in a family is transmitted. The bodily transmission of an individual science is something very rare. Do the sons of philologists easily become philologists? Dubito. Thus there is no such accumulation of philological capacity as there was, let us say, in Beethoven's family of musical capacity.[Pg 116] Most philologists begin from the beginning, and even then they learn from books, and not through travels, &c. They get some training, of course.
Let’s consider how differently a science spreads compared to how any specific talent runs in a family. The direct passing down of a unique science is quite rare. Do the children of philologists easily become philologists themselves? I doubt it. So, there isn't a build-up of philological talent like there was, for example, in Beethoven's family with musical talent.[Pg 116] Most philologists start from scratch, and even then, they learn from books rather than through travel, etc. They do get some training, of course.
12
Most men are obviously in the world accidentally; no necessity of a higher kind is seen in them. They work at this and that, their talents are average. How strange! The manner in which they live shows that they think very little of themselves: they merely esteem themselves in so far as they waste their energy on trifles (whether these be mean or frivolous desires, or the trashy concerns of their everyday calling). In the so-called life's calling, which everyone must choose, we may perceive a touching modesty on the part of mankind. They practically admit in choosing thus. "We are called upon to serve and to be of advantage to our equals—the same remark applies to our neighbour and to his neighbour, so everyone serves somebody else; no one is carrying out the duties of his calling for his own sake, but always for the sake of others and thus we are like geese which support one another by the one leaning against the other. When the aim of each one of us is centred in another, then we have all no object in existing; and this 'existing for others' is the most comical of comedies."
Most men are clearly just going through life by chance; there's no sign of a deeper purpose in them. They dabble in various things, and their abilities are pretty average. It's odd! The way they live shows that they think very little of themselves: they only value themselves to the extent that they spend their energy on trivial matters (whether those are petty or silly desires, or the pointless concerns of their daily job). In the so-called career path that everyone must take, we can see a touching humility among people. They effectively acknowledge in their choices: "We're meant to serve and help our peers—this also applies to our neighbor and his neighbor, so everyone is serving someone else; no one is fulfilling their role for their own sake, but always for the benefit of others, and in this way, we're like geese supporting one another, with one leaning on the other. When each of us focuses our purpose on someone else, then none of us really have any reason to exist; and this 'existing for others' is the most ridiculous of comedies."
13
Vanity is the involuntary inclination to set one's self up for an individual while not really being one; that is to say, trying to appear independent when one is dependent. The case of wisdom is the exact[Pg 117] contrary: it appears to be dependent while in reality it is independent.
Vanity is the involuntary tendency to present oneself as an individual without truly being one; in other words, trying to look independent while actually being dependent. Wisdom, on the other hand, is the complete opposite: it looks dependent but is actually independent.
14
The Hades of Homer—From what type of existence is it really copied? I think it is the description of the philologist: it is better to be a day-labourer than to have such an anæmic recollection of the past.—[1]
The Hades of Homer—What kind of existence is it really based on? I believe it reflects the view of the philologist: it's better to be a day laborer than to have such a weak memory of the past.—[1]
15
The attitude of the philologist towards antiquity is apologetic, or else dictated by the view that what our own age values can likewise be found in antiquity. The right attitude to take up, however, is the reverse one, viz., to start with an insight into our modern topsyturviness, and to look back from antiquity to it—and many things about antiquity which have hitherto displeased us will then be seen to have been most profound necessities.
The philologist’s attitude towards ancient times is often one of justification or shaped by the belief that the values of our current era can also be found in the past. However, the correct approach should be the opposite; that is, we should begin by recognizing the chaotic nature of our modern world and then look back at antiquity from this perspective. Many aspects of ancient times that have previously bothered us will then appear to be essential truths.
We must make it clear to ourselves that we are acting in an absurd manner when we try to defend or to beautify antiquity: who are we!
We need to be honest with ourselves that we’re being ridiculous when we try to defend or glorify the past: who are we!
16
We are under a false impression when we say that there is always some caste which governs a nation's culture, and that therefore savants are necessary; for savants only possess knowledge concerning culture (and even this only in exceptional cases). Among learned men themselves there might be a few, certainly not a caste, but even these would indeed be rare.[Pg 118]
We are mistaken when we say that there's always a group that controls a nation's culture, and that experts are essential; because experts only have knowledge about culture (and even this is true only in some rare cases). Among scholars, there may be a few, but they certainly don't form a group, and even those would be quite rare.[Pg 118]
17
One very great value of antiquity consists in the fact that its writings are the only ones which modern men still read carefully.
One of the greatest values of ancient times is that its writings are the only ones that modern people still read closely.
Overstraining of the memory—very common among philologists, together with a poor development of the judgment.
Overloading of the memory—very common among language scholars—along with weak judgment skills.
18
Busying ourselves with the culture-epochs of the past: is this gratitude? We should look backwards in order to explain to ourselves the present conditions of culture: we do not become too laudatory in regard to our own circumstances, but perhaps we should do so in order that we may not be too severe on ourselves.
Busying ourselves with the cultural eras of the past: is this gratitude? We should look back to understand the current state of culture: we don’t become overly praising of our own situation, but maybe we should in order not to be too hard on ourselves.
19
He who has no sense for the symbolical has none for antiquity: let pedantic philologists bear this in mind.
He who doesn’t appreciate symbolism doesn’t appreciate history either: let scholarly linguists keep this in mind.
20
My aim is to bring about a state of complete enmity between our present "culture" and antiquity. Whoever wishes to serve the former must hate the latter.
My goal is to create a complete divide between our current "culture" and the past. Anyone who wants to support the former must reject the latter.
21
Careful meditation upon the past leads to the impression that we are a multiplication of many pasts · so how can we be a final aim? But why not? In most instances, however, we do not wish to be this. We take up our positions again in the[Pg 119] ranks, work in our own little corner, and hope that what we do may be of some small profit to our successors. But that is exactly the case of the cask of the Danæ · and this is useless, we must again set about doing everything for ourselves, and only for ourselves—measuring science by ourselves, for example with the question · What is science to us? not . what are we to science? People really make life too easy for themselves when they look upon themselves from such a simple historical point of view, and make humble servants of themselves. "Your own salvation above everything"—that is what you should say; and there are no institutions which you should prize more highly than your own soul.—Now, however, man learns to know himself: he finds himself miserable, despises himself, and is pleased to find something worthy of respect outside himself. Therefore he gets rid of himself, so to speak, makes himself subservient to a cause, does his duty strictly, and atones for his existence. He knows that he does not work for himself alone; he wishes to help those who are daring enough to exist on account of themselves, like Socrates. The majority of men are as it were suspended in the air like toy balloons; every breath of wind moves them.—As a consequence the savant must be such out of self-knowledge, that is to say, out of contempt for himself—in other words he must recognise himself to be merely the servant of some higher being who comes after him. Otherwise he is simply a sheep.[Pg 120]
Careful reflection on the past gives the impression that we are a combination of many histories, so how can we be a final goal? But why not? In most cases, though, we don't want to be that. We take our places again in the[Pg 119] ranks, work in our own little corners, and hope that our efforts will benefit those who come after us. But this is exactly like the cask of Danæ—it's pointless. We must focus on doing everything for ourselves, only for ourselves—measuring science by asking ourselves, "What is science to us?" instead of "What are we to science?" People make life too easy for themselves by viewing their existence from such a simplistic historical perspective, becoming humble servants to their own limitations. "Your own salvation above everything"—that's what you should prioritize; there’s no institution more valuable than your own soul. But now, people learn to understand themselves: they find themselves pitiable, dislike themselves, and are eager to find something worthy of respect outside of themselves. So, they effectively rid themselves of their individuality, becoming subservient to a cause, diligently fulfilling their duties to atone for their existence. They know they don’t work just for their own sake; they want to aid those brave enough to exist for their own reasons, like Socrates. Most people float through life like toy balloons, swayed by every gust of wind. Consequently, a scholar must come from self-awareness, which means recognizing their own shortcomings—in other words, seeing themselves merely as the servant of something greater that comes after them. Otherwise, they're just a sheep.[Pg 120]
22
It is the duty of the free man to live for his own sake, and not for others. It was on this account that the Greeks looked upon handicrafts as unseemly.
It is the responsibility of a free person to live for their own benefit, not for others. This is why the Greeks viewed manual labor as unbecoming.
As a complete entity Greek antiquity has not yet been fully valued · I am convinced that if it had not been surrounded by its traditional glorification, the men of the present day would shrink from it horror stricken. This glorification, then, is spurious; gold-paper.
As a whole, Greek antiquity hasn’t been fully appreciated yet. I believe that if it weren’t wrapped in its traditional glorification, people today would be horrified by it. So, this glorification is fake; just glitter.
23
The false enthusiasm for antiquity in which many philologists live. When antiquity suddenly comes upon us in our youth, it appears to us to be composed of innumerable trivialities; in particular we believe ourselves to be above its ethics. And Homer and Walter Scott—who carries off the palm? Let us be honest! If this enthusiasm were really felt, people could scarcely seek their life's calling in it. I mean that what we can obtain from the Greeks only begins to dawn upon us in later years: only after we have undergone many experiences, and thought a great deal.
The false enthusiasm for the past that many scholars have. When the past hits us in our youth, it seems made up of countless trivialities; we often think we know better than its morals. And Homer or Walter Scott—who’s better? Let’s be real! If this enthusiasm were genuine, people wouldn’t be looking for their life's purpose in it. What we can truly gain from the Greeks usually starts to make sense to us later in life, after we’ve gone through various experiences and done a lot of thinking.
24
People in general think that philology is at an end—while I believe that it has not yet begun.
People generally think that philology is finished—while I believe it hasn’t even started.
The greatest events in philology are the appearance of Goethe, Schopenhauer, and Wagner; standing on their shoulders we look far into the distance. The fifth and sixth centuries have still to be discovered.
The most significant moments in philology are marked by the emergence of Goethe, Schopenhauer, and Wagner; by standing on their shoulders, we can see much further ahead. The fifth and sixth centuries are still waiting to be uncovered.
25
Where do we see the effect of antiquity? Not in language, not in the imitation of something or other, and not in perversity and waywardness, to which uses the French have turned it. Our museums are gradually becoming filled up: I always experience a sensation of disgust when I see naked statues in the Greek style in the presence of this thoughtless philistinism which would fain devour everything.[Pg 122]
Where do we see the influence of ancient times? Not in language, not in trying to copy something, and not in the oddities and quirks that the French have embraced. Our museums are slowly getting filled up: I always feel a sense of disgust when I see nude statues in the Greek style alongside this mindless philistinism that seems eager to consume everything.[Pg 122]
PLANS AND THOUGHTS RELATING TO A WORK ON PHILOLOGY
(1875)
26
Of all sciences philology at present is the most favoured · its progress having been furthered for centuries by the greatest number of scholars in every nation who have had charge of the noblest pupils. Philology has thus had one of the best of all opportunities to be propagated from generation to generation, and to make itself respected. How has it acquired this power?
Of all the sciences, philology is currently the most favored. Its development has been supported for centuries by a large number of scholars from every nation, who have taught the brightest students. As a result, philology has had one of the best opportunities to be passed down from generation to generation and to earn respect. How did it gain this power?
Calculations of the different prejudices in its favour.
Calculations of the various biases in its favor.
How then if these were to be frankly recognised as prejudices? Would not philology be superfluous if we reckoned up the interests of a position in life or the earning of a livelihood? What if the truth were told about antiquity, and its qualifications for training people to live in the present?
How would it be if we openly acknowledged these as biases? Wouldn't studying language and literature be unnecessary if we considered the interests tied to social status or making a living? What if we revealed the truth about the past and its value in preparing people to live in the present?
In order that the questions set forth above may be answered let us consider the training of the philologist, his genesis: he no longer comes into being where these interests are lacking.
In order to answer the questions mentioned above, let's look at the training of the philologist and where it comes from: he no longer exists in a context where these interests are missing.
If the world in general came to know what an unseasonable thing for us antiquity really is, philo[Pg 123]logists would no longer be called in as the educators of our youth.
If the world understood how out of place antiquity is for us, people wouldn’t turn to philologists as the teachers of our young people.
Effect of antiquity on the non-philologist likewise nothing. If they showed themselves to be imperative and contradictory, oh, with what hatred would they be pursued! But they always humble themselves.
Effect of the past on those who aren’t linguists is nothing. If they came across as demanding and inconsistent, oh, how fiercely they would be chased! But they always lower themselves.
Philology now derives its power only from the union between the philologists who will not, or cannot, understand antiquity and public opinion, which is misled by prejudices in regard to it.
Philology now gets its strength solely from the connection between philologists who won’t, or can’t, grasp the past and public opinion, which is confused by biases about it.
The real Greeks, and their "watering down" through the philologists.
The true Greeks, and their "watering down" by the philologists.
The future commanding philologist sceptical in regard to our entire culture, and therefore also the destroyer of philology as a profession.
The future will have a commanding linguist who is skeptical about our entire culture, and therefore also the one who undermines philology as a profession.
The Love for Old Things
27
If a man approves of the investigation of the past he will also approve and even praise the fact—and will above all easily understand it—that there are scholars who are exclusively occupied with the investigation of Greek and Roman antiquity: but that these scholars are at the same time the teachers of the children of the nobility and gentry is not equally easy of comprehension—here lies a problem.
If a man values studying the past, he will also support and even commend the idea—and will especially find it easy to understand—that there are scholars who focus solely on exploring Greek and Roman history. However, the fact that these scholars also teach the children of the nobility and upper class isn't as straightforward to grasp—this presents a dilemma.
Why philologists precisely? This is not altogether such a matter of course as the case of a professor of medicine, who is also a practical physician and surgeon. For, if the cases were identical, preoccupation with Greek and Roman antiquity would be[Pg 124] identical with the "science of education." In short, the relationship between theory and practice in the philologist cannot be so quickly conceived. Whence comes his pretension to be a teacher in the higher sense, not only of all scientific men, but more especially of all cultured men? This educational power must be taken by the philologist from antiquity; and in such a case people will ask with astonishment: how does it come that we attach such value to a far-off past that we can only become cultured men with the aid of its knowledge?
Why philologists, specifically? It's not as straightforward as a medical professor who is also a practicing doctor and surgeon. If the situations were the same, focusing on Greek and Roman history would be identical to "the science of education." In short, the connection between theory and practice for a philologist isn't easily understood. Where does the claim come from that they can be a teacher in a deeper sense, not just for scientists but especially for all educated individuals? This educational influence must be derived from antiquity; and in that case, people will wonder in disbelief: how is it that we value a distant past so much that we can only become educated individuals through its knowledge?
These questions, however, are not asked as a rule: The sway of philology over our means of instruction remains practically unquestioned; and antiquity has the importance assigned to it. To this extent the position of the philologist is more favourable than that of any other follower of science. True, he has not at his disposal that great mass of men who stand in need of him—the doctor, for example, has far more than the philologist. But he can influence picked men, or youths, to be more accurate, at a time when all their mental faculties are beginning to blossom forth—people who can afford to devote both time and money to their higher development. In all those places where European culture has found its way, people have accepted secondary schools based upon a foundation of Latin and Greek as the first and highest means of instruction. In this way philology has found its best opportunity of transmitting itself, and commanding respect: no other science has been so well favoured. As a general rule all those who have passed through such institutions have afterwards borne testimony to the[Pg 125] excellence of their organisation and curriculum, and such people are, of course, unconscious witnesses in favour of philology. If any who have not passed through these institutions should happen to utter a word in disparagement of this education, an unanimous and yet calm repudiation of the statement at once follows, as if classical education were a kind of witchcraft, blessing its followers, and demonstrating itself to them by this blessing. There is no attempt at polemics · "We have been through it all." "We know it has done us good."
These questions, however, are not typically asked: The influence of philology over our educational methods remains largely unchallenged; and ancient studies hold the significance attributed to them. In this sense, the role of the philologist is more advantageous than that of any other scholar. It's true that he doesn't have the large number of people relying on him—the doctor, for example, has far more followers than the philologist. But he can impact select individuals or young people to be more precise at a time when their mental abilities are starting to thrive—those who can afford both time and money for their advanced education. In all the places where European culture has established itself, people have embraced secondary schools based on a foundation of Latin and Greek as the primary and highest means of learning. In this way, philology has found its best opportunity for passing itself on and gaining respect: no other field of study has been as well supported. Generally, all who have attended such institutions have later testified to the[Pg 125] quality of their organization and curriculum, and these individuals are, of course, unintentional advocates for philology. If anyone who hasn't gone through these institutions dares to speak negatively about this education, a unanimous and composed rejection of that claim quickly follows, as if classical education were a kind of magic, blessing its practitioners and revealing itself to them through this blessing. There is no argument—“We’ve experienced it all.” “We know it has benefited us.”
Now there are so many things to which men have become so accustomed that they look upon them as quite appropriate and suitable, for habit intermixes all things with sweetness; and men as a rule judge the value of a thing in accordance with their own desires. The desire for classical antiquity as it is now felt should be tested, and, as it were, taken to pieces and analysed with a view to seeing how much of this desire is due to habit, and how much to mere love of adventure—I refer to that inward and active desire, new and strange, which gives rise to a productive conviction from day to day, the desire for a higher goal, and also the means thereto · as the result of which people advance step by step from one unfamiliar thing to another, like an Alpine climber.
Now there are so many things that people have gotten so used to that they see them as totally normal and fitting, because habit mixes everything with comfort. Generally, people judge the value of things based on their own desires. The current desire for classical antiquity should be examined and analyzed to figure out how much of this desire comes from habit and how much is just a simple love for adventure. I’m talking about that inner and active desire, new and exciting, which sparks a productive belief day by day—a desire for a higher purpose and the means to achieve it. As a result, people move forward step by step from one unfamiliar experience to another, like a mountain climber tackling the Alps.
What is the foundation on which the high value attached to antiquity at the present time is based, to such an extent indeed that our whole modern culture is founded on it? Where must we look for the origin of this delight in antiquity, and the preference shown for it?[Pg 126]
What is the basis for the great value we place on the past today, to the point that our entire modern culture is built on it? Where should we search for the source of this fascination with antiquity and the preference we give to it?[Pg 126]
I think I have recognised in my examination of the question that all our philology—that is, all its present existence and power—is based on the same foundation as that on which our view of antiquity as the most important of all means of training is based. Philology as a means of instruction is the clear expression of a predominating conception regarding the value of antiquity, and the best methods of education. Two propositions are contained in this statement. In the first place all higher education must be a historical one, and secondly, Greek and Roman history differs from all others in that it is classical. Thus the scholar who knows this history becomes a teacher. We are not here going into the question as to whether higher education ought to be historical or not; but we may examine the second and ask: in how far is it classic?
I believe I have recognized in my analysis of the issue that all our philology—that is, its current state and influence—rests on the same foundation as our belief that studying antiquity is the most important method of education. Philology as a teaching tool clearly reflects a dominant idea about the value of ancient history and the best educational practices. This statement includes two key points. First, all higher education must have a historical basis, and second, Greek and Roman history is unique in being classical. Therefore, a scholar knowledgeable in this history becomes a teacher. We won’t delve into whether higher education should be historical; instead, we can focus on the second point and ask: in what way is it considered classic?
On this point there are many widespread prejudices. In the first place there is the prejudice expressed in the synonymous concept, "The study of the humanities": antiquity is classic because it is the school of the humane.
On this point, there are many common misconceptions. First of all, there’s the misconception expressed in the similar idea, "The study of the humanities": the past is considered classic because it teaches us about being humane.
Secondly: "Antiquity is classic because it is enlightened——"
Secondly: "Antiquity is classic because it is enlightened——"
28
It is the task of all education to change certain conscious actions and habits into more or less unconscious ones; and the history of mankind is in this sense its education. The philologist now practises unconsciously a number of such occupations and habits. It is my object to ascertain how[Pg 127] his power, that is, his instinctive methods of work, is the result of activities which were formerly conscious, but which he has gradually come to feel as such no longer: but that consciousness consisted of prejudices. The present power of philologists is based upon these prejudices, for example the value attached to the ratio as in the cases of Bentley and Hermann. Prejudices are, as Lichtenberg says, the art impulses of men.
It’s the job of education to turn certain conscious actions and habits into more or less unconscious ones; and from this perspective, the history of humanity is its education. A philologist now unknowingly practices a number of these actions and habits. My goal is to determine how[Pg 127] their abilities, which are their instinctive work methods, come from activities that were once conscious but have gradually become automatic: but that consciousness was made up of prejudices. The current skills of philologists are based on these prejudices, for example, the importance placed on the ratio as seen in the cases of Bentley and Hermann. Prejudices are, as Lichtenberg says, the creative impulses of people.
29
It is difficult to justify the preference for antiquity since it has arisen from prejudices:
It’s hard to explain why we prefer the old days when it just comes from biases:
1. From ignorance of all non-classical antiquity.
1. From a lack of knowledge about all non-classical ancient history.
2. From a false idealisation of humanitarianism, whilst Hindoos and Chinese are at all events more humane.
2. From a distorted view of humanitarianism, while Hindus and Chinese are definitely more compassionate.
3. From the pretensions of school-teachers.
3. From the attitudes of schoolteachers.
4. From the traditional admiration which emanated from antiquity itself.
4. From the classic admiration that originated from ancient times.
5. From opposition to the Christian church; or as a support for this church.
5. As a challenge to the Christian church or as a support for this church.
6. From the impression created by the century-long work of the philologists, and the nature of this work. It must be a gold mine, thinks the spectator.
6. From the impression left by the century-long efforts of the philologists and the nature of this work, the observer thinks it must be a gold mine.
7. The acquirement of knowledge attained as the result of the study. The preparatory school of science.
7. The gaining of knowledge achieved through study. The preparatory school of science.
In short, partly from ignorance, wrong impressions, and misleading conclusions; and also from the interest which philologists have in raising their science to a high level in the estimation of laymen.[Pg 128]
In short, partly due to ignorance, misconceptions, and misleading conclusions; and also from the interest that linguists have in elevating their field to a high status in the eyes of the general public.[Pg 128]
Also the preference for antiquity on the part of the artists, who involuntarily assume proportion and moderation to be the property of all antiquity. Purity of form. Authors likewise.
Also, artists tend to favor the past, often assuming that proportion and moderation are characteristics of all ancient works. They value purity of form. Authors do too.
The preference for antiquity as an abbreviation of the history of the human race, as if there were an autochthonous creation here by which all becoming might be studied.
The preference for the past as a summary of human history, as if there were a native creation here from which all development could be explored.
The fact actually is that the foundations of this preference are being removed one by one, and if this is not remarked by philologists themselves, it is certainly being remarked as much as it can possibly be by people outside their circle. First of all history had its effect, and then linguistics brought about the greatest diversion among philologists themselves, and even the desertion of many of them. They have still the schools in their hands: but for how long! In the form in which it has existed up to the present philology is dying out; the ground has been swept from under its feet. Whether philologists may still hope to maintain their status is doubtful; in any case they are a dying race.
The reality is that the basis for this preference is being dismantled piece by piece, and while philologists might not notice it, many outsiders certainly do. First, history made its mark, and then linguistics created significant divisions among philologists, leading some to abandon the field altogether. They still control the schools, but for how much longer? As it stands, philology is fading away; the support has been taken from beneath them. Whether philologists can still hope to keep their position is uncertain; in any case, they are a dwindling group.
30
The peculiarly significant situation of philologists: a class of people to whom we entrust our youth, and who have to investigate quite a special antiquity. The highest value is obviously attached to this antiquity. But if this antiquity has been wrongly valued, then the whole foundation upon which the high position of the philologist is based suddenly collapses. In any case this antiquity has[Pg 129] been very differently valued, and our appreciation of the philologists has constantly been guided by it. These people have borrowed their power from the strong prejudices in favour of antiquity,—this must be made clear.
The uniquely important role of philologists: a group of people we trust with our youth, who have to study a specific type of ancient knowledge. This knowledge is clearly considered highly valuable. But if this ancient knowledge has been misjudged, then the entire foundation of the philologist's esteemed position collapses. In any case, this ancient knowledge has[Pg 129] been valued very differently, and our view of philologists has always been shaped by it. These individuals have gained their influence from the strong biases in favor of the past—this needs to be made clear.
Philologists now feel that when these prejudices are at last refuted, and antiquity depicted in its true colours, the favourable prejudices towards them will diminish considerably. It is thus to the interest of their profession not to let a clear impression of antiquity come to light; in particular the impression that antiquity in its highest sense renders one "out of season?" i.e., an enemy to one's own time.
Philologists now believe that once these biases are finally challenged, and the past is shown in its true light, the positive biases towards them will significantly decrease. Therefore, it's in their profession's interest not to allow a clear understanding of the past to emerge; especially the idea that the past in its most profound sense makes someone "out of sync?" i.e., an adversary to their own time.
It is also to the interest of philologists as a class not to let their calling as teachers be regarded from a higher standpoint than that to which they themselves can correspond.
It’s also in the interest of philologists as a group not to let their role as teachers be seen from a higher perspective than what they can actually achieve.
31
It is to be hoped that there are a few people who look upon it as a problem why philologists should be the teachers of our noblest youths. Perhaps the case will not be always so—It would be much more natural per se if our children were instructed in the elements of geography, natural science, political economy, and sociology, if they were gradually led to a consideration of life itself, and if finally, but much later, the most noteworthy events of the past were brought to their knowledge. A knowledge of antiquity should be among the last subjects which a student would take up; and would not this position of antiquity in the curriculum of a school be more honourable for it than the present one?[Pg 130]—Antiquity is now used merely as a propædeutic for thinking, speaking, and writing; but there was a time when it was the essence of earthly knowledge, and people at that time wished to acquire by means of practical learning what they now seek to acquire merely by means of a detailed plan of study—a plan which, corresponding to the more advanced knowledge of the age, has entirely changed.
It’s hoped that some people wonder why philologists are the ones teaching our brightest young minds. Perhaps that won't always be the case—it would make much more sense if our children were taught the basics of geography, natural science, political economy, and sociology. They should gradually learn about life itself, and only much later should they be introduced to the significant events of history. Learning about the past should be one of the last subjects a student tackles; wouldn’t this approach give history a more respected place in the school curriculum than it has now?[Pg 130]—Right now, history is just a stepping stone for thinking, speaking, and writing. But there was a time when it represented the core of earthly knowledge, and people then aimed to gain practical insights that are now often sought through a detailed study plan—a plan that has completely evolved to reflect the more advanced knowledge of our times.
Thus the inner purpose of philological teaching has been entirely altered; it was at one time material teaching, a teaching that taught how to live, but now it is merely formal.[2]
Thus, the main goal of teaching philology has completely changed; it used to focus on practical knowledge, teaching how to live, but now it is just about the structure and form.[2]
32
If it were the task of the philologist to impart formal education, it would be necessary for him to teach walking, dancing, speaking, singing, acting, or arguing · and the so-called formal teachers did impart their instruction this way in the second and third centuries. But only the training of a scientific man is taken into account, which results in "formal" thinking and writing, and hardly any speaking at all.
If it were the job of the linguist to provide formal education, he would need to teach walking, dancing, speaking, singing, acting, or debating. And the so-called formal teachers did provide their instruction this way in the second and third centuries. But only the training of a scientific person is considered, which leads to "formal" thinking and writing, and barely any speaking at all.
33
If the gymnasium is to train young men for science, people now say there can be no more pre[Pg 131]liminary preparation for any particular science, so comprehensive have all the sciences become. As a consequence teachers have to train their students generally, that is to say for all the sciences—for scientificality in other words; and for that classical studies are necessary! What a wonderful jump! a most despairing justification! Whatever is, is right,[3] even when it is clearly seen that the "right" on which it has been based has turned to wrong.
If the gym is supposed to prepare young men for science, people now say that there’s no longer a need for specific preparation for any particular science, since all the sciences have become so interconnected. As a result, teachers need to educate their students broadly, meaning they must prepare them for all the sciences—for scientific thinking, in other words; and for that, classical studies are essential! What a remarkable leap! A truly frustrating justification! Whatever exists, is acceptable, even when it's obvious that the "right" it was built on has become wrong.
34
It is accomplishments which are expected from us after a study of the ancients: formerly, for example, the ability to write and speak. But what is expected now! Thinking and deduction . but these things are not learnt from the ancients, but at best through the ancients, by means of science. Moreover, all historical deduction is very limited and unsafe, natural science should be preferred.
It’s achievements that are expected from us after studying the ancients: in the past, for instance, the ability to write and speak. But what’s expected now? Thinking and reasoning. However, these skills aren’t learned from the ancients, but at best through them, using science. Furthermore, all historical reasoning is quite limited and unreliable; natural science should be favored.
35
It is the same with the simplicity of antiquity as it is with the simplicity of style: it is the highest thing which we recognise and must imitate; but it is also the last. Let it be remembered that the classic prose of the Greeks is also a late result.
It’s the same with the simplicity of the past as it is with simple styles: it’s the best we recognize and should emulate; but it’s also the final outcome. Keep in mind that the classic prose of the Greeks is also a later development.
36
What a mockery of the study of the "humanities" lies in the fact that they were also called "belles lettres" (bellas litteras)![Pg 132]
What a joke the study of the "humanities" is, considering they were also called "belles lettres" (beautiful letters)![Pg 132]
37
Wolf's[4] reasons why the Egyptians, Hebrews, Persians, and other Oriental nations were not to be set on the same plane with the Greeks and Romans: "The former have either not raised themselves, or have raised themselves only to a slight extent, above that type of culture which should be called a mere civilisation and bourgeois acquirement, as opposed to the higher and true culture of the mind." He then explains that this culture is spiritual and literary: "In a well-organised nation this may be begun earlier than order and peacefulness in the outward life of the people (enlightenment)."
Wolf's[4] reasons why the Egyptians, Hebrews, Persians, and other Oriental nations should not be considered on the same level as the Greeks and Romans: "The former have either not progressed, or have only slightly advanced, beyond a type of culture that can be called mere civilization and middle-class achievement, in contrast to the higher and true culture of the mind." He then explains that this culture is spiritual and literary: "In a well-organized nation, this can begin earlier than order and peace in the external life of the people (enlightenment)."
He then contrasts the inhabitants of easternmost Asia ("like such individuals, who are not wanting in clean, decent, and comfortable dwellings, clothing, and surroundings; but who never feel the necessity for a higher enlightenment") with the Greeks ("in the case of the Greeks, even among the most educated inhabitants of Attica, the contrary often happens to an astonishing degree; and the people neglect as insignificant factors that which we, thanks to our love of order, are in the habit of looking upon as the foundations of mental culture itself").
He then contrasts the people of easternmost Asia ("like those individuals, who have clean, decent, and comfortable homes, clothing, and environments; but who never feel the need for a higher understanding") with the Greeks ("in the case of the Greeks, even among the most educated people in Attica, the opposite often occurs to an astonishing degree; and they overlook as unimportant factors what we, because of our love of order, usually see as the foundations of mental culture itself").
38
Our terminology already shows how prone we are to judge the ancients wrongly: the exaggerated sense of literature, for example, or, as Wolf, when[Pg 133] speaking of the "inner history of ancient erudition," calls it, "the history of learned enlightenment."
Our language already reveals how easily we misjudge the ancients: the inflated perception of literature, for instance, or, as Wolf, when[Pg 133] referring to the "inner history of ancient erudition," describes it, "the history of learned enlightenment."
39
According to Goethe, the ancients are "the despair of the emulator." Voltaire said. "If the admirers of Homer were honest, they would acknowledge the boredom which their favourite often causes them."
According to Goethe, the ancients are "the despair of the emulator." Voltaire said, "If the fans of Homer were honest, they would admit the boredom that their favorite often brings them."
40
The position we have taken up towards classical antiquity is at bottom the profound cause of the sterility of modern culture; for we have taken all this modern conception of culture from the Hellenised Romans. We must distinguish within the domain of antiquity itself: when we come to appreciate its purely productive period, we condemn at the same time the entire Romano-Alexandrian culture. But at the same time also we condemn our own attitude towards antiquity, and likewise our philology.
The stance we've adopted toward classical antiquity is fundamentally the deep reason for the stagnation of modern culture; we've derived our modern understanding of culture from the Hellenized Romans. We need to differentiate within the realm of antiquity itself: when we start to value its purely creative period, we simultaneously criticize the whole Romano-Alexandrian culture. But at the same time, we also criticize our own approach to antiquity and our philology.
41
There has been an age-long battle between the Germans and antiquity, i.e., a battle against the old culture. It is certain that precisely what is best and deepest in the German resists it. The main point, however, is that such resistance is only justifiable in the case of the Romanised culture; for this culture, even at that time, was a falling-off from something more profound and noble. It is this latter that the Germans are wrong in resisting.[Pg 134]
There has been a long-standing struggle between the Germans and ancient culture, i.e. a fight against the old ways. It's clear that what is most valuable and profound in German culture pushes back against it. The key issue, though, is that this pushback is only justified when it comes to Roman culture; even back then, it was a decline from something deeper and more noble. The Germans are mistaken to resist that deeper culture.[Pg 134]
42
Everything classic was thoroughly cultivated by Charles the Great, whilst he combated everything heathen with the severest possible measures of coercion. Ancient mythology was developed, but German mythology was treated as a crime. The feeling underlying all this, in my opinion, was that Christianity had already overcome the old religion · people no longer feared it, but availed themselves of the culture that rested upon it. But the old German gods were feared.
Everything classic was carefully nurtured by Charlemagne, while he aggressively fought against anything pagan. Ancient mythology was expanded, but German mythology was treated like a crime. In my view, the underlying sentiment was that Christianity had already triumphed over the old religion—people no longer feared it but took advantage of the culture that was built upon it. However, the old German gods were still feared.
A great superficiality in the conception of antiquity—little else than an appreciation of its formal accomplishments and its knowledge—must thereby have been brought about. We must find out the forces that stood in the way of increasing our insight into antiquity. First of all, the culture of antiquity is utilised as an incitement towards the acceptance of Christianity · it became, as it were, the premium for conversion, the gilt with which the poisonous pill was coated before being swallowed. Secondly, the help of ancient culture was found to be necessary as a weapon for the intellectual protection of Christianity. Even the Reformation could not dispense with classical studies for this purpose.
A huge superficiality in how we understand ancient times—mostly just an appreciation of its formal achievements and knowledge—must have developed as a result. We need to uncover the factors that hindered our deeper understanding of antiquity. First, ancient culture was used to encourage the acceptance of Christianity; it became like a reward for conversion, the shiny coating on a bitter pill before being swallowed. Second, ancient culture was seen as necessary for safeguarding Christianity intellectually. Even the Reformation relied on classical studies for this reason.
The Renaissance, on the other hand, now begins, with a clearer sense of classical studies, which, however, are likewise looked upon from an anti-Christian standpoint: the Renaissance shows an awakening of honesty in the south, like the Reformation in the north. They could not but clash; for a sincere leaning towards antiquity renders one unchristian.[Pg 135]
The Renaissance, on the other hand, begins now, with a clearer focus on classical studies, which are also viewed from an anti-Christian perspective: the Renaissance brings about a revival of honesty in the south, similar to the Reformation in the north. They were bound to conflict because a genuine appreciation for antiquity makes one un-Christian.[Pg 135]
On the whole, however, the Church succeeded in turning classical studies into a harmless direction . the philologist was invented, representing a type of learned man who was at the same time a priest or something similar. Even in the period of the Reformation people succeeded in emasculating scholarship. It is on this account that Friedrich August Wolf is noteworthy he freed his profession from the bonds of theology. This action of his, however, was not fully understood; for an aggressive, active element, such as was manifested by the poet-philologists of the Renaissance, was not developed. The freedom obtained benefited science, but not man.
Overall, the Church managed to steer classical studies in a less threatening direction. The concept of the philologist emerged, representing a type of educated individual who was also a priest or something similar. Even during the Reformation, people managed to weaken academic pursuits. This makes Friedrich August Wolf significant; he liberated his field from the constraints of theology. However, this move wasn't entirely grasped, as there was no strong, dynamic element like the poet-philologists of the Renaissance. The freedom achieved helped academia, but not humanity.
43
It is true that both humanism and rationalism have brought antiquity into the field as an ally; and it is therefore quite comprehensible that the opponents of humanism should direct their attacks against antiquity also. Antiquity, however, has been misunderstood and falsified by humanism · it must rather be considered as a testimony against humanism, against the benign nature of man, &c. The opponents of humanism are wrong to combat antiquity as well; for in antiquity they have a strong ally.
It’s true that both humanism and rationalism have brought the ideas of the past into their corner; so it's understandable that critics of humanism also target these ideas. However, the past has been misrepresented and distorted by humanism—it should actually be viewed as evidence against humanism, against the idea of man's inherently good nature, etc. Critics of humanism are mistaken to fight against the past too; because in the past, they have a powerful ally.
44
It is so difficult to understand the ancients. We must wait patiently until the spirit moves us. The human element which antiquity shows us must not be confused with humanitarianism. This contrast must be strongly emphasised: philology suffers by endeavouring to substitute the humanitarian,[Pg 136] young men are brought forward as students of philology in order that they may thereby become humanitarians. A good deal of history, in my opinion, is quite sufficient for that purpose. The brutal and self-conscious man will be humbled when he sees things and values changing to such an extent.
It's really hard to understand the ancients. We have to wait patiently until we're inspired. The human connections that history shows us shouldn’t be confused with humanitarianism. This difference needs to be emphasized: philology suffers when it tries to replace the humanitarian aspect,[Pg 136] young men are encouraged to study philology so they can become humanitarians. I believe a fair amount of history is enough for that. The harsh and self-aware person will feel humbled when they see values and perspectives changing so drastically.
The human element among the Greeks lies within a certain naiveté, through which man himself is to be seen—state, art, society, military and civil law, sexual relations, education, party. It is precisely the human element which may be seen everywhere and among all peoples, but among the Greeks it is seen in a state of nakedness and inhumanity which cannot be dispensed with for purposes of instruction. In addition to this, the Greeks have created the greatest number of individuals, and thus they give us so much insight into men,—a Greek cook is more of a cook than any other.
The human aspect of the Greeks is marked by a certain naiveté, through which we can understand humanity—its state, art, society, military and civil law, sexual relationships, education, and politics. This human element is present everywhere and among all people, but among the Greeks, it is displayed in a raw and brutal form that is essential for teaching. Furthermore, the Greeks have produced a remarkable number of individuals, giving us deep insights into human nature— a Greek cook is more of a cook than anyone else.
45
I deplore a system of education which does not enable people to understand Wagner, and as the result of which Schopenhauer sounds harsh and discordant in our ears . such a system of education has missed its aim.
I regret an education system that doesn't help people understand Wagner, making Schopenhauer seem harsh and dissonant to us. Such an education system has failed its purpose.
46
(The Final Draft of Chapter One.)
Il faut dire la vérité et s'immoler—Voltaire.
Il faut dire la vérité et se sacrifier—Voltaire.
Let us suppose that there were freer and more superior spirits who were dissatisfied with the education now in vogue, and that they summoned it to their tribunal, what would the defendant say to[Pg 137] them? In all probability something like this: "Whether you have a right to summon anyone here or not, I am at all events not the proper person to be called. It is my educators to whom you should apply. It is their duty to defend me, and I have a right to keep silent. I am merely what they have made me."
Let’s assume there are more liberated and superior minds who are unhappy with the current education system, and they call it to account. What would the defendant say to[Pg 137] them? Probably something like this: “Whether you have the right to summon anyone here or not, I am definitely not the right person to be called. You should be addressing my educators. It’s their job to defend me, and I have the right to remain silent. I am simply a product of their teachings.”
These educators would now be hauled before the tribunal, and among them an entire profession would be observed · the philologists. This profession consists in the first place of those men who make use of their knowledge of Greek and Roman antiquity to bring up youths of thirteen to twenty years of age, and secondly of those men whose task it is to train specially-gifted pupils to act as future teachers—i.e., as the educators of educators. Philologists of the first type are teachers at the public schools, those of the second are professors at the universities.
These educators would now be brought before the tribunal, and among them would be an entire profession: the philologists. This profession primarily includes those individuals who use their knowledge of Greek and Roman history to educate youths aged thirteen to twenty, and secondly, it includes those who train particularly gifted students to become future teachers—i.e., the educators of educators. The first group of philologists are teachers at public schools, while the second group are professors at universities.
The first-named philologists are entrusted with the care of certain specially-chosen youths, those who, early in life, show signs of talent and a sense of what is noble, and whose parents are prepared to allow plenty of time and money for their education. If other boys, who do not fulfil these three conditions, are presented to the teachers, the teachers have the right to refuse them. Those forming the second class, the university professors, receive the young men who feel themselves fitted for the highest and most responsible of callings, that of teachers and moulders of mankind; and these professors, too, may refuse to have anything to do with young men who are not adequately equipped or gifted for the task.[Pg 138]
The first group of language experts is responsible for guiding a select group of talented young people who, from an early age, demonstrate promise and a sense of honor, and whose parents are willing to invest significant time and resources into their education. If other boys, who do not meet these three criteria, are presented to the educators, the educators have the right to decline them. The second group, the university professors, takes on young men who believe they are suited for the highest and most significant professions, that of teachers and shapers of society; these professors, too, have the right to refuse to engage with young men who are not properly prepared or talented for the role.[Pg 138]
If, then, the educational system of a period is condemned, a heavy censure on philologists is thereby implied: either, as the consequence of their wrong-headed view, they insist on giving bad education in the belief that it is good; or they do not wish to give this bad education, but are unable to carry the day in favour of education which they recognise to be better. In other words, their fault is either due to their lack of insight or to their lack of will. In answer to the first charge they would say that they knew no better, and in answer to the second that they could do no better. As, however, these philologists bring up their pupils chiefly with the aid of Greek and Roman antiquity, their want of insight in the first case may be attributed to the fact that they do not understand antiquity, and again to the fact that they bring forward antiquity into the present age as if it were the most important of all aids to instruction, while antiquity, generally speaking, does not assist in training, or at all events no longer does so.
If the educational system of a certain time is criticized, it also reflects poorly on philologists. This implies that either, because of their misguided views, they are giving poor education while thinking it's good, or they don't want to provide this poor education but can't win support for the better education they know exists. In other words, their problem is either a lack of understanding or a lack of motivation. In response to the first accusation, they might say they didn't know any better, and to the second, they might claim they couldn't do any better. However, since these philologists primarily educate their students using Greek and Roman classics, their lack of understanding in the first case may stem from not truly grasping these ancient texts. Furthermore, they present antiquity as if it were the most valuable tool for teaching, even though, generally speaking, it doesn't effectively train students anymore, or at least not in the same way.
On the other hand, if we reproach our professors with their lack of will, they would be quite right in attributing educational significance and power to antiquity; but they themselves could not be said to be the proper instruments by means of which antiquity could exhibit such power. In other words, the professors would not be real teachers and would be living under false colours, but how, then, could they have reached such an irregular position? Through a misunderstanding of themselves and their qualifications. In order, then, that we may ascribe to philologists their share in this bad educational system of the present time, we may sum up the different[Pg 139] factors of their innocence and guilt in the following sentence: the philologist, if he wishes for a verdict of acquittal, must understand three things antiquity, the present time, and himself · his fault lies in the fact that he either does not understand antiquity, or the present time, or himself.
On the flip side, if we criticize our professors for their lack of will, they would be justified in pointing to the influence and importance of the past; however, it wouldn't be accurate to say that they are the right tools for showcasing that influence. In other words, the professors wouldn’t be genuine teachers and would be living under false pretenses, but how did they end up in such a questionable position? It stems from a misunderstanding of themselves and their capabilities. To give philologists their due share of blame in this flawed educational system today, we can summarize the various[Pg 139] factors of their innocence and guilt in this way: a philologist seeking to be exonerated must comprehend three things—antiquity, the present, and themselves. Their shortcoming lies in their inability to fully grasp either antiquity, the present, or themselves.
47
It is not true to say that we can attain culture through antiquity alone. We may learn something from it, certainly; but not culture as the word is now understood. Our present culture is based on an emasculated and mendacious study of antiquity. In order to understand how ineffectual this study is, just look at our philologists · they, trained upon antiquity, should be the most cultured men. Are they?
It’s not accurate to say that we can achieve culture solely through ancient times. We can definitely learn something from it, but not culture in the way we understand it today. Our current culture relies on a diluted and dishonest study of the past. To see how ineffective this study is, just look at our philologists—they’re trained in ancient texts and should be the most cultured individuals. Are they?
48
Origin of the philologist. When a great work of art is exhibited there is always some one who not only feels its influence but wishes to perpetuate it. The same remark applies to a great state—to everything, in short, that man produces. Philologists wish to perpetuate the influence of antiquity and they can set about it only as imitative artists. Why not as men who form their lives after antiquity?
Origin of the philologist. When a great piece of art is displayed, there’s always someone who feels its impact and wants to keep that influence alive. The same can be said for a great nation—and really, for everything that humans create. Philologists want to preserve the influence of the past, and they can only do this as artists who imitate. But why not as individuals who shape their lives based on the past?
49
The decline of the poet-scholars is due in great part to their own corruption: their type is continually arising again; Goethe and Leopardi, for example, belong to it. Behind them plod the philologist-savants. This type has its origin in the sophisticism of the second century.[Pg 140]
The decline of the poet-scholars is largely due to their own corruption: this type keeps reappearing; Goethe and Leopardi, for instance, are part of it. Behind them follow the philologist-scholars. This type has its roots in the sophistry of the second century.[Pg 140]
50
Ah, it is a sad story, the story of philology! The disgusting erudition, the lazy, inactive passivity, the timid submission.—Who was ever free?
Ah, it’s a sad tale, the tale of philology! The awful knowledge, the lazy, inactive passivity, the fearful submission.—Who has ever been truly free?
51
When we examine the history of philology it is borne in upon us how few really talented men have taken part in it. Among the most celebrated philologists are a few who ruined their intellect by acquiring a smattering of many subjects, and among the most enlightened of them were several who could use their intellect only for childish tasks. It is a sad story · no science, I think, has ever been so poor in talented followers. Those whom we might call the intellectually crippled found a suitable hobby in all this hair-splitting.
When we look at the history of philology, it becomes clear how few truly talented people have been involved in it. Among the most famous philologists are some who damaged their intellect by dabbling in too many topics, and among the most insightful of them were several who could only apply their minds to trivial tasks. It's a disappointing tale—no science, in my opinion, has ever had so few talented followers. Those we could describe as intellectually limited found a fitting pastime in all this nitpicking.
52
The teacher of reading and writing, and the reviser, were the first types of the philologist.
The reading and writing teacher, along with the editor, were the first examples of a philologist.
53
Friedrich August Wolf reminds us how apprehensive and feeble were the first steps taken by our ancestors in moulding scholarship—how even the Latin classics, for example, had to be smuggled into the university market under all sorts of pretexts, as if they had been contraband goods. In the "Gottingen Lexicon" of 1737, J. M. Gesner tells us of the Odes of Horace: "ut imprimis, quid prodesse in severioribus studiis possint, ostendat."[Pg 141]
Friedrich August Wolf highlights how anxious and weakly the first steps taken by our ancestors to shape scholarship really were—how even the Latin classics had to be sneaked into the university scene under various pretenses, as if they were illegal items. In the "Gottingen Lexicon" of 1737, J. M. Gesner mentions the Odes of Horace: "to show primarily what benefit in more serious studies they can provide."[Pg 141]
54
I was pleased to read of Bentley "non tam grande pretium emendatiunculis meis statuere soleo, ut singularem aliquam gratiam inde sperem aut exigam."
I was pleased to read that Bentley "does not usually set such a high price on my small corrections that I hope or expect to gain any special favor from it."
Newton was surprised that men like Bentley and Hare should quarrel about a book of ancient comedies, since they were both theological dignitaries.
Newton was surprised that people like Bentley and Hare would argue over a book of ancient comedies, especially since they were both religious leaders.
55
Horace was summoned by Bentley as before a judgment seat, the authority of which he would have been the first to repudiate. The admiration which a discriminating man acquires as a philologist is in proportion to the rarity of the discrimination to be found in philologists. Bentley's treatment of Horace has something of the schoolmaster about it It would appear at first sight as if Horace himself were not the object of discussion, but rather the various scribes and commentators who have handed down the text: in reality, however, it is actually Horace who is being dealt with. It is my firm conviction that to have written a single line which is deemed worthy of being commented upon by scholars of a later time, far outweighs the merits of the greatest critic. There is a profound modesty about philologists. The improving of texts is an entertaining piece of work for scholars, it is a kind of riddle-solving; but it should not be looked upon as a very important task. It would be an argument against antiquity if it should speak less clearly to us because a million words stood in the way![Pg 142]
Horace was summoned by Bentley as if he were standing before a judge, an authority that he would have been the first to reject. The admiration that an insightful person gains as a linguist depends on how rare such insight is among linguists. Bentley's approach to Horace has a bit of a schoolmaster vibe. It might seem at first that Horace himself isn’t the main focus, but rather the various scribes and commentators who have passed down the text; in truth, however, it’s actually Horace who is the topic of discussion. I truly believe that writing just one line that future scholars find worthy of commentary is far more impressive than the achievements of the greatest critic. There’s a genuine humility among linguists. Improving texts is an enjoyable challenge for scholars; it’s like solving a puzzle. But it shouldn't be seen as a particularly significant task. It would be a bad sign for the past if it communicated less clearly to us because of a million words standing in the way![Pg 142]
56
A school-teacher said to Bentley, "Sir, I will make your grandchild as great a scholar as you are yourself." "How can you do that," replied Bentley, "when I have forgotten more than you ever knew?"
A school teacher said to Bentley, "Sir, I will make your grandchild as great a scholar as you are." "How can you do that," Bentley replied, "when I've forgotten more than you'll ever know?"
57
Bentley's clever daughter Joanna once lamented to her father that he had devoted his time and talents to the criticism of the works of others instead of writing something original. Bentley remained silent for some time as if he were turning the matter over in his mind. At last he said that her remark was quite right; he himself felt that he might have directed his gifts in some other channel. Earlier in life, nevertheless, he had done something for the glory of God and the improvement of his fellow-men (referring to his "Confutation of Atheism"), but afterwards the genius of the pagans had attracted him, and, despairing of attaining their level in any other way, he had mounted upon their shoulders so that he might thus be able to look over their heads.
Bentley’s clever daughter Joanna once told her father that he had spent his time and skills critiquing the works of others instead of creating something original himself. Bentley was quiet for a while, as if he was considering her words. Finally, he acknowledged that she was completely right; he recognized that he could have channeled his talents in a different direction. However, earlier in his life, he had contributed something for the glory of God and the betterment of his fellow humans (referring to his "Confutation of Atheism"), but later, he found himself drawn to the genius of the ancients and, feeling hopeless about reaching their level in any other way, he chose to stand on their shoulders to gain a better perspective.
58
Bentley, says Wolf, both as man of letters and individual, was misunderstood and persecuted during the greater part of his life, or else praised maliciously.
Bentley, according to Wolf, both as a writer and a person, was misunderstood and mistreated for most of his life, or alternatively, falsely praised.
Markland, towards the end of his life—as was the case with so many others like him—became imbued with a repugnance for all scholarly reputation, to such an extent, indeed, that he partly tore[Pg 143] up and partly burnt several works which he had long had in hand.
Markland, near the end of his life—like many others—developed a strong dislike for academic recognition. In fact, he went so far as to partly tear[Pg 143] up and partly burn several works he had been working on for a long time.
Wolf says: "The amount of intellectual food that can be got from well-digested scholarship is a very insignificant item."
Wolf says: "The amount of knowledge you can get from solid scholarship is really a small thing."
In Winckelmann's youth there were no philological studies apart from the ordinary bread-winning branches of the science—people read and explained the ancients in order to prepare themselves for the better interpretation of the Bible and the Corpus Juris.
In Winckelmann's youth, there were no philological studies besides the usual practical subjects—people read and interpreted the classics to improve their understanding of the Bible and the Corpus Juris.
59
In Wolf's estimation, a man has reached the highest point of historical research when he is able to take a wide and general view of the whole and of the profoundly conceived distinctions in the developments in art and the different styles of art. Wolf acknowledges, however, that Winckelmann was lacking in the more common talent of philological criticism, or else he could not use it properly: "A rare mixture of a cool head and a minute and restless solicitude for hundreds of things which, insignificant in themselves, were combined in his case with a fire that swallowed up those little things, and with a gift of divination which is a vexation and an annoyance to the uninitiated."
In Wolf's view, a person has truly mastered historical research when they can take a broad and comprehensive perspective on everything and understand the significant distinctions in the evolution of art and its various styles. However, Wolf points out that Winckelmann lacked the more common skill of philological criticism, or he couldn't apply it effectively: "A rare blend of a clear mind and a constant, restless concern for countless details that, while trivial on their own, were in his case combined with a passion that overwhelmed those minor details, along with an intuitive insight that frustrates and irritates those who are inexperienced."
60
Wolf draws our attention to the fact that antiquity was acquainted only with theories of oratory and poetry which facilitated production, τἑχναι and artes that formed real orators and poets, "while at the present day we shall soon have theories upon[Pg 144] which it would be as impossible to build up a speech or a poem as it would be to form a thunderstorm upon a brontological treatise."
Wolf highlights that in ancient times, people only understood theories of oratory and poetry that helped create real orators and poets, "while today, we are quickly getting theories upon[Pg 144] that make it just as impossible to construct a speech or a poem as it would be to generate a thunderstorm from a brontological paper."
61
Wolf's judgment on the amateurs of philological knowledge is noteworthy: "If they found themselves provided by nature with a mind corresponding to that of the ancients, or if they were capable of adapting themselves to other points of view and other circumstances of life, then, with even a nodding acquaintance with the best writers, they certainly acquired more from those vigorous natures, those splendid examples of thinking and acting, than most of those did who during their whole life merely offered themselves to them as interpreters."
Wolf's opinion on the amateur philologists is striking: "If they had a natural mindset similar to that of the ancients, or if they could adapt to different perspectives and life situations, then, with just a basic familiarity with the best writers, they definitely gained more from those strong personalities, those remarkable examples of thought and action, than most who spent their entire lives simply serving as their interpreters."
62
Says Wolf again · "In the end, only those few ought to attain really complete knowledge who are born with artistic talent and furnished with scholarship, and who make use of the best opportunities of securing, both theoretically and practically, the necessary technical knowledge" True!
Says Wolf again · "In the end, only a few should really gain complete knowledge, those who are born with artistic talent and have academic training, and who take advantage of the best opportunities to secure the necessary technical knowledge, both in theory and practice." True!
63
Instead of forming our students on the Latin models I recommend the Greek, especially Demosthenes · simplicity! This may be seen by a reference to Leopardi, who is perhaps the greatest stylist of the century.
Instead of shaping our students on the Latin models, I suggest using the Greek ones, especially Demosthenes' simplicity! This can be shown by looking at Leopardi, who is arguably the greatest stylist of this century.
64
"Classical education" · what do people see in it? Something that is useless beyond rendering a period[Pg 145] of military service unnecessary and securing a degree![5]
"Classical education" — what do people find appealing about it? Something that only serves to make long military service unnecessary and to earn a degree![5]
65
When I observe how all countries are now promoting the advancement of classical literature I say to myself, "How harmless it must be!" and then, "How useful it must be!" It brings these countries the reputation of promoting "free culture." In order that this "freedom" may be rightly estimated, just look at the philologists!
When I see how all countries are now pushing for the promotion of classical literature, I think to myself, "How harmless it must be!" and then, "How beneficial it must be!" It gives these countries a reputation for supporting "free culture." To truly understand this "freedom," just take a look at the linguists!
66
Classical education! Yea, if there were only as much paganism as Goethe found and glorified in Winckelmann, even that would not be much. Now, however, that the lying Christendom of our time has taken hold of it, the thing becomes overpowering, and I cannot help expressing my disgust on the point—People firmly believe in witchcraft where this "classical education" is concerned. They, however, who possess the greatest knowledge of antiquity should likewise possess the greatest amount of culture, viz., our philologists; but what is classical about them?
Classical education! Yeah, if there was as much paganism as Goethe found and celebrated in Winckelmann, even that wouldn't be much. However, now that the false Christianity of our time has taken over, it becomes overwhelming, and I can't help but express my disgust about it—People genuinely believe in witchcraft when it comes to this "classical education." Those who have the most knowledge of antiquity should also have the highest level of culture, specifically our philologists; but what’s really classical about them?
67
Classical philology is the basis of the most shallow rationalism always having been dishonestly applied, it has gradually become quite ineffective. Its effect is one more illusion of the modern man. Philologists are nothing but a guild of sky-pilots who are[Pg 146] not known as such · this is why the State takes an interest in them. The utility of classical education is completely used up, whilst, for example, the history of Christianity still shows its power.
Classical philology is the foundation of a superficial rationalism that has always been misused, and as a result, it has become largely ineffective. Its impact is just another illusion of modern society. Philologists are essentially a group of intellectuals not recognized as such, which is why the State pays attention to them. The value of classical education has been fully exhausted, while, for instance, the history of Christianity still proves to be influential.
68
Philologists, when discussing their science, never get down to the root of the subject . they never set forth philology itself as a problem. Bad conscience? or merely thoughtlessness?
Philologists, when talking about their field, never really get to the heart of the matter. They never present philology itself as an issue. Is it guilt? Or just a lack of awareness?
69
We learn nothing from what philologists say about philology: it is all mere tittle-tattle—for example, Jahn's[6] "The Meaning and Place of the Study of Antiquity in Germany." There is no feeling for what should be protected and defended: thus speak people who have not even thought of the possibility that any one could attack them.
We don’t gain any insights from what linguists say about linguistics; it’s all just chatter—for instance, Jahn's[6] "The Meaning and Place of the Study of Antiquity in Germany." There’s no sense of what needs to be safeguarded and defended: this is how people talk who haven’t even considered that anyone might challenge them.
70
Philologists are people who exploit the vaguely-felt dissatisfaction of modern man, and his desire for "something better," in order that they may earn their bread and butter.
Philologists are individuals who take advantage of the subtle dissatisfaction of modern people and their yearning for "something better" to make a living.
I know them—I myself am one of them.
I know them—I’m one of them.
71
Our philologists stand in the same relation to true educators as the medicine-men of the wild Indians do to true physicians What astonishment will be felt by a later age![Pg 147]
Our language experts are to genuine educators what shamans of Native American tribes are to real doctors. Future generations will be amazed![Pg 147]
72
What they lack is a real taste for the strong and powerful characteristics of the ancients. They turn into mere panegyrists, and thus become ridiculous.
What they lack is a genuine appreciation for the strong and powerful traits of the ancients. They become nothing more than flattering admirers, making themselves look foolish.
73
They have forgotten how to address other men; and, as they cannot speak to the older people, they cannot do so to the young.
They’ve forgotten how to talk to other men; and since they can’t speak to older people, they also can’t talk to the young.
74
When we bring the Greeks to the knowledge of our young students, we are treating the latter as if they were well-informed and matured men. What, indeed, is there about the Greeks and their ways which is suitable for the young? In the end we shall find that we can do nothing for them beyond giving them isolated details. Are these observations for young people? What we actually do, however, is to introduce our young scholars to the collective wisdom of antiquity. Or do we not? The reading of the ancients is emphasised in this way.
When we introduce the Greeks to our young students, we're treating them as if they were knowledgeable and mature individuals. What is it about the Greeks and their culture that is appropriate for the young? Ultimately, we will discover that all we can provide them with are disconnected facts. Are these insights meant for young people? What we're really doing is connecting our young scholars to the collective knowledge of the past. Or are we not? This is how we highlight the importance of reading the ancients.
My belief is that we are forced to concern ourselves with antiquity at a wrong period of our lives. At the end of the twenties its meaning begins to dawn on one.
My belief is that we're made to think about the past at the wrong time in our lives. By the end of our twenties, its significance starts to become clear.
75
There is something disrespectful about the way in which we make our young students known to the ancients: what is worse, it is unpedagogical; or what can result from a mere acquaintance with[Pg 148] things which a youth cannot consciously esteem! Perhaps he must learn to "believe" and this is why I object to it.
There’s something disrespectful about how we introduce our young students to ancient knowledge: even worse, it’s not educational; or what can come from a superficial understanding of[Pg 148] things that a young person can’t truly value! Maybe they need to learn to "believe" and that’s why I have a problem with it.
76
There are matters regarding which antiquity instructs us, and about which I should hardly care to express myself publicly.
There are issues from the past that teach us, and I would prefer not to discuss them openly.
77
All the difficulties of historical study to be elucidated by great examples.
All the challenges of studying history can be clarified through significant examples.
Why our young students are not suited to the Greeks.
Why our young students aren't suited to the Greeks.
The consequences of philology.
The impact of philology.
Arrogant expectation.
Culture-philistinism.
Superficiality.
Too high an esteem for reading and writing.
Estrangement from the nation and its needs.Overconfidence in expectations.
Lack of cultural awareness.
Superficiality.
An exaggerated importance given to reading and writing.
Alienation from the country and its needs.
The philologists themselves, the historians, philosophers, and jurists all end in smoke.
The linguists, historians, philosophers, and legal experts all come to nothing.
Our young students should be brought into contact with real sciences.
Our young students should be exposed to real science.
Likewise with real art.
Same goes for real art.
In consequence, when they grew older, a desire for real history would be shown.
In time, as they got older, a desire for real history would emerge.
78
Inhumanity: even in the "Antigone," even in Goethe's "Iphigenia."
Inhumanity: even in "Antigone," even in Goethe's "Iphigenia."
The want of "rationalism" in the Greeks.
The lack of "rationalism" in the Greeks.
Young people cannot understand the political affairs of antiquity.
Young people can’t grasp the political issues of the past.
79
Do the philologists know the present time? Their judgments on it as Periclean, their mistaken judgments when they speak of Freytag's[7] genius as resembling that of Homer, and so on; their following in the lead of the littérateurs, their abandonment of the pagan sense, which was exactly the classical element that Goethe discovered in Winckelmann.
Do the language experts understand the current times? Their opinions about it being Periclean, and their incorrect views when they compare Freytag's[7] genius to Homer's, and so on; their tendency to follow the writers, their disregard for the pagan perspective, which was precisely the classical aspect that Goethe found in Winckelmann.
80
The condition of the philologists may be seen by their indifference at the appearance of Wagner. They should have learnt even more through him than through Goethe, and they did not even glance in his direction. That shows that they are not actuated by any strong need, or else they would have an instinct to tell them where their food was to be found.
The situation of the language scholars is evident in their lack of interest when Wagner emerged. They should have taken away even more from him than from Goethe, yet they didn’t even look his way. This indicates that they aren’t driven by any strong desire; otherwise, they would instinctively know where to find what they needed.
81
Wagner prizes his art too highly to go and sit in a corner with it, like Schumann. He either surrenders himself to the public ("Rienzi") or he makes the public surrender itself to him. He educates it up to his music. Minor artists, too, want their public, but they try to get it by inartistic means, such as through the Press, Hanslick,[8] &c.
Wagner values his art too much to hide away with it, like Schumann. He either opens himself up to the audience ("Rienzi") or makes the audience embrace him. He elevates their understanding to match his music. Lesser artists also seek an audience, but they attempt to gain it through unartistic methods, like using the Press, Hanslick,[8] & etc.
82
Wagner perfected the inner fancy of man . later generations will see a renaissance in sculpture. Poetry must precede the plastic art.[Pg 150]
Wagner refined the inner imagination of humanity. Future generations will witness a revival in sculpture. Poetry must come before the visual arts.[Pg 150]
83
I observe in philologists ·
I notice in linguists
1. Want of respect for antiquity.
1. Lack of respect for old traditions.
2. Tenderness and flowery oratory; even an apologetic tone.
2. Softness and flowery speech; even a sorry tone.
3. Simplicity in their historical comments.
3. Simplicity in their historical remarks.
4. Self-conceit.
4. Arrogance.
5. Under-estimation of the talented philologists.
Underestimating skilled linguists.
84
Philologists appear to me to be a secret society who wish to train our youth by means of the culture of antiquity · I could well understand this society and their views being criticised from all sides. A great deal would depend upon knowing what these philologists understood by the term "culture of antiquity"—If I saw, for example, that they were training their pupils against German philosophy and German music, I should either set about combating them or combating the culture of antiquity, perhaps the former, by showing that these philologists had not understood the culture of antiquity. Now I observe:
Philologists seem to me like a secret society trying to educate our youth through the culture of the past. I can totally see why this group and their ideas would face criticism from all sides. It would really depend on what these philologists mean by "culture of antiquity." If I saw, for instance, that they were teaching their students to reject German philosophy and German music, I would either start fighting against them or against the culture of antiquity, probably the former, by demonstrating that these philologists misunderstood the culture of antiquity. Now I notice:
1. A great indecision in the valuation of the culture of antiquity on the part of philologists.
1. A significant uncertainty among philologists regarding the value of ancient culture.
2. Something very non-ancient in themselves; something non-free.
2. Something very modern in itself; something not free.
3. Want of clearness in regard to the particular type of ancient culture they mean.
3. Lack of clarity about the specific type of ancient culture they are referring to.
4. Want of judgment in their methods of instruction, e.g., scholarship.
4. Poor judgment in their teaching methods, e.g., academic performance.
5. Classical education is served out mixed up with Christianity.[Pg 151]
5. Classical education is blended with Christianity.[Pg 151]
85
It is now no longer a matter of surprise to me that, with such teachers, the education of our time should be worthless. I can never avoid depicting this want of education in its true colours, especially in regard to those things which ought to be learnt from antiquity if possible, for example, writing, speaking, and so on.
It’s no longer surprising to me that, with teachers like these, our education today is essentially worthless. I can't help but highlight this lack of education for what it really is, particularly when it comes to the subjects we should ideally be learning from the past, like writing, speaking, and so on.
86
The transmission of the emotions is hereditary: let that be recollected when we observe the effect of the Greeks upon philologists.
The passing down of emotions is hereditary: let's keep that in mind when we notice the impact of the Greeks on language scholars.
87
Even in the best of cases, philologists seek for no more than mere "rationalism" and Alexandrian culture—not Hellenism.
Even in the best situations, philologists aim for nothing more than simple "rationalism" and Alexandrian culture—not true Hellenism.
88
Very little can be gained by mere diligence, if the head is dull. Philologist after philologist has swooped down on Homer in the mistaken belief that something of him can be obtained by force. Antiquity speaks to us when it feels a desire to do so, not when we do.
Very little can be achieved through hard work alone if you're not sharp. Scholar after scholar has rushed to tackle Homer, wrongly thinking they can get something from him by sheer effort. The past communicates with us when it chooses to, not when we want it to.
89
The inherited characteristic of our present-day philologists · a certain sterility of insight has resulted, for they promote the science, but not the philologist.[Pg 152]
The inherited trait of today’s linguists—a certain lack of meaningful insight—has led to a situation where they advance the science but not the linguist.[Pg 152]
90
The following is one way of carrying on classical studies, and a frequent one: a man throws himself thoughtlessly, or is thrown, into some special branch or other, whence he looks to the right and left and sees a great deal that is good and new. Then, in some unguarded moment, he asks himself: "But what the devil has all this to do with me?" In the meantime he has grown old and has become accustomed to it all; and therefore he continues in his rut—just as in the case of marriage.
The following is one way of pursuing classical studies, and it's a common one: a person dives in without much thought, or is pushed into a specific area, where they look around and notice a lot that is good and new. Then, in a moment of reflection, they ask themselves: "But what does all this have to do with me?" Meanwhile, they've gotten older and have grown used to everything; so they keep going in the same routine—just like in marriage.
91
In connection with the training of the modern philologist the influence of the science of linguistics should be mentioned and judged; a philologist should rather turn aside from it . the question of the early beginnings of the Greeks and Romans should be nothing to him . how can they spoil their own subject in such a way?
In relation to the training of today’s philologist, it's important to acknowledge the impact of linguistics; however, a philologist should avoid it. The issue of the early beginnings of the Greeks and Romans shouldn't matter to him. How can they ruin their own field like that?
92
A morbid passion often makes its appearance from time to time in connection with the oppressive uncertainty of divination, a passion for believing and feeling sure at all costs: for example, when dealing with Aristotle, or in the discovery of magic numbers, which, in Lachmann's case, is almost an illness.
A dark fascination often shows up occasionally in relation to the heavy uncertainty of fortune-telling, a desire to believe and be certain at any cost: for instance, when dealing with Aristotle, or in the quest for magical numbers, which, in Lachmann's situation, is nearly a sickness.
93
The consistency which is prized in a savant is pedantry if applied to the Greeks.[Pg 153]
The consistency that people admire in a genius is just being overly concerned with details when it comes to the Greeks.[Pg 153]
94
(The Greeks and the Linguists.)
The Greeks. | The Linguists are · |
render homage to beauty, develop the body, speak clearly, are religious transfigurers of everyday occurrences, are listeners and observers, have an aptitude for the symbolical, are in full possession of their freedom as men, can look innocently out into the world, are the pessimists of thought. |
babblers and triflers, ugly-looking creatures, stammerers, filthy pedants, quibblers and scarecrows, unfitted for the symbolical, ardent slaves of the State, Christians in disguise, philistines. |
95
Bergk's "History of Literature": Not a spark of Greek fire or Greek sense.
Bergk's "History of Literature": Not a trace of Greek brilliance or Greek reasoning.
96
People really do compare our own age with that of Pericles, and congratulate themselves on the reawakening of the feeling of patriotism: I remember a parody on the funeral oration of Pericles by G. Freytag,[9] in which this prim and strait-laced "poet" depicted the happiness now experienced by sixty-year-old men.—All pure and simple carica[Pg 154]ture! So this is the result! And sorrow and irony and seclusion are all that remain for him who has seen more of antiquity than this.
People actually compare our current era to that of Pericles and congratulate themselves on the revival of patriotic feelings. I remember a parody of Pericles' funeral oration by G. Freytag,[9] where this uptight "poet" portrayed the joy experienced by sixty-year-old men. It’s all just pure and simple caricature! So this is the outcome! All that’s left for someone who's explored more of the past than this is sorrow, irony, and isolation.
97
If we change a single word of Lord Bacon's we may say . infimarum Græcorum virtutum apud philologos laus est, mediarum admiratio, supremarum sensus nullus.
If we change even one word of Lord Bacon's, we might say . infimarum Græcorum virtutum apud philologos laus est, mediarum admiratio, supremarum sensus nullus.
98
How can anyone glorify and venerate a whole people! It is the individuals that count, even in the case of the Greeks.
How can anyone glorify and worship an entire people? It’s the individuals that matter, even when it comes to the Greeks.
99
There is a great deal of caricature even about the Greeks · for example, the careful attention devoted by the Cynics to their own happiness.
There are a lot of stereotypes about the Greeks; for example, the focused effort that the Cynics put into their own happiness.
100
The only thing that interests me is the relationship of the people considered as a whole to the training of the single individuals · and in the case of the Greeks there are some factors which are very favourable to the development of the individual. They do not, however, arise from the goodwill of the people, but from the struggle between the evil instincts.
The only thing that interests me is how people as a group relate to the development of individual members. In the case of the Greeks, there are several factors that greatly support individual growth. However, these factors don't come from the people's goodwill; they stem from the conflict between negative instincts.
By means of happy inventions and discoveries, we can train the individual differently and more highly than has yet been done by mere chance and accident. There are still hopes . the breeding of superior men.[Pg 155]
Through innovative inventions and discoveries, we can train individuals in a way that's better and more effective than what’s happened by mere chance so far. There’s still hope for cultivating exceptional people.[Pg 155]
101
The Greeks are interesting and quite disproportionately important because they had such a host of great individuals. How was that possible? This point must be studied.
The Greeks are fascinating and significantly important because they produced so many great individuals. How was that possible? This point needs to be explored.
102
The history of Greece has hitherto always been written optimistically.
The history of Greece has always been written with an optimistic perspective.
103
Selected points from antiquity: the power, fire, and swing of the feeling the ancients had for music (through the first Pythian Ode), purity in their historical sense, gratitude for the blessings of culture, the fire and corn feasts.
Selected points from antiquity: the power, passion, and energy the ancients had for music (through the first Pythian Ode), a clear understanding of their history, appreciation for the gifts of culture, and the celebrations of fire and harvest.
The ennoblement of jealousy: the Greeks the most jealous nation.
The elevation of jealousy: the Greeks are the most jealous nation.
Suicide, hatred of old age, of penury. Empedocles on sexual love.
Suicide, dislike of aging, of poverty. Empedocles on romantic love.
104
Nimble and healthy bodies, a clear and deep sense for the observation of everyday matters, manly freedom, belief in good racial descent and good upbringing, warlike virtues, jealousy in the ἁριστεὑειν, delight in the arts, respect for leisure, a sense for free individuality, for the symbolical.
Nimble and healthy bodies, a clear and deep understanding of everyday matters, strong freedom, belief in good heritage and upbringing, warrior-like qualities, a competitive spirit, enjoyment of the arts, respect for leisure, an appreciation for individuality, and an appreciation for the symbolic.
105
The spiritual culture of Greece an aberration of the amazing political impulse towards ἁριστεὑειν. The πὁλις utterly opposed to new education; culture nevertheless existed.[Pg 156]
The spiritual culture of Greece was a deviation from the incredible political drive toward excellence. The city-state was completely against new education; culture still managed to thrive.[Pg 156]
106
When I say that, all things considered, the Greeks were more moral than modern men what do I mean by that? From what we can perceive of the activities of their soul, it is clear that they had no shame, they had no bad conscience. They were more sincere, open-hearted, and passionate, as artists are; they exhibited a kind of child-like naiveté. It thus came about that even in all their evil actions they had a dash of purity about them, something approaching the holy. A remarkable number of individualities: might there not have been a higher morality in that? When we recollect that character develops slowly, what can it be that, in the long run, breeds individuality? Perhaps vanity, emulation? Possibly. Little inclination for conventional things.
When I say that, all things considered, the Greeks were more moral than modern people, what do I mean by that? From what we can see of the activities of their souls, it’s clear they had no shame and no bad conscience. They were more sincere, open-hearted, and passionate, like artists; they showed a kind of child-like naiveté. This led to the fact that even in all their evil actions, there was a touch of purity about them, something almost holy. A remarkable number of unique individuals: could there have been a higher morality in that? When we remember that character develops slowly, what is it that, in the end, fosters individuality? Maybe vanity, competition? Possibly. A little interest in conventional things.
107
The Greeks as the geniuses among the nations.
The Greeks were the geniuses among nations.
Their childlike nature, credulousness.
Their childlike nature, gullibility.
Passionate. Quite unconsciously they lived in such a way as to procreate genius. Enemies of shyness and dulness. Pain. Injudicious actions. The nature of their intuitive insight into misery, despite their bright and genial temperament. Profoundness in their apprehension and glorifying of everyday things (fire, agriculture). Mendacious, unhistorical. The significance of the πὁλις in culture instinctively recognised, favourable as a centre and periphery for great men (the facility of surveying a community, and also the possibility of addressing it as a whole). Individuality raised to the highest power through the πὁλις. Envy, jealousy, as among gifted people.[Pg 157]
Passionate. They unconsciously lived in a way that cultivated genius. They were against shyness and dullness. Pain. Poor choices. Their intuitive understanding of suffering was evident, even with their bright and cheerful personalities. They had a deep appreciation for and celebrated everyday things (like fire and farming). Dishonest, unhistorical. They recognized the importance of the city in culture, instinctively seeing it as a center and periphery for great people (the ease of observing a community, along with the chance to address it as a whole). Individuality pushed to its highest expression through the city. Envy and jealousy existed among gifted individuals.[Pg 157]
108
The Greeks were lacking in sobriety and caution. Over-sensibility, abnormally active condition of the brain and the nerves; impetuosity and fervour of the will.
The Greeks lacked sobriety and caution. They were overly sensitive, with an excessively active brain and nervous system; their will was marked by impulsiveness and passion.
109
"Invariably to see the general in the particular is the distinguishing characteristic of genius," says Schopenhauer. Think of Pindar, &c.—"Σωφροσὑιη," according to Schopenhauer, has its roots in the clearness with which the Greeks saw into themselves and into the world at large, and thence became conscious of themselves.
"Invariably, the ability to see the general in the specific is what sets genius apart," says Schopenhauer. Consider Pindar, etc.—"Σωφροσὑιη," according to Schopenhauer, stems from the clarity with which the Greeks understood themselves and the wider world, allowing them to become self-aware.
The "wide separation of will and intellect" indicates the genius, and is seen in the Greeks.
The "big gap between will and intellect" shows genius and can be observed in the Greeks.
"The melancholy associated with genius is due to the fact that the will to live, the more clearly it is illuminated by the contemplating intellect, appreciates all the more clearly the misery of its condition," says Schopenhauer. Cf. the Greeks.
"The sadness that comes with genius is because the desire to live, when it's examined closely by the thinking mind, understands the misery of its situation even better," says Schopenhauer. See. the Greeks.
110
The moderation of the Greeks in their sensual luxury, eating, and drinking, and their pleasure therein; the Olympic plays and their worship . that shows what they were.
The Greeks' moderation in their sensual pleasures, eating, and drinking, as well as their enjoyment of these things; the Olympic games and their worship—this reveals what they were like.
In the case of the genius, "the intellect will point out the faults which are seldom absent in an instrument that is put to a use for which it was not intended."
In the case of the genius, "the intellect will highlight the flaws that are rarely missing in a tool used for a purpose it wasn't designed for."
"The will is often left in the lurch at an awkward moment: hence genius, where real life is concerned,[Pg 158] is more or less unpractical—its behaviour often reminds us of madness."
"The will is often caught off guard at an uncomfortable moment: therefore, genius, when it comes to real life,[Pg 158] is pretty much impractical—its actions often make us think of madness."
111
We contrast the Romans, with their matter-of-fact earnestness, with the genial Greeks! Schopenhauer: "The stern, practical, earnest mode of life which the Romans called gravitas presupposes that the intellect does not forsake the service of the will in order to roam far off among things that have no connection with the will."
We compare the Romans, with their serious and straightforward attitude, to the friendly Greeks! Schopenhauer: "The serious, practical, and earnest way of life that the Romans referred to as gravitas implies that the mind stays focused on serving the will instead of wandering off into things that have no link to it."
112
It would have been much better if the Greeks had been conquered by the Persians instead of by the Romans.
It would have been much better if the Greeks had been conquered by the Persians instead of by the Romans.
113
The characteristics of the gifted man who is lacking in genius are to be found in the average Hellene—all the dangerous characteristics of such a disposition and character.
The traits of a gifted person who lacks true genius can be seen in the average Greek—all the risky traits that come with that kind of disposition and character.
114
Genius makes tributaries of all partly-talented people: hence the Persians themselves sent their ambassadors to the Greek oracles.
Genius draws in all those with even a little talent: that's why the Persians sent their ambassadors to the Greek oracles.
115
The happiest lot that can fall to the genius is to exchange doing and acting for leisure; and this was something the Greeks knew how to value. The blessings of labour! Nugari was the Roman name for all the exertions and aspirations of the Greeks.[Pg 159]
The best situation for a genius is to trade work and action for relaxation, and this is something the Greeks truly appreciated. The joys of hard work! Nugari was the Roman term for all the efforts and ambitions of the Greeks.[Pg 159]
No happy course of life is open to the genius, he stands in contradiction to his age and must perforce struggle with it. Thus the Greeks . they instinctively made the utmost exertions to secure a safe refuge for themselves (in the polis). Finally, everything went to pieces in politics. They were compelled to take up a stand against their enemies . this became ever more and more difficult, and at last impossible.
No happy life path is available to the genius; he inherently conflicts with his time and must struggle against it. Similarly, the Greeks instinctively made every effort to find a secure refuge for themselves in the polis. Eventually, everything fell apart politically. They had to take a stand against their enemies, which became increasingly difficult and ultimately impossible.
116
Greek culture is based on the lordship of a small class over four to nine times their number of slaves. Judged by mere numbers, Greece was a country inhabited by barbarians. How can the ancients be thought to be humane? There was a great contrast between the genius and the breadwinner, the half-beast of burden. The Greeks believed in a racial distinction. Schopenhauer wonders why Nature did not take it into her head to invent two entirely separate species of men.
Greek culture is built on the rule of a small elite over four to nine times their number of slaves. By sheer numbers, Greece was a land filled with barbarians. How can we consider the ancients to be humane? There was a significant contrast between the brilliant minds and the hardworking laborers, seen as half-beasts of burden. The Greeks held strong beliefs about racial differences. Schopenhauer questions why Nature didn't decide to create two completely separate species of humans.
The Greeks bear the same relation to the barbarians "as free-moving or winged animals do to the barnacles which cling tightly to the rocks and must await what fate chooses to send them"—Schopenhauer's simile.
The Greeks have the same relationship to the barbarians "as free-moving or flying animals do to the barnacles that cling tightly to the rocks and must wait for whatever fate decides to send them"—Schopenhauer's comparison.
117
The Greeks as the only people of genius in the history of the world. Such they are even when considered as learners; for they understand this best of all, and can do more than merely trim and adorn themselves with what they have borrowed, as did the Romans.[Pg 160]
The Greeks are the only truly genius people in the history of the world. They stand out even as learners; they grasp this better than anyone else and can do more than just embellish themselves with what they’ve borrowed, like the Romans did.[Pg 160]
The constitution of the polis is a Phœnician invention, even this has been imitated by the Hellenes. For a long time they dabbled in everything, like joyful dilettanti. Aphrodite is likewise Phœnician. Neither do they disavow what has come to them through immigration and does not originally belong to their own country.
The structure of the polis is a Phoenician invention, and even this has been copied by the Greeks. For a long time, they experimented with everything, like happy amateurs. Aphrodite is also Phoenician. They don't reject what has come to them through migration, even if it doesn't originally belong to their own land.
118
The happy and comfortable constitution of the politico-social position must not be sought among the Greeks . that is a goal which dazzles the eyes of our dreamers of the future! It was, on the contrary, dreadful; for this is a matter that must be judged according to the following standard: the more spirit, the more suffering (as the Greeks themselves prove). Whence it follows, the more stupidity, the more comfort. The philistine of culture is the most comfortable creature the sun has ever shone upon: and he is doubtless also in possession of the corresponding stupidity.
The happy and comfortable nature of the political and social situation shouldn't be sought among the Greeks. That's a dream that dazzles the eyes of our visionaries for the future! In reality, it was quite the opposite; it was terrible. This is something that needs to be judged by this standard: the more spirit there is, the more suffering there is (as the Greeks themselves show). Therefore, it follows that the more ignorance, the more comfort. The cultureless person is the most comfortable being the sun has ever warmed, and they certainly also possess the corresponding ignorance.
119
The Greek polis and the αἱεν ἁριστεὑειν grew up out of mutual enmity. Hellenic and philanthropic are contrary adjectives, although the ancients flattered themselves sufficiently.
The Greek polis and the αἱεν ἁριστεὑειν emerged from mutual hostility. Hellenic and philanthropic are opposing terms, even though the ancients were quite self-satisfied.
Homer is, in the world of the Hellenic discord, the pan-Hellenic Greek. The ἁγὡν of the Greeks is also manifested in the Symposium in the shape of witty conversation.
Homer is, in the context of Greek conflict, the unifying Greek figure. The competition of the Greeks also shows up in the Symposium as clever conversation.
120
Wanton, mutual annihilation inevitable: so long as a single polis wished to exist—its envy for every[Pg 161]thing superior to itself, its cupidity, the disorder of its customs, the enslavement of the women, lack of conscience in the keeping of oaths, in murder, and in cases of violent death.
Wanton, mutual destruction was unavoidable: as long as a single city wanted to survive—its jealousy of anything better than itself, its greed, the chaos of its traditions, the oppression of women, disregard for keeping promises, in murder, and in cases of violent death.
Tremendous power of self-control: for example in a man like Socrates, who was capable of everything evil.
Tremendous power of self-control: for example in a man like Socrates, who was capable of anything evil.
121
Its noble sense of order and systematic arrangement had rendered the Athenian state immortal—The ten strategists in Athens! Foolish! Too big a sacrifice on the altar of jealousy.
Its noble sense of order and systematic arrangement had made the Athenian state immortal—The ten strategists in Athens! Ridiculous! Too great a sacrifice on the altar of jealousy.
122
The recreations of the Spartans consisted of feasting, hunting, and making war · their every-day life was too hard. On the whole, however, their state is merely a caricature of the polls, a corruption of Hellas. The breeding of the complete Spartan—but what was there great about him that his breeding should have required such a brutal state!
The Spartans' pastimes included feasting, hunting, and going to war; their daily life was too tough. Overall, though, their society was just a distorted version of the city-states, a perversion of Greece. The raising of the ideal Spartan—but what was so exceptional about him that his upbringing needed such a harsh environment!
123
The political defeat of Greece is the greatest failure of culture; for it has given rise to the atrocious theory that culture cannot be pursued unless one is at the same time armed to the teeth. The rise of Christianity was the second greatest failure: brute force on the one hand, and a dull intellect on the other, won a complete victory over the aristocratic genius among the nations. To be a Philhellenist now means to be a foe of brute force and stupid intellects. Sparta was the ruin of Athens in so far[Pg 162] as she compelled Athens to turn her entire attention to politics and to act as a federal combination.
The political defeat of Greece is the biggest failure of culture; it led to the terrible idea that you can't pursue culture unless you're heavily armed. The rise of Christianity was the second biggest failure: raw power on one side and a dull brain on the other completely triumphed over the noble genius of the nations. Nowadays, being a Philhellenist means being against brute force and ignorance. Sparta was the downfall of Athens because it forced Athens to focus all its efforts on politics and to operate as a federal union.
124
There are domains of thought where the ratio will only give rise to disorder, and the philologist, who possesses nothing more, is lost through it and is unable to see the truth · e.g. in the consideration of Greek mythology. A merely fantastic person, of course, has no claim either · one must possess Greek imagination and also a certain amount of Greek piety. Even the poet does not require to be too consistent, and consistency is the last thing Greeks would understand.
There are areas of thought where logic will only lead to chaos, and the language expert, who only has that at their disposal, gets lost and fails to perceive the truth, for example, in the study of Greek mythology. A purely imaginative person, of course, has no right to claim understanding either; one must have a grasp of Greek imagination along with a degree of Greek reverence. Even the poet doesn’t need to be completely consistent, and consistency is the last thing the Greeks would comprehend.
125
Almost all the Greek divinities are accumulations of divinities . we find one layer over another, soon to be hidden and smoothed down by yet a third, and so on. It scarcely seems to me to be possible to pick these various divinities to pieces in a scientific manner, for no good method of doing so can be recommended: even the poor conclusion by analogy is in this instance a very good conclusion.
Almost all the Greek gods are collections of deities. We can see one layer on top of another, soon buried and smoothed out by yet another layer, and so on. It hardly seems possible to break these various gods down in a scientific way, as there’s no effective method for doing so: even the weak conclusion through analogy is, in this case, a solid conclusion.
126
At what a distance must one be from the Greeks to ascribe to them such a stupidly narrow autochthony as does Ottfried Muller![10] How Christian it is to assume, with Welcker,[11] that the Greeks were[Pg 163] originally monotheistic! How philologists torment themselves by investigating the question whether Homer actually wrote, without being able to grasp the far higher tenet that Greek art long exhibited an inward enmity against writing, and did not wish to be read at all.
At what distance must one be from the Greeks to claim such a ridiculously narrow view of their origins as Ottfried Muller does![10] How naive it is to assume, as Welcker does,[11] that the Greeks were[Pg 163] originally monotheistic! It’s amusing to see philologists struggle with whether Homer actually wrote, without realizing the much deeper idea that Greek art had a long-standing resistance to writing and didn’t actually want to be read at all.
127
In the religious cultus an earlier degree of culture comes to light a remnant of former times. The ages that celebrate it are not those which invent it, the contrary is often the case. There are many contrasts to be found here. The Greek cultus takes us back to a pre-Homeric disposition and culture. It is almost the oldest that we know of the Greeks—older than their mythology, which their poets have considerably remoulded, so far as we know it—Can this cult really be called Greek? I doubt it: they are finishers, not inventors. They preserve by means of this beautiful completion and adornment.
In religious practices, an earlier level of culture is revealed as a remnant of past times. The eras that celebrate it aren't necessarily the ones that created it; in fact, the opposite is often true. There are many contrasts to explore here. The Greek practices take us back to a pre-Homeric mindset and culture. It’s almost the oldest we know of the Greeks—older than their mythology, which their poets have significantly reshaped, as far as we can tell. Can we really call this practice Greek? I’m not sure: they are finishers, not creators. They preserve through this beautiful refinement and embellishment.
128
It is exceedingly doubtful whether we should draw any conclusion in regard to nationality and relationship with other nations from languages. A victorious language is nothing but a frequent (and not always regular) indication of a successful campaign. Where could there have been autochthonous peoples! It shows a very hazy conception of things to talk about Greeks who never lived in Greece. That which is really Greek is much less the result of natural aptitude than of adapted institutions, and also of an acquired language.[Pg 164]
It’s highly questionable whether we can make any conclusions about nationality or relationships with other nations based on languages. A dominant language is merely a frequent (and not always consistent) sign of a successful campaign. Where could there have been native peoples? It reflects a very unclear understanding to talk about Greeks who never lived in Greece. What is truly Greek is much less about natural talent and much more about adopted institutions and a learned language.[Pg 164]
129
To live on mountains, to travel a great deal, and to move quickly from one place to another . in these ways we can now begin to compare ourselves with the Greek gods. We know the past, too, and we almost know the future. What would a Greek say, if only he could see us!
To live in the mountains, to travel extensively, and to quickly move from one place to another—in these ways, we can now start to compare ourselves to the Greek gods. We understand the past well, and we have a good sense of the future, too. What would a Greek think if they could see us now!
130
The gods make men still more evil; this is the nature of man. If we do not like a man, we wish that he may become worse than he is, and then we are glad. This forms part of the obscure philosophy of hate—a philosophy which has never yet been written, because it is everywhere the pudendum that every one feels.
The gods make people even more evil; that's just how humans are. If we don't like someone, we hope they get worse, and then we feel satisfied. This is part of the hidden philosophy of hate—a philosophy that's never been written down, because it's the embarrassing truth that everyone knows.
131
The pan-Hellenic Homer finds his delight in the frivolity of the gods; but it is astounding how he can also give them dignity again. This amazing ability to raise one's self again, however, is Greek.
The pan-Hellenic Homer takes joy in the playfulness of the gods; yet it's impressive how he can restore their dignity as well. This remarkable ability to lift oneself back up is, however, distinctly Greek.
132
What, then, is the origin of the envy of the gods? people did not believe in a calm, quiet happiness, but only in an exuberant one. This must have caused some displeasure to the Greeks; for their soul was only too easily wounded: it embittered them to see a happy man. That is Greek. If a man of distinguished talent appeared, the flock of envious people must have become astonishingly large. If any one met with a misfortune, they[Pg 165] would say of him: "Ah! no wonder! he was too frivolous and too well off." And every one of them would have behaved exuberantly if he had possessed the requisite talent, and would willingly have played the role of the god who sent the unhappiness to men.
What, then, is the source of the gods' envy? People didn't believe in a calm, quiet happiness, but only in a loud, exuberant one. This must have annoyed the Greeks, since their souls were easily hurt; it made them bitter to see someone happy. That’s just how the Greeks were. If a person of great talent appeared, the number of envious people would grow remarkably large. If someone faced misfortune, they[Pg 165] would say, "Oh! No surprise there! He was too reckless and too well-off." And each one of them would have acted exuberantly if they had the needed talent and would have gladly taken on the role of the god who brought misfortune to men.
133
The Greek gods did not demand any complete changes of character, and were, generally speaking, by no means burdensome or importunate . it was thus possible to take them seriously and to believe in them. At the time of Homer, indeed, the nature of the Greek was formed · flippancy of images and imagination was necessary to lighten the weight of its passionate disposition and to set it free.
The Greek gods didn’t require any drastic changes in personality and, for the most part, were not overly demanding or nagging. This made it easier to take them seriously and have faith in them. During Homer’s time, the nature of the Greeks was shaped; a playful approach to images and imagination was essential to ease the heaviness of their intense emotions and to allow them to be free.
134
Every religion has for its highest images an analogon in the spiritual condition of those who profess it. The God of Mohammed . the solitariness of the desert, the distant roar of the lion, the vision of a formidable warrior. The God of the Christians . everything that men and women think of when they hear the word "love". The God of the Greeks: a beautiful apparition in a dream.
Every religion has its highest images reflecting the spiritual state of its followers. The God of Mohammed is seen in the solitude of the desert, the distant roar of a lion, and the image of a powerful warrior. The God of Christians encompasses all that people think of when they hear the word "love." The God of the Greeks appears as a beautiful figure in a dream.
135
A great deal of intelligence must have gone to the making up of a Greek polytheism . the expenditure of intelligence is much less lavish when people have only one God.
A lot of intelligence must have gone into creating Greek polytheism. The use of intelligence is far less extravagant when people believe in only one God.
136
Greek morality is not based on religion, but on the polis.[Pg 166]
Greek morality isn’t rooted in religion, but in the polis.[Pg 166]
There were only priests of the individual gods; not representatives of the whole religion . i.e., no guild of priests. Likewise no Holy Writ.
There were only priests for each individual god; there weren't any representatives for the entire religion. i.e., there was no priestly guild. Similarly, there was no Holy Scripture.
137
The "lighthearted" gods · this is the highest adornment which has ever been bestowed upon the world—with the feeling, How difficult it is to live!
The "lighthearted" gods · this is the greatest blessing that has ever been given to the world—with the thought, How difficult it is to live!
138
If the Greeks let their "reason" speak, their life seems to them bitter and terrible. They are not deceived. But they play round life with lies: Simonides advises them to treat life as they would a play; earnestness was only too well known to them in the form of pain. The misery of men is a pleasure to the gods when they hear the poets singing of it. Well did the Greeks know that only through art could even misery itself become a source of pleasure, vide tragœdiam.
If the Greeks let their "reason" take over, they see life as harsh and awful. They aren't fooled. But they surround life with illusions: Simonides suggests they treat life like a performance; they were all too familiar with seriousness as pain. The suffering of people entertains the gods when they hear poets sing about it. The Greeks understood well that only through art could even suffering turn into a source of pleasure, vide tragœdiam.
139
It is quite untrue to say that the Greeks only took this life into their consideration—they suffered also from thoughts of death and Hell. But no "repentance" or contrition.
It is definitely not accurate to say that the Greeks only focused on this life—they also dealt with thoughts of death and Hell. But there was no "repentance" or remorse.
140
The incarnate appearance of gods, as in Sappho's invocation to Aphrodite, must not be taken as poetic licence · they are frequently hallucinations. We conceive of a great many things, including the will to die, too superficially as rhetorical.[Pg 167]
The physical presence of gods, like in Sappho's call to Aphrodite, shouldn’t just be seen as poetic freedom; they are often visions. We think about many things, including the desire to die, too simplistically as just figures of speech.[Pg 167]
141
The "martyr" is Hellenic: Prometheus, Hercules. The hero-myth became pan-Hellenic: a poet must have had a hand in that!
The "martyr" is Greek: Prometheus, Hercules. The hero-myth became widely Greek: a poet must have contributed to that!
142
How realistic the Greeks were even in the domain of pure inventions! They poetised reality, not yearning to lift themselves out of it. The raising of the present into the colossal and eternal, e.g., by Pindar.
How realistic the Greeks were even in the realm of pure inventions! They turned reality into poetry, not trying to escape from it. They elevated the present into the grand and timeless, e.g., by Pindar.
143
What condition do the Greeks premise as the model of their life in Hades? Anæmic, dreamlike, weak . it is the continuous accentuation of old age, when the memory gradually becomes weaker and weaker, and the body still more so. The senility of senility . this would be our state of life in the eyes of the Hellenes.
What condition do the Greeks suggest as the model of their life in Hades? Anemic, dreamlike, weak... it's the ongoing emphasis on old age, when memory fades more and more, and the body deteriorates even faster. The decline of decline... this would be our state of life in the view of the Greeks.
144
The naive character of the Greeks observed by the Egyptians.
The naive nature of the Greeks noticed by the Egyptians.
145
The truly scientific people, the literary people, were the Egyptians and not the Greeks. That which has the appearance of science among the Greeks, originated among the Egyptians and later on returned to them to mingle again with the old current. Alexandrian culture is an amalgamation of Hellenic and Egyptian . and when our world again founds its culture upon the Alexandrian culture, then....[12][Pg 168]
The truly scientific and literary people were the Egyptians, not the Greeks. What seems like science among the Greeks actually originated with the Egyptians and later came back to them, mixing again with the old traditions. Alexandrian culture is a blend of Hellenic and Egyptian influences, and when our world re-establishes its culture based on Alexandrian culture, then....[12][Pg 168]
146
The Egyptians are far more of a literary people than the Greeks. I maintain this against Wolf. The first grain in Eleusis, the first vine in Thebes, the first olive-tree and fig-tree. The Egyptians had lost a great part of their mythology.
The Egyptians are much more of a literary culture than the Greeks. I stand by this against Wolf. The first grain in Eleusis, the first vine in Thebes, the first olive tree, and fig tree. The Egyptians had lost a significant portion of their mythology.
147
The unmathematical undulation of the column in Paestum is analogous to the modification of the tempo: animation in place of a mechanical movement.
The irregular wobble of the column in Paestum is similar to the change in the tempo: lively movement instead of a mechanical function.
148
The desire to find something certain and fixed in æsthetic led to the worship of Aristotle: I think, however, that we may gradually come to see from his works that he understood nothing about art, and that it is merely the intellectual conversations of the Athenians, echoing in his pages, which we admire.
The desire to find something certain and fixed in aesthetics led to the worship of Aristotle. However, I think we might gradually come to realize from his works that he understood nothing about art, and that it’s just the intellectual discussions of the Athenians echoing in his pages that we admire.
149
In Socrates we have as it were lying open before us a specimen of the consciousness out of which, later on, the instincts of the theoretic man originated: that one would rather die than grow old and weak in mind.
In Socrates, we have a clear example of the consciousness that later shaped the instincts of the theoretical person: that one would prefer to die than to grow old and deteriorate mentally.
150
At the twilight of antiquity there were still wholly unchristian figures, which were more beautiful, harmonious, and pure than those of any Christians: e.g., Proclus. His mysticism and syncretism were things that precisely Christianity cannot reproach him with. In any case, it would be my desire to live together[Pg 169] with such people. In comparison with them Christianity looks like some crude brutalisation, organised for the benefit of the mob and the criminal classes.
At the end of ancient times, there were still completely unchristian figures who were more beautiful, harmonious, and pure than any Christians: e.g. Proclus. His mysticism and syncretism are things that Christianity can't criticize him for. In any case, I would prefer to live alongside[Pg 169] such people. Compared to them, Christianity seems like a rough form of brutalization, set up for the benefit of the masses and the criminal elements.
Proclus, who solemnly invokes the rising moon.
Proclus, who seriously calls upon the rising moon.
151
With the advent of Christianity a religion attained the mastery which corresponded to a pre-Greek condition of mankind: belief in witchcraft in connection with all and everything, bloody sacrifices, superstitious fear of demoniacal punishments, despair in one's self, ecstatic brooding and hallucination, man's self become the arena of good and evil spirits and their struggles.
With the rise of Christianity, a religion gained control that reflected an earlier state of humanity: a belief in witchcraft related to everything, bloody sacrifices, superstitious fear of demonic punishment, despair in oneself, ecstatic contemplation, and hallucination—where a person's inner self became the battleground for good and evil spirits and their conflicts.
152
All branches of history have experimented with antiquity · critical consideration alone remains. By this term I do not mean conjectural and literary-historical criticism.
All branches of history have explored ancient times; only critical examination remains. By this term, I don't mean speculative or literary-historical criticism.
153
Antiquity has been treated by all kinds of historians and their methods. We have now had enough experience, however, to turn the history of antiquity to account without being shipwrecked on antiquity itself.
Antiquity has been examined by various historians and their methods. However, we now have enough experience to make use of the history of antiquity without getting lost in it.
154
We can now look back over a fairly long period of human existence · what will the humanity be like which is able to look back at us from an equally long distance? which finds us lying intoxicated among the débris of old culture! which finds its only consolation in "being good" and in holding[Pg 170] out the "helping hand," and turns away from all other consolations!—Does beauty, too, grow out of the ancient culture? I think that our ugliness arises from our metaphysical remnants . our confused morals, the worthlessness of our marriages, and so on, are the cause. The beautiful man, the healthy, moderate, and enterprising man, moulds the objects around him into beautiful shapes after his own image.
We can now reflect on a pretty long stretch of human history. What will humanity be like when they look back at us from an equally long distance? What will they think of us lying drunk amidst the remnants of past cultures? They might find their only comfort in "being good" and extending a "helping hand," turning away from all other sources of comfort. Does beauty also emerge from that ancient culture? I believe our ugliness stems from our leftover metaphysical beliefs. Our muddled morals, the emptiness of our marriages, and so on, are to blame. The attractive person—someone who is healthy, balanced, and ambitious—shapes the world around them into beautiful forms that reflect their own nature.
155
Up to the present time all history has been written from the standpoint of success, and, indeed, with the assumption of a certain reason in this success. This remark applies also to Greek history: so far we do not possess any. It is the same all round, however: where are the historians who can survey things and events without being humbugged by stupid theories? I know of only one, Burckhardt. Everywhere the widest possible optimism prevails in science. The question: "What would have been the consequence if so and so had not happened?" is almost unanimously thrust aside, and yet it is the cardinal question. Thus everything becomes ironical. Let us only consider our own lives. If we examine history in accordance with a preconceived plan, let this plan be sought in the purposes of a great man, or perhaps in those of a sex, or of a party. Everything else is a chaos.—Even in natural science we find this deification of the necessary.
Up to now, all of history has been written from the perspective of success, and there's often an assumption that this success has a clear rationale. This observation also applies to Greek history: we still don't have a complete account. It's the same everywhere: where are the historians who can analyze events without getting distracted by misguided theories? I only know of one, Burckhardt. In every field, there's a prevailing sense of extreme optimism. The question, "What would have happened if certain events hadn’t occurred?" is almost universally ignored, even though it’s the most crucial question. This makes everything seem ironic. Just look at our own lives. If we study history with a predetermined agenda, whether focused on the goals of a great individual, a gender, or a political party, everything else becomes chaotic. Even in the natural sciences, we see this worship of what is deemed necessary.
Germany has become the breeding-place of this historical optimism; Hegel is perhaps to blame for this. Nothing, however, is more responsible for[Pg 171] the fatal influence of German culture. Everything that has been kept down by success gradually rears itself up: history as the scorn of the conqueror; a servile sentiment and a kneeling down before the actual fact—"a sense for the State," they now call it, as if that had still to be propagated! He who does not understand how brutal and unintelligent history is will never understand the stimulus to make it intelligent. Just think how rare it is to find a man with as great an intelligent knowledge of his own life as Goethe had . what amount of rationality can we expect to find arising out of these other veiled and blind existences as they work chaotically with and in opposition to each other?
Germany has become the breeding ground for this historical optimism; Hegel is probably to blame for this. However, nothing is more responsible for[Pg 171] the damaging influence of German culture. Everything that has been suppressed by success eventually rises up: history as the mockery of the conqueror; a submissive attitude and a bowing down before reality—“a sense for the State,” they now call it, as if that still needs to be instilled! Anyone who doesn’t grasp how brutal and unintelligent history is will never understand the drive to make it intelligent. Just consider how rare it is to find someone with as profound an understanding of his own life as Goethe had. What level of rationality can we expect to emerge from these other obscured and blind existences as they chaotically interact and oppose each other?
And it is especially naive when Hellwald, the author of a history of culture, warns us away from all "ideals," simply because history has killed them off one after the other.
And it's particularly naive when Hellwald, the author of a cultural history, advises us to steer clear of all "ideals," just because history has eliminated them one by one.
156
To bring to light without reserve the stupidity and the want of reason in human things · that is the aim of our brethren and colleagues. People will then have to distinguish what is essential in them, what is incorrigible, and what is still susceptible of further improvement. But "Providence" must be kept out of the question, for it is a conception that enables people to take things too easily. I wish to breathe the breath of this purpose into science. Let us advance our knowledge of mankind! The good and rational in man is accidental or apparent, or the contrary of something very irrational. There will come a time when training will be the only thought.[Pg 172]
To openly reveal the foolishness and lack of reason in human matters—that's the goal of our peers and colleagues. People will then need to identify what’s truly important, what can’t be changed, and what can still improve. But we have to leave "Providence" out of it, as it encourages people to take things too lightly. I want to infuse this purpose into science. Let’s enhance our understanding of humanity! The good and rational aspects of people are either random or merely seem reasonable, or they contradict something very irrational. Eventually, training will be our only focus.[Pg 172]
157
Surrender to necessity is exactly what I do not teach—for one must first know this necessity to be necessary. There may perhaps be many necessities; but in general this inclination is simply a bed of idleness.
Surrendering to necessity is exactly what I don’t teach—because you have to first recognize that this necessity is truly necessary. There might be many necessities; but generally, this tendency is just a state of laziness.
158
To know history now means · to recognise how all those who believed in a Providence took things too easily. There is no such thing. If human affairs are seen to go forward in a loose and disordered way, do not think that a god has any purpose in view by letting them do so or that he is neglecting them. We can now see in a general way that the history of Christianity on earth has been one of the most dreadful chapters in history, and that a stop must be put to it. True, the influence of antiquity has been observed in Christianity even in our own time, and, as it diminishes, so will our knowledge of antiquity diminish also to an even greater extent. Now is the best time to recognise it: we are no longer prejudiced in favour of Christianity, but we still understand it, and also the antiquity that forms part of it, so far as this antiquity stands in line with Christianity.
To understand history today means recognizing how everyone who believed in a higher power took things too lightly. There isn’t one. If human events seem to unfold in a chaotic and disorganized manner, don't assume that a god has any plan for allowing it to happen or that they are being overlooked. We can now generally see that the history of Christianity on earth has been one of the most terrible chapters in history, and it must come to an end. It's true that the influence of the past has been evident in Christianity even in our time, and as that influence fades, our knowledge of that past will also diminish even more. Now is the best time to acknowledge this: we are no longer biased in favor of Christianity, but we still comprehend it, along with the aspects of the past that relate to it, as long as those aspects align with Christianity.
159
Philosophic heads must occupy themselves one day with the collective account of antiquity and make up its balance-sheet. If we have this, antiquity will be overcome. All the shortcomings which now vex us have their roots in antiquity, so that we cannot continue to treat this account with[Pg 173] the mildness which has been customary up to the present. The atrocious crime of mankind which rendered Christianity possible, as it actually became possible, is the guilt of antiquity. With Christianity antiquity will also be cleared away.—At the present time it is not so very far behind us, and it is certainly not possible to do justice to it. It has been availed of in the most dreadful fashion for purposes of repression, and has acted as a support for religious oppression by disguising itself as "culture." It was common to hear the saying, "Antiquity has been conquered by Christianity."
Philosophical thinkers need to eventually deal with the overall story of ancient times and come up with a clear assessment. Once we accomplish this, we’ll move past antiquity. All the issues that trouble us today have their origins in the past, so we can’t keep handling this matter with[Pg 173] the gentleness that’s been typical so far. The terrible wrongdoing of humanity that made Christianity possible, as it actually emerged, is the guilt of antiquity. With the rise of Christianity, antiquity will also be set aside. Right now, it's not that far behind us, and we certainly can't fully appreciate it. It has been used in the most awful ways for oppression and has supported religious tyranny while pretending to be "culture." It was often said, "Christianity has conquered antiquity."
This was a historical fact, and it was thus thought that no harm could come of any dealings with antiquity. Yes, it is so plausible to say that we find Christian ethics "deeper" than Socrates! Plato was easier to compete with! We are at the present time, so to speak, merely chewing the cud of the very battle which was fought in the first centuries of the Christian era—with the exception of the fact that now, instead of the clearly perceptible antiquity which then existed, we have merely its pale ghost; and, indeed, even Christianity itself has become rather ghostlike. It is a battle fought after the decisive battle, a post-vibration. In the end, all the forces of which antiquity consisted have reappeared in Christianity in the crudest possible form: it is nothing new, only quantitatively extraordinary.
This was a historical fact, and it was believed that no harm could come from any interactions with the past. Yes, it makes sense to say that we find Christian ethics "deeper" than those of Socrates! Plato was easier to compare against! Right now, we're essentially just revisiting the same fight that took place in the early centuries of Christianity—except now, instead of the clearly defined antiquity that existed then, we only have its faded echo; and, in fact, even Christianity itself has become quite ghostly. It's a battle fought after the decisive battle, a post-vibration. In the end, all the elements of antiquity have reemerged in Christianity in the most basic form: it's nothing new, just extraordinarily different in quantity.
160
What severs us for ever from the culture of antiquity is the fact that its foundations have become too shaky for us. A criticism of the Greeks is at[Pg 174] the same time a criticism of Christianity; for the bases of the spirit of belief, the religious cult, and witchcraft, are the same in both—There are many rudimentary stages still remaining, but they are by this time almost ready to collapse.
What separates us forever from ancient culture is that its foundations have become too unstable for us. Critiquing the Greeks also serves as a critique of Christianity; the foundations of belief, religious practices, and superstition are similar in both. There are still many basic stages present, but they are nearly about to crumble.
This would be a task . to characterise Greek antiquity as irretrievably lost, and with it Christianity also and the foundations upon which, up to the present time, our society and politics have been based.
This would be a task to describe Greek antiquity as completely lost, along with Christianity and the foundations on which our society and politics have been built up to now.
161
Christianity has conquered antiquity—yes; that is easily said. In the first place, it is itself a piece of antiquity, in the second place, it has preserved antiquity, in the third place, it has never been in combat with the pure ages of antiquity. Or rather: in order that Christianity itself might remain, it had to let itself be overcome by the spirit of antiquity—for example, the idea of empire, the community, and so forth. We are suffering from the uncommon want of clearness and uncleanliness of human things; from the ingenious mendacity which Christianity has brought among men.
Christianity has taken over the ancient world—sure, that sounds easy to say. First off, it’s a part of that ancient world itself; secondly, it has preserved its history; and thirdly, it has never really fought against the true essence of antiquity. Or rather, for Christianity to survive, it had to let itself be influenced by the spirit of antiquity—like the concepts of empire, community, and so on. We are struggling with the unusual lack of clarity and the messiness of human affairs; we are facing the clever deception that Christianity has introduced among people.
162
It is almost laughable to see how nearly all the sciences and arts of modern times grow from the scattered seeds which have been wafted towards us from antiquity, and how Christianity seems to us here to be merely the evil chill of a long night, a night during which one is almost inclined to believe that all is over with reason and honesty among men. The battle waged against the natural man has given rise to the unnatural man.[Pg 175]
It’s almost amusing to see how nearly all modern sciences and arts come from the scattered seeds that have drifted to us from the past, and how Christianity appears to us as just the cold, dark shadow of a long night—a night during which it feels like reason and honesty among people are lost. The struggle against our natural selves has created the unnatural self.[Pg 175]
163
With the dissolution of Christianity a great part of antiquity has become incomprehensible to us, for instance, the entire religious basis of life. On this account an imitation of antiquity is a false tendency . the betrayers or the betrayed are the philologists who still think of such a thing. We live in a period when many different conceptions of life are to be found: hence the present age is instructive to an unusual degree; and hence also the reason why it is so ill, since it suffers from the evils of all its tendencies at once. The man of the future . the European man.
With the decline of Christianity, a large part of ancient history has become hard for us to understand, including the whole religious foundation of life. Because of this, trying to replicate the past is misguided. The ones who are deceiving or being deceived are those scholars who still entertain such ideas. We live in a time with many different perspectives on life, making this era unusually educational; however, that’s also why it’s so troubled, as it struggles with the challenges of all its various views at once. The person of the future... the European person.
164
The German Reformation widened the gap between us and antiquity: was it necessary for it to do so? It once again introduced the old contrast of "Paganism" and "Christianity"; and it was at the same time a protest against the decorative culture of the Renaissance—it was a victory gained over the same culture as had formerly been conquered by early Christianity.
The German Reformation deepened the divide between us and ancient times: was that really necessary? It reintroduced the old conflict of “Paganism” versus “Christianity,” and it also served as a protest against the ornamental culture of the Renaissance—it was a win against the same culture that early Christianity had previously triumphed over.
In regard to "worldly things," Christianity preserved the grosser views of the ancients. All the nobler elements in marriage, slavery, and the State are unchristian. It required the distorting characteristics of worldliness to prove itself.
In relation to "worldly things," Christianity held onto the more crude perspectives of the ancients. All the more admirable aspects of marriage, slavery, and the State are not aligned with Christian values. It needed the twisted traits of worldliness to validate itself.
165
166
I understand religions as narcotics: but when they are given to such nations as the Germans, I think they are simply rank poison.
I see religions as drugs: but when they're taken by nations like the Germans, I believe they are just pure poison.
167
All religions are, in the end, based upon certain physical assumptions, which are already in existence and adapt the religions to their needs . for example, in Christianity, the contrast between body and soul, the unlimited importance of the earth as the "world," the marvellous occurrences in nature. If once the opposite views gain the mastery—for instance, a strict law of nature, the helplessness and superfluousness of all gods, the strict conception of the soul as a bodily process—all is over. But all Greek culture is based upon such views.
All religions ultimately rely on certain physical assumptions that already exist and shape the religions to fit their needs. For example, in Christianity, there's the distinction between body and soul, the immense significance of Earth as the "world," and the extraordinary events in nature. If the opposing views take over—for instance, a rigid natural law, the uselessness of all gods, and the idea of the soul as merely a physical process—then everything changes. But all Greek culture is built on these kinds of ideas.
168
When we look from the character and culture of the Catholic Middle Ages back to the Greeks, we see them resplendent indeed in the rays of higher humanity; for, if we have anything to reproach these Greeks with, we must reproach the Middle Ages with it also to a much greater extent. The worship of the ancients at the time of the Renaissance was therefore quite honest and proper. We have carried matters further in one particular point, precisely in connection with that dawning ray of light. We have outstripped the Greeks in the clarifying of the world by our studies of nature and men. Our knowledge is much greater, and our judgments are more moderate and just.[Pg 177]
When we look from the character and culture of the Catholic Middle Ages back to the Greeks, we see them shining brightly in the light of higher humanity. If we have any criticisms of the Greeks, we should apply those same criticisms to the Middle Ages even more so. The admiration for the ancients during the Renaissance was therefore completely genuine and appropriate. In one specific area, we've gone even further, especially in relation to that emerging light. We've surpassed the Greeks in our understanding of the world through our studies of nature and humanity. Our knowledge is much greater, and our judgments are fairer and more balanced.[Pg 177]
In addition to this, a more gentle spirit has become widespread, thanks to the period of illumination which has weakened mankind—but this weakness, when turned into morality, leads to good results and honours us. Man has now a great deal of freedom: it is his own fault if he does not make more use of it than he does; the fanaticism of opinions has become much milder. Finally, that we would much rather live in the present age than in any other is due to science, and certainly no other race in the history of mankind has had such a wide choice of noble enjoyments as ours—even if our race has not the palate and stomach to experience a great deal of joy. But one can live comfortably amid all this "freedom" only when one merely understands it and does not wish to participate in it—that is the modern crux. The participants appear to be less attractive than ever · how stupid they must be!
In addition to this, a more gentle spirit has become widespread, thanks to a period of enlightenment that has weakened humanity—but this weakness, when transformed into morality, leads to positive outcomes and honors us. People now have a lot of freedom; it's their own fault if they don’t take more advantage of it than they do. The intensity of opinions has become much milder. Ultimately, our preference to live in this current age rather than any other is thanks to science, and certainly no other culture in history has had such a wide range of noble pleasures as ours—even if our culture lacks the appetite and ability to experience a lot of joy. But one can only live comfortably amid all this "freedom" when one merely understands it and does not wish to engage with it—that's the modern dilemma. Those who participate seem less appealing than ever—how foolish they must be!
Thus the danger arises that knowledge may avenge itself on us, just as ignorance avenged itself on us during the Middle Ages. It is all over with those religions which place their trust in gods, Providences, rational orders of the universe, miracles, and sacraments, as is also the case with certain types of holy lives, such as ascetics; for we only too easily conclude that such people are the effects of sickness and an aberrant brain. There is no doubt that the contrast between a pure, incorporeal soul and a body has been almost set aside. Who now believes in the immortality of the soul! Everything connected with blessedness or damnation, which was based upon certain erroneous physiological assumptions, falls to the ground as soon as these[Pg 178] assumptions are recognised to be errors. Our scientific assumptions admit just as much of an interpretation and utilisation in favour of a besotting philistinism—yea, in favour of bestiality—as also in favour of "blessedness" and soul-inspiration. As compared with all previous ages, we are now standing on a new foundation, so that something may still be expected from the human race.
Thus, the risk exists that knowledge might turn against us, just as ignorance did during the Middle Ages. Religions that rely on gods, divine providence, rational orders of the universe, miracles, and sacraments are fading away, as are some lifestyles, like those of ascetics; we too easily conclude that such individuals are the products of illness and a disturbed mind. There's no doubt that the distinction between a pure, immaterial soul and the body has nearly been disregarded. Who still believes in the immortality of the soul? Everything related to salvation or damnation, which was based on certain misguided physiological beliefs, crumbles once these[Pg 178] beliefs are recognized as fallacies. Our scientific beliefs can be interpreted and exploited just as much to support a dull, materialistic outlook—or even to encourage brutality—as they can to promote "blessedness" and inspiration of the soul. Compared to all previous eras, we're now on a new foundation, so there’s still hope for humanity.
As regards culture, we have hitherto been acquainted with only one complete form of it, i.e., the city-culture of the Greeks, based as it was on their mythical and social foundations; and one incomplete form, the Roman, which acted as an adornment of life, derived from the Greek. Now all these bases, the mythical and the politico-social, have changed; our alleged culture has no stability, because it has been erected upon insecure conditions and opinions which are even now almost ready to collapse.—When we thoroughly grasp Greek culture, then, we see that it is all over with it. The philologist is thus a great sceptic in the present conditions of our culture and training · that is his mission. Happy is he if, like Wagner and Schopenhauer, he has a dim presentiment of those auspicious powers amid which a new culture is stirring.
When it comes to culture, we’ve only really known one complete version of it, which is the city culture of the Greeks. This culture was built on their myths and social structures. We also have an incomplete version, the Roman culture, which was more of an enhancement of life, drawn from the Greek. Now, all those foundations—the myths and the political-social aspects—have changed. Our so-called culture lacks stability because it’s built on shaky conditions and opinions that are nearly ready to fall apart. So, when we fully understand Greek culture, it feels like it's all over. The philologist is, therefore, a significant skeptic about the current state of our culture and education—that’s their role. They’re fortunate if, like Wagner and Schopenhauer, they have a vague intuition of the promising forces that are ushering in a new culture.
169
Those who say: "But antiquity nevertheless remains as a subject of consideration for pure science, even though all its educational purposes may be disowned," must be answered by the words, What is pure science here! Actions and characteristics must be judged; and those who judge them must stand[Pg 179] above them: so you must first devote your attention to overcoming antiquity. If you do not do that, your science is not pure, but impure and limited . as may now be perceived.
Those who argue, "But ancient times are still worth studying for pure science, even if we reject all its educational goals," need to be reminded: What do we mean by pure science here? We must evaluate actions and traits; and those who evaluate them must rise above them: so you first need to focus on overcoming ancient ideas. If you fail to do that, your science is not pure, but rather impure and restricted, as is clear now.[Pg 179]
170
To overcome Greek antiquity through our own deeds: this would be the right task. But before we can do this we must first know it!—There is a thoroughness which is merely an excuse for inaction. Let it be recollected how much Goethe knew of antiquity: certainly not so much as a philologist, and yet sufficient to contend with it in such a way as to bring about fruitful results. One should not even know more about a thing than one could create. Moreover, the only time when we can actually recognise something is when we endeavour to make it. Let people but attempt to live after the manner of antiquity, and they will at once come hundreds of miles nearer to antiquity than they can do with all their erudition.—Our philologists never show that they strive to emulate antiquity in any way, and thus their antiquity remains without any effect on the schools.
To surpass Greek antiquity with our own actions: that should be our goal. But before we can do this, we must first understand it!—There’s a thoroughness that serves only as an excuse for inaction. Let's remember how much Goethe knew about antiquity: certainly not as much as a scholar, yet enough to engage with it in ways that led to meaningful outcomes. One should not even need to know more about something than what one can create. Besides, the only time we can truly recognize something is when we try to create it. If people just tried to live like those in antiquity, they would find themselves hundreds of miles closer to it than they could ever get with all their knowledge. Our scholars never show that they aim to emulate antiquity in any way, and thus their antiquity has no impact on the schools.
The study of the spirit of emulation (Renaissance, Goethe), and the study of despair.
The exploration of the spirit of competition (Renaissance, Goethe) and the exploration of despair.
The non-popular element in the new culture of the Renaissance: a frightful fact!
The unpopular aspect of the new Renaissance culture: a shocking reality!
171
The worship of classical antiquity, as it was to be seen in Italy, may be interpreted as the only earnest, disinterested, and fecund worship which has yet fallen to the lot of antiquity. It is a splendid[Pg 180] example of Don Quixotism; and philology at best is such Don Quixotism. Already at the time of the Alexandrian savants, as with all the sophists of the first and second centuries, the Atticists, &c., the scholars are imitating something purely and simply chimerical and pursuing a world that never existed. The same trait is seen throughout antiquity · the manner in which the Homeric heroes were copied, and all the intercourse held with the myths, show traces of it. Gradually all Greek antiquity has become an object of Don Quixotism. It is impossible to understand our modern world if we do not take into account the enormous influence of the purely fantastic. This is now confronted by the principle · there can be no imitation. Imitation, however, is merely an artistic phenomenon, i.e., it is based on appearance . we can accept manners, thoughts, and so on through imitation; but imitation can create nothing. True, the creator can borrow from all sides and nourish himself in that way. And it is only as creators that we shall be able to take anything from the Greeks. But in what respect can philologists be said to be creators! There must be a few dirty jobs, such as knackers' men, and also text-revisers: are the philologists to carry out tasks of this nature?
The worship of classical antiquity, as seen in Italy, can be viewed as the only genuine, selfless, and fruitful reverence for the past that has ever occurred. It serves as a great[Pg 180] example of Don Quixote-like idealism, and at best, philology resembles this idealism. Even back during the time of the Alexandrian scholars and all the sophists of the first and second centuries, like the Atticists, scholars were imitating something that was purely imaginary and chasing after a world that never existed. This characteristic is evident throughout antiquity; the way the Homeric heroes were emulated, and all the dealings with myths, reflect this. Over time, all of Greek antiquity has become an object of Quixotic pursuit. It’s impossible to understand our modern world without acknowledging the massive influence of the purely fantastic. This is now countered by the principle that there can be no true imitation. Imitation, however, is just an artistic occurrence, meaning it relies on surface appearances. We can adopt manners, thoughts, and so on through imitation, but imitation cannot create anything new. True, a creator can borrow from everywhere and feed off of that. But we can only take from the Greeks as creators. In what way can we say that philologists are creators? There must be some undesirable tasks, like those of knacker’s men, and also text-revisers: are philologists meant to handle jobs like these?
172
What, then, is antiquity now, in the face of modern art, science, and philosophy? It is no longer the treasure-chamber of all knowledge; for in natural and historical science we have advanced greatly beyond it. Oppression by the church has[Pg 181] been stopped. A pure knowledge of antiquity is now possible, but perhaps also a more ineffective and weaker knowledge.—This is right enough, if effect is known only as effect on the masses; but for the breeding of higher minds antiquity is more powerful than ever.
What, then, is antiquity now, in light of modern art, science, and philosophy? It’s no longer the ultimate source of all knowledge; we've advanced significantly beyond it in natural and historical sciences. The oppression from the church has[Pg 181] ended. A pure understanding of antiquity is now possible, though it might also be less effective and weaker. That may be true if we only consider its impact on the masses; however, for the development of higher minds, antiquity remains more powerful than ever.
Goethe as a German poet-philologist; Wagner as a still higher stage: his clear glance for the only worthy position of art. No ancient work has ever had so powerful an effect as the "Orestes" had on Wagner. The objective, emasculated philologist, who is but a philistine of culture and a worker in "pure science," is, however, a sad spectacle.
Goethe as a German poet and scholar; Wagner as an even greater figure: he recognized the true value of art. No ancient work has ever impacted Wagner as much as "Orestes" did. However, the objective, stripped-down scholar, who is just a cultural outsider and a practitioner of "pure science," is a rather disheartening sight.
173
Between our highest art and philosophy and that which is recognised to be truly the oldest antiquity, there is no contradiction: they support and harmonise with one another. It is in this that I place my hopes.
Between our greatest art and philosophy and what is acknowledged as the oldest antiquity, there is no contradiction: they support and complement each other. This is where I place my hopes.
174
The main standpoints from which to consider the importance of antiquity:
The main perspectives to consider when thinking about the significance of the past:
1. There is nothing about it for young people, for it exhibits man with an entire freedom from shame.
1. There's nothing appealing about it for young people because it shows a person completely unashamed.
2. It is not for direct imitation, but it teaches by which means art has hitherto been perfected in the highest degree.
2. It’s not meant to be copied directly, but it shows the ways in which art has been perfected to the highest level so far.
3. It is accessible only to a few, and there should be a police des mœurs, in charge of it—as there should be also in charge of bad pianists who play Beethoven.
3. It is only accessible to a select few, and there should be a police des mœurs, responsible for it—just like there should be one for bad pianists who attempt to play Beethoven.
4. These few apply this antiquity to the judg[Pg 182]ment of our own time, as critics of it; and they judge antiquity by their own ideals and are thus critics of antiquity.
4. These few look at this ancient history through the lens of today's judgments as critics of it; they evaluate the past based on their own ideals and, in doing so, become critics of that past.
5. The contract between the Hellenic and the Roman should be studied, and also the contrast between the early Hellenic and the late Hellenic.—Explanation of the different types of culture.
5. The agreement between the Greeks and the Romans should be examined, along with the differences between early Greek culture and late Greek culture.—Explanation of the various types of culture.
175
The advancement of science at the expense of man is one of the most pernicious things in the world. The stunted man is a retrogression in the human race: he throws a shadow over all succeeding generations The tendencies and natural purpose of the individual science become degenerate, and science itself is finally shipwrecked: it has made progress, but has either no effect at all on life or else an immoral one.
The advancement of science at the expense of humanity is one of the most harmful things in the world. A diminished person represents a setback for the human race; they cast a shadow over all future generations. The tendencies and natural purpose of individual sciences become corrupted, and science itself ultimately fails: it may have progressed, but it has either no impact on life or an immoral one.
176
Men not to be used like things!
Men shouldn't be treated like objects!
From the former very incomplete philology and knowledge of antiquity there flowed out a stream of freedom, while our own highly developed knowledge produces slaves and serves the idol of the State.
From the once very limited understanding of language and ancient history, a wave of freedom emerged, while our own advanced knowledge creates subservience and worships the idol of the State.
177
There will perhaps come a time when scientific work will be carried on by women, while the men will have to create, using the word in a spiritual sense: states, laws, works of art, &c.
There may come a time when women will do scientific work, while men will have to create, using the term in a spiritual way: states, laws, artworks, etc.
People should study typical antiquity just as they do typical men: i.e., imitating what they under[Pg 183]stand of it, and, when the pattern seems to lie far in the distance, considering ways and means and preliminary preparations, and devising stepping-stones.
People should study typical ancient times just like they study typical people: i.e., by imitating what they understand of it, and when the example seems to be far away, figuring out ways and means, making preliminary preparations, and creating stepping-stones.
178
The whole feature of study lies in this: that we should study only what we feel we should like to imitate; what we gladly take up and have the desire to multiply. What is really wanted is a progressive canon of the ideal model, suited to boys, youths, and men.
The main point of studying is this: we should focus on what we genuinely want to imitate; what we enthusiastically engage with and want to expand upon. What we truly need is an evolving set of the ideal model, tailored for boys, young men, and adult men.
179
Goethe grasped antiquity in the right way · invariably with an emulative soul. But who else did so? One sees nothing of a well-thought-out pedagogics of this nature: who knows that there is a certain knowledge of antiquity which cannot be imparted to youths!
Goethe understood ancient times in the right way, always with a spirit of emulation. But who else did? There's no evidence of a well-planned approach to this kind of education: who knows that there's a certain understanding of ancient times that can't be taught to young people!
The puerile character of philology: devised by teachers for pupils.
The childish nature of philology: created by teachers for students.
180
The ever more and more common form of the ideal: first men, then institutions, finally tendencies, purposes, or the want of them. The highest form: the conquest of the ideal by a backward movement from tendencies to institutions, and from institutions to men.
The increasingly common representation of the ideal: first individuals, then organizations, and finally movements, goals, or the lack of them. The ultimate form: achieving the ideal by reversing from movements to organizations, and from organizations to individuals.
181
I will set down in writing what I no longer believe—and also what I do believe. Man stands in the midst of the great whirlpool of forces, and imagines[Pg 184] that this whirlpool is rational and has a rational aim in view: error! The only rationality that we know is the small reason of man: he must exert it to the utmost, and it invariably leaves him in the lurch if he tries to place himself in the hands of "Providence."
I’m going to write down what I no longer believe—and also what I do believe. People find themselves in the middle of a huge whirlpool of forces and think[Pg 184] that this whirlpool is logical and has a purpose: wrong! The only logic we truly understand is the limited reasoning of humans: they have to use it to the fullest, and it always fails them if they try to rely on "Providence."
Our only happiness lies in reason; all the remainder of the world is dreary. The highest reason, however, is seen by me in the work of the artist, and he can feel it to be such: there may be something which, when it can be consciously brought forward, may afford an even greater feeling of reason and happiness: for example, the course of the solar system, the breeding and education of a man.
Our only happiness comes from reason; everything else in the world feels dull. However, I see the highest form of reason in the work of the artist, and he is able to feel that too. There might be something that, when consciously recognized, could provide an even deeper sense of reason and happiness: for instance, the workings of the solar system, or the growth and education of a person.
Happiness lies in rapidity of feeling and thinking: everything else is slow, gradual, and stupid. The man who could feel the progress of a ray of light would be greatly enraptured, for it is very rapid.
Happiness comes from quick emotions and thoughts: everything else is slow, gradual, and dull. A person who could sense the movement of a beam of light would be incredibly thrilled, because it moves so fast.
Thinking of one's self affords little happiness. But when we do experience happiness therein the reason is that we are not thinking of ourselves, but of our ideal. This lies far off; and only the rapid man attains it and rejoices.
Thinking about ourselves brings little happiness. But when we do feel happy, it's because we're not focused on ourselves, but on our ideals. These ideals are distant, and only those who move quickly can reach them and find joy.
An amalgamation of a great centre of men for the breeding of better men is the task of the future. The individual must become familiarised with claims that, when he says Yea to his own will, he also says Yea to the will of that centre—for example, in reference to a choice, as among women for marriage, and likewise as to the manner in which his child shall be brought up. Until now no single individuality, or only the very rarest, have been free: they were influenced by these conceptions, but likewise[Pg 185] by the bad and contradictory organisation of the individual purposes.
An integration of a strong community focused on raising better individuals is the challenge ahead. Each person needs to understand that when they agree to their own desires, they're also agreeing to the goals of that community—for instance, when choosing a partner for marriage or deciding how to raise their child. Until now, no individual, or very few, have truly been free: they were shaped by these ideas, as well as by the flawed and conflicting structures of personal ambitions.[Pg 185]
182
Education is in the first place instruction in what is necessary, and then in what is changing and inconstant. The youth is introduced to nature, and the sway of laws is everywhere pointed out to him; followed by an explanation of the laws of ordinary society. Even at this early stage the question will arise: was it absolutely necessary that this should have been so? He gradually comes to need history to ascertain how these things have been brought about. He learns at the same time, however, that they may be changed into something else. What is the extent of man's power over things? This is the question in connection with all education. To show how things may become other than what they are we may, for example, point to the Greeks. We need the Romans to show how things became what they were.
Education starts with teaching what is essential, and then it moves on to what is changing and uncertain. Young people are introduced to nature, and the influence of laws is highlighted throughout; this is followed by an explanation of the laws of everyday society. Even at this early stage, the question arises: was it really necessary for things to be this way? They gradually come to realize that they need history to understand how these situations have developed. At the same time, they learn that these situations can be transformed into something different. What is the extent of human power over things? This is the core question linked to all education. To demonstrate how things can change, we can look at the Greeks. We need the Romans to illustrate how things became what they were.
183
If, then, the Romans had spurned the Greek culture, they would perhaps have gone to pieces completely. When could this culture have once again arisen? Christianity and Romans and barbarians: this would have been an onslaught: it would have entirely wiped out culture. We see the danger amid which genius lives. Cicero was one of the greatest benefactors of humanity, even in his own time.
If the Romans had rejected Greek culture, they might have completely fallen apart. When could this culture have emerged again? Christianity, Romans, and barbarians: this would have been an overwhelming force that could have completely destroyed culture. We see the peril in which genius exists. Cicero was one of humanity's greatest benefactors, even during his own time.
There is no "Providence" for genius; it is only for the ordinary run of people and their wants that[Pg 186] such a thing exists: they find their satisfaction, and later on their justification.
There’s no “Providence” for genius; it only exists for regular people and their needs. They find their satisfaction and later their justification. [Pg 186]
184
Thesis: the death of ancient culture inevitable. Greek culture must be distinguished as the archetype; and it must be shown how all culture rests upon shaky conceptions.
Thesis: the death of ancient culture is inevitable. Greek culture should be seen as the model; and it needs to be demonstrated how all culture is built on unstable ideas.
The dangerous meaning of art: as the protectress and galvanisation of dead and dying conceptions; history, in so far as it wishes to restore to us feelings which we have overcome. To feel "historically" or "just" towards what is already past, is only possible when we have risen above it. But the danger in the adoption of the feelings necessary for this is very great . let the dead bury their dead, so that we ourselves may not come under the influence of the smell of the corpses.
The risky nature of art: as the guardian and revival of outdated and fading ideas; history, as long as it wants to bring back feelings we've moved beyond. To feel "historically" or "just" about what’s already in the past is only possible when we’ve moved past it. But the danger in embracing the feelings required for this is significant. Let the dead bury their dead, so we don't end up influenced by the stench of the dead.
The End of the Old Culture.
1. The signification of the studies of antiquity hitherto pursued: obscure; mendacious.
1. The meaning of the studies of the past that have been conducted so far: unclear; misleading.
2. As soon as they recognise the goal they condemn themselves to death · for their goal is to describe ancient culture itself as one to be demolished.
2. As soon as they realize the goal, they condemn themselves to death · for their goal is to portray ancient culture itself as something to be destroyed.
3. The collection of all the conceptions out of which Hellenic culture has grown up. Criticism of religion, art, society, state, morals.
3. The gathering of all the ideas that led to the development of Hellenic culture. Critique of religion, art, society, government, and ethics.
4. Christianity is likewise denied.
4. Christianity is also denied.
5. Art and history—dangerous.
Art and history—risky.
6. The replacing of the study of antiquity which has become superfluous for the training of our youth.
6. The replacement of studying ancient times that has become unnecessary for educating our young people.
Thus the task of the science of history is completed[Pg 187] and it itself has become superfluous, if the entire inward continuous circle of past efforts has been condemned. Its place must be taken by the science of the future.
Thus the task of the science of history is finished[Pg 187] and it has become unnecessary, if the whole ongoing cycle of past efforts has been judged worthless. Its place must be taken by the science of the future.
185
"Signs" and "miracles" are not believed; only a "Providence" stands in need of such things. There is no help to be found either in prayer or asceticism or in "vision." If all these things constitute religion, then there is no more religion for me.
"Signs" and "miracles" aren't really believed in; only a "Providence" needs those kinds of things. There's no assistance to be found in prayer, self-denial, or in "vision." If all of this is what religion is about, then I want no part of it.
My religion, if I can still apply this name to something, lies in the work of breeding genius . from such training everything is to be hoped. All consolation comes from art. Education is love for the offspring; an excess of love over and beyond our self-love. Religion is "love beyond ourselves." The work of art is the model of such a love beyond ourselves, and a perfect model at that.
My belief, if I can still call it that, is in the work of nurturing genius. We can hope for everything from that kind of training. All comfort comes from art. Education is about caring for the next generation; it's a form of love that goes beyond just loving ourselves. Religion is "love that extends beyond ourselves." A work of art is the ideal example of that kind of love, and a perfect one at that.
186
The stupidity of the will is Schopenhauer's greatest thought, if thoughts be judged from the standpoint of power. We can see in Hartmann how he juggled away this thought. Nobody will ever call something stupid—God.
The foolishness of the will is Schopenhauer's most significant idea, if we assess thoughts based on their impact. We can see in Hartmann how he dismissed this idea. No one would ever label something stupid—God.
187
This, then, is the new feature of all the future progress of the world · men must never again be ruled over by religious conceptions. Will they be any worse? It is not my experience that they behave well and morally under the yoke of religion; I am not on the side of Demopheles[14] The fear of a[Pg 188] beyond, and then again the fear of divine punishments will hardly have made men better.
This is the new aspect of all future progress in the world: people should never again be controlled by religious beliefs. Will they be any worse? From what I’ve seen, they don’t act well or morally under the constraints of religion; I don’t side with Demopheles[14]. The fear of an afterlife, along with the fear of divine punishment, hasn’t really made people better.
188
Where something great makes its appearance and lasts for a relatively long time, we may premise a careful breeding, as in the case of the Greeks. How did so many men become free among them? Educate educators! But the first educators must educate themselves! And it is for these that I write.
Where something amazing shows up and sticks around for a while, we can assume there's been some careful cultivation, like with the Greeks. How did so many people gain their freedom there? Educate the educators! But the first educators need to educate themselves! And it's for them that I'm writing.
189
The denial of life is no longer an easy matter: a man may become a hermit or a monk—and what is thereby denied! This conception has now become deeper . it is above all a discerning denial, a denial based upon the will to be just; not an indiscriminate and wholesale denial.
The denial of life is no longer a simple issue: a person can choose to be a hermit or a monk—and look at what is sacrificed! This idea has now become more profound. It’s mainly a thoughtful denial, a denial grounded in the desire to be fair; not a random and complete rejection.
190
The seer must be affectionate, otherwise men will have no confidence in him · Cassandra.
The seer needs to be warm and caring; otherwise, people won't trust him. · Cassandra.
191
The man who to-day wishes to be good and saintly has a more difficult task than formerly . in order to be "good," he must not be so unjust to knowledge as earlier saints were. He would have to be a knowledge-saint: a man who would link love with knowledge, and who would have nothing to do with gods or demigods or "Providence," as the Indian saints likewise had nothing to do with them. He should[Pg 189] also be healthy, and should keep himself so, otherwise he would necessarily become distrustful of himself. And perhaps he would not bear the slightest resemblance to the ascetic saint, but would be much more like a man of the world.
The man who wants to be good and virtuous today faces a tougher challenge than in the past. To be seen as "good," he can’t disregard knowledge like earlier saints did. He needs to be a knowledge-saint: someone who combines love with knowledge, avoiding any connection with gods, demigods, or "Providence," just as Indian saints did. He should[Pg 189] also prioritize his health and maintain it; otherwise, he will likely become doubtful of himself. He might not resemble the traditional ascetic saint at all, but instead, be much more like an everyday person.
192
The better the state is organised, the duller will humanity be.
The better organized the state is, the less interesting humanity will be.
To make the individual uncomfortable is my task!
To make the person uncomfortable is my job!
The great pleasure experienced by the man who liberates himself by fighting.
The intense satisfaction felt by the man who frees himself through struggle.
Spiritual heights have had their age in history; inherited energy belongs to them. In the ideal state all would be over with them.
Spiritual heights have had their time in history; they possess inherited energy. In the ideal state, everything would be resolved with them.
193
The highest judgment on life only arising from the highest energy of life. The mind must be removed as far as possible from exhaustion.
The greatest understanding of life comes only from the highest energy of life. The mind needs to be kept as far from exhaustion as possible.
In the centre of the world-history judgment will be the most accurate; for it was there that the greatest geniuses existed.
In the center of world history, judgment will be the most accurate; because that's where the greatest minds thrived.
The breeding of the genius as the only man who can truly value and deny life.
The breeding of the genius as the only person who can truly appreciate and reject life.
Save your genius! shall be shouted unto the people: set him free! Do all you can to unshackle him.
Save your genius! should be shouted to the people: let him be free! Do everything you can to break his chains.
The feeble and poor in spirit must not be allowed to judge life.
The weak and spiritually poor shouldn't be allowed to judge life.
194
[Pg 190]I dream of a combination of men who shall make no concessions, who shall show no consideration, and who shall be willing to be called "destroyers": they apply the standard of their criticism to everything and sacrifice themselves to truth. The bad and the false shall be brought to light! We will not build prematurely: we do not know, indeed, whether we shall ever be able to build, or if it would not be better not to build at all. There are lazy pessimists and resigned ones in this world—and it is to their number that we refuse to belong!
[Pg 190]I dream of a group of people who won’t compromise, who won’t show mercy, and who aren’t afraid to be called “destroyers”: they hold everything up to their critical standards and dedicate themselves to the truth. The bad and the false will be exposed! We won’t rush to build: we don’t even know if we’ll ever be able to build, or if it might be better not to build at all. There are lazy pessimists and those who have given up in this world—and we refuse to be part of that group!
FOOTNOTES:
[1] No doubt a reminiscence of the "Odyssey," Bk. ix—Tr.
The text is unchanged. Clearly a reflection of the "Odyssey," Bk. ix—Tr.
[2] Formal education is that which tends to develop the critical and logical faculties, as opposed to material education, which is intended to deal with the acquisition of knowledge and its valuation, e.g., history, mathematics, &c. "Material" education, of course, has nothing to do with materialism—Tr.
[2] Formal education focuses on developing critical and logical thinking skills, while material education is about acquiring knowledge and understanding its value, like history, mathematics, etc. "Material" education, of course, is not related to materialism—Tr.
Done.
Printed at The Darien Press, Edinburgh
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!