This is a modern-English version of Evolution, Old & New: Or, the Theories of Buffon, Dr. Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck,; as compared with that of Charles Darwin, originally written by Butler, Samuel.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
Evolution,
Old & New
"The want of a practical acquaintance with Natural History leads the author to take an erroneous view of the bearing of his own theories on those of Mr. Darwin.—Review of 'Life and Habit,' by Mr. A. R. Wallace, in 'Nature,' March 27, 1879.
"The lack of a practical understanding of Natural History causes the author to misunderstand how his theories relate to those of Mr. Darwin.—Review of 'Life and Habit,' by Mr. A. R. Wallace, in 'Nature,' March 27, 1879.
"Neither lastly would our observer be driven out of his conclusion, or from his confidence in its truth, by being told that he knows nothing at all about the matter. He knows enough for his argument; he knows the utility of the end; he knows the subserviency and adaptation of the means to the end. These points being known, his ignorance concerning other points, his doubts concerning other points, affect not the certainty of his reasoning. The consciousness of knowing little need not beget a distrust of that which he does know."
"Lastly, our observer wouldn't be swayed from his conclusion or lose confidence in its truth just because someone says he doesn't know anything about the topic. He knows enough to support his argument; he understands the importance of the goal; he sees how the means align with that goal. Knowing these things means that his ignorance or doubts about other aspects don't undermine the certainty of his reasoning. Being aware of his limited knowledge doesn’t have to make him distrust what he does know."
Paley's 'Natural Theology,' chap. i.
Paley's 'Natural Theology,' chapter 1.
Evolution, Old & New
Or the Theories of Buffon, Dr.
Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck,
as compared with that of
Charles Darwin
Or the theories of Buffon, Dr. Erasmus Darwin, and Lamarck,
compared to that of Charles Darwin.
by
by
Samuel Butler
Sam Butler
New York
E. P. Dutton & Company
681 Fifth Avenue
New York
E. P. Dutton & Company
681 Fifth Avenue
Made and printed in
Great Britain
Made and printed in
UK
The demand for a new edition of "Evolution, Old and New," gives me an opportunity of publishing Butler's latest revision of his work. The second edition of "Evolution, Old and New," which was published in 1882 and re-issued with a new title-page in 1890, was merely a re-issue of the first edition with a new preface, an appendix, and an index. At a later date, though I cannot say precisely when, Butler revised the text of the book in view of a future edition. The corrections that he made are mainly verbal and do not, I think, affect the argument to any considerable extent. Butler, however, attached sufficient importance to them to incur the expense of having the stereos of more than fifty pages cancelled and new stereos substituted. I have also added a few entries to the index, which are taken from a copy of the book, now in my possession, in which Butler made a few manuscript notes.
The demand for a new edition of "Evolution, Old and New" gives me the chance to publish Butler's latest revision of his work. The second edition of "Evolution, Old and New," published in 1882 and re-issued with a new title page in 1890, was simply a re-release of the first edition with a new preface, an appendix, and an index. Later on, although I can't say exactly when, Butler revised the text of the book in preparation for a future edition. The corrections he made are mostly verbal and, I believe, don’t significantly impact the argument. However, Butler thought they were important enough to cover the cost of cancelling the stereos for more than fifty pages and having new ones made. I've also added a few entries to the index, which come from a copy of the book I have in my possession, where Butler made some handwritten notes.
R. A. STREATFEILD.
R.A. Streatfeild.
October, 1911.
October 1911.
AUTHOR'S PREFACE
TO
THE SECOND EDITION
AUTHOR'S PREFACE
TO
THE 2ND EDITION
Since the proof-sheets of the Appendix to this book left my hands, finally corrected, and too late for me to be able to recast the first of the two chapters that compose it, I hear, with the most profound regret, of the death of Mr. Charles Darwin.
Since the proof-sheets of the Appendix to this book were finalized and it was too late for me to revise the first of the two chapters that make it up, I’m deeply saddened to hear about the death of Mr. Charles Darwin.
It being still possible for me to refer to this event in a preface, I hasten to say how much it grates upon me to appear to renew my attack upon Mr. Darwin under the present circumstances.
It’s still possible for me to mention this event in a preface, so I want to quickly say how much it bothers me to seemingly restart my criticism of Mr. Darwin under the current circumstances.
I have insisted in each of my three books on Evolution upon the immensity of the service which Mr. Darwin rendered to that transcendently important theory. In "Life and Habit," I said: "To the end of time, if the question be asked, 'Who taught people to believe in Evolution?' the answer must be that it was Mr. Darwin." This is true; and it is hard to see what palm of higher praise can be awarded to any philosopher.
I have emphasized in each of my three books on Evolution the incredible contribution that Mr. Darwin made to this profoundly important theory. In "Life and Habit," I stated: "For as long as time goes on, if someone asks, 'Who encouraged people to believe in Evolution?' the answer will have to be Mr. Darwin." This is true; and it's difficult to think of a higher compliment that could be given to any philosopher.
I have always admitted myself to be under the deepest obligations to Mr. Darwin's works; and it was with the greatest reluctance, not to say repugnance,[Pg viii] that I became one of his opponents. I have partaken of his hospitality, and have had too much experience of the charming simplicity of his manner not to be among the readiest to at once admire and envy it. It is unfortunately true that I believe Mr. Darwin to have behaved badly to me; this is too notorious to be denied; but at the same time I cannot be blind to the fact that no man can be judge in his own case, and that after all Mr. Darwin may have been right, and I wrong.
I have always acknowledged that I owe a lot to Mr. Darwin's works; and it was with great reluctance, if not outright reluctance,[Pg viii] that I became one of his critics. I have enjoyed his hospitality, and I've had enough experience with his charming simplicity to readily admire and envy it. Unfortunately, I do believe Mr. Darwin has treated me poorly; this is too well-known to deny; but at the same time, I can't ignore the fact that no one can be objective about their own situation, and ultimately, Mr. Darwin might be right, and I could be wrong.
At the present moment, let me impress this latter alternative upon my mind as far as possible, and dwell only upon that side of Mr. Darwin's work and character, about which there is no difference of opinion among either his admirers or his opponents.
Right now, let me focus on this latter option as much as I can, and only consider that aspect of Mr. Darwin's work and character where there’s no disagreement among his supporters or critics.
April 21, 1882.
April 21, 1882.
Contrary to the advice of my friends, who caution me to avoid all appearance of singularity, I venture upon introducing a practice, the expediency of which I will submit to the judgment of the reader. It is one which has been adopted by musicians for more than a century—to the great convenience of all who are fond of music—and I observe that within the last few years two such distinguished painters as Mr. Alma-Tadema and Mr. Hubert Herkomer have taken to it. It is a matter for regret that the practice should not have been general at an earlier date, not only among painters and musicians, but also among the people who write books. It consists in signifying the number of a piece of music, picture, or book by the abbreviation "Op." and the number whatever it may happen to be.
Against the advice of my friends, who warn me to avoid looking unique, I’m going to introduce a practice that I’ll leave up to the reader to judge. This practice has been used by musicians for over a century—greatly benefiting all music lovers—and I’ve noticed that in the past few years, two well-known painters, Mr. Alma-Tadema and Mr. Hubert Herkomer, have adopted it as well. It’s unfortunate that this practice wasn’t more common earlier, not just among painters and musicians, but also among authors. It involves designating the number of a piece of music, artwork, or book with the abbreviation "Op." followed by the respective number.
No work can be judged intelligently unless not only the author's relations to his surroundings, but also the relation in which the work stands to the life and other works of the author, is understood and borne in mind; nor do I know any way of conveying this information at a glance, comparable to that which I now borrow from musicians. When we see the number against a work of Beethoven, we need ask no further to be informed concerning the general character of the[Pg x] music. The same holds good more or less with all composers. Handel's works were not numbered—not at least his operas and oratorios. Had they been so, the significance of the numbers on Susanna and Theodora would have been at once apparent, connected as they would have been with the number on Jephthah, Handel's next and last work, in which he emphatically repudiates the influence which, perhaps in a time of self-distrust, he had allowed contemporary German music to exert over him. Many painters have dated their works, but still more have neglected doing so, and some of these have been not a little misconceived in consequence. As for authors, it is unnecessary to go farther back than Lord Beaconsfield, Thackeray, Dickens, and Scott, to feel how much obliged we should have been to any custom that should have compelled them to number their works in the order in which they were written. When we think of Shakespeare, any doubt which might remain as to the advantage of the proposed innovation is felt to disappear.
No work can be understood properly unless we consider both the author's relationship with their surroundings and how the work relates to the author's life and other works. I don't know of any better way to convey this at a glance than what I borrow from musicians. When we see the number assigned to a piece by Beethoven, we instantly grasp the general character of the music. This is true for most composers. Handel's works weren’t numbered—at least not his operas and oratorios. If they had been, the significance of the numbers for Susanna and Theodora would have been clear, as they would connect to the number for Jephthah, Handel's next and last work, where he strongly rejects the influence that contemporary German music, perhaps during a time of self-doubt, had on him. Many painters dated their works, but many more did not, leading to some misunderstandings. As for authors, looking back to figures like Lord Beaconsfield, Thackeray, Dickens, and Scott shows how much we would have benefited from a system that numbered their works in the order they were written. When we think of Shakespeare, any lingering doubts about the need for this change seem to fade away.
My friends, to whom I urged all the above, and more, met me by saying that the practice was doubtless a very good one in the abstract, but that no one was particularly likely to want to know in what order my books had been written. To which I answered that even a bad book which introduced so good a custom would not be without value, though the value might lie in the custom, and not in the book itself; whereon, seeing that I was obstinate, they left me, and interpreting their doing so into at any rate a modified approbation of my design, I have carried it into practice.[Pg xi]
My friends, to whom I suggested all the above and more, responded by saying that while the idea was certainly good in theory, no one would really care about the order in which I wrote my books. To this, I replied that even a poorly written book that encouraged such a positive practice would still have some value, even if that value was more in the practice itself than the book. Eventually, since I was being stubborn, they left me, and I took that as a somewhat modified approval of my plan, so I went ahead and put it into action.[Pg xi]
The edition of the 'Philosophie Zoologique' referred to in the following volume, is that edited by M. Chas. Martins, Paris, Librairie F. Savy, 24, Rue de Hautefeuille, 1873.
The edition of the 'Philosophie Zoologique' mentioned in the following volume is the one edited by M. Chas. Martins, Paris, Librairie F. Savy, 24, Rue de Hautefeuille, 1873.
The edition of the 'Origin of Species' is that of 1876, unless another edition be especially named.
The edition of the 'Origin of Species' is from 1876, unless another edition is specifically mentioned.
The italics throughout the book are generally mine, except in the quotations from Miss Seward, where they are all her own.
The italics in the book are mostly my doing, except for the quotes from Miss Seward, which are all hers.
I am anxious also to take the present opportunity of acknowledging the obligations I am under to my friend Mr. H. F. Jones, and to other friends (who will not allow me to mention their names, lest more errors should be discovered than they or I yet know of), for the invaluable assistance they have given me while this work was going through the press. If I am able to let it go before the public with any comfort or peace of mind, I owe it entirely to the carefulness of their supervision.
I’m also eager to take this chance to recognize the help I’ve received from my friend Mr. H. F. Jones, along with other friends (who prefer to remain anonymous to avoid having their names linked to any mistakes we might not have caught yet) for their invaluable support while this work was being published. If I can release it to the public with any sense of comfort or peace of mind, I owe that entirely to their careful oversight.
I am also greatly indebted to Mr. Garnett, of the British Museum, for having called my attention to many works and passages of which otherwise I should have known nothing.
I also owe a big thanks to Mr. Garnett from the British Museum for pointing out many works and passages that I otherwise wouldn't have known about.
March 31, 1879.
March 31, 1879.
CHAPTER I. | |
Statement of the Question—Current Opinion Against Teleology | 1 |
CHAPTER II. | |
The Teleology of Paley and the Theologians | 12 |
CHAPTER III. | |
The Weakness of Paley's Conclusion—The Purposefulness of the Evolutionist | 24 |
CHAPTER IV. | |
The First Evolutionists' Failure to Recognize Their Position as Teleological | 34 |
CHAPTER V. | |
The Purposeful Evolution of Organisms—The Philosophy of the Unconscious | 43 |
CHAPTER VI. | |
Outline of the Remaining Work—Historical Overview of the Theory of Evolution | 60 |
CHAPTER VII. | |
Pre-Buffonian Evolution and Some German Writers | 68 |
CHAPTER VIII. | |
Buffon—Biography | 74 |
CHAPTER IX. | |
Buffon's Method—The Ironic Nature of His Work | 78 |
CHAPTER X. | |
Alleged Changes in Opinion—Causes or Methods of Species Transformation | 97 |
CHAPTER XI. | |
Buffon—Puller Quotes | 107 |
CHAPTER XII. | |
A Brief Overview of Dr. Erasmus Darwin's Life | 173 |
CHAPTER XIII. | |
Philosophy of Dr. Erasmus Darwin | 195 |
CHAPTER XIV. | |
Fuller Quotes from the 'Zoonomia' | 214 |
CHAPTER XV. | |
Lamarck's Memoir | 235 |
CHAPTER XVI. | |
Common Misunderstanding About Lamarck—His Philosophical Stance | 244 |
CHAPTER XVII. | |
Summary of 'Zoological Philosophy' | 261 |
CHAPTER XVIII. | |
Mr. Patrick Matthew, MM. Étienne and Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire, and Mr. Herbert Spencer | 315 |
CHAPTER XIX. | |
Main Points of Agreement and Difference Between the Old and New Theories of Evolution | 335 |
CHAPTER XX. | |
Natural Selection Viewed as a Method of Change—The Confusion Caused by This Term | 345 |
CHAPTER XXI. | |
Mr. Darwin's Defense of the Term, Natural Selection—Professor Mivart and Natural Selection | 362 |
CHAPTER XXII. | |
The Case of the Madeira Beetles Illustrating the Difference Between Lamarck's Evolution and Charles Darwin's—Conclusion | 373 |
APPENDIX | 385 |
INDEX | 409 |
EVOLUTION, OLD AND NEW
STATEMENT OF THE QUESTION. CURRENT OPINION ADVERSE TO TELEOLOGY.
STATEMENT OF THE QUESTION. CURRENT OPINION AGAINST TELEOLOGY.
Of all the questions now engaging the attention of those whose destiny has commanded them to take more or less exercise of mind, I know of none more interesting than that which deals with what is called teleology—that is to say, with design or purpose, as evidenced by the different parts of animals and plants.
Of all the questions capturing the interest of those whose destiny has led them to engage in some form of intellectual exercise, I know of none more intriguing than the one related to what we call teleology—that is, the design or purpose seen in the various parts of animals and plants.
The question may be briefly stated thus:—
The question can be simply put like this:—
Can we or can we not see signs in the structure of animals and plants, of something which carries with it the idea of contrivance so strongly that it is impossible for us to think of the structure, without at the same time thinking of contrivance, or design, in connection with it?
Can we or can we not see signs in the structure of animals and plants, of something that suggests design so clearly that it’s impossible for us to think about their structure without also considering design or intention along with it?
It is my object in the present work to answer this question in the affirmative, and to lead my reader to agree with me, perhaps mainly, by following the history[Pg 2] of that opinion which is now supposed to be fatal to a purposive view of animal and vegetable organs. I refer to the theory of evolution or descent with modification.
It is my goal in this work to answer this question positively and to convince my reader to agree with me, mainly by exploring the history[Pg 2] of the opinion that is now considered detrimental to a purposeful understanding of animal and plant organs. I am referring to the theory of evolution or descent with modification.
Let me state the question more at large.
Let me broaden the question a bit.
When we see organs, or living tools—for there is no well-developed organ of any living being which is not used by its possessor as an instrument or tool for the effecting of some purpose which he considers or has considered for his advantage—when we see living tools which are as admirably fitted for the work required of them, as is the carpenter's plane for planing, or the blacksmith's hammer and anvil for the hammering of iron, or the tailor's needle for sewing, what conclusion shall we adopt concerning them?
When we look at organs, or living tools—because there isn't a well-developed organ in any living being that isn't used by its owner as a tool to achieve some goal they think is beneficial for them—when we observe living tools that are perfectly suited for the tasks they perform, just like a carpenter's plane for smoothing wood, or a blacksmith's hammer and anvil for shaping metal, or a tailor's needle for stitching fabric, what conclusion should we reach about them?
Shall we hold that they must have been designed or contrived, not perhaps by mental processes indistinguishable from those by which the carpenter's saw or the watch has been designed, but still by processes so closely resembling these that no word can be found to express the facts of the case so nearly as the word "design"? That is to say, shall we imagine that they were arrived at by a living mind as the result of scheming and contriving, and thinking (not without occasional mistakes) which of the courses open to it seemed best fitted for the occasion, or are we to regard the apparent connection between such an organ, we will say, as the eye, and the sight which is affected by it, as in no way due to the design or plan of a living intelligent being, but as caused simply by the accumulation, one upon another, of an almost infinite series of small pieces of good fortune?[Pg 3]
Should we believe that they were designed or created, not necessarily through mental processes identical to those used to create a carpenter's saw or a watch, but through processes similar enough that no term fits the situation better than "design"? In other words, should we think that they resulted from a living mind actively planning and thinking (not without some errors) about which of the available options was most suitable for the situation, or should we see the apparent connection between something like the eye and the vision it influences as not the result of the design or plan of a living intelligent being, but merely a product of countless instances of good luck stacked on top of one another?[Pg 3]
In other words, shall we see something for which, as Professor Mivart has well said, "to us the word 'mind' is the least inadequate and misleading symbol," as having given to the eagle an eyesight which can pierce the sun, but which, in the night is powerless; while to the owl it has given eyes which shun even the full moon, but find a soft brilliancy in darkness? Or shall we deny that there has been any purpose or design in the fashioning of these different kinds of eyes, and see nothing to make us believe that any living being made the eagle's eye out of something which was not an eye nor anything like one, or that this living being implanted this particular eye of all others in the eagle's head, as being most in accordance with the habits of the creature, and as therefore most likely to enable it to live contentedly and leave plenitude of offspring? And shall we then go on to maintain that the eagle's eye was formed little by little by a series of accidental variations, each one of which was thrown for, as it were, with dice?
In other words, can we look at this as something that, as Professor Mivart has aptly put it, “to us the word ‘mind’ is the least inadequate and misleading symbol,” which has granted the eagle eyesight strong enough to pierce the sun, but leaves it blind at night; while the owl has been given eyes that avoid even the full moon, yet shine softly in the dark? Or should we reject the idea that there’s been any purpose or design behind these different types of eyes and see nothing to suggest that a living being crafted the eagle's eye from something that wasn't an eye or anything similar, or that this living being specifically chose this eye for the eagle to best suit its habits, making it more likely to live well and produce many offspring? And should we then insist that the eagle's eye developed gradually through a series of random variations, each decided as if by rolling dice?
We shall most of us feel that there must have been a little cheating somewhere with these accidental variations before the eagle could have become so great a winner.
We all probably think that there must have been a bit of luck involved with these random changes before the eagle could have become such a big winner.
I believe I have now stated the question at issue so plainly that there can be no mistake about its nature, I will therefore proceed to show as briefly as possible what have been the positions taken in regard to it by our forefathers, by the leaders of opinion now living, and what I believe will be the next conclusion that will be adopted for any length of time by any considerable number of people.[Pg 4]
I think I've made the question clear enough that there shouldn't be any confusion about what it involves. So, I will now briefly outline the views held by our ancestors, the current thought leaders, and what I believe will be the next conclusion that a significant number of people will accept for a while.[Pg 4]
In the times of the ancients the preponderance of opinion was in favour of teleology, though impugners were not wanting. Aristotle[1] leant towards a denial of purpose, while Plato[2] was a firm believer in design. From the days of Plato to our own times, there have been but few objectors to the teleological or purposive view of nature. If an animal had an eye, that eye was regarded as something which had been designed in order to enable its owner to see after such fashion as should be most to its advantage.
In ancient times, most people believed in teleology, although there were some who disagreed. Aristotle[1] leaned towards rejecting the idea of purpose, while Plato[2] strongly believed in design. From Plato's era to today, there have been very few critics of the teleological or purposeful view of nature. If an animal had an eye, it was seen as something designed to help it see in a way that would be most beneficial for it.
This, however, is now no longer the prevailing opinion either in this country or in Germany.
This, however, is no longer the common opinion in this country or in Germany.
Professor Haeckel holds a high place among the leaders of German philosophy at the present day. He declares a belief in evolution and in purposiveness to be incompatible, and denies purpose in language which holds out little prospect of a compromise.
Professor Haeckel is a prominent figure in contemporary German philosophy. He asserts that belief in evolution and the idea of purpose are incompatible, and he rejects the notion of purpose in language, which offers little hope for a middle ground.
"As soon, in fact," he writes, "as we acknowledge the exclusive activity of the physico-chemical causes in living (organic) bodies as well as in so-called inanimate (inorganic) nature,"—and this is what Professor Haeckel holds we are bound to do if we accept the theory of descent with modification—"we concede exclusive dominion to that view of the universe, which we may designate as mechanical, and which is opposed to the teleological conception. If we compare all the ideas of the universe prevalent among different nations at different times, we can divide them all into two[Pg 5] sharply contrasted groups—a causal or mechanical, and a teleological or vitalistic. The latter has prevailed generally in biology until now, and accordingly the animal and vegetable kingdoms have been considered as the products of a creative power, acting for a definite purpose. In the contemplation of every organism, the unavoidable conviction seemed to press itself upon us, that such a wonderful machine, so complicated an apparatus for motion as exists in the organism, could only be produced by a power analogous to, but infinitely more powerful than the power of man in the construction of his machines."[3]
"As soon as we recognize that the physico-chemical processes are the sole factors in living (organic) bodies as well as in what we call inanimate (inorganic) nature,"—and this is what Professor Haeckel argues we must accept if we embrace the theory of evolution—"we give complete authority to that view of the universe, which we can label as mechanical, and which stands in contrast to the teleological perspective. If we look at all the ideas about the universe that have existed among different cultures throughout history, we can categorize them into two[Pg 5] clearly differentiated groups—a causal or mechanical, and a teleological or vitalistic. The latter has been the dominant view in biology until now, leading to the belief that the animal and plant kingdoms are the products of a creative force, working with a specific intent. When we examine any organism, it becomes increasingly evident that such an intricate machine, such a complex mechanism for motion that exists in living beings, could only arise from a power similar to, yet infinitely greater than, the power of humans in building their machines."[3]
A little lower down he continues:—
A little further down, he continues:—
"I maintain with regard to" this "much talked of 'purpose in nature' that it has no existence but for those persons who observe phenomena in plants and animals in the most superficial manner. Without going more deeply into the matter, we can see at once that the rudimentary organs are a formidable obstacle to this theory. And, indeed, anyone who makes a really close study of the organization and mode of life of the various animals and plants, ... must necessarily come to the conclusion, that this 'purposiveness' no more exists than the much talked of 'beneficence' of the Creator."[4]
"I maintain regarding" this "much-discussed 'purpose in nature' that it only exists for those who observe phenomena in plants and animals in the most superficial way. Without delving deeper, we can immediately see that the rudimentary organs are a significant challenge to this theory. And, indeed, anyone who thoroughly studies the organization and way of life of different animals and plants, ... must inevitably conclude that this 'purposiveness' exists no more than the much-discussed 'beneficence' of the Creator."[4]
Professor Haeckel justly sees no alternative between, upon the one hand, the creation of independent species by a Personal God—by a "Creator," in fact, who "becomes an organism, who designs a plan, reflects upon and varies this plan, and finally forms creatures according[Pg 6] to it, as a human architect would construct his building,"[5]—and the denial of all plan or purpose whatever. There can be no question but that he is right here. To talk of a "designer" who has no tangible existence, no organism with which to think, no bodily mechanism with which to carry his purposes into effect; whose design is not design inasmuch as it has to contend with no impediments from ignorance or impotence, and who thus contrives but by a sort of make-believe in which there is no contrivance; who has a familiar name, but nothing beyond a name which any human sense has ever been able to perceive—this is an abuse of words—an attempt to palm off a shadow upon our understandings as though it were a substance. It is plain therefore that there must either be a designer who "becomes an organism, designs a plan, &c.," or that there can be no designer at all and hence no design.
Professor Haeckel rightly sees no alternative between, on one hand, the creation of independent species by a Personal God—a "Creator" who "becomes an organism, designs a plan, reflects on and modifies this plan, and ultimately creates creatures according to it, just like a human architect builds his structure,"[Pg 6][5]—and the complete rejection of any plan or purpose. There's no doubt that he is correct here. To speak of a "designer" who has no real existence, no organism to think with, no physical mechanism to carry out his intentions; whose design isn't really a design as it faces no challenges from ignorance or inability, and who thus comes up with concepts through a kind of fantasy where there's no real creation; who has a familiar title but nothing more than a name that any human sense has ever been able to grasp—this is a misuse of language—an attempt to pass off a shadow as if it were a substance. So, it's clear that there must either be a designer who "becomes an organism, designs a plan, etc.," or there can be no designer at all and therefore no design.
We have seen which of these alternatives Professor Haeckel has adopted. He holds that those who accept evolution are bound to reject all "purposiveness." And here, as I have intimated, I differ from him, for reasons which will appear presently. I believe in an organic and tangible designer of every complex structure, for so long a time past, as that reasonable people will be incurious about all that occurred at any earlier time.
We have seen which of these options Professor Haeckel has chosen. He believes that those who accept evolution must reject all notions of "purpose." And here, as I've hinted, I disagree with him for reasons that will become clear shortly. I believe in a concrete and organic designer of every complex structure, so much so that reasonable people will be uninterested in what happened at any earlier time.
Professor Clifford, again, is a fair representative of opinions which are finding favour with the majority of our own thinkers. He writes:—
Professor Clifford is a good representative of the views that are gaining popularity among most of our thinkers. He writes:—
"There are here some words, however, which require careful definition. And first the word purpose. A[Pg 7] thing serves a purpose when it is adapted for some end; thus a corkscrew is adapted to the end of extracting corks from bottles, and our lungs are adapted to the end of respiration. We may say that the extraction of corks is the purpose of the corkscrew, and that respiration is the purpose of the lungs, but here we shall have used the word in two different senses. A man made the corkscrew with a purpose in his mind, and he knew and intended that it should be used for pulling out corks. But nobody made our lungs with a purpose in his mind and intended that they should be used for breathing. The respiratory apparatus was adapted to its purpose by natural selection, namely, by the gradual preservation of better and better adaptations, and by the killing-off of the worse and imperfect adaptations."[6]
There are some words here that need to be clearly defined. First, let's look at the word "purpose." A thing serves a purpose when it's designed for a specific function; for example, a corkscrew is designed to pull corks out of bottles, and our lungs are designed for breathing. We can say that pulling corks is the purpose of the corkscrew, and that breathing is the purpose of the lungs, but in doing so, we're using the word in two different ways. A person created the corkscrew with a specific purpose in mind, and he intended for it to be used for removing corks. However, nobody created our lungs with a specific purpose in mind or intended for them to be used for breathing. The respiratory system was shaped for its function through natural selection, which means it gradually preserved better adaptations while eliminating less effective and imperfect ones.[6]
No denial of anything like design could be more explicit. For Professor Clifford is well aware that the very essence of the "Natural Selection" theory, is that the variations shall have been mainly accidental and without design of any sort, but that the adaptations of structure to need shall have come about by the accumulation, through natural selection, of any variation that happened to be favourable.
No denial of anything resembling design could be more clear. Professor Clifford knows that the core of the "Natural Selection" theory is that the variations are primarily random and without any intention, but that the adaptations in structure to meet needs occur through the accumulation of any variation that just so happens to be beneficial, thanks to natural selection.
It will be my business on a later page not only to show that the lungs are as purposive as the corkscrew, but furthermore that if drawing corks had been a matter of as much importance to us as breathing is, the list of our organs would have been found to comprise one corkscrew at the least, and possibly two, twenty, or ten thousand; even as we see that the trowel without which[Pg 8] the beaver cannot plaster its habitation in such fashion as alone satisfies it, is incorporate into the beaver's own body by way of a tail, the like of which is to be found in no other animal.
It will be my job on a later page not only to show that the lungs are just as purposeful as a corkscrew, but also that if removing corks had been as important to us as breathing is, our list of organs would have included at least one corkscrew, and possibly two, twenty, or even ten thousand; just like we see that the trowel, which the beaver needs to construct its home in the way it prefers, is incorporated into the beaver’s own body through its tail, which no other animal has.
To take a name which carries with it a far greater authority, that of Mr. Charles Darwin. He writes:—
To use a name that holds much more authority, that of Mr. Charles Darwin. He writes:—
"It is scarcely possible to avoid comparing the eye with a telescope. We know that this instrument has been perfected by the long-continued efforts of the highest human intellects; and we naturally infer that the eye has been formed by a somewhat analogous process. But may not this inference be presumptuous? Have we any right to declare that the Creator works by intellectual powers like those of man?"[7]
"It’s hard not to compare the eye to a telescope. We know this instrument has been refined through the sustained efforts of the greatest human minds; so it's natural to think that the eye has been shaped by a similar process. But could this assumption be arrogant? Do we have any right to say that the Creator works using intellectual powers similar to ours?"[7]
Here purposiveness is not indeed denied point-blank, but the intention of the author is unmistakable, it is to refer the wonderful result to the gradual accumulation of small accidental improvements which were not due as a rule, if at all, to anything "analogous" to design.
Here, the concept of purpose isn't outright rejected, but the author's intention is clear: it's to attribute the remarkable outcome to the gradual buildup of minor accidental improvements that typically weren't the result of anything "similar" to design.
"Variation," he says, "will cause the slight alterations;" that is to say, the slight successive variations whose accumulation results in such a marvellous structure as the eye, are caused by—variation; or in other words, they are indefinite, due to nothing that we can lay our hands upon, and therefore certainly not due to design. "Generation," continues Mr. Darwin, "will multiply them almost infinitely, and natural selection will pick out with unerring skill each improvement. Let this process go on for millions of years, and during each year on millions of individuals of many kinds; and[Pg 9] may we not believe that a living optical instrument might be thus formed as superior to one of glass, as the works of the Creator are to those of man?"[8]
"Variation," he states, "will cause the slight changes;" in other words, the small, gradual variations that build up to create something as incredible as the eye come from—variation. They are not definite, stemming from something intangible that we cannot grasp, and therefore definitely not from design. "Generation," Mr. Darwin goes on, "will increase these variations almost infinitely, and natural selection will skillfully identify each improvement. If this process continues for millions of years, affecting millions of individuals of various kinds each year; can we not believe that a living optical instrument could be formed that is better than one made of glass, just as the works of the Creator surpass those of man?"[Pg 9][8]
The reader will observe that the only skill—and this involves design—supposed by Mr. Darwin to be exercised in the foregoing process, is the "unerring skill" of natural selection. Natural selection, however, is, as he himself tells us, a synonym for the survival of the fittest, which last he declares to be the "more accurate" expression, and to be "sometimes" equally convenient.[9] It is clear then that he only speaks metaphorically when he here assigns "unerring skill" to the fact that the fittest individuals commonly live longest and transmit most offspring, and that he sees no evidence of design in the numerous slight successive "alterations"—or variations—which are "caused by variation."
The reader will notice that the only skill—and this includes design—that Mr. Darwin suggests is involved in the process discussed is the "unerring skill" of natural selection. However, as he points out, natural selection is just another way of saying the survival of the fittest, which he claims is the "more accurate" term and is "sometimes" equally useful.[9] It’s clear then that he is speaking metaphorically when he attributes "unerring skill" to the idea that the fittest individuals usually live longer and have more offspring, and that he sees no evidence of design in the many small successive "alterations"—or variations—that result from "variation."
It were easy to multiply quotations which should prove that the denial of "purposiveness" is commonly conceived to be the inevitable accompaniment of a belief in evolution. I will, however, content myself with but one more—from Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire.
It would be easy to gather many quotes to show that denying "purposiveness" is usually seen as a natural part of believing in evolution. However, I’ll stick to just one more—from Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire.
"Whoever," says this author, "holds the doctrine of final causes, will, if he is consistent, hold also that of the immutability of species; and again, the opponent of the one doctrine will oppose the other also."[10]
"Whoever," says this author, "believes in the concept of final causes will, if they are consistent, also believe in the immutability of species; and likewise, someone who opposes one concept will also oppose the other."[10]
Nothing can be plainer; I believe, however, that even without quotation the reader would have recognized[Pg 10] the accuracy of my contention that a belief in the purposiveness or design of animal and vegetable organs is commonly held to be incompatible with the belief that they have all been evolved from one, or at any rate, from not many original, and low, forms of life. Generally, however, as this incompatibility is accepted, it is not unchallenged. From time to time a voice is uplifted in protest, whose tones cannot be disregarded.
Nothing could be clearer; I believe, though, that even without quoting, the reader would recognize[Pg 10] the accuracy of my point that believing in the purpose or design of animal and plant organs is often seen as incompatible with the idea that they all evolved from a single, or at least a few, simple forms of life. However, while this incompatibility is widely accepted, it is not without opposition. Occasionally, a voice speaks up in protest, and its message cannot be ignored.
"I have always felt," says Sir William Thomson, in his address to the British Association, 1871, "that this hypothesis" (natural selection) "does not contain the true theory of evolution, if indeed evolution there has been, in biology. Sir John Herschel, in expressing a favourable judgment on the hypothesis of zoological evolution (with however some reservation in respect to the origin of man), objected to the doctrine of natural selection on the ground that it was too like the Laputan method of making books, and that it did not sufficiently take into account a continually guiding and controlling intelligence. This seems to me a most valuable and instructive criticism. I feel profoundly convinced that the argument of design has been greatly too much lost sight of in recent zoological speculations. Reaction against the frivolities of teleology such as are to be found in the notes of the learned commentators on Paley's 'Natural Theology,' has, I believe, had a temporary effect in turning attention from the solid and irrefragable argument so well put forward in that excellent old book. But overpoweringly strong proofs of intelligent and benevolent design lie all around us,"[11] &c. [Pg 11]Sir William Thomson goes on to infer that all living beings depend on an ever-acting Creator and Ruler—meaning, I am afraid, a Creator who is not an organism. Here I cannot follow him, but while gladly accepting his testimony to the omnipresence of intelligent design in almost every structure, whether of animal or plant, I shall content myself with observing the manner in which plants and animals act and with the consequences that are legitimately deducible from their action.
"I've always felt," says Sir William Thomson in his speech to the British Association in 1871, "that this hypothesis" (natural selection) "doesn't capture the true theory of evolution, if evolution has indeed occurred in biology. Sir John Herschel, while giving a positive view of the hypothesis of zoological evolution (though with some reservations about the origin of humans), criticized the doctrine of natural selection on the grounds that it resembled the Laputan method of creating books and failed to adequately acknowledge a consistently guiding and controlling intelligence. I believe this is a very valuable and instructive critique. I am deeply convinced that the argument of design has been significantly overlooked in recent zoological theories. The backlash against the trivialities of teleology found in the comments of learned commentators on Paley's 'Natural Theology' has, I believe, temporarily shifted focus away from the solid and undeniable arguments presented in that excellent old book. But overwhelming evidence of intelligent and benevolent design surrounds us,"[11] &c. [Pg 11] Sir William Thomson goes on to suggest that all living beings rely on an ever-active Creator and Ruler—implying, I fear, a Creator who is not an organism. Here, I cannot follow him, but while I gladly acknowledge his assertion of the omnipresence of intelligent design in almost every structure, whether in animals or plants, I will focus on observing how plants and animals behave and the conclusions that can rightfully be drawn from their behavior.
FOOTNOTES:
[1] See note to Mr. Darwin, Historical Sketch, &c., 'Origin of Species, p. xiii. ed. 1876, and Arist. 'Physicæ Auscultationes,' lib. ii. cap. viii. s. 2.
[1] See note to Mr. Darwin, Historical Sketch, &c., 'Origin of Species, p. xiii. ed. 1876, and Arist. 'Physics Studies,' book ii. chapter viii. section 2.
[2] See Phædo and Timæus.
[4] Ibid. p. 19.
Ibid. p. 19.
[9] Page 49.
THE TELEOLOGY OF PALEY AND THE THEOLOGIANS.
THE TELEOLOGY OF PALEY AND THE THEOLOGIANS.
Let us turn for a while to Paley, to whom Sir W. Thomson has referred us. His work should be so well known that an apology is almost due for quoting it, yet I think it likely that at least nine out of ten of my readers will (like myself till reminded of it by Sir W. Thomson's address) have forgotten its existence.
Let’s take a moment to look at Paley, who Sir W. Thomson mentioned. His work should be familiar enough that I should probably apologize for quoting it, but I suspect that at least nine out of ten of my readers will, like I did until Sir W. Thomson's address brought it back to mind, have forgotten about it.
"In crossing a heath," says Paley, "suppose I pitched my foot against a stone, and were asked how the stone came to be there; I might possibly answer that for anything I knew to the contrary, it had lain there for ever; nor would it perhaps be very easy to show the absurdity of this answer. But suppose I had found a watch upon the ground, and it should be inquired how the watch happened to be in that place; I should hardly think of the answer I had before given—that for anything I knew the watch might have been always there. Yet, why should not this answer serve for the watch as well as for the stone? Why is it not as admissible in the second case as in the first? For this reason, and for no other, viz. that when we come to inspect the watch, we perceive (what we could not discover in the stone) that its several parts are framed and put together[Pg 13] for a purpose, e. g. that they are so formed and adjusted as to produce motion, and that motion so regulated as to point out the hour of the day: that if the different parts had been differently shaped from what they are, of a different size from what they are, or placed after any other manner, or in any other order, than that in which they are placed, either no motion at all would have been carried on in the machine, or none that would have answered the use which is now served by it. To reckon up a few of the plainest of these parts, and of their offices all tending to one result: we see a cylindrical box containing a coiled elastic spring, which, by its endeavours to relax itself, turns round the box. We next observe a flexible chain (artificially wrought for the sake of flexure) communicating the action of the spring from the box to the fusee. We then find a series of wheels the teeth of which catch in, and apply to each other, conducting the motion from the fusee to the balance, and from the balance to the pointer; and at the same time by the size and shape of those wheels so regulating the motion as to terminate in causing an index, by an equable and measured progression, to pass over a given space in a given time. We take notice that the wheels are made of brass in order to keep them from rust; the springs of steel, no other metal being so elastic; that over the face of the watch there is placed a glass, a material employed on no other part of the work, but in the room of which if there had been any other than a transparent substance, the hour could not have been observed without opening the case. This mechanism being observed, ... the inference, we[Pg 14] think, is inevitable that the watch must have had a maker; that there must have existed, at some time, and at some place or other, an artificer or artificers who formed it for the purpose which we find it actually to answer; who comprehended its construction and designed its use."[12]
"In crossing a heath," says Paley, "let's say I accidentally kicked a stone, and someone asked how the stone got there; I might answer that, for all I know, it’s been there forever. It might not be easy to show why that answer is absurd. But if I found a watch on the ground and someone inquired how the watch ended up there, I wouldn’t even think to give the same answer—that for all I know, the watch could have always been there. So why shouldn’t that answer work for the watch as well as for the stone? Why is it not acceptable in the second case as it is in the first? The reason is simple: when we examine the watch, we notice (which we can’t do with the stone) that its various parts are designed and assembled[Pg 13] for a specific purpose, for example, that they are formed and adjusted to create motion, and that this motion is controlled to indicate the time of day. If the parts had been shaped or sized differently, or arranged in any other way, then either the machine wouldn’t work at all or it wouldn’t fulfill the purpose it currently serves. To highlight just a few of the obvious parts and their functions all contributing to one result: we see a cylindrical box that holds a coiled spring, which, as it tries to unwind, turns the box. Next, there’s a flexible chain (specially crafted for bending) that transfers the spring’s action from the box to the fusee. Then we find a series of gears whose teeth fit together, transmitting motion from the fusee to the balance, and from the balance to the pointer; while regulating the motion through the size and shape of those gears to ensure that an index moves smoothly and consistently over a specific distance in a set amount of time. We notice that the gears are made of brass to prevent rust, and the springs are steel, as no other metal is as elastic; that there’s a piece of glass over the watch face, which is a material not used anywhere else in the watch, and if it were any substance other than a clear one, we wouldn’t be able to see the time without opening the case. Observing this mechanism, ... we believe the conclusion is unavoidable that the watch must have had a maker; that at some point, in some place, there was a creator or creators who designed it for the purpose we observe it serving." [12]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"That an animal is a machine, is a proposition neither correctly true nor wholly false.... I contend that there is a mechanism in animals; that this mechanism is as properly such, as it is in machines made by art; that this mechanism is intelligible and certain; that it is not the less so because it often begins and terminates with something which is not mechanical; that wherever it is intelligible and certain, it demonstrates intention and contrivance, as well in the works of nature as in those of art; and that it is the best demonstration which either can afford."[13]
"Claiming that an animal is a machine is a statement that isn't completely true or entirely false.... I argue that there is a mechanism in animals; this mechanism is just as much a mechanism as it is in machines created by humans; this mechanism can be understood and is definite; it doesn't lose clarity just because it often begins and ends with something that isn't mechanical; wherever it is understandable and definite, it shows intention and design, both in nature and in human creations; and it's the best evidence that either can provide."[13]
There is only one legitimate inference deducible from these premises if they are admitted as sound, namely, that there must have existed "at some time, and in some place, an artificer" who formed the animal mechanism after much the same mental processes of observation, endeavour, successful contrivance, and after a not wholly unlike succession of bodily actions, as those with which a watchmaker has made a watch. Otherwise the conclusion is impotent, and the whole argument becomes a mere juggle of words.
There is only one valid conclusion to draw from these premises if we accept them as true: there must have been "at some time, and in some place, a creator" who designed the animal structure using a similar process of observation, effort, successful creativity, and a reasonably comparable series of physical actions as those that a watchmaker uses to create a watch. Otherwise, the conclusion is meaningless, and the entire argument turns into just a play on words.
"Now, supposing or admitting," continues Paley, "that we know nothing of the proper internal constitution of a[Pg 15] gland, or of the mode of its acting upon the blood; then our situation is precisely like that of an unmechanical looker-on who stands by a stocking loom, a corn mill, a carding machine, or a threshing machine, at work, the fabric and mechanism of which, as well as all that passes within, is hidden from his sight by the outside case; or if seen, would be too complicated for his uninformed, uninstructed understanding to comprehend. And what is that situation? This spectator, ignorant as he is, sees at one end a material enter the machine, as unground grain the mill, raw cotton the carding machine, sheaves of unthreshed corn the threshing machine, and when he casts his eye to the other end of the apparatus, he sees the material issuing from it in a new state and what is more, a state manifestly adapted for its future uses: the grain in meal fit for the making of bread, the wool in rovings fit for the spinning into threads, the sheaf in corn fit for the mill. Is it necessary that this man, in order to be convinced that design, that intention, that contrivance has been employed about the machine, should be allowed to pull it to pieces, should be enabled to examine the parts separately, explore their action upon one another, or their operation, whether simultaneous or successive, upon the material which is presented to them? He may long to do this to satisfy his curiosity; he may desire to do it to improve his theoretic knowledge; ... but for the purpose of ascertaining the existence of counsel and design in the formation of the machine, he wants no such intromission or privity. The effect upon the material, the change produced in it, the utility of the[Pg 16] change for future applications, abundantly testify, be the concealed part of the machine, or of its construction, what it will, the hand and agency of a contriver."[14]
"Now, assuming," Paley continues, "that we know nothing about the proper internal structure of a[Pg 15] gland or how it acts on the blood; our situation is exactly like that of someone who doesn’t understand machinery, standing next to a stocking loom, a corn mill, a carding machine, or a threshing machine as they work. The design and mechanism of these machines, as well as everything happening inside, are hidden from view by their outer casing; and even if visible, they would be too complicated for an uninformed person to grasp. So what is this situation? This observer, though clueless, sees a material going into the machine, like unground grain in the mill, raw cotton in the carding machine, and sheaves of unthreshed corn in the threshing machine. When he looks at the other end of the machine, he sees the material coming out in a new state, one clearly suited for future use: the grain becomes meal for making bread, the wool turns into rovings for spinning into threads, and the sheaf turns into corn ready for the mill. Does this person need to take the machine apart, examine each part separately, or explore how they interact to be convinced that design, intention, and planning went into the machine? He may want to do this to satisfy his curiosity or enhance his theoretical knowledge; ... but to establish the existence of purpose and design in the machine’s construction, he doesn’t need to delve into its inner workings. The effect on the material, the change it undergoes, and the usefulness of that change for future applications clearly indicate, whether we understand the concealed parts of the machine or not, the hand and agency of a designer."[14]
This is admirably put, but it will apply to the mechanism of animal and vegetable bodies only, if it is used to show that they too must have had a contriver who has a hand, or something tantamount to one; who does act; who, being a contriver, has what all other contrivers must have, if they are to be called contrivers—a body which can suffer more or less pain or chagrin if the contrivance is unsuccessful. If this is what Paley means, his argument is indeed irrefragable; but if he does not intend this, his words are frivolous, as so clear and acute a reasoner must have perfectly well known.
This is well stated, but it only applies to how animal and plant bodies work if it's used to demonstrate that they too must have had a creator who has a hand, or something similar; who does take action; who, being a creator, possesses what all other creators must have to be considered creators—a body that can experience some level of pain or disappointment if the creation fails. If this is what Paley means, his argument is truly unassailable; but if that's not his intention, then his words are pointless, as such a clear and sharp thinker must have understood.
Whether Paley's argument will prove a source of lasting strength to himself or no, is a point which my readers will decide presently; but I am very clear about its usefulness to my own position. I know few writers whom I would willingly quote more largely, or from whom I find it harder to leave off quoting when I have once begun. A few more passages, however, must suffice.
Whether Paley's argument will end up being a lasting strength for him or not is something my readers will decide shortly; but I am definitely convinced of its value to my own standpoint. I know of few writers I would rather quote extensively, or from whom I find it tougher to stop quoting once I've started. A few more excerpts, however, will have to do.
"I challenge any man to produce in the joints and pivots of the most complicated or the most flexible machine that ever was contrived, a construction more artificial" (here we have it again), "or more evidently artificial than the human neck. Two things were to be done. The head was to have the power of bending forward and backward as in the act of nodding, stooping,[Pg 17] looking upwards or downwards; and at the same time of turning itself round upon the body to a certain extent, the quadrant, we will say, or rather perhaps a hundred and twenty degrees of a circle. For these two purposes two distinct contrivances are employed. First the head rests immediately upon the uppermost part of the vertebra, and is united to it by a hinge-joint; upon this joint the head plays freely backward and forward as far either way as is necessary or as the ligaments allow, which was the first thing required.
"I challenge anyone to create in the joints and pivots of the most complicated or flexible machine that has ever been designed a construction more artificial" (here we have it again), "or more obviously artificial than the human neck. Two things needed to happen. The head had to be able to bend forward and backward, like when nodding, stooping,[Pg 17] or looking up and down; and at the same time, it needed to turn around on the body to a certain degree, let’s say, or maybe about a hundred and twenty degrees of a circle. For these two tasks, two different mechanisms are used. First, the head rests directly on the top part of the vertebra and is connected to it by a hinge joint; on this joint, the head moves freely back and forth as far as necessary or as the ligaments allow, which was the first requirement.
"But then the rotatory motion is thus unprovided for; therefore, secondly, to make the head capable of this a further mechanism is introduced, not between the head and the uppermost bone of the neck, where the hinge is, but between that bone and the next underneath it. It is a mechanism resembling a tenon and mortise. This second or uppermost bone but one has what the anatomists call a process, viz. a projection somewhat similar in size and shape to a tooth, which tooth, entering a corresponding hollow socket in the bone above it, forms a pivot or axle, upon which that upper bone, together with the head which it supports, turns freely in a circle, and as far in the circle as the attached muscles permit the head to turn. Thus are both motions perfect without interfering with each other. When we nod the head we use the hinge-joint, which lies between the head and the first bone of the neck. When we turn the head round, we use the tenon and mortise, which runs between the first bone of the neck and the second. We see the same contrivance and the same principle employed in the frame or mounting of a telescope. It[Pg 18] is occasionally requisite that the object end of the instrument be moved up and down as well as horizontally or equatorially. For the vertical motion there is a hinge upon which the telescope plays, for the horizontal or equatorial motion, an axis upon which the telescope and the hinge turn round together. And this is exactly the mechanism which is applied to the action of the head, nor will anyone here doubt of the existence of counsel and design, except it be by that debility of mind which can trust to its own reasonings in nothing."[15]
"But then the rotational movement isn't accounted for; therefore, to enable the head to do this, another mechanism is added, not between the head and the top bone of the neck where the hinge is, but between that bone and the one right below it. It resembles a tenon and mortise joint. This second or uppermost bone has what anatomists refer to as a process, a projection that looks somewhat like a tooth. This tooth fits into a corresponding hollow socket in the bone above it, forming a pivot or axle, which allows that upper bone and the head it supports to turn freely in a circle, as far as the attached muscles permit. This means both movements are smooth and don't interfere with one another. When we nod our head, we use the hinge joint between the head and the first bone of the neck. When we turn our head, we use the tenon and mortise joint between the first bone of the neck and the second. We see the same design and principle in the frame or mounting of a telescope. It is sometimes necessary to move the object end of the instrument both up and down as well as side to side. For vertical movement, there is a hinge that the telescope pivots on, and for horizontal movement, there is an axis around which the telescope and hinge turn together. This is exactly the mechanism applied to the movement of the head, and no one here can doubt the existence of planning and design, except by that weakness of mind which can trust its own reasoning in nothing."[15]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"The patella, or knee-pan, is a curious little bone; in its form and office unlike any other bone in the body. It is circular, the size of a crown-piece, pretty thick, a little convex on both sides, and covered with a smooth cartilage. It lies upon the front of the knee, and the powerful tendons by which the leg is brought forward pass through it (or rather make it a part of their continuation) from their origin in the thigh to their insertion in the tibia. It protects both the tendon and the joint from any injury which either might suffer by the rubbing of one against the other, or by the pressure of unequal surfaces. It also gives to the tendons a very considerable mechanical advantage by altering the line of their direction, and by advancing it farther out of the centre of motion; and this upon the principles of the resolution of force, upon which all machinery is founded. These are its uses. But what is most observable in it is that it appears to be supplemental, as it[Pg 19] were, to the frame; added, as it should almost seem, afterwards; not quite necessary, but very convenient. It is separate from the other bones; that is, it is not connected with any other bones by the common mode of union. It is soft, or hardly formed in infancy; and is produced by an ossification, of the inception or progress of which no account can be given from the structure or exercise of the part."[16]
The patella, or kneecap, is a unique little bone; its shape and function are unlike any other bone in the body. It’s round, about the size of a coin, fairly thick, slightly curved on both sides, and covered with smooth cartilage. It sits at the front of the knee, and the strong tendons that move the leg forward pass through it (or more accurately, include it in their pathway) from their start in the thigh to their attachment in the tibia. It protects both the tendon and the joint from any injury that might occur from rubbing against each other or from pressure from uneven surfaces. It also provides the tendons with a significant mechanical advantage by changing their line of direction and moving them further away from the center of motion, based on the principles of force resolution that all machinery relies on. These are its functions. But the most notable thing about it is that it seems to be an addition to the skeletal structure; it almost looks like it was added later; not strictly necessary, but very useful. It stands alone from the other bones; that is, it isn’t connected to any other bones in the usual way. It’s soft, or barely formed in infants, and it develops through a process of ossification that can’t be easily explained by the structure or use of the part.[16]
It is positively painful to me to pass over Paley's description of the joints, but I must content myself with a single passage from this admirable chapter.
It’s really hard for me to skip over Paley’s description of the joints, but I have to settle for just one quote from this excellent chapter.
"The joints, or rather the ends of the bones which form them, display also in their configuration another use. The nerves, blood-vessels, and tendons which are necessary to the life, or for the motion of the limbs, must, it is evident in their way from the trunk of the body to the place of their destination, travel over the moveable joints; and it is no less evident that in this part of their course they will have from sudden motions, and from abrupt changes of curvature, to encounter the danger of compression, attrition, or laceration. To guard fibres so tender against consequences so injurious, their path is in those parts protected with peculiar care; and that by a provision in the figure of the bones themselves. The nerves which supply the fore arm, especially the inferior cubital nerves, are at the elbow conducted by a kind of covered way, between the condyle, or rather under the inner extuberances, of the bone which composes the upper part of the arm. At the knee the extremity of the thigh-bone is divided by[Pg 20] a sinus or cliff into two heads or protuberances; and these heads on the back part stand out beyond the cylinder of the bone. Through the hollow which lies between the hind parts of these two heads, that is to say, under the ham, between the ham strings, and within the concave recess of the bone formed by the extuberances on either side; in a word, along a defile between rocks pass the great vessels and nerves which go to the leg. Who led these vessels by a road so defended and secured? In the joint at the shoulder, in the edge of the cup which receives the head of the bone, is a notch which is covered at the top with a ligament. Through this hole thus guarded the blood-vessels steal to their destination in the arm instead of mounting over the edge of the concavity."[17]
The joints, or rather the ends of the bones that form them, show another function in their shape. The nerves, blood vessels, and tendons essential for life and movement of the limbs must travel from the body trunk to their destination. It's clear that along this route, they will have to face sudden movements and abrupt bends, which puts them at risk of being compressed, worn down, or torn. To protect these delicate fibers from such harmful effects, their path is carefully safeguarded in these areas by the structure of the bones themselves. The nerves that supply the forearm, especially the lower cubital nerves, travel at the elbow through a sort of covered passage between the condyle, or rather under the inner bumps of the bone that makes up the upper arm. At the knee, the end of the thigh bone is divided by a groove into two heads that stick out at the back beyond the cylinder of the bone. The great vessels and nerves that lead to the leg pass through the space between these two heads, meaning between the hamstrings and within the concave area of the bone formed by the bumps on either side; in short, they navigate through a narrow pathway between rock-like formations. Who directed these vessels along such a protected and secure route? In the shoulder joint, the edge of the cup that holds the head of the bone has a notch that is covered on top by a ligament. Through this guarded opening, the blood vessels make their way to the arm instead of going over the edge of the concavity.[17]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"What contrivance can be more mechanical than the following, viz.: a slit in one tendon to let another tendon pass through it? This structure is found in the tendons which move the toes and fingers. The long tendon, as it is called in the foot, which bends the first joint of the toe, passes through the short tendon which bends the second joint; which course allows to the sinews more liberty and a more commodious action than it would otherwise have been capable of exerting. There is nothing, I believe, in a silk or cotton mill, in the belts or straps or ropes by which the motion is communicated from one part of the machine to another that is more artificial, or more evidently so, than this perforation.
"What mechanism can be more mechanical than this: a slit in one tendon allowing another tendon to pass through it? This structure is found in the tendons that move the toes and fingers. The long tendon in the foot, which bends the first joint of the toe, passes through the short tendon that bends the second joint. This arrangement gives the sinews more freedom and a more efficient action than they would otherwise be able to have. There’s nothing, I believe, in a silk or cotton mill, in the belts, straps, or ropes that transmit motion from one part of the machine to another, that is more artificial or more obviously so than this perforation."
"The next circumstance which I shall mention under[Pg 21] this head of muscular arrangement, is so decidedly a mark of intention, that it always appeared to me to supersede in some measure the necessity of seeking for any other observation upon the subject; and that circumstance is the tendons which pass from the leg to the foot being bound down by a ligament at the ankle, the foot is placed at a considerable angle with the leg. It is manifest, therefore, that flexible strings passing along the interior of the angle, if left to themselves, would, when stretched, start from it. The obvious" (and it must not be forgotten that the preventive was obvious) "preventive is to tie them down. And this is done in fact. Across the instep, or rather just above it, the anatomist finds a strong ligament, under which the tendons pass to the foot. The effect of the ligament as a bandage can be made evident to the senses, for if it be cut the tendons start up. The simplicity, yet the clearness of this contrivance, its exact resemblance to established resources of art, place it amongst the most indubitable manifestations of design with which we are acquainted."
"The next point I want to mention under[Pg 21] this topic of muscular arrangement is such a clear sign of intention that it seems to me to lessen the need to look for any other observations on the subject. This point is that the tendons connecting the leg to the foot are held down by a ligament at the ankle, causing the foot to be at a significant angle to the leg. It's clear that flexible structures running along the inside of the angle, if left unsupported, would shift out of position when stretched. The obvious (and it should be noted that the preventive was obvious) solution is to secure them. And this is actually what happens. Just above the instep, the anatomist finds a strong ligament through which the tendons pass to the foot. The effect of the ligament as a binding agent can be directly observed because if it's cut, the tendons pop up. The simplicity and clarity of this design, along with its striking resemblance to established techniques in craftsmanship, make it one of the most undeniable examples of intentional design that we know of."
Then follows a passage which is interesting, as being the earliest attempt I know of to bring forward an argument against evolution, which was, even in Paley's day, called "Darwinism," after Dr. Erasmus Darwin its propounder.[18] The argument, I mean, which is drawn from the difficulty of accounting for the[Pg 22] incipiency of complex structures. This has been used with greater force by the Rev. J. J. Murphy, Professor Mivart, and others, against that (as I believe) erroneous view of evolution which is now generally received as Darwinism.
Then there's a section that’s interesting because it’s the earliest attempt I know of to present an argument against evolution, which was even referred to as "Darwinism" in Paley's time, named after Dr. Erasmus Darwin, who proposed it.[18] I mean the argument that comes from the challenge of explaining how complex structures first emerged. This has been argued more strongly by Rev. J. J. Murphy, Professor Mivart, and others against what I believe is the mistaken view of evolution that is now widely accepted as Darwinism.
"There is also a further use," says Paley, "to be made of this present example, and that is as it precisely contradicts the opinion, that the parts of animals may have been all formed by what is called appetency, i. e. endeavour, perpetuated and imperceptibly working its effect through an incalculable series of generations. We have here no endeavour, but the reverse of it; a constant resistency and reluctance. The endeavour is all the other way. The pressure of the ligament constrains the tendons; the tendons react upon the pressure of the ligament. It is impossible that the ligament should ever have been generated by the exercise of the tendons, or in the course of that exercise, forasmuch as the force of the tendon perpendicularly resists the fibre which confines it, and is constantly endeavouring not to form but to rupture and displace the threads of which the ligament is composed."[19]
"There’s also another point," Paley says, "to be made from this example, and that is that it directly contradicts the idea that the parts of animals were all formed by what is called appetency, meaning effort that is passed down and subtly influences the results over countless generations. In this case, we see no effort at all, but rather the opposite; there’s a constant resistance and reluctance. The effort is actually in the opposite direction. The tension from the ligament limits the tendons; the tendons counteract the tension from the ligament. It’s impossible for the ligament to have been formed by the action of the tendons, or through that action, because the force from the tendon directly resists the fiber that contains it, constantly trying to disrupt and displace the threads that make up the ligament."[19]
This must suffice.
This should be enough.
"True theories," says M. Flourens, inspired by a passage from Fontenelle, which he proceeds to quote, "true theories make themselves," they are not made, but are born and grow; they cannot be stopped from insisting upon their vitality by anything short of intellectual violence, nor will a little violence only suffice to kill them. "True theories," he continues,[Pg 23] "are but the spontaneous mental coming together of facts, which have combined with one another by virtue only of their own natural affinity."[20]
"True theories," says M. Flourens, inspired by a quote from Fontenelle, which he goes on to share, "true theories create themselves," they aren't constructed, but are born and develop; they can't be stopped from asserting their life force by anything less than intellectual violence, nor will just a little violence be enough to destroy them. "True theories," he continues,[Pg 23] "are simply the natural mental gathering of facts, which have combined with one another solely due to their own inherent connection."[20]
When a number of isolated facts, says Fontenelle, take form, group themselves together coherently, and present the mind so vividly with an idea of their interdependence and mutual bearing upon each other, that no matter how violently we tear them asunder they insist on coming together again; then, and not till then, have we a theory.
When several isolated facts, as Fontenelle puts it, come together, connect coherently, and clearly show us how they depend on and relate to each other, such that no matter how forcefully we pull them apart, they still keep coming back together; that’s when we have a theory, and not before.
Now I submit that there is hardly one of my readers who can be considered as free from bias or prejudice, who will not feel that the idea of design—or perception by an intelligent living being, of ends to be obtained and of the means of obtaining them—and the idea of the tendons of the foot and of the ligament which binds them down, come together so forcibly, that no matter how strongly Professors Haeckel and Clifford and Mr. Darwin may try to separate them, they are no sooner pulled asunder than they straightway fly together again of themselves.
Now I propose that there’s hardly a single reader who can honestly say they are free from bias or prejudice, who won’t recognize that the concept of design—or the awareness by an intelligent being of goals to achieve and the ways to achieve them—and the notion of the tendons in the foot and the ligament that holds them in place, are so closely connected that no matter how much Professors Haeckel, Clifford, and Mr. Darwin may try to separate them, they immediately come back together on their own as soon as they are pulled apart.
I shall argue, therefore, no further upon this head, but shall assume it as settled, and shall proceed at once to the consideration that next suggests itself.
I won't continue debating this point any further; instead, I'll assume it's agreed upon and move on to the next topic that comes to mind.
FOOTNOTES:
[13] Ch. vii.
[14] Ch. vii.
[15] 'Natural Theology.' ch. viii.
'Natural Theology.' ch. 8.
[16] 'Natural Theology,' ch. viii.
[17] 'Natural Theology,' ch. viii.
[18] "What!" says Coleridge, in a note on Stillingfleet, to which Mr. Garnett, of the British Museum, has kindly called my attention, "Did Sir Walter Raleigh believe that a male and female ounce (and if so why not two tigers and lions, &c.?) would have produced in course of generations a cat, or a cat a lion? This is Darwinising with a vengeance."—See 'Athenæum,' March 27, 1875, p. 423.
[18] "What!" Coleridge says in a note on Stillingfleet, which Mr. Garnett from the British Museum has kindly brought to my attention, "Did Sir Walter Raleigh really think that a male and female ounce (and if so, why not two tigers and lions, etc.?) would eventually produce a cat, or a cat would become a lion over generations? This is Darwinism taken to the extreme."—See 'Athenæum,' March 27, 1875, p. 423.
[19] 'Natural Theology,' ch. ix.
[20] "La vraie théorie n'est que l'enchaînement naturel des faits, qui dès qu'ils sont assez nombreux, se touchent, et se lient, les uns aux autres par leur seule vertu propre."—Flourens, 'Buffon, Hist. de ses Travaux.' Paris, 1844, p. 82.
[20] "The real theory is just the natural connection of facts, which, once they are numerous enough, relate to each other and link together by their own inherent qualities."—Flourens, 'Buffon, Hist. de ses Travaux.' Paris, 1844, p. 82.
IMPOTENCE OF PALEY'S CONCLUSION. THE TELEOLOGY OF THE EVOLUTIONIST.
IMPOTENCE OF PALEY'S CONCLUSION. THE TELEOLOGY OF THE EVOLUTIONIST.
Though the ideas of design, and of the foot, have come together in our minds with sufficient spontaneity, we yet feel that there is a difference—and a wide difference if we could only lay our hands upon it—between the design and manufacture of the ligament and tendons of the foot on the one hand, and on the other the design, manufacture, and combination of artificial strings, pieces of wood, and bandages, whereby a model of the foot might be constructed.
Though the concepts of design and the foot have merged in our minds quite naturally, we still sense that there is a distinction—and a significant one if we could pinpoint it—between the design and creation of the ligaments and tendons of the foot on one hand, and, on the other hand, the design, creation, and assembly of artificial strings, wooden pieces, and bandages, through which a foot model could be built.
If we conceive of ourselves as looking simultaneously upon a real foot, and upon an admirably constructed artificial one, placed by the side of it, the idea of design, and design by an intelligent living being with a body and soul (without which, as has been already insisted on, the use of the word design is delusive), will present itself strongly to our minds in connection both with the true foot, and with the model; but we find another idea asserting itself with even greater strength, namely, that the design of the true foot is far more intricate, and yet is carried into execution in far more masterly manner than that of the model. We not only feel that there is a wider difference between the ability, time,[Pg 25] and care which have been lavished on the real foot and upon the model, than there is between the skill and the time taken to produce Westminster Abbey, and that bestowed upon a gingerbread cake stuck with sugar plums so as to represent it, but also that these two objects must have been manufactured on different principles. We do not for a moment doubt that the real foot was designed, but we are so astonished at the dexterity of the designer that we are at a loss for some time to think who could have designed it, where he can live, in what manner he studied, for how long, and by what processes he carried out his design, when matured, into actual practice. Until recently it was thought that there was no answer to many of these questions, more especially to those which bear upon the mode of manufacture. For the last hundred years, however, the importance of a study has been recognized which does actually reveal to us in no small degree the processes by which the human foot is manufactured, so that in the endeavour to lay our hands upon the points of difference between the kind of design with which the foot itself is designed, and the design of the model, we turn naturally to the guidance of those who have made this study their specialty; and a very wide difference does this study, embryology, at once reveal to us.
If we think of ourselves looking at a real foot and a well-made artificial foot next to it, the idea of design—created by an intelligent being with a body and a soul (without which, as previously noted, the term design is misleading)—will definitely come to our minds in relation to both the real foot and the model. However, another idea stands out even more: that the design of the real foot is much more complex and executed with far greater skill than that of the model. We not only recognize that there’s a much bigger difference in the ability, time, [Pg 25] and effort that has gone into the real foot compared to the model, than there is between the skill and time taken to create Westminster Abbey versus a gingerbread cake decorated with candy to look like it, but we also see that these two items must have been made using different principles. We have no doubt that the real foot was designed, but we are so impressed by the skill of the designer that we find ourselves wondering who could have created it, where they might reside, how they studied, for how long, and what processes they used to bring their design to life. Until recently, it was thought there were no answers to many of these questions, especially regarding the production methods. However, for the last hundred years, the significance of a certain field of study has been acknowledged, which indeed reveals quite a bit about how the human foot is made. Thus, in our effort to identify the differences between the design of the foot itself and the design of the model, we naturally turn to experts in this field of study; and this study, embryology, reveals a significant difference right away.
Writing of the successive changes through which each embryo is forced to pass, the late Mr. G. H. Lewes says that "none of these phases have any adaptation to the future state of the animal, but are in positive contradiction to it or are simply purposeless; whereas[Pg 26] all show stamped on them the unmistakable characters of ancestral adaptation, and the progressions of organic evolution. What does the fact imply? There is not a single known example of a complex organism which is not developed out of simpler forms. Before it can attain the complex structure which distinguishes it, there must be an evolution of forms similar to those which distinguish the structure of organisms lower in the series. On the hypothesis of a plan which prearranged the organic world, nothing could be more unworthy of a supreme intelligence than this inability to construct an organism at once, without making several previous tentative efforts, undoing to-day what was so carefully done yesterday, and repeating for centuries the same tentatives in the same succession. Do not let us blink this consideration. There is a traditional phrase much in vogue among the anthropomorphists, which arose naturally enough from a tendency to take human methods as an explanation of the Divine—a phrase which becomes a sort of argument—'The Great Architect.' But if we are to admit the human point of view, a glance at the facts of embryology must produce very uncomfortable reflections. For what should we say to an architect who was unable, or being able was obstinately unwilling, to erect a palace except by first using his materials in the shape of a hut, then pulling them down and rebuilding them as a cottage, then adding story to story and room to room, not with any reference to the ultimate purposes of the palace, but wholly with reference to the way in which houses were constructed in ancient times? What should we say to the architect[Pg 27] who could not form a museum out of bricks and mortar, but was forced to begin as if going to construct a mansion, and after proceeding some way in this direction, altered his plan into a palace, and that again into a museum? Yet this is the sort of succession on which organisms are constructed. The fact has long been familiar; how has it been reconciled with infinite wisdom? Let the following passage answer for a thousand:—'The embryo is nothing like the miniature of the adult. For a long while the body in its entirety and in its details, presents the strangest of spectacles. Day by day and hour by hour, the aspect of the scene changes, and this instability is exhibited by the most essential parts no less than by the accessory parts. One would say that nature feels her way, and only reaches the goal after many times missing the path' (on dirait que la nature tâtonne et ne conduit son œuvre à bon fin, qu'après s'être souvent trompée)."[21]
In discussing the various changes that every embryo goes through, the late Mr. G. H. Lewes notes that "none of these stages serve any purpose for the future state of the animal; instead, they contradict it or are simply pointless. However, they all bear the clear marks of ancestral adaptation and the evolution of life forms. What does this suggest? There’s not a single example of a complex organism that doesn’t develop from simpler forms. Before reaching its complex structure, it must undergo changes similar to those that characterize the structures of lower organisms. If we consider a preordained plan for the organic world, nothing seems less fitting for a supreme intelligence than the inability to create an organism all at once, without making several prior attempts, undoing today what was carefully crafted yesterday, and repeating the same trials in the same order for centuries. We shouldn’t ignore this fact. A popular saying among anthropomorphists—a phrase that naturally comes from the tendency to interpret human methods as a way to explain the Divine—refers to 'The Great Architect.' But if we adopt a human perspective, a look at embryology should lead to some troubling thoughts. What would we think of an architect who couldn’t, or who stubbornly wouldn’t, build a palace without first using materials to construct a hut, then tearing it down and rebuilding it as a cottage, before adding stories and rooms, not with any regard for the final purpose of the palace, but solely based on how houses were built in ancient times? What would we say to an architect[Pg 27] who couldn't create a museum from bricks and mortar but had to start as if he was going to build a mansion, only to change his mind to a palace, and then to a museum? Yet, this is how organisms are built. This fact has long been known; how has it been reconciled with infinite wisdom? The following passage sums it up perfectly: 'The embryo is nothing like a smaller version of the adult. For a long time, the body, both in its entirety and its details, presents the strangest sight. Day by day and hour by hour, the appearance of the scene changes, and this instability is evident in the most essential parts as well as the accessory parts. One could say that nature feels its way and only reaches the goal after many missteps' (on dirait que la nature tâtonne et ne conduit son œuvre à bon fin, qu'après s'être souvent trompée)."[21]
The above passage does not, I think, affect the evidence for design which we adduced in the preceding chapter. However strange the process of manufacture may appear, when the work comes to be turned out the design is too manifest to be doubted.
The above passage doesn’t, I believe, change the evidence for design that we presented in the previous chapter. No matter how odd the manufacturing process may seem, when the final product is produced, the design is clearly undeniable.
If the reader were to come upon some lawyer's deed which dealt with matters of such unspeakable intricacy, that it baffled his imagination to conceive how it could ever have been drafted, and if in spite of this he were to find the intricacy of the provisions to be made, exceeded only by the ease and simplicity with which the[Pg 28] deed providing for them was found to work in practice; and after this, if he were to discover that the deed, by whomsoever drawn, had nevertheless been drafted upon principles which at first seemed very foreign to any according to which he was in the habit of drafting deeds himself, as for example, that the draftsman had begun to draft a will as a marriage settlement, and so forth—yet an observer would not, I take it, do either of two things. He would not in the face of the result deny the design, making himself judge rather of the method of procedure than of the achievement. Nor yet after insisting in the manner of Paley, on the wonderful proofs of intention and on the exquisite provisions which were to be found in every syllable—thus leading us up to the highest pitch of expectation—would he present us with such an impotent conclusion as that the designer, though a living person and a true designer, was yet immaterial and intangible, a something, in fact, which proves to be a nothing: an omniscient and omnipotent vacuum.
If the reader were to come across a lawyer's deed that dealt with matters so complicated that it was hard to imagine how it could have ever been created, and if, despite this, he found that the complexity of the required provisions was only surpassed by the ease and simplicity with which the[Pg 28] deed worked in practice; and after this, if he were to discover that the deed, no matter who drafted it, was created based on principles that initially seemed very different from the ones he was used to when drafting deeds himself, such as the draftsman starting a will as a marriage settlement, and so on—yet an observer would not, I believe, do one of two things. He would not, despite the outcome, deny the design, judging the method of procedure instead of the result. Nor would he, after insisting like Paley on the incredible proofs of intention and the detailed provisions found in every word—leading us to the highest expectations—present us with such a weak conclusion as that the designer, though a living person and a true designer, was somehow immaterial and intangible, basically a nothing: an all-knowing and all-powerful vacuum.
Our observer would feel he need not have been at such pains to establish his design if this was to be the upshot of his reasoning. He would therefore admit the design, and by consequence the designer, but would probably ask a little time for reflection before he ventured to say who, or what, or where the designer was. Then gaining some insight into the manner in which the deed had been drawn, he would conclude that the draftsman was a specialist who had had long practice in this particular kind of work, but who now worked almost as it might be said automatically and[Pg 29] without consciousness, and found it difficult to depart from a habitual method of procedure.
Our observer would think he didn’t need to go to such lengths to explain his idea if this was the conclusion of his reasoning. He would acknowledge the idea and, as a result, the creator, but he’d likely ask for a little time to think before he dared to say who, or what, or where the creator was. Then, after gaining some understanding of how the work had been executed, he would conclude that the person who drafted it was a specialist who had extensive experience in this type of task, but now worked almost automatically and[Pg 29] without awareness, finding it hard to break free from a routine approach.
We turn, then, on Paley, and say to him: "We have admitted your design and your designer. Where is he? Show him to us. If you cannot show him to us as flesh and blood, show him as flesh and sap; show him as a living cell; show him as protoplasm. Lower than this we should not fairly go; it is not in the bond or nexus of our ideas that something utterly inanimate and inorganic should scheme, design, contrive, and elaborate structures which can make mistakes: it may elaborate low unerring things, like crystals, but it cannot elaborate those which have the power to err. Nevertheless, we will commit such abuse with our understandings as to waive this point, and we will ask you to show him to us as air which, if it cannot be seen, yet can be felt, weighed, handled, transferred from place to place, be judged by its effects, and so forth; or if this may not be, give us half a grain of hydrogen, diffused through all space and invested with some of the minor attributes of matter; or if you cannot do this, give us an imponderable like electricity, or even the higher mathematics, but give us something or throw off the mask and tell us fairly out that it is your paid profession to hoodwink us on this matter if you can, and that you are but doing your best to earn an honest living."
We now turn to Paley and say to him: "We’ve accepted your design and your designer. Where is he? Show him to us. If you can't show him to us as flesh and blood, show him as flesh and sap; show him as a living cell; show him as protoplasm. We shouldn't have to go lower than this; it doesn't fit with our understanding that something completely inanimate and inorganic could plan, design, create, and build structures that can make mistakes: it may create simple, flawless things, like crystals, but it can't create those that have the ability to err. Still, we'll set aside this issue and ask you to show him to us as air, which, although unseen, can be felt, weighed, handled, moved from place to place, and judged by its effects, and so on; or if that's not possible, give us half a grain of hydrogen, spread throughout space and infused with some basic properties of matter; or if you can't do that, give us something like electricity, which is weightless, or even higher mathematics, but give us something or take off the mask and honestly tell us that your job is to mislead us on this matter if you can, and that you’re just trying to make a living."
We may fancy Paley as turning the tables upon us and as saying: "But you too have admitted a designer—you too then must mean a designer with a body and soul, who must be somewhere to be found in space, and[Pg 30] who must live in time. Where is this your designer? Can you show him more than I can? Can you lay your finger on him and demonstrate him so that a child shall see him and know him, and find what was heretofore an isolated idea concerning him, combine itself instantaneously with the idea of the designer, we will say, of the human foot, so that no power on earth shall henceforth tear those two ideas asunder? Surely if you cannot do this, you too are trifling with words, and abusing your own mind and that of your reader. Where, then, is your designer of man? Who made him? And where, again, is your designer of beasts and birds, of fishes, and of plants?"
We can imagine Paley turning the tables on us and saying: "But you too have accepted a designer—you must then mean a designer with a body and soul, who must exist somewhere in space, and[Pg 30] who must live in time. Where is this designer of yours? Can you show him more clearly than I can? Can you point him out and demonstrate him so that a child can see him and know him, and unite what was once an isolated idea about him with the idea of the designer, let’s say, of the human foot, so that no power on earth can ever separate those two concepts again? Surely, if you can't do this, you are also just playing with words, misleading yourself and your reader. So where is your designer of humans? Who created him? And where, again, is your designer of animals and birds, of fish, and of plants?"
Our answer is simple enough; it is that we can and do point to a living tangible person with flesh, blood, eyes, nose, ears, organs, senses, dimensions, who did of his own cunning after infinite proof of every kind of hazard and experiment scheme out, and fashion each organ of the human body. This is the person whom we claim as the designer and artificer of that body, and he is the one of all others the best fitted for the task by his antecedents, and his practical knowledge of the requirements of the case—for he is man himself.
Our answer is straightforward: we can point to a real, physical person with flesh, blood, eyes, nose, ears, organs, senses, and dimensions, who, through his own intelligence and after countless tests and experiments, devised and shaped every part of the human body. This is the person we recognize as the designer and creator of that body, and he is uniquely qualified for this task because of his background and practical understanding of what’s needed—because he is human.
Not man, the individual of any given generation, but man in the entirety of his existence from the dawn of life onwards to the present moment. In like manner we say that the designer of all organisms is so incorporate with the organisms themselves—so lives, moves, and has its being in those organisms, and is so one with them—they in it, and it in them—that it is more consistent with reason and the common use[Pg 31] of words to see the designer of each living form in the living form itself, than to look for its designer in some other place or person.
Not individual people from any generation, but humanity as a whole from the beginning of life until now. Similarly, we can say that the creator of all living things is so intertwined with the organisms themselves—so integrated, so alive, and so present within those organisms—that it makes more sense, both logically and in everyday language, to find the creator of each living being within the being itself, rather than searching for the creator somewhere else or in another person.
Thus we have a third alternative presented to us.
Thus, we have a third option presented to us.
Mr. Charles Darwin and his followers deny design, as having any appreciable share in the formation of organism at all.
Mr. Charles Darwin and his supporters reject the idea of design as playing any significant role in the formation of organisms.
Paley and the theologians insist on design, but upon a designer outside the universe and the organism.
Paley and the theologians emphasize design, but they attribute it to a designer who exists outside of the universe and the organism.
The third opinion is that suggested in the first instance, and carried out to a very high degree of development by Buffon. It was improved, and, indeed, made almost perfect by Dr. Erasmus Darwin, but too much neglected by him after he had put it forward. It was borrowed, as I think we may say with some confidence, from Dr. Darwin by Lamarck, and was followed up by him ardently thenceforth, during the remainder of his life, though somewhat less perfectly comprehended by him than it had been by Dr. Darwin. It is that the design which has designed organisms, has resided within, and been embodied in, the organisms themselves.
The third opinion is the one suggested initially and taken to a very advanced level by Buffon. Dr. Erasmus Darwin improved it and nearly perfected it, but he paid it less attention after presenting it. Lamarck, I believe confidently, borrowed this idea from Dr. Darwin and passionately pursued it for the rest of his life, although he didn't fully grasp it as well as Dr. Darwin had. This opinion is that the design guiding organisms exists within them and is embodied in the organisms themselves.
With but a very little change in the present signification of words, the question resolves itself into this.
With just a small change in the current meaning of words, the question boils down to this.
Shall we see God henceforth as embodied in all living forms; as dwelling in them; as being that power in them whereby they have learnt to fashion themselves, each one according to its ideas of its own convenience, and to make itself not only a microcosm, or little world, but a little unwritten history of the universe from its own point of view into the bargain? From everlasting, in time past, only in so far as life has[Pg 32] lasted; invisible, only in so far as the ultimate connection between the will to do and the thing which does is invisible; imperishable, only in so far as life as a whole is imperishable; omniscient and omnipotent, within the limits only of a very long and large experience, but ignorant and impotent in respect of all else—limited in all the above respects, yet even so incalculably vaster than anything that we can conceive?
Should we now see God as present in all living things; as residing within them; as the power that enables them to shape themselves, each according to their own sense of convenience, and to create not just a microcosm, or small world, but a little unwritten history of the universe from their own perspective? From forever, in times past, only insofar as life has[Pg 32] persisted; unseen, only to the extent that the ultimate link between the will to act and the action itself is not visible; eternal, only as long as life as a whole is eternal; all-knowing and all-powerful, but only within the boundaries of extensive experience, yet ignorant and weak regarding everything else—limited in all these ways, yet still infinitely greater than anything we can imagine?
Or shall we see God as we were taught to say we saw him when we were children—as an artificial and violent attempt to combine ideas which fly asunder and asunder, no matter how often we try to force them into combination?
Or should we think of God like we were taught to believe we saw him when we were kids—as a fake and aggressive effort to link ideas that keep pulling apart, no matter how many times we try to make them fit together?
"The true mainspring of our existence," says Buffon, "lies not in those muscles, veins, arteries, and nerves, which have been described with so much minuteness, it is to be found in the more hidden forces which are not bounden by the gross mechanical laws which we would fain set over them. Instead of trying to know these forces by their effects, we have endeavoured to uproot even their very idea, so as to banish them utterly from philosophy. But they return to us and with renewed vigour; they return to us in gravitation, in chemical affinity, in the phenomena of electricity, &c. Their existence rests upon the clearest evidence; the omnipresence of their action is indisputable, but that action is hidden away from our eyes, and is a matter of inference only; we cannot actually see them, therefore we find difficulty in admitting that they exist; we wish to judge of everything by its exterior; we imagine that the exterior is the whole, and deeming[Pg 33] that it is not permitted us to go beyond it, we neglect all that may enable us to do so."[22]
"The true driving force of our existence," Buffon says, "is not found in those muscles, veins, arteries, and nerves, which have been described in great detail; it lies in the deeper forces that aren’t confined by the basic mechanical laws we try to impose on them. Instead of trying to understand these forces by their effects, we've attempted to eliminate even the idea of them, so as to completely remove them from philosophy. But they come back to us with even more strength; they show up in gravitation, in chemical affinity, in the phenomena of electricity, and so on. Their existence is supported by clear evidence; the constant presence of their action is undeniable, but that action is hidden from our view and is only a matter of inference. We can't actually see them, which makes it hard for us to accept that they exist; we prefer to judge everything by its appearance; we think the exterior is everything, and believing that we shouldn't go beyond it, we ignore everything that might allow us to do so."
Or may we not say that the unseen parts of God are those deep buried histories, the antiquity and the repeatedness of which go as far beyond that of any habit handed down to us from our earliest protoplasmic ancestor, as the distance of the remotest star in space transcends our distance from the sun?
Or can we not say that the hidden aspects of God are those deeply buried histories, whose age and recurrence go far beyond any habits passed down to us from our earliest ancestors, just as the distance of the farthest star in space surpasses our distance from the sun?
By vivisection and painful introspection we can rediscover many a long buried history—rekindling that sense of novelty in respect of its action, whereby we can alone become aware of it. But there are other remoter histories, and more repeated thoughts and actions, before which we feel so powerless to reawaken fresh interest concerning them, that we give up the attempt in despair, and bow our heads, overpowered by the sense of their immensity. Thus our inability to comprehend God is coextensive with our difficulty in going back upon the past—and our sense of him is a dim perception of our own vast and now inconceivably remote history.
Through intense scrutiny and painful self-reflection, we can uncover many long-hidden stories—reviving that feeling of freshness regarding their actions, which is the only way we can truly become aware of them. However, there are other deeper histories, along with more familiar thoughts and actions, that make us feel so helpless in reigniting our interest that we eventually give up in frustration, feeling overwhelmed by their vastness. Therefore, our struggle to understand God mirrors our challenge in revisiting the past—and our perception of Him is just a faint awareness of our own immense and now unfathomably distant history.
FAILURE OF THE FIRST EVOLUTIONISTS TO SEE THEIR POSITION AS TELEOLOGICAL.
FAILURE OF THE FIRST EVOLUTIONISTS TO VIEW THEIR POSITION AS PURPOSE-DRIVEN.
It follows necessarily from the doctrine of Dr. Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck, if not from that of Buffon himself, that the greater number of organs are as purposive to the evolutionist as to the theologian, and far more intelligibly so. Circumstances, however, prevented these writers from acknowledging this fact to the world, and perhaps even to themselves. Their crux was, as it still is to so many evolutionists, the presence of rudimentary organs, and the processes of embryological development. They would not admit that rudimentary and therefore useless organs were designed by a Creator to take their place once and for ever as part of a scheme whose main idea was, that every animal structure was to serve some useful end in connection with its possessor.
It necessarily follows from the teachings of Dr. Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck, if not from Buffon himself, that most organs are just as meaningful to the evolutionist as to the theologian, and in much clearer terms. However, circumstances prevented these writers from acknowledging this fact to the world, and perhaps even to themselves. Their challenge was, and still is for many evolutionists, the existence of rudimentary organs and the processes of embryological development. They wouldn’t accept that rudimentary and therefore useless organs were designed by a Creator to permanently exist as part of a scheme whose main idea was that every animal structure was intended to serve some useful purpose related to its possessor.
This was the doctrine of final causes as then commonly held; in the face of rudimentary organs it was absurd. Buffon was above all things else a plain matter of fact thinker, who refused to go far beyond the obvious. Like all other profound writers, he was, if I may say so, profoundly superficial. He felt that the aim of research does not consist in the knowing this or that, but in the easing of the desire to know or understand[Pg 35] more completely—in the peace of mind which passeth all understanding. His was the perfection of a healthy mental organism by which over effort is felt instinctively to be as vicious and contemptible as indolence. He knew this too well to know the grounds of his knowledge, but we smaller people who know it less completely, can see that such felicitous instinctive tempering together of the two great contradictory principles, love of effort and love of ease, has underlain every step of all healthy growth through all conceivable time. Nothing is worth looking at which is seen either too obviously or with too much difficulty. Nothing is worth doing or well done which is not done fairly easily, and some little deficiency of effort is more pardonable than any very perceptible excess; for virtue has ever erred rather on the side of self-indulgence than of asceticism, and well-being has ever advanced through the pleasures rather than through austerity.
This was the idea of final causes as it was commonly understood back then; faced with basic organs, it seemed ridiculous. Buffon was, above all, a straightforward thinker who didn’t go far beyond what was obvious. Like all profound writers, he was, if I may put it this way, deeply superficial. He believed the goal of research isn't just to know this or that, but to ease the desire to know or understand more completely—in the peace of mind that surpasses all understanding. His was the perfection of a healthy mental state, where overexertion is instinctively seen as just as harmful and contemptible as laziness. He understood this too well to fully grasp the basis of his knowledge, but we lesser individuals, who grasp it less completely, can see that this fortunate instinctual balancing of the two major opposing ideas—hard work and comfort—has been at the heart of every step of healthy progress throughout time. Nothing is worth looking at if it’s either too obvious or too difficult to see. Nothing is worth doing, or done well, if it isn't accomplished fairly easily, and a slight lack of effort is more forgivable than any noticeable excess; for virtue has historically leaned more toward self-indulgence than asceticism, and well-being has always progressed through enjoyment rather than through strictness.
According to Buffon, then—as also according to Dr. Darwin, who was just such another practical and genial thinker, and who was distinctly a pupil of Buffon, though a most intelligent and original one—if an organ after a reasonable amount of inspection appeared to be useless, it was to be called useless without more ado, and theories were to be ordered out of court if they were troublesome. In like manner, if animals bred freely inter se before our eyes, as for example the horse and ass, the fact was to be noted, but no animals were to be classed as capable of interbreeding until they had asserted their right to such classification by breeding with tolerable certainty. If,[Pg 36] again, an animal looked as if it felt, that is to say, if it moved about pretty quickly or made a noise, it must be held to feel; if it did neither of these things, it did not look as if it felt and therefore it must be said not to feel. De non apparentibus et non existentibus eadem est lex was one of the chief axioms of their philosophy; no writers have had a greater horror of mystery or of ideas that have not become so mastered as to be, or to have been, superficial. Lamarck was one of those men of whom I believe it has been said that they have brain upon the brain. He had his theory that an animal could not feel unless it had a nervous system, and at least a spinal marrow—and that it could not think at all without a brain—all his facts, therefore, have to be made to square with this. With Buffon and Dr. Darwin we feel safe that however wrong they may sometimes be, their conclusions have always been arrived at on that fairly superficial view of things in which, as I have elsewhere said, our nature alone permits us to be comforted.
According to Buffon, and also Dr. Darwin, who was another practical and insightful thinker and a clear student of Buffon, although a very intelligent and original one—if an organ seemed useless after a reasonable amount of examination, it could be labeled useless without further discussion, and any troublesome theories should be disregarded. Similarly, if animals bred freely with each other in front of us, like horses and donkeys, that fact should be noted, but no animals should be classified as capable of interbreeding until they demonstrated that ability by breeding reliably. Additionally, if an animal appeared to feel something, meaning it moved around a lot or made noise, it should be considered to feel; if it did neither of those things, it wouldn’t seem to feel and should be regarded as not feeling. De non apparentibus et non existentibus eadem est lex was one of the main principles of their philosophy; no writers have had a greater aversion to mystery or to ideas that remain unexamined or superficial. Lamarck was one of those people who some might say had intellect layered upon intellect. He theorized that an animal couldn’t feel unless it had a nervous system and at least a spinal cord—and that it couldn’t think at all without a brain—so all his facts had to align with this. With Buffon and Dr. Darwin, we can feel confident that even if they are sometimes wrong, their conclusions are based on that fairly superficial perspective of things in which, as I’ve mentioned elsewhere, our nature allows us to find comfort.
To these writers, then, the doctrine of final causes for rudimentary organs was a piece of mystification and an absurdity; no less fatal to any such doctrine were the processes of embryological development. It was plain that the commonly received teleology must be given up; but the idea of design or purpose was so associated in their minds with theological design that they avoided it altogether. They seem to have forgotten that an internal teleology is as much teleology as an external one; hence, unfortunately, though their whole theory of development is intensely purposive, it is the fact[Pg 37] rather than the name of teleology which has hitherto been insisted upon, even by the greatest writers on evolution—the name having been denied even by those who were most insisting on the thing itself.
To these writers, the idea of final causes for basic organs was just a form of confusion and nonsense; the processes of embryonic development were equally damaging to that belief. It was clear that the commonly accepted teleology had to be abandoned; however, the concept of design or purpose was so tied to theological ideas in their minds that they completely steered clear of it. They seemed to have overlooked that an internal teleology is just as valid as an external one; thus, unfortunately, while their entire theory of development is deeply purposeful, it is the fact[Pg 37] rather than the term teleology that has been emphasized, even by the leading authors on evolution—the term having been rejected even by those who most strongly advocated for the concept itself.
It is easy to understand the difficulty felt by the fathers of evolution when we remember how much had to be seen before the facts could lie well before them. It was necessary to attain, firstly, to a perception of the unity of person between parents and offspring in successive generations; secondly, it must be seen that an organism's memory goes back for generations beyond its birth, to the first beginnings in fact, of which we know anything whatever; thirdly, the latency of that memory, as of memory generally till the associated ideas are reproduced, must be brought to bear upon the facts of heredity; and lastly, the unconsciousness with which habitual actions come to be performed, must be assigned as the explanation of the unconsciousness with which we grow and discharge most of our natural functions.
It's easy to understand the challenges faced by the pioneers of evolution when we consider how much needed to be recognized before the facts became clear to them. First, they had to grasp the connection between parents and their offspring across generations. Second, it had to be understood that an organism's memory extends back through generations to the very beginnings of life that we know anything about. Third, the hidden nature of that memory, like memory in general until associated ideas are triggered, had to be connected to the facts of heredity. Finally, the unconscious nature of routine actions had to be identified as the reason for the unconsciousness with which we grow and carry out most of our natural functions.
Buffon was too busy with the fact that animals descended with modification at all, to go beyond the development and illustration of this great truth. I doubt whether he ever saw more than the first, and that dimly, of the four considerations above stated.
Buffon was too focused on the fact that animals evolved with changes to explore further the development and explanation of this significant truth. I doubt he ever fully grasped more than the first of the four points mentioned above, and even that only vaguely.
Dr. Darwin was the first to point out the first two considerations with some clearness, but he can hardly be said to have understood their full importance: the two latter ideas do not appear to have occurred to him.
Dr. Darwin was the first to clearly highlight the first two points, but it’s difficult to say he fully grasped their significance; he doesn’t seem to have contemplated the latter two ideas at all.
Lamarck had little if any perception of any one of the four. When, however, they are firmly seized and brought into their due bearings one upon another,[Pg 38] the facts of heredity become as simple as those of a man making a tobacco pipe, and rudimentary organs are seen to be essentially of the same character as the little rudimentary protuberance at the bottom of the pipe to which I referred in 'Erewhon.'[23]
Lamarck had little, if any, understanding of any one of the four. However, when they are clearly understood and related to each other,[Pg 38] the facts of heredity become as straightforward as a person making a tobacco pipe, and rudimentary organs are recognized as being essentially similar to the small rudimentary bump at the bottom of the pipe that I mentioned in 'Erewhon.'[23]
These organs are now no longer useful, but they once were so, and were therefore once purposive, though not so now. They are the expressions of a bygone usefulness; sayings, as it were, about which there was at one time infinite wrangling, as to what both the meaning and the expression should best be, so that they then had living significance in the mouths of those who used them, though they have become such mere shibboleths and cant formulæ to ourselves that we think no more of their meaning than we do of Julius Cæsar in the month of July. They continue to be reproduced through the force of habit, and through indisposition to get out of any familiar groove of action until it becomes too unpleasant for us to remain in it any longer. It has long been felt that embryology and rudimentary structures indicated community of descent. Dr. Darwin and Lamarck insisted on this, as have all subsequent writers on evolution; but the explanation of why and how the structures come to be repeated—namely, that they are simply examples of the force of habit—can only be perceived intelligently by those who admit so much unity between parents and offspring that the self-development of the latter can be properly called habitual (as being a repetition of an act by one and the same individual), and can only be fully sympathized[Pg 39] with by those who recognize that if habit be admitted as the key to the fact at all, the unconscious manner in which the habit comes to be repeated is only of a piece with all our other observations concerning habit. For the fuller development of the foregoing, I must refer the reader to my work 'Life and Habit.'
These organs are no longer useful, but they once served a purpose and were meaningful back then. They reflect a past usefulness; like sayings that were hotly debated regarding their meaning and expression, giving them significance to those who used them. Now, they have become just clichéd phrases and buzzwords to us, so meaningless that we think no more of their significance than we do of Julius Caesar in July. They keep being used out of habit and a reluctance to change until staying in that rut becomes too uncomfortable. It's long been recognized that embryology and rudimentary structures suggest a common ancestry. Dr. Darwin and Lamarck emphasized this, as have all writers on evolution since; however, the reason behind why and how these structures are repeated—essentially that they are examples of habit—can only be understood by those who accept that there is a strong connection between parents and offspring, making the self-development of the latter a habitual process (a repetition of actions by the same individual). This idea can only be fully appreciated by those who acknowledge that if we consider habit the key to understanding the phenomenon, then the unconscious way habits repeat is in line with all our other observations about habit. For a more in-depth explanation of this, I encourage you to read my work 'Life and Habit.'
The purposiveness, which even Dr. Darwin, and Lamarck still less, seem never to have quite recognized in spite of their having insisted so much on what amounts to the same thing, now comes into full view. It is seen that the organs external to the body, and those internal to it are, the second as much as the first, things which we have made for our own convenience, and with a prevision that we shall have need of them; the main difference between the manufacture of these two classes of organs being, that we have made the one kind so often that we can no longer follow the processes whereby we make them, while the others are new things which we must make introspectively or not at all, and which are not yet so incorporate with our vitality as that we should think they grow instead of being manufactured. The manufacture of the tool, and the manufacture of the living organ prove therefore to be but two species of the same genus, which, though widely differentiated, have descended as it were from one common filament of desire and inventive faculty. The greater or less complexity of the organs goes for very little. It is only a question of the amount of intelligence and voluntary self-adaptation which we must admit, and this must be settled rather by an appeal to what we find[Pg 40] in organism, and observe concerning it, than by what we may have imagined à priori.
The purposefulness that even Dr. Darwin and, to an even lesser extent, Lamarck seem to have never fully recognized, despite their focus on something similar, is now completely clear. It's evident that both the external and internal organs of the body are objects we’ve created for our own convenience, anticipating that we would need them. The main difference between these two types of organs is that we've created the first type so many times that we no longer remember the processes involved, while the second type consists of new creations that we must develop internally or not at all, and which are not yet integrated with our vitality to the point where we consider them to grow instead of being made. Thus, the creation of tools and the creation of living organs turn out to be just two different kinds of the same overarching process, which, although significantly varied, have evolved from a common source of desire and creativity. The complexity of the organs matters very little. It really comes down to the level of intelligence and voluntary self-adaptation we need to acknowledge, and this should be determined more by what we observe in organisms than by our preconceived notions [Pg 40].
Given a small speck of jelly with some kind of circumstance-suiting power, some power of slightly varying its actions in accordance with slightly varying circumstances and desires—given such a jelly-speck with a power of assimilating other matter, and thus, of reproducing itself, given also that it should be possessed of a memory, and we can show how the whole animal world can have descended it may be from an amœba without interference from without, and how every organ in every creature is designed at first roughly and tentatively but finally fashioned with the most consummate perfection, by the creature which has had need of that organ, which best knew what it wanted, and was never satisfied till it had got that which was the best suited to its varying circumstances in their entirety. We can even show how, if it becomes worth the Ethiopian's while to try and change his skin, or the leopard's to change his spots, they can assuredly change them within a not unreasonable time and adapt their covering to their own will and convenience, and to that of none other; thus what is commonly conceived of as direct creation by God is moved back to a time and space inconceivable in their remoteness, while the aim and design so obvious in nature are shown to be still at work around us, growing ever busier and busier, and advancing from day to day both in knowledge and power.
Given a tiny blob of jelly with some sort of adaptive power, the ability to slightly change its actions based on varying circumstances and desires—given such a jelly blob that can absorb other materials and thus reproduce itself, and also has a memory, we can explain how the entire animal kingdom might have evolved from an amoeba without outside interference. Furthermore, we can illustrate how every organ in every creature is initially designed roughly and tentatively but ultimately shaped to perfection by the creature that needs that organ, which best understands what it wants and is never satisfied until it has achieved what fits its changing circumstances perfectly. We can even demonstrate how, if it becomes worthwhile for the Ethiopian to try to change his skin, or for the leopard to alter its spots, they can definitely make those changes within a reasonable timeframe and adapt their appearance to their own preferences and needs, and to no one else’s. Thus, what is often thought of as direct creation by God is pushed back to an almost unimaginable time and space, while the evident aim and design in nature continue to be active around us, becoming busier and advancing daily in both knowledge and power.
It was reserved for Mr. Darwin and for those who have too rashly followed him to deny purpose as having[Pg 41] had any share in the development of animal and vegetable organs; to see no evidence of design in those wonderful provisions which have been the marvel and delight of observers in all ages. The one who has drawn our attention more than perhaps any other living writer to those very marvels of coadaptation, is the foremost to maintain that they are the result not of desire and design, either within the creature or without it, but of blind chance, working no whither, and due but to the accumulation of innumerable lucky accidents.
It was left to Mr. Darwin and those who have too quickly followed him to deny that purpose had any role in the development of animal and plant organs; to see no evidence of design in those amazing features that have fascinated and delighted observers throughout history. The person who has drawn our attention more than perhaps any other living writer to those amazing instances of coadaptation is the first to argue that they are the result not of intention and design, whether inside or outside the creature, but of random chance, working aimlessly, and arising solely from the accumulation of countless fortunate accidents.
"There are men," writes Professor Tyndall in the 'Nineteenth Century,' for last November, "and by no means the minority, who, however wealthy in regard to facts, can never rise into the region of principles; and they are sometimes intolerant of those that can. They are formed to plod meritoriously on in the lower levels of thought; unpossessed of the pinions necessary to reach the heights, they cannot realize the mental act—the act of inspiration it might well be called—by which a man of genius, after long pondering and proving, reaches a theoretic conception which unravels and illuminates the tangle of centuries of observation and experiment. There are minds, it may be said in passing, who, at the present moment, stand in this relation to Mr. Darwin."
"There are men," writes Professor Tyndall in the 'Nineteenth Century,' for last November, "and they are by no means a minority, who, despite being rich in facts, can never advance to the level of principles; and they can be intolerant of those who do. They are meant to diligently work away in the lower levels of thought; lacking the wings needed to reach greater heights, they can't grasp the mental leap—an act of inspiration, as it could be called—by which a genius, after much reflection and validation, arrives at a theoretical idea that untangles and sheds light on the complexities of centuries of observation and experimentation. It can be noted, in passing, that there are minds currently relating to Mr. Darwin in this way."
The more rhapsodical parts of the above must go for what they are worth, but I should be sorry to think that what remains conveyed a censure which might fall justly on myself. As I read the earlier part of the passage I confess that I imagined the conclusion was going to be very different from what it proved to be.[Pg 42] Fresh from the study of the older men and also of Mr. Darwin himself, I failed to see that Mr. Darwin had "unravelled and illuminated" a tangled skein, but believed him, on the contrary, to have tangled and obscured what his predecessors had made in great part, if not wholly, plain. With the older writers, I had felt as though in the hands of men who wished to understand themselves and to make their reader understand them with the smallest possible exertion. The older men, if not in full daylight, at any rate saw in what quarter of the sky the dawn was breaking, and were looking steadily towards it. It is not they who have put their hands over their own eyes and ours, and who are crying out that there is no light, but chance and blindness everywhere.
The more poetic parts of the above should be taken for what they are, but I would hate to think that what remains reflects a criticism that could rightly be directed at me. As I read the earlier part of the text, I honestly thought the conclusion would be very different from what it turned out to be.[Pg 42] Fresh from studying the older thinkers and Mr. Darwin himself, I failed to realize that Mr. Darwin had "unraveled and clarified" a complicated issue; instead, I believed he had tangled and obscured what his predecessors had mostly, if not entirely, made clear. With the older authors, I felt like I was in the hands of people who wanted to understand themselves and help the reader understand them with minimal effort. The older thinkers, if not in full light, at least knew in which direction the dawn was breaking and were focused on it. They are not the ones covering their own eyes and ours, claiming there is no light, but that chaos and ignorance reign everywhere.
FOOTNOTES:
[23] Page 210, first edition.
THE TELEOLOGICAL EVOLUTION OF ORGANISM—THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE UNCONSCIOUS.
THE TELEOLOGICAL EVOLUTION OF ORGANISMS—THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE UNCONSCIOUS.
I have stated the foregoing in what I take to be an extreme logical development, in order that the reader may more easily perceive the consequences of those premises which I am endeavouring to re-establish. But it must not be supposed that an animal or plant has ever conceived the idea of some organ widely different from any it was yet possessed of, and has set itself to design it in detail and grow towards it.
I have explained the above in what I believe is a clear logical progression, so that readers can better understand the implications of the premises I’m trying to re-establish. However, it should not be assumed that any animal or plant has ever imagined an organ completely different from what it currently has and has then worked to design it in detail and grow toward it.
The small jelly-speck, which we call the amœba, has no organs save what it can extemporize as occasion arises. If it wants to get at anything, it thrusts out part of its jelly, which thus serves it as an arm or hand: when the arm has served its purpose, it is absorbed into the rest of the jelly, and has now to do the duty of a stomach by helping to wrap up what it has just purveyed. The small round jelly-speck spreads itself out and envelops its food, so that the whole creature is now a stomach, and nothing but a stomach. Having digested its food, it again becomes a jelly-speck, and is again ready to turn part of itself into hand or foot as its next convenience may dictate. It is not to be believed that such a creature as this, which is probably just sensitive to light and[Pg 44] nothing more, should be able to form a conception of an eye and set itself to work to grow one, any more than it is believable that he who first observed the magnifying power of a dew drop, or even he who first constructed a rude lens, should have had any idea in his mind of Lord Rosse's telescope with all its parts and appliances. Nothing could be well conceived more foreign to experience and common sense. Animals and plants have travelled to their present forms as man has travelled to any one of his own most complicated inventions. Slowly, step by step, through many blunders and mischances which have worked together for good to those that have persevered in elasticity. They have travelled as man has travelled, with but little perception of a want till there was also some perception of a power, and with but little perception of a power till there was a dim sense of want; want stimulating power, and power stimulating want; and both so based upon each other that no one can say which is the true foundation, but rather that they must be both baseless and, as it were, meteoric in mid air. They have seen very little ahead of a present power or need, and have been then most moral, when most inclined to pierce a little into futurity, but also when most obstinately declining to pierce too far, and busy mainly with the present. They have been so far blindfolded that they could see but for a few steps in front of them, yet so far free to see that those steps were taken with aim and definitely, and not in the dark.
The small jelly speck, which we call the ameba, has no organs except for what it can create on the spot as needed. If it wants to reach something, it extends part of its jelly, which then acts like an arm or hand: once it's finished, the arm is absorbed back into the jelly and now has to function like a stomach by wrapping up what it just captured. The small round jelly speck spreads out and surrounds its food, making itself entirely a stomach, and nothing but a stomach. After digesting its food, it becomes a jelly speck again, ready to turn part of itself into a hand or foot as the situation calls for it. It's hard to believe that a creature like this, which probably only responds to light and[Pg 44] nothing more, could develop the idea of an eye and set out to create one, just like it's hard to believe that the person who first noticed how a dewdrop magnifies things, or even the one who made a simple lens, could have envisioned Lord Rosse's telescope with all its components and features. Nothing could seem more alien to experience and common sense. Animals and plants have evolved into their current forms just as humans have advanced in their own most complex inventions. Slowly, step by step, through many mistakes and misfortunes that ultimately benefited those who remained adaptable. They have evolved as humans have, with little awareness of a need until they recognized some kind of ability, and with only vague awareness of an ability until they felt a faint sense of need; need sparking ability, and ability sparking need; both so intertwined that it’s impossible to determine which is the true foundation, or if they are both groundless and, in a way, floating in mid-air. They have seen very little beyond their current power or urgency and have been most focused when trying to glimpse a bit into the future, but also when most stubbornly avoiding looking too far ahead, mainly concentrating on the present. They have been so blindfolded that they could only see a few steps in front of them, yet they have been free enough to see that those steps were taken with intention and clarity, not in darkness.
"Plus il a su," says Buffon, speaking of man, "plus il a pu, mais aussi moins il a fait, moins il a su." This[Pg 45] holds good wherever life holds good. Wherever there is life there is a moral government of rewards and punishments understood by the amœba neither better nor worse than by man. The history of organic development is the history of a moral struggle.
"the more he knows," says Buffon, talking about humans, "the more he is capable of, but also the less he does, the less he understands." This[Pg 45] applies wherever life exists. Wherever there is life, there is a moral order of rewards and punishments that the amoeba understands just as well as humans do. The history of organic development is the history of a moral struggle.
We know nothing as yet about the origin of a creature able to feel want and power, nor yet what want and power spring from. It does not seem worth while to go into these questions until an understanding has been come to as to whether the interaction of want and power in some low form or forms of life which could assimilate matter, reproduce themselves, vary their actions, and be capable of remembering, will or will not suffice to explain the development of the varied organs and desires which we see in the higher vertebrates and man. When this question has been settled, then it will be time to push our inquiries farther back.
We still don't know where a creature that can feel desire and power comes from, or what these feelings really are. It doesn't seem useful to explore these questions until we figure out if the interaction of desire and power in some basic forms of life that can take in matter, reproduce, change their behaviors, and have memory, is enough to explain how the diverse organs and desires we observe in higher vertebrates and humans developed. Once we have settled this question, we can then move on to explore further back.
But given such a low form of life as here postulated, and there is no force in Paley's pretended objection to the Darwinism of his time.
But given such a low form of life as proposed here, there is no validity to Paley's supposed objection to the Darwinism of his time.
"Give our philosopher," he says, "appetencies; give him a portion of living irritable matter (a nerve or the clipping of a nerve) to work upon; give also to his incipient or progressive forms the power of propagating their like in every stage of their alteration; and if he is to be believed, he could replenish the world with all the vegetable and animal productions which we now see in it."[24]
"Provide our philosopher," he says, "with desires; give him some living, responsive material (a nerve or a piece of a nerve) to work with; also, give his early or developing forms the ability to reproduce themselves at every stage of their change; and if we are to take his word for it, he could fill the world with all the plant and animal life that we currently observe." [24]
After meeting this theory with answers which need not detain us, he continues:[Pg 46]—
After reviewing this theory with responses that don't require our attention, he goes on:[Pg 46]—
"The senses of animals appear to me quite incapable of receiving the explanation of their origin which this theory affords. Including under the word 'sense' the organ and the perception, we have no account of either. How will our philosopher get at vision or make an eye? Or, suppose the eye formed, would the perception follow? The same of the other senses. And this objection holds its force, ascribe what you will to the hand of time, to the power of habit, to changes too slow to be observed by man, or brought within any comparison which he is able to make of past things with the present. Concede what you please to these arbitrary and unattested superstitions, how will they help you? Here is no inception. No laws, no course, no powers of nature which prevail at present, nor any analogous to these would give commencement to a new sense; and it is in vain to inquire how that might proceed which would never begin."
"The senses of animals seem completely unable to understand the origin explained by this theory. When we talk about 'sense,' including both the organ and the perception, we have no explanation for either. How will our philosopher create vision or an eye? Or, if the eye already exists, will perception come afterward? The same applies to the other senses. And this objection remains valid, regardless of how you attribute it to the passage of time, the influence of habit, changes too gradual for humans to notice, or any comparisons they could make between the past and the present. No matter what you accept about these unfounded and questionable beliefs, how will they assist you? There is no beginning. No laws, no processes, no natural powers that operate today, nor any similar ones, could generate a new sense; and it’s pointless to ask how something could develop that would never actually start."
In answer to this, let us suppose that some inhabitants of another world were to see a modern philosopher so using a microscope that they should believe it to be a part of the philosopher's own person, which he could cut off from and join again to himself at pleasure, and suppose there were a controversy as to how this microscope had originated, and that one party maintained the man had made it little by little because he wanted it, while the other declared this to be absurd and impossible; I ask, would this latter party be justified in arguing that microscopes could never have been perfected by degrees through the preservation of and accumulation of small successive improvements, inasmuch[Pg 47] as men could not have begun to want to use microscopes until they had had a microscope which should show them that such an instrument would be useful to them, and that hence there is nothing to account for the beginning of microscopes, which might indeed make some progress when once originated, but which could never originate?
In response to this, let's imagine that some residents of another world were to see a modern philosopher using a microscope in such a way that they would think it was a part of the philosopher's body, which he could detach and reattach whenever he wanted. Now, suppose there’s a debate about how this microscope came to be, and one group argues that the philosopher created it gradually because he wanted it, while the other group insists this is ridiculous and impossible. I ask, would the latter group be justified in claiming that microscopes could never have been developed step by step through the preservation and accumulation of small improvements, since humans couldn't have even started wanting microscopes until they had one that showed them how useful such an instrument would be? Therefore, there is no explanation for the beginning of microscopes, which might make progress once they were created, but could never come into existence?
It might be pointed out to such a reasoner, firstly, that as regards any acquired power the various stages in the acquisition of which he might be supposed able to remember, he would find that, logic notwithstanding, the wish did originate the power, and yet was originated by it, both coming up gradually out of something which was not recognisable as either power or wish, and advancing through vain beating of the air, to a vague effort, and from this to definite effort with failure, and from this to definite effort with success, and from this to success with little consciousness of effort, and from this to success with such complete absence of effort that he now acts unconsciously and without power of introspection, and that, do what he will, he can rarely or never draw a sharp dividing line whereat anything shall be said to begin, though none less certain that there has been a continuity in discontinuity, and a discontinuity in continuity between it and certain other past things; moreover, that his opponents postulated so much beginning of the microscope as that there should be a dew drop, even as our evolutionists start with a sense of touch, of which sense all the others are modifications, so that not one of them but is resolvable into touch by more or less easy stages; and secondly,[Pg 48] that the question is one of fact and of the more evident deductions therefrom, and should not be carried back to those remote beginnings where the nature of the facts is so purely a matter of conjecture and inference.
It could be pointed out to such a thinker, firstly, that regarding any acquired skill, he might remember various stages in its acquisition. He would realize that, regardless of logic, the desire did initiate the skill, and yet was also generated by it, both emerging gradually from something that wasn't recognizable as either skill or desire, and moving from aimless attempts to vague efforts, then to clear efforts with failures, then to clear efforts with successes, and eventually to success with little awareness of effort, and finally to success with such a complete lack of effort that he now acts unconsciously and without the ability to reflect on his actions. He finds it nearly impossible to draw a clear dividing line indicating where anything begins, yet it is undeniable that there has been a continuity within discontinuity, and vice versa, between it and certain earlier occurrences. Furthermore, his opponents assume a starting point for the microscope, similar to how our evolutionists begin with touch, which all other senses are just variations of, so that each sense can be traced back to touch through more or less straightforward stages; and secondly, [Pg 48] that the issue is one of fact and the more obvious conclusions drawn from it, and should not be traced back to those distant beginnings where the nature of the facts is largely speculative and interpretive.
No plant or animal, then, according to our view, would be able to conceive more than a very slight improvement on its organization at a given time, so clearly as to make the efforts towards it that would result in growth of the required modification; nor would these efforts be made with any far-sighted perception of what next and next and after, but only of what next; while many of the happiest thoughts would come like all other happy thoughts—thoughtlessly; by a chain of reasoning too swift and subtle for conscious analysis by the individual, as will be more fully insisted on hereafter. Some of these modifications would be noticeable, but the majority would involve no more noticeable difference than can be detected between the length of the shortest day, and that of the shortest but one.
No plant or animal, then, in our view, would be able to conceive more than a slight improvement in its structure at any given time, clearly enough to make the efforts needed for growth and change; nor would these efforts be made with any long-term understanding of what would come next, but only of the immediate next steps; while many of the best ideas would come about thoughtlessly, like all other good ideas—through a chain of reasoning that's too quick and subtle for the individual to consciously analyze, as will be explained further later. Some of these changes would be noticeable, but most would show no more difference than can be detected between the length of the shortest day and the second shortest.
Thus a bird whose toes were not webbed, but who had under force of circumstances little by little in the course of many generations learned to swim, either from having lived near a lake, and having learnt the art owing to its fishing habits, or from wading about in shallow pools by the sea-side at low water, and finding itself sometimes a little out of its depth and just managing to scramble over the intermediate yard or so between it and safety—such a bird did not probably conceive the idea of swimming on the water and set itself to learn to do so, and then conceive the idea of webbed feet and set itself to get webbed feet. The[Pg 49] bird found itself in some small difficulty, out of which it either saw, or at any rate found that it could extricate itself by striking out vigorously with its feet and extending its toes as far as ever it could; it thus began to learn the art of swimming and conceived the idea of swimming synchronously, or nearly so; or perhaps wishing to get over a yard or two of deep water, and trying to do so without being at the trouble of rising to fly, it would splash and struggle its way over the water, and thus practically swim, though without much perception of what it had been doing. Finding that no harm had come to it, the bird would do the same again, and again; it would thus presently lose fear, and would be able to act more calmly; then it would begin to find out that it could swim a little, and if its food lay much in the water so that it would be of great advantage to it to be able to alight and rest without being forced to return to land, it would begin to make a practice of swimming. It would now discover that it could swim the more easily according as its feet presented a more extended surface to the water; it would therefore keep its toes extended whenever it swam, and as far as in it lay, would make the most of whatever skin was already at the base of its toes. After very many generations it would become web-footed, if doing as above described should have been found continuously convenient, so that the bird should have continuously used the skin about its toes as much as possible in this direction.
So, a bird whose toes weren’t webbed but, due to circumstances, gradually learned to swim over many generations—perhaps because it lived near a lake and learned to swim from its fishing habits, or from wading through shallow pools at low tide and sometimes finding itself in over its head, managing to scramble back to safety—didn’t likely come up with the idea of swimming on its own and then decide to learn how to do it, or think about getting webbed feet and then set out to develop them. The bird found itself in a bit of trouble and noticed that it could get out by kicking its legs vigorously and stretching its toes as far as they would go. It began to learn how to swim and figured out how to do it more effectively; or, maybe while trying to cross a couple of yards of deeper water without the effort of flying, it would splash and struggle its way across, essentially swimming, even without fully realizing what it was doing. Realizing that it didn’t get hurt, the bird would repeat the process over and over, gradually losing its fear and becoming calmer. Eventually, it would realize that it could swim a little. If its food was predominantly in the water, making it beneficial to rest without having to return to the shoreline, it would start practicing swimming regularly. It would also discover that it could swim more easily by spreading its toes out to create a larger surface area in the water, so it would stretch its toes whenever it swam and make the most of any skin already present at the base of its toes. After many generations of doing this, if it remained consistently advantageous, the bird would develop webbed feet, continuously using the skin around its toes in that way.
For there is a margin in every organic structure (and perhaps more than we imagine in things inorganic[Pg 50] also), which will admit of references, as it were, side notes, and glosses upon the original text. It is on this margin that we may err or wander—the greatness of a mistake depending rather upon the extent of the departure from the original text, than on the direction that the departure takes. A little error on the bad side is more pardonable, and less likely to hurt the organism than a too great departure upon the right one. This is a fundamental proposition in any true system of ethics, the question what is too much or too sudden being decided by much the same higgling as settles the price of butter in a country market, and being as invisible as the link which connects the last moment of desire with the first of power and performance, and with the material result achieved.
For every organic structure, and maybe even more than we realize in inorganic things[Pg 50], there's space for annotations, side notes, and clarifications on the main text. It's in this space that we can make mistakes or stray—the severity of a mistake is more about how far we drift from the original text than the direction we take. A small error on the negative side is often more forgivable and less damaging to the organism than a significant deviation in the positive direction. This is a basic principle in any genuine ethical system, where the question of what constitutes too much or too sudden is determined by a negotiation similar to how the price of butter is settled in a local market, and is as unseen as the link that connects the final moment of desire with the first moment of action and the tangible outcome achieved.
It is on this margin that the fulcrum is to be found, whereby we obtain the little purchase over our structure, that enables us to achieve great results if we use it steadily, with judgment, and with neither too little effort nor too much. It is by employing this that those who have a fancy to move their ears or toes without moving other organs learn to do so. There is a man at the Agricultural Hall now playing the violin with his toes, and playing it, as I am told, sufficiently well. The eye of the sailor, the wrist of the conjuror, the toe of the professional medium, are all found capable of development to an astonishing degree, even in a single lifetime; but in every case success has been attained by the simple process of making the best of whatever power a man has had at any given time, and by being on the look out to take advantage of[Pg 51] accident, and even of misfortune. If a man would learn to paint, he must not theorize concerning art, nor think much what he would do beforehand, but he must do something—it does not matter what, except that it should be whatever at the moment will come handiest and easiest to him; and he must do that something as well as he can. This will presently open the door for something else, and a way will show itself which no conceivable amount of searching would have discovered, but which yet could never have been discovered by sitting still and taking no pains at all. "Dans l'animal," says Buffon, "il y a moins de jugement que de sentiment."[25]
It is at this point that we find the balance, which allows us to get a slight grip on our abilities, enabling us to achieve significant results if we apply it consistently, thoughtfully, and with just the right amount of effort. This is how people who want to move their ears or toes without using other parts of their bodies learn to do so. There’s a guy at the Agricultural Hall right now playing the violin with his toes, and I’ve heard he’s doing quite well. The sailor's eye, the magician's wrist, the toe of the professional medium, all can be developed to an impressive degree, even in just one lifetime; but success in each case comes from making the most of whatever skills a person has at any given time and being ready to take advantage of chance and even setbacks. If someone wants to learn to paint, they shouldn’t just theorize about art or overthink what they’re going to do ahead of time; they just need to do something—it doesn't really matter what, as long as it’s something that is easy and convenient for them at that moment; and they should do that task as well as they can. This will eventually open the door to new opportunities, revealing a path that no amount of searching could have found but that could never have been discovered by remaining idle and making no effort at all. "Dans l'animal," says Buffon, "il y a moins de jugement que de sentiment."[25]
It may appear as though this were blowing hot and cold with the same breath, inasmuch as I am insisting that important modifications of structure have been always purposive; and at the same time am denying that the creature modified has had any purpose in the greater part of all those actions which have at length modified both structure and instinct. Thus I say that a bird learns to swim without having any purpose of learning to swim before it set itself to make those movements which have resulted in its being able to do so. At the same time I maintain that it has only learned to swim by trying to swim, and this involves the very purpose which I have just denied. The reconciliation of these two apparently irreconcilable contentions must be found in the consideration that the bird was not the less trying to swim, merely because it did not know the name we have chosen to give to the art[Pg 52] which it was trying to master, nor yet how great were the resources of that art. A person, who knew all about swimming, if from some bank he could watch our supposed bird's first attempt to scramble over a short space of deep water, would at once declare that the bird was trying to swim—if not actually swimming. Provided then that there is a very little perception of, and prescience concerning, the means whereby the next desired end may be attained, it matters not how little in advance that end may be of present desires or faculties; it is still reached through purpose, and must be called purposive. Again, no matter how many of these small steps be taken, nor how absolute was the want of purpose or prescience concerning any but the one being actually taken at any given moment, this does not bar the result from having been arrived at through design and purpose. If each one of the small steps is purposive the result is purposive, though there was never purpose extended over more than one, two, or perhaps at most three, steps at a time.
It might seem like I’m contradicting myself since I’m arguing that important changes in structure are always intentional, while also saying that the creature undergoing these changes didn’t have a purpose for most of the actions that ultimately modified both structure and instinct. For example, a bird learns to swim without intending to learn how to swim before it begins making the movements that enable it to do so. At the same time, I argue that it only learns to swim by actually trying to swim, which involves the very purpose I just denied. The key to reconciling these seemingly conflicting ideas lies in recognizing that the bird was trying to swim, even if it didn’t know the term we've chosen for the skill it was attempting to acquire, or how extensive that skill's resources were. A person who understood swimming, observing our hypothetical bird's first attempts to navigate a small stretch of deep water from the shore, would immediately conclude that the bird was trying to swim—even if it wasn't fully swimming yet. As long as there is at least some awareness and foresight regarding how to achieve the next desired goal, it doesn’t matter how far removed that goal is from current desires or abilities; it is still achieved through intention and should be considered intentional. Furthermore, regardless of how many of these small steps are taken, or how completely lacking in intention or foresight a creature may be about anything but the immediate step it is taking, that doesn’t prevent the outcome from having been reached through intention and planning. If each of these small steps is intentional, then the final result is intentional, even if there was never any overarching intention that spanned more than one, two, or at most three steps at a time.
Returning to the art of painting for an example, are we to say that the proficiency which such a student as was supposed above will certainly attain, is not due to design, merely because it was not until he had already become three parts excellent that he knew the full purport of all that he had been doing? When he began he had but vague notions of what he would do. He had a wish to learn to represent nature, but the line into which he has settled down has probably proved very different from that which he proposed to himself originally. Because he has taken advantage of his accidents, is it,[Pg 53] therefore, one whit the less true that his success is the result of his desires and his design? The 'Times' pointed out not long ago that the theory which now associates meteors and comets in the most unmistakable manner, was suggested by one accident, and confirmed by another. But the writer added well that "such accidents happen only to the zealous student of nature's secrets." In the same way the bird that is taking to the habit of swimming, and of making the most of whatever skin it already has between its toes, will have doubtless to thank accidents for no small part of its progress; but they will be such accidents as could never have happened to, or been taken advantage of by any creature which was not zealously trying to make the most of itself—and between such accidents as this, and design, the line is hard to draw; for if we go deep enough we shall find that most of our design resolves itself into as it were a shaking of the bag to see what will come out that will suit our purpose, and yet at the same time that most of our shaking of the bag resolves itself into a design that the bag shall contain only such and such things, or thereabouts.
Returning to painting as an example, should we say that the skill a student is expected to achieve isn’t due to intention, just because he didn’t fully understand what he was doing until he had already become really good? When he started, he only had vague ideas about what he wanted to create. He wanted to learn how to represent nature, but the path he ended up taking is probably very different from what he originally envisioned. Just because he has benefited from unexpected events, does that mean that it’s any less true that his success comes from his aspirations and intentions? The 'Times' mentioned recently that the theory connecting meteors and comets in a clear way was sparked by one random event and confirmed by another. However, the writer noted that "such accidents only happen to those who are passionate about uncovering nature’s secrets." Similarly, a bird that starts swimming and adapts its feet for the water will likely owe a good deal of its progress to chance; but these will be occurrences that could never happen to or be seized upon by any creature that wasn’t actively trying to optimize itself—and distinguishing between these types of chance events and intention is tricky; for if we look closely enough, we’ll see that much of our intention boils down to shaking a bag to see what comes out that fits our needs, and yet at the same time, much of our bag-shaking is influenced by a design to ensure that the bag contains only certain things.
Again, the fact that animals are no longer conscious of design and purpose in much that they do, but act unreflectingly, and as we sometimes say concerning ourselves "automatically" or "mechanically"—that they have no idea whatever of the steps whereby they have travelled to their present state, and show no sign of doubt about what must have been at one time the subject of all manner of doubts, difficulties, and discussions—that whatever sign of reflection they now exhibit[Pg 54] is to be found only in case of some novel feature or difficulty presenting itself; these facts do not bar that the results achieved should be attributed to an inception in reason, design, and purpose, no matter how rapidly and as we call it instinctively, the creatures may now act.
Once again, the fact that animals are no longer aware of design and purpose in much of what they do, but act instinctively, and as we sometimes describe ourselves as "automatically" or "mechanically"—that they have no understanding of the steps that led to their current state and show no signs of questioning what must have once been the topic of many doubts, difficulties, and discussions—that any sign of thought they now show[Pg 54] is only seen when a new challenge or obstacle arises; these facts do not prevent the results achieved from being credited to an origin in reason, design, and purpose, regardless of how quickly and instinctively the creatures may act now.
For if we look closely at such an invention as the steam engine in its latest and most complicated developments, about which there can be no dispute but that they are achievements of reason, purpose, and design, we shall find them present us with examples of all those features the presence of which in the handiwork of animals is too often held to bar reason and purpose from having had any share therein.
For if we take a close look at an invention like the steam engine in its most advanced and complex forms, which everyone agrees are results of intelligence, intention, and design, we'll find that they showcase all the characteristics that people often claim exclude reason and purpose from the creations of animals.
Assuredly such men as the Marquis of Worcester and Captain Savery had very imperfect ideas as to the upshot of their own action. The simplest steam engine now in use in England is probably a marvel of ingenuity as compared with the highest development which appeared possible to these two great men, while our newest and most highly complicated engines would seem to them more like living beings than machines. Many, again, of the steps leading to the present development have been due to action which had but little heed of the steam engine, being the inventions of attendants whose desire was to save themselves the trouble of turning this or that cock, and who were indifferent to any other end than their own immediate convenience. No step in fact along the whole route was ever taken with much perception of what would be the next step after the one being taken at any given moment.[Pg 55]
Surely, men like the Marquis of Worcester and Captain Savery had a limited understanding of the outcome of their actions. The simplest steam engine currently in use in England is likely a marvel of creativity compared to what these two great figures thought was possible, while our latest and most complex engines might seem more like living beings than machines to them. Many of the advancements that led to our current technology resulted from efforts that paid little attention to the steam engine itself, created by workers who simply wanted to make their tasks easier and had no interest in anything beyond their immediate convenience. In fact, no step along this entire journey was taken with much awareness of what the next step would be after the one being executed at that moment.[Pg 55]
Nor do we find that an engine made after any old and well-known pattern is now made with much more consciousness of design than we can suppose a bird's nest to be built with. The greater number of the parts of any such engine, are made by the gross as it were like screws and nuts, which are turned out by machinery and in respect of which the labour of design is now no more felt than is the design of him who first invented the wheel. It is only when circumstances require any modification in the article to be manufactured that thought and design will come into play again; but I take it few will deny that if circumstances compel a bird either to give up a nest three-parts built altogether, or to make some trifling deviation from its ordinary practice, it will in nine cases out of ten make such deviation as shall show that it had thought the matter over, and had on the whole concluded to take such and such a course, that is to say, that it had reasoned and had acted with such purpose as its reason had dictated.
We don’t find that a machine made after any old and well-known design is created with much more awareness of design than we imagine a bird’s nest to be made. Most of the parts of such a machine are produced en masse, like screws and nuts, which are churned out by machines. In this case, the effort put into design is no more noticeable than the design of the person who first invented the wheel. It’s only when situations demand a change in the product being made that thought and design come into play again. However, it’s fair to say that if a bird is forced to either abandon a nest that’s mostly built or make a small change from its normal behavior, it will usually choose to make a change that shows it has considered the situation and decided on a specific course of action, meaning it has reasoned through it and acted based on its reasoning.
And I imagine that this is the utmost that anyone can claim even for man's own boasted powers. Set the man who has been accustomed to make engines of one type, to make engines of another type without any intermediate course of training or instruction, and he will make no better figure with his engines than a thrush would do if commanded by her mate to make a nest like a blackbird. It is vain then to contend that the ease and certainty with which an action is performed, even though it may have now become matter of such fixed habit that it cannot be suddenly and seriously modified without rendering the whole[Pg 56] performance abortive, is any argument against that action having been an achievement of design and reason in respect of each one of the steps that have led to it; and if in respect of each one of the steps then as regards the entire action; for we see our own most reasoned actions become no less easy, unerring, automatic, and unconscious, than the actions which we call instinctive when they have been repeated a sufficient number of times.
And I think this is the most anyone can claim about human abilities. If you take a person who's always built one kind of machine and ask them to build a different kind without any training or guidance, they'll do no better than a thrush would if her mate asked her to build a nest like a blackbird's. It's pointless to argue that the ease and certainty with which someone performs an action—even if it has become such a fixed habit that it can't be suddenly changed without ruining the whole performance—means that the action wasn't the result of design and reasoning for each step that led to it. If that's true for each step, then it applies to the whole action too. We see our most thought-out actions become just as easy, precise, automatic, and unconscious as actions we call instinctive when they've been repeated enough times.
This has been often pointed out, but I insisted upon it and developed it in 'Life and Habit,' more I believe than has been done hitherto, at the same time making it the key to many phenomena of growth and heredity which without such key seem explained by words rather than by any corresponding peace of mind in our ideas concerning them. Seeing that I dwelt much on the importance of bearing in mind the vanishing tendency of consciousness, volition, and memory upon their becoming intense, a tendency which no one after five minutes' reflection will venture to deny, some reviewers have imagined that I am advocating the same views as have been put forward by Von Hartmann under the title of 'the Philosophy of the Unconscious.' Unless, however, I am much mistaken, their opinion is without foundation. For so far as I can gather, Von Hartmann personifies the unconscious and makes it act and think—in fact deifies it—whereas I only infer a certain history for certain of our growths and actions in consequence of observing that often repeated actions come in time to be performed unconsciously. I cannot think I have done more than note a fact which all must acknowledge, and drawn from it an inference which may[Pg 57] or may not be true, but which is at any rate perfectly intelligible, whereas if Von Hartmann's meaning is anything like what Mr. Sully says it is,[26] I can only say that it has not been given to me to form any definite conception whatever as to what that meaning may be. I am encouraged moreover to hope that I am not in the same condemnation with Von Hartmann—if, indeed, Von Hartmann is to be condemned, about which I know nothing—by the following extract from a German Review of 'Life and Habit.'
This has been pointed out often, but I emphasized it and expanded on it in 'Life and Habit,' more than I believe has been done before, making it central to many aspects of growth and heredity that, without this perspective, seem explained by words rather than by any genuine understanding in our thoughts about them. I highlighted the importance of remembering the fading nature of consciousness, will, and memory when they become intense, a tendency that no one will deny after five minutes of thought. Some reviewers have assumed that I'm promoting the same ideas as Von Hartmann’s 'Philosophy of the Unconscious.' However, unless I'm mistaken, their opinion is unfounded. From what I gather, Von Hartmann personifies the unconscious and gives it the ability to act and think—in fact, he deifies it—while I merely suggest a certain history for some of our growths and actions based on the observation that frequently repeated actions eventually become unconscious. I believe I have only noted a fact that everyone must accept and drawn from it an inference that may or may not be true, but is at least completely understandable, whereas if Von Hartmann's meaning aligns with what Mr. Sully claims it to be, I can only say that I have not been able to form any clear idea of what that meaning could be. I am also hopeful that I am not in the same predicament as Von Hartmann—if, indeed, he should be condemned, about which I'm uncertain—based on the following extract from a German Review of 'Life and Habit.'
"Der erste dieser beiden Erklärungsversuche, ist eine wahre 'Philosophie des Unbewussten' nicht des Hartmann'schen Unbewussten welches hellsehend und wunderthätig von aussen in die natürliche Entwickelung der Organismen eingreift, sondern eines Unbewussten welches wie der Verfasser zeigt, in allen organischen Wesen anzunehmen unsere eigene Erfahrung und die Stufenfolge der Organismen von den Moneren und Amœben bis zu den höchsten Pflanzen und Thieren und uns selbst aufwärts—uns gestattet, wenn nicht uns nöthigt. Der Gedankengang dieser neuen oder wenigstens in diesem Sinne wohl zum ersten Male consequent im Einzelnen durchgeführten Philosophie des Unbewussten ist, seinen Hauptzügen nach kurz angedeutet, folgender."[27]
"Der erste dieser beiden Erklärungsversuche ist eine wahre 'Philosophie des Unbewussten', nicht das Hartmann'sche Unbewusste, das hellsehend und wundernd von außen in die natürliche Entwicklung der Organismen eingreift, sondern ein Unbewusstes, das, wie der Verfasser zeigt, in allen organischen Wesen vorhanden ist. Unsere eigene Erfahrung und die Abfolge der Organismen, von Moneren und Amöben bis zu den höchsten Pflanzen, Tieren und uns selbst, ermöglicht uns, wenn nicht zwingt. Der Gedankengang dieser neuen oder zumindest zum ersten Mal in diesem Sinne konsequent durchgeführten Philosophie des Unbewussten wird in seinen Hauptzügen kurz skizziert wie folgt." [27]
Even here I am made to personify more than I like; I do not wish to say that the unconscious does this or that, but that when we have done this or that sufficiently often we do it unconsciously.
Even here, I find myself having to personify more than I’d prefer; I’m not saying that the unconscious does this or that, but that when we’ve done this or that enough times, we end up doing it unconsciously.
If the foregoing be granted, and it be admitted that the unconsciousness and seeming automatism with which any action may be performed is no bar to its having a foundation in memory, reason, and at one time consciously recognized effort—and this I believe to be the chief addition which I have ventured to make to the theory of Buffon and Dr. Erasmus Darwin—then the wideness of the difference between the Darwinism of eighty years ago and the Darwinism of to-day becomes immediately apparent, and it also becomes apparent, how important and interesting is the issue which is raised between them.
If we accept the above points, and recognize that the unconsciousness and apparent automatism with which any action can be carried out doesn't prevent it from being rooted in memory, reason, and, at one time, conscious effort—and I believe this is the main contribution I've made to the theories of Buffon and Dr. Erasmus Darwin—then the significant differences between Darwinism from eighty years ago and today’s Darwinism become clear, as does the importance and interest of the issues they raise.
According to the older Darwinism the lungs are just as purposive as the corkscrew. They, no less than the corkscrew, are a piece of mechanism designed and gradually improved upon and perfected by an intelligent creature for the gratification of its own needs. True there are many important differences between mechanism which is part of the body, and mechanism which is no such part, but the differences are such as do not affect the fact that in each case the result, whether, for example, lungs or corkscrew, is due to desire, invention, and design.
According to traditional Darwinism, lungs are just as purposeful as a corkscrew. They, just like the corkscrew, are a type of mechanism developed and gradually enhanced by an intelligent being to meet its own needs. While there are many significant differences between mechanisms that are part of the body and those that are not, these differences do not change the fact that in both cases, whether it's lungs or a corkscrew, the outcome is the result of desire, creativity, and design.
And now I will ask one more question, which may seem, perhaps, to have but little importance, but which I find personally interesting. I have been told by a reviewer, of whom upon the whole I have little reason[Pg 59] to complain, that the theory I put forward in 'Life and Habit,' and which I am now again insisting on, is pessimism—pure and simple. I have a very vague idea what pessimism means, but I should be sorry to believe that I am a pessimist. Which, I would ask, is the pessimist? He who sees love of beauty, design, steadfastness of purpose, intelligence, courage, and every quality to which success has assigned the name of "worth," as having drawn the pattern of every leaf and organ now and in all past time, or he who sees nothing in the world of nature but a chapter of accidents and of forces interacting blindly?
And now I have one more question to ask, which might seem a bit unimportant, but I personally find it interesting. A reviewer, who for the most part I have no reason to complain about, told me that the theory I presented in 'Life and Habit,' which I'm emphasizing again now, is just pessimism—nothing more. I have a pretty vague idea of what pessimism actually means, but I would hate to think of myself as a pessimist. So, who exactly is the pessimist? Is it the person who sees love of beauty, design, unwavering purpose, intelligence, courage, and all the qualities that success has labeled as "worthy" as the blueprint for every leaf and organ both now and in the past? Or is it the person who views the natural world as nothing but a series of random events and blindly interacting forces?
FOOTNOTES:
[24] 'Nat. Theol.,' ch. xxiii.
[25] 'Oiseaux,' vol. i. p. 5.
[27] Translation: "The first of these two attempts is a true 'philosophy of the unconscious,' not Hartmann's unconscious, which influences the natural evolution of organism from without as though by Providence and miracle, but of an unconscious, which, as the author shows, our own experience and the progressive succession of organisms from the monads and amœbæ up to the highest plants and animals, including ourselves, allows, if it does not compel us to assume [as obtaining] in all organic beings. This philosophy of the unconscious is new, or at any rate now for the first time carried out consequentially in detail; its main features, briefly stated are as follows."
[27] Translation: "The first of these two attempts is a genuine 'philosophy of the unconscious,' not Hartmann's version, which suggests that the unconscious influences the natural evolution of organisms from the outside as if by Providence and miracle. Instead, it represents an unconscious that, as the author demonstrates, our own experiences and the progressive development of organisms—from monads and amoebas to the most advanced plants and animals, including us—allow, if not require us to assume exists in all living beings. This philosophy of the unconscious is new, or at least it is presented in detail and consistently for the first time; its main features, briefly outlined, are as follows."
SCHEME OF THE REMAINDER OF THE WORK. HISTORICAL SKETCH OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION.
SCHEME OF THE REMAINDER OF THE WORK. HISTORICAL SKETCH OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION.
I have long felt that evolution must stand or fall according as it is made to rest or not on principles which shall give a definite purpose and direction to the variations whose accumulation results in specific, and ultimately in generic differences. In other words, according as it is made to stand upon the ground first clearly marked out for it by Dr. Erasmus Darwin and afterwards adopted by Lamarck, or on that taken by Mr. Charles Darwin.
I have always believed that evolution depends on whether it's based on principles that provide a clear purpose and direction to the variations that accumulate and lead to specific and ultimately generic differences. In other words, whether it's grounded in the ideas first clearly outlined by Dr. Erasmus Darwin and later taken up by Lamarck, or on those introduced by Mr. Charles Darwin.
There is some reason to fear that in consequence of the disfavour into which modern Darwinism is seen to be falling by those who are more closely watching the course of opinion upon this subject, evolution itself may be for a time discredited as something inseparable from the theory that it has come about mainly through "the means" of natural selection. If people are shown that the arguments by which a somewhat startling conclusion has been reached will not legitimately lead to that conclusion, they are very ready to assume that the conclusion must be altogether unfounded, especially when, as in the present case, there is a vast mass of vested interests opposed to the conclusion. Few know that there[Pg 61] are other great works upon descent with modification besides Mr. Darwin's. Not one person in ten thousand has any distinct idea of what Buffon, Dr. Darwin, and Lamarck propounded. Their names have been discredited by the very authors who have been most indebted to them; there is hardly a writer on evolution who does not think it incumbent upon him to warn Lamarck off the ground which he at any rate made his own, and to cast a stone at what he will call the "shallow speculations" or "crude theories" or the "well-known doctrine" of the foremost exponent of Buffon and Dr. Darwin. Buffon is a great name, Dr. Darwin is no longer even this, and Lamarck has been so systematically laughed at that it amounts to little less than philosophical suicide for anyone to stand up in his behalf. Not one of our scientific elders or chief priests but would caution a student rather to avoid the three great men whom I have named than to consult them. It is a perilous task therefore to try and take evolution from the pedestal on which it now appears to stand so securely, and to put it back upon the one raised for it by its propounders; yet this is what I believe will have to be done sooner or later unless the now general acceptance of evolution is to be shaken more rudely than some of its upholders may anticipate. I propose therefore to give a short biographical sketch of the three writers whose works form new departures in the history of evolution, with a somewhat full résumé of the positions they took in regard to it. I will also touch briefly upon some other writers who have handled the same subject. The reader will thus be enabled to[Pg 62] follow the development of a great conception as it has grown up in the minds of successive men of genius, and by thus growing with it, as it were, through its embryonic stages, he will make himself more thoroughly master of it in all its bearings.
There’s some reason to be concerned that because of the declining popularity of modern Darwinism among those closely observing public opinion on this topic, evolution itself might be temporarily discredited as something that can only be explained through natural selection. If people realize that the arguments leading to a somewhat surprising conclusion don’t legitimately support that conclusion, they’re likely to assume it must be completely unfounded, especially when, as in this case, there’s a huge amount of vested interests against it. Few people know that there are other significant works on descent with modification besides Mr. Darwin's. Not one in ten thousand has a clear understanding of what Buffon, Dr. Darwin, and Lamarck proposed. Their names have been discredited by the very authors who owe much to them; hardly any writer on evolution feels it necessary to warn others away from the territory that Lamarck originally claimed and to criticize what they might call “shallow speculations,” “crude theories,” or the “well-known doctrine” of the leading interpreter of Buffon and Dr. Darwin. Buffon is a respected name, Dr. Darwin isn’t recognized even as such anymore, and Lamarck has been laughed at so consistently that it’s nearly philosophical suicide for anyone to defend him. Not one of our scientific elders or major authorities would advise a student to study the three influential figures I’ve mentioned instead of simply avoiding them. It’s a risky task, then, to try to take evolution down from the pedestal where it currently seems so stable and put it back on the foundation built by its original advocates; yet I believe this will need to happen sooner or later unless the current widespread acceptance of evolution is shaken more severely than some of its defenders might expect. Therefore, I plan to provide a brief biographical overview of the three authors whose works represent new milestones in the history of evolution, along with a more detailed summary of their viewpoints on the subject. I will also briefly mention some other authors who have addressed the same topic. This way, the reader will be able to follow the development of a significant idea as it has evolved in the minds of successive brilliant thinkers, and by growing with it, so to speak, through its early stages, they will gain a more complete understanding of it in all its aspects.
I will then contrast the older with the newer Darwinism, and will show why the 'Origin of Species,' though an episode of incalculable value, cannot, any more than the 'Vestiges of Creation,' take permanent rank in the literature of evolution.
I will then compare the older and newer Darwinism, and I will demonstrate why the 'Origin of Species,' despite being an incredibly valuable work, cannot, just like the 'Vestiges of Creation,' hold a permanent place in the literature of evolution.
It will appear that the evolution of evolution has gone through the following principal stages:—
It seems that the evolution of evolution has gone through the following main stages:—
I. A general conception of the fact that specific types were not always immutable.
I. A general understanding that certain types weren't always fixed.
This was common to many writers, both ancient and modern; it has been occasionally asserted from the times of Anaximander and Lucretius to those of Bacon and Sir Walter Raleigh.
This was common among many writers, both ancient and modern; it has been occasionally claimed from the times of Anaximander and Lucretius to those of Bacon and Sir Walter Raleigh.
II. A definite conception that animal and vegetable forms were so extensively mutable that few (and, if so, perhaps but one) could claim to be of an original stock; the direct effect of changed conditions being assigned as the cause of modification, and the important consequences of the struggle for existence being in many respects fully recognized. The fact of design or purpose in connection with organism, as causing habits and thus as underlying all variation, was also indicated with some clearness, but was not thoroughly understood.
II. A clear understanding that animal and plant forms were so changeable that few (and maybe just one) could truly claim to be of an original lineage; the direct impact of altered conditions was seen as the reason for these changes, and the significant effects of the struggle for survival were largely acknowledged. The idea of design or purpose related to organisms, influencing behaviors and thus underlining all variations, was also pointed out with some clarity, but it wasn't completely understood.
This phase must be identified with the name of Buffon, who, as I will show reason for believing, would have carried his theory much further if he had not[Pg 63] felt that he had gone as far in the right direction as was then desirable. Buffon put forward his opinions, with great reserve and yet with hardly less frankness, in volume after volume from 1749 to 1788, the year of his death, but they do not appear to have taken root at once in France. They took root in England, and were thence transplanted back to France.
This phase should be associated with Buffon, who, as I will demonstrate, might have advanced his theory much further if he hadn't[Pg 63] felt he had already progressed as far in the right direction as was appropriate at the time. Buffon expressed his views, with a mix of caution and honesty, in volume after volume from 1749 to 1788, the year he died, but they didn't seem to gain immediate acceptance in France. Instead, they took hold in England and were later brought back to France.
III. A development in England of the Buffonian system, marked by glimpses of the unity between offspring and parents, and broad suggestions to the effect that the former must be considered as capable of remembering, under certain circumstances, what had happened to it, and what it did, when it was part of the personality of those from whom it had descended.
III. A development in England of the Buffonian system, highlighted by insights into the connection between offspring and parents, and broad suggestions that the former can remember, under certain circumstances, what happened to them and what they did when they were part of the personality of their ancestors.
A definite belief, openly expressed, that not only are many species mutable, but that all living forms, whether animal or vegetable, are descended from a single, or at any rate from not many, original low forms of life, and this as the direct consequence of the actions and requirements of the living forms themselves, and as the indirect consequence of changed conditions. A definite cause is thus supposed to underlie variations, and the resulting adaptations become purposive; but this was not said, nor, I am afraid, seen.
A clear belief, openly stated, is that not only are many species changeable, but that all living things, whether animal or plant, come from a single, or at least a few, original simple forms of life. This is seen as a direct result of the actions and needs of the living forms themselves, and an indirect result of changed conditions. A specific cause is believed to underlie variations, making adaptations purposeful; however, this was neither stated nor, I’m afraid, recognized.
This is the original Darwinism of Dr. Erasmus Darwin. It was put forward in his 'Zoonomia,' in 1794, and was adopted almost in its entirety by Lamarck, who, when he had caught the leading idea (probably through a French translation of the 'Loves of the Plants,' which appeared in 1800), began to expound it in 1801; in 1802, 1803, 1806, and 1809,[Pg 64] he developed it with greater fulness of detail than Dr. Darwin had done, but perhaps with a somewhat less nice sense of some important points. Till his death, in 1831, Lamarck, as far as age and blindness would permit, continued to devote himself to the exposition of the theory of descent with modification.
This is the original Darwinism of Dr. Erasmus Darwin. It was presented in his 'Zoonomia' in 1794 and was mostly adopted by Lamarck. After grasping the main idea (likely through a French translation of 'Loves of the Plants,' which came out in 1800), he began to explain it in 1801; in 1802, 1803, 1806, and 1809,[Pg 64] he elaborated on it with more detail than Dr. Darwin, although perhaps with a slightly less refined understanding of some key points. Until his death in 1831, Lamarck, as much as his age and blindness allowed, continued to focus on explaining the theory of descent with modification.
IV. A more distinct perception of the unity of parents and offspring, with a bolder reference of the facts of heredity (whether of structure or instinct), to memory pure and simple; a clearer perception of the consequences that follow from the survival of the fittest, and a just view of the relation in which those consequences stand to "the circumstance-suiting" power of animals and plants; a reference of the variations whose accumulation results in species, to the volition of the animal or plant which varies, and perhaps a dawning perception that all adaptations of structure to need must therefore be considered as "purposive."
IV. A clearer understanding of the connection between parents and their children, with a more straightforward reference to heredity facts (whether related to structure or instinct); a better grasp of the implications of the survival of the fittest, and a fair perspective on how these implications relate to the adaptability of animals and plants; a connection between the variations that lead to new species and the choices made by the animals or plants that change, and maybe even an emerging recognition that all adaptations in structure to meet needs should be viewed as "intentional."
This must be connected with Mr. Matthew's work on 'Naval Timber and Arboriculture,' which appeared in 1831. The remarks which it contains in reference to evolution are confined to an appendix, but when brought together, as by Mr. Matthew himself, in the 'Gardeners' Chronicle' for April 7, 1860, they form one of the most perfect yet succinct expositions of the theory of evolution that I have ever seen. I shall therefore give them in full.[28] This book was well received, and was reviewed in the 'Quarterly Review,'[29] but seems to have been valued rather for its views on naval timber than on evolution. Mr. Matthew's merit[Pg 65] lies in a just appreciation of the importance of each one of the principal ideas which must be present in combination before we can have a correct conception of evolution, and of their bearings upon one another. In his scheme of evolution I find each part kept in due subordination to the others, so that the whole theory becomes more coherent and better articulated than I have elsewhere found it; but I do not detect any important addition to the ideas which Dr. Darwin and Lamarck had insisted upon.
This is likely related to Mr. Matthew's work on 'Naval Timber and Arboriculture,' which was published in 1831. The comments regarding evolution are limited to an appendix, but when compiled together, as Mr. Matthew did in the 'Gardeners' Chronicle' on April 7, 1860, they create one of the clearest and most concise explanations of the theory of evolution I have ever encountered. Therefore, I will present them in full.[28] This book was well received and reviewed in the 'Quarterly Review,'[29] but seemed to be appreciated more for its insights on naval timber than on evolution. Mr. Matthew's strength[Pg 65] lies in recognizing the significance of each of the main concepts that must work together to form a proper understanding of evolution and how they relate to one another. In his evolutionary framework, I find each part appropriately subordinate to the others, making the entire theory more coherent and well-structured than I have encountered elsewhere; however, I do not see any significant additions to the ideas that Dr. Darwin and Lamarck emphasized.
I pass over the 'Vestiges of Creation,' which should be mentioned only as having, as Mr. Charles Darwin truly says, "done excellent service in this country, in calling attention to this subject, in removing prejudice, and in thus preparing the ground for the reception of analogous views."[30] The work neither made any addition to ideas which had been long familiar, nor arranged old ones in a satisfactory manner. Such as it is, it is Dr. Darwin and Lamarck, but Dr. Darwin and Lamarck spoiled. The first edition appeared in 1844.
I will skip over the 'Vestiges of Creation,' which should only be mentioned because, as Mr. Charles Darwin rightly states, it "did excellent service in this country, in calling attention to this subject, in removing prejudice, and in thus preparing the ground for the reception of analogous views."[30] The work didn’t add any new ideas that had not been known for a long time, nor did it organize old ones in a clear way. As it stands, it’s like Dr. Darwin and Lamarck, but a messed-up version of them. The first edition came out in 1844.
I also pass over Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire's 'Natural History,' which appeared 1854-62, and the position of which is best described by calling it intermediate between the one which Buffon thought fit to pretend to take, and that actually taken by Lamarck. The same may be said also of Étienne Geoffroy. I will, however, just touch upon these writers later on.
I also skip over Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire's 'Natural History,' which was published from 1854 to 1862, and the best way to describe its position is that it's in between the stance Buffon tried to adopt and the one actually taken by Lamarck. The same can be said for Étienne Geoffroy. However, I will briefly mention these writers later on.
A short notice, again, will suffice for the opinions of Goethe, Treviranus, and Oken, none of whom can I discover as having originated any important new idea;[Pg 66] but knowing no German, I have taken this opinion from the résumé of each of these writers, given by Professor Haeckel in his 'History of Creation.'
A brief note will be enough for the views of Goethe, Treviranus, and Oken, none of whom seem to have introduced any significant new ideas; [Pg 66] but since I don't know German, I have based this opinion on the summaries of each of these writers provided by Professor Haeckel in his 'History of Creation.'
V. A time of retrogression, during which we find but little apparent appreciation of the unity between parents and offspring; no reference to memory in connection with heredity, whether of instinct or structure; an exaggerated view of the consequences which may be deduced from the fact that the fittest commonly survive in the struggle for existence; the denial of any known principle as underlying variations; comparatively little appreciation of the circumstance-suiting power of plants and animals, and a rejection of purposiveness. By far the most important exponent of this phase of opinion concerning evolution is Mr. Charles Darwin, to whom, however, we are more deeply indebted than to any other living writer for the general acceptance of evolution in one shape or another. The 'Origin of Species' appeared in 1859, the same year, that is to say, as the second volume of Isidore Geoffroy's 'Histoire Naturelle Générale.'
V. A time of regression, where there’s little visible understanding of the connection between parents and their children; no mention of memory related to heredity, whether of instinct or physical traits; an inflated perspective on the implications of the fact that the fittest tend to survive in the fight for survival; a rejection of any known principle that explains variations; a limited recognition of how well plants and animals adapt to their circumstances, and a dismissal of purposefulness. The most significant proponent of this viewpoint on evolution is Mr. Charles Darwin, to whom we owe a great deal more than to any other contemporary writer for the widespread acceptance of evolution in various forms. The 'Origin of Species' was published in 1859, the same year, that is, as the second volume of Isidore Geoffroy's 'Histoire Naturelle Générale.'
VI. A reaction against modern Darwinism, with a demand for definite purpose and design as underlying variations. The best known writers who have taken this line are the Rev. J. J. Murphy and Professor Mivart, whose 'Habit and intelligence' and 'Genesis of Species' appeared in 1869 and 1871 respectively. In Germany Professor Hering has revived the idea of memory as explaining the phenomena of heredity satisfactorily, without probably having been more aware that it had been advanced already than[Pg 67] I was myself when I put it forward recently in 'Life and Habit.' I have never seen the lecture in which Professor Hering has referred the phenomena of heredity to memory, but will give an extract from it which appeared in the 'Athenæum,' as translated by Professor Ray Lankester.[31] The only new feature which I believe I may claim to have added to received ideas concerning evolution, is a perception of the fact that the unconsciousness with which we go through our embryonic and infantile stages, and with which we discharge the greater number and more important of our natural functions, is of a piece with what we observe concerning all habitual actions, as well as concerning memory; an explanation of the phenomena of old age; and of the main principle which underlies longevity. I may, perhaps, claim also to have more fully explained the passage of reason into instinct than I yet know of its having been explained elsewhere.[32]
VI. A reaction against modern Darwinism calls for a clear purpose and design behind variations. The most well-known writers who have taken this stance are Rev. J. J. Murphy and Professor Mivart, whose works 'Habit and Intelligence' and 'Genesis of Species' were published in 1869 and 1871, respectively. In Germany, Professor Hering has revived the idea of memory as a satisfactory explanation for heredity phenomena, likely without knowing it had already been proposed, just as I was unaware when I recently introduced it in 'Life and Habit.' I haven’t seen the lecture where Professor Hering linked heredity to memory, but I will provide an excerpt from it that appeared in the 'Athenæum,' translated by Professor Ray Lankester.[31] The only new aspect I believe I can claim to have added to existing ideas about evolution is the realization that the unconscious way we go through our embryonic and early life stages—and how we carry out most of our natural functions—is connected to what we observe in all habitual actions and memory; this also helps explain the phenomena of old age and the main principle behind longevity. Additionally, I may also claim to have more fully clarified how reason transitions into instinct than I am aware of being done anywhere else.[32]
FOOTNOTES:
[29] Vol. xlix. p. 125.
[32] Apropos of this, a friend has kindly sent me the following extract from Balzac:—"Historiquement, les paysans sont encore au lendemain de la Jacquerie, leur défaite est restée inscrite dans leur cervelle. Ils ne se souviennent plus du fait, il est passé à l'état d'idée instinctive."—Balzac, 'Les Paysans,' v.
[32] In this regard, a friend has kindly sent me the following excerpt from Balzac:—"Historically, the peasants are still living in the aftermath of the Jacquerie; their defeat is permanently etched in their minds. They no longer remember the event; it has become an instinctive idea."—Balzac, 'Les Paysans,' v.
PRE-BUFFONIAN EVOLUTION, AND SOME GERMAN WRITERS.
PRE-BUFFONIAN EVOLUTION, AND SOME GERMAN WRITERS.
Let us now proceed to the fuller development of the foregoing sketch.
Let’s now move on to a more detailed version of the previous outline.
"Undoubtedly," says Isidore Geoffroy, "from the most ancient times many philosophers have imagined vaguely that one species can be transformed into another. This doctrine seems to have been adopted by the Ionian school from the sixth century before our era.... Undoubtedly also the same opinion reappeared on several occasions in the middle ages, and in modern times; it is to be found in some of the hermetic books, where the transmutation of animal and vegetable species, and that of metals, are treated as complementary to one another. In modern times we again find it alluded to by some philosophers, and especially by Bacon, whose boldness is on this point extreme. Admitting it as 'incontestable that plants sometimes degenerate so far as to become plants of another species,' Bacon did not hesitate to try and put his theory into practice. He tried, in 1635, to give 'the rules' for the art of changing 'plants of one species into those of another.'"
"Definitely," says Isidore Geoffroy, "from ancient times, many philosophers have vaguely imagined that one species can transform into another. This idea seems to have been adopted by the Ionian school in the sixth century BCE.... It's clear that the same belief appeared several times during the Middle Ages and in modern times; it's found in some of the hermetic texts, where the transformation of animal and plant species, as well as metals, is discussed as interconnected. In modern times, we see it mentioned again by some philosophers, especially Bacon, who was particularly bold on this subject. He accepted it as 'undeniable that plants sometimes degenerate to the point of becoming plants of another species,' and he didn't hesitate to attempt to implement his theory. In 1635, he sought to provide 'the rules' for the art of changing 'plants of one species into those of another.'"
This must be an error. Bacon died in 1626. The passage of Bacon referred to is in 'Nat. Hist.,' Cent. vi.[Pg 69] ("Experiments in consort touching the degenerating of plants, and the transmutation of them one into another"), and is as follows:—
This has to be a mistake. Bacon died in 1626. The section of Bacon mentioned is in 'Nat. Hist.,' Cent. vi.[Pg 69] ("Experiments together on the degeneration of plants and their transformation into each other"), and it states:—
"518. This rule is certain, that plants for want of culture degenerate to be baser in the same kind; and sometimes so far as to change into another kind. 1. The standing long and not being removed maketh them degenerate. 2. Drought unless the earth, of itself, be moist doth the like. 3. So doth removing into worse earth, or forbearing to compost the earth; as we see that water mint turneth into field mint, and the colewort into rape by neglect, &c."
"518. It's a definite rule that plants decline in quality due to a lack of care, sometimes even changing into a different type. 1. When plants stay in one place for too long without being moved, they deteriorate. 2. Drought causes the same issue unless the soil is naturally moist. 3. The same happens when plants are moved to poorer soil or when there’s a failure to enrich the soil; for example, we see water mint turning into field mint and cabbage turning into kale due to neglect, etc."
"525. It is certain that in very steril years corn sown will grow to another kind:—
"525. It's clear that in very barren years, corn that's planted will transform into a different type."
"Unfortunate wild oats, and barren oats dominate."
And generally it is a rule that plants that are brought forth for culture, as corn, will sooner change into other species, than those that come of themselves; for that culture giveth but an adventitious nature, which is more easily put off."
And generally, it’s a rule that cultivated plants, like corn, will change into other species more quickly than those that grow naturally on their own; because cultivation gives them an artificial nature that can be more easily discarded.
Changed conditions, according to Bacon (though he does not use these words), appear to be "the first rule for the transmutation of plants."
Changed conditions, according to Bacon (though he doesn’t use these words), seem to be "the first rule for the transmutation of plants."
"But how much value," continues M. Geoffroy, "ought to be attached to such prophetic glimpses, when they were neither led up to, nor justified by any serious study? They are conjectures only, which, while bearing evidence to the boldness or rashness of those who hazarded them, remain almost without effect upon the advance of science. Bacon excepted, they hardly deserve[Pg 70] to be remembered. As for De Maillet, who makes birds spring from flying fishes, reptiles from creeping fishes, and men from tritons, his dreams, taken in part from Anaximander, should have their place not in the history of science, but in that of the aberrations of the human mind."[33]
"But how much value," continues M. Geoffroy, "should we really place on such prophetic insights when they aren't supported by any serious research? They are just guesses, which, while showcasing the boldness or recklessness of those who made them, have little impact on the progress of science. Except for Bacon, they hardly deserve[Pg 70] to be remembered. As for De Maillet, who claims that birds come from flying fish, reptiles from crawling fish, and humans from tritons, his ideas, partly drawn from Anaximander, should be seen not in the history of science, but in the history of human misconceptions."[33]
A far more forcible and pregnant passage, however, is the following, from Sir Walter Raleigh's 'History of the World,' which Mr. Garnett has been good enough to point out to me:—
A much more powerful and impactful passage, however, is the following from Sir Walter Raleigh's 'History of the World,' which Mr. Garnett has kindly brought to my attention:—
"For mine owne opinion I find no difference but only in magnitude between the Cat of Europe, and the Ounce of India; and even those dogges which are become wild in Hispagniola, with which the Spaniards used to devour the naked Indians, are now changed to Wolves, and begin to destroy the breed of their Cattell, and doe often times teare asunder their owne children. The common crow and rooke of India is full of red feathers in the droun'd and low islands of Caribana, and the blackbird and thrush hath his feathers mixt with black and carnation in the north parts of Virginia. The Dog-fish of England is the Sharke of the South Ocean. For if colour or magnitude made a difference of Species, then were the Negroes, which wee call the Blacke-Mores, non animalia rationalia, not Men but some kind of strange Beasts, and so the giants of the South America should be of another kind than the people of this part of the World. We also see it dayly that the nature of fruits are changed by transplantation."[34]
"In my opinion, I see no difference other than size between the European cat and the Indian ounce; even those dogs that have become wild in Hispaniola, which the Spaniards used to eat along with the naked Indians, have now turned into wolves and are starting to wipe out livestock, even tearing apart their own young. The common crow and rook in India are covered with red feathers in the drowned and low islands of Caribana, while the blackbird and thrush have feathers mixed with black and pink in the northern regions of Virginia. The dogfish in England is the same as the shark in the South Ocean. If color or size determined species, then the Negroes, whom we call the Black Moors, would be non animalia rationalia, not human but some sort of strange beasts, and the giants of South America would be entirely different from the people in this part of the world. We also observe daily that the nature of fruits changes when they are transplanted." [34]
[Pg 71] For information concerning the earliest German writers on evolution, I turn to Professor Haeckel's 'History of Creation,' and find Goethe's name to head the list. I do not gather, however, that Goethe added much to the ideas which Buffon had already made sufficiently familiar. Professor Haeckel does not seem to be aware of Buffon's work, and quotes Goethe as making an original discovery when he writes, in the year 1796:—"Thus much then we have gained, that we may assert without hesitation that all the more perfect organic natures, such as fishes, amphibious animals, birds, mammals, and man at the head of the last, were all formed upon one original type, which only varies more or less in parts which were none the less permanent, and still daily changes and modifies its form by propagation."[35] But these, as we shall see, are almost Buffon's own words—words too that Buffon insisted on for many years. Again Professor Haeckel quotes Goethe as writing in the year 1807:—
[Pg 71] For information on the earliest German writers about evolution, I look to Professor Haeckel's 'History of Creation' and see that Goethe's name tops the list. However, I don't get the impression that Goethe contributed much beyond what Buffon had already made quite familiar. Professor Haeckel doesn't seem to recognize Buffon's work and cites Goethe as making an original discovery when he writes in 1796:—"So far, we have gained this much: we can confidently assert that all the more advanced organic beings, like fish, amphibians, birds, mammals, and man as the most advanced, were all developed from one original type, which varies slightly in different permanent parts, and continues to change and modify its form through reproduction."[35] But these are almost exactly Buffon's own words—words that Buffon emphasized for many years. Again, Professor Haeckel quotes Goethe as writing in 1807:—
"If we consider plants and animals in their most imperfect condition, they can hardly be distinguished." This, however, had long been insisted upon by Bonnet and Dr. Erasmus Darwin, the first of whom was a naturalist of world-wide fame, while the 'Zoonomia' of Dr. Darwin had been translated into German between the years 1795 and 1797, and could hardly have been unknown to Goethe in 1807, who continues: "But this much we may say, that the creatures which by degrees emerge as plants and animals out of a common phase where they are barely distinguishable, arrive at perfection in two opposite directions, so that the plant in the[Pg 72] end reaches its highest glory in the tree, which is immovable and stiff, the animal in man who possesses the greatest elasticity and freedom." Professor Haeckel considers this to be a remarkable passage, but I do not think it should cause its author to rank among the founders of the evolution theory, though he may justly claim to have been one of the first to adopt it. Goethe's anatomical researches appear to have been more important, but I cannot find that he insisted on any new principle, or grasped any unfamiliar conception, which had not been long since grasped and widely promulgated by Buffon and by Dr. Erasmus Darwin.
"If we look at plants and animals in their most basic form, they can hardly be told apart." This idea had been emphasized for a long time by Bonnet and Dr. Erasmus Darwin, the former being a well-known naturalist, while Dr. Darwin's 'Zoonomia' was translated into German between 1795 and 1797, and it’s hard to believe Goethe didn’t know about it by 1807. He goes on to say, "What we can say is that the creatures that gradually evolve into plants and animals from a common stage where they are barely distinguishable end up reaching their highest forms in two completely different ways: the plant culminates in the tree, which is still and rigid, while the animal culminates in man, who has the greatest flexibility and freedom." Professor Haeckel considers this a significant statement, but I don’t think it should elevate its author to the status of a founder of evolutionary theory, although he can rightly claim to have been one of its early adopters. Goethe’s anatomical studies seem more significant, but I can’t find evidence that he proposed any new principles or grasped any novel concepts that hadn’t already been understood and widely spread by Buffon and Dr. Erasmus Darwin.
Treviranus (1776-1837), whom Professor Haeckel places second to Goethe, is clearly a disciple of Buffon, and uses the word "degeneration" in the same sense as Buffon used it many years earlier, that is to say, as "descent with modification," without any reference to whether the offspring was, as Buffon says, "perfectionné ou dégradé." He cannot claim, any more than Goethe, to rank as a principal figure in the history of evolution.
Treviranus (1776-1837), whom Professor Haeckel ranks just after Goethe, is obviously a follower of Buffon and uses the term "degeneration" in the same way Buffon did many years earlier, meaning "descent with modification," without indicating whether the offspring was, as Buffon puts it, "perfectionné ou dégradé." Like Goethe, he cannot be considered a leading figure in the history of evolution.
Of Oken, Professor Haeckel says that his 'Naturphilosophie,' which appeared in 1809—in the same year, that is to say, as the 'Philosophie Zoologique' of Lamarck—was "the nearest approach to the natural theory of descent, newly established by Mr. Charles Darwin," of any work that appeared in the first decade of our century. But I do not detect any important difference of principle between his system and that of Dr. Erasmus Darwin, among whose disciples he should be reckoned.
Of Oken, Professor Haeckel says that his 'Naturphilosophie,' which came out in 1809—in the same year as Lamarck's 'Philosophie Zoologique'—was "the closest thing to the natural theory of evolution, recently established by Mr. Charles Darwin," of any work published in the first decade of our century. However, I don't see any significant difference in principle between his system and that of Dr. Erasmus Darwin, among whose followers he should be considered.
"We now turn," says Professor Haeckel after referring to a few more German writers who adopted a belief in[Pg 73] evolution, "from the German to the French nature-philosophers who have likewise held the theory of descent, since the beginning of this century. At their head stands Jean Lamarck, who occupies the first place next to Darwin and Goethe in the history of the doctrine of Filiation."[36] This is rather a surprising assertion, but I will leave the reader of the present volume to assign the value which should be attached to it.
"We now turn," says Professor Haeckel after mentioning a few more German writers who embraced the idea of evolution, "from the German to the French nature philosophers who have also supported the theory of descent since the beginning of this century. Leading the way is Jean Lamarck, who holds a prominent position right after Darwin and Goethe in the history of the doctrine of Filiation." This is quite a bold statement, but I will let the reader of this volume determine the significance it deserves.
Professor Haeckel devotes ten lines to Dr. Erasmus Darwin, who he declares "expresses views very similar to those of Goethe and Lamarck, without, however, then knowing anything about these two men;" which is all the more strange inasmuch as Dr. Darwin preceded them, and was a good deal better known to them, probably, than they to him; but it is plain Professor Haeckel has no acquaintance with the 'Zoonomia' of Dr. Erasmus Darwin. From all, then, that I am able to collect, I conclude that I shall best convey to the reader an idea of the different phases which the theory of descent with modification has gone through, by confining his attention almost entirely to Buffon, Dr. Erasmus Darwin, Lamarck, and Mr. Charles Darwin.
Professor Haeckel spends ten lines on Dr. Erasmus Darwin, whom he claims "expresses ideas very similar to those of Goethe and Lamarck, without, however, then knowing anything about these two men;" which is even more surprising since Dr. Darwin came before them and was likely better known to them than they were to him. However, it’s clear that Professor Haeckel isn’t familiar with Dr. Erasmus Darwin's 'Zoonomia.' Therefore, from everything I’ve gathered, I believe I can best give the reader an understanding of the different stages that the theory of descent with modification has gone through by focusing primarily on Buffon, Dr. Erasmus Darwin, Lamarck, and Mr. Charles Darwin.
FOOTNOTES:
BUFFON—MEMOIR.
BUFFON—MEMOIR.
Buffon, says M. Flourens, was born at Montbar, on the 7th of September, 1707; he died in Paris, at the Jardin du Roi, on the 16th of April, 1788, aged 81 years. More than fifty of these years, as he used himself to say, he had passed at his writing-desk. His father was a councillor of the parliament of Burgundy. His mother was celebrated for her wit, and Buffon cherished her memory.
Buffon, as M. Flourens notes, was born in Montbar on September 7, 1707. He died in Paris at the Jardin du Roi on April 16, 1788, at the age of 81. For more than fifty of those years, as he often remarked, he spent his time at his writing desk. His father was a councillor in the parliament of Burgundy. His mother was known for her sharp wit, and Buffon held her memory dear.
He studied at Dijon with much éclat, and shortly after leaving became accidentally acquainted with the Duke of Kingston, a young Englishman of his own age, who was travelling abroad with a tutor. The three travelled together in France and Italy, and Buffon then passed some months in England.
He studied in Dijon with great flair, and soon after finishing, he happened to meet the Duke of Kingston, a young Englishman his age, who was traveling abroad with a tutor. The three of them traveled together through France and Italy, and then Buffon spent several months in England.
Returning to France, he translated Hales's 'Vegetable Statics' and Newton's 'Treatise on Fluxions.' He refers to several English writers on natural history in the course of his work, but I see he repeatedly spells the English name Willoughby, "Willulghby." He was appointed superintendent of the Jardin du Roi in 1739, and from thenceforth devoted himself to science.
Returning to France, he translated Hales's 'Vegetable Statics' and Newton's 'Treatise on Fluxions.' He mentions several English writers on natural history throughout his work, but I notice he keeps spelling the English name Willoughby as "Willulghby." He was appointed superintendent of the Jardin du Roi in 1739, and from then on, he dedicated himself to science.
In 1752 Buffon married Mdlle. de Saint Bélin, whose beauty and charm of manner were extolled by all her[Pg 75] contemporaries. One son was born to him, who entered the army, became a colonel, and I grieve to say, was guillotined at the age of twenty-nine, a few days only before the extinction of the Reign of Terror.
In 1752, Buffon married Mdlle. de Saint Bélin, whose beauty and charm were praised by everyone around her[Pg 75]. They had one son who joined the army, rose to the rank of colonel, and, sadly, was guillotined at the age of twenty-nine, just a few days before the end of the Reign of Terror.
Of this youth, who inherited the personal comeliness and ability of his father, little is recorded except the following story. Having fallen into the water and been nearly drowned when he was about twelve years old, he was afterwards accused of having been afraid: "I was so little afraid," he answered, "that though I had been offered the hundred years which my grandfather lived, I would have died then and there, if I could have added one year to the life of my father;" then thinking for a minute, a flush suffused his face, and he added, "but I should petition for one quarter of an hour in which to exult over the thought of what I was about to do."
Of this young man, who inherited his father's charm and talent, not much is recorded except for this story. When he was about twelve years old, he fell into the water and nearly drowned. Later, he was accused of being scared. He replied, "I was so little afraid that even if I had been offered the hundred years my grandfather lived, I would have died right then if it meant adding just one more year to my father's life." After thinking for a moment, he blushed and added, "But I would ask for a quarter of an hour to celebrate the thought of what I was about to do."
On the scaffold he showed much composure, smiling half proudly, half reproachfully, yet wholly kindly upon the crowd in front of him. "Citoyens," he said, "Je me nomme Buffon," and laid his head upon the block.
On the scaffold, he appeared very calm, smiling partly with pride, partly with reproach, but overall with kindness at the crowd in front of him. "Citizens," he said, "My name is Buffon," and laid his head on the block.
The noblest outcome of the old and decaying order, overwhelmed in the most hateful birth frenzy of the new. So in those cataclysms and revolutions which take place in our own bodies during their development, when we seem studying in order to become fishes and suddenly make, as it were, different arrangements and resolve on becoming men—so, doubtless, many good cells must go, and their united death cry comes up, it may be, in the pain which an infant feels on teething.
The most honorable result of the old and outdated system, crushed by the intense, ugly rush of the new. Just like the huge changes and upheavals that happen in our own bodies as we develop, when we appear to be evolving into fish but then suddenly decide to become humans—many good cells must die, and their collective cry of death could be expressed in the pain a baby feels while teething.
But to return. The man who could be father of[Pg 76] such a son, and who could retain that son's affection, as it is well known that Buffon retained it, may not perhaps always be strictly accurate, but it will be as well to pay attention to whatever he may think fit to tell us. These are the only people whom it is worth while to look to and study from.
But to get back to the point. The man who could be the father of[Pg 76] such a son, and who could maintain that son's affection, as it is well known Buffon did, may not always be completely accurate, but it's still wise to pay attention to whatever he thinks is worth sharing. These are the only people it’s worth looking up to and learning from.
"Glory," said Buffon, after speaking of the hours during which he had laboured, "glory comes always after labour if she can—and she generally can." But in his case she could not well help herself. "He was conspicuous," says M. Flourens, "for elevation and force of character, for a love of greatness and true magnificence in all he did. His great wealth, his handsome person, and graceful manners seemed in correspondence with the splendour of his genius, so that of all the gifts which Fortune has it in her power to bestow she had denied him nothing."
"Glory," said Buffon, after talking about the hours he had worked, "glory always comes after hard work if it can—and it usually can." But in his case, it really couldn’t help but show up. "He stood out," says M. Flourens, "for his high standards and strong character, for his love of greatness and true magnificence in everything he did. His substantial wealth, attractive appearance, and elegant manners seemed to match the brilliance of his genius, so that of all the gifts Fortune has the power to give, she denied him nothing."
Many of his epigrammatic sayings have passed into proverbs: for example, that "genius is but a supreme capacity for taking pains." Another and still more celebrated passage shall be given in its entirety and with its original setting.
Many of his witty sayings have become proverbs: for example, that "genius is just a top-level ability to work hard." Another even more famous quote will be provided in full with its original context.
"Style," says Buffon, "is the only passport to posterity. It is not range of information, nor mastery of some little known branch of science, nor yet novelty of matter that will ensure immortality. Works that can claim all this will yet die if they are conversant about trivial objects only, or written without taste, genius and true nobility of mind; for range of information, knowledge of details, novelty of discovery are of a volatile essence and fly off readily into other hands[Pg 77] that know better how to treat them. The matter is foreign to the man, and is not of him; the manner is the man himself."[37]
"Style," Buffon says, "is the only passport to lasting recognition. It's not just about how much information you have, or being skilled in some obscure area of science, or even having new ideas that guarantees you will be remembered. Even works that have all of these qualities will fade away if they focus on trivial subjects, or if they are written without taste, creativity, and true nobility of spirit; because information, detailed knowledge, and innovative discoveries are easily forgotten and taken by others who know how to present them better. The content isn't inherently part of the person; the way it's presented is what defines the person himself.[Pg 77]
"Le style, c'est l'homme même." Elsewhere he tells us what true style is, but I quote from memory and cannot be sure of the passage. "Le style," he says, "est comme le bonheur; il vient de la douceur de l'âme."
"Style is a reflection of the individual." In other places, he explains what true style is, but I'm quoting from memory and can't guarantee the exact wording. "Style," he says, "is like happiness; it comes from the gentleness of the soul."
Is it possible not to think of the following?—
Is it possible to not think about the following?—
"But whether there be prophecies they shall fail; whether there be tongues they shall cease; whether there be knowledge it shall vanish away ... and now abideth faith, hope and charity, these three; but the greatest of these is charity."[38]
"But whether there are prophecies, they will end; whether there are languages, they will stop; whether there is knowledge, it will disappear... and now faith, hope, and love remain, these three; but the greatest of these is love."[38]
FOOTNOTES:
[38] 1 Cor. xiii. 8, 13.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 1 Cor. 13:8, 13.
BUFFON'S METHOD—THE IRONICAL CHARACTER OF HIS WORK.
BUFFON'S METHOD—THE IRONICAL CHARACTER OF HIS WORK.
Buffon's idea of a method amounts almost to the denial of the possibility of method at all. "The true method," he writes, "is the complete description and exact history of each particular object,"[39] and later on he asks, "is it not more simple, more natural and more true to call an ass an ass, and a cat a cat, than to say, without knowing why, that an ass is a horse, and a cat a lynx."[40]
Buffon's concept of a method nearly rejects the idea of a method altogether. "The true method," he writes, "is to fully describe and accurately narrate each specific object,"[39] and later he questions, "Isn’t it simpler, more natural, and more accurate to call an ass an ass and a cat a cat, rather than to say, without understanding why, that an ass is a horse and a cat is a lynx?"[40]
He admits such divisions as between animals and vegetables, or between vegetables and minerals, but that done, he rejects all others that can be founded on the nature of things themselves. He concludes that one who could see things in their entirety and without preconceived opinions, would classify animals according to the relations in which he found himself standing towards them:—
He acknowledges divisions like those between animals and plants, or between plants and minerals, but beyond that, he dismisses any other divisions based on the essence of things themselves. He concludes that someone who could see everything as a whole and without any biases would categorize animals based on the relationships they have with them:—
"Those which he finds most necessary and useful to him will occupy the first rank; thus he will give the precedence among the lower animals to the dog and the horse; he will next concern himself with those which without being domesticated, nevertheless occupy the[Pg 79] same country and climate as himself, as for example stags, hares, and all wild animals; nor will it be till after he has familiarized himself with all these that curiosity will lead him to inquire what inhabitants there may be in foreign climates, such as elephants, dromedaries, &c. The same will hold good for fishes, birds, insects, shells, and for all nature's other productions; he will study them in proportion to the profit which he can draw from them; he will consider them in that order in which they enter into his daily life; he will arrange them in his head according to this order, which is in fact that in which he has become acquainted with them, and in which it concerns him to think about them. This order—the most natural of all—is the one which I have thought it well to follow in this volume. My classification has no more mystery in it than the reader has just seen ... it is preferable to the most profound and ingenious that can be conceived, for there is none of all the classifications which ever have been made or ever can be, which has not more of an arbitrary character than this has. Take it for all in all," he concludes, "it is more easy, more agreeable, and more useful, to consider things in their relation to ourselves than from any other standpoint."[41]
"Those that he finds most necessary and useful will come first; for example, he will prioritize the dog and the horse among domesticated animals. Next, he will pay attention to animals that, while not domesticated, still share his environment, like deer, hares, and other wild creatures. Only after he has become familiar with these will his curiosity lead him to explore what other animals exist in distant lands, such as elephants and camels. The same goes for fish, birds, insects, shells, and other aspects of nature; he will study them based on the benefits they offer him. He will consider them according to how they fit into his daily life, organizing them in his mind based on this order, which reflects how he has encountered them and the relevance they hold for him. This order—the most natural one—is the approach I have chosen for this volume. My classification is as straightforward as the reader has just seen. It is better than the most intricate and clever systems that can be devised because no classification that has ever existed or could exist is less arbitrary than this one. Overall,” he concludes, “it is easier, more enjoyable, and more useful to think about things in relation to ourselves rather than from any other perspective."
"Has it not a better effect not only in a treatise on natural history, but in a picture or any work of art to arrange objects in the order and place in which they are commonly found, than to force them into association in virtue of some theory of our own? Is it not better to let the dog which has toes, come after the horse which[Pg 80] has a single hoof, in the same way as we see him follow the horse in daily life, than to follow up the horse by the zebra, an animal which is little known to us, and which has no other connection with the horse than the fact that it has a single hoof?"[42]
"Isn’t it more effective, not just in a natural history essay but also in a painting or any artwork, to organize objects in the way and order that we typically see them, rather than forcing them together based on some theory we have? Isn't it better to show the dog with toes coming after the horse with a single hoof, just like we see in real life, instead of following the horse with the zebra, an animal we don’t know much about, and which is only similar to the horse because it also has a single hoof?"[Pg 80][42]
Can we suppose that Buffon really saw no more connection than this? The writer whom we shall presently find[43] declining to admit any essential difference between the skeletons of man and of the horse, can here see no resemblance between the zebra and the horse, except that they each have a single hoof. Is he to be taken at his word?
Can we assume that Buffon truly saw no more connection than this? The writer we will soon encounter[43] refusing to recognize any significant difference between the skeletons of humans and horses can only see one similarity between zebras and horses, which is that they both have a single hoof. Should we take his word for it?
It is perhaps necessary to tell the reader that Buffon carried the foregoing scheme into practice as nearly as he could in the first fifteen volumes of his 'Natural History.' He begins with man—and then goes on to the horse, the ass, the cow, sheep, goat, pig, dog, &c. One would be glad to know whether he found it always more easy to decide in what order of familiarity this or that animal would stand to the majority of his readers than other classifiers have found it to know whether an individual more resembles one species or another; probably he never gave the matter a thought after he had gone through the first dozen most familiar animals, but settled generally down into a classification which becomes more and more specific—as when he treats of the apes and monkeys—till he reaches the birds, when he openly abandons his original idea, in deference, as he says, to the opinion of "le peuple des naturalistes."
It might be helpful to mention that Buffon implemented his plan as closely as he could in the first fifteen volumes of his 'Natural History.' He starts with humans, then moves on to the horse, donkey, cow, sheep, goat, pig, dog, and so on. It would be interesting to know if he found it easier to determine how familiar different animals were to most of his readers compared to what other classifiers have found when figuring out whether an individual more closely resembles one species or another. It’s likely that he didn't think much about this after he went through the first dozen well-known animals and instead settled into a classification that became increasingly specific—as seen when he discusses apes and monkeys—until he reaches birds, at which point he openly abandons his original idea, deferring, as he says, to the opinion of "le peuple des naturalistes."
Perhaps the key to this piece of apparent extravagance is to be found in the word "mystérieuse."[44] Buffon wished to raise a standing protest against mystery mongering. Or perhaps more probably, he wished at once "to turn to animals and plants under domestication," so as to insist early on the main object of his work—the plasticity of animal forms.
Perhaps the key to this seemingly extravagant piece lies in the word "mysterieuse."[44] Buffon wanted to make a strong statement against mystery-seeking. Or more likely, he intended to "focus on animals and plants that are domesticated," emphasizing early on the main goal of his work—the adaptability of animal forms.
I am inclined to think that a vein of irony pervades the whole, or much the greater part of Buffon's work, and that he intended to convey, one meaning to one set of readers, and another to another; indeed, it is often impossible to believe that he is not writing between his lines for the discerning, what the undiscerning were not intended to see. It must be remembered that his 'Natural History' has two sides,—a scientific and a popular one. May we not imagine that Buffon would be unwilling to debar himself from speaking to those who could understand him, and yet would wish like Handel and Shakespeare to address the many, as well as the few? But the only manner in which these seemingly irreconcilable ends could be attained, would be by the use of language which should be self-adjusting to the capacity of the reader. So keen an observer can hardly have been blind to the signs of the times which were already close at hand. Free-thinker though he was, he was also a powerful member of the aristocracy, and little likely to demean himself—for so he would doubtless hold it—by playing the part of Voltaire or Rousseau. He would help those who could see to see still further, but he would not dazzle eyes that were yet[Pg 82] imperfect with a light brighter than they could stand. He would therefore impose upon people, as much as he thought was for their good; but, on the other hand, he would not allow inferior men to mystify them.
I tend to think that there's a thread of irony running throughout most of Buffon's work, and that he meant to communicate one message to one group of readers and something different to another. It's often hard to believe that he's not writing between the lines for those who can grasp it, while the less discerning aren't meant to see it. We should keep in mind that his 'Natural History' has two aspects—a scientific one and a popular one. Can't we imagine that Buffon would hesitate to limit himself from speaking to those who could understand him, while still wanting to reach both the masses and the elites, like Handel and Shakespeare? The only way he could achieve these seemingly conflicting goals would be to use language that adjusts to the reader's understanding. Such a sharp observer could hardly have missed the signs of the times that were already upon him. Even though he was a free thinker, he was also a significant member of the aristocracy and unlikely to lower himself—for that's how he would likely see it—by taking on the role of Voltaire or Rousseau. He would help those who could see to see even further, but he wouldn’t overwhelm those whose vision was still imperfect with a light too bright for them to handle. Therefore, he would challenge people as much as he deemed beneficial, but at the same time, he wouldn’t let lesser minds confuse them.
"In the private character of Buffon," says Sir William Jardine in a characteristic passage, "we regret there is not much to praise; his disposition was kind and benevolent, and he was generally beloved by his inferiors, followers, and dependents, which were numerous over his extensive property; he was strictly honourable, and was an affectionate parent. In early youth he had entered into the pleasures and dissipations of life, and licentious habits seem to have been retained to the end. But the great blemish in such a mind was his declared infidelity; it presents one of those exceptions among the persons who have been devoted to the study of nature; and it is not easy to imagine a mind apparently with such powers, scarcely acknowledging a Creator, and when noticed, only by an arraignment for what appeared wanting or defective in his great works. So openly, indeed, was the freedom of his religious opinions expressed, that the indignation of the Sorbonne was provoked. He had to enter into an explanation which he in some way rendered satisfactory; and while he afterwards attended to the outward ordinances of religion, he considered them as a system of faith for the multitude, and regarded those most impolitic who most opposed them."[45]
"In the private life of Buffon," says Sir William Jardine in a characteristic passage, "we note that there isn't much to praise; he had a kind and charitable nature, and he was generally loved by his subordinates, followers, and many dependents across his vast estate; he was strictly honorable and a caring parent. In his youth, he indulged in the pleasures and excesses of life, and those reckless habits seem to have followed him throughout his life. However, the significant flaw in such a mind was his open infidelity; it stands out as an exception among those who have dedicated themselves to studying nature; it's hard to imagine a mind with such apparent abilities that barely acknowledges a Creator, and when mentioned, it’s only to criticize what seemed lacking or flawed in his great works. His expression of religious freedom was so blatant that it provoked outrage from the Sorbonne. He had to provide an explanation that he somehow made satisfactory; and while he later adhered to the outward practices of religion, he viewed them as a system of belief for the masses and considered those who most opposed them to be the most unwise."[45]
This is partly correct and partly not. Buffon was a free-thinker, and as I have sufficiently explained, a[Pg 83] decided opponent of the doctrine that rudimentary and therefore useless organs were designed by a Creator in order to serve some useful end throughout all time to the creature in which they are found.
This is partly true and partly not. Buffon was a free-thinker, and as I've explained enough, a[Pg 83] determined opponent of the idea that rudimentary and therefore useless organs were created by a Creator to fulfill some useful purpose for the creature in which they exist throughout all time.
He was not, surely, to hide the magnificent conceptions which he had been the first to grasp, from those who were worthy to receive them; on the other hand he would not tell the uninstructed what they would interpret as a license to do whatever they pleased, inasmuch as there was no God. What he did was to point so irresistibly in the right direction, that a reader of any intelligence should be in no doubt as to the road he ought to take, and then to contradict himself so flatly as to reassure those who would be shocked by a truth for which they were not yet ready. If I am right in the view which I have taken of Buffon's work, it is not easy to see how he could have formed a finer scheme, nor have carried it out more finely.
He definitely didn’t intend to keep the amazing ideas he was the first to understand from those who were ready to receive them; however, he also wouldn’t share them with the uneducated, who might misinterpret them as a free pass to do whatever they wanted, since there was no God. What he did was point so clearly in the right direction that any intelligent reader should know exactly which path to follow, while also contradicting himself so obviously that it would reassure those who might be unsettled by a truth they weren’t ready for yet. If I’m correct in my interpretation of Buffon's work, it’s hard to see how he could have created a better plan or executed it more beautifully.
I should, however, warn the reader to be on his guard against accepting my view too hastily. So far as I know I stand alone in taking it. Neither Dr. Darwin nor Flourens, nor Isidore Geoffroy, nor Mr. Charles Darwin see any subrisive humour in Buffon's pages; but it must be remembered that Flourens was a strong opponent of mutability, and probably paid but little heed to what Buffon said on this question; Isidore Geoffroy is not a safe guide, as will appear presently; Mr. Charles Darwin seems to have adopted the one half of Isidore Geoffroy's conclusions without verifying either; and Dr. Erasmus Darwin, who has no small share of a very pleasant conscious humour, yet sometimes[Pg 84] rises to such heights of unconscious humour, that Buffon's puny labour may well have been invisible to him. Dr. Darwin wrote a great deal of poetry, some of which was about the common pump. Miss Seward tells us, as we shall see later on, that he "illustrated this familiar object with a picture of Maternal Beauty administering sustenance to her infant." Buffon could not have done anything like this.
I should, however, warn the reader to be careful not to accept my view too quickly. As far as I know, I stand alone in this opinion. Neither Dr. Darwin, nor Flourens, nor Isidore Geoffroy, nor Mr. Charles Darwin see any sarcastic humor in Buffon's writings; but it must be noted that Flourens was a strong opponent of change, and probably paid little attention to what Buffon said on this topic. Isidore Geoffroy is not a reliable source, as will become clear shortly; Mr. Charles Darwin seems to have accepted part of Isidore Geoffroy's conclusions without verifying them; and Dr. Erasmus Darwin, who has a good sense of humor, sometimes rises to such levels of unintentional humor that Buffon's minor efforts might have gone unnoticed by him. Dr. Darwin wrote a lot of poetry, some of which was about the common pump. Miss Seward tells us, as we will see later, that he "illustrated this familiar object with a picture of Maternal Beauty administering sustenance to her infant." Buffon could not have done anything like this.
Buffon never, then, "arraigned the Creator for what was wanting or defective in His works;" on the contrary, whenever he has led up by an irresistible chain of reasoning to conclusions which should make men recast their ideas concerning the Deity, he invariably retreats under cover of an appeal to revelation. Naturally enough, the Sorbonne objected to an artifice which even Buffon could not conceal completely. They did not like being undermined; like Buffon himself, they preferred imposing upon the people, to seeing others do so. Buffon made his peace with the Sorbonne immediately, and, perhaps, from that time forward, contradicted himself a little more impudently than heretofore.
Buffon never "accused the Creator of having flaws or shortcomings in His works;" instead, whenever he reached conclusions through an undeniable chain of reasoning that should prompt people to rethink their views of God, he consistently fell back on an appeal to revelation. It’s no surprise that the Sorbonne objected to a tactic that even Buffon couldn't fully hide. They didn’t like being undermined; like Buffon himself, they preferred to deceive the public rather than see others do it. Buffon quickly made amends with the Sorbonne, and perhaps from that point on, he contradicted himself a bit more boldly than before.
It is probably for the reasons above suggested that Buffon did not propound a connected scheme of evolution or descent with modification, but scattered his theory in fragments up and down his work in the prefatory remarks with which he introduces the more striking animals or classes of animals. He never wastes evolutionary matter in the preface to an uninteresting animal; and the more interesting the animal, the more evolution will there be commonly found. When he comes to describe the animal more familiarly—and he generally[Pg 85] begins a fresh chapter or half chapter when he does so—he writes no more about evolution, but gives an admirable description, which no one can fail to enjoy, and which I cannot think is nearly so inaccurate as is commonly supposed. These descriptions are the parts which Buffon intended for the general reader, expecting, doubtless, and desiring that such a reader should skip the dry parts he had been addressing to the more studious. It is true the descriptions are written ad captandum, as are all great works, but they succeed in captivating, having been composed with all the pains a man of genius and of great perseverance could bestow upon them. If I am not mistaken, he looked to these parts of his work to keep the whole alive till the time should come when the philosophical side of his writings should be understood and appreciated.
It’s likely for the reasons mentioned above that Buffon didn’t present a unified theory of evolution or descent with modification, but instead scattered his ideas in fragments throughout his work, particularly in the introductory remarks he uses for the more notable animals or groups of animals. He never discusses evolutionary concepts in the preface of an uninteresting animal; the more intriguing the animal, the more discussion of evolution you’ll typically find. When he describes the animal in more detail—and he usually[Pg 85] starts a new chapter or half chapter at this point—he doesn’t talk about evolution anymore but provides an excellent description that everyone can appreciate, and I believe it’s far more accurate than is often thought. These descriptions were meant for the general reader, and he likely expected that such readers would skip over the drier parts aimed at the more serious audience. Admittedly, the descriptions are written ad captandum, like all great works, but they succeed in engaging readers, having been crafted with all the effort a talented and determined person could put into them. If I’m not mistaken, he intended these sections of his work to keep the whole alive until the philosophical aspects of his writings could be understood and appreciated.
Thus the goat breeds with the sheep, and may therefore serve as the text for a dissertation on hybridism, which is accordingly given in the preface to this animal. The presence of rudimentary organs under a pig's hoof suggests an attack upon the doctrine of final causes in so far as it is pretended that every part of every animal or plant was specially designed with a view to the wants of the animal or plant itself once and for ever throughout all time. The dog with his great variety of breeds gives an opportunity for an article on the formation of breeds and sub-breeds by man's artificial selection. The cat is not honoured with any philosophical reflections, and comes in for nothing but abuse. The hare suggests the rabbit, and the rabbit is a rapid breeder, although the hare is an unusually slow one; but this is near[Pg 86] enough, so the hare shall serve us for the theme of a discourse on the geometrical ratio of increase and the balance of power which may be observed in nature. When we come to the carnivora, additional reflections follow upon the necessity for death, and even for violent death; this leads to the question whether the creatures that are killed suffer pain; here, then, will be the proper place for considering the sensations of animals generally.
So, the goat breeds with the sheep, and this can serve as the basis for a discussion on hybridism, which is explained in the preface to this animal. The existence of rudimentary organs under a pig's hoof challenges the idea of final causes, which suggests that every part of every animal or plant was specifically designed for the needs of that animal or plant once and for all. The dog, with its wide variety of breeds, provides an opportunity for an article on how breeds and sub-breeds are formed through artificial selection by humans. The cat doesn’t receive any philosophical insights and is only met with criticism. The hare leads us to the rabbit, which breeds quickly, even though the hare itself breeds much more slowly; but this is close enough, so we will use the hare as the topic for a discussion on the geometric ratio of increase and the balance of power seen in nature. When we look at carnivores, we also need to reflect on the necessity of death, including violent death; this brings up whether the animals that are killed experience pain, so this is where we should consider the sensations of animals in general.
Perhaps the most pregnant passage concerning evolution is to be found in the preface to the ass, which is so near the beginning of the work as to be only the second animal of which Buffon treats after having described man himself. It points strongly in the direction of his having believed all animal forms to have been descended from one single common ancestral type. Buffon did not probably choose to take his very first opportunity in order to insist upon matter that should point in this direction; but the considerations were too important to be deferred long, and are accordingly put forward under cover of the ass, his second animal.
Perhaps the most significant passage about evolution can be found in the preface to the donkey, which is so close to the beginning of the work that it's only the second animal Buffon discusses after describing humans. It strongly suggests he believed all animal forms descended from a single common ancestor. Buffon likely didn’t mean to use his first chance to emphasize this idea, but the points were too important to delay, so they are presented in the context of the donkey, his second animal.
When we consider the force with which Buffon's conclusion is led up to; the obviousness of the conclusion itself when the premises are once admitted; the impossibility that such a conclusion should be again lost sight of if the reasonableness of its being drawn had been once admitted; the position in his scheme which is assigned to it by its propounder; the persistency with which he demonstrates during forty years thereafter that the premises, which he has declared should establish the conclusion in question, are indisputable;—when we consider, too, that we are dealing with a[Pg 87] man of unquestionable genius, and that the times and circumstances of his life were such as would go far to explain reserve and irony—is it, I would ask, reasonable to suppose that Buffon did not, in his own mind, and from the first, draw the inference to which he leads his reader, merely because from time to time he tells the reader, with a shrug of the shoulders, that he draws no inferences opposed to the Book of Genesis? Is it not more likely that Buffon intended his reader to draw his inferences for himself, and perhaps to value them all the more highly on that account?
When we think about how strongly Buffon's conclusion is argued; how obvious the conclusion itself is once we accept the premises; and how unlikely it is that such a conclusion would be overlooked again if its logical basis was acknowledged from the start; also considering where in his framework this conclusion is placed by its author; and the way he tirelessly supports the premises he claims should justify the conclusion for the next forty years as indisputable— when we also take into account that we are talking about a[Pg 87] man of undeniable brilliance, and that the circumstances of his life could easily explain his restraint and irony—can we really believe that Buffon didn't, in his own mind, draw the inference he guides his reader towards simply because he occasionally mentions, with a shrug, that he doesn’t argue against the Book of Genesis? Isn’t it more probable that Buffon wanted his readers to make their own inferences and perhaps to appreciate them even more for that reason?
The passage to which I am alluding is as follows:—
The passage I'm referring to is as follows:—
"If from the boundless variety which animated nature presents to us, we choose the body of some animal or even that of man himself to serve as a model with which to compare the bodies of other organized beings, we shall find that though all these beings have an individuality of their own, and are distinguished from one another by differences of which the gradations are infinitely subtle, there exists at the same time a primitive and general design which we can follow for a long way, and the departures from which (dégénérations) are far more gentle than those from mere outward resemblance. For not to mention organs of digestion, circulation, and generation, which are common to all animals, and without which the animal would cease to be an animal, and could neither continue to exist nor reproduce itself—there is none the less even in those very parts which constitute the main difference in outward appearance, a striking resemblance which carries with it irresistibly the idea of a single pattern[Pg 88] after which all would appear to have been conceived. The horse, for example—what can at first sight seem more unlike mankind? Yet when we compare man and horse point by point and detail by detail, is not our wonder excited rather by the points of resemblance than of difference that are to be found between them? Take the skeleton of a man; bend forward the bones in the region of the pelvis, shorten the thigh bones, and those of the leg and arm, lengthen those of the feet and hands, run the joints together, lengthen the jaws, and shorten the frontal bone, finally, lengthen the spine, and the skeleton will now be that of a man no longer, but will have become that of a horse—for it is easy to imagine that in lengthening the spine and the jaws we shall at the same time have increased the number of the vertebræ, ribs, and teeth. It is but in the number of these bones, which may be considered accessory, and by the lengthening, shortening, or mode of attachment of others, that the skeleton of the horse differs from that of the human body.... We find ribs in man, in all the quadrupeds, in birds, in fishes, and we may find traces of them as far down as the turtle, in which they seem still to be sketched out by means of furrows that are to be found beneath the shell. Let it be remembered that the foot of the horse, which seems so different from a man's hand, is, nevertheless, as M. Daubenton has pointed out, composed of the same bones, and that we have at the end of each of our fingers a nail corresponding to the hoof of a horse's foot. Judge, then, whether this hidden resemblance is not more marvellous than any outward differences[Pg 89]—whether this constancy to a single plan of structure which we may follow from man to the quadrupeds, from the quadrupeds to the cetacea, from the cetacea to birds, from birds to reptiles, from reptiles to fishes—in which all such essential parts as heart, intestines, spine, are invariably found—whether, I say, this does not seem to indicate that the Creator when He made them would use but a single main idea, though at the same time varying it in every conceivable way, so that man might admire equally the magnificence of the execution and the simplicity of the design.[46]
"If we look at the vast variety that nature shows us and choose the body of some animal or even that of a human as a model to compare with other living beings, we'll see that while each has its own individuality and is distinguished by differences that are incredibly subtle, there is also a fundamental and general design we can follow for a long way. The variations from this design (dégénérations) are much more gradual than those from mere outward similarities. Besides the common organs of digestion, circulation, and reproduction that all animals share, which are essential for them to exist and reproduce—there is still a strong resemblance even in those parts that primarily set them apart in appearance, suggesting a single blueprint from which all are derived. Take the horse, for example—at first glance, it seems completely different from humans. Yet when we compare humans and horses in detail, isn't our amazement stirred more by their similarities than their differences? If we take a human skeleton, bend the pelvis bones forward, shorten the thigh and leg bones, lengthen the bones of the feet and hands, merge the joints, lengthen the jaw, shorten the frontal bone, and finally, lengthen the spine, the skeleton will no longer belong to a human but will transform into that of a horse. It's easy to imagine that lengthening the spine and jaw would also increase the number of vertebrae, ribs, and teeth. The only differences between a horse's skeleton and a human's are in the number of these accessory bones and in the length, shortening, or attachment of others. Ribs are found in humans, in all quadrupeds, in birds, in fish, and even traces of them can be seen in turtles, where they seem to be outlined by furrows beneath the shell. It's worth noting that the horse's foot, which appears so different from a human hand, is actually made up of the same bones. As M. Daubenton pointed out, the tip of each of our fingers has a nail that corresponds to the hoof of a horse's foot. So, consider whether this hidden resemblance is even more remarkable than any outward differences—whether this consistency in a single structural plan, which connects humans to quadrupeds, cetaceans, birds, reptiles, and fish—all of which have essential parts like the heart, intestines, and spine—does not suggest that the Creator, when making them, used only one main idea while varying it in every possible way so that humans could appreciate both the magnificence of the execution and the simplicity of the design."
"If we regard the matter thus, not only the ass and the horse, but even man himself, the apes, the quadrupeds, and all animals might be regarded but as forming members of one and the same family. But are we to conclude that within this vast family which the Creator has called into existence out of nothing, there are other and smaller families, projected as it were by Nature, and brought forth by her in the natural course of events and after a long time, of which some contain but two members, as the ass and the horse, others many members, as the weasel, martin, stoat, ferret, &c., and that on the same principle there are families of vegetables, containing ten, twenty, or thirty plants, as the case may be? If such families had any real existence they could have been formed only by crossing, by the accumulation of successive variations (variation successive), and by degeneration from an original type; but if we once admit that there are families of plants and animals, so that the ass may be of the family of the[Pg 90] horse, and that the one may only differ from the other through degeneration from a common ancestor, we might be driven to admit that the ape is of the family of man, that he is but a degenerate man, and that he and man have had a common ancestor, even as the ass and horse have had. It would follow then that every family, whether animal or vegetable, had sprung from a single stock, which after a succession of generations, had become higher in the case of some of its descendants and lower in that of others."
"If we look at it this way, not only the donkey and the horse, but even humans, apes, four-legged animals, and all creatures could be seen as members of the same family. But should we conclude that within this vast family created by the Creator from nothing, there are smaller families, formed as it were by Nature, and developed over time, some containing just two members like the donkey and the horse, while others consist of many members, like the weasel, marten, stoat, ferret, etc.? And on the same principle, might there be families of plants, containing ten, twenty, or thirty species, depending on the situation? If such families actually existed, they could only have been created through crossbreeding, by accumulating successive variations (variation successive), and by degeneration from an original type; but if we accept that there are families of plants and animals, meaning the donkey could belong to the family of the[Pg 90] horse, and that they may only differ through degeneration from a common ancestor, we might have to accept that the ape is part of the family of humans, that it is just a degenerate version of a human, and that both humans and apes share a common ancestor, just as the donkey and the horse do. It would then follow that every family, whether animal or plant, originated from a single stock, which after many generations has become more advanced in some descendants and more primitive in others."
What inference could be more aptly drawn? But it was not one which Buffon was going to put before the general public. He had said enough for the discerning, and continues with what is intended to make the conclusions they should draw even plainer to them, while it conceals them still more carefully from the general reader.
What conclusion could be more fitting? But it wasn’t something Buffon was going to share with the general public. He had said enough for those who can think critically and continues with what’s meant to make the conclusions they should reach even clearer, while keeping them even more hidden from the average reader.
"The naturalists who are so ready to establish families among animals and vegetables, do not seem to have sufficiently considered the consequences which should follow from their premises, for these would limit direct creation to as small a number of forms as anyone might think fit (reduisoient le produit immédiat de la création, à un nombre d'individus aussi petit que l'on voudroit). For if it were once shown that we had right grounds for establishing these families; if the point were once gained that among animals and vegetables there had been, I do not say several species, but even a single one, which had been produced in the course of direct descent from another species; if for example it could be once shown that the ass was but a degeneration from the horse—then[Pg 91] there is no further limit to be set to the power of nature, and we should not be wrong in supposing that with sufficient time she could have evolved all other organized forms from one primordial type (et l'on n'auroit pas tort de supposer, que d'un seul être elle a su tirer avec le temps tous les autres êtres organisés)."
"The naturalists who are eager to create categories for animals and plants don’t seem to have fully considered the implications of their ideas, as these would restrict direct creation to a very limited number of forms, based on anyone's preference. If it were once demonstrated that we had valid reasons for categorizing these families; if it were established that among animals and plants there was, I’m not saying several species, but even just one, that came about through direct descent from another species; for instance, if it could be shown that the donkey is just a variation of the horse—then[Pg 91] there would be no further limit to nature's power, and we wouldn’t be wrong in believing that given enough time, she could have evolved all other organized forms from a single original type."
Buffon now felt that he had sailed as near the wind as was desirable. His next sentence is as follows:—
Buffon now felt that he had sailed as close to the wind as was necessary. His next sentence is as follows:—
"But no! It is certain from revelation that all animals have alike been favoured with the grace of an act of direct creation, and that the first pair of every species issued full formed from the hands of the Creator."[47]
"But no! It is clear from revelation that all animals have been equally blessed with the grace of direct creation, and that the first pair of every species came fully formed from the hands of the Creator."[47]
This might be taken as bonâ fide, if it had been written by Bonnet, but it is impossible to accept it from Buffon. It is only those who judge him at second hand, or by isolated passages, who can hold that he failed to see the consequences of his own premises. No one could have seen more clearly, nor have said more lucidly, what should suffice to show a sympathetic reader the conclusion he ought to come to. Even when ironical, his irony is not the ill-natured irony of one who is merely amusing himself at other people's expense, but the serious and legitimate irony of one who must either limit the circle of those to whom he appeals, or must know how to make the same language appeal differently to the different capacities of his readers, and who trusts to the good sense of the discerning to understand the difficulty of his position, and make due allowance for it.[Pg 92]
This could be considered bonâ fide if it were written by Bonnet, but it’s hard to accept it from Buffon. Only those who judge him from a distance or by cherry-picked excerpts can believe he didn’t recognize the implications of his own ideas. No one understood more clearly, or expressed more clearly, what should be obvious to a thoughtful reader about the conclusion they should reach. Even when he’s being ironic, it isn’t the malicious irony of someone just getting a kick out of others’ misfortunes, but the genuine and valid irony of someone who has to either narrow his audience or find a way to make his message resonate differently with various readers. He relies on the good judgment of the perceptive to grasp the complexity of his situation and to account for it.[Pg 92]
The compromise which he thought fit to put before the public was that "Each species has a type of which the principal features are engraved in indelible and eternally permanent characters, while all accessory touches vary."[48] It would be satisfactory to know where an accessory touch is supposed to begin and end.
The compromise he decided to present to the public was that "Each species has a type with main features that are marked in lasting and permanent traits, while all additional details differ."[48] It would be helpful to know where an additional detail is supposed to begin and end.
And again:—
And again:—
"The essential characteristics of every animal have been conserved without alteration in their most important parts.... The individuals of each genus still represent the same forms as they did in the earliest ages, especially in the case of the larger animals" (so that the generic forms even of the larger animals prove not to be the same, but only 'especially' the same as in the earliest ages).[49]
"The key features of every animal have remained unchanged in their most significant parts... The members of each genus still look like they did in the earliest times, particularly with the larger animals" (meaning that the generic forms, especially of the larger animals, are not completely the same, but only 'especially' similar to those from the earliest ages).[49]
This transparently illogical position is maintained ostensibly from first to last, much in the same spirit as in the two foregoing passages, written at intervals of thirteen years. But they are to be read by the light of the earlier one—placed as a lantern to the wary upon the threshold of his work in 1753—to the effect that a single, well substantiated case of degeneration would make it conceivable that all living beings were descended from a single common ancestor. If after having led up to this by a remorseless logic, a man is found five-and-twenty years later still substantiating cases of degeneration, as he has been substantiating them unceasingly in thirty quartos during the whole interval, there should be little[Pg 93] question how seriously we are to take him when he wishes us to stop short of the conclusions he has told us we ought to draw from the premises that he has made it the business of his life to establish—especially when we know that he has a Sorbonne to keep a sharp eye upon him.
This obviously illogical stance is maintained from start to finish, similar to the two previous passages written over a span of thirteen years. But they should be interpreted in light of the earlier one—serving as a guiding light for those cautious about approaching his work in 1753—suggesting that a single, well-documented case of degeneration could make it plausible that all living beings descended from a single common ancestor. If, after laying this out with relentless logic, a man is found twenty-five years later still presenting cases of degeneration, as he has been doing continuously in thirty volumes throughout that time, there should be little[Pg 93] doubt about how seriously we should take him when he wants us to refrain from the conclusions he has indicated we should draw from the premises he has dedicated his life to establishing—especially knowing he has a Sorbonne watching closely over him.
I believe that if the reader will bear in mind the twofold, serious and ironical, character of Buffon's work he will understand it, and feel an admiration for it which will grow continually greater and greater the more he studies it, otherwise he will miss the whole point.
I think that if the reader keeps in mind the dual nature—both serious and ironic—of Buffon's work, they will understand it and develop an admiration for it that will keep increasing the more they study it; otherwise, they will completely miss the point.
Buffon on one of the early pages of his first volume protested against the introduction of either "plaisanterie" or "équivoque" (p. 25) into a serious work. But I have observed that there is an unconscious irony in most disclaimers of this nature. When a writer begins by saying that he has "an ineradicable tendency to make things clear," we may infer that we are going to be puzzled; so when he shows that he is haunted by a sense of the impropriety of allowing humour to intrude into his work, we may hope to be amused as well as interested. As showing how far the objection to humour which he expressed upon his twenty-fifth page succeeded in carrying him safely over his twenty-sixth and twenty-seventh, I will quote the following, which begins on page twenty-six:—
Buffon, on one of the early pages of his first volume, objected to the inclusion of either "plaisanterie" or "équivoque" (p. 25) in a serious work. However, I've noticed that there's often an unintentional irony in most disclaimers like this. When a writer starts by claiming that he has "an irresistible urge to clarify things," we can assume we’re going to be confused; and when he indicates that he feels it’s inappropriate to let humor seep into his work, we can expect to be entertained as well as intrigued. To illustrate how far his objection to humor, stated on his twenty-fifth page, managed to carry him safely through his twenty-sixth and twenty-seventh, I will quote the following, which begins on page twenty-six:—
"Aldrovandus is the most learned and laborious of all naturalists; after sixty years of work he has left an immense number of volumes behind him, which have been printed at various times, the greater number of[Pg 94] them after his death. It would be possible to reduce them to a tenth part if we could rid them of all useless and foreign matter, and of a prolixity which I find almost overwhelming; were this only done, his books should be regarded as among the best we have on the subject of natural history in its entirety. The plan of his work is good, his classification distinguished for its good sense, his dividing lines well marked, his descriptions sufficiently accurate—monotonous it is true, but painstaking; the historical part of his work is less good; it is often confused and fabulous, and the author shows too manifestly the credulous tendencies of his mind.
"Aldrovandus is the most knowledgeable and hardworking of all naturalists; after sixty years of work, he has left behind an immense number of volumes, which have been printed at various times, most of them[Pg 94] after his death. We could reduce them to a tenth of their current size if we could eliminate all the unnecessary and irrelevant content, along with the excessive detail that I find almost overwhelming; if this were done, his books should be considered among the best we have on the topic of natural history as a whole. The organization of his work is solid, his classification is marked by common sense, his categories are clearly defined, and his descriptions are fairly accurate—monotonous, it's true, but meticulously detailed; however, the historical aspect of his work is less impressive; it is often confusing and fantastical, and the author clearly displays the gullible tendencies of his mind."
"While going over his work, I have been struck with that defect, or rather excess, which we find in almost all the books of a hundred or a couple of hundred years ago, and which prevails still among the Germans—I mean with that quantity of useless erudition with which they intentionally swell out their works, and the result of which is that their subject is overlaid with a mass of extraneous matter on which they enlarge with great complacency, but with no consideration whatever for their readers. They seem, in fact, to have forgotten what they have to say in their endeavour to tell us what has been said by other people.
"While reviewing his work, I noticed that flaw, or rather excess, that's common in almost all the books from a hundred or even two hundred years ago, and it's still present among the Germans. I’m referring to the amount of unnecessary scholarship they deliberately add to their works, resulting in their subject being buried under a pile of irrelevant information that they discuss with great satisfaction, but with no regard for their readers. They seem to have forgotten what they need to say while trying to share what others have already said."
"I picture to myself a man like Aldrovandus, after he has once conceived the design of writing a complete natural history. I see him in his library reading, one after the other, ancients, moderns, philosophers, theologians, jurisconsults, historians, travellers, poets, and[Pg 95] reading with no other end than with that of catching at all words and phrases which can be forced from far or near into some kind of relation with his subject. I see him copying all these passages, or getting them copied for him, and arranging them in alphabetical order. He fills many portfolios with all manner of notes, often taken without either discrimination or research, and at last sets himself to write with a resolve that not one of all these notes shall remain unused. The result is that when he comes to his account of the cow or of the hen, he will tell us all that has ever yet been said about cows or hens; all that the ancients ever thought about them; all that has ever been imagined concerning their virtues, characters, and courage; every purpose to which they have ever yet been put; every story of every old woman that he can lay hold of; all the miracles which certain religions have ascribed to them; all the superstitions they have given rise to; all the metaphors and allegories which poets have drawn from them; the attributes that have been assigned to them; the representations that have been made of them in hieroglyphics and armorial bearings, in a word all the histories and all fables in which there was ever yet any mention either of a cow or hen. How much natural history is likely to be found in such a lumber room? and how is one to lay one's hand upon the little that there may actually be?"[50]
I imagine a man like Aldrovandus, after he decides to write a comprehensive natural history. I see him in his library, reading through a mix of ancient and modern texts, philosophers, theologians, legal experts, historians, travelers, and poets, just trying to collect every word and phrase that might relate to his topic. I see him copying these passages or having them copied and organizing them in alphabetical order. He fills multiple folders with notes, often taken without much care or thoroughness, and eventually commits to writing with the goal that not a single note will go unused. As a result, when he writes about cows or hens, he ends up including everything that has ever been said about them—every idea the ancients had, every imagined virtue, character, and bravery, every use they’ve been put to, every story from old tales he can find, all the miracles assigned to them by certain religions, all the superstitions surrounding them, the metaphors and allegories poets have drawn, the attributes ascribed to them, and the depictions found in hieroglyphics and coats of arms. In short, he includes every history and fable that ever mentioned a cow or hen. How much actual natural history will be in such a cluttered collection, and how can anyone find the little that might be there? [50]
It is hoped that the reader will see Buffon, much us Buffon saw the learned Aldrovandus. He should see[Pg 96] him going into his library, &c., and quietly chuckling to himself as he wrote such a passage as the one in which we lately found him saying that the larger animals had "especially" the same generic forms as they had always had. And the reader should probably see Daubenton chuckling also.
It is hoped that the reader will see Buffon just as Buffon saw the knowledgeable Aldrovandus. He should picture[Pg 96] him entering his library, etc., and quietly laughing to himself as he wrote a passage like the one where we recently found him saying that the larger animals had "especially" the same generic forms as they always had. And the reader should probably also imagine Daubenton chuckling.
FOOTNOTES:
[39] Tom. i. p. 24, 1749.
[40] Tom. i. p. 40, 1749.
[41] Vol. i. p. 34, 1749.
[42] Tom. i. p. 36.
[44] Tom. i. p. 33.
[46] Tom. iv. p. 381, 1753.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Tom. iv. p. 381, 1753.
[48] Tom. xiii. p. ix. 1765.
[50] Tom. i. p. 28, 1749.
SUPPOSED FLUCTUATIONS OF OPINION—CAUSES OR MEANS OF THE TRANSFORMATION OF SPECIES.
SUPPOSED FLUCTUATIONS OF OPINION—CAUSES OR MEANS OF THE TRANSFORMATION OF SPECIES.
Enough, perhaps, has been already said to disabuse the reader's mind of the common misconception of Buffon, namely, that he was more or less of an elegant trifler with science, who cared rather about the language in which his ideas were clothed than about the ideas themselves, and that he did not hold the same opinions for long together; but the accusation of instability has been made in such high quarters that it is necessary to refute it still more completely.
Enough has probably been said to clear up the common misunderstanding about Buffon, which portrays him as someone who was more of a stylish dabbler in science, focusing more on how he presented his ideas than on the ideas themselves, and who often changed his opinions. However, the claim of inconsistency has been made from such respected sources that it's essential to refute it even more thoroughly.
Mr. Darwin, for example, in his "Historical Sketch of the Recent Progress of Opinion on the Origin of Species" prefixed to all the later editions of his own 'Origin of Species,' says of Buffon that he "was the first author who, in modern times, has treated" the origin of species "in a scientific spirit. But," he continues, "as his opinions fluctuated greatly at different periods, and as he does not enter on the causes or means of the transformation of species, I need not here enter on details."[51]
Mr. Darwin, for instance, in his "Historical Sketch of the Recent Progress of Opinion on the Origin of Species" included in all the later editions of his own 'Origin of Species,' mentions Buffon as "the first author who, in modern times, has treated" the origin of species "in a scientific spirit. However," he adds, "since his opinions changed significantly at different times, and since he doesn't discuss the causes or means of species transformation, I won't go into details here."[51]
Mr. Darwin seems to have followed the one half of Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire's "full account of Buffon's[Pg 98] conclusions" upon the subject of descent with modification,[52] to which he refers with approval on the second page of his historical sketch.[53]
Mr. Darwin appears to have adopted part of Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire's "complete summary of Buffon's conclusions" regarding descent with modification, which he mentions favorably on the second page of his historical sketch.
Turning, then, to Isidore Geoffroy's work, I find that in like manner he too has been following the one half of what Buffon actually said. But even so, he awards Buffon very high praise.
Turning now to Isidore Geoffroy's work, I see that he, too, has been focusing on only half of what Buffon actually stated. However, he still gives Buffon a lot of credit.
"Buffon," he writes, "is to the doctrine of the mutability of species what Linnæus is to that of its fixity. It is only since the appearance of Buffon's 'Natural History,' and in consequence thereof, that the mutability of species has taken rank among scientific questions."[54]
"Buffon," he writes, "is to the idea of species changing over time what Linnæus is to the idea of species remaining the same. It’s only after Buffon’s 'Natural History' was published that the concept of species mutability became a serious scientific topic."[54]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"Buffon, who comes next in chronological order after Bacon, follows him in no other respect than that of time. He is entirely original in arriving at the doctrine of the variability of organic types, and in enouncing it after long hesitation, during which one can watch the labour of a great intelligence freeing itself little by little from the yoke of orthodoxy.
"Buffon, who comes next in chronological order after Bacon, follows him in no other respect than that of time. He is completely original in reaching the idea of the variability of organic types and in stating it after a long period of uncertainty, during which one can observe the effort of a great mind gradually breaking free from the constraints of orthodoxy."
"But from this source come difficulties in the interpretation of Buffon's work which have misled many writers. Buffon expresses absolutely different opinions in different parts of his natural history—so much so that partisans and opponents of the doctrine of the fixity of species have alike believed and still believe themselves at liberty to claim Buffon as one of the great authorities upon their side."[Pg 99]
"But from this source come difficulties in interpreting Buffon's work that have confused many writers. Buffon expresses completely different opinions in various parts of his natural history—so much so that both supporters and opponents of the idea of the fixity of species have claimed and still claim Buffon as a significant authority on their side."[Pg 99]
Then follow the quotations upon which M. Geoffroy relies—to which I will return presently—after which the conclusion runs thus:—
Then check out the quotes that M. Geoffroy depends on—I'll get back to those in a bit—after which the conclusion states:—
"The dates, however, of the several passages in question are sufficient to explain the differences in their tenor, in a manner worthy of Buffon. Where are the passages in which Buffon affirms the immutability of species? At the beginning of his work. His first volume on animals[55] is dated 1753. The two following are those in which Buffon still shares the views of Linnæus; they are dated 1755 and 1756. Of what date are those in which Buffon declares for variability? From 1761 to 1766. And those in which, after having admitted variability and declared in favour of it, he proceeds to limit it? From 1765 to 1778.
"The dates of the various sections in question are enough to explain the differences in their content, in a way that would impress Buffon. Where can we find the sections where Buffon claims that species are unchangeable? At the beginning of his work. His first volume on animals[55] is from 1753. The next two volumes reflect Buffon's alignment with Linnæus; they were published in 1755 and 1756. When does Buffon speak about variability? From 1761 to 1766. And when, after acknowledging variability and supporting it, does he start to put limits on it? From 1765 to 1778."
"The inference is sufficiently simple. Buffon does but correct himself. He does not fluctuate. He goes once for all from one opinion to the other, from what he accepted at starting on the authority of another to what he recognized as true after twenty years of research. If while trying to set himself free from the prevailing notions, he in the first instance went, like all other innovators, somewhat to the opposite extreme, he essays as soon as may be to retrace his steps in some measure, and thenceforward to remain unchanged.
"The conclusion is quite straightforward. Buffon simply adjusts his views. He doesn’t waver. He makes a definitive switch from one belief to another, moving from what he initially accepted based on someone else's authority to what he identified as true after two decades of research. If, in his effort to break away from common ideas, he initially leaned a bit too far in the opposite direction like many other innovators, he quickly attempts to find his way back and then maintains his position moving forward."
"Let the reader cast his eye over the general table of contents wherein Buffon, at the end of his 'Natural History,' gives a résumé of all of it that he is anxious to preserve. He passes over alike the passages in which he affirms and those in which he unreservedly denies[Pg 100] the immutability of species, and indicates only the doctrine of the permanence of essential features and the variability of details (toutes les touches accessoires); he repeats this eleven years later in his 'Époques de la Nature'" (published 1778).[56]
"Let the reader take a look at the general table of contents where Buffon, at the end of his 'Natural History,' provides a summary of everything he wants to keep. He skips over both the sections where he affirms and those where he outright denies the immutability of species, and only highlights the idea of the permanence of essential features and the variability of details (toutes les touches accessoires); he repeats this eleven years later in his 'Époques de la Nature' (published 1778).[56]"
But I think I can show that the passages which M. Geoffroy brings forward, to prove that Buffon was in the first instance a supporter of invariability, do not bear him out in the deduction he has endeavoured to draw from them.
But I believe I can demonstrate that the passages M. Geoffroy presents to argue that Buffon was initially a supporter of invariability do not support the conclusion he is trying to draw from them.
"What author," he asks, "has ever pronounced more decidedly than Buffon in favour of the invariability of species? Where can we find a more decided expression of opinion than the following?
"What author," he asks, "has ever spoken more definitively than Buffon in favor of the invariability of species? Where can we find a stronger expression of opinion than the following?
"'The different species of animals are separated from one another by a space which Nature cannot overstep.'"
"'Different species of animals are separated from each other by a boundary that Nature cannot cross.'"
On turning, however, to Buffon himself, I find the passage to stand as follows:—
On turning, however, to Buffon himself, I find the passage reads as follows:—
"Although the different species of animals are separated from one another by a space which Nature cannot overstep—yet some of them approach so nearly to one another in so many respects that there is only room enough left for the getting in of a line of separation between them,"[57] and on the following page he distinctly encourages the idea of the mutability of species in the following passage:—
"Even though different species of animals are kept apart by a distance that Nature can't bridge—some of them are so similar in many ways that there's barely enough space to draw a line separating them,"[57] and on the next page he clearly supports the concept of species changing over time in the following passage:—
"In place of regarding the ass as a degenerate horse, there would be more reason in calling the horse a more perfect kind of ass (un âne perfectionné), and the[Pg 101] sheep a more delicate kind of goat, that we have tended, perfected, and propagated for our use, and that the more perfect animals in general—especially the domestic animals—draw their origin from some less perfect species of that kind of wild animal which they most resemble. Nature alone not being able to do as much as Nature and man can do in concert with one another."[58]
"Instead of seeing the donkey as a lesser version of a horse, it makes more sense to view the horse as a more refined type of donkey, and the sheep as a more delicate kind of goat, which we have raised, refined, and bred for our needs. The more refined animals, especially domestic ones, generally come from some less perfect species of the wild animals they most resemble. Nature alone cannot achieve as much as nature and humans can accomplish together." [58]
But Buffon had long ago declared that if the horse and the ass could be considered as being blood relations there was no stopping short of the admission that all animals might also be blood relations—that is to say, descended from common ancestors—and now he tells us that the ass and horse are in all probability descended from common ancestors. Will a reader of any literary experience hold that so laborious, and yet so witty a writer, and one so studious of artistic effect, could ignore the broad lines he had laid down for himself, or forget how what he had said would bear on subsequent passages, and subsequent passages on it? A less painstaking author than Buffon may yet be trusted to remember his own work well enough to avoid such literary bad workmanship as this. If Buffon had seen reason to change his mind he would have said so, and would have contradicted the inference he had originally pronounced to be deducible from an admission of kinship between the ass and the horse. This, it is hardly necessary to say, he never does, though he frequently thinks it well to remind his reader of the fact that the ass and the horse are in all probability[Pg 102] closely related. This is bringing two and two together with sufficient closeness for all practical purposes.
But Buffon once stated that if the horse and the donkey could be seen as relatives, then it wouldn't be far off to say that all animals might also be related—meaning, descended from common ancestors. Now he tells us that the donkey and horse probably do share common ancestors. Can any well-read reader believe that such a diligent and clever writer, who pays attention to artistic effects, would overlook the broad principles he established for himself or forget how what he wrote would relate to later sections, and how those later sections would connect back to it? A less meticulous author than Buffon might still be expected to remember their work well enough to avoid such poor literary craftsmanship. If Buffon had found reason to change his mind, he would have stated it and contradicted the conclusion he originally said could be deduced from claiming kinship between the donkey and the horse. This, it hardly needs to be said, he never does, even though he often thinks it important to remind his readers that the donkey and horse are probably closely related. This is combining two and two closely enough for all practical purposes.
Should not M. Geoffroy's question, then, have rather been "Who has ever pronounced more grudgingly, even in an early volume, &c., &c., and who has more completely neutralized whatever concession he might appear to have been making?"
Shouldn't M. Geoffroy's question have been, "Who has ever spoken more reluctantly, even in an early volume, etc., etc., and who has completely undermined any concession they might seem to have made?"
Nor does the only other passage which M. Geoffroy brings forward to prove that Buffon was originally a believer in the fixity of species bear him out much better. It is to be found on the opening page of a brief introduction to the wild animals. M. Geoffroy quotes it thus: "We shall see Nature dictating her laws, so simple yet so unchangeable, and imprinting her own immutable characters upon every species." But M. Geoffroy does not give the passage which, on the same page, admits mutability among domesticated animals, in the case of which he declares we find Nature "rarement perfectionnée, souvent alterée, défigurée;" nor yet does he deem it necessary to show that the context proves that this unchangeableness of wild animals is only relative; and this he should certainly have done, for two pages later on Buffon speaks of the American tigers, lions, and panthers as being "degenerated, if their original nature was cruel and ferocious; or, rather, they have experienced the effect of climate, and under a milder sky have assumed a milder nature, their excesses have become moderated, and by the changes which they have undergone they have become more in conformity with the country they inhabit."[59]
Nor does the other passage that M. Geoffroy presents to show that Buffon initially believed in the fixity of species support him any better. It's found on the opening page of a short introduction to wild animals. M. Geoffroy quotes it like this: "We shall see Nature dictating her laws, so simple yet so unchangeable, and imprinting her own immutable characters upon every species." However, M. Geoffroy does not mention the passage on the same page that acknowledges mutability among domesticated animals, where he states we find Nature "rarement perfectionnée, souvent altérée, défigurée;" nor does he think it's necessary to show that the context indicates this unchangeableness of wild animals is only relative; and he definitely should have done so, because two pages later Buffon talks about American tigers, lions, and panthers as being "degenerated, if their original nature was cruel and ferocious; or rather, they have experienced the effect of climate, and under a milder sky have assumed a milder nature, their excesses have become moderated, and by the changes they have undergone they have become more in conformity with the country they inhabit."[59]
[Pg 103]And again:—
And again:—
"If we consider each species in the different climates which it inhabits, we shall find perceptible varieties as regards size and form: they all derive an impress to a greater or less extent from the climate in which they live. These changes are only made slowly and imperceptibly. Nature's great workman is Time. He marches ever with an even pace, and does nothing by leaps and bounds, but by degrees, gradations, and succession he does all things; and the changes which he works—at first imperceptible—become little by little perceptible, and show themselves eventually in results about which there can be no mistake.
"If we look at each species in the different climates they live in, we’ll notice clear variations in size and shape: they all show some influence from the climate where they exist. These changes happen slowly and subtly. Nature’s greatest craftsman is Time. He moves steadily and doesn’t make changes suddenly; instead, he progresses through gradual steps and sequences. The changes he brings about—initially unnoticed—become gradually noticeable and ultimately result in obvious outcomes."
"Nevertheless animals in a free, wild state are perhaps less subject than any other living beings, man not excepted, to alterations, changes, and variations of all kinds. Being free to choose their own food and climate, they vary less than domestic animals vary."[60] The conditions of their existence, in fact, remaining practically constant, the animals are no less constant themselves.
"Still, animals in their natural, wild state are probably less affected than any other living beings, including humans, by changes and variations of all kinds. Free to choose their own food and environment, they change less than domestic animals do.[60] Since the conditions of their existence remain almost constant, these animals themselves are also quite stable."
The writer of the above could hardly be claimed as a very thick and thin partisan of immutability, even though he had not shown from the first how clearly he saw that there was no middle position between the denial of all mutability, and the admission that in the course of sufficient time any conceivable amount of mutability is possible. I will give a considerable part of what I have found in the first six volumes of Buffon to bear one way or the other on his views concerning the mutability of species; and I think the reader, so far from agreeing with M. Isidore Geoffroy that Buffon[Pg 104] began his work with a belief in the fixity of species, will find, that from the very first chapter onward, he leant strongly to mutability, even if he did not openly avow his belief in it.
The writer above cannot really be seen as a staunch supporter of immutability, even though he didn't initially show how clearly he understood that there was no middle ground between rejecting all mutability and accepting that, given enough time, any amount of mutability is possible. I will present a significant portion of what I've found in the first six volumes of Buffon to support his views on the mutability of species. I believe the reader, contrary to M. Isidore Geoffroy's claim that Buffon[Pg 104] started his work believing in the fixity of species, will see that right from the very first chapter, he leaned heavily toward mutability, even if he didn't explicitly express his belief in it.
In support of this assertion, one quotation must suffice:—
In support of this statement, one quote will be enough:—
"Nature advances by gradations which pass unnoticed. She passes from one species, and often from one genus to another by imperceptible degrees, so that we meet with a great number of mean species and objects of such doubtful characters that we know not where to place them."[61]
"Nature progresses through subtle changes that often go unnoticed. She transitions from one species, and frequently from one genus to another, through barely perceptible steps, resulting in a large number of intermediate species and items with such uncertain classifications that we can't determine where to categorize them."[61]
The reader who turns to Buffon himself will find the idea that Buffon took a less advanced position in his old age than he had taken in middle life is also without foundation.
The reader who looks at Buffon himself will find that the idea that he held a less advanced position in his old age than he did in middle age is also unfounded.
Mr. Darwin has said that Buffon "does not enter into the causes or means of the transformation of species." It is not easy to admit the justice of this. Independently of his frequently insisting on the effect of all kinds of changed surroundings, he has devoted a long chapter of over sixty quarto pages to this very subject; it is to be found in his fourteenth volume, and is headed "De la Dégénération des Animaux," of which words "On descent with modification" will be hardly more than a literal translation. I shall give a fuller but still too brief outline of the chapter later on, and will confine myself here to saying that the three principal causes of modification which Buffon brings forward are changes of climate, of food, and the effects of domestication.[Pg 105] He may be said to have attributed variation to the direct and specific action of changed conditions of life, and to have had but little conception of the view which he was himself to suggest to Dr. Erasmus Darwin, and through him to Lamarck.
Mr. Darwin mentioned that Buffon "does not delve into the causes or means of species transformation." It's hard to accept this point as completely accurate. Besides frequently emphasizing the impact of various altered environments, he dedicated a lengthy chapter of over sixty quarto pages to this very topic; you can find it in his fourteenth volume, titled "De la Dégénération des Animaux," which could be translated literally as "On descent with modification." I’ll provide a more detailed but still brief summary of the chapter later, but for now, I’ll just mention that Buffon identifies three main causes of modification: changes in climate, food, and the effects of domestication.[Pg 105] He can be seen as having linked variation to the direct and specific influence of changed living conditions, while having a limited understanding of the perspective he would later inspire in Dr. Erasmus Darwin, and subsequently in Lamarck.
Isidore Geoffroy, writing of Lamarck, and comparing his position with that taken by Buffon, says, on the whole truly, that "what Buffon ascribes to the general effects of climate, Lamarck maintains to be caused, especially in the case of animals, by the force of habits; so that, according to him, they are not, properly speaking, modified by the conditions of their existence, but are only induced by these conditions to set about modifying themselves."[62] But it is very hard to say how much Buffon saw and how much he did not see. He may be trusted to have seen that if he once allowed the thin end of this wedge into his system, he could no more assign limits to the effect which living forms might produce upon their own organisms by effort and ingenuity in the course of long time, than he could set limits to what he had called the power of Nature if he was once to admit that an ass and a horse might, through that power, have been descended from a common ancestor. Nevertheless, he shows no unwillingness or recalcitrancy about letting the wedge enter, for he speaks of domestication as inducing modifications "sufficiently profound to become constant and hereditary in successive generations ... by its action on bodily habits it influences also their natures, instincts, and most inward qualities."[63]
Isidore Geoffroy, writing about Lamarck and comparing his views with those of Buffon, notes, generally accurately, that "what Buffon attributes to the overall effects of climate, Lamarck believes is caused, particularly in animals, by the power of habits; which means that, according to him, they are not, strictly speaking, changed by their living conditions, but are simply prompted by these conditions to begin changing themselves."[62] However, it's really difficult to say how much Buffon understood and how much he missed. We can trust that he realized that if he once allowed even a small part of this idea into his system, he couldn't possibly limit the extent to which living beings might influence their own bodies through effort and creativity over long periods, any more than he could set boundaries on what he called the power of Nature if he accepted that a donkey and a horse could, because of that power, have evolved from a common ancestor. Still, he doesn’t seem resistant or hesitant about letting this idea in, as he refers to domestication as causing modifications "sufficiently profound to become constant and hereditary in successive generations ... through its influence on bodily habits, it also affects their natures, instincts, and deepest qualities."[63]
[Pg 106] This is a very thick thin end to have been allowed to slip in unawares; but it is astonishing how little Buffon can see when he likes. I hardly doubt but he would have been well enough pleased to have let the wedge enter still farther, but this fluctuating writer had assigned himself his limits some years before, and meant adhering to them. Again, in this very chapter on Degeneration, to which M. Geoffroy has referred, there are passages on the callosities on a camel's knees, on the llama, and on the haunches of pouched monkeys which might have been written by Dr. Darwin himself.[64] They will appear more fully presently. Buffon now probably felt that he had said enough, and that others might be trusted to carry the principle farther when the time was riper for its enforcement.
[Pg 106] This is a stark contradiction to have gone unnoticed; yet it's surprising how little Buffon chooses to see when it suits him. I have no doubt he would have been happy to let the wedge go in deeper, but this inconsistent writer had set his own boundaries years earlier and intended to stick to them. Again, in this very chapter on Degeneration, which M. Geoffroy mentioned, there are sections about the calluses on a camel's knees, the llama, and the thighs of pouched monkeys that could have been written by Dr. Darwin himself.[64] They will be discussed in more detail shortly. Buffon probably now felt he had said enough, trusting that others would take the principle further when the time was right for its application.
FOOTNOTES:
[55] Tom. iv.
[57] Tom. v. p. 59, 1755.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Tom. p. 59, 1755.
[58] Tom. v. p. 60.
[59] Tom. vi. p. 58, 1756.
[60] Tom. vi. pp. 59-60, 1756.
[61] Tom. i. p. 13, 1749.
BUFFON—FULLER QUOTATIONS.
BUFFON—FULLER QUOTES.
Let us now proceed to those fuller quotations which may answer the double purpose of bearing me out in the view of Buffon's work which I have taken in the foregoing pages, and of inducing the reader to turn to Buffon himself.
Let’s now move on to those longer quotes that can both support my perspective on Buffon's work that I’ve discussed in the previous pages and encourage the reader to check out Buffon himself.
I have already said that from the very commencement of his work Buffon showed a proclivity towards considerations which were certain to lead him to a theory of evolution, even though he had not, as I believe he had, already taken a more comprehensive view of the subject than he thought fit to proclaim unreservedly.
I’ve already mentioned that from the very start of his work, Buffon showed a tendency toward ideas that were bound to lead him to a theory of evolution, even if he hadn't, as I believe he had, taken a broader perspective on the topic than he felt comfortable sharing openly.
In 1749, at the beginning of his first volume he writes:—
In 1749, at the start of his first volume, he writes:—
"The first truth that makes itself apparent on serious study of Nature, is one that man may perhaps find humiliating; it is this—that he, too, must take his place in the ranks of animals, being, as he is, an animal in every material point. It is possible also that the instinct of the lower animals will strike him as more unerring, and their industry more marvellous than his own. Then, running his eye over the different objects of which the universe is composed, he will observe with astonishment[Pg 108] that we can descend by almost imperceptible degrees from the most perfect creature to the most formless matter—from the most highly organized animal to the most entirely inorganic substance. He will recognize this gradation as the great work of Nature; and he will observe it not only as regards size and form, but also in respect of movements, and in the successive generations of every species.[65]
"The first truth that becomes clear when you seriously study nature is one that might seem humbling: that humans must also accept their place among animals, as they are, in every physical way, animals themselves. It might also occur to him that the instincts of lower animals appear to be more reliable, and their diligence more impressive than our own. As he examines the various elements that make up the universe, he will be amazed[Pg 108] to see how we can gradually descend from the most perfect beings to the most formless matter—from the most highly organized animal to entirely inorganic substances. He will acknowledge this progression as a significant aspect of nature; he will observe it not only in terms of size and shape but also regarding movement and the successive generations of every species.[65]
"Hence," he continues, "arises the difficulty of arriving at any perfect system or method in dealing either with Nature as a whole or even with any single one of her subdivisions. The gradations are so subtle that we are often obliged to make arbitrary divisions. Nature knows nothing about our classifications, and does not choose to lend herself to them without reserve. We therefore see a number of intermediate species and objects which it is very hard to classify, and which of necessity derange our system whatever it may be."[66]
"Thus," he goes on, "the challenge of creating any perfect system or method for understanding Nature as a whole or even any specific part of it arises. The differences are so subtle that we often have to make arbitrary divisions. Nature doesn’t recognize our classifications and doesn’t easily conform to them. As a result, we encounter a number of intermediate species and objects that are difficult to categorize, which inevitably disrupts whatever system we try to establish."[66]
"The attempt to form perfect systems has led to such disastrous results that it is now more easy to learn botany than the terminology which has been adopted as its language."[67]
"The effort to create perfect systems has resulted in such disastrous outcomes that it's now easier to study botany than to understand the terminology that has been adopted as its language."[67]
After saying that "la marche de la Nature" has been misunderstood, and that her progress has ever been by a succession of slow steps, he maintains that the only proper course is to class together whatever objects resemble one another, and to separate those which are unlike. If individual specimens are absolutely alike, or differ so little that the differences can hardly be perceived, they must be classed as of the same species;[Pg 109] if the differences begin to be perceptible, but if at the same time there is more resemblance than difference, the individuals presenting these features should be classed as of a different species, but as of the same genus; if the differences are still more marked, but nevertheless do not exceed the resemblances, then they must be taken as not only specific but generic, though as not sufficient to warrant the individuals in which they appear, being placed in different classes. If they are still greater, then the individuals are not even of the same class; but it should be always understood that the resemblances and differences are to be considered in reference to the entirety of the plant or animal, and not in reference to any particular part only.[68] The two rocks which are equally to be avoided are, on the one hand, absence of method, and, on the other, a tendency to over-systematize.[69]
After stating that "la marche de la Nature" has been misunderstood and that her progress has always been a series of slow steps, he argues that the right approach is to group together similar objects and separate those that are different. If individual specimens are exactly the same or differ so slightly that the differences are hardly noticeable, they should be classified as the same species; [Pg 109] if the differences become noticeable but there is still more similarity than difference, the individuals showing these traits should be classified as a different species but within the same genus. If the differences are more pronounced but do not outnumber the similarities, they should be considered both specific and generic, though not enough to place the individuals in different classes. If the differences are even greater, then the individuals do not belong to the same class at all; however, it should always be understood that similarities and differences must be evaluated concerning the whole plant or animal, not just individual parts.[68] The two extremes to avoid are, on one side, a lack of method, and on the other, a tendency to impose too rigid a system.[69]
Like Dr. Erasmus Darwin, and more recently Mr. Francis Darwin, Buffon is more struck with the resemblances than with the differences between animals and plants, but he supposes the vegetable kingdom to be a continuation of the animal, extending lower down the scale, instead of holding as Dr. Darwin did, that animals and vegetables have been contemporaneous in their degeneration from a common stock.
Like Dr. Erasmus Darwin and, more recently, Mr. Francis Darwin, Buffon is more focused on the similarities than the differences between animals and plants. However, he believes that the plant kingdom is a continuation of the animal kingdom, extending lower down the scale, rather than agreeing with Dr. Darwin's view that animals and plants have descended simultaneously from a common ancestor.
"We see," he writes, "that there is no absolute and essential difference between animals and vegetables, but that Nature descends by subtle gradations from what we deem the most perfect animal to one which is less so, and again from this to the vegetable. The[Pg 110] fresh-water polypus may perhaps be considered as the lowest animal, and as at the same time the highest plant."[70]
"We can see," he writes, "that there is no clear and essential difference between animals and plants. Instead, Nature transitions through subtle gradations from what we consider the most perfect animal to one that is less so, and then from there to plants. The[Pg 110] fresh-water polyp may perhaps be seen as the simplest animal and at the same time the most advanced plant."[70]
Looking to the resemblances between animals and plants, he declares that their modes of reproduction and growth involve such close analogy that no difference of an essential nature can be admitted between them.[71]
Noticing the similarities between animals and plants, he states that their methods of reproduction and growth are so closely related that we can't recognize any fundamental differences between them.[71]
On the other hand, Buffon appears, at first sight, to be more struck with the points of difference between the mental powers of the lower animals and man than with those which they present in common. It is impossible, however, to accept this as Buffon's real opinion, on the strength of isolated passages, and in face of a large number of others which point stealthily but irresistibly to an exactly opposite conclusion. We find passages which show a clear apprehension of facts that the world is only now beginning to consider established, followed by others which no man who has kept a dog or cat will be inclined to agree with. I think I have already explained this sufficiently by referring it to the impossibility of his taking any other course under the circumstances of his own position and the times in which he lived. Buffon does not deal with such pregnant facts, as, for example, the geometrical ratio of increase, in such manner as to suggest that he was only half aware of their importance and bearing. On the contrary, in the very middle of those passages which, if taken literally, should most shake confidence in his judgment, there comes a sustaining sentence, so quiet that it shall pass unnoticed by all who are not attentive[Pg 111] listeners, yet so encouraging to those who are taking pains to understand their author that their interest is revived at once.
On the other hand, Buffon seems, at first glance, to focus more on the differences between the mental abilities of lower animals and humans than on their similarities. However, it's impossible to accept this as Buffon's true opinion based solely on isolated quotes, especially when faced with numerous others that subtly but surely point to the opposite conclusion. There are passages that clearly recognize facts that the world is only now starting to acknowledge, followed by others that anyone who has owned a dog or cat would likely disagree with. I think I've already explained this well by attributing it to the challenges he faced given his own circumstances and the times he lived in. Buffon doesn't address significant facts, like the geometric ratio of increase, in a way that suggests he fully understands their importance and implications. On the contrary, right in the midst of those passages that, if taken literally, should severely undermine confidence in his judgment, there's a supporting sentence so subtle that it goes unnoticed by anyone who isn't paying close attention[Pg 111]. However, it is so uplifting for those who are making an effort to understand his work that it quickly rekindles their interest.
Thus, he has insisted, and means insisting much further, on the many points of resemblance between man and the lower animals, and it has now become necessary to neutralize the effect of what he has written upon the minds of those who are not yet fitted to see instinct and reason as differentiations of a single faculty. He accordingly does this, and, as is his wont, he does it handsomely; so handsomely that even his most admiring followers begin to be uncomfortable. Whereon he begins his next paragraph with "Animals have excellent senses, but not generally, all of them, as good as man's."[72] We have heard of damning with faint praise. Is not this to praise with faint damnation? Yet we can lay hold of nothing. It was not Buffon's intention that we should. An ironical writer, concerning whom we cannot at once say whether he is in earnest or not, is an actor who is continually interrupting his performance in order to remind the spectator that he is acting. Complaint, then, against an ironical writer on the score that he puzzles us, is a complaint against irony itself; for a writer is not ironical unless he puzzles. He should not puzzle unless he believes that this is the best manner of making his reader understand him in the end, or without having a bonne bouche for those who will be at the pains to puzzle over him; and he should make it plain that for long parts of his work together he is to be taken according to the literal interpretation[Pg 112] of his words; but if he has observed the above duly, he is a successful or unsuccessful writer according as he puzzles or fails to do so, and should be praised or blamed accordingly. To condemn irony entirely, is to say that there should be no people allowed to go about the world but those to whom irony would be an impertinence.
Thus, he has insisted, and continues to insist even more, on the many similarities between humans and lower animals, and it has now become necessary to counter the impact of what he has written on those who are not yet ready to see instinct and reason as aspects of the same ability. He does this, as usual, quite elegantly; so elegantly that even his most devoted followers start to feel uneasy. He then begins his next paragraph with "Animals have excellent senses, but not generally, all of them, as good as man's."[72] We've heard of damning with faint praise. Is this not a case of praising with faint damnation? Yet we can't grab hold of anything. It wasn't Buffon's aim for us to. An ironic writer, about whom we can't immediately tell whether he is serious or not, is like an actor who constantly interrupts his performance to remind the audience that he’s acting. Complaining about an ironic writer for being puzzling is essentially a complaint against irony itself; because a writer is not being ironic unless he creates confusion. He shouldn't confuse unless he believes that this is the best way to ultimately help his reader understand him, or to provide a bonne bouche for those willing to invest effort into figuring him out; and he should clarify that for long stretches of his work, he should be taken at face value[Pg 112] according to the literal meaning of his words; but if he has followed these guidelines well, he is a successful or unsuccessful writer based on whether he puzzles or fails to do so, and should be praised or criticized accordingly. To entirely reject irony would mean saying that only those who wouldn’t find irony offensive should be permitted to roam the world.
Having already in some measure reassured us by the faintness with which he disparages the senses of the lower animals, Buffon continues, that these senses, whether in man or in animals, may be greatly developed by exercise: which we may suppose that a man of even less humour than Buffon must know to be great nonsense, unless it be taken to involve that animals as well as man can reflect and remember; it now, therefore, becomes necessary to reassure the other side, and to maintain that animals cannot reflect, and have no memory. "Je crois," he writes, "qu'on peut démontrer que les animaux n'ont aucune connaissance du passé, aucune idée du temps, et que par conséquent ils n'ont pas la mémoire."[73]
Having already reassured us somewhat by the way he downplays the senses of lower animals, Buffon goes on to say that these senses, in both humans and animals, can be significantly enhanced through practice. We can assume that someone even less humorous than Buffon would recognize this as ridiculous nonsense, unless it implies that animals, like humans, can reflect and remember. Therefore, it is now necessary to reassure the opposite side and argue that animals cannot reflect and have no memory. "I believe," he writes, "that it can be demonstrated that animals have no knowledge of the past, no concept of time, and therefore they do not have memory."[73]
I am ashamed of even arguing seriously against the supposition that this was Buffon's real opinion. The very sweepingness of the assertion, the baldness, and I might say brutality with which it is made, are convincing in their suggestiveness of one who is laughing very quietly in his sleeve.
I feel embarrassed even to argue seriously against the idea that this was Buffon's true opinion. The sheer boldness of the claim, its bluntness, and I might even say harshness, are all telling in how it suggests someone who is quietly laughing behind the scenes.
"Society," he continues, later on, "considered even in the case of a single human family, involves the power of reason; it involves feeling in such of the lower[Pg 113] animals as form themselves into societies freely and of their own accord, but it involves nothing whatever in the case of bees, who have found themselves thrown together through no effort of their own. Such societies can only be, and it is plain have only been, the results—neither foreseen, nor ordained, nor conceived by those who achieve them—of the universal mechanism and of the laws of movement established by the Creator."[74] A hive of bees, in fact, is to be considered as composed of "ten thousand animated automata."[75] Years later he repeats these views with little if any modification.[76] A still more remarkable passage is to be found a little farther on. "If," he asks, "animals have neither understanding, mind, nor memory, if they are wholly without intelligence, and if they are limited to the exercise and experience of feeling only," and it must be remembered that Buffon has denied all these powers to the inferior animals, "whence comes that remarkable prescient instinct which so many of them exhibit? Is the mere power of feeling sensations sufficient to make them garner up food during the summer, on which food they may subsist in winter? Does not this involve the power of comparing dates, and the idea of a coming future, an 'inquiétude raisonnée'? Why do we find in the hole of the field-mouse enough acorns to keep him until the following summer? Why do we find such an abundant store of honey and wax within the bee-hive? Why do ants store food? Why should birds make nests if they do not know that they will have[Pg 114] need of them? Whence arise the stories that we hear of the wisdom of foxes, which hide their prey in different spots, that they may find it at their need and live upon it for days together? Or of the subtilty of owls, which husband their store of mice by biting off their feet, so that they cannot run away? Or of the marvellous penetration of bees, which know beforehand that their queen should lay so many eggs in such and such a time, and that so many of these eggs should be of a kind which will develop into drones, and so many more of such another kind as should become neuters; and who in consequence of this their foreknowledge build so many larger cells for the first, and so many smaller for the second?"[77]
"Society," he continues later on, "even when considering a single human family, involves the power of reason; it involves emotions in the lower[Pg 113] animals that freely come together by their own choice, but it involves nothing at all in the case of bees, who find themselves grouped together without any effort of their own. Such societies can only exist, and it’s clear they have only ever been, the results—neither anticipated, nor planned, nor imagined by those that create them—of the universal mechanism and the laws of movement set by the Creator."[74] A hive of bees, in reality, is to be seen as made up of "ten thousand animated automatons."[75] Years later, he reiterates these views with little to no modification.[76] A even more striking observation can be found a little further on. "If," he asks, "animals lack understanding, thought, and memory, if they are entirely devoid of intelligence, and if they are limited only to feeling sensations," and we must remember that Buffon has denied all these abilities to the lower animals, "where does that remarkable instinct we often see come from? Is simply being able to feel sensations enough to make them gather food in the summer for their winter survival? Doesn’t this imply the ability to compare times, and the notion of a future, a 'reasoned unrest'? Why do we find in the field mouse’s burrow enough acorns to last until the next summer? Why do we see such an abundant supply of honey and wax in the beehive? Why do ants collect food? Why do birds build nests if they don’t know they’ll need them? How do we explain the stories we hear about the cleverness of foxes, which hide their prey in different places so they can find it later and eat it for days? Or the cunning of owls, which save their supply of mice by biting off their feet so they can’t escape? Or the extraordinary insight of bees, which know in advance how many eggs their queen should lay at certain times, and how many of these eggs will turn into drones, and how many will become workers; and as a result of this foresight, they build larger cells for the drones and smaller ones for the workers?"[77]
Buffon answers these questions thus:—
Buffon answers these questions like this:—
"Before replying to them," he says, "we should make sure of the facts themselves;—are they to be depended upon? Have they been narrated by men of intelligence and philosophers, or are they popular fables only?" (How many delightful stories of the same character does he not soon proceed to tell us himself). "I am persuaded that all these pretended wonders will disappear, and the cause of each one of them be found upon due examination. But admitting their truth for a moment, and granting to the narrators of them that animals have a presentiment, a forethought, and even a certainty concerning coming events, does it therefore follow that this should spring from intelligence? If so, theirs is assuredly much greater than our own. For our foreknowledge amounts to conjecture only; the vaunted[Pg 115] light of our reason doth but suffice to show us a little probability; whereas the forethought of animals is unerring, and must spring from some principle far higher than any we know of through our own experience. Does not such a consequence, I ask, prove repugnant alike to religion and common sense?"[78]
"Before we respond to them," he says, "we should confirm the facts themselves; are they reliable? Have they been shared by knowledgeable individuals and philosophers, or are they just popular myths?" (He goes on to tell us many delightful stories of the same kind himself). "I'm convinced that all these supposed wonders will vanish, and we will find clear explanations upon proper investigation. But for a moment, let's accept their truth and concede to the storytellers that animals have an instinct, a premonition, and even certainty about future events. Does that mean this comes from intelligence? If that’s the case, then theirs is certainly greater than ours. Our foresight is mere speculation; the so-called light of our reason shows us only a bit of probability, whereas the foresight of animals is infallible and must come from a principle much higher than anything we know from our own experience. Doesn't such a conclusion seem to contradict both religion and common sense?"[78]
This is Buffon's way. Whenever he has shown us clearly what we ought to think, he stops short suddenly on religious grounds. It is incredible that the writer who at the very commencement of his work makes man take his place among the animals, and who sees a subtle gradation extending over all living beings "from the most perfect creature"—who must be man—"to the most entirely inorganic substance"—I say it is incredible that such a writer should not see that he had made out a stronger case in favour of the reason of animals than against it.
This is Buffon's approach. Whenever he clearly shows us what we should think, he abruptly halts on religious grounds. It's surprising that the writer who, right at the beginning of his work, places humans among animals, and who notices a fine gradation spanning all living things "from the most perfect creature"—which has to be humans—"to the most completely inorganic substance"—I mean, it’s astonishing that such a writer does not recognize that he has actually presented a stronger argument in support of animal reasoning than against it.
According to him, the test whether a thing is to have such and such a name is whether it looks fairly like other things to which the same name is given; if it does, it is to have the name; if it does not, it is not. No one accepted this lesson more heartily than Dr. Darwin, whose shrewd and homely mind, if not so great as Buffon's, was still one of no common order. Let us see the view he took of this matter. He writes:—
According to him, the way to determine if something should be called a certain name is whether it looks similar to other things that share that name; if it does, it gets the name; if it doesn’t, it doesn’t. No one embraced this idea more enthusiastically than Dr. Darwin, whose sharp and practical mind, though not as brilliant as Buffon's, was still quite exceptional. Let’s take a look at his perspective on this issue. He writes:—
"If we were better acquainted with the histories of those insects which are formed into societies, as the bees, wasps, and ants, I make no doubt but we should find that their arts and improvements are not so similar[Pg 116] and uniform as they now appear to us, but that they arose in the same manner from experience and tradition, as the arts of our own species; though their reasoning is from fewer ideas, is busied about fewer objects, and is executed with less energy."[79]
"If we knew more about the histories of social insects like bees, wasps, and ants, I’m sure we would find that their skills and advancements aren’t as alike and consistent as they seem to us now. They likely developed in similar ways through experience and tradition, much like our own advancements; although their reasoning is based on fewer ideas, focuses on fewer things, and is carried out with less intensity."[Pg 116][79]
And again, a little later:—
And again, shortly after:—
"According to the late observations of Mr. Hunter, it appears that beeswax is not made from the dust of the anthers of flowers, which they bring home on their thighs, but that this makes what is termed bee-bread, and is used for the purpose of feeding the bee-maggots; in the same way butterflies live on honey, but the previous caterpillar lives on vegetable leaves, while the maggots of large flies require flesh for their food. What induces the bee, who lives on honey, to lay up vegetable powder for its young? What induces the butterfly to lay its eggs on leaves when itself feeds on honey?... If these are not deductions from their own previous experience or observation, all the actions of mankind must be resolved into instincts."[80]
"According to Mr. Hunter’s recent findings, it seems that beeswax isn’t made from the pollen they collect on their thighs. Instead, that pollen turns into what’s called bee-bread, which is used to feed the bee larvae. Similarly, butterflies eat honey, but their caterpillars feed on plant leaves, while the larvae of larger flies need meat. What drives a bee, which survives on honey, to gather plant material for its offspring? What makes a butterfly lay its eggs on leaves when it feeds on honey? If these actions aren’t based on their past experiences or observations, then we have to consider all of humanity's actions as instinctual."[80]
Or again:—
Or again:—
"Common worms stop up their holes with leaves or straws to prevent the frost from injuring them, or the centipes from devouring them. The habits of peace or the stratagems of war of these subterranean nations are covered from our view; but a friend of mine prevailed on a distressed worm to enter the hole of another worm on a bowling green, and he presently returned much wounded about the head, ... which evinces[Pg 117] they have design in stopping the mouths of their habitations."[81]
"Common worms block their holes with leaves or straw to keep the frost from harming them or the centipedes from eating them. The peaceful habits or tactical moves of these underground creatures are hidden from our sight; however, a friend of mine convinced a struggling worm to go into another worm's hole on a bowling green, and it quickly came back injured around the head, ... which shows[Pg 117] they have a reason for blocking the entrances to their homes."[81]
Does it not look as if Dr. Darwin had in his mind the very passage of Buffon which I have been last quoting? and is it likely that the facts which were accepted by Dr. Darwin without question, or the conclusions which were obvious to him, were any less accepted by or obvious to Buffon?
Doesn't it seem like Dr. Darwin had the exact passage from Buffon I just quoted in mind? And is it reasonable to think that the facts Dr. Darwin took for granted, or the conclusions that were clear to him, were any less accepted or obvious to Buffon?
The Goat—Hybridism.
The Goat—Hybridism.
In his prefatory remarks upon the goat, Buffon complains of the want of systematic and certified experiment as to what breeds and species will be fertile inter se, and with what results. The passage is too long to quote, but is exceedingly good, and throughout involves belief in a very considerable amount of modification in the course of successive generations. I may give the following as an example:—
In his introductory comments about the goat, Buffon expresses his frustration with the lack of organized and verified experiments regarding which breeds and species can successfully breed with each other and what the outcomes are. The section is too lengthy to quote, but it's really insightful and consistently suggests a strong belief in significant changes occurring over many generations. Here's an example:—
"We do not know whether or no the zebra would breed with the horse or ass—whether the large-tailed Barbary sheep would be fertile if crossed with our own—whether the chamois is not a wild goat; and whether it would not form an intermediate breed if crossed with our domesticated goats; we do not know whether the differences between apes are really specific, or whether apes are not like dogs, one single species, of which there are many different breeds.... Our ignorance concerning all these facts is almost inevitable, as the experiments which would decide them require more time, pains, and money than can be spared from, the life and[Pg 118] fortune of an ordinary man. I have spent many years in experiments of this kind, and will give my results when I come to my chapter on mules; but I may as well say at once that they have thrown but little light upon the subject, and have been for the most part unsuccessful."[82]
"We don't know if the zebra can breed with the horse or donkey—if the large-tailed Barbary sheep would produce offspring if crossed with our own—if the chamois is actually a wild goat; and if it could create a hybrid breed with our domestic goats. We also don't know if the differences among apes are truly distinct species, or if apes are like dogs, one species with many different breeds.... Our lack of knowledge about all these facts is nearly unavoidable, as the experiments needed to clarify them require more time, effort, and money than an average person's life and[Pg 118] resources can afford. I've spent many years on this type of experimentation, and I’ll share my findings when I reach the chapter on mules; but I might as well say upfront that they haven't shed much light on the topic and have mostly been unsuccessful."[82]
"But these," he continues, "are the very points which must determine our whole knowledge concerning animals, their right division into species, and the true understanding of their history." He proposes therefore, in the present lack of knowledge, "to regard all animals as different species which do not breed together under our eyes," and to leave time and experiment to correct mistakes.[83]
"But these," he continues, "are the key points that should shape our entire understanding of animals, how we categorize them into different species, and the true grasp of their history." He suggests, given our current gaps in knowledge, "to consider all animals as distinct species that don’t interbreed in front of us," and to let time and experimentation fix any errors.[83]
The Pig—Doctrine of Final Causes.
The Pig—Theory of Final Causes.
We have seen that the doctrine of the mutability of species has been unfortunately entangled with that of final causes, or the belief that every organ and every part of each animal or plant has been designed to serve some purpose useful to the animal, and this not only useful at some past time, but useful now, and for all time to come. He who believes species to be mutable will see in many organs signs of the history of the individual, but nothing more. Buffon, as I have said, is explicit in his denial of final causes in the sense expressed above. After pointing out that the pig is an animal whose relation to other animals it is difficult to define, he says:—
We have seen that the idea of species changing over time has unfortunately become mixed up with the concept of final causes, or the belief that every organ and part of each animal or plant was designed to serve a purpose useful to the organism—not just in the past, but valuable now and for the future. Someone who believes that species can change will recognize in many organs evidence of the individual’s history, but nothing more. Buffon, as I mentioned, clearly denies the idea of final causes in the way described above. After noting that the pig is an animal whose relationship to other animals is hard to define, he says:—
"In a word, it is of a nature altogether equivocal[Pg 119] and ambiguous, or, rather, it must appear so to those who believe the hypothetical order of their own ideas to be the real order of things, and who see nothing in the infinite chain of existences but a few apparent points to which they will refer everything.
"In short, it’s completely unclear and ambiguous[Pg 119], or rather, it must seem that way to those who think the way they see things is the actual order of reality, and who perceive only a few obvious points in the endless chain of existence to which they relate everything."
"But we cannot know Nature by inclosing her action within the narrow circle of our own thoughts.... Instead of limiting her action, we should extend it through immensity itself; we should regard nothing as impossible, but should expect to find all things—supposing that all things are possible—nay, are. Doubtful species, then, irregular productions, anomalous existences will henceforth no longer surprise us, and will find their place in the infinite order of things as duly as any others. They fill up the links of the chain; they form knots and intermediate points, and also they mark its extremities: they are of especial value to human intelligence, as providing it with cases in which Nature, being less in conformity with herself, is taken more unawares, so that we can recognize singular characters and fleeting traits which show us that her ends are much more general than are our own views of those ends, and that, though she does nothing in vain, yet she does but little with the designs which we ascribe to her."[84]
"But we can't understand Nature by confining her actions to the limited scope of our own thoughts.... Instead of restricting her, we should embrace her vastness; we shouldn’t consider anything impossible but should expect to find everything—assuming that everything is possible—actually is. Uncertain species, unusual creations, and strange beings will no longer astonish us, and they will occupy their place in the infinite order of things just like everything else. They complete the links in the chain; they create knots and interim points, and they also mark its ends: they are particularly valuable to human understanding, as they present situations where Nature, being less consistent with herself, surprises us, allowing us to recognize unique characteristics and fleeting traits that reveal to us that her purposes are much broader than our limited perspectives on those purposes, and that while she does nothing without reason, she accomplishes very little with the intentions we attribute to her."[84]
"The pig," he continues, "is not formed on an original, special, and perfect type; its type is compounded of that of many other animals. It has parts which are evidently useless, or which at any rate it cannot use—such as toes, all the bones of which are[Pg 120] perfectly formed but which are yet of no service to it. Nature then is far from subjecting herself to final causes in the composition of her creatures. Why should she not sometimes add superabundant parts, seeing she so often omits essential ones?" "How many animals are there not which lack sense and limbs? Why is it considered so necessary that every part in an individual should be useful to the other parts and to the whole animal? Should it not be enough that they do not injure each other nor stand in the way of each other's fair development? All parts coexist which do not injure each other enough to destroy each other, and perhaps in the greater number of living beings the parts which must be considered as relative, useful, or necessary, are fewer than those which are indifferent, useless, and superabundant. But we—ever on the look out to refer all parts to a certain end—when we can see no apparent use for them suppose them to have hidden uses, and imagine connections which are without foundation, and serve only to obscure our perception of Nature as she really is: we fail to see that we thus rob philosophy of her true character, which is to inquire into the 'how' of things—into the manner in which Nature acts—and that we substitute for this true object a vain idea, seeking to divine the 'why'—the ends which she has proposed in acting."[85]
"The pig," he goes on, "is not based on a unique, special, and perfect model; its form is a mix of many other animals. It has features that are clearly useless or that it can’t use at all—like toes, which are fully formed but serve no purpose. Nature, then, doesn't strictly adhere to final causes in creating her creatures. Why shouldn't she sometimes add extra parts, especially since she often leaves out essential ones?" "How many animals lack senses or limbs? Why is it thought to be so vital that every part of a creature be useful to the other parts and to the whole? Shouldn't it be sufficient that they don't harm each other or obstruct each other's proper growth? All parts exist as long as they don't cause enough harm to destroy one another, and perhaps for most living beings, the parts that are truly relative, useful, or necessary are fewer than those that are indifferent, useless, and excessive. Yet we—always eager to connect every part to a specific purpose—when we can't see an obvious use for them, assume they have hidden ones, and create connections that lack foundation, which only cloud our understanding of Nature as it truly is: we fail to recognize that we are thus stripping philosophy of its true essence, which is to explore the 'how' of things—how Nature operates—and instead, we replace this genuine goal with a pointless idea, attempting to uncover the 'why'—the purposes she has in her actions."[85]
The Dog—Varieties in consequence of Man's Selection.
The Dog—Different Types Due to Human Selection.
"Of all animals the dog is most susceptible of impressions, and becomes most easily modified by moral[Pg 121] causes. He is also the one whose nature is most subject to the variations and alterations caused by physical influences: he varies to a prodigious extent, in temperament, mental powers, and in habits: his very form is not constant;" ... but presents so many differences that "dogs have nothing in common but conformity of interior organization, and the power of interbreeding freely."...
"Of all animals, dogs are the most open to influences and can be easily shaped by moral[Pg 121] reasons. They are also the ones whose nature is most affected by physical factors: they differ significantly in temperament, mental abilities, and habits; even their physical form isn't consistent; they show so many variations that 'dogs have nothing in common except for their internal structure and the ability to breed freely.'"
... "How then can we detect the characters of the original race? How recognize the effects produced by climate, food, &c.? How, again, distinguish these from those other effects which come from the intermixture of races, either when wild or in a state of domestication? All these causes, in the course of time, alter even the most constant forms, so that the imprint of Nature does not preserve its sharpness in races which man has dealt with largely. Those animals which are free to choose climate and food for themselves can best conserve their original character, ... but those which man has subjected to his own influence—which he has taken with him from clime to clime, whose food, habits, and manner of life he has altered—must also have changed their form far more than others; and as a matter of fact we find much greater variety in the species of domesticated animals than in those of wild ones. Of all these, however, the dog is the one most closely attached to man, living like man the least regular manner of life; he is also the one whose feelings so master him as to make him docile, obedient, susceptible of every kind of impression, and even of every kind of constraint; it is not surprising, then, that[Pg 122] he should of all animals present us with the greatest variety in shape, stature, colour, and all physical and mental qualities."
... "So how can we identify the traits of the original race? How can we recognize the effects of climate, food, etc.? And how do we distinguish these from the effects that come from mixing races, whether in the wild or when domesticated? Over time, all these factors change even the most stable characteristics, so the imprint of Nature loses its clarity in races that have been significantly influenced by humans. Animals that can choose their own climate and food are better at preserving their original traits, but those that humans have influenced—those we’ve taken from place to place, whose food, habits, and lifestyles we’ve changed—must have altered their forms much more than others. In fact, we see much greater variety among domesticated animals than in wild ones. Of all these animals, the dog is the one most closely bonded to humans, living a life that is the least regular; it is also the animal whose emotions affect it so deeply that it becomes docile, obedient, and receptive to various kinds of influence and control. It’s not surprising, then, that[Pg 122] the dog shows us the greatest diversity in shape, size, color, and all physical and mental traits."
Here again the direct cause of modification is given as being the inner feelings of the animal modified, change of conditions being the indirect cause as with Dr. Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck.
Here again, the main reason for change is described as the internal feelings of the animal that changes, while changes in conditions are the indirect cause, similar to what Dr. Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck proposed.
"Other circumstances, however, concur to produce these results. The dog is short-lived: he breeds often and freely: he is perpetually under the eye of man; hence when—by some chance common enough with Nature—a variation or special feature has made its appearance, man has tried to perpetuate it by uniting together the individuals in which it has appeared, as people do now who wish to form new breeds of dogs and other animals. Moreover, though species were all formed at the same time, yet the number of generations since the creation has been much greater in the short-lived than in the long-lived species: hence variations, alterations, and departure from the original type, may be expected to have become more perceptible in the case of animals which are so much farther removed from their original stock.
"Other factors, however, come together to produce these results. Dogs have a short lifespan: they breed frequently and easily: they are constantly under human supervision; therefore, when—due to some common occurrence in Nature—a variation or unique trait appears, humans have tried to maintain it by breeding the individuals in which it has appeared, similar to what people do now when they want to create new breeds of dogs and other animals. Additionally, while all species were formed at the same time, the number of generations since their creation has been much larger in short-lived species than in long-lived ones: as a result, variations, changes, and deviations from the original type are likely to be more noticeable in animals that are much further removed from their original lineage."
"Man is now eight times nearer Adam than the dog is to the first dog—for man lives eighty years, while the dog lives but ten. If, then, these species have an equal tendency to depart from their original type, the departure should be eight times more apparent with the dog than with man."[86]
"Humans are now eight times closer to Adam than dogs are to the first dog—humans live about eighty years, while dogs only live around ten. So, if both species have the same tendency to stray from their original type, the differences should be eight times more noticeable in dogs than in humans."[86]
Here follow remarks upon the great variability of ephemeral insects and of animal plants, on the impossibility[Pg 123] of discovering the parent-stock of our wheat and of others of our domesticated plants,[87] and on the tendency of both plants and animals to resume feral characteristics on becoming wild again after domestication.[88]
Here are some thoughts on the significant variability of short-lived insects and certain plants, the challenges of identifying the original source of our wheat and other domesticated plants,[87] and the tendency of both plants and animals to revert to their wild traits when they go back to the wild after being domesticated.[88]
The Hare—Geometrical Ratio of Increase.
The Hare—Growth Ratio.
We have already seen that it was Buffon's pleasure to consider the hare a rabbit for the time being, and to make it the text for a discourse upon fecundity. I have no doubt he enjoyed doing this, and would have found comparatively little pleasure in preaching the same discourse upon the rabbit. Speaking of the way in which even the races of mankind have struggled and crowded each other out, Buffon says:—
We’ve already noted that Buffon liked to think of the hare as a rabbit for the moment and used it as a basis for discussing fertility. I’m sure he enjoyed this and would have found far less pleasure in giving the same speech about the rabbit. When talking about how even different races of humans have competed and pushed each other aside, Buffon says:—
"These great events—these well-marked epochs in the history of the human race—are yet but ripples, as it were, on the current of life; which, as a general rule, flows onward evenly and in equal volume.
"These significant events—these clearly defined periods in human history—are ultimately just ripples on the flow of life; which, generally speaking, moves forward smoothly and with consistent intensity."
"It may be said that the movement of Nature turns upon two immovable pivots—one, the illimitable fecundity which she has given to all species; the other, the innumerable difficulties which reduce the results of that fecundity, and leave throughout time nearly the same quantity of individuals in every species.[89]...[Pg 124] Taking the earth as a whole, and the human race in its entirety, the numbers of mankind, like those of animals, should remain nearly constant throughout time; for they depend upon an equilibrium of physical causes which has long since been reached, and which neither man's moral nor his physical efforts can disturb, inasmuch as these moral efforts do but spring from physical causes, of which they are the special effects. No matter what care man may take of his own species, he can only make it more abundant in one place by destroying it or diminishing its numbers in another. When one part of the globe is overpeopled, men emigrate, spread themselves over other countries, destroy one another, and establish laws and customs which sometimes only too surely prevent excess of population. In those climates where fecundity is greatest, as in China, Egypt, and Guinea, they banish, mutilate, sell, or drown infants. Here, we condemn them to a perpetual celibacy. Those who are in being find it easy to assert rights over the unborn. Regarding themselves as the necessary, they annihilate the contingent, and suppress future generations for their own pleasure and advantage. Man does for his own race, without perceiving it, what he does also for the inferior animals: that is to say, he protects it and encourages it to increase, or neglects it according to his sense of need—according as advantage or inconvenience is expected as the consequence of either course. And since all these moral effects themselves depend upon physical causes, which have been in permanent equilibrium ever since the world was formed, it follows that the numbers of[Pg 125] mankind, like those of animals, should remain constant.
It can be said that the cycle of Nature revolves around two unchanging points—one is the limitless ability to reproduce that she has granted to all species; the other is the countless challenges that limit the outcomes of that reproduction, keeping the population of each species nearly the same over time.[89]...[Pg 124] Taking the earth as a whole and considering the human race in its entirety, the number of people, like that of animals, should remain relatively stable throughout time; this is because they depend on a balance of physical factors that has long been established and which neither human moral efforts nor physical actions can disrupt, since these moral actions arise from physical causes, of which they are specific consequences. No matter how much care people take of their own kind, they can only increase the population in one area by decreasing it or harming it in another. When one part of the world becomes overcrowded, people migrate, spread to other areas, compete with each other, and create laws and customs that often effectively prevent overpopulation. In regions where reproduction is highest, such as in China, Egypt, and Guinea, they may abandon, mutilate, sell, or drown infants. Here, we condemn them to lifelong celibacy. Those who are alive easily claim rights over those not yet born. Considering themselves essential, they eliminate the potential lives of future generations for their own comfort and benefit. Humanity acts towards its own kind, often without realizing it, in the same way it does towards lesser animals: that is, it either protects and encourages growth or neglects them based on perceived needs—determining beneficial or detrimental outcomes for either choice. Since all these moral effects depend on physical causes that have been in constant balance since the world began, it follows that the population of[Pg 125] mankind, like that of animals, should remain stable.
"Nevertheless, this fixed state, this constant number, is not absolute, all physical and moral causes, and all the results which spring from them, balance themselves, as though, upon a see-saw, which has a certain play, but never so much as that equilibrium should be altogether lost. As everything in the universe is in movement, and as all the forces which are contained in matter act one against the other and counterbalance one another, all is done by a kind of oscillation; of which the mean points are those to which we refer as being the ordinary course of nature, while the extremes are the periods which deviate from that course most widely. And, as a matter of fact, with animals as much as with plants, a time of unusual fecundity is commonly followed by one of sterility; abundance and dearth come alternately, and often at such short intervals that we may foretell the production of a coming year by our knowledge of the past one. Our apples, pears, oaks, beeches, and the greater number of our fruit and forest trees, bear freely but about one year in two. Caterpillars, cockchafers, woodlice, which in one year may multiply with great abundance, will appear but sparsely in the next. What indeed would become of all the good things of the earth, what would become of the useful animals, and indeed of man himself, if each individual in these years of excess was to leave its quotum of offspring? This, however, does not happen, for destruction and sterility follow closely upon excessive fecundity, and, independently of the contagion which follows inevitably upon[Pg 126] overcrowding, each species has its own special sources of death and destruction, which are of themselves sufficient to compensate for excess in any past generation.
"Still, this fixed state, this constant number, isn’t absolute. All physical and moral causes, along with the results that come from them, balance out like a see-saw, which has a bit of movement, but never so much that equilibrium is completely lost. Since everything in the universe is in motion, and because all the forces contained in matter act against one another and counterbalance each other, everything operates through a kind of oscillation; the mean points of this oscillation represent what we refer to as the normal course of nature, while the extremes are the periods that deviate most from that course. In fact, both animals and plants experience a time of unusual fertility that is usually followed by a time of barrenness; abundance and scarcity occur alternately, often with such short intervals that we can predict the yield of the coming year based on what we know about the previous one. Our apples, pears, oaks, beeches, and the majority of our fruit and forest trees produce abundantly about every other year. Caterpillars, cockchafers, and woodlice, which may multiply in great numbers one year, will be sparse the next. What would happen to all the good things on earth, to useful animals, and even to humans, if every individual in these years of plenty were to leave their share of offspring? Fortunately, that doesn’t happen, as destruction and sterility closely follow periods of excessive fertility. Beyond the inevitable contagion that follows overcrowding, each species has its specific causes of death and destruction, which are sufficient on their own to offset any surplus from a past generation."
"Nevertheless the foregoing should not be taken in an absolute sense, nor yet too strictly,—especially in the case of those races which are not left entirely to the care of Nature. Those which man takes care of—commencing with his own—are more abundant than they would be without his care, yet, as his power of taking this care is limited, the increase which has taken place is also fixed, and has long been restrained within impassable boundaries. Again, though in civilized countries man, and all the animals useful to him, are more numerous than in other places, yet their numbers never become excessive, for the same power which brings them into being destroys them as soon as they are found inconvenient."[90]
"However, the points mentioned should not be interpreted too literally or rigidly—especially regarding those groups that aren't solely under Nature's care. The ones that humans look after—starting with ourselves—are more plentiful than they would be without our attention. Yet, since our ability to provide that care is limited, the growth we've seen is also capped and has long been kept within unbreakable limits. Moreover, even though in developed countries, both humans and the animals that benefit us are more numerous than elsewhere, their populations never become excessive. This is because the same force that allows them to flourish also removes them when they start to become a burden." [90]
The Carnivora—Sensation.
The Carnivora—Excitement.
Buffon begins his seventh volume with some remarks on the carnivora in general, which I would gladly quote at fuller length than my space will allow. He dwells on the fact that the number, as well as the fecundity of the insect races is greater than that of the mammalia, and even than of plants; and he points out that "violent death is almost as necessary an usage as is the law that we must all, in one way or another, die." This leads him to the question whether animals can feel. "To speak seriously," (au réel) he says (and why this, if he had[Pg 127] always spoken seriously?[91]), "can we doubt that those animals whose organization resembles our own, feel the same sensations as we do? They must feel, for they have senses, and they must feel more and more in proportion as their senses are more active and more perfect." Those whose organ of any sense is imperfect, have but imperfect perception in respect of that sense; and those that are entirely without the organ want also all corresponding sensation. "Movement is the necessary consequence of acts of perception. I have already shown that in whatever manner a living being is organized, if it has perceptions at all, it cannot fail to show that it has them by some kind of movement of its body. Hence plants, though highly organized, have no feeling, any more than have those animals which, like plants, manifest no power of motion. Among animals there are those which, like the sensitive plant, have but a certain power of movement about their own parts, and which have no power of locomotion; such animals have as yet but little perception. Those, again, which have power of locomotion, but which, like automata, do but a small number of things, and always after the same fashion, can have only small powers of perception, and these limited to a small number of objects. But in the case of man, what automata, indeed, have we not here! How much do not education and the intercommunication of ideas increase our powers and vivacity of perception. What difference can we not see in this respect between civilized and uncivilized races, between the peasant girl, and the woman of the world? And in like manner among[Pg 128] animals, those which live with us have their perceptions increased in range, while those that are wild have but their natural instinct, which is often more certain but always more limited in range than is the intelligence of domesticated animals."[92]
Buffon starts his seventh volume with some comments about the carnivora in general, which I would happily quote at greater length if I had the space. He emphasizes that the number and reproductive capacity of insects is greater than that of mammals and even plants; he notes that "violent death is nearly as essential a practice as the fact that we must all, in one way or another, die." This brings him to the question of whether animals can feel. "To speak seriously," he says (and why this, if he had[Pg 127] always spoken seriously?[91]), "can we doubt that those animals whose structure is similar to ours feel the same sensations? They must feel, because they have senses, and they must feel increasingly as their senses become more active and refined." Those whose sense organs are imperfect have only an imperfect perception in that regard; and those that lack the organ entirely lack all corresponding sensation. "Movement is the inevitable result of acts of perception. I have already shown that no matter how a living being is organized, if it has perceptions, it will inevitably express them through some form of body movement. Therefore, while plants are highly organized, they have no feelings, just like those animals that, like plants, show no ability to move. Among animals, there are those that, like the sensitive plant, have only limited movement concerning their own parts and no ability for locomotion; such animals have very little perception. Those that can move but act mechanically, performing only a few actions in the same way, have only a limited perception, and this is restricted to a small number of objects. But in the case of humans, what mechanical beings we have here! Education and the exchange of ideas significantly enhance our abilities and perceptive vitality. We can see a noticeable difference in this regard between civilized and uncivilized people, between a peasant girl and a sophisticated woman. Similarly, among[Pg 128] animals, those that live with us have an expanded range of perceptions, while wild animals rely solely on their natural instincts, which, while often more reliable, are always more limited than the intelligence of domesticated animals."[92]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"For perception to exist in its fullest development in any animal body, that body must form a whole—an ensemble, which shall not only be capable of feeling in all its parts, but shall be so arranged that all these feeling parts shall have a close correspondence with one another, and that no one of them can be disturbed without communicating a portion of that disturbance to every other part. There must also be a single chief centre, with which all these different disturbances may be connected, and from which, as from a common point d'appui, the reactions against them may take their rise. Hence man, and those animals whose organization most resembles man's, will be the most capable of perceptions, while those whose unity is less complete, whose parts have a less close correspondence with each other—which have several centres of sensation, and which seem, in consequence, less to envelope a single existence in a single body than to contain many centres of existence separated and different from one another—these will have fewer and duller perceptions. The polypus, which can be reproduced by fission; the wasp, whose head even after separation from the body still moves, lives, acts, and even eats as heretofore; the lizard which we deprive neither of sensation nor movement by cutting[Pg 129] off part of its body; the lobster which can restore its amputated limbs; the turtle whose heart beats long after it has been plucked out, in a word all the animals whose organization differs from our own, have but small powers of perception, and the smaller the more they differ from us."[93]
"For perception to fully develop in any animal, that animal's body needs to function as a complete unit—an ensemble. This means it must be able to feel in all its parts and be arranged so that these feeling parts correspond closely with one another. If one part is disturbed, it should also affect the others. There should be a central point where all these disturbances connect, serving as a common point d'appui from which reactions can emerge. Therefore, humans and animals with a structure similar to ours will have the greatest capacity for perception. In contrast, animals whose unity is less complete, with parts that have a looser correspondence, multiple centers of sensation, and that appear to contain separate existences rather than a single entity, will have fewer and less intense perceptions. Consider the polyp that can reproduce by fission; the wasp whose head continues to move, live, act, and even eat after being separated from the body; the lizard that still has sensation and movement after part of its body is cut off; the lobster that can regenerate its lost limbs; the turtle whose heart still beats long after being removed. In short, all animals whose organization differs from ours have limited perceptual capabilities, and the more they differ from us, the less perceptive they tend to be."[Pg 129]
This is Buffon's way of satirizing our inability to bear in mind that we are compelled to judge all things by our own standards. He also wishes to reassure those who might be alarmed at the tendency of some of his foregoing remarks, and who he knew would find comfort in being told that a thing which does not express itself as they do does not feel at all.
This is Buffon's way of poking fun at our tendency to judge everything by our own standards. He also wants to reassure those who might be worried about some of his earlier comments, knowing they would find comfort in hearing that something that doesn't express itself like they do doesn't feel anything at all.
The diaphragm according to Buffon appears to be the centre of the powers of sensation; the slightest injury "even to the attachments of the diaphragm is followed by strong convulsions, and even by death. The brain which has been called the seat of 'sensations' is yet not the centre of 'perception,' since we can wound it, and even take considerable parts of it away, without death's ensuing, and without preventing an animal from living, moving and feeling in all its parts."
The diaphragm, according to Buffon, seems to be the center of our sensory abilities; even a minor injury to the diaphragm can lead to severe convulsions and even death. Although the brain has been called the center of 'sensations,' it is not the center of 'perception,' since we can injure it and even remove significant portions of it without causing death, and without stopping an animal from living, moving, and feeling throughout its body.
Buffon thus distinguishes between "sensation" and "perception." "Sensation," he says, "is simply the activity of a sense, but perception is the pleasantness or unpleasantness of this sensation," "perceived by its being propagated and becoming active throughout the entire system." I have therefore several times, when translating from Buffon, rendered the word "sentiment" by "perception," and shall continue to do so. "I say,"[Pg 130] writes Buffon, "the pleasantness or unpleasantness, because this is the very essence of perception; the one feature of perception consists in perceiving either pain or pleasure; and though movements which do not affect us in either one or the other of these two ways may indeed take place within us, yet we are indifferent to them, and do not perceive that we are affected by them. All external movement, and all exercise of the animal powers, spring from perception; its action is proportionate to the extent of its excitation, to the extent of the feeling which is being felt.[94] And this same part, which we regard as the centre of sensation, will also be that of all the animal powers; or, if it is preferred to call it so, it will be the common point d'appui from which they all take rise. The diaphragm is to the animal what the 'stock' is to the plant; both divide an organism transversely, both serve as the point d'appui of opposing forces; for the forces which push upward those parts of a tree which should form its trunk and branches, bear upon and are supported by the 'stock,' as do those opposing forces, which drive the roots downwards.
Buffon distinguishes between "sensation" and "perception." "Sensation," he explains, "is simply the activity of a sense, while perception is the pleasantness or unpleasantness of that sensation," "perceived as it spreads and becomes active throughout the entire system." Therefore, when translating from Buffon, I have often rendered the word "sentiment" as "perception," and I will continue to do so. "I say,"[Pg 130] Buffon writes, "the pleasantness or unpleasantness, because this is the essence of perception; the main aspect of perception is recognizing either pain or pleasure; and while movements that don't affect us in either of these ways may occur within us, we remain indifferent to them and don't perceive any impact from them. All external movement and all uses of animal powers originate from perception; its action is proportional to the intensity of its stimulation, to the degree of feeling that is being experienced.[94] Similarly, the part we consider the center of sensation will also be at the core of all animal powers; or, if preferred, it will be the common point d'appui from which they all arise. The diaphragm functions for the animal in the same way the 'stock' does for the plant; both divide an organism horizontally, and both serve as the point d'appui for opposing forces; the forces that push upward those parts of a tree intended to form its trunk and branches rely on and are supported by the 'stock,' just as those opposing forces drive the roots downwards.
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"Even on a cursory examination we can see that all our innermost affections, our most lively emotions, our most expansive moments of delight, and, on the other hand, our sudden starts, pains, sicknesses, and swoons—in fact, all our strong impressions concerning the pleasure or pain of any sensation—make themselves felt within the body, and about the region of the diaphragm. The brain, on the contrary, shows no sign of being a seat[Pg 131] of perception. In the head there are pure sensations and nothing else, or rather, there are but the representations of sensations stripped of the character of perception; that is to say, we can remember and call to mind whether such and such a sensation was pleasant to us or otherwise, and if this operation, which goes on in the head, is followed by a vivid perception, then the impression made is perceived in the interior of the body, and always in the region of the diaphragm. Hence, in the fœtus where this membrane is without use, there is no perception, or so little that nothing comes of it, the movements of the fœtus, such as they are, being rather mechanical than dependent on sensation and will.
"Even with a quick look, we can see that all our deepest feelings, our most intense emotions, our most joyful moments, and, on the flip side, our sudden jolts, pains, illnesses, and fainting spells—in fact, all our strong reactions to pleasure or pain—are felt in the body, particularly around the diaphragm. The brain, on the other hand, doesn't show any signs of being the center of perception. In the head, there are only pure sensations and nothing more, or rather, just representations of sensations that lack the quality of perception; in other words, we can remember and think back on whether a certain sensation was pleasant or not, and if this mental process, which occurs in the head, is followed by a strong perception, then the impression made is felt within the body, and always around the diaphragm area. Therefore, in the fetus, where this membrane is not functional, there is no perception, or so little that it doesn’t matter, with the fetus's movements being more mechanical than based on sensation and will."
"Whatever the matter may be which serves as the vehicle of perception, and produces muscular movement, it is certain that it is propagated through the nerves, and that it communicates itself instantaneously from one extremity of the system to the other. In whatever manner this operation is conducted, whether by the vibrations, as it were, of elastic cords or by a subtle fire, or by a matter resembling electricity, which not only resides in animal as in all other bodies, but is being continually renewed in them by the movements of the heart and lungs, by the friction of the blood within the arteries, and also by the action of exterior causes upon our organs of sense—in whatever manner, I say, the operation is conducted, it is nevertheless certain that the nerves and membranes are the only parts in an animal body that can feel. The blood, lymphs, and all other fluids, the fats, bone, flesh, and all other solids, are of themselves void of sensation. And[Pg 132] so also is the brain; it is a soft and inelastic substance, incapable therefore of producing or of propagating the movement, vibrations, or concussions which, result in perception. The meninges, on the other hand, are exceedingly sensitive, and are the envelopes of all the nerves; like the nerves, they take rise in the head; and, dividing themselves like the branches of the nerves, they extend even to their smallest ramifications: they are, so to speak, flattened nerves; they are of the same substance as the nerves, are nearly of the same degree of elasticity, and form a necessary part of the system of sensation. If, then, the seat of the sensations must be placed in the head, let it be placed in the meninges, and not in the medullary part of the brain, which is of an entirely different substance."[95]
"Whatever the issue might be that allows us to perceive and produces movement, it's clear that it travels through the nerves and communicates itself instantly from one part of the body to another. However this process occurs—whether by vibrations like elastic cords, a subtle fire, or a matter similar to electricity, which exists in animals just like in all other bodies, but is continually replenished by the movements of the heart and lungs, by the friction of blood within the arteries, and by external influences on our senses—no matter how it happens, it’s certain that only the nerves and membranes in an animal body can feel. The blood, lymph, and all other fluids, as well as fats, bones, flesh, and all other solids, are unable to sense anything on their own. And so is the brain; it’s a soft and non-elastic substance and therefore can't produce or transmit the movements, vibrations, or shocks that lead to perception. The meninges, however, are highly sensitive and wrap around all the nerves; like the nerves, they originate in the head and branch out, extending to their smallest outgrowths. They are, in a sense, flattened nerves; they are made of the same material as the nerves, have nearly the same elasticity, and are an essential part of the sensation system. Therefore, if the source of sensations must be located in the head, it should be placed in the meninges, not in the medullary part of the brain, which is made of entirely different material."[95]
If this is so, it appears from what will follow as though the meninges must be the "stock" rather than the diaphragm.
If that's the case, it seems from what follows that the meninges must be the "stock" instead of the diaphragm.
"What perhaps has given rise to the opinion that the seat of all sensations and the centre of all sensibility is in the brain, is the fact that the nerves, which are the organs of perception, all attach themselves to the brain, which has hence come to be regarded as the one common centre which can receive all their vibrations and impressions. This fact alone has sufficed to indicate the brain as the origin of perceptions—as the essential organ of sensations; in a word, as the common sensorium. This supposition has appeared so simple and natural that its physical impossibility has been overlooked, an impossibility, however, which should be[Pg 133] sufficiently apparent. For how can a part which cannot feel—a soft inactive substance like the brain—be the very organ of perception and movement? How can this soft and perceptionless part not only receive impressions, but preserve them for a length of time, and transmit their undulatory movements (en propage les ébranlements) throughout all the solid and feeling parts of the body? It may perhaps be maintained with Descartes and M. de Peyronie that the principle of sensation does not reside in the brain, but in the pineal gland or in the corpus callosum; but a glance at the conformation of the brain itself will suffice to show that these parts do not join on to the nerves, but that they are entirely surrounded by those parts of the brain which do not feel, and are so separated from the nerves that they cannot receive any movement from them; whence it follows that this second supposition is as groundless as the first."[96]
"What seems to have led to the belief that the source of all sensations and the center of all sensitivity is in the brain is the fact that the nerves, which are the organs of perception, all connect to the brain. This has caused the brain to be seen as the single central hub that can receive all their vibrations and impressions. This fact alone has been enough to identify the brain as the source of perceptions—essentially the organ of sensations; in other words, as the common sensorium. This idea has seemed so straightforward and natural that its physical impossibility has been overlooked, an impossibility that should be[Pg 133] quite obvious. For how can a part that cannot feel—a soft, inactive substance like the brain—be the very organ of perception and movement? How can this soft and insensate part not only receive impressions but also retain them for a long time and transmit their undulating movements (en propage les ébranlements) throughout all the solid and feeling parts of the body? It might be argued, along with Descartes and M. de Peyronie, that the principle of sensation does not reside in the brain but in the pineal gland or the corpus callosum; however, a look at the structure of the brain itself makes it clear that these parts do not connect to the nerves, but are completely surrounded by those areas of the brain that do not feel, and are so separated from the nerves that they cannot receive any movement from them. Thus, it follows that this second assumption is just as unfounded as the first."[96]
What, then, asks Buffon, is the use of the brain? Man, the quadrupeds, and birds all have larger brains, and at the same time more extended perceptions, than fishes, insects, and those other living beings whose brains are smaller in proportion. "When the brain is compressed, there is suspension of all power of movement. If this part is not the source of our powers of motion, why is it so necessary and so essential? Why, again, does it seem so proportionate in each animal to the amount of perceiving power which that animal possesses?
What, then, asks Buffon, is the purpose of the brain? Humans, quadrupeds, and birds all have larger brains and, at the same time, more extensive perceptions than fish, insects, and other living beings with smaller brains in proportion. "When the brain is compressed, all movement ability is halted. If this part isn't the source of our ability to move, why is it so necessary and essential? And why does it appear to be proportionate in each animal to the level of perception that animal has?"
"I think I can answer this question in a satisfactory[Pg 134] manner, difficult though it seems; but in order that I may do so, I would ask the reader to lend me his attention for a few moments while we regard the brain simply as brain, and have no other idea concerning it than we can derive from inspection and reflection. The brain, as well as the medulla oblongata and the spinal marrow, which are but prolongations of the brain itself, is only a kind of hardly organized mucilage; we find in it nothing but the extremities of small arteries, which run into it in very great numbers, but which convey a white and nourishing lymph instead of blood. When the parts of the brain are disunited by maceration, these same small arteries, or lymphatic vessels, appear as very delicate threads throughout their whole length. The nerves, on the contrary, do not penetrate the substance of the brain; they abut upon its surface only; before reaching it they lose their elasticity and solidity, and the extremities of the nerves which are nearest to the brain are soft, and nearly mucilaginous. From this exposition, in which there is nothing hypothetical, it appears that the brain, which is nourished by the lymphatic arteries, does in its turn provide nourishment for the nerves, and that we must regard these as a kind of vegetation which rises as trunks and branches from the brain, and become subsequently subdivided into an infinite number, as it were, of twigs. The brain is to the nerves what the earth is to plants: the last extremities of the nerves are the roots, which with every vegetable are more soft and tender than the trunk or branches; they contain a ductile matter fit for the growth and nourishment of the nervous tree or fibre;[Pg 135] they draw the ductile matter from the substance of the brain itself, to which the arteries are continually bringing the lymph that is necessary to supply it. The brain, then, instead of being the seat of the sensations, and the originator of perception, is an organ of secretion and nutrition only, though a very essential organ, without which the nerves could neither grow nor be maintained.
"I think I can answer this question in a satisfying[Pg 134] way, even though it seems challenging; but to do so, I’d like the reader to take a moment to focus on the brain as brain, without any other ideas aside from what we can observe and reflect upon. The brain, along with the medulla oblongata and the spinal cord, which are extensions of the brain itself, is essentially just a kind of poorly organized gel. Inside, we find only the ends of small arteries that enter it in huge numbers, carrying a white, nourishing fluid instead of blood. When the parts of the brain are separated by decay, these same small arteries, or lymphatic vessels, show up as very fine threads throughout. In contrast, the nerves do not invade the brain’s substance; they only connect to its surface. Before reaching the brain, they lose their elasticity and firmness, and the tips of the nerves closest to the brain are soft and nearly gel-like. From this straightforward explanation, it's clear that the brain, nourished by the lymphatic arteries, in turn nourishes the nerves, which we should think of as a kind of plant growth that branches out from the brain and subsequently divides into countless smaller twigs. The brain is to the nerves what the earth is to plants: the very tips of the nerves are the roots, which, like all plants, are softer and more delicate than the trunk or branches. They contain a flexible substance that is essential for the growth and sustenance of the nervous tree or fiber;[Pg 135] they draw this flexible material from the brain itself, to which the arteries constantly supply the necessary lymph. So, the brain is not the center of sensations or the source of perception; it is solely an organ of secretion and nourishment, albeit a vital one, without which the nerves could neither develop nor survive."
"This organ is greater in man, in quadrupeds, and in birds, because the number or bulk of the nerves is greater in these animals than in fishes or insects, whose power of perception is more feeble, for this very reason, that they have but a small brain; one, in fact, that is proportioned to the small quantity of nerves which that brain must support. Nor can I omit to state here that man has not, as has been pretended by some, a larger brain than has any other animal; for there are apes and cetacea which have more brain than man in proportion to the volume of their bodies—another fact which proves that the brain is neither the seat of sensations nor the originator of perception, since in that case these animals would have more sensations and perception than man.
"This organ is larger in humans, in four-legged animals, and in birds because the number or size of the nerves is greater in these species than in fish or insects, whose ability to perceive is weaker, largely because they have smaller brains; in fact, their brains are sized according to the limited number of nerves that they need to support. I should also point out that humans do not have a larger brain than any other animal, as some have claimed; there are apes and whales that have more brain tissue than humans do relative to their body size—another fact that demonstrates that the brain is not the center of sensations nor the source of perception, or else those animals would possess more sensations and perception than humans do."
"If we consider the manner in which plants derive their nourishment, we shall find that they do not draw up the grosser parts either of earth or water; these parts must be reduced by warmth into subtle vapours before the roots can suck them up into the plant. In like manner the nutrition of the nerves is only effected by means of the more subtle parts of the humidity of the brain, which are sucked up by the roots or extremities[Pg 136] of the nerves, and are carried thence through all the branches of the sensory system. This system forms, as we have said, a whole, all whose parts are interconnected by so close a union that we cannot wound one without communicating a violent shock to all the others; the wounding or simply pulling of the smallest nerve is sufficient to cause lively irritation to all the others, and to put the body in convulsion; nor can we ease this pain and convulsion except by cutting the nerve higher up than the injured part; but on this all the parts abutting on this nerve become thenceforward senseless and immovable for ever. The brain should not be considered as of the same character, nor as an organic portion of the nervous system, for it has not the same properties nor the same substance, being neither solid nor elastic, nor yet capable of feeling. I admit that on its compression perception ceases, but this very fact shows it to be a body foreign to the nervous system itself, which, acting by its weight, or pressure, against the extremities of the nerves, oppresses them and stupefies them in the same way as a weight placed upon the arm, leg, or any other part of the body, stupefies the nerves and deadens the perceptions of that part. And it is evident that this cessation of sensation on compression is but a suspension and temporary stupefaction, for the moment the compression of the brain ceases, perception and the power of movement returns. Again, I admit that on tearing the medullary substance, and on wounding the brain till the corpus callosum is reached, convulsion, loss of sensation, and death ensue; but this is because the nerves are so entirely deranged that they[Pg 137] are, so to speak, torn up by the roots and wounded all together, and at their source.
"If we look at how plants get their nourishment, we’ll see that they don’t take in the coarser parts of earth or water directly; instead, these materials need to be heated to turn into fine vapors before the roots can absorb them. Similarly, the nutrition of the nerves only happens through the finer parts of the moisture in the brain, which are drawn in by the ends of the nerves and then transported throughout the entire sensory system. This system is, as we’ve said, a whole, where all the parts are so closely linked that if one is injured, it sends a shock throughout all the others; even the smallest nerve being hurt can cause a painful reaction in all the others and lead the body into convulsions. The only way to alleviate this pain and convulsion is by cutting the nerve higher up from the injury, but this will render all the parts connected to that nerve senseless and immovable from then on. The brain shouldn’t be seen as the same type of structure or as a part of the nervous system, because it has different properties and composition, neither solid nor elastic, and it's not capable of feeling. I acknowledge that if it’s compressed, sensation stops, but this fact shows it to be something separate from the nervous system; when it exerts pressure on the ends of the nerves, it oppresses and dulls them just like a weight on an arm, leg, or any other part of the body dulls the nerves and blunts sensations there. It's clear that this loss of sensation due to compression is only a temporary state, because once the pressure on the brain stops, sensation and movement return. Additionally, I agree that if the medullary substance is torn or the brain is injured to the point of reaching the corpus callosum, convulsions, loss of sensation, and death can happen; this occurs because the nerves are so completely disrupted that they are, in a sense, uprooted and injured all at once, right from their source."
"In further proof that the brain is neither the centre of perception nor the seat of the sensations, I may remind the reader that animals and even children have been born without heads and brains, and have yet had feeling, movement, and life. There are also whole classes of animals, like insects and worms, with a brain that is by no means a distinct mass nor of sensible volume, but with only something which corresponds with the medulla oblongata and the spinal marrow. There would be more reason, then, in placing the seat of the feelings and perceptions in the spinal marrow, which no animal is without, than in the brain which is not an organ common to all creatures that can feel."
"In further proof that the brain is neither the center of perception nor the source of sensations, I want to remind readers that animals and even children have been born without heads and brains, yet they still experienced feeling, movement, and life. There are also entire groups of animals, like insects and worms, that have a brain which is not a distinct mass or noticeable size, but only something similar to the medulla oblongata and the spinal cord. So, it would make more sense to place the source of feelings and perceptions in the spinal cord, which all animals have, rather than in the brain, which is not an organ common to all beings that can feel."
If Buffon's ideas concerning the brain are as just as they appear to be, the resemblance between plants and animals is more close than is apparent, even to a superficial observer, on a first inspection of the phenomena. Such an observer, however, on looking but a little more intently, will see the higher vertebrata as perambulating vegetables planted upside down. So the man who had been born blind, on being made to see, and on looking at the objects before him with unsophisticated eyes, said without hesitation that he saw "men as trees walking," thus seeing with more prophetic insight than either he or the bystanders could interpret. For our skull is as a kind of flower-pot, and holds the soil from which we spring, that is to say the brain; our mouth and stomach are roots, in two stories or stages; our bones are the trellis-work to which we cling while going about in[Pg 138] search of sustenance for our roots; or they are as the woody trunk of a tree; we are the nerves which are rooted in the brain, and which draw thence the sustenance which is supplied it by the stomach; our lungs are leaves which are folded up within us, as the blossom of a fig is hidden within the fruit itself.
If Buffon's ideas about the brain are as accurate as they seem, the similarity between plants and animals is closer than it first appears, even to someone casually observing the phenomena. However, if that observer looks a little more closely, they will see higher vertebrates as upside-down plants moving around. Similarly, the man who was born blind, upon gaining sight and looking at the objects in front of him with innocent eyes, said without hesitation that he saw "men as trees walking," revealing a deeper understanding than he or the onlookers could fully grasp. Our skull acts like a flower pot, holding the soil from which we grow, which is the brain; our mouth and stomach are like roots, in two levels or stages; our bones serve as the framework we rely on while searching for nutrients for our roots; they resemble the sturdy trunk of a tree; we are the nerves rooted in the brain, drawing nourishment supplied by the stomach; our lungs are like leaves folded inside us, just as the blossom of a fig is hidden within the fruit itself.
This is what should follow if Buffon's theory of the brain is allowed to stand, which I hope will prove to be the case, for it is the only comfortable thought concerning the brain that I have met with in any writer. I have given it here at some length on account of its importance, and for the illustration it affords of Buffon's hatred of mystery, rather than for its bearing upon evolution. The fact that our leading men of science have adopted other theories will weigh little with those who have watched scientific orthodoxy with any closeness. What Buffon thought of that orthodoxy may be gathered from the following:—
This is what should happen if Buffon's theory of the brain is accepted, which I hope will be the case since it's the only reassuring idea about the brain I've encountered from any writer. I've detailed it here at some length because of its significance and the insight it provides into Buffon's disdain for mystery, rather than its relevance to evolution. The fact that our prominent scientists have embraced other theories won’t matter much to those who have observed scientific norms closely. What Buffon thought of that orthodoxy can be understood from the following:—
"The greatest obstacles to the advancement of human knowledge lie less in things themselves than in man's manner of considering them. However complicated a machine the human body may be, it is still less complicated than are our own ideas concerning it. It is less difficult to see Nature as she is, than as she is presented to us. She carries a veil only, while we would put a mask over her face; we load her with our own prejudices, and suppose her to act and to conduct her operations even after the same fashion as ourselves.[97]
"The biggest barriers to the growth of human knowledge are more about how we think about things than the things themselves. No matter how complex the human body is, our ideas about it are even more complicated. It’s easier to see Nature for what she is than how we choose to interpret her. She only wears a veil, while we want to cover her face with a mask; we burden her with our own biases and expect her to behave and operate just like we do.[97]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"I am by no means speaking of those purely arbitrary[Pg 139] systems which we are able at a glance to detect as chimeras that are being pretended to us as realities, but I refer to the methods whereby people have set themselves seriously to study nature. Even the experimental method itself has been more fertile of error than of truth, for though it is indeed the surest, yet is it no surer than the hand of him who uses it. No matter how little we incline out of the straight path, we soon find ourselves wandering in a sterile wilderness, where we can see but a few obscure objects scattered sparsely; nevertheless we do violence to these facts and to ourselves, and resemble them together on a conceit of analogies and common properties amongst them. Then, passing and repassing complaisantly over the tortuous path which we have ourselves beaten, we deem the road a worn one, and though it leads no whither, the world follows it, adopts it, and accepts its supposed consequences as first principles. I could show this by laying bare the origin of that which goes by the name of 'principle' in all the sciences, whether abstract or natural. In the case of the former, the basis of principle is abstraction—that is to say, one or more suppositions: in that of the second, principles are but the consequences, better or worse, of the methods which may have been followed. And to speak here of anatomy only, did not he who first surmounted his natural repugnance and set himself to work to open a human body—did he not believe that through going all over it, dissecting it, dividing it into all its parts, he would soon learn its structure, mechanism, and functions? But he found the task greater than he had expected, and[Pg 140] renouncing such pretensions, was fain to content himself with a method—not for seeing and judging, but for seeing after an orderly fashion. This method ... is still the sole business of our ablest anatomists, but it is not science. It is the road which should lead scienceward, and might perhaps have reached science itself, if instead of walking ever on a single narrow path men had set the anatomy of man and that of animals face to face with one another. For, what real knowledge can be drawn from an isolated pursuit? Is not the foundation of all science seen to consist in the comparison which the human mind can draw between different objects in the matter of their resemblances and differences—of their analogous or conflicting properties, and of all the relations in which they stand to one another? The absolute, if it exist at all, is but of the concurrence of man's own knowledge; we judge and can judge of things only by their bearings one upon another; hence whenever a method limits us to only a single subject, whenever we consider it in its solitude and without regard to its resemblances or to its differences from other objects, we can attain to no real knowledge, nor yet, much less, reach any general principle. We do but give names, and make descriptions of a thing, and of all its parts. Hence comes it that, after three thousand years of dissection, anatomy is still but a nomenclature, and has hardly advanced a step towards its true object, which is the science of animal economy. Furthermore, what defects are there not in the method itself, which should above all things else be simple and easy to be understood, depending as it does upon inspection and[Pg 141] having denominations only for its end! For seeing that nomenclature has been mistaken for knowledge, men have made it their chief business to multiply names, instead of limiting things; they have crushed themselves under the burden of details, and been on the look out for differences where there was no distinction. When they had given a new name they conceived of it as a new thing, and described the smallest parts with the most minutious exactness, while the description of some still smaller part, forgotten or neglected by previous anatomists, has been straightway hailed as a discovery. The denominations themselves being often taken from things which had no relation to the object that it was desired to denominate, have served but to confound confusion. The part of the brain, for example, which is called testes and nates, wherein does it so differ from the rest of the brain that it should deserve a name? These names, taken at haphazard or springing from some preconceived opinion, have themselves become the parents of new prejudices and speculations; other names given to parts which have been ill observed, or which are even non-existent, have been sources of new errors. What functions and uses has it not been attempted to foist upon the pineal gland, and on the alleged empty space in the brain which is called the arch, the first of which is but a gland, while the very existence of the other is doubtful,—the empty space being perhaps produced by the hand of the anatomist and the method of dissection."[98]
"I’m not talking about those purely arbitrary[Pg 139] systems that we can easily identify as illusions being presented to us as truths. Instead, I’m referring to the ways in which people have seriously tried to study nature. Even the experimental method has produced more errors than truths, because while it is indeed the most reliable, it’s only as reliable as the person using it. No matter how slightly we stray from the straight path, we quickly find ourselves lost in a barren wilderness, where only a few indistinct objects are scattered around. Still, we distort these facts and ourselves, forcing them together based on a notion of analogies and shared properties. Then, as we repeatedly travel over the winding path we've made for ourselves, we come to believe it is a well-traveled road, and even though it leads nowhere, the world follows it, embraces it, and accepts its supposed results as fundamental truths. I could demonstrate this by uncovering the origin of what is called 'principle' in all sciences, both abstract and natural. In the case of the former, the basis of principle is abstraction—that is, one or more assumptions; in the case of the latter, principles are simply the better or worse outcomes of the methods that may have been used. Speaking only of anatomy, did not the first person who overcame his natural aversion and set out to open a human body believe that by thoroughly examining it, dissecting it, and dividing it into parts, he would soon understand its structure, function, and mechanisms? However, he discovered that the task was more complex than he anticipated, and[Pg 140] abandoning such pretensions, he settled for a method—not for observing and judging, but for observing in a systematic way. This method... remains the primary focus of our leading anatomists, but it isn’t science. It is a pathway that should lead to science and could perhaps have reached it if instead of sticking to a narrow approach, people had compared human anatomy with that of animals. For what real understanding can come from studying something in isolation? Isn’t the foundation of all science based on the comparisons the human mind can make between different objects regarding their similarities and differences—their analogous or conflicting properties, and all the relationships they have with one another? The absolute, if it exists at all, is merely a product of human understanding; we can only evaluate things based on how they relate to one another. Therefore, whenever a method confines us to a single subject, examining it in isolation without considering its similarities or differences to other objects, we cannot gain real knowledge, much less achieve any general principle. We merely assign names and create descriptions for a thing and all its parts. This is why, after three thousand years of dissection, anatomy remains just a naming system and has hardly progressed towards its true goal, which is the science of animal function. Moreover, what flaws exist in the method itself, which should be simple and easy to understand, as it relies on observation and[Pg 141] only aims for naming? Since nomenclature has been mistaken for knowledge, people have focused on creating more names instead of clarifying concepts; they have burdened themselves with unnecessary details and searched for differences where none exist. When they assigned a new name, they thought it referred to a new discovery and described even the smallest components with painstaking accuracy, while the description of some even smaller part, previously overlooked or ignored by past anatomists, was immediately celebrated as a breakthrough. The names themselves are often drawn from unrelated concepts, contributing to further confusion. For example, the part of the brain called testes and nates—how does it really differ from the rest of the brain to warrant its own name? These names, chosen randomly or based on preconceived ideas, have led to new biases and speculations; other names given to poorly observed or even nonexistent parts have resulted in new mistakes. What functions and roles have been ascribed to the pineal gland and the supposed empty space in the brain known as the arch, the first of which is just a gland, while the second’s existence is uncertain—the empty space possibly created by the anatomist’s hand and the dissection method?"
The Genus felis.
The genus Felis.
In his preliminary remarks upon the lion, Buffon while still professing to believe in some considerable mutability of species, seems very far from admitting that all living forms are capable of modification. But he has shown us long since how clearly he saw the impossibility of limiting mutability, if he once admitted so much of the thin end of the wedge as that a horse and an ass might be related. It is plain, therefore, that he is not speaking "au réel" here, and we accordingly find him talking clap-trap about the nobleness of the lion in having no species immediately allied to it. A few lines lower on he reminds us in a casual way that the ass and horse are related.
In his initial comments about the lion, Buffon, while still claiming to believe in some significant changes in species, seems quite far from accepting that all living forms can be modified. However, he clearly showed us long ago that he understood the impossibility of limiting change if he conceded even a little bit that a horse and a donkey might be related. It’s obvious, then, that he isn’t speaking "au réel" here, and instead, we find him making empty statements about the nobleness of the lion because it has no species closely related to it. A few lines later, he casually reminds us that the donkey and horse are indeed related.
He writes:—
He writes:—
"Added to all these noble individual features the lion has also what may be called a specific nobility. For I call those species noble which are constant, invariable, and which are above suspicion of having degenerated. These species are commonly isolated, and the only ones of their genus. They are distinguished by such well-marked features that they cannot be mistaken, nor confounded with any other species. To begin for example with man, the noblest of created beings; he is but of a single species, inasmuch as men and women will breed freely inter se in spite of all existing differences of race, climate and colour; and also inasmuch as there is no other animal which can claim either a distant or near relationship with him. The horse, on the other hand, is more noble as an individual than as a species,[Pg 143] for he has the ass as his near neighbour, and seems himself to be nearly enough related to it; ... the dog is perhaps of even less noble species, approaching as he does to the wolf, fox, and jackal, which we can only consider to be the degenerated species of a single family"[99]—all which may seem very natural opinions for a French aristocrat in the days before the Revolution, but which cannot for a moment be believed to have been Buffon's own. I have not ascertained the date of Buffon's little quarrel with the Sorbonne, but I cannot doubt that if we knew the inner history of the work we are considering, we should find this passage and others like it explained by the necessity of quieting orthodox adversaries. He concludes the paragraph from which I have just been quoting by saying, "To class man and the ape together, or the lion with the cat, and to say that the lion is a cat with a mane and a long tail—this were to degrade and disfigure nature instead of describing her and denominating her species." Buffon very rarely uses italics, but those last given are his, not mine; could words be better chosen to make us see the lion and the cat as members of the same genus? No wonder the Sorbonne considered him an infelicitous writer; why could he not have said "cat," and have done with it, instead of giving a couple of sly but telling touches, which make the cat as like a lion as possible, and then telling us that we must not call her one? Sorbonnes never do like people who write in this way.
"Along with all these noble individual traits, the lion also has what can be called a specific nobility. I define noble species as those that are constant, unchanging, and beyond suspicion of having degenerated. These species are usually isolated and are the only ones in their genus. They have such distinct features that they cannot be confused with any other species. For example, take humans, the noblest of all created beings; they belong to a single species since men and women can breed freely inter se despite all existing differences in race, climate, and color. Additionally, there’s no other animal that can claim a close or distant relationship with humans. The horse, on the other hand, is more noble as an individual than as a species,[Pg 143] because it has the donkey as a close relative, and it seems to be closely related to it; ... the dog is perhaps an even less noble species, as it is related to the wolf, fox, and jackal, which we can only consider as degenerated species from a single family"[99]—all of which might seem like natural opinions for a French aristocrat before the Revolution, but they cannot possibly reflect Buffon's own views. I haven't confirmed the date of Buffon's small dispute with the Sorbonne, but I have no doubt that if we knew the deeper story behind the work we are discussing, we would find this passage and others like it explained by the need to appease orthodox opposition. He finishes the paragraph I've just quoted by stating, "To group man with the ape, or the lion with the cat, and to claim that the lion is a cat with a mane and a long tail—that would degrade and distort nature instead of accurately describing her and naming her species." Buffon rarely uses italics, but those last ones are his, not mine; could words be better selected to help us see the lion and the cat as part of the same genus? It’s no surprise the Sorbonne viewed him as an unfortunate writer; why couldn't he have simply said "cat," and left it at that, instead of subtly suggesting how similar a cat is to a lion and then insisting we shouldn’t call her one? The Sorbonne never likes people who write this way.
"The lion, then, belongs to a most noble species, standing as he does alone, and incapable of being confounded[Pg 144] with the tiger, leopard, ounce, &c., while, on the contrary, those species, which appear to be least distant from the lion, are very sufficiently indistinguishable, so that travellers and nomenclators are continually confounding them."[100]
"The lion is part of a truly noble species, standing out on its own and can't be mistaken[Pg 144] for the tiger, leopard, ounce, etc. On the other hand, those species that seem most similar to the lion are often not easily distinguishable, leading travelers and those who name species to frequently confuse them." [100]
If this is not pure malice, never was a writer more persistently unfortunate in little ways. Why remind us here that the species which come nearest to the lion are so hard to distinguish? Why not have said nothing about it? As it is, the case stands thus: we are required to admit close resemblance between the leopard and the tiger, while we are to deny it between the tiger and the lion, in spite of there being no greater outward difference between the first than between the second pair, and in spite of the hurried whisper "cat with a mane and a long tail" still haunting our ears. Isidore Geoffroy and his followers may consent to this arrangement, but I hope the majority of my readers will not do so.
If this isn’t pure malice, then no writer has ever been as consistently unfortunate in small ways. Why bring up here that the species closest to the lion are so hard to tell apart? Why not just say nothing about it? As it stands, we have to accept a close resemblance between the leopard and the tiger while denying it between the tiger and the lion, even though there’s no bigger outward difference between the first pair than between the second, and even with the hasty whisper "cat with a mane and a long tail" still echoing in our ears. Isidore Geoffroy and his supporters might go along with this arrangement, but I hope most of my readers won’t.
I went on to the account of the tiger with some interest to see the line which Buffon would take concerning it. I anticipated that we should find cats, pumas, lynxes, &c., to be really very like tigers, and was surprised to learn that the "true" tiger, though certainly not unlike these animals, was still to be distinguished from "many others which had since been called tigers." He is on no account to be confounded with these, in spite of the obvious temptation to confound him. He is "a rare animal, little known to the ancients, and badly described by the moderns." He is[Pg 145] a beast "of great ferocity, of terrible swiftness, and surpassing even the proportions of the lion." The effect of the description is that we no longer find the lion standing alone, but with the tiger on a par with him if not above him; but at the same time we fall easy victims to the temptation to confound the tiger with "the many other animals which are also called tigers." A surface stream has swept the members of the cat family in different directions, but a stealthy undercurrent has seized them from beneath, and they are now happily reunited.
I approached the section about the tiger with curiosity to see Buffon's perspective on it. I expected to find that cats, pumas, lynxes, etc., would closely resemble tigers, and I was surprised to discover that the "true" tiger, while certainly similar to these animals, should still be distinguished from "many others that have since been labeled tigers." It's important not to confuse him with these others, despite the obvious temptation to do so. He is "a rare animal, little known to the ancients, and poorly described by moderns." He is[Pg 145] a creature "of great ferocity, tremendous speed, and exceeding even the size of the lion." The impact of this description is that we no longer see the lion in isolation but instead view the tiger as an equal, if not superior. However, we still easily fall into the trap of confusing the tiger with "the many other animals that are also called tigers." A surface stream has carried the members of the cat family in different directions, but a hidden undercurrent has pulled them back together, and they are now happily reunited.
Animals of the Old and New World—Changed Geographical Distribution.
Animals of the Old and New World—Altered Geographic Distribution.
Writing upon the animals of the old world,[101] and referring to the humps of the camel and the bison, Buffon shows that very considerable modification may be effected in some animals within even a few generations, but he attributes the effect produced to the direct influence of climate. Buffon concludes his sketch of the animals of the new world by pointing out that the larger animals of the African torrid zone have been hindered by sea and desert from finding their way to America, and by claiming to be the first "even to have suspected" that there was not a single denizen of the torrid zone of one continent which was common also to the other.[102]
Writing about the animals of the old world,[101] and mentioning the humps of the camel and the bison, Buffon demonstrates that significant changes can occur in some animals within just a few generations, but he believes that these changes are primarily due to the direct impact of climate. Buffon wraps up his overview of the animals of the new world by pointing out that the larger animals in the African tropical zone have been blocked by the sea and desert from reaching America, and he asserts that he is the first to "even suspect" that there isn't a single inhabitant of the tropical zone on one continent that is also found on the other.[102]
The animals common to both continents are those which can stand the cold and which are generally suited for a temperate climate. These, Buffon believes, to[Pg 146] have travelled either over some land still unknown, or "more probably," over territory which has long since been submerged. The species of the old and new world are never without some well-marked difference, which however should not be held sufficient for us to refuse to admit their practical identity. But he maintains, I imagine wilfully, that there is a tendency in all the mammalia to become smaller on being transported to the new world, and refers the fact to the quality of the earth, the condition of the climate, the degrees of heat and humidity, to the height of mountains, amounts of running or stagnant waters, extent of forest, and above all to the brutal condition of nature in a new country, which he evidently regards with true aristocratic abhorrence.[103]
The animals found on both continents are those that can handle the cold and generally thrive in a temperate climate. Buffon believes they either migrated over some unknown land or, "more likely," over areas that have long been underwater. The species from the old and new worlds always show distinct differences, but that shouldn't lead us to deny their practical similarities. However, he insists—probably in a stubborn way—that there's a trend among mammals to become smaller when they arrive in the new world, attributing this to soil quality, climate conditions, temperature and humidity levels, mountain heights, the presence of flowing or stagnant waters, the extent of forests, and especially to the harshness of nature in a new land, which he clearly views with a sense of aristocratic disdain.[103]
Then follows a passage which I had better perhaps give in full:—
Then follows a section that I might as well give word for word:—
The mammoth "was certainly the greatest and strongest of all quadrupeds; but it has disappeared; and if so, how many smaller, feebler, and less remarkable species must have also perished without leaving us any traces or even hints of their having existed? How many other species have changed their nature, that is to say, become perfected or degraded, through great changes in the distribution of land and ocean, through the cultivation or neglect of the country which they inhabit, through the long-continued effects of climatic changes, so that they are no longer the same animals that they once were? Yet of all living beings after[Pg 147] man, the quadrupeds are the ones whose nature is most fixed and form most constant: birds and fishes vary much more easily; insects still more again than these, and if we descend to plants, which certainly cannot be excluded from animated nature, we shall be surprised at the readiness with which species are seen to vary, and at the ease with which they change their forms and adopt new natures.
The mammoth was definitely the biggest and strongest of all four-legged animals; but it has gone extinct, and if that’s the case, how many smaller, weaker, and less impressive species must have also disappeared without leaving any evidence or even signs that they ever existed? How many other species have changed in their nature, meaning they have either evolved or declined, due to major shifts in land and ocean distribution, the cultivation or neglect of their habitats, or the long-term effects of climate changes, making them no longer the same animals they once were? Yet among all living beings after[Pg 147] humans, quadrupeds have the most stable nature and consistent form: birds and fish change much more easily; insects change even more than those, and when we look at plants, which definitely belong to the natural world, we are surprised at how readily species vary, and how easily they change their forms and take on new characteristics.
"It is probable then that all the animals of the new world are derived from congeners in the old, without any deviation from the ordinary course of nature. We may believe that having become separated in the lapse of ages, by vast oceans and countries which they could not traverse, they have gradually been affected by, and derived impressions from, a climate which has itself been modified so as to become a new one through the operation of those same causes which dissociated the individuals of the old and new world from one another; thus in the course of time they have grown smaller and changed their characters. This, however, should not prevent our classifying them as different species now, for the difference is no less real whether it is caused by time, climate and soil, or whether it dates from the creation. Nature I maintain is in a state of continual flux and movement. It is enough for man if he can grasp her as she is in his own time, and throw but a glance or two upon the past and future, so as to try and perceive what she may have been in former times and what one day she may attain to."[104]
"It’s likely that all the animals in the new world come from similar species in the old world, without any break from the normal order of nature. We can assume that after being separated over countless ages by vast oceans and lands they couldn’t cross, they gradually adapted to and were influenced by a climate that itself changed into something new due to the same forces that kept the old and new worlds apart; thus, over time, they have become smaller and altered their traits. However, this shouldn’t stop us from classifying them as different species now, because the difference is just as real whether it’s due to time, climate, and soil, or if it goes back to the moment of creation. I argue that nature is always changing and evolving. It’s enough for humans if we can understand it as it is in our own time and take a moment to look back and forward to get a sense of what it might have been in the past and what it may become one day."[104]
The Buffalo—Animals under Domestication.
The Buffalo—Animals in Domestication.
"The bison and the aurochs," says Buffon, "differ only in unessential characteristics, and are, by consequence, of the same species as our domestic cattle, so that I believe all the pretended species of the ox, whether ancient or modern, may be reduced to three—the bull, the buffalo, and the bubalus.
"The bison and the aurochs," Buffon says, "differ only in minor traits, and are, therefore, the same species as our domestic cattle. I believe that all the supposed species of oxen, whether from ancient times or modern, can be categorized into three: the bull, the buffalo, and the bubalus."
"The case of animals under domestication is in many respects different from that of wild ones; they vary much more in disposition, size and shape, especially as regards the exterior parts of their bodies: the effects of climate, so powerful throughout nature, act with far greater effect upon captive animals than upon wild ones. Food prepared by man, and often ill chosen, combined with the inclemency of an uncongenial climate—these eventuate in modifications sufficiently profound to become constant and hereditary in successive generations. I do not pretend to say that this general cause of modification is so powerful as to change radically the nature of beings which have had their impress stamped upon them in that surest of moulds—heredity; but it nevertheless changes them in not a few respects; it masks and transforms their outward appearance; it suppresses some of their parts, and gives them new ones; it paints them with various colours, and by its action on bodily habits influences also their natures, instincts, and most inward qualities" (and what is this but "radically changing their nature"?). "The modification of but a single part, moreover, in a whole as perfect as an animal body, will necessitate a correlative[Pg 149] modification in every other part, and it is from this cause that our domestic animals differ almost as much in nature and instinct, as in form, from those from which they originally sprung."[105]
"The situation with domesticated animals is quite different from that of wild animals in many ways; they show a much wider range in behavior, size, and shape, particularly concerning the external features of their bodies. The effects of climate, which are significant throughout nature, have a much stronger impact on domesticated animals than on wild ones. Man-made food, often poorly chosen, combined with an unsuitable climate, leads to changes that are deep enough to become permanent and passed down through generations. I'm not claiming that this general cause of change is strong enough to radically alter the essence of beings shaped by the most reliable factor—heredity; however, it does change them in many ways. It conceals and changes their outward appearance; it removes some parts and introduces new ones; it colors them in various hues, and through its influence on physical habits, it also affects their natures, instincts, and most intrinsic traits (isn't that just "radically changing their nature"?). "Altering just one part in a completely formed system like an animal's body will require a corresponding [Pg 149] change in all other parts, which is why our domestic animals vary almost as much in nature and instinct as they do in shape from their wild ancestors." [105]
Buffon confirms this last assertion by quoting the sheep as an example—an animal which can now no longer exist in a wild state. Then returning to cattle, he repeats that many varieties have been formed by the effects—"diverse in themselves, and diverse in their combinations—of climate, food, and treatment, whether under domestication or in their wild state." These are the main causes of variation ("causes générales de variété"),[106] among our domesticated animals, but by far the greatest is changed climate in consequence of their accompanying man in his migrations. The effects of the foregoing causes of modification, especially the last of them, are repeatedly insisted on in the course of the forty pages which complete the preliminary account of the buffalo.
Buffon backs up this last point by using sheep as an example—an animal that can no longer live in the wild. He then goes back to cattle and emphasizes that many breeds have developed due to the effects—"varied in themselves, and in their combinations—of climate, food, and treatment, whether domesticated or in the wild." These are the main causes of variation (“causes générales de variété”),[106] among our domesticated animals, but by far the biggest factor is the change in climate due to their moving with humans during migrations. The impact of these modifying factors, especially the last one, is repeatedly highlighted over the forty pages that provide the introductory account of the buffalo.
What holds good for the buffalo does so also for the mouflon or wild sheep. This, Buffon declares to be the source of all our domesticated breeds: of these there are in all some four or five, "all of them being but degenerations from a single stock, produced by man's agency, and propagated for his convenience."[107] At the same time that man has protected them he has hunted out the original race which was "less useful to him,"[108] so that it is now to be found only in a few secluded spots, such as the mountains of Greece, Cyprus, and Sardinia.[Pg 150] Buffon does not consider even the differences between sheep and goats to be sufficiently characteristic to warrant their being classed as different species.
What applies to the buffalo also applies to the mouflon or wild sheep. Buffon states that this is the source of all our domesticated breeds; there are about four or five of them, "all of them being just variations from a single stock, created by human intervention, and bred for his convenience."[107] While humans have protected these animals, they have hunted the original breed which was "less useful to him,"[108] so now it can only be found in a few remote areas, like the mountains of Greece, Cyprus, and Sardinia.[Pg 150] Buffon does not even see the differences between sheep and goats as significant enough to classify them as different species.
"I shall never tire," he continues, "of repeating—seeing how important the matter is—that we must not form our opinions concerning nature, nor differentiate (différencier) her species, by a reference to minor special characteristics. And, again, that systems, far from having illustrated the history of animals, have, on the contrary, served rather to obscure it ... leading, as they do, to the creation of arbitrary species which nature knows nothing about; perpetually confounding real and hypothetical existences; giving us false ideas as to the very essence of species; uniting them and separating them without foundation or knowledge, and often without our having seen the animal with which we are dealing."[109]
"I will never get tired," he continues, "of saying—especially since this is such an important issue—that we shouldn't form our opinions about nature, or classify her species, based on minor special traits. Moreover, systems have not illuminated the history of animals; rather, they have obscured it... leading to the creation of arbitrary species that nature doesn’t recognize; constantly mixing up real and hypothetical existences; giving us misleading ideas about the true nature of species; categorizing them and separating them without any real foundation or understanding, and often without having even observed the animal in question."[109]
First and Second Views of Nature.
First and Second Views of Nature.
The twelfth volume begins with a preface, entitled "A First View of Nature," from which I take the following:—
The twelfth volume starts with a preface called "A First Look at Nature," from which I take the following:—
"What cannot Nature effect with such means at her disposal? She can do all except either create matter or destroy it. These two extremes of power the deity has reserved for himself only; creation and destruction are the attributes of his omnipotence. To alter and undo, to develop and to renew—these are powers which he has handed over to the charge of Nature."[110]
"What can’t Nature achieve with all the resources at her disposal? She can do everything except create matter or destroy it. These two extremes of power are reserved for the deity alone; creation and destruction are the signs of his all-powerful nature. To change and undo, to grow and renew—these are powers that he has entrusted to Nature." [110]
The thirteenth volume opens with a second view of nature. After describing what a man would have observed[Pg 151] if he could have lived during many continuous ages, Buffon goes on to say:—
The thirteenth volume starts with another perspective on nature. After explaining what a person would have seen[Pg 151] if they could have lived through many successive ages, Buffon continues:—
"And as the number, sustenance, and balance of power among species is constant, Nature would present ever the same appearance, and would be in all times and under all climates absolutely and relatively the same, if it were not her fashion to vary her individual forms as much as possible. The type of each species is founded in a mould of which the principal features have been cut in characters that are ineffaceable and eternally permanent, but all the accessory touches vary; no one individual is the exact facsimile of any other, and no species exists without a large number of varieties. In the human race on which the divine seal has been set most firmly, there are yet varieties of black and white, large and small races, the Patagonian, Hottentot, European, American, Negro, which, though all descended from a common father, nevertheless exhibit no very brotherly resemblance to one another."[111]
"And since the number, sustenance, and balance of power among species remain constant, Nature would always look the same and would be absolutely and relatively identical in all times and climates if it weren’t for her tendency to vary individual forms as much as possible. The type of each species is based on a mold with key features that are carved in an indelible and eternally permanent way, but all the additional details change; no individual is an exact replica of another, and no species exists without many varieties. In the human race, which bears the strongest divine seal, there are still varieties like black and white, large and small races, including the Patagonian, Hottentot, European, American, and Negro, which, despite all descending from a common ancestor, do not show much resemblance to one another." [111]
On an earlier page there is a passage which I may quote as showing Buffon to have not been without some—though very imperfect—perception of the fact which evidently made so deep an impression upon his successor, Dr. Erasmus Darwin. I refer to that continuity of life in successive generations, and that oneness of personality between parents and offspring, which is the only key that will make the phenomena of heredity intelligible.
On an earlier page, there's a section that I can quote to show that Buffon had some—although very limited—understanding of the idea that clearly had a profound impact on his successor, Dr. Erasmus Darwin. I'm talking about the continuity of life across generations and the connection between parents and their children, which is the only key that can make the phenomena of heredity understandable.
"Man," he says, "and especially educated man, is no longer a single individual, but represents no small[Pg 152] part of the human race in its entirety. He was the first to receive from his fathers the knowledge which their own ancestors had handed down to them. These, having discovered the divine art of fixing their thoughts so that they can transmit them to their posterity, become, as it were, one and the same people with their descendants (se sont, pour ainsi dire, identifiés avec leur neveux); while our descendants will in their turn be one and the same people with ourselves (s'identifieront avec nous). This reunion in a single person of the experience of many ages, throws back the boundaries of man's existence to the utmost limits of the past; he is no longer a single individual, limited as other beings are to the sensations and experiences of to-day. In place of the individual we have to deal, as it were, with the whole species."[112]
"Man," he says, "and especially educated man, is no longer just one individual; he represents a significant part of the entire human race. He was the first to inherit knowledge from his ancestors, who had passed it down through generations. Those ancestors, having mastered the divine skill of organizing their thoughts to share them with future generations, essentially become one with their descendants; meanwhile, our descendants will, in turn, become one with us. This merging of the experiences from many ages into a single person extends the boundaries of human existence back to the farthest reaches of the past. He is no longer just an individual, limited like other beings to the sensations and experiences of today. Instead of just dealing with a single person, we are engaging with the entire species."
"Differences in exterior are nothing in comparison with those in interior parts. These last must be regarded as the causes, while the others are but the effects. The interior parts of living beings are the foundation of the plan of their design; this is their essential form, their real shape, their exterior is only the surface, or rather the drapery in which their true figure is enveloped. How often does not the study of comparative anatomy show us that two exteriors which differ widely conceal interiors absolutely like each other, and, on the contrary, that the smallest internal difference is accompanied by the most marked differences of outward appearance, changing as it does even the natural habits, faculties and attributes of the animal?"[113]
"Differences in appearance are minor compared to those in internal features. The latter should be seen as the root causes, while the former are just the results. The internal structures of living beings are the foundation of their design; this is their true form, their actual shape, while the exterior is merely the surface or the wrapping that covers their real appearance. How often does the study of comparative anatomy reveal that two beings with vastly different exteriors can have interiors that are essentially identical? Conversely, even the smallest internal difference can result in significant outward variations, which can alter their natural behaviors, abilities, and characteristics."[113]
Apes and Monkeys.
Apes and Monkeys.
The fourteenth volume is devoted to apes and monkeys, and to the chapter with which the volumes on quadrupeds are brought to a conclusion—a chapter for which perhaps the most important position in the whole work is thus assigned. It is very long, and is headed "On Descent with Modification" ("De la Dégénération des Animaux"). This is the chapter in which Buffon enters more fully into the "causes or means" of the transformation of species.
The fourteenth volume focuses on apes and monkeys, along with the chapter that concludes the volumes on quadrupeds—a chapter that arguably holds the most significant place in the entire work. It is quite lengthy and titled "On Descent with Modification" ("De la Dégénération des Animaux"). This is the chapter where Buffon delves deeper into the "causes or means" of species transformation.
At the opening of the chapter on the nomenclature of monkeys, the theory is broached that there is a certain fixed amount of life-substance as of matter in nature; and that neither can be either augmented or diminished. Buffon maintains this organic and living substance to be as real and durable as inanimate matter; as permanent in its state of life as the other in that of death; it is spread over the whole of nature, and passes from vegetables to animals by way of nutrition, and from animals back to vegetables through putrefaction, thus circulating incessantly to the animation of all that lives.
At the start of the chapter on monkey naming, the idea is introduced that there is a fixed amount of life substance, just like there is with matter in nature; neither can be increased or decreased. Buffon argues that this organic and living substance is just as real and lasting as inanimate matter; it remains alive just as permanently as inanimate matter is in a state of death. It is distributed throughout nature, moving from plants to animals through nutrition and then from animals back to plants through decay, constantly circulating to fuel all living things.
As might be expected, Buffon is loud in his protest against any real similarity between man and the apes—man has had the spirit of the Deity breathed into his nostrils, and the lowest creature with this is higher than the highest without it. Having settled this point, he makes it his business to show how little difference in other respects there is between the apes and man.
As you might expect, Buffon strongly argues against any real resemblance between humans and apes—humans have the spirit of the Deity breathed into them, and even the lowest creature with this is higher than the highest creature without it. Once he establishes this point, he sets out to demonstrate how little difference there is in other respects between apes and humans.
"One who could view," he writes, "Nature in her[Pg 154] entirety, from first to last, and then reflect upon the manner in which these two substances—the living and the inanimate—act and react upon one another, would see that every living being is a mould which casts into its own shape those substances upon which it feeds; that it is this assimilation which constitutes the growth of the body, whose development is not simply an augmentation of volume, but an extension in all its dimensions, a penetration of new matter into all parts of its mass: he would see that these parts augment proportionately with the whole, and the whole proportionately with these parts, while general configuration remains the same until the full development is accomplished.... He would see that man, the quadruped, the cetacean, the bird, reptile, insect, tree, plant, herb, all are nourished, grow, and reproduce themselves on this same system, and that though their manner of feeding and of reproducing themselves may appear so different, this is only because the general and common cause upon which these operations depend can only operate in the individual agreeably with the form of each species. Travelling onward (for it has taken the human mind ages to arrive at these great truths, from which all others are derived), he would compare living forms, give them names to distinguish them, and other names to connect them with each other. Taking his own body as the model with which all living forms should be compared, and having measured them, explained them thoroughly, and compared them in all their parts, he would see that there is but small difference between the forms of living beings; that by dissecting the ape he could arrive at[Pg 155] the anatomy of man, and that taking some other animal we find always the same ultimate plan of organization, the same senses, the same viscera, the same bones, the same flesh, the same movements of the fluids, the same play and action of the solids; he would find all of them with a heart, veins, arteries, in all the same organs of circulation, respiration, digestion, nutrition, secretion; in all of them a solid frame, composed of pieces put together in nearly the same manner; and he would find this system always the same, from man to the ape, from the ape to the quadrupeds, from the quadrupeds to the cetacea, birds, fishes, reptiles; this system or plan then, I say, if firmly laid hold of and comprehended by the human mind, is a true copy of nature; it is the simplest and most general point of view from which we can consider her, and if we extend our view, and go on from what lives to what vegetates, we may see this plan—which originally did but vary almost imperceptibly—change its scope and descend gradually from reptiles to insects, from insects to worms, from worms to zoophytes, from zoophytes to plants, and yet keeping ever the same fundamental unity in spite of differences of detail, insomuch that nutrition, development, and reproduction remain the common traits of all organic bodies; traits eternally essential and divinely implanted; which time, far from effacing or destroying, does but make plainer and plainer continually."
"One who could see," he writes, "Nature in her[Pg 154] entirety, from beginning to end, and then think about how these two substances—the living and the non-living—interact with each other, would realize that every living being shapes the substances it consumes into its own form; that this process of assimilation is what leads to the growth of the body, which isn’t just an increase in size but an expansion in all its dimensions, a penetration of new matter throughout its entire structure: he would see that these parts grow in proportion to the whole, and the whole grows in proportion to these parts, while the overall shape stays constant until full development is reached.... He would see that humans, quadrupeds, cetaceans, birds, reptiles, insects, trees, plants, and herbs all are nourished, grow, and reproduce following this same system, and that while their feeding and reproduction methods may seem very different, this is only due to the underlying general cause affecting them individually in accordance with the characteristics of each species. Moving forward (since it has taken humanity ages to grasp these great truths, from which all others are built), he would compare living forms, label them to distinguish them, and use other names to relate them to each other. Using his own body as the standard for comparing all living forms, and after having measured, fully explained, and compared them in all their components, he would find that there is very little difference among the forms of living beings; that by dissecting an ape, he could understand[Pg 155] the anatomy of a human, and that examining any other animal would reveal the same underlying organizational structure, the same senses, the same internal organs, the same bones, the same flesh, the same movements of fluids, the same interactions of solids; he would find all of them equipped with a heart, veins, arteries, and the same organs for circulation, respiration, digestion, nutrition, and secretion; all possessing a solid framework, constructed from components assembled in nearly the same way; and he would see this system consistently replicated, from humans to apes, from apes to quadrupeds, and from quadrupeds to cetaceans, birds, fish, reptiles; this system or plan, I assert, if understood and embraced by the human mind, is a genuine reflection of nature; it represents the simplest and most universal perspective from which we can observe her, and if we broaden our view and move from the realm of the living to that of the vegetation, we can observe this plan—which initially varied almost imperceptibly—gradually shifting and descending from reptiles to insects, from insects to worms, from worms to zoophytes, from zoophytes to plants, while still maintaining the same essential unity despite the differences in details, ensuring that nutrition, development, and reproduction remain the common traits of all organic bodies; traits that are eternally essential and divinely instilled; which time, far from erasing or destroying, only brings into clearer focus."
This is the writer who can see nothing in common between the horse and the zebra except that each has a solid hoof.[114] He continues:—
This is the writer who sees nothing shared between the horse and the zebra except that both have solid hooves.[114] He goes on:—
"If from this grand tableau of resemblances, in [Pg 156]which the living universe presents itself to our eyes as though it were a single family, we pass to a tableau rather of the differences between living forms, we shall see that, with the exception of some of the greater species, such as the elephant, rhinoceros, hippopotamus, tiger, lion, which must each have their separate place, the other races seem all to blend with neighbouring forms, and to fall into groups of likenesses, greater or lesser, and of genera which our nomenclators represent to us by a network of shapes, of which some are held together by the feet, others by the teeth, horns, and skin, and others by points of still minor importance. And even those whose form strikes us as most perfect, as approaching most nearly to our own—even the apes—require some attention before they can be distinguished from one another, for the privilege of being an isolated species has been assigned less to form than to size; and man himself, though of a separate species and differing infinitely from all or any others, has but a medium size, and is less isolated and has nearer neighbours than have the greater animals. If we study the Orang-outang with regard only to his configuration, we might regard him, with equal justice, as either the highest of the apes or as the lowest of mankind, because, with the exception of the soul, he wants nothing of what we have ourselves, and because, as regards his body, he differs less from man than he does from other animals which are still called apes."[115]
"If we look at this grand picture of similarities, in [Pg 156]where the living universe appears as a single family, and then shift to examining the differences among living forms, we’ll notice that, aside from a few large species like the elephant, rhinoceros, hippopotamus, tiger, and lion, which each require their distinct classification, the other species tend to blend with nearby forms and group into varying degrees of similarity. Our classification systems represent these connections with a web of shapes, some linked by feet, others by teeth, horns, and skin, and some by less significant features. Even those forms we see as most perfect, closest to our own—including apes—demand some attention to tell them apart; the distinction of being a separate species hinges more on size than on form. Even humans, despite being a unique species vastly different from all others, have an average size and are less isolated, having closer relatives than the larger animals. If we examine the orangutan based solely on its structure, we could justly consider it either the highest of the apes or the lowest of humans, as it lacks only a soul compared to what we possess, and in terms of its body, it differs less from humans than from other creatures still referred to as apes."[115]
The want of a soul Buffon maintains to be the only essential difference between the Orang-outang and[Pg 157] man—"his body, limbs, senses, brain and tongue are the same as ours. He can execute whatever movements man can execute; yet he can neither think nor speak, nor do any action of a distinctly human character. Is this merely through want of training? or may it not be through wrong comparison on our own parts? We compare the wild ape in the woods to the civilized citizen of our great towns. No wonder the ape shows to disadvantage. He should be compared with the hideous Hottentot rather, who is himself almost as much above the lowest man, as the lowest man is above the Orang-outang."[116]
The lack of a soul is what Buffon claims to be the only real difference between the orangutan and man—"his body, limbs, senses, brain, and tongue are the same as ours. He can perform any movements that humans can perform; yet he cannot think or speak, nor perform any actions that are distinctly human. Is this simply due to a lack of training? Or could it be because we are making a flawed comparison? We compare the wild ape in the forest to the refined citizen of our large cities. It's no surprise that the ape comes off poorly in this comparison. He should rather be compared to the unattractive Hottentot, who is himself almost as much above the lowest human as the lowest human is above the orangutan."[116]
The passage is a much stronger one than I have thought it fit to quote. The reader can refer to it for himself. After reading it I entertain no further doubt that Buffon intended to convey the impression that men and apes are descended from common ancestors. He was not, however, going to avow this conclusion openly.
The passage is much stronger than I thought it was worth quoting. The reader can check it out for themselves. After reading it, I have no doubt that Buffon wanted to suggest that men and apes share common ancestors. However, he wasn't going to state this conclusion outright.
"I admit," he continues, "that if we go by mere structure the ape might be taken for a variety of the human race; the Creator did not choose to model mankind upon an entirely distinct system from the other animals: He comprised their form and man's under a plan which is in the main uniform."[117] Buffon then dwells upon the possession of a soul by man; "even the lowest creature," he avers, "which had this, would have become man's rival."
"I admit," he continues, "that if we look at just the physical form, the ape could be seen as a kind of human. The Creator didn’t design humans to be completely different from other animals: He included their shape and ours in a mostly consistent plan." [117] Buffon then discusses the idea that humans have a soul; "even the simplest creature," he claims, "that had this would have become a competitor with man."
"The ape then is purely an animal, far from being a variety of our own species, he does not even come first in[Pg 158] the order of animals, since he is not the most intelligent: the high opinion which men have of the intelligence of apes is a prejudice based only upon the resemblance between their outward appearance and our own."[118] But the undiscerning were not only to be kept quiet, they were to be made happy. With this end, if I am not much mistaken, Buffon brings his chapter on the nomenclature of apes to the following conclusion:—
"The ape is just an animal; it's not even a variation of our species, nor does it rank first among animals because it isn't the smartest. The high regard that people have for the intelligence of apes is just a bias based on the similarity of their appearance to ours.[Pg 158] But it wasn't enough to simply quiet the unknowing; they also needed to be made happy. To this end, if I'm not mistaken, Buffon concludes his chapter on ape nomenclature with the following:"
"The ape, which the philosopher and the uneducated have alike regarded as difficult to define, and as being at best equivocal, and midway between man and the lower animals, proves in fact to be an animal and nothing more; he is masked externally in the shape of man, but internally he is found incapable of thought, and of all that constitutes man; apes are below several of the other animals in respect of qualities corresponding to their own, and differ essentially from man, in nature, temperament, the time which must be spent upon their gestation and education, in their period of growth, duration of life, and in fact in all those profounder habits which constitute what is called the 'nature' of any individual existence."[119] This is handsome, and leaves the more timorous reader in full possession of the field.
"The ape, which both philosophers and the uneducated alike find hard to define and see as ambiguous, and as being somewhere between humans and lower animals, is actually just an animal and nothing more. Externally, it appears similar to a human, but internally, it lacks the capacity for thought and everything that defines humanity. Apes fall short compared to several other animals in terms of qualities that relate to their kind, and they fundamentally differ from humans in nature, temperament, the time needed for gestation and upbringing, growth periods, lifespan, and in all those deeper habits that determine what is known as the 'nature' of any individual existence."[119] This is attractive, and allows the more cautious reader full control of the discussion.
Buffon is accordingly at liberty in the following chapter to bring together every fact he can lay his hands on which may point the resemblance between man and the Orang-outang most strongly; but he is careful to use inverted commas here much more freely than is his wont. Having thus made out a strong case for the near affinity between man and the Orang-outang,[Pg 159] and having thrown the responsibility on the original authors of the passages he quotes, he excuses himself for having quoted them on the ground that "everything may seem important in the history of a brute which resembles man so nearly," and then insists upon the points of difference between the Orang-outang and ourselves. They do not, however, in Buffon's hands come to much, until the end of the chapter, when, after a résumé dwelling on the points of resemblance, the differences are again emphatically declared to have the best of it.
Buffon is free in the following chapter to gather every fact he can find that highlights the similarities between humans and the Orangutan; however, he is careful to use quotation marks here more often than usual. After making a strong case for the close relationship between humans and the Orangutan,[Pg 159] and placing the responsibility on the original authors of the quotes, he justifies his quotes by stating that "everything may seem important in the history of an animal that resembles man so closely," and then emphasizes the differences between the Orangutan and us. However, in Buffon’s analysis, these differences don’t amount to much until the end of the chapter, when, after a summary focusing on the similarities, he strongly reiterates that the differences ultimately prevail.
I need not follow Buffon through his description of the remaining monkeys. It comprises 250 pp., and is confined to details with which we have no concern; but the last chapter—"De la Dégénération des Animaux"—deserves much fuller quotation than my space will allow me to make from it. The chapter is very long, comprising, as I have said, over sixty quarto pages. It is impossible, therefore, for me to give more than an outline of its contents.
I don’t need to go through Buffon’s description of the other monkeys. It’s 250 pages long and focuses on details that aren’t relevant to us; however, the last chapter—"On the Degeneration of Animals"—deserves a lot more attention than I can give it here. The chapter is quite lengthy, spanning over sixty pages. Therefore, I can only provide a brief overview of its content.
Causes or Means of the Transformation of Species.
Causes or Means of the Transformation of Species.
The human race is declared to be the one most capable of modification, all its different varieties being descended from a common stock, and owing their more superficial differences to changes of climate, while their profounder ones, such as woolly hair, flat noses, and thick lips, are due to differences of diet, which again will vary with the nature of the country inhabited by any race. Changes will be exceedingly gradual; it will take centuries of unbroken habit to bring about modifications which can[Pg 160] be transmitted with certainty so as to eventuate in national characteristics.[120] It is a pleasure to find that here, too, habit is assigned as the main cause which underlies heredity.
The human race is considered the most capable of change, with all its various types coming from a shared origin. Their obvious differences arise from climate changes, while deeper differences, like curly hair, flat noses, and thick lips, result from dietary variations, which depend on the type of environment each race inhabits. Changes will happen very slowly; it will take centuries of consistent habits to create modifications that can[Pg 160] be reliably passed down to develop national characteristics.[120] It's encouraging to see that habit is recognized as the primary factor influencing heredity.
Modification will be much prompter with animals. When compelled to abandon their native land, they undergo such rapid and profound modification, that at first sight they can hardly be recognized as the same race, and cannot be detected in their disguise till after the most careful inspection, and on grounds of analogy only. Domestication will produce still more surprising results; the stigmata of their captivity, the marks of their chains, can be seen upon all those animals which man has enslaved; the older and more confirmed the servitude, the deeper will be its scars, until at length it will be found impossible to rehabilitate the creature and restore to it its lost attributes.
Modification will happen much faster with animals. When forced to leave their natural habitat, they change so quickly and deeply that at first glance, they can barely be recognized as the same species, and it's only through careful examination and similarities that you can identify them in disguise. Domestication leads to even more astonishing changes; the signs of their captivity, the marks of their chains, are visible on all the animals that humans have enslaved; the longer and more established the captivity, the deeper the scars will be, until eventually, it becomes impossible to restore the creature and return its lost traits.
"Temperature of climate, quality of food, and the ills of slavery—here are the three main causes of the alteration and degeneration of animals. The consequences of each of these should be particularly considered, so that by examining Nature as she is to-day we may thus perceive what she was in her original condition."[121]
"Climate temperature, food quality, and the issues of slavery—these are the three main causes of changes and decline in animals. Each of these consequences should be closely examined, so that by looking at Nature as it is today, we can understand what it was like in its original state."[121]
I have more than once admitted that there is a wide difference between this opinion, which assigns modification to the direct influence of climate, food, and other changed conditions of life, and that of Dr. Erasmus Darwin, which assigns only an indirect effect to these, while the direct effect is given to changed actions in[Pg 161] consequence of changed desires; but it is surprising how nearly Buffon has approached the later and truer theory, which may perhaps have been suggested to Dr. Darwin by the following pregnant passage—as pregnant, probably, to Buffon himself as to another:—
I’ve admitted more than once that there’s a big difference between this opinion, which says that climate, food, and other changes in lifestyle directly influence things, and Dr. Erasmus Darwin’s view, which claims these factors only have an indirect effect while direct effects come from changes in behavior due to new desires; it’s surprising how closely Buffon has come to the later and more accurate theory, which Dr. Darwin might have been inspired by in the following significant passage—likely just as significant to Buffon himself as it is to others:—
"The camel is the animal which seems to me to have felt the weight of slavery most profoundly. He is born with wens upon his back and callosities upon his knees and chest; these callosities are the unmistakable results of rubbing, for they are full of pus and of corrupted blood. The camel never walks without carrying a heavy burden, and the pressure of this has hindered, for generations, the free extension and uniform growth of the muscular parts of the back; whenever he reposes or sleeps his driver compels him to do so upon his folded legs, so that little by little this position becomes habitual with him. All the weight of his body bears, during several hours of the day continuously, upon his chest and knees, so that the skin of these parts, pressed and rubbed against the earth, loses its hair, becomes bruised, hardened, and disorganized.
"The camel is the animal that seems to me to have experienced the harshest burden of slavery. He is born with lumps on his back and thickened skin on his knees and chest; these thickened areas are clear signs of continuous wear, as they are filled with pus and infected blood. The camel never walks without carrying a heavy load, and this pressure has prevented, for generations, the free expansion and even growth of the muscles in his back; whenever he rests or sleeps, his handler forces him to do so on his folded legs, making this position gradually become his habit. For several hours each day, the weight of his body presses continuously on his chest and knees, causing the skin in these areas, pressed against the ground, to lose its hair, become bruised, hardened, and damaged."
"The llama, which like the camel passes its life beneath burdens, and also reposes only by resting its weight upon its chest, has similar callosities, which again are perpetuated in successive generations. Baboons, and pouched monkeys, whose ordinary position is a sitting one, whether waking or sleeping, have callosities under the region of the haunches, and this hard skin has even become inseparable from the bone against which it is being continually pressed by the weight of the body; in the case, however, of these animals the[Pg 162] callosities are dry and healthy, for they do not come from the constraint of trammels, nor from the burden of a foreign weight, but are the effects only of the natural habits of the animal, which cause it to continue longer seated than in any other position. There are callosities of these pouched monkeys which resemble the double sole of skin which we have ourselves under our feet; this sole is a natural hardness which our continued habit of walking or standing upright will make thicker or thinner according to the greater or less degree of friction to which we subject our feet."[122]
"The llama, like the camel, lives carrying loads and only rests by putting its weight on its chest. It also has calluses that are passed down through generations. Baboons and pouch monkeys, which usually sit whether they're awake or asleep, have calluses under their haunches. This tough skin has even fused with the bone underneath it due to the continuous pressure from their body weight. In these animals, however, the calluses are dry and healthy because they result from their natural sitting habits rather than from constraints or carrying external weight. There are calluses on these pouch monkeys that are similar to the thickened skin we have on the soles of our feet; this hardness develops naturally from our constant habit of walking or standing upright and can become thicker or thinner based on how much friction our feet experience."
This involves the whole theory of Dr. Darwin.
This includes the entire theory of Dr. Darwin.
Wild animals would not change either their food or climate if left to themselves, and in this case they would not vary, but either man or some other enemies have harassed most of them into migrations; "those whose nature was sufficiently flexible to lend itself to the new situation spread far and wide, while others have had no resource but the deserts in the neighbourhood of their own countries."[123]
Wild animals wouldn’t change their food or environment if they were left alone, and in that case, they wouldn’t adapt. However, humans or other threats have pushed most of them to migrate; those that were adaptable enough to handle the new circumstances spread out, while others had no choice but to retreat to nearby deserts.[123]
Since food and climate, and still less man's empire over them, can have but little effect upon wild animals, Buffon refers their principal varieties in great measure to their sexual habits, variations being much less frequent among animals that pair and breed slowly, than among those which do not mate and breed more freely. After running rapidly over several animals, and discussing the flexibility or inflexibility of their organizations, he declares the elephant to be the only one on which a state of domestication has produced[Pg 163] no effect, inasmuch as "it refuses to breed under confinement, and cannot therefore transmit the badges of its servitude to its descendants."[124]
Since food and climate, and even less so humanity's control over them, have little impact on wild animals, Buffon attributes their main varieties largely to their mating habits. Changes are much less common among animals that mate and reproduce slowly than among those that mate and reproduce more freely. After briefly examining several animals and discussing how flexible or rigid their bodies are, he concludes that the elephant is the only animal for which domestication has had no effect, as it "refuses to breed in captivity and therefore cannot pass on the marks of its servitude to its offspring."[Pg 163][124]
Here is an example of Buffon's covert manner, in the way he maintains that descent with modification may account not only for specific but for generic differences.
Here is an example of Buffon's subtle approach, in the way he claims that descent with modification can explain not just specific but also general differences.
"But after having taken a rapid survey of the varieties which indicate to us the alterations that each species has undergone, there arises a broader and more important question, how far, namely, species themselves can change—how far there has been an older degeneration, immemorial from all antiquity, which has taken place in every family, or, if the term is preferred, in all the genera under which those species are comprehended which neighbour one another without presenting points of any very profound dissimilarity? We have only a few isolated species, such as man, which form at once the species and the whole genus; the elephant, the rhinoceros, the hippopotamus, and the giraffe form genera, or simple species, which go down in a single line, with no collateral branches. All other races appear to form families, in which we may perceive a common source or stock from which the different branches seem to have sprung in greater or less numbers according as the individuals of each species are smaller and more fecund."[125]
"But after quickly looking over the different types that show us the changes each species has gone through, a bigger and more significant question comes up: how much can species themselves change? How far back does an ancient degeneration go, one that has happened in every family, or if we prefer the term, in all the genera that include species living close to one another without showing major differences? We only have a few isolated species, like humans, which represent both the species and the entire genus; elephants, rhinoceroses, hippos, and giraffes form genera or simple species that follow a single line with no side branches. All other types seem to form families, in which we can see a common origin or stock from which different branches appear to have evolved, in greater or fewer numbers, depending on how small and more fertile the individuals of each species are."[125]
I can see no explanation of the introduction of this passage unless that it is intended to raise the question whether modification may be not only specific but generic, the point of the paragraph lying in the words[Pg 164] "dans chaque famille, ou si l'on veut, dans chacun des genres." We are told in the next paragraph, that if we choose to look at the matter in this light, well—in that case—we ought to see not only the ass and the horse, but the zebra too, as members of the same family; "the number of their points of resemblance being infinitely greater than those in respect of which they differ."[126] Thus, at the close of his work on the quadrupeds, he thinks it well, as at the commencement seventeen years earlier, to emphasize—in his own quiet way—his perception that the principles on which he has been insisting should be carried much farther than he has chosen to carry them.
I can't find any reason for the introduction of this passage unless it's meant to raise the question of whether modification can be not just specific but also generic, with the main point of the paragraph being the words[Pg 164] "in every family, or if you prefer, in each of the genres." In the next paragraph, we're told that if we decide to look at it this way, then—we should also see not only the donkey and the horse but the zebra too as part of the same family; "the number of their similarities being infinitely greater than the number of their differences."[126] Therefore, at the end of his work on quadrupeds, he finds it important, just like he did seventeen years earlier at the beginning, to quietly emphasize his belief that the principles he has been focusing on should go much further than he has chosen to explore.
His conclusion is, that "after comparing all the animals and bringing them each under their proper genus, we shall find the two hundred species we have already described to be reducible into a sufficiently small number of families or main stocks from which it is not impossible that all the others may be derived."[127]
His conclusion is that "after comparing all the animals and categorizing them into their appropriate genera, we will discover that the two hundred species we have already described can be grouped into a manageable number of families or main categories, from which it’s likely that all the others may have originated."[127]
The chapter closes thus:—
The chapter ends like this:—
"To account for the origin of these animals" (certain of those peculiar to America), "we must go back to the time when the two continents were not yet separated, and call to mind the earliest geological changes. At the same time, we must consider the two hundred existing species of quadrupeds as reduced to thirty-eight families. And though this is not at all the state of Nature as she is in our time, and as she has been represented in this volume, and though, in fact, it is a condition which we can only arrive at by induction,[Pg 165] and by analogies almost as difficult to lay hold of as is the time which has effaced the greater number of their traces, I shall, nevertheless, endeavour to ascend to these first ages of Nature by the aid of facts and monuments which yet remain to us, and to represent the epochs which these facts seem to indicate."[128]
"To understand where these animals come from" (specifically those unique to America), "we need to look back to when the two continents were still connected and remember the earliest geological changes. We also have to think about the two hundred species of mammals that exist today, which can be grouped into thirty-eight families. While this doesn’t reflect the current state of Nature, as depicted in this book, and even though it’s a state we can only reach through reasoning,[Pg 165] and by drawing analogies that are almost as hard to grasp as the time that has erased most of the evidence, I will still try to explore these early ages of Nature using the facts and remnants that are still available to us, and to outline the periods that these facts seem to suggest."[128]
The fifteenth volume contains a description of a few more monkeys, as also of some animals which Buffon had never actually seen, a great part being devoted to indices.
The fifteenth volume includes descriptions of a few more monkeys, as well as some animals that Buffon had never actually seen, with a large portion dedicated to indices.
Supplement.
Extra.
The first four volumes of the Supplement to Buffon's 'Natural History,' 1774-1789, contain little which throws additional light upon his opinions concerning the mutability of species. At the beginning, however, of the fifth volume I find the following:—
The first four volumes of the Supplement to Buffon's 'Natural History,' 1774-1789, contain little that provides extra insight into his views on the mutability of species. However, at the start of the fifth volume, I find the following:—
"On comparing these ancient records of the first ages of life [fossils] with the productions of to-day, we see with sufficient clearness that the essential form has been preserved without alteration in its principal parts: there has been no change whatever in the general type of each species; the plan of the inner parts has been preserved without variation. However long a time we may imagine for the succession of ages, whatever number of generations we may suppose, the individuals of to-day present to us in each genus the same forms as they did in the earliest ages; and this is more especially true of the greater species, whose characters are more invariable and nature more fixed; for the inferior species[Pg 166] have, as we have said, experienced in a perceptible manner all the effects of different causes of degeneration. Only it should be remarked in regard to these greater species, such as the elephant and hippopotamus, that in comparing their fossil remains with the existing forms we find the earlier ones to have been larger. Nature was then in the full vigour of her youth, and the interior heat of the earth gave to her productions all the force and all the extent of which they were capable ... if there have been lost species, that is to say animals which existed once, but no longer do so, these can only have been animals which required a heat greater than that of our present torrid zone."[129]
"By comparing these ancient records from the early ages of life [fossils] with today's specimens, it's clear that the fundamental structure has remained unchanged in its main parts: there’s been no shift in the general type of each species; the design of the inner parts has remained consistent. Regardless of the time we might imagine for the progression of ages, or the number of generations we consider, today’s individuals in each genus show the same forms as they did in the earliest times; and this is especially true for the larger species, which exhibit more stable characteristics and nature. In contrast, the smaller species[Pg 166] have noticeably undergone various degeneration effects. It's worth noting that for these larger species, like the elephant and hippopotamus, when we compare their fossil remains with the current forms, we find that the earlier ones were larger. Nature was then in the peak of her youth, and the Earth's internal heat provided her creations with all the vitality and range they could achieve... If some species have gone extinct, meaning animals that once existed but no longer do, these must have been animals that needed a higher temperature than what our current tropical regions provide."[129]
The context proves Buffon to have been thinking of such huge creatures as the megatherium and mastodon, but his words seem to limit the extinction of species to the denizens of a hot climate which had turned colder. It is not at all likely that Buffon meant this, as the passage quoted at p. 146 of this work will suffice to show. The whole paragraph is ironical.
The context shows that Buffon was considering large animals like the megatherium and mastodon, but his words appear to restrict the extinction of species to those living in warmer climates that became colder. It's unlikely that Buffon intended this, as the excerpt referenced on p. 146 of this work demonstrates. The entire paragraph is ironic.
I can see nothing to justify the conclusion drawn from this passage by Isidore Geoffroy, that Buffon had modified his opinions, and was inclined to believe in a more limited mutability than he had done a few years earlier. His exoteric position is still identical with what it was in the outset, and his esoteric may be seen from the spirit which is hardly concealed under the following:—
I can see no reason to support Isidore Geoffroy's conclusion from this passage that Buffon had changed his views and was starting to believe in more limited change than he did a few years before. His public stance is still the same as it was at the beginning, and his private beliefs are evident in the underlying spirit of the following:—
"I shall be told that analogy points towards the belief that our own race has followed the same path,[Pg 167] and dates from the same period as other species; that it has spread itself even more widely than they; and that if man's creation has a later date than that of the other animals, nothing shows that he has not been subjected to the same laws of nature, the same alterations, and the same changes as they. We will grant that the human species does not differ essentially from others in the matter of bodily organs, and that, in respect of these, our lot has been much the same as that of other animals."[130]
"I’ll be told that analogy suggests our own species has followed a similar path,[Pg 167] and originated around the same time as other species; that it has spread even more widely than they have; and that even if humans were created later than other animals, there’s nothing to indicate that we haven’t been subject to the same laws of nature, the same changes, and the same transformations as they have. We can agree that the human species doesn’t fundamentally differ from others in terms of physical organs, and that, in these respects, our experiences have been much like those of other animals."[130]
Plants under Domestication.
Plants in Domestication.
"If more modern and even recent examples are required in order to prove man's power over the vegetable kingdom, it is only necessary to compare our vegetables, flowers, and fruits with the same species such as they were a hundred and fifty years ago; this can be done with much ease and certainty by running the eye over the great collection of coloured drawings begun in the time of Gaston of Orleans, and continued to the present day at the Jardin du Roi. We find with surprise that the finest flowers of that date, as the ranunculuses, pinks, tulips, bear's ears, &c., would be rejected now, I do not say by our florists, but by our village gardeners. These flowers, though then already cultivated, were still not far above their wild condition. They had a single row of petals only, long pistils, colours hard and false; they had little velvety texture, variety, or gradation of tints, and, in fact, presented all the characteristics of untamed nature. Of herbs there[Pg 168] was a single kind of endive, and two of lettuce—both bad—while we can now reckon more than fifty lettuces and endives, all excellent. We can even name the very recent dates of our best pippins and kernel fruits—all of them differing from those of our forefathers, which they resemble in name only. In most cases things remain while names change; here, on the contrary, it is the names that have been constant while the things have varied.[131]
"If we need more contemporary examples to showcase humanity's dominance over the plant kingdom, we just have to compare our vegetables, flowers, and fruits with the same species from a hundred and fifty years ago. This can be easily and accurately achieved by looking at the extensive collection of colored drawings started during the time of Gaston of Orleans and continued to the present day at the Jardin du Roi. We are surprised to find that the best flowers from that time, like ranunculus, pinks, tulips, and bear's ears, would today be dismissed, not just by our professional florists, but even by local gardeners. Although these flowers were already being cultivated back then, they were still quite close to their wild counterparts. They had only a single row of petals, long pistils, and colors that were harsh and artificial. They lacked velvety texture, variety, or subtle shades, and truly displayed all the traits of untamed nature. In terms of herbs, there was only one kind of endive and two types of lettuce—both of poor quality—while now we have more than fifty varieties of lettuces and endives, all excellent. We can even point to the recent origins of our best apple and nut varieties—each one different from those of our ancestors, which they only resemble in name. In most cases, things stay the same while names change; here, however, it's the names that have remained constant while the items have evolved.[131]"
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"It is not that every one of these good varieties did not arise from the same wild stock; but how many attempts has not man made on Nature before he succeeded in getting them. How many millions of germs has he not committed to the earth, before she has rewarded him by producing them? It was only by sowing, tending, and bringing to maturity an almost infinite number of plants of the same kind that he was able to recognize some individuals with fruits sweeter and better than others; and this first discovery, which itself involves so much care, would have remained for ever fruitless if he had not made a second, which required as much genius as the first required patience—I mean the art of grafting those precious individuals, which, unfortunately, cannot continue a line as noble as their own, nor themselves propagate their rare and admirable qualities? And this alone proves that these qualities are purely individual, and not specific, for the pips or stones of these excellent fruits bring forth the original wild stock, so that they do not form species[Pg 169] essentially different from this. Man, however, by means of grafting, produces what may be called secondary species, which he can propagate at will; for the bud or small branch which he engrafts upon the stock contains within itself the individual quality which cannot be transmitted by seed, but which needs only to be developed in order to bring forth the same fruits as the individual from which it was taken in order to be grafted on to the wild stock. The wild stock imparts none of its bad qualities to the bud, for it did not contribute to the forming thereof, being, as it were, a wet nurse, and no true mother.
"It’s not that all these varieties didn’t come from the same wild species; it’s just that how many attempts have humans made on Nature before they succeeded in cultivating them? How many millions of seeds have they planted in the earth before it rewarded them with these results? It was only by planting, caring for, and nurturing an almost endless number of the same type of plants that they were able to find some individuals with fruits that were sweeter and better than others. This initial discovery, which demanded a lot of care, would have been useless forever if they hadn’t made a second discovery, which required as much creativity as the first required patience—I mean the skill of grafting those precious individuals, which unfortunately cannot produce a lineage as noble as their own, nor propagate their rare and remarkable qualities. This alone shows that these qualities are purely individual and not specific because the seeds or pits of these excellent fruits yield the original wild stock, meaning they don’t form species that are essentially different from it. However, humans, through grafting, create what can be called secondary species, which they can propagate at will. The bud or small branch they graft onto the stock contains the individual quality that can’t be passed on by seed, but just needs to be nurtured to produce the same fruits as the individual from which it was taken to be grafted onto the wild stock. The wild stock doesn’t pass on any of its negative traits to the bud since it didn’t contribute to its formation, acting more like a wet nurse than a true mother."
"In the case of animals, the greater number of those features which appear individual, do not fail to be transmitted to offspring, in the same way as specific characters. It was easier then for man to produce an effect upon the natures of animals than of plants. The different breeds in each animal species are variations that have become constant and hereditary, while vegetable species on the other hand present no variations that can be depended on to be transmitted with certainty.
"In the case of animals, most of the individual traits are passed down to their offspring just like specific characteristics. It was therefore easier for humans to influence the nature of animals than that of plants. The different breeds within each animal species are stable and hereditary variations, whereas plant species do not show reliable variations that can be consistently inherited."
"In the species of the fowl and the pigeon alone, a large number of breeds have been formed quite recently, which are all constant, and in other species we daily improve breeds by crossing them. From time to time we acclimatize and domesticate some foreign and wild species. All these examples of modern times prove that man has but tardily discovered the extent of his own power, and that he is not even yet sufficiently aware of it. It depends entirely upon the exercise of his intelligence;[Pg 170] the more, therefore, he observes and cultivates nature the more means he will find of making her subservient to him, and of drawing new riches from her bosom without diminishing the treasures of her inexhaustible fecundity."[132]
"In just the fowl and pigeon species, a lot of new breeds have been created recently, all of which are stable, and we’re continually improving breeds of other species through crossbreeding. Occasionally, we also acclimatize and domesticate some foreign and wild species. All these modern examples show that humanity has only slowly realized the full extent of its own power and still isn’t fully aware of it. This realization relies completely on how we use our intelligence; the more we observe and cultivate nature, the more ways we’ll find to make her work for us and to extract new riches from her without depleting the vast resources of her endless fertility.[Pg 170][132]"
Birds.
Birds.
In the preface to his volumes upon birds, Buffon says that these are not only much more numerous than quadrupeds, but that they also exhibit a far larger number of varieties, and individual variations.
In the preface to his volumes on birds, Buffon states that there are not only many more species than quadrupeds, but also a much greater number of varieties and individual differences.
"The diversities," he declares, "which arise from the effects of climate and food, of domestication, captivity, transportation, voluntary and compulsory migration—all the causes in fact of alteration and degeneration—unite to throw difficulties in the way of the ornithologist."[133]
"The differences," he says, "that come from the impact of climate and diet, domestication, captivity, transportation, voluntary and forced migration—basically all the reasons for change and decline—combine to create challenges for the ornithologist."[133]
He points out the infinitely keener vision of birds than that of man and quadrupeds, and connects it with their habits and requirements.[134] He does not appear to consider it as caused by those requirements, though it is quite conceivable that he saw this, but thought he had already said enough. He repeatedly refers to the effects of changed climate and of domestication, but I find nothing in the first volume which modifies the position already taken by him in regard to descent with modification: it is needless, therefore, to repeat the few passages which are to be found bearing at all upon the subject. The chapter on the birds that cannot fly,[Pg 171] contains a sentence which seems to be the germ that has been developed, in the hands of Lamarck, into the comparison between nature and a tree. Buffon says that the chain of nature is not a single long chain, but is comparable rather to something woven, "which at certain intervals throws out a branch sideways that unites it with the strands of some other weft."[135] On the following page there is a passage which has been quoted as an example of Buffon's contempt for the men of science of his time. The writer maintains that the most lucid arrangement of birds, would have been to begin with those which most resembled quadrupeds. "The ostrich, which approaches the camel in the shape of its legs, and the porcupine in the quills with which its wings are armed, should have immediately followed the quadrupeds, but philosophy is often obliged to make a show of yielding to popular opinions, and the tribe of naturalists is both numerous and impatient of any disturbance of its methods. It would only, then, have regarded this arrangement as an unreasonable innovation caused by a desire to contradict and to be singular."[136]
He highlights that birds have a much sharper vision than humans and other four-legged animals, linking it to their behaviors and needs.[134] He doesn't seem to think that this sharper vision is a result of those needs, although it’s possible he realized this but felt he had already said enough. He often discusses the impacts of changing climate and domestication, but I don't see anything in the first volume that changes his previous stance on evolution through modification: so there's no need to repeat the few sections that touch on this topic. The chapter about flightless birds,[Pg 171] includes a line that seems to have inspired Lamarck's idea of comparing nature to a tree. Buffon states that the chain of nature isn't just one long chain, but is more like something woven, "which at certain intervals throws out a branch sideways that connects it with strands from another weave."[135] On the next page, there’s a passage often cited as an example of Buffon’s disdain for the scientists of his day. The author argues that the best way to arrange birds would have been to start with those that most closely resemble four-legged animals. "The ostrich, which resembles the camel in the shape of its legs, and the porcupine in the quills on its wings, should have gone right after the four-legged animals, but philosophy often has to pretend to bend to popular opinion, and the group of naturalists is both large and resistant to any changes in its methods. They would have viewed this arrangement as an unreasonable innovation born from a desire to be contrary and unique."[136]
It is, I believe, held not only by "le peuple des naturalistes," but by most sensible persons, that the proposed arrangement would not have been an improvement. I find, however, in the preface to the third volume on birds that M. Gueneau de Montbeillard described all the birds from the ostrich to the quail, so the foregoing passage is perhaps his and not Buffon's. If so, the imitation is fair, but when we reflect upon it[Pg 172] we feel uncertain whether it is or is not beneath Buffon's dignity.
I think most reasonable people, including “the people of naturalists,” agree that the proposed arrangement wouldn’t have been an improvement. However, I found in the preface to the third volume on birds that M. Gueneau de Montbeillard described all the birds from the ostrich to the quail, so the passage above might belong to him instead of Buffon. If that’s the case, the imitation is fitting, but when we think about it[Pg 172] we are left unsure whether it is beneath Buffon's dignity or not.
Here, as often with pictures and music, we cannot criticise justly without taking more into consideration than is actually before us. We feel almost inclined to say that if the passage is by Buffon it is probably right, and if by M. Gueneau de Montbeillard, probably wrong. It must also be remembered that, as we learn from the preface already referred to, Buffon was seized at this point in his work with a long and painful illness, which continued for two years; a single hasty passage in so great a writer may well be pardoned under such circumstances.
Here, just like with art and music, we can't fairly critique without considering more than what's right in front of us. We almost want to say that if the passage is by Buffon, it’s probably accurate, and if it’s by M. Gueneau de Montbeillard, it’s probably incorrect. It’s also important to remember that, as mentioned in the previously referenced preface, Buffon was dealing with a lengthy and painful illness at this point in his work, which lasted for two years; a single rushed passage from such a prominent writer can certainly be forgiven under those circumstances.
Looking through the third and remaining volumes on birds, the greater part of which was by Gueneau de Montbeillard, and bearing in mind that in point of date they are synchronous with some of those upon quadrupeds from which I have already extracted as much as my space will allow, and not seeing anything on a rapid survey which promises to throw new light upon the author's opinions, I forbear to quote further. I therefore leave Buffon with the hope that I have seen him more justly than some others have done, but with the certainty that the points I have caught and understood are few in comparison with those that I have missed.
Looking through the third and final volumes about birds, most of which was written by Gueneau de Montbeillard, and remembering that they were published around the same time as some of the works on mammals that I've already summarized as much as I could, I didn’t see anything that stands out on a quick look that would provide new insights into the author's views, so I’ll refrain from quoting more. I’ll therefore conclude with Buffon, hoping that I’ve understood him more accurately than some others have, but knowing that the aspects I’ve grasped and understood are few compared to those I’ve overlooked.
FOOTNOTES:
[66] Ibid.
Ibid.
[67] Ibid. p. 16.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 16.
[68] Tom. i. p. 21.
[69] Ibid. p. 23.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 23.
[70] Tom. ii. p. 9, 1749.
[71] Ibid. p. 10.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Ibid. p. 10.
[72] Tom. iv. p. 31, 1753.
[73] Tom. iv. p. 55.
[74] Tom. iv. p. 98, 1753.
[75] Ibid.
Ibid.
[77] Tom. iv. p. 102, 1760.
[78] Tom. iv. p. 103, 1753.
[80] Ibid. p. 184.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 184.
[82] Tom. v. p. 63, 1755.
[83] Ibid. p. 64.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 64.
[84] Tom. v. p. 103, 1755.
[85] Tom. v. p. 104, 1755.
[86] Tom. v. pp. 192-195, 1755.
[87] Tom. v. p. 195.
[88] Tom. v. pp. 196, 197.
[89] This passage would seem to be the one which has suggested the following to the author of 'The Vestiges of Creation':—
[89] This section seems to have inspired the writer of 'The Vestiges of Creation':—
"He [the Deity] has endowed the families which enjoy His bounty with an almost infinite fecundity, ... but the limitation of the results of this fecundity ... is accomplished in a befitting manner by His ordaining that certain other animals shall have endowments sure so to act as to bring the rest of animated beings to a proper balance" (p. 317, ed. 1853).
"He [the Deity] has blessed the families that benefit from His generosity with nearly limitless fertility, ... but the limitation of the outcomes of this fertility ... is appropriately achieved by His decree that certain other animals shall possess traits that ensure a proper balance among all living beings" (p. 317, ed. 1853).
[90] Tom. vi. p. 252, 1756.
[92] Tom. vii. p. 9, 1758.
[93] Tom. vii. p. 10, 1758.
[94] Tom. vii. p. 12, 1758.
[95] Tom. vii. p. 14, 1758
[96] Tom. vii. p. 15, 1758.
[97] Tom. vii. p. 19, 1758.
[99] Tom. ix. p. 10, 1761.
[100] Tom. ix. p. 11, 1761.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Tom. ix. p. 11, 1761.
[101] Tom. ix. p. 68, 1761.
[102] Ibid. p. 96, 1761.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same page, p. 96, 1761.
[104] Tom. ix. p. 127, 1761.
[106] Ibid. p. 296.
Ibid. p. 296.
[107] Ibid. p. 363.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 363.
[108] Ibid. p. 363.
Ibid. p. 363.
[109] Tom. xi. p. 370, 1764.
[111] Tom. xiii., preface, x. 1765.
[112] Tom. xiii., preface, iv. 1765.
[113] Ibid. xiii. p. 37.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 37.
[115] Tom. xiv. p. 30, 1766.
[116] Tom. xiv. p. 31, 1766.
[117] Ibid. p. 32, 1766.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Ibid. p. 32, 1766.
[118] Tom. xiv. p. 38, 1766.
[119] Ibid. p. 42, 1766.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 42, 1766.
[120] Tom. xiv. p. 316, 1766.
[121] Ibid. p. 317.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 317.
[122] Tom. xiv. p. 326, 1766.
[123] Ibid. p. 327.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same page, p. 327.
[124] Tom. xiv. p. 333.
[125] Ibid. p. 335, 1766.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 335, 1766.
[127] Tom. xiv. p. 358, 1766.
[128] Tom. xiv. p. 374, 1766.
[134] Ibid. pp. 9-11.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Ibid. pp. 9-11.
[136] Ibid. p. 396, 1771.
Ibid. p. 396, 1771.
SKETCH OF DR. ERASMUS DARWIN'S LIFE.
SKETCH OF DR. ERASMUS DARWIN'S LIFE.
Proceeding now to the second of the three founders of the theory of evolution, I find, from a memoir by Dr. Dowson, that Dr. Erasmus Darwin was born at Elston, near Newark, in Nottinghamshire, on the 12th of December, 1731, being the seventh child and fourth son of Robert Darwin, "a private gentleman, who had a taste for literature and science, which he endeavoured to impart to his sons. Erasmus received his early education at Chesterfield School, and later on was entered at St. John's College, Cambridge, where he obtained a scholarship of about 16l. a year, and distinguished himself by his poetical exercises, which he composed with uncommon facility. He took the degree of M.B. there in 1755, and afterwards prepared himself for the practice of medicine by attendance on the lectures of Dr. Hunter in London, and a course of studies in Edinburgh.
Now moving on to the second of the three founders of the theory of evolution, I learned from a memoir by Dr. Dowson that Dr. Erasmus Darwin was born in Elston, near Newark, in Nottinghamshire, on December 12, 1731. He was the seventh child and the fourth son of Robert Darwin, "a private gentleman who had a passion for literature and science, which he tried to share with his sons." Erasmus received his early education at Chesterfield School and later enrolled at St. John's College, Cambridge, where he got a scholarship worth about 16l. a year and stood out for his poetry, which he wrote with exceptional ease. He earned his M.B. degree there in 1755 and subsequently prepared for a medical career by attending Dr. Hunter's lectures in London and studying in Edinburgh.
"He first settled as a physician at Nottingham; but meeting with no success there, he removed in the autumn of 1756, his twenty-fifth year, to Lichfield, where he was more fortunate; for a few weeks after his arrival, to use the words of Miss Seward, 'he brilliantly opened his career of fame.' A young gentleman of family and fortune lay sick of a dangerous[Pg 174] fever. A physician who had for many years possessed the confidence of Lichfield and the neighbourhood attended, but at length pronounced the case hopeless, and took his leave. Dr. Darwin was then called in, and by 'a reverse and entirely novel kind of treatment' the patient recovered."[137]
"He first settled as a doctor in Nottingham, but didn’t find success there. In the autumn of 1756, at the age of twenty-five, he moved to Lichfield, where he had better luck; a few weeks after arriving, as Miss Seward put it, 'he brilliantly opened his career of fame.' A young man from a wealthy family was seriously ill with a dangerous fever. A doctor who had been trusted in Lichfield and the surrounding area attended to him, but eventually declared the case hopeless and left. Dr. Darwin was then called in, and with 'a reverse and entirely novel kind of treatment,' the patient recovered."
Of Dr. Darwin's personal appearance Miss Seward says:—
Of Dr. Darwin's personal appearance, Miss Seward says:—
"He was somewhat above the middle size; his form athletic, and inclined to corpulence; his limbs were too heavy for exact proportion; the traces of a severe smallpox disfigured features and a countenance which, when they were not animated by social pleasure, were rather saturnine than sprightly; a stoop in the shoulders, and the then professional appendage—a large full-bottomed wig—gave at that early period of life an appearance of nearly twice the years he bore. Florid health and the earnest of good humour, a funny smile on entering a room and on first accosting his friends, rendered in his youth that exterior agreeable, to which beauty and symmetry had not been propitious.
He was a bit taller than average; his build was athletic but leaning towards being overweight; his limbs were a bit too heavy for perfect proportion; the scars from a severe case of smallpox disfigured his features, and his expression, when not brightened by social enjoyment, was more gloomy than cheerful; he had a stoop in his shoulders, and the typical accessory of the time—a large full-bottomed wig—made him appear nearly twice his actual age at that early point in his life. Yet, his robust health and genuine sense of humor, along with a friendly smile when he entered a room and greeted his friends, made his youthful appearance appealing, despite the lack of conventional beauty and symmetry.
"He stammered extremely, but whatever he said, whether gravely or in jest, was always well worth waiting for, though the inevitable impression it made might not be always pleasant to individual self-love. Conscious of great native elevation above the general standard of intellect, he became early in life sore upon opposition, whether in argument or conduct, and always resented it by sarcasm of very keen edge. Nor was he less impatient of the sallies of egotism and vanity,[Pg 175] even when they were in so slight a degree that strict politeness would rather tolerate than ridicule them. Dr. Darwin seldom failed to present their caricature in jocose but wounding irony. If these ingredients of colloquial despotism were discernible in unworn existence, they increased as it advanced, fed by an ever growing reputation within and without the pale of medicine."[138]
"He stammered a lot, but whatever he said, whether seriously or jokingly, was always worth the wait, even if it didn’t always feel great for individual egos. Aware of his natural intelligence being above the average, he became sensitive to opposition early on, whether in conversation or actions, and always reacted with sharp sarcasm. He was also quick to lose patience with egotism and vanity, even when they were expressed in such minor ways that good manners would suggest tolerating them instead of mocking. Dr. Darwin often managed to highlight their absurdity through playful yet hurtful irony. If these traits of conversational dominance were noticeable in his early interactions, they only intensified as he gained more recognition, both within the medical field and beyond." [Pg 175]
I imagine that this portrait is somewhat too harshly drawn. Dr. Darwin's taste for English wines is the worst trait which I have been able to discover in his character. On this head Miss Seward tells us that "he despised the prejudice which deems foreign wines more wholesome than the wines of the country. 'If you must drink wine,' said he, 'let it be home-made.'" "It is well known," she continues, "that Dr. Darwin's influence and example have sobered the county of Derby; that intemperance in fermented fluid of every species is almost unknown among its gentlemen,"[139] which, if he limited them to cowslip wine, is hardly to be wondered at.
I think this portrait might be a bit too harsh. Dr. Darwin’s appreciation for English wines is the only negative trait I could find in his character. In this regard, Miss Seward tells us that "he ignored the bias that views foreign wines as healthier than the wines from our own country. 'If you have to drink wine,' he said, 'make sure it’s local.'" "It is well known," she adds, "that Dr. Darwin's influence and example have made the county of Derby more sober; that drunkenness from any type of fermented drink is almost unheard of among its gentlemen,"[139] which, if he only allowed them to drink cowslip wine, is hardly surprising.
Dr. Dowson, quoting Miss Edgeworth, says that Dr. Darwin attributed almost all the diseases of the upper classes to the too great use of fermented liquors. "This opinion he supported in his writings with the force of his eloquence and reason; and still more in conversation by all those powers of wit, satire, and peculiar humour, which never appeared fully to the public in his works, but which gained him strong[Pg 176] ascendancy in private society.... When he heard that my father was bilious, he suspected that this must be the consequence of his having, since his residence in Ireland, and in compliance with the fashion of the country, indulged too freely in drinking. His letter, I remember, concluded with, 'Farewell, my dear friend; God keep you from whisky—if He can.'"[140]
Dr. Dowson, quoting Miss Edgeworth, mentions that Dr. Darwin believed almost all the diseases of the wealthy were due to excessive consumption of alcoholic beverages. "He backed this opinion in his writings with compelling eloquence and reasoning; and even more so in conversation with his sharp wit, satire, and unique humor, which were never fully showcased in his published works, but earned him considerable influence in social circles.... When he learned that my father was experiencing digestive issues, he suspected it was due to his indulgence in drinking since moving to Ireland, conforming to the local trend. I recall his letter ended with, 'Farewell, my dear friend; God keep you away from whisky—if He can.'"[Pg 176][140]
On the other hand, Dr. Darwin seems to have been a very large eater. "Acid fruits with sugar, and all sorts of creams and butter were his luxuries; but he always ate plentifully of animal food. This liberal alimentary regimen he prescribed to people of every age where unvitiated appetite rendered them capable of following it; even to infants."
On the other hand, Dr. Darwin appears to have been quite the big eater. "He indulged in acidic fruits with sugar, along with various creams and butter as his treats; but he always had a hearty amount of meat. He recommended this generous diet to people of all ages who had a healthy appetite and could follow it, even to infants."
Dr. Dowson writes:—
Dr. Dowson writes:—
"I have mentioned already that he had in his carriage a receptacle for paper and pencils, with which he wrote as he travelled, and in one corner a pile of books; but he had also a receptacle for a knife, fork, and spoon, and in the other corner a hamper, containing fruit and sweetmeats, cream and sugar. He provided also for his horses by having a large pail lashed to his carriage for watering them, as well as hay and oats to be eaten on the road. Mrs. Schimmelpenninck says that when he came on a professional visit to her father's house they had, as was the custom whenever he came, 'a luncheon-table set out with hothouse fruits and West India sweetmeats, clotted cream, stilton cheese, &c. While the conversation went on, the dishes in his vicinity were rapidly emptied, and what,' she adds,[Pg 177] 'was my astonishment when, at the end of the three hours during which the meal had lasted, he expressed his joy at hearing the dressing bell, and hoped dinner would soon be announced.' This was not mere gluttony; he thought an abundance, or what most people would consider a superabundance of food, conducive to health. 'Eat or be eaten' is said to have been often his medical advice. He had especially a very high opinion of the nutritive value of sugar, and said 'that if ever our improved chemistry should discover the art of making sugar from fossil or aerial matter without the assistance of vegetation, food for animals would then become as plentiful as water, and mankind might live upon the earth as thick as blades of grass, with no restraint to their numbers but want of room.'—Botanic Garden, vol. i. p. 470."[141]
"I’ve already mentioned that he had a spot in his carriage for paper and pencils, which he used to write while traveling, and in one corner a stack of books. He also had a place for a knife, fork, and spoon, and in the other corner, a hamper filled with fruit, sweets, cream, and sugar. He took care of his horses too, as he had a large bucket tied to his carriage for watering them, along with hay and oats for the journey. Mrs. Schimmelpenninck says that when he visited her father's house, they always set up a lunch table with hothouse fruits, West India sweets, clotted cream, Stilton cheese, etc. During the conversation, the dishes around him quickly emptied, and what,’ she adds,[Pg 177] ‘surprised me was that at the end of the three hours the meal lasted, he expressed his delight at hearing the dressing bell and hoped dinner would be announced soon.’ This wasn’t just gluttony; he believed that having an abundance—or what most people would see as an excess—of food was good for health. ‘Eat or be eaten’ was said to be his frequent medical advice. He had a particularly high opinion of the nutritional value of sugar and claimed that ‘if our advanced chemistry could ever figure out how to make sugar from fossil or aerial substances without relying on plants, food for animals would become as abundant as water, and humans could live on earth as densely as blades of grass, with only lack of space limiting their numbers.’—Botanic Garden, vol. i. p. 470."[141]
"Professional generosity," says Miss Seward, "distinguished Dr. Darwin's practice. Whilst resident in Lichfield he always cheerfully gave to the priest and lay vicars of its cathedral and their families his advice, but never took fees from any of them. Diligently also did he attend the health of the poor in that city, and afterwards at Derby, and supplied their necessities by food, and all sort of charitable assistance. In each of those towns his was the cheerful board of almost open-housed hospitality, without extravagance or parade; generosity, wit, and science were his household gods."[142]
"Professional generosity," says Miss Seward, "set Dr. Darwin apart in his practice. While living in Lichfield, he always happily offered his advice to the priest and lay vicars of the cathedral and their families but never accepted payment from any of them. He also diligently cared for the health of the poor in that city and later in Derby, providing them with food and all kinds of charitable assistance. In each of those towns, he had a welcoming home with almost open-door hospitality, without extravagance or show; generosity, humor, and knowledge were his household treasures." [142]
Of his first marriage the following account is given:[Pg 178]—
Of his first marriage, the following account is provided:[Pg 178]—
"In 1757 he married Miss Howard, of the Close of Lichfield, a blooming and lovely young lady of eighteen.... Mrs. Darwin's own mind, by nature so well endowed, strengthened and expanded in the friendship, conversation, and confidence of so beloved a preceptor. But alas! upon her too early youth, and too delicate constitution, the frequency of her maternal situation, during the first five years of her marriage, had probably a baneful effect. The potent skill and assiduous cares of him before whom disease daily vanished from the frame of others, could not expel it radically from that of her he loved. It was, however, kept at bay during thirteen years.
"In 1757, he married Miss Howard from the Close of Lichfield, a beautiful and lovely young woman of eighteen... Mrs. Darwin's own mind, naturally gifted, grew and expanded through the friendship, conversation, and trust of such a cherished teacher. But sadly, her early youth and fragile health, combined with the frequent pregnancies during the first five years of her marriage, likely had a harmful impact. The powerful skill and diligent care of the man who could make disease disappear from others could not completely remove it from the woman he loved. However, it was kept at bay for thirteen years.
"Upon the distinguished happiness of those years she spoke with fervour to two intimate female friends in the last week of her existence, which closed at the latter end of the summer 1770. 'Do not weep for my impending fate,' said the dying angel with a smile of unaffected cheerfulness. 'In the short term of my life a great deal of happiness has been comprised. The maladies of my frame were peculiar; those of my head and stomach which no medicine could eradicate, were spasmodic and violent; and required stronger measures to render them supportable while they lasted than my constitution could sustain without injury. The periods of exemption from those pains were frequently of several days' duration, and in my intermissions I felt no indications of malady. Pain taught me the value of ease, and I enjoyed it with a glow of spirit, seldom, perhaps, felt by the habitually healthy. While Dr. Darwin combated and assuaged my disease from time[Pg 179] to time, his indulgence to all my wishes, his active desire to see me amused and happy, proved incessant. His house, as you know, has ever been the resort of people of science and merit. If, from my husband's great and extensive practice, I had much less of his society than I wished, yet the conversation of his friends, and of my own, was ever ready to enliven the hours of his absence. As occasional malady made me doubly enjoy health, so did those frequent absences give a zest even to delight, when I could be indulged with his company. My three boys have ever been docile and affectionate. Children as they are, I could trust them with important secrets, so sacred do they hold every promise they make. They scorn deceit and falsehood of every kind, and have less selfishness than generally belongs to childhood. Married to any other man, I do not suppose I could have lived a third part of the years which I have passed with Dr. Darwin; he has prolonged my days, and he has blessed them.'
"During the joyful years of her life, she spoke passionately with two close female friends in the final week of her existence, which came to an end in late summer 1770. 'Don’t cry for my impending fate,' said the dying angel with a sincere smile. 'In my short life, I’ve experienced a lot of happiness. The ailments I faced were unique; those affecting my head and stomach were intense and spasmodic, and no medicine could cure them. They required stronger measures to make them bearable than my body could handle without suffering. The times I was free from those pains often lasted several days, and during those breaks, I felt no signs of illness. Pain taught me to appreciate comfort, and I enjoyed it with a sense of joy that is rarely felt by those who are usually healthy. While Dr. Darwin treated and alleviated my illness from time to time, his willingness to fulfill my wishes and his constant effort to keep me entertained and happy were unwavering. As you know, his home has always been a gathering place for people of intellect and merit. Although I saw less of my husband than I wished due to his busy practice, the conversations of his friends and my own always brightened his absence. Just as periods of illness made me appreciate good health even more, his frequent absences added a special joy to our time together whenever I could enjoy his company. My three boys have always been gentle and loving. Even though they are children, I can trust them with important secrets; they hold every promise they make in high regard. They reject deceit and falsehood, and they are less selfish than is typical for children. I doubt I could have lived even a third of the years I’ve spent with Dr. Darwin if I had married anyone else; he has extended my days and blessed them.'”
"Thus died this superior woman, in the bloom of life, sincerely regretted by all who knew how to value her excellence, and passionately regretted by the selected few whom she honoured with her personal and confidential friendship."[143]
"Thus died this remarkable woman, in the prime of her life, genuinely missed by everyone who recognized her worth, and deeply missed by the select few she honored with her personal and trusted friendship."[143]
I find Miss Seward's pages so fascinating, that I am in danger of following her even in those parts of her work which have no bearing on Dr. Darwin. I must, however, pass over her account of Mr. Edgeworth and of his friend Mr. Day, the author of 'Sandford and Merton,' "which, by wise parents, is put into every[Pg 180] youthful hand," but the description of Mr. Day's portrait cannot be omitted.
I find Miss Seward's writing so fascinating that I'm at risk of getting sidetracked by sections that don't even relate to Dr. Darwin. However, I need to skip her account of Mr. Edgeworth and his friend Mr. Day, the author of 'Sandford and Merton,' "which, according to thoughtful parents, is given to every[Pg 180] young person," but I can't leave out the description of Mr. Day's portrait.
"In the course of the year 1770, Mr. Day stood for a full-length picture to Mr. Wright, of Derby. A strong likeness and a dignified portrait were the result. Drawn in the open air, the surrounding sky is tempestuous, lurid, dark. He stands leaning his left arm against a column inscribed to Hambden (sic). Mr. Day looks upwards, as enthusiastically meditating on the contents of a book held in his dropped right hand. The open leaf is the oration of that virtuous patriot in the senate, against the grant of ship money, demanded by King Charles I. A flash of lightning plays in Mr. Day's hair, and illuminates the contents of the volume. The poetic fancy and what were then the politics of the original, appear in the choice of subject and attitude. Dr. Darwin sat to Mr. Wright about the same period. That was a simply contemplative portrait, of the most perfect resemblance."[144]
"In the year 1770, Mr. Day posed for a full-length portrait by Mr. Wright of Derby. The result was a strong likeness and a dignified image. Created outdoors, the surrounding sky is stormy, vivid, and dark. He is leaning his left arm against a column dedicated to Hampden (sic). Mr. Day gazes upward, deeply engaged in the book held loosely in his right hand. The open page features the speech of that virtuous patriot in the Senate, opposing the ship money demand by King Charles I. A flash of lightning illuminates Mr. Day's hair, highlighting the contents of the book. The poetic imagination and the political views of the time are reflected in the choice of subject and pose. Dr. Darwin also sat for Mr. Wright around the same time. That portrait was simply contemplative, showcasing a perfect likeness."[144]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"In the year 1768, Dr. Darwin met with an accident of irretrievable injury to the human frame. His propensity to mechanics had unfortunately led him to construct a very singular carriage. It was a platform with a seat fixed upon a very high pair of wheels, and supported in the front upon the back of the horse, by means of a kind of proboscis which, forming an arch, reached over the hind-quarters of the horse, and passed through a ring, placed on an upright piece of iron, which worked in a socket fixed in the saddle. The[Pg 181] horse could thus move from one side of the road to the other, quartering, as it is called, at the will of the driver, whose constant attention was necessarily employed to regulate a piece of machinery contrived, but not well contrived, for that purpose."
"In 1768, Dr. Darwin had an accident that caused severe injury to his body. His interest in mechanics had sadly led him to create a very unusual carriage. It was a platform with a seat mounted on a very high pair of wheels, supported at the front by a kind of arm that arched over the horse's back and attached to a ring on an upright piece of iron, which moved in a socket fixed to the saddle. The[Pg 181] horse could then move from one side of the road to the other, turning as it’s called, at the will of the driver, whose constant focus was required to manage this piece of machinery that was designed, but not well designed, for that purpose."
I cannot help the reader to understand the foregoing description. "From this whimsical carriage, however, the doctor was several times thrown, and the last time he used it had the misfortune, from a similar accident, to break the patella of his right knee, which caused, as it must always cause, an incurable weakness in the fractured part, and a lameness not very discernible, indeed, when walking on even ground."[145]
I can't help the reader understand the previous description. "However, the doctor was thrown from this quirky carriage several times, and the last time he used it, he unfortunately broke the kneecap of his right knee in a similar incident, which led to, as it always does, an unhealable weakness in that area, and a slight limp that's not very noticeable when walking on flat ground."[145]
Miss Seward presently tells a story which reads as though it might have been told by Plutarch of some Greek or Roman sage. Much as we must approve of Dr. Darwin's habitual sobriety, we shall most of us be agreed that a few more such stories would have been cheaply purchased by a corresponding number of lapses on the doctor's part.
Miss Seward is now sharing a story that seems like it could have come from Plutarch about some Greek or Roman philosopher. While we definitely appreciate Dr. Darwin's consistent seriousness, most of us would agree that a few more stories like this would have been worth a few slips on his part.
Miss Seward writes:—
Miss Seward writes:—
"Since these memoirs commenced, an odd anecdote of Dr. Darwin's early residence at Lichfield, was narrated to a friend of the author by a gentleman, who was of the party in which it happened. Mr. Sneyd, then of Bishton, and a few more gentlemen of Staffordshire, prevailed upon the doctor to join them in an expedition by water from Burton to Nottingham, and on to Newark. They had cold provisions on board, and plenty of wine. It was midsummer; the day ardent[Pg 182] and sultry. The noon-tide meal had been made, and the glass had gone gaily round. It was one of those few instances in which the medical votary of the Naiads transgressed his general and strict sobriety," in which, in fact, he may be said to have—remembered himself.
"Since these memoirs began, a funny story about Dr. Darwin's early time in Lichfield was shared with a friend of the author by a man who was part of the group involved. Mr. Sneyd, then from Bishton, and a few other gentlemen from Staffordshire convinced the doctor to join them on a boat trip from Burton to Nottingham and then to Newark. They had cold food on board and plenty of wine. It was midsummer; the day was hot and humid. They had their midday meal, and the drinks were flowing cheerfully. It was one of those rare instances where the medical devotee of the water nymphs broke his usual strict sobriety, in fact, he can be said to have—enjoyed himself."
"If not absolutely intoxicated, his spirits were in a high state of vinous exhilaration. On the boat approaching Nottingham, within the distance of a few fields, he surprised his companions by stepping, without any previous notice, from the boat into the middle of the river, and swimming to shore. They saw him get upon the bank, and walk coolly over the meadows towards the town: they called to him in vain, but he did not once turn his head.
"If he wasn't completely drunk, he was definitely in a great mood from the wine. While on the boat heading to Nottingham, just a few fields away, he shocked his friends by suddenly stepping out of the boat and diving into the river to swim to the shore. They watched as he climbed onto the bank and casually walked across the meadows toward the town. They called out to him, but he didn’t even look back."
"Anxious lest he should take a dangerous cold by remaining in his wet clothes, and uncertain whether or not he intended to desert the party, they rowed instantly to the town at which they had not designed to have touched, and went in search of their river-god.
"Feeling anxious that he might catch a bad cold from staying in his wet clothes, and unsure if he was planning to leave the group, they quickly rowed to the town they hadn’t intended to stop at, searching for their river-god."
"In passing through the market-place they saw him standing upon a tub, encircled by a crowd of people, and resisting the entreaties of an apothecary of the place, one of his old acquaintances, who was importuning him to his house, and to accept other raiments till his own could be dried.
"In passing through the market, they saw him standing on a tub, surrounded by a crowd of people, and refusing the pleas of a local apothecary, an old acquaintance, who was urging him to come to his house and accept other clothes until his own could be dried."
"The party on pressing through the crowd were surprised to hear him speaking without any degree of his usual stammer:—'Have I not told you, my friend, that I had drank a considerable quantity of wine before I committed myself to the river. You know my general sobriety, and as a professional man you ought to know[Pg 183] that the unusual existence of internal stimulus would, in its effects upon the system, counteract the external cold and moisture.'"
"The group pushing through the crowd was surprised to hear him speaking without his usual stammer: ‘Haven't I told you, my friend, that I had consumed a good amount of wine before I jumped into the river? You know I'm generally sober, and as a professional, you should know[Pg 183] that the unusual presence of internal stimulation would counteract the external cold and moisture on my body.'"
"Then perceiving his companions near him, he nodded, smiled, and waived his hand, as enjoining them silence, thus, without hesitation, addressing the populace:—
"Then noticing his friends nearby, he nodded, smiled, and waved his hand, signaling them to be quiet, and without pause, he spoke to the crowd:—
"'Ye men of Nottingham, listen to me. You are ingenious and industrious mechanics. By your industry life's comforts are procured for yourselves and families. If you lose your health the power of being industrious will forsake you. That you know, but you may not know that to breathe fresh and changed air constantly, is not less necessary to preserve health than sobriety itself. Air becomes unwholesome in a few hours if the windows are shut. Open those of your sleeping rooms whenever you quit them to go to your workshops. Keep the windows of your workshops open whenever the weather is not insupportably cold. I have no interest in giving you this advice; remember what I, your countryman and a physician, tell you. If you would not bring infection and disease upon yourselves, and to your wives and little ones, change the air you breathe, change it many times a day, by opening your windows.'
"'You men of Nottingham, listen up. You are smart and hardworking mechanics. Because of your efforts, you provide comforts for yourselves and your families. If you lose your health, you won't be able to work. That you understand, but you may not realize that breathing fresh, clean air regularly is just as essential for maintaining health as staying sober. Air gets unhealthy in just a few hours if the windows are closed. Open the windows in your bedrooms whenever you leave them to go to your workshops. Keep the windows in your workshops open whenever the weather isn't freezing. I have no personal stake in giving you this advice; remember what I, your fellow citizen and a doctor, am telling you. If you want to avoid bringing illness and disease upon yourselves, your wives, and your children, change the air you breathe frequently throughout the day by opening your windows.'
"So saying, he stepped down from the tub, and, returning with his party to their boat, they pursued their voyage."[146]
"So saying, he stepped down from the tub and, returning with his friends to their boat, they continued their journey."[146]
Could any missionary be more perfectly sober and sensible, or more alive to the immorality of trying to effect too sudden a modification in the organisms[Pg 184] he was endeavouring to influence? If the men of Nottingham want a statue in their market-place, I would respectfully suggest that a subject is here afforded them.
Could any missionary be more perfectly sober and sensible, or more aware of the immorality of trying to make too sudden a change in the organisms[Pg 184] he was trying to influence? If the people of Nottingham want a statue in their market square, I would respectfully suggest that this would be a good subject for it.
"Dr. Johnson was several times at Lichfield on visits to Mrs. Lucy Porter, his daughter-in-law, while Dr. Darwin was one of the inhabitants. They had one or two interviews, but never afterwards sought each other. Mutual and strong dislike subsisted between them. It is curious that in Johnson's various letters to Mrs. Thrale, now Mrs. Piozzi, published by that lady after his death, many of them dated from Lichfield, the name of Darwin cannot be found, nor, indeed, that of any of the ingenious and lettered people who lived there; while of its mere common-life characters there is frequent mention, with many hints of Lichfield's intellectual barrenness, while it could boast a Darwin and other men of classical learning, poetic talents, and liberal information."[147]
Dr. Johnson visited Lichfield several times to see Mrs. Lucy Porter, his daughter-in-law, while Dr. Darwin was one of the local residents. They had a couple of meetings, but never reached out to each other again. There was a strong mutual dislike between them. It's interesting that in Johnson's various letters to Mrs. Thrale, now Mrs. Piozzi, published by her after his death—many dated from Lichfield—the name Darwin doesn’t appear, nor do any of the other smart and educated people who lived there. However, he frequently mentioned the everyday people of Lichfield, often hinting at the town's lack of intellectual vibrancy, despite it having a Darwin and other men of classical knowledge, poetic ability, and broad learning. [147]
Here there follows a pleasant sketch of the principal Lichfield notabilities, which I am compelled to omit.
Here’s a nice overview of the main notable people from Lichfield that I have to skip.
"These were the men," exclaims Miss Seward, "whose intellectual existence passed unnoticed by Dr. Johnson in his depreciating estimate of Lichfield talents. But Johnson liked only worshippers. Archdeacon Vyse, Mr. Seward, and Mr. Robinson paid all the respect and attention to Dr. Johnson, on these his visits to their town, due to his great abilities, his high reputation, and to whatever was estimable in his mixed character; but they were not in the herd that 'paged his heels,' and[Pg 185] sunk in servile silence under the force of his dogmas, when their hearts and their judgments bore contrary testimony.
"These were the men," exclaims Miss Seward, "whose intellectual existence went unnoticed by Dr. Johnson in his dismissive view of Lichfield talents. But Johnson preferred worshippers. Archdeacon Vyse, Mr. Seward, and Mr. Robinson showed the respect and attention to Dr. Johnson that he deserved during his visits to their town, due to his great abilities, his high reputation, and everything admirable in his mixed character; however, they were not among those who 'paged his heels,' and[Pg 185] fell into a servile silence under the weight of his beliefs, even when their hearts and minds testified against them with contrary opinions."
"Certainly, however, it was an arduous hazard to the feelings of the company to oppose in the slightest degree Dr. Johnson's opinions. His stentor lungs; that combination of wit, humour, and eloquence, which 'could make the worse appear the better reason,' that sarcastic contempt of his antagonist, never suppressed or even softened by the due restraints of good breeding, were sufficient to close the lips in his presence, of men who could have met him in fair argument, on any ground, literary or political, moral or characteristic.
"Of course, it was a tough challenge for the group to disagree even slightly with Dr. Johnson's views. His booming voice, that mix of wit, humor, and eloquence that 'could make the worse seem the better argument,' along with his sarcastic disdain for anyone opposing him, which was never held back by common courtesy, was enough to silence even those who could have engaged him in a fair debate on any topic, whether literary, political, moral, or personal."
"Where Dr. Johnson was, Dr. Darwin had no chance of being heard, though at least his equal in genius, his superior in science; nor, indeed, from his impeded utterance, in the company of any overbearing declaimer; and he was too intellectually great to be an humble listener to Johnson. Therefore he shunned him on having experienced what manner of man he was. The surly dictator felt the mortification, and revenged it by affecting to avow his disdain of powers too distinguished to be objects of genuine scorn.
"Where Dr. Johnson was, Dr. Darwin had no chance of being heard, even though he was at least Johnson's equal in talent and superior in science. He struggled to express himself in the presence of such a dominating speaker, and he was too intellectually accomplished to be a passive listener to Johnson. So, he avoided Johnson after realizing what kind of person he was. The grumpy authority figure felt embarrassed and took revenge by pretending to express disdain for talents that were too remarkable to genuinely scorn."
"Dr. Darwin, in his turn, was not much more just to Dr. Johnson's genius. He uniformly spoke of him in terms which, had they been deserved, would have justified Churchill's 'immane Pomposo' as an appellation of scorn; since if his person was huge, and his manners pompous and violent, so were his talents vast and powerful, in a degree from which only prejudice and resentment could withhold respect.[Pg 186]
"Dr. Darwin, for his part, wasn't much kinder to Dr. Johnson's talent. He always referred to him in ways that, if they were deserved, would make Churchill's 'immane Pomposo' a fitting term of scorn; because while his size was large and his behavior pompous and aggressive, his abilities were also immense and strong, to an extent that only bias and bitterness could prevent respect.[Pg 186]"
"Though Dr. Darwin's hesitation in speaking precluded his flow of colloquial eloquence, it did not impede, or at all lessen, the force of that conciser quality, wit. Of satiric wit he possessed a very peculiar species. It was neither the dead-doing broadside of Dr. Johnson's satire, nor the aurora borealis of Gray ... whose arch yet coy and quiet fastidiousness of taste and feeling, as recorded by Mason, glanced bright and cold through his conversation, while it seemed difficult to define its nature; and while its effects were rather perceived than felt, exciting surprise more than mirth, and never awakening the pained sense of being the object of its ridicule. That unique in humorous verse, the Long Story, is a complete and beautiful specimen of Gray's singular vein.
"Although Dr. Darwin's hesitation in speaking limited his ability to express himself fluidly, it didn’t take away from the impact of his concise wit. He had a very unique type of satirical wit. It was neither the blunt force of Dr. Johnson's satire nor the cold brilliance of Gray... whose clever yet reserved taste, as noted by Mason, shone bright and cool in his conversation, making it hard to pinpoint its essence; its effects were more often perceived than felt, sparking surprise rather than laughter, and never making the listener feel like the target of ridicule. The Long Story, a unique piece of humorous verse, is a perfect example of Gray's distinctive style."
"Darwinian wit is not more easy to be defined; instances will best convey an idea of its character to those who never conversed with its possessor.
"Darwinian wit is not easier to define; examples will best convey an idea of its nature to those who have never spoken with its owner."
"Dr. Darwin was conversing with a brother botanist concerning the plant kalmia, then a just imported stranger in our greenhouses and gardens. A lady who was present, concluding he had seen it, which in fact he had not, asked the doctor what were the colours of the plant. He replied, 'Madam, the kalmia has precisely the colours of a seraph's wing.' So fancifully did he express his want of consciousness concerning the appearance of a flower, whose name and rareness were all he knew of the matter.
"Dr. Darwin was chatting with a fellow botanist about the kalmia plant, which had just arrived in our greenhouses and gardens. A woman who was there assumed he had seen it, which he actually hadn’t, and asked the doctor what colors the plant had. He replied, 'Madam, the kalmia has exactly the colors of a seraph's wing.' In such a creative way, he conveyed his ignorance about what the flower actually looked like, knowing only its name and rarity."
"Dr. Darwin had a large company at tea. His servant announced a stranger, lady and gentleman. The female was a conspicuous figure, ruddy, corpulent,[Pg 187] and tall. She held by the arm a little, meek-looking, pale, effeminate man, who, from his close adherence to the side of the lady, seemed to consider himself as under her protection.
"Dr. Darwin had a large gathering for tea. His servant announced a couple of newcomers, a lady and a gentleman. The woman was a striking figure, rosy-cheeked, overweight, and tall. She had a little, timid-looking, pale, delicate man by the arm who, by sticking close to her side, seemed to see himself as being under her protection.[Pg 187]"
"'Dr. Darwin, I seek you not as a physician, but as a Belle Esprit. I make this husband of mine,' and she looked down with a side glance upon the animal, 'treat me every summer with a tour through one of the British counties, to explore whatever it contains worth the attention of ingenious people. On arriving at the several inns in our route I always search out the man of the vicinity most distinguished for his genius and taste, and introduce myself, that he may direct as the objects of our examination, whatever is curious in nature, art, or science. Lichfield will be our headquarters during several days. Come, doctor, whither must we go; what must we investigate to-morrow, and the next day, and the next? Here are my tablets and pencil.'
"'Dr. Darwin, I'm not seeking you as a doctor, but as a Belle Esprit. My husband,' and she cast a sideways glance at the animal, 'takes me every summer on a tour through one of the British counties to discover whatever is noteworthy for creative minds. When we reach the various inns on our journey, I always look for the local person known for their brilliance and taste, and I introduce myself so they can guide us to whatever is interesting in nature, art, or science. We'll be based in Lichfield for several days. Come on, doctor, where should we go; what should we explore tomorrow, the next day, and the day after? Here are my notebooks and pencil.'
"'You arrive, madam, at a fortunate juncture. To-morrow you will have an opportunity of surveying an annual exhibition perfectly worthy your attention. To-morrow, madam, you will go to Tutbury bull-running.'
"'You arrive, ma'am, at a lucky moment. Tomorrow you will have the chance to check out an annual exhibition that's definitely worth your time. Tomorrow, ma'am, you will go to Tutbury bull-running.'"
"The satiric laugh with which he stammered out the last word more keenly pointed this sly, yet broad rebuke to the vanity and arrogance of her speech. She had been up amongst the boughs, and little expected they would break under her so suddenly, and with so little mercy. Her large features swelled, and her eyes flashed with anger—'I was recommended to a man of genius, and I find him insolent and ill-bred.' Then,[Pg 188] gathering up her meek and alarmed husband, whom she had loosed when she first spoke, under the shadow of her broad arm and shoulder, she strutted out of the room.
"The sarcastic laugh with which he stumbled over the last word made his sly but obvious criticism of her vanity and arrogance even sharper. She had been up in the branches and hardly expected them to break under her so suddenly and without warning. Her strong features tensed, and her eyes burned with anger—'I was referred to a person of talent, and I find him rude and uncouth.' Then,[Pg 188] gathering her meek and startled husband, whom she had released when she first spoke, under the shadow of her broad arm and shoulder, she strutted out of the room.
"After the departure of this curious couple, his guests told their host he had been very unmerciful. 'I chose,' replied he, 'to avenge the cause of the little man, whose nothingness was so ostentatiously displayed by his lady-wife. Her vanity has had a smart emetic. If it abates the symptoms, she will have reason to thank her physician who administered without hope of a fee.'"[148]
"After this unusual couple left, his guests told their host that he had been very cruel. 'I chose,' he replied, 'to defend the little man, whose worthlessness was so obviously highlighted by his wife. Her vanity has received a strong dose of reality. If it eases the situation, she will have reason to be grateful to the doctor who treated her without expecting payment.'"[148]
"In the spring of 1778 the children of Colonel and Mrs. Pole of Radburn, in Derbyshire, had been injured by a dangerous quantity of the cicuta, injudiciously administered to them in the hooping-cough by a physician of the neighbourhood. Mrs. Pole brought them to the house of Dr. Darwin in Lichfield, remaining with them there a few weeks, till by his art the poison was expelled from their constitutions and their health restored.
"In the spring of 1778, the children of Colonel and Mrs. Pole from Radburn, Derbyshire, were harmed by a dangerous amount of hemlock that a local doctor carelessly gave them for whooping cough. Mrs. Pole took them to Dr. Darwin's house in Lichfield, staying with them for a few weeks until he was able to remove the poison from their bodies and restore their health."
"Mrs. Pole was then in the full bloom of her youth and beauty. Agreeable features; the glow of health; a fine form, tall and graceful; playful sprightliness of manner; a benevolent heart, and maternal affection, in all its unwearied cares and touching tenderness, contributed to inspire Dr. Darwin's admiration, and to secure his esteem."[149]
"Mrs. Pole was at the peak of her youth and beauty. She had attractive features, a healthy glow, a tall and graceful figure, and a playful, lively manner. Her kind heart and motherly love, shown in her tireless care and touching tenderness, led Dr. Darwin to admire her and hold her in high regard."[149]
"In the autumn of this year" (1778) "Mrs. Pole of Radburn was taken ill; her disorder a violent fever.[Pg 189] Dr. Darwin was called in, and never perhaps since the death of Mrs. Darwin, prescribed with such deep anxiety. Not being requested to continue in the house during the ensuing night, which he apprehended might prove critical, he passed the remaining hours till day-dawn beneath a tree opposite her apartment, watching the passing and repassing lights in the chamber. During the period in which a life so passionately valued was in danger, he paraphrased Petrarch's celebrated sonnet, narrating a dream whose prophecy was accomplished by the death of Laura. It took place the night on which the vision arose amid his slumber. Dr. Darwin extended the thought of that sonnet into the following elegy:—
"In the autumn of this year" (1778) "Mrs. Pole of Radburn became ill; her illness was a severe fever.[Pg 189] Dr. Darwin was called in and, perhaps for the first time since Mrs. Darwin's passing, prescribed with such deep worry. Since he wasn’t asked to stay overnight, which he feared might be critical, he spent the remaining hours until dawn under a tree across from her room, watching the flickering lights inside. While a life he valued so deeply was in peril, he paraphrased Petrarch's famous sonnet about a dream whose prophecy was fulfilled by Laura's death. This dream occurred the night the vision appeared during his sleep. Dr. Darwin expanded on the concept of that sonnet into the following elegy:—
Clutched by your dark wing, my throbbing head, While to imagination's surprised ear The slow bell tolled for bright Eliza, who has died.
Across her pale forehead, the fake lace was tied, And love and virtues draped their garlands around.
Or awaken the lyre to every joyful sound? How sad my heart would be for others' sorrow!
How light this heart for the sake of others' joy!
Why should I sigh, and why should I cry again? Unreal shapes my trembling doubts into confusion,
And desperate grief fears the true vision.
Go tell my love all my gentle worries,
How love's tender sorrows disturb the quiet night,
"And soak my pillow with tears that no one cares about."
Unwilling as I am to extend this memoir, I must give Miss Seward's criticism on the foregoing.
Unwilling as I am to lengthen this memoir, I need to share Miss Seward's comments on what I've just mentioned.
"The second verse of this charming elegy affords an instance of Dr. Darwin's too exclusive devotion to distinct picture in poetry; that it sometimes betrayed him into bringing objects so precisely to the eye as to lose in such precision their power of striking forcibly on the heart. The pathos in the second verse is much injured by the words 'mimic lace,' which allude to the perforated borders on the shroud. The expression is too minute for the solemnity of the subject. Certainly it cannot be natural for a shocked and agitated mind to observe, or to describe with such petty accuracy. Besides, the allusion is not sufficiently obvious. The reader pauses to consider what the poet means by 'mimic lace.' Such pauses deaden sensation and break the course of attention. A friend of the doctor's pleaded greatly that the line might run thus:—
"The second verse of this charming elegy shows an example of Dr. Darwin's tendency to focus too much on creating vivid imagery in poetry; sometimes it led him to depict things so clearly that they lost their emotional impact. The emotional weight in the second verse suffers due to the phrase 'mimic lace,' which refers to the perforated edges of the shroud. This detail is too small for the gravity of the topic. It's unlikely that someone in shock and distress would notice or describe things with such trivial precision. Additionally, the reference isn't clear enough. The reader stops to think about what the poet means by 'mimic lace.' Such pauses diminish the feeling and disrupt the flow of attention. A friend of the doctor strongly suggested that the line could be rephrased to say:—"
but the alteration was rejected. Inattention to the rules of grammar in the first verse was also pointed out to him at the same time. The dream is addressed:
but the change was denied. His lack of attention to grammar rules in the first verse was also highlighted to him at that moment. The dream is addressed:
but nothing is said to it, and therefore the sense is left unfinished, while the elegy proceeds to give a picture of the lifeless beauty. The same friend suggested[Pg 191] a change which would have remedied the defect. Thus:—
but nothing is mentioned about it, so the meaning feels incomplete, while the elegy continues to depict the beauty of lifelessness. The same friend suggested[Pg 191] a change that would have fixed the issue. Thus:—
Clutched by its dark wing, my throbbing head, While to" &c., &c.
"Hence not only the grammatic error would have been done away, but the grating sound produced by the near alliteration of the harsh dr in 'dread dream' removed, by placing those words at a greater distance from each other.
"Hence, not only would the grammatical error be eliminated, but the harsh sound created by the near alliteration of the rough dr in 'dread dream' would be softened by putting those words further apart from each other."
"This alteration was, for the same reason, rejected. The doctor would not spare the word hovering, which he said strengthened the picture; but surely the image ought not to be elaborately precise, by which a dream is transformed into an animal with black wings."[150]
"This change was rejected for the same reason. The doctor refused to drop the word hovering, claiming it enhanced the imagery; but surely the image shouldn't be overly detailed, turning a dream into an animal with black wings."[150]
Then Mrs. Pole got well, and the doctor wrote more verses and Miss Seward more criticism. It was not for nothing that Dr. Johnson came down to Lichfield.
Then Mrs. Pole recovered, and the doctor wrote more poems while Miss Seward wrote more critiques. Dr. Johnson didn't come down to Lichfield for no reason.
In 1780 Colonel Pole died, and his widow, still young, handsome, witty, and—for those days—rich, was in no want of suitors.
In 1780, Colonel Pole died, and his widow, still young, attractive, clever, and—especially for that time—wealthy, had no shortage of admirers.
"Colonel Pole," says Miss Seward, "had numbered twice the years of his fair wife. His temper was said to have been peevish and suspicious; yet not beneath those circumstances had her kind and cheerful attentions to him grown cold or remiss. He left her a jointure of 600l. per annum, a son to inherit his estate, and two female children amply portioned.[Pg 192]
"Colonel Pole," says Miss Seward, "was twice the age of his beautiful wife. His temper was described as irritable and mistrustful; still, under those conditions, her kind and cheerful care for him never faded or slackened. He left her an annual income of 600l., a son to inherit his estate, and two daughters well provided for.[Pg 192]
"Mrs. Pole, it has already been remarked, had much vivacity and sportive humour, with very engaging frankness of temper and manners. Early in her widowhood she was rallied in a large company upon Dr. Darwin's passion for her, and was asked what she would do with her captive philosopher. 'He is not very fond of churches, I believe,' said she, 'and even if he would go there for my sake, I shall scarcely follow him. He is too old for me.' 'Nay, Madam,' was the answer, 'what are fifteen years on the right side?' She replied, with an arch smile, 'I have had so much of that right side.'
"Mrs. Pole, as already noted, was full of energy and playful humor, with a very charming openness in her personality and behavior. Shortly after becoming a widow, she was teased in a large gathering about Dr. Darwin's affection for her and was asked what she would do with her captivated philosopher. 'I don’t think he’s much into churches,' she said, 'and even if he would go there for my sake, I doubt I’d follow him. He's too old for me.' 'Come now, Madam,' was the response, 'what’s fifteen years on the right side?' She replied, with a playful smile, 'I’ve had so much of that right side.'"
"This confession was thought inauspicious for the doctor's hopes, but it did not prove so. The triumph of intellect was complete."[151]
"This confession seemed like bad news for the doctor's hopes, but it didn't turn out that way. The victory of intellect was total."[151]
Mrs. Pole had taken a strong dislike to Lichfield, and had made it a condition of her marriage that Dr. Darwin should not reside there after he had married her. In 1781, therefore, immediately after his marriage, he removed to Derby, and continued to live there till a fortnight before his death.
Mrs. Pole really disliked Lichfield and made it a condition of her marriage that Dr. Darwin wouldn’t live there after they got married. So, in 1781, right after the wedding, he moved to Derby and stayed there until two weeks before he died.
Here he wrote 'The Botanic Garden' and a great part of the 'Zoonomia.' Those who wish for a detailed analysis of 'The Botanic Garden' can hardly do better than turn to Miss Seward's pages. Opening them at random, I find the following:—
Here he wrote 'The Botanic Garden' and much of 'Zoonomia.' Anyone looking for a thorough analysis of 'The Botanic Garden' can't go wrong by checking out Miss Seward's work. When I flip through her pages at random, I discover the following:—
"The mention of Brindley, the father of commercial canals, has propriety as well as happiness. Similitude for their course to the sinuous track of a serpent, produces a fine picture of a gliding animal of that[Pg 193] species, and it is succeeded by these supremely happy lines:—
"The mention of Brindley, the father of commercial canals, is both fitting and joyful. Comparing their path to the winding route of a serpent creates a vivid image of a sliding creature of that[Pg 193] kind, followed by these wonderfully happy lines:—
&c. &c. &c.
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"The mechanism of the pump is next described with curious ingenuity. Common as is the machine, it is not unworthy a place in this splendid composition, as being, after the sinking of wells, the earliest of those inventions, which in situations of exterior aridness gave ready accession to water. This familiar object is illustrated by a picture of Maternal Beauty administering sustenance to her infant."[153]
"The pump's mechanism is then described with interesting creativity. Although it's a common machine, it deserves a spot in this remarkable work because, after well drilling, it's one of the earliest inventions that provided easy access to water in dry areas. This well-known object is depicted in a picture of Maternal Beauty nourishing her baby."[153]
Here we will leave the poetical part of the 'Botanic Garden.' The notes, however, to which are "still," as Dr. Dowson says, "instructive and amusing," and contain matter which, at the time they were written, was for the most part new.
Here we will shift away from the poetic section of the 'Botanic Garden.' The notes, however, remain, as Dr. Dowson says, "instructive and amusing," and include information that was mostly new at the time they were written.
Of the 'Zoonomia' there is no occasion to speak here, as a sufficient number of extracts from those parts that concern us as bearing upon evolution will be given presently.
Of the 'Zoonomia,' there's no need to discuss it here, since enough excerpts from the relevant sections that pertain to us regarding evolution will be provided shortly.
On the 18th of April, 1802, Dr. Darwin had written "one page of a very sprightly letter to Mr. Edgeworth, describing the Priory and his purposed alterations there, when the fatal signal was given. He rang the bell and ordered the servant to send Mrs. Darwin to him. She came immediately, with his daughter, Miss Emma Darwin. They saw him shivering and pale.[Pg 194] He desired them to send to Derby for his surgeon, Mr. Hadley. They did so, but all was over before he could arrive.
On April 18, 1802, Dr. Darwin wrote "a lively page" in a letter to Mr. Edgeworth, discussing the Priory and his planned changes there when the tragic signal was given. He rang the bell and asked the servant to fetch Mrs. Darwin. She arrived right away, along with their daughter, Miss Emma Darwin. They found him shivering and pale.[Pg 194] He asked them to send for his surgeon, Mr. Hadley, in Derby. They did, but it was too late for him to make it in time.
"It was reported at Lichfield that, perceiving himself growing rapidly worse, he said to Mrs. Darwin, 'My dear, you must bleed me instantly.' 'Alas! I dare not, lest—' 'Emma, will you? There is no time to be lost.' 'Yes, my dear father, if you will direct me.' At that moment he sank into his chair and expired."[154]
"It was reported at Lichfield that, realizing he was getting much worse, he said to Mrs. Darwin, 'My dear, you need to bleed me right away.' 'Oh no! I can't, for fear that—' 'Emma, will you? There’s no time to waste.' 'Yes, my dear father, if you guide me.' At that moment, he collapsed into his chair and passed away."[154]
Dr. Dowson gives the letter to Mr. Edgeworth, which is as follows:—
Dr. Dowson hands the letter to Mr. Edgeworth, which reads as follows:—
"Dear Edgeworth,
"Dear Edgeworth,"
"I am glad to find that you still amuse yourself with mechanism, in spite of the troubles of Ireland.
"I’m glad to see that you still enjoy working with machinery, despite the issues in Ireland."
"The use of turning aside or downwards the claw of a table, I don't see; as it must then be reared against a wall, for it will not stand alone. If the use be for carriage, the feet may shut up, like the usual brass feet of a reflecting telescope.
"The use of turning the claw of a table to the side or downwards doesn’t make sense to me; it will have to be propped against a wall because it can't stand on its own. If it's meant for transport, the legs could fold up, similar to the typical brass legs of a reflecting telescope."
"We have all been now removed from Derby about a fortnight, to the Priory, and all of us like our change of situation. We have a pleasant house, a good garden, ponds full of fish, and a pleasing valley, somewhat like Shenstone's—deep, umbrageous, and with a talkative stream running down it. Our house is near the top of the valley, well screened by hills from the east and north, and open to the south, where at four miles distance we see Derby tower.
"We've been away from Derby for about two weeks now, at the Priory, and we all enjoy our new surroundings. We have a lovely house, a nice garden, ponds full of fish, and a charming valley, somewhat like Shenstone's—deep, shaded, and with a babbling stream flowing through it. Our house is situated near the top of the valley, well sheltered by hills to the east and north, and open to the south, where we can see Derby tower about four miles away."
"Four or more strong springs rise near the house, and have formed the valley which, like that of Petrarch, may be called Val Chiusa, as it begins, or is shut at the situation of the house. I hope you like the description, and hope farther that yourself and any part of your family will sometimes do us the pleasure of a visit.
"Four or more strong springs emerge near the house and have created the valley, which, like Petrarch's, could be called Val Chiusa, as it begins, or is closed off at the location of the house. I hope you enjoy the description and also hope that you and any members of your family will occasionally visit us."
"Pray tell the authoress" (Miss Maria Edgeworth) "that the water-nymphs of our valley will be happy to assist her next novel.
"Please let the author" (Miss Maria Edgeworth) "know that the water nymphs of our valley will be happy to help with her next novel.
"My bookseller, Mr. Johnson, will not begin to print the 'Temple of Nature' till the price of paper is fixed by Parliament. I suppose the present duty is paid...."
"My bookseller, Mr. Johnson, won’t start printing the 'Temple of Nature' until Parliament sets the price of paper. I guess the current tax is paid...."
At these words Dr. Darwin's pen stopped. What followed was written on the opposite side of the paper by another hand.
At these words, Dr. Darwin's pen paused. What came next was written on the other side of the paper by a different hand.
FOOTNOTES:
[139] Ibid.
Ibid.
[143] 'Memoirs,' &c., p. 14.
[144] 'Memoirs,' &c., p. 21.
[145] 'Memoirs,' &c., p. 62.
[146] 'Memoirs,' &c., p. 68.
[147] Miss Seward's 'Memoirs,' p. 69.
[148] 'Memoirs,' &c., p. 84.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 'Memoirs,' etc., p. 84.
[149] Ibid., p. 105.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 105.
[150] 'Memoirs,' &c., p. 120.
[151] 'Memoirs,' &c., p. 149.
[152] 'Memoirs,' &c., p. 249.
[153] 'Memoirs,' &c., p. 250.
[154] 'Memoirs,' &c., p. 426.
PHILOSOPHY OF DR. ERASMUS DARWIN.
PHILOSOPHY OF DR. ERASMUS DARWIN.
Considering the wide reputation enjoyed by Dr. Darwin at the beginning of this century, it is surprising how completely he has been lost sight of. The 'Botanic Garden' was translated into Portuguese in 1803; the 'Loves of the Plants' into French and Italian in 1800 and 1805; while, as I have already said, the 'Zoonomia' had appeared some years earlier in Germany. Paley's 'Natural Theology' is written throughout at the 'Zoonomia,' though he is careful, more suo, never to mention this work by name. Paley's success was probably one of the chief causes of the neglect into which the Buffonian and Darwinian systems fell in this country. Dr. Darwin is as reticent about teleology as Buffon, and presumably for the same reason, but the evidence in favour of design was too obvious; Paley, therefore, with his usual keen-sightedness seized upon this weak point, and had the battle all his own way, for Dr. Darwin died the same year as that in which the 'Natural Theology' appeared. The unfortunate failure to see that evolution involves design and purpose as necessarily and far more intelligibly than the theological view of creation, has retarded our[Pg 196] perception of many important facts for three-quarters of a century.
Considering the widespread reputation Dr. Darwin had at the start of this century, it's surprising how completely he has been forgotten. The 'Botanic Garden' was translated into Portuguese in 1803; 'Loves of the Plants' was translated into French and Italian in 1800 and 1805; and, as I mentioned earlier, 'Zoonomia' had been published a few years earlier in Germany. Paley's 'Natural Theology' is based on 'Zoonomia,' yet he is careful, more suo, never to mention it by name. Paley's success was likely one of the main reasons why the Buffonian and Darwinian theories fell out of favor in this country. Dr. Darwin is as reserved about teleology as Buffon, probably for the same reasons, but the evidence supporting design was too clear; thus, Paley, with his usual sharp insight, seized on this weak point, winning the argument easily since Dr. Darwin died the same year 'Natural Theology' was published. The unfortunate failure to recognize that evolution involves design and purpose just as necessarily—and in a much clearer way—than the theological perspective on creation has hindered our[Pg 196] understanding of many important facts for the past seventy-five years.
However this may be, Dr. Darwin's name has been but little before the public during the controversies of the last thirty years. Mr. Charles Darwin, indeed, in the "historical sketch" which he has prefixed to the later editions of his 'Origin of Species,' says, "It is curious how largely my grandfather, Dr. Erasmus Darwin, anticipated the views and erroneous grounds of opinion of Lamarck in his 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. pp. 500-510, published in 1794."[155] And a few lines lower Mr. Darwin adds, "It is rather a singular instance of the manner in which similar views arise at about the same time, that Goethe in Germany, and Geoffroy St. Hilaire (as we shall immediately see) in France, came to the same conclusion on the 'Origin of Species' in the years 1794-1796." Acquaintance with Buffon's work will explain much of the singularity, while those who have any knowledge of the writings of Dr. Darwin and Étienne Geoffroy St. Hilaire will be aware that neither would admit the other as "coming to the same conclusion," or even nearly so, as himself. Dr. Darwin goes beyond his successor, Lamarck, while Étienne Geoffroy does not even go so far as Dr. Darwin's predecessor, Buffon, had thought fit to let himself be known as going. I have found no other reference to Dr. Darwin in the 'Origin of Species,' except the two just given from the same note. In the first edition I find no mention of him.
However this may be, Dr. Darwin's name hasn’t been widely known to the public during the debates of the last thirty years. Mr. Charles Darwin, in the "historical sketch" he included in the later editions of his 'Origin of Species,' mentions, "It’s interesting how much my grandfather, Dr. Erasmus Darwin, anticipated the ideas and mistaken opinions of Lamarck in his 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. pp. 500-510, published in 1794."[155] He also notes a few lines later, "It's a rather unusual example of how similar ideas emerge around the same time that Goethe in Germany and Geoffroy St. Hilaire (as we will soon see) in France reached the same conclusion about the 'Origin of Species' between 1794 and 1796." Familiarity with Buffon's work will clarify much of the uniqueness, while anyone who knows the writings of Dr. Darwin and Étienne Geoffroy St. Hilaire would recognize that neither would agree that the other was "coming to the same conclusion," or even close, as he himself did. Dr. Darwin goes further than his successor, Lamarck, while Étienne Geoffroy doesn't even go as far as Dr. Darwin's predecessor, Buffon, had indicated he would. I have found no other reference to Dr. Darwin in the 'Origin of Species,' except the two just mentioned from the same note. In the first edition, there’s no mention of him at all.
The chief fault to be found with Dr. Darwin's treatise[Pg 197] on evolution is that there is not enough of it; what there is, so far from being "erroneous," is admirable. But so great a subject should have had a book to itself, and not a mere fraction of a book. If his opponents, not venturing to dispute with him, passed over one book in silence, he should have followed it up with another, and another, and another, year by year, as Buffon and Lamarck did; it is only thus that men can expect to succeed against vested interests. Dr. Darwin could speak with a freedom that was denied to Buffon. He took Buffon at his word as well as he could, and carried out his principles to what he conceived to be their logical conclusion. This was doubtless what Buffon had desired and reckoned on, but, as I have said already, I question how far Dr. Darwin understood Buffon's humour; he does not present any of the phenomena of having done so, and therefore I am afraid he must be said to have missed it.
The main issue with Dr. Darwin's book[Pg 197] on evolution is that it’s too short; what is there, far from being "wrong," is impressive. But such a big topic deserves a full book, not just a small part of one. If his critics, not daring to challenge him, ignored one book, he should have followed up with more, year after year, just like Buffon and Lamarck did; that’s the only way to make progress against established interests. Dr. Darwin was able to speak freely in a way Buffon could not. He interpreted Buffon’s ideas as best as he could and pushed them to what he thought was their logical conclusion. This was likely what Buffon wanted and expected, but, as I mentioned before, I doubt Dr. Darwin fully grasped Buffon's humor; he doesn’t show any signs of understanding it, so I’m afraid he missed the mark.
Like Buffon, Dr. Darwin had no wish to see far beyond the obvious; he missed good things sometimes, but he gained more than he lost; he knew that it is always on the margin, as it were, of the self-evident that the greatest purchase against the nearest difficulty is obtainable. His life was not one of Herculean effort, but, like the lives of all those organisms that are most likely to develop and transmit a useful modification, it was one of well-sustained activity; it was a long-continued keeping open of the windows of his own mind, much after the advice he gave to the Nottingham weavers. Dr. Darwin knew, and, I imagine, quite instinctively, that nothing tends to oversight like overseeing.[Pg 198] He does not trouble himself about the origin of life; as for the perceptions and reasoning faculties of animals and plants, it is enough for him that animals and plants do things which we say involve sensation and consciousness when we do them ourselves or see others do them. If, then, plants and animals appear as if they felt and understood, let the matter rest there, and let us say they feel and understand—being guided by the common use of language, rather than by any theories concerning brain and nervous system. If any young writer happens to be in want of a subject, I beg to suggest that he may find his opportunity in a 'Philosophy of the Superficial.'
Like Buffon, Dr. Darwin didn't seek to look too far beyond the obvious; he sometimes overlooked good things, but he gained more than he lost; he understood that the greatest solutions to immediate challenges are often found at the edges of what seems self-evident. His life wasn't one of massive effort, but like that of all organisms most likely to develop and pass on useful changes, it was characterized by consistent activity; it was a long-term commitment to keeping the windows of his mind open, much like the advice he gave to the Nottingham weavers. Dr. Darwin intuitively knew that nothing leads to oversight quite like being preoccupied with overseeing.[Pg 198] He didn't concern himself with the origins of life; regarding the perceptions and reasoning abilities of animals and plants, it was enough for him that they engage in actions we associate with sensation and consciousness when we or others do them. So, if plants and animals seem to feel and understand, let's leave it at that, and agree that they feel and understand—guided by common language rather than by any theories about the brain and nervous system. If any young writer is looking for a topic, I suggest they might find inspiration in a 'Philosophy of the Superficial.'
Though Dr. Darwin was more deeply impressed than Buffon with the oneness of personality between parents and offspring, so that these latter are not "new" creatures, but "elongations of the parents," and hence "may retain some of the habits of the parent system," he did not go on to infer definitely all that he might easily have inferred from such a pregnant premiss. He did not refer the repetition by offspring, of actions which their parents have done for many generations, but which they can never have seen those parents do, to the memory (in the strict sense of the word) of their having done those actions when they were in the persons of their parents; which memory, though dormant until awakened by the presence of associated ideas, becomes promptly kindled into activity when a sufficient number of these ideas are reproduced.
Though Dr. Darwin was more struck than Buffon by the idea that parents and their children share a fundamental personality, meaning that children are not "new" beings but rather "extensions of the parents," and therefore "may keep some of the habits of the parent system," he didn't fully explore all the implications of such a significant premise. He didn't connect the way children replicate actions their parents have performed for many generations—even when they have never witnessed those actions—to the memory (in the strictest sense) of having done those actions when they were part of their parents. This memory, though hidden until triggered by related ideas, quickly comes to life when a sufficient number of these ideas are brought back.
This, I gather, is the theory put forward by Professor Hering, of whose work, however, I know no more[Pg 199] than is told us by Professor Ray Lankester in an article which, appeared in 'Nature,' July 13th, 1876. This theory seems to be adopted by Professor Haeckel, and to receive support from Professor Ray Lankester himself. Knowing no German, I have been unable to make myself acquainted with Professor Hering's position in detail, but its similarity to, if not identity with, that taken by myself subsequently, but independently, in 'Life and Habit,' seems sufficiently established by the following extracts; it is to be wished, however, that a full account of this lecture were accessible to English readers. The extracts are as follows:—
This, as I understand it, is the theory proposed by Professor Hering, whose work I know only from what Professor Ray Lankester mentions in an article that appeared in 'Nature' on July 13, 1876. This theory seems to be accepted by Professor Haeckel and is supported by Professor Ray Lankester himself. Since I don't know German, I haven't been able to get a detailed understanding of Professor Hering's position, but its similarity to, if not complete alignment with, the one I later presented independently in 'Life and Habit' seems sufficiently established by the following excerpts. It would be great if a full account of this lecture were available to English readers. The excerpts are as follows:—
"Professor Hering has the merit of introducing some striking phraseology into his treatment of the subject which serves to emphasize the leading idea. He points out that since all transmission of 'qualities' from cell to cell in the growth and repair of one and the same organ, or from parent to offspring, is a transmission of vibrations or affections of material particles, whether these qualities manifest themselves as form, or as a facility for entering on a given series of vibrations, we may speak of all such phenomena as 'memory,' whether it be the conscious memory exhibited by the nerve cells of the brain or the unconscious memory we call habit, or the inherited memory we call instinct; or whether, again, it be the reproduction of parental form and minute structure. All equally may be called the 'memory of living matter.' From the earliest existence of protoplasm to the present day the memory of living matter is continuous. Though individuals die, the universal memory of living matter is carried on.
"Professor Hering deserves credit for introducing some striking language in his discussion of the topic, which highlights the main idea. He points out that since all transmission of 'qualities' from cell to cell in the growth and repair of the same organ, or from parent to offspring, involves the transfer of vibrations or influences of material particles—whether these qualities appear as form or as an ability to engage in a specific series of vibrations—we can refer to all these phenomena as 'memory.' This includes the conscious memory shown by the nerve cells in the brain, the unconscious memory we refer to as habit, the inherited memory known as instinct, and the reproduction of parental form and minute structure. All can be termed the 'memory of living matter.' From the earliest existence of protoplasm to now, the memory of living matter has been continuous. Even though individuals die, the universal memory of living matter continues."
"Professor Hering, in short, helps us to a comprehensive[Pg 200] conception of the nature of heredity and adaptation, by giving us the term 'memory' conscious or unconscious, for the continuity of Mr. Herbert Spencer's polar forces, or polarities of physiological units.
"Professor Hering, in short, provides us with a comprehensive[Pg 200] understanding of heredity and adaptation by introducing the term 'memory'—both conscious and unconscious—as a way to explain Mr. Herbert Spencer's polar forces or polarities of physiological units."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"The undulatory movement of the plastidules is the key to the mechanical explanation of all the essential phenomena of life. The plastidules are liable to have their undulations affected by every external force, and, once modified, the movement does not return to its pristine condition. By assimilation they continually increase to a certain point in size, and then divide, and thus perpetuate in the undulatory movement of successive generations, the impressions or resultants due to the action of external agencies on individual plastidules. This is Memory. All plastidules possess memory; and Memory which we see in its ultimate analysis is identical with reproduction, is the distinguishing feature of the plastidule; is that which it alone of all molecules possesses, in addition to the ordinary properties of the physicist's molecule; is, in fact, that which distinguishes it as vital. To the sensitiveness of the movement of plastidules is due Variability—to their unconscious Memory the power of Hereditary Transmission. As we know them to-day they may 'have learnt little, and forgotten nothing' in one organism, and 'have learnt much, and forgotten much' in another; but in all, their memory if sometimes fragmentary, yet reaches back to the dawn of life upon the earth.—E. Ray Lankester."[Pg 201]
"The wave-like motion of plastidules is crucial to understanding all the essential aspects of life. Plastidules are sensitive to external forces, and when their movements change, they don't go back to how they were originally. Through the process of assimilation, they keep growing in size until they reach a certain point, at which they divide, thus carrying on the wave-like motion of future generations, reflecting the effects of external influences on individual plastidules. This is Memory. All plastidules have memory; and when we break it down, Memory is the same as reproduction, which is what sets plastidules apart; it gives them a quality that no other molecules have, in addition to the standard properties of molecules in physics; it actually defines them as living. The sensitivity of plastidule movement leads to Variability, while their unconscious Memory provides the ability for Hereditary Transmission. As we understand them today, they can 'have learned little, and forgotten nothing' in one organism, and 'have learned much, and forgotten much' in another; but in all cases, their memory, although sometimes incomplete, stretches all the way back to the beginning of life on Earth.—E. Ray Lankester."[Pg 201]
Nothing can well be plainer and more uncompromising than the above. Professor Hering would, I gather, no less than myself, refer the building of its nest by a bird to the intense—but unconscious, owing to its very perfection and intensity—recollection by the bird of the nests it built when it was in the persons of its ancestors; this memory would begin to stimulate action when the surrounding associations, such as temperature, state of vegetation, &c., reminded it of the time when it had been in the habit of beginning to build in countless past generations. Dr. Darwin does not go so far as this. He says that wild birds choose spring as their building time "from their acquired knowledge that the mild temperature of the air is more convenient for hatching their eggs," and a little lower down he speaks of the fact that graminivorous animals generally produce their young in spring, as "part of the traditional knowledge which they learn from the example of their parents."[156]
Nothing can be clearer or more straightforward than the above. Professor Hering, like myself, believes that a bird’s nest-building comes from an intense—but unconscious, due to its very nature—memory of the nests built by its ancestors. This memory triggers action when the bird senses certain conditions, like temperature and the state of vegetation, reminding it of the times when it used to build nests in countless past generations. Dr. Darwin doesn’t go as far as this. He says that wild birds choose spring to build their nests "from their acquired knowledge that the mild temperature of the air is better for hatching their eggs," and he also mentions that herbivorous animals typically have their young in spring as "part of the traditional knowledge they learn from the example of their parents." [156]
Again he says, that birds "seem to be instructed how to build their nests from their observation of that in which they were educated, and from their knowledge of those things that are most agreeable to their touch in respect to warmth, cleanliness, and stability."
Again he says that birds "seem to learn how to build their nests from observing what they experienced during their upbringing, and from understanding what feels best to them in terms of warmth, cleanliness, and stability."
Had Dr. Darwin laid firmly hold of two superficial facts concerning memory which we can all of us test for ourselves—I mean its dormancy until kindled by the return of a sufficient number of associated ideas, and its unselfconsciousness upon becoming intense and perfect—and had he connected these two facts with the unity of life through successive generations—an idea[Pg 202] which plainly haunted him—he would have been saved from having to refer instinct to imitation, in the face of the fact that in a thousand instances the creature imitating can never have seen its model, save when it was a part of its parents,—seeing what they saw, doing what they did, feeling as they felt, and remembering what they remembered.
If Dr. Darwin had fully grasped two basic facts about memory that we can all easily verify—namely, that it lies dormant until triggered by a sufficient number of related ideas, and that it becomes unselfconscious when it is intense and perfect—and if he had linked these two facts to the continuity of life across generations—an idea[Pg 202] that clearly preoccupied him—he would have avoided having to attribute instinct to imitation, despite the fact that in countless cases, the creature imitating might never have seen its role model except when it was part of its parents—seeing what they saw, doing what they did, feeling as they felt, and remembering what they remembered.
Miss Seward tells us that Dr. Darwin read his chapter on instinct "to a lady who was in the habit of rearing canary birds. She observed that the pair which he then saw building their nest in her cage, were a male and female, who had been hatched and reared in that very cage, and were not in existence when the mossy cradle was fabricated in which they first saw light." She asked him, and quite reasonably, "how, upon his principle of imitation, he could account for the nest he then saw building, being constructed even to the precise disposal of every hair and shred of wool upon the model of that in which the pair were born, and on which every other canary bird's nest is constructed, when the proper materials are furnished. That of the pyefinch," she added, "is of much compacter form, warmer, and more comfortable. Pull one of these nests to pieces for its materials; and place another nest before these canary birds as a pattern, and see if they will make the slightest attempt to imitate their model! No, the result of their labour will, upon instinctive hereditary impulse, be exactly the slovenly little mansion of their race, the same with that which their parents built before themselves were hatched. The Doctor could not do away the force of that single[Pg 203] fact, with which his system was incompatible, yet he maintained that system with philosophic sturdiness, though experience brought confutation from a thousand sources."[157]
Miss Seward tells us that Dr. Darwin read his chapter on instinct "to a lady who regularly raised canary birds. She noticed that the pair he saw building their nest in her cage were a male and female, who had been hatched and raised in that very cage, and didn't exist when the mossy cradle was made in which they first saw light." She reasonably asked him, "how, based on his principle of imitation, could he explain the nest he was currently seeing being built, which was constructed with the exact arrangement of every hair and little piece of wool, just like that in which the pair were born, and on which every other canary bird's nest is made when the right materials are available? The nest of the pyefinch," she added, "is much more compact, warmer, and more comfortable. Take one of these nests apart for its materials; and place another nest in front of these canary birds as a template, and see if they will even attempt to imitate their model! No, their work will, driven by instinctive hereditary impulse, be exactly the messy little home of their species, just like the one their parents built before they were hatched. The Doctor couldn't dismiss the impact of that single[Pg 203] fact, which contradicted his theory, yet he held onto that theory with philosophical determination, even though experience contradicted it from countless directions."[157]
As commonly happens in such disputes, both were right and both were wrong. The lady was right in refusing to refer instinct to imitation, and the Doctor was right in maintaining reason and instinct to be but different degrees of perfection of the same mental processes. Had he substituted "memory" for "imitation," and asked the lady to define "sameness" or "personal identity," he would have soon secured his victory.
As often happens in these kinds of arguments, both were correct and both were mistaken. The woman was right to reject the idea that instinct is just imitation, and the Doctor was right to argue that reason and instinct are simply different levels of the same mental processes. If he had replaced "imitation" with "memory" and asked her to define "sameness" or "personal identity," he would have quickly won the debate.
The main fact, compared with which all else is a matter of detail, is the admission that instinct is only reason become habitual. This admission involves, consciously or unconsciously, the admission of all the principles contended for in 'Life and Habit'; principles which, if admitted, make the facts of heredity intelligible by showing that they are of the same character as other facts which we call intelligible, but denial of which makes nonsense of half the terms in common use concerning it. For the view that instinct is habitual reason involves sameness of personality and memory as common to parents and offspring; it involves also the latency of that memory till rekindled by the return of a sufficient number of its associated ideas, and points the unconsciousness with which habitual actions are performed. These principles being grasped, the infertility inter se of widely distant species, the commonly observed sterility of hybrids, the sterility of[Pg 204] certain animals and plants under confinement, the phenomena of old age as well as those of growth, and the principle which underlies longevity and alternate generations, follow logically and coherently, as I showed in 'Life and Habit.' Moreover, we find that the terms in common use show an unconscious sense that some such view as I have insisted on was wanted and would come, for we find them made and to hand already; few if any will require altering; all that is necessary is to take common words according to their common meanings.
The main point, compared to which everything else is just details, is that instinct is really just reason that has become habitual. Accepting this idea, whether we realize it or not, also means accepting all the principles discussed in 'Life and Habit'; these principles, if accepted, help explain hereditary facts by showing they are similar to other facts we understand, whereas rejecting them makes much of the language we use about it meaningless. The idea that instinct is habitual reason requires a continuity of personality and memory shared between parents and their children; it also includes the idea that this memory can be dormant until it’s brought back by a sufficient number of related ideas, highlighting the unconscious way habitual actions are carried out. Once we grasp these principles, understanding the infertility between widely different species, the common sterility of hybrids, the sterility of certain animals and plants in captivity, the phenomena of aging and growth, as well as the principles underlying longevity and alternating generations, all become clear and logical, as I explained in 'Life and Habit.' Additionally, we see that the commonly used terms reflect an unconscious recognition that a perspective like the one I've emphasized was needed and would emerge, because they already exist and are readily available; few, if any, will need to be changed; all that's necessary is to interpret common words according to their usual meanings.
Dr. Darwin is very good on this head. Here, as everywhere throughout his work, if things or qualities appear to resemble one another sufficiently and without such traits of unlikeness, on closer inspection, as shall destroy the likeness which was apparent at first, he connects them, all theories notwithstanding. I have given two instances of his manner of looking at instinct and reason.[158] "If these are not," he concludes, "deductions from their own previous experience, or observation, all the actions of mankind must be resolved into instincts."[159]
Dr. Darwin is really insightful on this topic. Here, as in the rest of his work, if things or qualities seem to resemble each other enough and don't show any noticeable differences upon a closer look that would undermine the initial similarity, he connects them, regardless of any theories. I've provided two examples of how he views instinct and reason.[158] "If these are not," he concludes, "deductions from their own previous experience, or observation, then all human actions must be reduced to instincts."[159]
If by "previous experience" we could be sure that Dr. Darwin persistently meant "previous experience in the persons of their ancestors," he would be in an impregnable position. As it is, we feel that though he had caught sight of the truth, and had even held it in his hands, yet somehow or other it just managed to slip through his fingers.
If by "previous experience" we could be certain that Dr. Darwin consistently meant "previous experience from their ancestors," he would be in a strong position. As it stands, we feel that although he glimpsed the truth and even held it briefly, it somehow slipped away from him.
"So flies burn themselves in candles, deceived like mankind by the misapplication of their knowledge."
"So flies burn themselves in candles, tricked like humans by their own misuse of knowledge."
Again:—
Again:—
"An ingenious philosopher has lately denied that animals can enter into contracts, and thinks this an essential difference between them and the human creature: but does not daily observation convince us that they form contracts of friendship with each other and with mankind? When puppies and kittens play together is there not a tacit contract that they will not hurt each other? And does not your favourite dog expect you should give him his daily food for his services and attention to you? And thus barters his love for your protection? In the same manner that all contracts are made among men that do not understand each other's arbitrary language."[160]
"An insightful philosopher has recently argued that animals can't enter into contracts, claiming this is a key difference between them and humans. But doesn’t everyday observation show us that they form friendships with each other and with people? When puppies and kittens play together, isn’t there an unspoken agreement that they won't hurt one another? And doesn’t your favorite dog expect you to provide his daily food in return for his loyalty and companionship? So, he exchanges his affection for your care, just like how contracts are formed among people who don’t understand each other’s arbitrary language."[160]
One more extract from a chapter full of excellent passages must suffice.
One more excerpt from a chapter filled with great passages should be enough.
"One circumstance I shall relate which fell under my own eye, and showed the power of reason in a wasp, as it is exercised among men. A wasp on a gravel walk had caught a fly nearly as large as himself; kneeling on the ground, I observed him separate the tail and the head from the body part, to which the wings were attached. He then took the body part in his paws, and rose about two feet from the ground with it; but a gentle breeze wafting the wings of the fly turned him round in the air, and he settled again with his prey upon the gravel. I then distinctly observed him cut off with his mouth first one of the wings and then the[Pg 206] other, after which he flew away with it, unmolested by the wind.
"There's one thing I'll share that I witnessed myself, which demonstrated the reasoning ability of a wasp, similar to how it's seen in humans. A wasp on a gravel path had caught a fly almost as big as itself; kneeling down, I watched it separate the tail and head from the body part, to which the wings were attached. Then, it grabbed the body part with its legs and lifted it about two feet off the ground; but a light breeze blew the wings of the fly, turning it around in the air, and it landed back on the gravel with its catch. I then clearly saw it use its mouth to cut off one of the wings and then the other, after which it flew away with the body, unaffected by the wind."
"Go, proud reasoner, and call the worm thy sister!"[161]
"Go ahead, proud thinker, and call the worm your sister!"[161]
Dr. Darwin's views on the essential unity of animal and vegetable life are put forward in the following admirable chapter on "Vegetable Animation," which I will give in full, and which is confirmed in all important respects by the latest conclusions of our best modern scientists, so, at least, I gather from Mr. Francis Darwin's interesting lecture.[162]
Dr. Darwin's ideas about the fundamental connection between animal and plant life are presented in the following excellent chapter on "Vegetable Animation," which I will share in its entirety. These ideas are also supported by the latest findings of our top modern scientists, at least according to Mr. Francis Darwin's engaging lecture.[162]
"I. 1. The fibres of the vegetable world, as well as those of the animal, are excitable into a variety of motion by irritations of external objects. This appears particularly in the mimosa or sensitive plant, whose leaves contract on the slightest injury: the Dionæa muscipula, which was lately brought over from the marshes of America, presents us with another curious instance of vegetable irritability; its leaves are armed with spines on their upper edge, and are spread on the ground around the stem; when an insect creeps on any of them in its passage to the flower or seed, the leaf shuts up like a steel rat-trap, and destroys its enemy.[163]
I. 1. The fibers of both the plant world and the animal world can respond with various movements when they are stimulated by external objects. This is especially noticeable in the mimosa, or sensitive plant, whose leaves close at the slightest touch. The Dionæa muscipula, which was recently brought over from the marshes of America, offers another fascinating example of plant sensitivity; its leaves have spines along the upper edge and spread out on the ground around the stem. When an insect crawls onto any of them while making its way to the flower or seeds, the leaf snaps shut like a steel rat-trap and captures its prey.[163]
"The various secretions of vegetables as of odour, fruit, gum, resin, wax, honey, seem brought about in the same manner as in the glands of animals; the tasteless moisture of the earth is converted by the hop plant into a bitter juice; as by the caterpillar in the nutshell, the sweet powder is converted into a bitter powder.[Pg 207] While the power of absorption in the roots and barks of vegetables is excited into action by the fluids applied to their mouths like the lacteals and lymphatics of animals.
"The different secretions from plants, like their smells, fruit, gum, resin, wax, and honey, seem to happen in a way similar to how it works in animal glands. The tasteless moisture from the earth is transformed by the hop plant into a bitter juice, just as the caterpillar turns sweet powder in the nutshell into a bitter one.[Pg 207] Meanwhile, the absorption power in the roots and barks of plants is activated by fluids applied to their surfaces, much like the lacteals and lymphatics in animals."
"2. The individuals of the vegetable world may be considered as inferior or less perfect animals; a tree is a congeries of many living buds, and in this respect resembles the branches of the coralline, which are a congeries of a multitude of animals. Each of these buds of a tree has its proper leaves or petals for lungs, produces its viviparous or its oviparous offspring in buds or seeds; has its own roots, which, extending down the stem of the tree, are interwoven with the roots of the other buds, and form the bark, which is the only living part of the stem, is annually renewed and is superinduced upon the former bark, which then dies, and, with its stagnated juices gradually hardening into wood, forms the concentric circles which we see in blocks of timber.
"2. The individuals in the plant world can be seen as less complex animals. A tree is made up of many living buds, similar to how the branches of coral are made up of numerous animals. Each bud on a tree has its own leaves or petals that act like lungs, produces its offspring either through buds or seeds, and has its own roots. These roots extend down from the tree’s stem, intertwining with the roots of other buds, and form the bark, which is the only living part of the stem. The bark is renewed each year and layers on top of the old bark, which then dies and, as its juices stagnate and harden, forms wood and the concentric circles we see in timber."
"The following circumstances evince the individuality of the buds of trees. First, there are many trees whose whole internal wood is perished, and yet the branches are vegete and healthy. Secondly, the fibres of the bark of trees are chiefly longitudinal, resembling roots, as is beautifully seen in those prepared barks that were lately brought from Otaheita. Thirdly, in horizontal wounds of the bark of trees, the fibres of the upper lip are always elongated downwards like roots, but those of the lower lip do not approach to meet them. Fourthly, if you wrap wet moss round any joint of a vine, or cover it with moist earth, roots will shoot[Pg 208] out from it. Fifthly, by the inoculation or engrafting of trees many fruits are produced from one stem. Sixthly, a new tree is produced from a branch plucked from an old one and set in the ground. Whence it appears that the buds of deciduous trees are so many annual plants, that the bark is a contexture of the roots of each individual bud, and that the internal wood is of no other use but to support them in the air, and that thus they resemble the animal world in their individuality.
"The following circumstances show the uniqueness of tree buds. First, there are many trees where the entire inner wood is dead, yet the branches are still vibrant and healthy. Second, the fibers of tree bark mostly run longitudinally, resembling roots, which is beautifully illustrated in the prepared barks recently brought from Otaheita. Third, in horizontal wounds on tree bark, the fibers of the upper side always stretch downwards like roots, while those of the lower side do not meet them. Fourth, if you wrap wet moss around any joint of a vine or cover it with moist soil, roots will shoot out from it. Fifth, through grafting or inoculating trees, many fruits can be produced from a single stem. Sixth, a new tree can grow from a branch taken from an old one and planted in the ground. Thus, it appears that the buds of deciduous trees are like annual plants, that the bark serves as a network for the roots of each individual bud, and that the inner wood is only there to support them in the air, showing their uniqueness similar to that of the animal world."
"The irritability of plants, like that of animals, appears liable to be increased or decreased by habit; for those trees or shrubs which are brought from a colder climate to a warmer, put out their leaves and blossoms a fortnight sooner than the indigenous ones.
"The sensitivity of plants, like that of animals, seems to be affected by their environment; for those trees or shrubs that are moved from a colder climate to a warmer one produce their leaves and flowers about two weeks earlier than the local ones."
"Professor Kalm, in his travels in New York, observes that the apple trees brought from England blossom a fortnight sooner than the native ones. In our country, the shrubs that are brought a degree or two from the north are observed to flourish better than those which come from the south. The Siberian barley and cabbage are said to grow larger in this climate than the similar more southern vegetables; and our hoards of roots, as of potatoes and onions, germinate with less heat in spring, after they have been accustomed to the winter's cold, than in autumn, after the summer's heat.
"Professor Kalm, while traveling in New York, notices that the apple trees brought from England bloom two weeks earlier than the native ones. In our country, shrubs that come from slightly north of us tend to thrive better than those that come from the south. It's said that Siberian barley and cabbage grow larger in this climate compared to similar vegetables from further south; and our supplies of roots, like potatoes and onions, sprout with less warmth in spring, after experiencing the winter cold, than they do in autumn, following summer's heat."
"II. The stamens and pistils of flowers show evident marks of sensibility, not only from many of the stamens and some pistils approaching towards each other at the season of impregnation, but from many of them closing their petals and calyxes during the cold part of the[Pg 209] day. For this cannot be ascribed to irritation, because cold means a defect of the stimulus of heat; but as the want of accustomed stimuli produces pain, as in coldness, hunger, and thirst of animals, these motions of vegetables in closing up their flowers must be ascribed to the disagreeable sensation, and not to the irritation of cold. Others close up their leaves during darkness, which, like the former, cannot be owing to irritation, as the irritating material is withdrawn.
"II. The stamens and pistils of flowers clearly show signs of sensitivity, not just because many of the stamens and some pistils move closer together during the time of fertilization, but also because many of them close their petals and calyxes during the colder parts of the[Pg 209] day. This response can't be attributed to irritation since cold implies a lack of the heat stimulus; however, just like the absence of familiar stimuli leads to discomfort—like in the coldness, hunger, and thirst experienced by animals—these movements of plants in closing their flowers must be linked to an unpleasant sensation, rather than irritation from the cold. Other plants also close their leaves in darkness, which, similar to the previous case, cannot be due to irritation since the irritating factor is no longer present."
"The approach of the anthers in many flowers to the stigmas, and of the pistils of some flowers to the anthers, must be ascribed to the passion of love, and hence belongs to sensation, not to irritation.
"The way the anthers in many flowers move toward the stigmas, and how the pistils of some flowers approach the anthers, should be attributed to the passion of love, and therefore relates to sensation, not irritation."
"III. That the vegetable world possesses some degree of voluntary powers appears from their necessity to sleep, which we have shown in Section XVIII. to consist in the temporary abolition of voluntary power. This voluntary power seems to be exerted in the circular movement of the tendrils of the vines, and other climbing vegetables; or in the efforts to turn the upper surfaces of their leaves, or their flowers, to the light.
"III. The plant world has some level of voluntary abilities, as we demonstrated in Section XVIII, which involves a temporary loss of voluntary power during sleep. This voluntary power appears to be at work in the circular movement of the tendrils of vines and other climbing plants, as well as in their attempts to orient the upper surfaces of their leaves or flowers towards the light."
"IV. The associations of fibrous motions are observable in the vegetable world as well as in the animal. The divisions of the leaves of the sensitive plant have been accustomed to contract at the same time from the absence of light; hence, if by any other circumstance, as a slight stroke or injury, one division is irritated into contraction, the neighbouring ones contract also from their motions being associated with those of the irritated part. So the various stamina of the class of[Pg 210] syngenesia have been accustomed to contract together in the evening, and thence if you stimulate any one of them with a pin, according to the experiment of M. Colvolo, they all contract from their acquired associations.
"IV. The connections of fibrous movements can be seen in both the plant and animal worlds. The sections of the leaves of the sensitive plant usually shrink together when it's dark; therefore, if one section is triggered to contract due to some external factor, like a small touch or injury, the nearby sections contract too because their movements are linked to that of the affected part. Similarly, the various stamens in the hybrid class of [Pg 210] syngenesia also tend to contract together in the evening. So, if you poke any one of them with a pin, as shown in M. Colvolo's experiment, they all contract due to their established connections."
"To evince that the collapsing of the sensitive plant is not owing to any mechanical vibrations propagated along the whole branch when a single leaf is struck with the finger, a leaf of it was slit with sharp scissors, with as little disturbance as possible, and some seconds of time passed before the plant seemed sensible of the injury, and then the whole branch collapsed as far as the principal stem. This experiment was repeated several times with the least possible impulse to the plant.
"To show that the wilting of the sensitive plant isn’t caused by mechanical vibrations traveling through the entire branch when just one leaf is touched, a leaf was carefully cut with sharp scissors, causing minimal disturbance. Several seconds passed before the plant reacted to the injury, and then the whole branch drooped all the way to the main stem. This experiment was repeated several times with the least possible impact on the plant."
"V. 1. For the numerous circumstances in which vegetable buds are analogous to animals, the reader is referred to the additional notes at the end of 'Botanic Garden,' Part I. It is there shown that the roots of vegetables resemble the lacteal system of animals; the sap vessels in the early spring, before their leaves expand, are analogous to the placental vessels of the fœtus; that the leaves of land plants resemble lungs, and those of aquatic plants the gills of fish; that there are other systems of vessels resembling the vena portarum of quadrupeds, or the aorta of fish; that the digestive power of vegetables is similar to that of animals converting the fluids which they absorb into sugar;[164] that their seeds resemble the eggs of animals,[Pg 211] and their buds and bulbs their viviparous offspring; and lastly, that the anthers and stigmas are real animals attached to their parent tree like polypi or coral insects, but capable of spontaneous motion; that they are affected with the passion of love, and furnished with powers of reproducing their species, and are fed with honey like the moths and butterflies which plunder their nectaries.[165]
V. 1. For the many ways that plant buds are similar to animals, please check the additional notes at the end of 'Botanic Garden,' Part I. It shows that the roots of plants are like the lacteal system of animals; the sap vessels in early spring, before their leaves open up, are similar to the placental vessels of a fetus; the leaves of land plants are comparable to lungs, while those of aquatic plants are like fish gills; there are other vessels similar to the vena portarum of quadrupeds or the aorta of fish; the digestive process of plants is akin to that of animals, turning the fluids they take in into sugar;[164] their seeds are like animal eggs,[Pg 211] and their buds and bulbs resemble their live births; finally, the anthers and stigmas are actual creatures connected to their parent tree like polyps or coral insects, but capable of moving on their own; they experience love and have the ability to reproduce their kind, and they are nourished with nectar like the moths and butterflies that take from their flowers.[165]
"The male flowers of Vallisneria approach still nearer to apparent animality, as they detach themselves from the parent plant, and float on the surface of the water to the female ones.[166] Other flowers of the classes of monœcia and diœcia, and polygamia discharge the fecundating farina, which, floating in the air, is carried to the stigma of the female flowers, and that at considerable distances. Can this be effected by any specific attraction? Or, like the diffusion of the odorous particles of flowers, is it left to the currents of the winds, and the accidental miscarriages of it counteracted by the quantity of its production?
"The male flowers of Vallisneria get even closer to looking like animals as they detach from the parent plant and float on the water's surface to the female flowers.[166] Other flowers from the groups of monoecious and dioecious, and polygamous plants release their fertilizing pollen, which floats in the air and is carried to the stigma of the female flowers, even over long distances. Can this happen due to a specific attraction? Or, like how fragrant particles of flowers spread, is it left to the wind currents, with any mishaps being balanced out by the sheer amount of pollen produced?
"2. This leads us to a curious inquiry, whether vegetables have ideas of external things? As all our ideas are originally received by our senses, the question may be changed to whether vegetables possess any organs of sense? Certain it is that they possess a sense of heat and cold, another of moisture and dryness, and another of light and darkness, for they close their petals occasionally from the presence of cold, moisture, or darkness. And it has been already shown that these actions[Pg 212] cannot be performed simply from irritation, because cold and darkness are negative quantities, and on that account sensation, or volition are implied, and in consequence a sensorium or union of their nerves. So when we go into the light we contract the iris; not from any stimulus of the light on the fine muscles of the iris, but from its motions being associated with the sensation of too much light upon the retina, which could not take place without a sensorium or centre of union of the nerves of the iris, with those of vision.[167]
"2. This raises an interesting question: do plants have perceptions of the outside world? Since all our ideas come from our senses, we might ask if plants have any sensory organs. It’s clear that they can sense heat and cold, moisture and dryness, and light and darkness, because they sometimes close their petals in response to cold, moisture, or darkness. It has already been shown that these actions[Pg 212] can't just be the result of irritation, as cold and darkness are not active forces. This implies some form of sensation or intent, which suggests a connection of their nerves. For instance, when we enter a bright space, our iris contracts not merely due to the light stimulating the iris muscles, but because the movement is linked to the sensation of overwhelming light on the retina, which wouldn’t occur without a sensory center connecting the iris nerves to those of vision.[167]
"Besides these organs of sense, which distinguish cold, moisture, and darkness, the leaves of mimosa, and of dionæa, and of drosera, and the stamens of many flowers, as of the berbery, and the numerous class of syngenesia, are sensible to mechanic impact, that is, they possess a sense of touch, as well as a common sensorium, by the medium of which their muscles are excited into action. Lastly, in many flowers the anthers, when mature, approach the stigma, in others the female organ approaches to the male. In a plant of collinsonia, a branch of which is now before me, the two yellow stamens are about three-eighths of an inch high, and diverge from each other at an angle of about fifteen degrees, the purple style is half an inch high, and in some flowers is now applied to the stamen on the right hand, and in others to that of the left; and will, I suppose, change place to-morrow in those, where the anthers have not yet effused their powder.
"Besides these sensory organs, which detect cold, moisture, and darkness, the leaves of mimosa, dionae, and drosera, as well as the stamens of many flowers like barberry and various members of syngenesia, are responsive to mechanical impact, meaning they have a sense of touch, along with a common sensory system that activates their muscles. Lastly, in many flowers, the anthers, when mature, move closer to the stigma, while in others, the female organ moves towards the male. In a plant of collinsonia, a branch of which is in front of me, the two yellow stamens stand about three-eighths of an inch tall and diverge at an angle of about fifteen degrees. The purple style is half an inch high and, in some flowers, aligns with the stamen on the right, while in others, it aligns with the left; I expect it will switch places tomorrow in those where the anthers haven't released their pollen yet."
"I ask by what means are the anthers in many flowers and stigmas in other flowers directed to find[Pg 213] their paramours? How do either of them know that the other exists in their vicinity? Is this curious kind of storge produced by mechanic attraction, or by the sensation of love? The latter opinion is supported by the strongest analogy, because a reproduction of the species is the consequence; and then another organ of sense must be wanted to direct these vegetable amourettes to find each other, one probably analogous to our sense of smell, which in the animal world directs the new-born infant to its source of nourishment, and they may thus possess a faculty of perceiving as well as of producing odours.
"I wonder how the anthers in many flowers and the stigmas in other flowers manage to find each other[Pg 213]? How do they even know that the other is nearby? Is this strange kind of attraction due to mechanical forces, or is it a feeling of love? The second idea seems more plausible, as it leads to the reproduction of the species; however, another sense must be involved to help these plant romances connect, likely similar to our sense of smell, which guides newborn animals to their source of food, suggesting they might have the ability to sense as well as produce odors."
"Thus, besides a kind of taste at the extremity of their roots, similar to that of the extremities of our lacteal vessels, for the purpose of selecting their proper food, and besides different kinds of irritability residing in the various glands, which separate honey, wax, resin, and other juices from their blood; vegetable life seems to possess an organ of sense to distinguish the variations of heat, another to distinguish the varying degrees of moisture, another of light, another of touch, and probably another analogous to our sense of smell. To these must be added the indubitable evidence of their passion of love, and I think we may truly conclude that they are furnished with a common sensorium for each bud, and that they must occasionally repeat those perceptions, either in their dreams or waking hours, and consequently possess ideas of so many of the properties of the external world, and of their own existence."[168]
"Thus, in addition to having a kind of taste at the tips of their roots, similar to what we have at the ends of our lacteal vessels, which helps them select their food, and aside from the various types of irritability in the different glands that extract honey, wax, resin, and other juices from their sap; plant life seems to have sensory organs to detect changes in heat, moisture, light, touch, and possibly another sense like our sense of smell. We should also consider the undeniable evidence of their capacity for love, leading us to reasonably conclude that they have a common sensory experience for each bud, and that they must sometimes revisit those experiences, either in their dreams or while awake, which means they are aware of many qualities of the outside world and their own existence."[168]
FOOTNOTES:
[156] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 170.
[159] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 184.
[160] 'Zoonomia,' p. 171.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 'Zoonomia,' p. 171.
[161] 'Zoonomia,' p. 187.
[168] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 107.
FULLER QUOTATIONS FROM THE 'ZOONOMIA.'
FULLER QUOTES FROM THE 'ZOONOMIA.'
The following are the passages in the 'Zoonomia' which have the most important bearing on evolution:—
The following are the passages in the 'Zoonomia' that are most significant to evolution:—
"The ingenious Dr. Hartley, in his work on man, and some other philosophers have been of opinion, that our immortal part acquires during this life certain habits of action or of sentiment which become for ever indissoluble, continuing after death in a future state of existence; and add that if these habits are of the malevolent kind, they must render their possessor miserable even in Heaven. I would apply this ingenious idea to the generation or production of the embryon or new animal, which partakes so much of the form and propensities of its parent.
"The clever Dr. Hartley, in his work on humanity, along with some other philosophers, believes that our eternal part develops certain habits of action or feeling during this life that become permanently fixed, lasting even after death in a future existence. They also suggest that if these habits are negative, they can cause their owner to be unhappy even in Heaven. I'd like to apply this clever idea to the creation of the embryo or new animal, which shares so much in form and tendencies with its parent."
"Owing to the imperfection of language the offspring is termed a new animal, but is in truth a branch or elongation of the parent, since a part of the embryon-animal is, or was, a part of the parent, and therefore in strict language, cannot be said to be entirely new at the time of its production; and, therefore, it may retain some of the habits of the parent system.
Because language is imperfect, the offspring is called a new animal, but it’s really a continuation or extension of the parent, since part of the embryo was, or is, a part of the parent. Therefore, in precise terms, it can't be considered completely new at the time it's created, and it may keep some of the habits of the parent species.
"At the earliest period of its existence the embryon would seem to consist of a living filament with certain capabilities of irritation, sensation, volition, and association,[Pg 215] and also with some acquired habits or propensities peculiar to the parents; the former of these are in common with other animals; the latter seem to distinguish or produce the kind of animal, whether man or quadruped, with the similarity of feature or form to the parent."[169]
"At the earliest stage of its existence, the embryo appears to be a living thread with certain abilities for irritation, sensation, will, and association,[Pg 215] along with some learned habits or tendencies unique to the parents. The first abilities are shared with other animals; the latter seem to define or create the type of animal, whether human or four-legged, resembling the parent in features or shape."[169]
Going on to describe the gradual development of the embryo, Dr. Darwin continues:—
Going on to explain the gradual development of the embryo, Dr. Darwin continues:—
"As the want of this oxygenation of the blood is perpetual (as appears from the incessant necessity of breathing by lungs or gills), the vessels become extended by the efforts of pain or desire to seek this necessary object of oxygenation, and to remove the disagreeable sensations which this want occasions."[170]
"As the need for this oxygen in the blood is constant (as shown by the continuous need to breathe through lungs or gills), the vessels stretch from the efforts of discomfort or the desire to find this essential source of oxygen, and to alleviate the unpleasant feelings that this need causes."[170]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"The lateral production of plants by wires, while each new plant is thus chained to its parent, and continues to put forth another and another as the wire creeps onward on the ground, is exactly resembled by the tape-worm or tænia, so often found in the bowels, stretching itself in a chain quite from the stomach to the rectum. Linnæus asserts 'that it grows old at one extremity, while it continues to generate younger ones at the other, proceeding ad infinitum like a sort of grass; the separate joints are called gourd worms, and propagate new joints like the parent without end, each joint being furnished with its proper mouth and organs of digestion.'"[171]
"The lateral growth of plants through wires, where each new plant remains connected to its parent and keeps producing one after another as the wire moves along the ground, is exactly similar to a tapeworm, which is often found in the intestines, stretching itself in a chain from the stomach to the rectum. Linnaeus states that it ages at one end while continuously generating younger ones at the other, proceeding ad infinitum like a type of grass; the individual segments are known as gourd worms and create new segments just like the parent without end, with each segment equipped with its own mouth and digestive organs." [171]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"Many ingenious philosophers have found so great difficulty in conceiving the manner of the reproduction of animals, that they have supposed all the numerous progeny to have existed in miniature in the animal originally created; and that these infinitely minute forms are only evolved or distended, as the embryon increases in the womb. This idea, besides its being unsupported by any analogy we are acquainted with, ascribes a greater tenuity to organized matter than we can readily admit; as these included embryons are supposed each of them to consist of the various and complicate parts of animal bodies, they must possess a much greater degree of minuteness than that which was ascribed to the devils which tempted St. Anthony, of whom 20,000 were said to have been able to dance a saraband on the point of the finest needle without incommoding one another."[172]
"Many clever philosophers have found it really hard to understand how animals reproduce, so they imagined that all the countless offspring were already present in miniature in the original animal. They thought these tiny forms just grow or expand as the embryo develops in the womb. This idea, besides lacking any analogy we know of, suggests that organized matter is thinner than we can easily accept; since these tiny embryos are believed to each consist of the various and complex parts of animal bodies, they would have to be much smaller than the devils that tempted St. Anthony, who were said to be able to dance a saraband on the tip of the finest needle without bothering one another."[172]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"I conceive the primordium or rudiment of the embryon as secreted from the blood of the parent to consist of a simple living filament as a muscular fibre; which I suppose to be an extremity of a nerve of locomotion, as a fibre of the retina is an extremity of a nerve of sensation; as, for instance, one of the fibrils which compose the mouth of an absorbent vessel. I suppose this living filament of whatever form it may be, whether sphere, cube, or cylinder, to be endued with the capability of being excited into action by certain kinds of stimulus. By the stimulus of the surrounding fluid in which it is received from the male[Pg 217] it may bend into a ring, and thus form the beginning of a tube. Such moving filaments and such rings are described by those who have attended to microscopic animalculæ. This living ring may now embrace or absorb a nutritive particle of the fluid in which it swims; and by drawing it into its pores, or joining it by compression to its extremities, may increase its own length or crassitude, and by degrees the living ring may become a living tube.
"I think of the earliest form of the embryo as something secreted from the parent’s blood, consisting of a simple living strand like a muscle fiber. I believe this strand is an end part of a movement nerve, just like a fiber from the retina is the end part of a sensation nerve; for example, one of the fibers that make up the opening of an absorbent vessel. I assume this living strand, regardless of its shape—whether it's a sphere, cube, or cylinder—has the ability to be activated by certain kinds of stimuli. By the stimulus of the surrounding fluid it receives from the male[Pg 217], it may curve into a ring, thus starting to form a tube. Microscopic animal studies describe such moving strands and rings. This living ring can now surround or absorb a nutrient particle from the fluid it’s in; by drawing it into its pores or attaching it through compression to its edges, it may grow in length or thickness, gradually transforming the living ring into a living tube."
"With this new organization, or accretion of parts, new kinds of irritability may commence; for so long as there was but one living organ it could only be supposed to possess irritability; since sensibility may be conceived to be an extension of the effect of irritability over the rest of the system. These new kinds of irritability and of sensibility in consequence of new organization appear from variety of facts in the more mature animals; thus ... the lungs must be previously formed before their exertions to obtain fresh air can exist; the throat, or œsophagus, must be formed previous to the sensation or appetites of hunger and thirst, one of which seems to reside at the upper end and the other at the lower end of that canal."[173]
"With this new organization, or combination of parts, new kinds of irritability may start to develop; as long as there was only one living organ, it could only be assumed to have irritability since sensibility can be thought of as an expansion of the effects of irritability throughout the rest of the system. These new kinds of irritability and sensibility that arise from the new organization are evident from various observations in more mature animals; for example, the lungs must be fully formed before they can function to take in fresh air; the throat, or esophagus, must be formed before the feelings of hunger and thirst can occur, with one feeling seeming to originate at the top and the other at the bottom of that canal." [173]
It seems to me Dr. Darwin is wrong in supposing that the organ must have preceded the power to use it. The organ and its use—the desire to do and the power to do—have always gone hand in hand, the organism finding itself able to do more according as it advanced its desires, and desiring to do more simultaneously with any increase in power, so that neither[Pg 218] appetency nor organism can claim precedence, but power and desire must be considered as Siamese twins begotten together, conceived together, born together, and inseparable always from each other. At the same time they are torn by mutual jealousy; each claims, with some vain show of reason, to have been the elder brother; each intrigues incessantly from the beginning to the end of time to prevent the other from outstripping him; each is in turn successful, but each is doomed to death with the extinction of the other.
It seems to me that Dr. Darwin is mistaken in thinking that the organ had to come before the ability to use it. The organ and its use—the desire to act and the ability to act—have always gone together. The organism finds itself capable of doing more as it develops its desires and simultaneously wants to do more as its abilities increase. Therefore, neither[Pg 218] desire nor organism can claim priority; power and desire should be seen as inseparably linked, created together, born together, and always connected to each other. At the same time, they are in constant competition; each claims, with some misguided reasoning, to be the older sibling, and both continually work to prevent the other from getting ahead. Each experiences victories in turn, but both are destined to vanish alongside the other.
"So inflamed tendons and membranes, and even bones, acquire new sensations; and the parts of mutilated animals, as of wounded snails and polypi and crabs, are reproduced; and at the same time acquire sensations adapted to their situation. Thus when the head of a snail is reproduced after decollation with a sharp razor, those curious telescopic eyes are also reproduced, and acquire their sensibility to light, as well as their adapted muscles for retraction on the approach of injury.
"So inflamed tendons and membranes, and even bones, gain new sensations; and the parts of mutilated animals, like wounded snails, polypi, and crabs, regenerate while also developing sensations suited to their circumstances. So, when the head of a snail is regrown after being cut off with a sharp blade, those fascinating telescopic eyes are also regrown and develop their sensitivity to light, along with the muscles that help retract in response to potential harm."
"With every change, therefore, of organic form or addition of organic parts, I suppose a new kind of irritability or of sensibility to be produced; such varieties of irritability or of sensibility exist in our adult state in the glands; every one of which is furnished with an irritability or a taste or appetency, and a consequent mode of action peculiar to itself.
"With every change in organic form or addition of organic parts, I think a new kind of irritability or sensitivity is created; these different types of irritability or sensitivity exist in our adult bodies in the glands; each of which has its own irritability or taste or desire, and a unique way of acting."
"In this manner I conceive the vessels of the jaws to produce those of the teeth; those of the fingers to produce the nails; those of the skin to produce the hair; in the same manner as afterwards, about the age[Pg 219] of puberty, the beard and other great changes in the form of the body and disposition of the mind are produced in consequence of new developments; for, if the animal is deprived of these developments, those changes do not take place. These changes I believe to be formed not by elongation or distension of primeval stamina, but by apposition of parts; as the mature crab fish when deprived of a limb, in a certain space of time, has power to regenerate it; and the tadpole puts forth its feet after its long exclusion from the spawn, and the caterpillar in changing into a butterfly acquires a new form with new powers, new sensations, and new desires."[174]
"In this way, I understand that the structures in the jaw create the teeth; those in the fingers create the nails; and those in the skin create the hair; similarly, around the time of puberty, the beard and other significant changes in the body's shape and mental state occur due to new developments. If an animal does not experience these developments, those changes do not happen. I believe these changes are not caused by stretching or expanding the original materials but by the addition of new parts. For example, a mature crab can regenerate a limb after losing it within a certain timeframe, the tadpole grows legs after a long time spent as a spawn, and a caterpillar transforms into a butterfly, gaining a new form, new abilities, new sensations, and new desires."[174]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"From hence I conclude that with the acquisition of new parts, new sensations and new desires, as well as new powers are produced; and this by accretion to the old ones and not by distension of them. And finally, that the most essential parts of the system, as the brain for the purpose of distributing the powers of life, and the placenta for the purpose of oxygenating the blood, and the additional absorbent vessels, for the purpose of acquiring aliment, are first formed by the irritations above mentioned, and by the pleasurable sensations attending those irritations, and by the exertions in consequence of painful sensations similar to those of hunger and suffocation. After these an apparatus of limbs for future uses, or for the purpose of moving the body in its present natant state, and of lungs for future respiration, and of testes for future reproduction, are formed[Pg 220] by the irritations and sensations and consequent exertions of the parts previously existing, and to which the new parts are to be attached.[175]
"From this, I conclude that with the development of new parts, new sensations and desires, as well as new abilities, emerge; and this happens by adding to the existing ones rather than stretching them. Finally, the most essential parts of the system, like the brain for distributing life's functions, the placenta for oxygenating the blood, and the extra absorbent vessels for gathering nutrients, are initially formed by the irritations mentioned above, along with the pleasurable sensations that accompany those irritations, and by the efforts resulting from painful sensations similar to those of hunger and suffocation. After these, an arrangement of limbs for future use, or for moving the body in its current state, lungs for future breathing, and testes for future reproduction, are created through the irritations, sensations, and subsequent efforts of the existing parts to which the new parts will be attached.[Pg 220]"
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"The embryon" must "be supposed to be a living filament, which acquires or makes new parts, with new irritabilities as it advances in its growth."[176]
"The embryo" must "be considered as a living thread that develops new parts and new sensitivities as it grows."[176]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"From this account of reproduction it appears that all animals have a similar origin, viz. a single living filament; and that the difference of their forms and qualities has arisen only from the different irritabilities and sensibilities, or voluntarities, or associabilities, of this original living filament, and perhaps in some degree from the different forms of the particles of the fluids by which it has at first been stimulated into activity."[177]
"From this description of reproduction, it seems that all animals come from a similar source: a single living filament. The differences in their shapes and qualities have emerged solely due to the varying levels of irritability, sensitivity, willfulness, or ability to associate of this original living filament, and possibly to some extent from the different shapes of the particles in the fluids that initially stimulated it into action."[177]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"All animals, therefore, I contend, have a similar cause of their organization, originating from a single living filament, endued with different kinds of irritabilities and sensibilities, or of animal appetencies, which exist in every gland, and in every moving organ of the body, and are as essential to living organism as chemical affinities are to certain combinations of inanimate matter.
"All animals, I argue, have a similar reason for their structure, coming from a single living thread, equipped with various types of reactions and sensitivities, or animal desires, which are found in every gland and in every moving part of the body, and are as crucial to living organisms as chemical attractions are to specific combinations of non-living matter."
"If I might be indulged to make a simile in a philosophical work, I should say that the animal appetencies are not only perhaps less numerous originally than the chemical affinities, but that, like these latter, they change with every fresh combination; thus vital air and azote,[Pg 221] when combined, produce nitrous acid, which now acquires the property of dissolving silver; so that with every new additional part to the embryon, as of the throat or lungs, I suppose a new animal appetency to be produced."[178]
"If I could use a comparison in a philosophical discussion, I’d say that animal instincts are probably fewer in number than chemical connections at the start, but like those connections, they change with every new combination. For example, when oxygen and nitrogen combine, they create nitrous acid, which now has the ability to dissolve silver. So with every new part added to the embryo, like the throat or lungs, I believe a new animal instinct emerges."[Pg 221][178]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
Here, again, it should be insisted on that neither can the "additional part" precede "the appetency," nor the appetency precede the additional part for long together—the two advance nearly pari passu; sometimes the power a little ahead of the desire, stimulates the desire to an activity it would not otherwise have known; as those who have more money than they once had, feel new wants which they would not have known if they had not obtained the power to gratify them; sometimes, on the other hand, the desire is a little more active than the power, and pulls the power up to itself by means of the effort made to gratify the desire—as those who want a little more of this or that than they have money to pay for, will try all manner of shifts to earn the additional money they want, unless it is so much in excess of their present means that they give up the endeavour as hopeless; but whichever gets ahead, immediately sets to work to pull the other level with it, the getting ahead either of power or desire being exclusively the work of external agencies, while the coming up level of the other is due to agencies that are incorporate with the organism itself. Thus an unusually abundant supply of food, due to causes entirely beyond the control of the individual, is an[Pg 222] external agency; it will immediately set power a little ahead of desire. On this the individual will eat as much as it can—thus learning pro tanto to be able to eat more, and to want more under ordinary circumstances—and will also breed rapidly up to the balance of the abundance. This is the work of the agencies incorporate in the organism, and will bring desire level with power again. Famine, on the other hand, puts desire ahead of power, and the incorporate agencies must either bring power up by resource and invention, or must pull desire back by eating less, both as individuals, and as the race, that is to say, by breeding less freely; for breeding is an assimilation of outside matter so closely akin to feeding, that it is only the feeding of the race, as against that of the individual.
Here, again, it's important to emphasize that the "additional part" can't come before "the desire," nor can the desire come before the additional part for too long—the two progress almost simultaneously; sometimes the power is slightly ahead of the desire, which boosts the desire to an activity it wouldn’t have otherwise experienced; like those who have more money than before, feel new wants that they wouldn’t have recognized if they hadn’t gained the ability to satisfy them; sometimes, on the flip side, the desire is a bit more active than the power, and it pulls the power up to match it through the effort to fulfill the desire—just like people who want a bit more of something than they can afford will try various ways to earn the extra money they need, unless it's so much beyond their current means that they give up the effort as futile; but whichever takes the lead quickly works to bring the other up to its level, with the advance of either power or desire being entirely the result of external factors, while the leveling up of the other comes from forces built into the organism itself. So, an unusually plentiful supply of food, due to reasons entirely outside the individual's control, is an external factor; it will immediately lead the power to exceed the desire for a bit. On this, the individual will eat as much as it can—thus learning to eat more and want more under normal circumstances—and will also reproduce rapidly to match the abundance. This is the result of the natural forces within the organism, aiming to bring desire in line with power once again. Famine, however, places desire ahead of power, and the internal mechanisms must either enhance power through resourcefulness and creativity, or curb desire by consuming less, both as individuals and as a species, meaning they breed less freely; because breeding is an assimilation of external matter so similar to feeding that it is essentially the feeding of the species, as opposed to that of the individual.
I do not think the reader will find any clearer manner of picturing to himself the development of organism than by keeping the normal growth of wealth continually in his mind. He will find few of the phenomena of organic development which have not their counterpart in the acquisition of wealth. Thus a too sudden acquisition, owing to accidental and external circumstances and due to no internal source of energy, will be commonly lost in the next few generations. So a sudden sport due to a lucky accident of soil will not generally be perpetuated if the offspring plant be restored to its normal soil. Again, if the advance in power carry power suddenly far beyond any past desire, or be far greater than any past-remembered advance of power beyond desire—then desire will not come up level easily, but only with difficulty and all manner of[Pg 223] extravagance, such as is likely to destroy the power itself. Demand and Supply are also good illustrations.
I don’t think the reader will find a clearer way to visualize the development of an organism than by constantly considering the normal growth of wealth. There are very few phenomena of organic development that don’t have a parallel in accumulating wealth. For example, if wealth is acquired suddenly through random external factors and not through any internal source of energy, it is likely to be lost in the following generations. Similarly, a sudden mutation caused by a fortunate soil condition usually won’t be sustained if the new plant is returned to its usual soil. Additionally, if gaining power suddenly exceeds past desires or is much greater than any previously experienced increase in power, then desire won’t rise to match it easily; instead, it will do so with great difficulty and often through various forms of[Pg 223] extravagance that are likely to undermine that power. Demand and Supply also serve as good examples.
But to return to Dr. Darwin.
But let's get back to Dr. Darwin.
"When we revolve in our minds," he writes, "first the great changes which we see naturally produced in animals after their nativity, as in the production of the butterfly with painted wings from the crawling caterpillar; or of the respiring frog from the subnatant tadpole; from the boy to the bearded man, from the infant girl to the woman,—in both which cases mutilation will prevent due development.
"When we think about it," he writes, "first the significant changes that we naturally observe in animals after they are born, like how a colorful butterfly emerges from a crawling caterpillar; or how a breathing frog develops from a swimming tadpole; from a boy to a bearded man, and from an infant girl to a woman—mutilation will hinder proper development in both cases."
"Secondly, when we think over the great changes introduced into various animals by artificial or accidental cultivation, as in horses, which we have exercised for the different purposes of strength or swiftness, in carrying burthens or in running races, or in dogs which have been cultivated for strength and courage, as the bull-dog; or for acuteness of his sense of smell, as the hound or spaniel; or for the swiftness of his foot, as the greyhound; or for his swimming in the water or for drawing snow sledges, as the rough-haired dogs of the north; or, lastly, as a play dog for children, as the lapdog; with the changes of the forms of the cattle which have been domesticated from the greatest antiquity, as camels and sheep, which have undergone so total a transformation that we are now ignorant from what species of wild animal they had their origin. Add to these the great changes of shape and colour which we daily see produced in smaller animals from our domestication of them, as rabbits or pigeons, or from the difference of climates and even of seasons; thus the[Pg 224] sheep of warm climates are covered with hair instead of wool; and the hares and partridges of the latitudes which are long buried in snow become white during the winter months; add to these the various changes produced in the forms of mankind by their early modes of exertion, or by the diseases occasioned by their habits of life, both of which become hereditary, and that through many generations. Those who labour at the anvil, the oar, or the loom, as well as those who carry sedan chairs or who have been educated to dance upon the rope, are distinguishable by the shape of their limbs; and the diseases occasioned by intoxication deform the countenance with leprous eruptions, or the body with tumid viscera, or the joints with knots and distortions.
"Secondly, when we consider the significant changes brought about in various animals through artificial or accidental breeding, like horses, which we have trained for different purposes such as strength or speed, for carrying loads or racing, or dogs that have been bred for strength and bravery, like bulldogs; or for their keen sense of smell, like hounds or spaniels; or for their speed, like greyhounds; or for swimming or pulling sleds in the snow, like the rough-haired dogs from the north; or finally, as companion animals for children, like lapdogs; we also see the changes in domesticated cattle, like camels and sheep, which have transformed so completely that we no longer know their wild ancestors. Additionally, we observe the significant changes in the shape and color of smaller animals from our domestication efforts, such as rabbits or pigeons, or due to variations in climate and seasons; for instance, the [Pg 224] sheep from warm areas have hair instead of wool, and hares and partridges in snow-covered regions turn white during winter. We should also consider the various changes in human forms from their early activities or from diseases caused by their lifestyles, both of which can become hereditary over generations. Those who work at the anvil, row, or weave, as well as those who carry sedan chairs or are trained to perform acrobatics, can be recognized by the shape of their limbs. Furthermore, diseases resulting from heavy drinking can distort the face with leprous eruptions, cause the body to swell with internal issues, or lead to joint deformities."
"Thirdly, when we enumerate the great changes produced in the species of animals before their nativity, as, for example, when the offspring reproduces the effects produced upon the parent by accident or cultivation; or the changes produced by the mixture of species, as in mules; or the changes produced probably by the exuberance of nourishment supplied to the fetus, as in monstrous births with additional limbs; many of these enormities of shape are propagated and continued as a variety at least, if not as a new species of animal. I have seen a breed of cats with an additional claw on every foot; of poultry also with an additional claw, and with wings to their feet; and of others without rumps. Mr. Buffon mentions a breed of dogs without tails which are common at Rome and Naples—which he supposes to have been produced by a custom long established of cutting their tails close off. There are many kinds of[Pg 225] pigeons admired for their peculiarities which are more or less thus produced and propagated.[179]
"Thirdly, when we list the significant changes that occur in animal species before they are born, such as when the offspring reflects the effects of accidents or cultivation experienced by the parents; or the changes arising from the mixing of species, like in mules; or the changes possibly caused by an abundance of nourishment supplied to the fetus, leading to unusual births with extra limbs; many of these abnormalities in shape are passed down and continue as at least a variation, if not as a new species of animal. I have seen a breed of cats with an extra claw on each paw; chickens with an extra claw and wings on their feet; and others without rumps. Mr. Buffon mentions a breed of dogs without tails that are common in Rome and Naples, which he believes were created by the long-standing practice of cutting their tails off. There are also many types of [Pg 225] pigeons celebrated for their unique traits that have been similarly produced and passed down.[179]"
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"When we consider all these changes of animal form and innumerable others which may be collected from the books of natural history, we cannot but be convinced that the fetus or embryon is formed by apposition of new parts, and not by the distention of a primordial nest of germs included one within another like the cups of a conjurer.
"When we look at all these changes in animal shapes and countless others that can be found in natural history books, we can't help but believe that the fetus or embryo is created by adding new parts instead of just stretching a basic layer of germs that are nested inside each other like the cups of a magician."
"Fourthly, when we revolve in our minds the great similarity of structure which obtains in all the warm-blooded animals, as well quadrupeds, birds, and amphibious animals, as in mankind; from the mouse and bat to the elephant and whale; one is led to conclude that they have alike been produced from a similar living filament. In some this filament in its advance to maturity has acquired hands and fingers with a fine sense of touch, as in mankind. In others it has acquired claws or talons, as in tigers and eagles. In others, toes with an intervening web or membrane, as in seals and geese. In others it has acquired cloven hoofs, as in cows and swine; and whole hoofs in others, as in the horse: while in the bird kind this original living filament has put forth wings instead of arms or legs, and feathers instead of hair. In some it has protruded horns on the forehead instead of teeth in the fore part of the upper jaw; in others, tusks instead of horns; and in the others, beaks instead of either. And all this exactly as is seen daily in the transmutation of[Pg 226] the tadpole, which acquires legs and lungs when he wants them, and loses his tail when it is no longer of service to him.
"Fourthly, when we think about the strong similarities in the structure of all warm-blooded animals, including quadrupeds, birds, amphibians, and humans; from mice and bats to elephants and whales; it leads us to conclude that they all have come from a common living thread. In some, this thread has developed into hands and fingers with a keen sense of touch, like in humans. In others, it has formed claws or talons, as seen in tigers and eagles. In some cases, it has resulted in toes with webbing in between, like in seals and geese. In others, it has created split hooves, as in cows and pigs, and solid hooves in others, like in horses. In birds, this original living thread has transformed into wings instead of arms or legs, and feathers instead of fur. In some, it has developed horns on the head instead of teeth at the front of the upper jaw; in others, tusks instead of horns; and in others, beaks instead of either. And all of this is just like what we observe daily in the transformation of[Pg 226] the tadpole, which grows legs and lungs when it needs them, and loses its tail when it's no longer useful."
"Fifthly, from their first rudiment or primordium to the termination of their lives, all animals undergo perpetual transformations; which are in part produced by their own exertions in consequence of their desires and aversions, of their pleasures and their pains, or of irritations or of associations; and many of these acquired forms or propensities are transmitted to their posterity.
"Fifthly, from their initial stage to the end of their lives, all animals go through constant changes; some of which are caused by their own efforts due to their desires and dislikes, their joys and their sufferings, or from irritations or associations; and many of these learned traits or tendencies are passed down to their offspring."
"As air and water are supplied to animals in sufficient profusion, the three great objects of desire which have changed the forms of many animals by their desires to gratify them are those of lust, hunger, and security. A great want of one part of the animal world has consisted in the desire of the exclusive possession of the females; and these have acquired weapons to combat each other for this purpose, as the very thick, shield-like, horny skin on the shoulder of the boar is a defence only against animals of his own species who strike obliquely upwards, nor are his tusks for other purposes except to defend himself, as he is not naturally a carnivorous animal. So the horns of the stag are sharp to offend his adversary, but are branched for the purpose of parrying or receiving the thrust of horns similar to his own, and have therefore been formed for the purpose of combating other stags, for the exclusive possession of the females; who are observed like the ladies in the times of chivalry to attend the car of the victor.
"As animals have plenty of air and water, the three main desires that have transformed many species are lust, hunger, and security. A significant need in the animal kingdom has been the desire to exclusively possess females. Males have developed features to compete for them; for example, the thick, shield-like, tough skin on a boar’s shoulder protects it from rivals who attack from the side, and its tusks are primarily for defense, as boars aren’t naturally meat-eaters. Similarly, the stag has sharp horns to fend off opponents, but they are also branched to block or absorb the blows from other stags’ horns, designed specifically for fighting over females, who are often observed, much like ladies in chivalric times, attending the victors."
"The birds which do not carry food to their young,[Pg 227] and do not therefore marry, are armed with spurs for the purpose of fighting for the exclusive possession of the females, as cocks and quails. It is certain that these weapons are not provided for their defence against other adversaries, because the females of these species are without this armour. The final cause of this contest among the males seems to be that the strongest and most active animal should propagate the species, which should thence become improved."[180]
"The birds that don’t bring food to their young,[Pg 227] and therefore don’t mate, have spurs for the purpose of fighting for exclusive access to the females, like roosters and quails. It’s clear that these weapons aren’t meant for defending against other threats, since the females of these species lack this armor. The ultimate reason for this competition among the males appears to be that the strongest and most active individuals should reproduce, which would improve the species over time." [180]
Dr. Darwin would have been on stronger ground if he had said that the effect of the contest among the males was that the fittest should survive, and hence transmit any fit modifications which had occurred to them as vitally true, rather than that the desire to attain this end had caused the contest; but either way the sentence just given is sufficient to show that he was not blind to the fact that the fittest commonly survive, and to the consequences of this fact. The use, however, of the word "thence," as well as of the expression "final cause," is loose, as Dr. Darwin would no doubt readily have admitted. Improvement in the species is due quite as much, by Dr. Darwin's own showing, to the causes which have led to such and such an animal's making itself the fittest, as to the fact that if fittest it will be more likely to survive and transmit its improvement. There have been two factors in modification; the one provides variations, the other accumulates them; neither can claim exclusive right to the word "thence," as though the modification was due to it and to it only. Dr. Darwin's use of the word "thence"[Pg 228] here is clearly a slip, and nothing else; but it is one which brings him for the moment into the very error into which his grandson has fallen more disastrously.
Dr. Darwin would have been on firmer ground if he had said that the effect of competition among males was that the fittest survive and therefore pass on any advantageous traits they have developed, rather than suggesting that the desire to achieve this outcome caused the competition. Either way, the statement above clearly shows that he recognized the fact that the fittest tend to survive and the implications of this reality. However, the use of the word "thence" and the phrase "final cause" is vague, as Dr. Darwin would likely have acknowledged. Improvement in a species is just as much due, according to Dr. Darwin himself, to the reasons that enable certain animals to become the fittest, as it is to the fact that being the fittest increases their chances of surviving and passing on their improvements. There are two factors in the process of change; one provides variations and the other accumulates them; neither can claim sole credit for the term "thence," as if the change were solely due to one. Dr. Darwin's use of "thence" [Pg 228] here is clearly a mistake, but it’s one that momentarily leads him into the very error that his grandson has fallen into, but more severely.
"Another great want," he continues, "consists in the means of procuring food, which has diversified the forms of all species of animals. Thus the nose of the swine has become hard for the purpose of turning up the soil in search of insects and of roots. The trunk of the elephant is an elongation of the nose for the purpose of pulling down the branches of trees for his food, and for taking up water without bending his knees. Beasts of prey have acquired strong jaws or talons. Cattle have acquired a rough tongue and a rough palate to pull off the blades of grass, as cows and sheep. Some birds have acquired harder beaks to crack nuts, as the parrot. Others have acquired beaks to break the harder seeds, as sparrows. Others for the softer kinds of flowers, or the buds of trees, as the finches. Other birds have acquired long beaks to penetrate the moister soils in search of insects or roots, as woodcocks, and others broad ones to filtrate the water of lakes and to retain aquatic insects. All which seem to have been gradually produced during many generations by the perpetual endeavour of the creature to supply the want of food, and to have been delivered to their posterity with constant improvement of them for the purposes required.
"Another important need," he continues, "is finding food, which has changed how all animal species look. For example, the pig's nose has become tough so it can dig up soil to find insects and roots. The elephant's trunk is an extended nose that helps it reach tree branches for food and drink water without bending down. Predatory animals have strong jaws or claws. Cattle have developed a rough tongue and palate to graze on grass, like cows and sheep do. Some birds have stronger beaks for cracking nuts, like parrots. Others have beaks designed to break hard seeds, like sparrows. Some are adapted for softer flowers or tree buds, like finches. Other birds have long beaks to probe moist soil for insects or roots, like woodcocks, while some have broad beaks to filter water in lakes and catch aquatic insects. All of these adaptations seem to have gradually developed over many generations through the constant effort of the creature to meet its food needs, and have been passed down to their offspring with ongoing improvements to meet those needs.
"The third great want among animals is that of security, which seems to have diversified the forms of their bodies and the colour of them; these consist in the means of escaping other animals more powerful than themselves. Hence some animals have acquired[Pg 229] wings instead of legs, as the smaller birds, for purposes of escape. Others, great length of fin or of membrane, as the flying fish and the bat. Others have acquired hard or armed shells, as the tortoise and the Echinus marinus.
"The third major need among animals is security, which appears to have influenced the variety of their shapes and colors; these adaptations help them escape from predators stronger than they are. As a result, some animals have developed[Pg 229] wings instead of legs, like smaller birds, for the purpose of fleeing. Others have gained longer fins or membranes, such as flying fish and bats. Some have developed tough or armored shells, like turtles and the Echinus marinus.
"Mr. Osbeck, a pupil of Linnæus, mentions the American frog-fish, Lophius Histrio, which inhabits the large floating islands of sea-weed about the Cape of Good Hope, and has fulcra resembling leaves, that the fishes of prey may mistake it for the sea-weed, which it inhabits.[181]
"Mr. Osbeck, a student of Linnæus, talks about the American frog-fish, Lophius Histrio, which lives in the large floating islands of seaweed near the Cape of Good Hope and has leaf-like structures to help it blend in, so that predatory fish might confuse it with the seaweed it resides in.[181]
"The contrivances for the purposes of security extend even to vegetables, as is seen in the wonderful and various means of their concealing or defending their honey from insects and their seeds from birds. On the other hand, swiftness of wing has been acquired by hawks and swallows to pursue their prey; and a proboscis of admirable structure has been acquired by the bee, the moth, and the humming bird for the purpose of plundering the nectaries of flowers. All which seem to have been formed by the original living filament, excited into action by the necessities of the creatures which possess them, and on which their existence depends.
The ways that living things protect themselves even extend to plants, as seen in the amazing and diverse methods they use to hide their nectar from insects and their seeds from birds. Meanwhile, birds like hawks and swallows have gained swift wings to chase after their prey, and insects like bees, moths, and hummingbirds have developed incredible mouthparts to feed on flower nectar. All these adaptations appear to have come from a fundamental life force, activated by the needs of the creatures that have them, which their survival relies on.
"From thus meditating on the great similarity of the structure of the warm-blooded animals, and at the same time of the great changes they undergo both before and after their nativity; and by considering in how minute a portion of time many of the changes of animals above described have been produced; would it be too bold to imagine that in the great length of time[Pg 230] since the earth began to exist, perhaps millions of ages before the commencement of the history of mankind—would it be too bold to imagine that all warm-blooded animals have arisen from one living filament, which the Great First Cause endued with animality, with the power of attaining new parts, attended with new propensities, directed by irritations, sensations, volitions, and associations; and thus possessing the faculty of continuing to improve, by its own inherent activity, and of delivering down those improvements by generation to its posterity world without end!
"By reflecting on the striking similarities in the structure of warm-blooded animals and the significant changes they go through both before and after birth, and by thinking about how quickly many of the changes in the animals described above have occurred, would it be too much to suggest that over the vast stretches of time since the earth came into existence—perhaps millions of years before human history began—would it be too much to suggest that all warm-blooded animals have descended from a single living thread, which the Great First Cause infused with life, granted the ability to develop new traits, influenced by various stimuli, sensations, decisions, and connections; thus having the capacity to continue improving through its own innate activity and pass those improvements down through generations endlessly!"
"Sixthly, the cold-blooded animals, as the fish tribes, which are furnished with but one ventricle of the heart, and with gills instead of lungs, and with fins instead of feet or wings, bear a great similarity to each other; but they differ nevertheless so much in their general structure from the warm-blooded animals, that it may not seem probable at first view that the same living filament could have given origin to this kingdom of animals, as to the former. Yet are there some creatures which unite or partake of both these orders of animation, as the whales and seals; and more particularly the frog, who changes from an aquatic animal furnished with gills to an aerial one furnished with lungs.
"Sixthly, cold-blooded animals like fish have only one ventricle in their hearts, gills instead of lungs, and fins instead of feet or wings, showing a strong resemblance to one another. However, they are still quite different in overall structure from warm-blooded animals, so it might initially seem unlikely that the same living source could have led to the existence of both groups. Still, there are some creatures that have characteristics of both types, such as whales and seals; and particularly the frog, which transforms from a water-dwelling creature with gills to a land-dwelling one with lungs."
"The numerous tribes of insects without wings, from the spider to the scorpion, from the flea to the lobster; or with wings, from the gnat or the ant to the wasp and the dragon-fly, differ so totally from each other, and from the red-blooded classes above described, both in the forms of their bodies and in their modes of life; besides the organ of sense, which they seem to possess[Pg 231] in their antennæ or horns, to which it has been thought by some naturalists that other creatures have nothing similar; that it can scarcely be supposed that this nature of animals could have been produced by the same kind of living filament as the red-blooded classes above mentioned. And yet the changes which many of them undergo in their early state to that of their maturity, are as different as one animal can be from another. As those of the gnat, which passes his early state in water, and then stretching out his new wings and expanding his new lungs, rises in the air; as of the caterpillar and bee-nymph, which feed on vegetable leaves or farina, and at length bursting from their self-formed graves, become beautiful winged inhabitants of the skies, journeying from flower to flower, and nourished by the ambrosial food of honey.
"The many tribes of wingless insects, from spiders to scorpions, from fleas to lobsters; or winged ones, from gnats and ants to wasps and dragonflies, are so completely different from each other and from the red-blooded animals mentioned earlier, both in body shape and way of life. They also seem to have a unique organ of sense in their antennae or horns, which some naturalists believe other creatures don’t possess at all. It's hard to imagine that these creatures could have originated from the same living filament as the red-blooded animals talked about before. Yet, the transformations many of them undergo from their early stages to maturity are as different as one animal can be from another. For example, the gnat spends its early life in water and then, stretching out its new wings and expanding its lungs, takes to the air; similarly, the caterpillar and bee pupa, which feed on leaves or pollen, eventually break out of their self-made cocoons to become beautiful flying creatures, flitting from flower to flower and nourished by the sweet food of honey.[Pg 231]"
"There is still another class of animals which are termed vermes by Linnæus, which are without feet or brain, and are hermaphrodites, as worms, leeches, snails, shell-fish, coralline insects, and sponges, which possess the simplest structure of all animals, and appear totally different from those already described. The simplicity of their structure, however, can afford no argument against their having been produced from a single living filament, as above contended.
There’s another group of animals called vermes by Linnæus, which are footless, brainless, and hermaphroditic, including worms, leeches, snails, shellfish, coralline insects, and sponges. They have the simplest structure of all animals and seem completely different from the ones we've talked about before. However, their simple structure doesn’t argue against the idea that they came from a single living filament, as mentioned earlier.
"Last of all, the various tribes of vegetables are to be enumerated amongst the inferior orders of animals. Of these the anthers and stigmas have already been shown to possess some organs of sense, to be nourished by honey, and to have the power of generation like insects, and have thence been announced amongst the animal[Pg 232] kingdom in Section XIII.; and to these must be added the buds and bulbs, which constitute the viviparous offspring of vegetation. The former I suppose to be beholden to a single living filament for their seminal or amatorial procreation; and the latter to the same cause for their lateral or branching generation, which they possess in common with the polypus, tænia, and volvox, and the simplicity of which is an argument in favour of the similarity of its cause.
"Finally, the different types of vegetables should be counted among the lower orders of animals. It has already been shown that the anthers and stigmas have some sensory organs, are nourished by nectar, and can reproduce like insects, and because of this, they are classified within the animal[Pg 232] kingdom in Section XIII. Additionally, we must include the buds and bulbs, which are the living offspring of plants. I believe the former rely on a single living filament for their sexual or amorous reproduction, while the latter depend on the same source for their horizontal or branching growth, which they share with the polyp, tape worm, and volvox, and this simplicity suggests a common cause."
"Linnæus supposes, in the introduction to his natural orders, that very few vegetables were at first created, and that their numbers were increased by their intermarriages, and adds, 'Suaderet hæc Creatoris leges a simplicibus ad composita.' Many other changes appear to have arisen in them by their perpetual contest for light and air above ground, and for food or moisture beneath the soil. As noted in the 'Botanic Garden,' Part II., note on Cuscuta. Other changes of vegetables from climate or other causes are remarked in the note on Curcuma in the same work. From these one might be led to imagine that each plant at first consisted of a single bulb or flower to each root, as the gentianella and daisy, and that in the contest for air and light, new buds grew on the old decaying flower-stem, shooting down their elongated roots to the ground, and that in process of ages tall trees were thus formed, and an individual bulb became a swarm of vegetables. Other plants which in this contest for light and air were too slender to rise by their own strength, learned by degrees to adhere to their neighbours, either by putting forth roots like the ivy, or by tendrils like the[Pg 233] vine, or by spiral contortions like the honeysuckle, or by growing upon them like the mistleto, and taking nourishment from their barks, or by only lodging or adhering on them and deriving nourishment from the air as tillandsia.
"Linnaeus suggests in the introduction to his natural orders that very few plants were initially created, and that their numbers increased through interbreeding. He adds, 'This would support the Creator's laws from simple to complex.' Many other changes seem to have come about through their constant struggle for light and air above ground and for food or moisture below the soil. As mentioned in the 'Botanic Garden,' Part II., note on Cuscuta. Other changes in plants due to climate or other reasons are noted in the reference to Curcuma in the same work. From this, one might think that each plant initially had a single bulb or flower per root, like gentianella and daisy, and that in their struggle for air and light, new buds developed on the old, decaying flower-stem, sending down elongated roots into the ground. Over ages, this process led to the formation of tall trees, transforming a single bulb into a cluster of plants. Other plants, which were too weak to stand on their own in this battle for light and air, gradually learned to cling to their neighbors by either putting down roots like ivy, or using tendrils like the vine, or by twisting like honeysuckle, or growing on them like mistletoe, drawing nourishment from their bark, or simply resting on them and extracting nutrients from the air like tillandsia."
"Shall we then say that the vegetable living filament was originally different from that of each tribe of animals above described? And that the productive living filament of each of those tribes was different from the other? Or as the earth and ocean were probably peopled with vegetable productions long before the existence of animals; and many families of these animals, long before other families of them, shall we conjecture that one and the same kind of living filament is and has been the cause of all organic life?[182]
"Should we then conclude that the living plant filament was originally different from that of each animal group mentioned earlier? And that the productive living filament of each of those groups was distinct from the others? Since the earth and oceans were likely filled with plant life long before animals existed, and many groups of these animals appeared long before others, should we suppose that one single type of living filament is and has been the source of all organic life?[182]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"The late Mr. David Hume in his posthumous works places the powers of generation much above those of our boasted reason, and adds, that reason can only make a machine, as a clock or a ship, but the power of generation makes the maker of the machine; and probably from having observed that the greatest part of the earth has been formed out of organic recrements, as the immense beds of limestone, chalk, marble, from the shells of fish; and the extensive provinces of clay, sandstone, ironstone, coals, from decomposed vegetables; all of which have been first produced by generation, or by the secretion of organic life; he concludes that the world itself might have been generated rather than created; that it might have been gradually produced[Pg 234] from very small beginnings, increasing by the activity of its inherent principles, rather than by a sudden evolution of the whole by the Almighty fire. What a magnificent idea of the infinite power of the great Architect! The Cause of causes! Parent of parents! Ens entium!"[183]
The late Mr. David Hume, in his posthumous works, suggests that the powers of generation far exceed those of our praised reason. He argues that reason can only create machines like clocks or ships, but generation is what creates the maker of those machines. He likely noticed that much of the earth is made up of organic remains, like the massive deposits of limestone, chalk, and marble from fish shells, as well as vast areas of clay, sandstone, ironstone, and coal from decomposed plants. All of these materials originated from generation or the secretion of organic life. He concludes that the world might have been generated instead of created, that it could have gradually come into existence from very small beginnings, growing through the activity of its inherent principles rather than being suddenly formed by a supreme power. What a magnificent idea of the infinite power of the great Architect! The root of all causes! Parent of parents! Hooray!
FOOTNOTES:
[169] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 484.
[170] Ibid. p. 485.
Ibid. p. 485.
[171] Ibid. p. 493.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 493.
[172] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 494.
[173] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 497.
[174] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 498.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 'Zoonomia,' vol. 1, p. 498.
[175] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 500.
[176] Ibid. p. 501.
Ibid. p. 501.
[177] Ibid. p. 502.
Ibid. p. 502.
[178] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 503.
[179] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 505.
[180] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 507.
[181] 'Voyage to China,' p. 113.
[182] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 511.
[183] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 513.
MEMOIR OF LAMARCK.
Lamarck's Memoir.
I take the following memoir of Lamarck entirely from the biographical sketch prefixed by M. Martins to his excellent edition of the 'Philosophie Zoologique.'[184] From this sketch I find that "Lamarck was born August 1, 1744, at Barenton, in Picardy, being the eleventh child of Pierre de Monet, squire of the place, a man of old family, but poor. His father intended him for the Church, the ordinary resource of younger sons at that time, and accordingly placed him under the care of the Jesuits at Amiens. But this was not his vocation: the annals of his family spoke all to him of military glory; his eldest brother had died in the breaches at the siege of Bergen-op-Zoom; two others were still serving in the army, and France was exhausting her energies in an unequal struggle. His father would not yield to his wishes, but on his death, in 1760, Lamarck was left free to take his own line, and made his way at once—upon a very bad horse—to the army of Germany, then encamped at Lippstadt in Westphalia.
I take the following memoir of Lamarck completely from the biographical sketch written by M. Martins in his excellent edition of the 'Philosophie Zoologique.'[184] From this sketch, I learn that "Lamarck was born on August 1, 1744, in Barenton, Picardy, as the eleventh child of Pierre de Monet, a squire of the area, who came from an old family but was poor. His father wanted him to enter the Church, the usual path for younger sons at that time, and therefore placed him under the care of the Jesuits in Amiens. However, this wasn't his calling: the history of his family was filled with tales of military honor; his eldest brother had died during the siege of Bergen-op-Zoom, two others were still serving in the army, and France was exhausting its resources in an unfair fight. His father wouldn't give in to his desires, but after his death in 1760, Lamarck was free to choose his own path, and he set out immediately—on a very poor horse—to join the army of Germany, which was then camped at Lippstadt in Westphalia.
"He was the bearer of a letter written by Madame de Lameth, one of his neighbours in the country, and recommending him to M. de Lastic, colonel of the[Pg 236] regiment of Beaujolais. This gentleman, on seeing before him a lad of seventeen, whose somewhat stunted growth made him look still younger than he really was, sent the youth immediately to his own quarters. The next day a battle was immediately impending, and M. de Lastic, on passing his regiment in review, saw his protégé in the first rank of a company of grenadiers. The French army was under the orders of the Marshal de Broglie and of the Prince de Soubise; the allied troops were commanded by Ferdinand of Brunswick. The two French generals were beaten owing to their divided counsels, and Lamarck's company, almost annihilated by the enemy's fire, was forgotten in the confusion of the retreat. All the officers, commissioned and non-commissioned, were killed, and only fourteen men out of the whole company remained alive: the eldest proposed to retreat, but Lamarck, improvising himself as commander, declared that they ought not to retire without orders. Presently the colonel seeing that this company did not rally sent an orderly officer who made his way up to it by protected paths. Next day Lamarck was made an officer, and shortly afterwards lieutenant.
"He carried a letter written by Madame de Lameth, one of his neighbors in the countryside, recommending him to M. de Lastic, the colonel of the [Pg 236] regiment of Beaujolais. When this gentleman saw a seventeen-year-old boy before him, whose somewhat short stature made him look even younger, he immediately sent the young man to his own quarters. The next day, a battle was about to begin, and M. de Lastic, while reviewing his regiment, spotted his protégé in the front row of a company of grenadiers. The French army was under the command of Marshal de Broglie and Prince de Soubise, while the allied troops were led by Ferdinand of Brunswick. The two French generals were defeated due to their conflicting strategies, and Lamarck's company, nearly wiped out by the enemy's fire, was overlooked in the chaos of the retreat. All the officers, both commissioned and non-commissioned, were killed, leaving only fourteen men from the entire company alive. The oldest soldier suggested retreating, but Lamarck, stepping up as the leader, insisted that they shouldn't fall back without orders. Soon, the colonel realizing that this company wasn't regrouping, sent a messenger who found a safe route to reach them. The following day, Lamarck was promoted to officer, and shortly after, to lieutenant."
"Fortunately for science," continues M. Martins, "this brilliant début was not to decide his career. After peace had been signed he was sent into garrison at Toulon and Monaco, where an inflammation of the lymphatic ganglions of the neck necessitated an operation which left him deeply scarred for life.
"Fortunately for science," M. Martins continues, "this impressive début did not determine his career. After peace was established, he was assigned to garrison duty in Toulon and Monaco, where an inflammation of the lymphatic glands in his neck required surgery that left him permanently scarred."
"The vegetation in the neighbourhood of Toulon and Monaco now arrested the young officer's attention. He[Pg 237] had already derived some little knowledge of botany from the 'Traité des Plantes usuelles' of Chomel. Having retired from the service, and having nothing beyond his modest pension of four hundred francs a year, he took a situation at Paris with a banker; but drawn irresistibly to the study of nature, he used to study from his attic window the forms and movements of clouds, and made himself familiar with the plants in the Jardin du Roi or in the public gardens. He began to feel that he was on his right path, and understood, as Voltaire said of Condorcet, that discoveries of permanent value could make him no less illustrious than military glory.
The plants around Toulon and Monaco caught the young officer's attention. He[Pg 237] had picked up some basic knowledge of botany from Chomel's 'Traité des Plantes usuelles'. After retiring from the military and living on his modest pension of four hundred francs a year, he got a job in Paris with a banker. However, he felt a strong pull towards studying nature, and often spent time at his attic window observing the shapes and movements of clouds, getting to know the plants in the Jardin du Roi and public gardens. He started to realize that he was following the right path and understood, like Voltaire said of Condorcet, that discoveries of lasting value could make him just as famous as military achievements.
"Dissatisfied with the botanical systems of his time, in six months he wrote his 'Flore française,' preceded by the 'Clé dichotomique,' with the help of which it is easy even for a beginner to arrive with certainty at the name of the plant before him." Of this work, M. Martins tells us in a note, that the second edition, published by Candolle in 1815, is still the standard work on French plants.
"Dissatisfied with the plant classification systems of his time, within six months he wrote his 'Flore française,' which was prefaced by the 'Clé dichotomique,' making it easy even for a beginner to accurately identify the name of the plant in front of them." In a note, M. Martins informs us that the second edition, published by Candolle in 1815, remains the authoritative work on French plants.
"In 1778 Rousseau had brought botany into vogue. Women and men of fashion took to it. Buffon had the three volumes of 'Flore française' printed at the royal press, and in the following year Lamarck entered the Academy of Sciences. Buffon being anxious that his son should travel, gave him Lamarck for his companion and tutor. He thus made a trip through Holland, Germany, and Hungary, and became acquainted with Gleditsch at Berlin, with Jacquin at Vienna, and with Murray at Gottingen.[Pg 238]
"In 1778, Rousseau made botany popular. Fashionable men and women embraced it. Buffon had three volumes of 'Flore française' printed at the royal press, and the following year, Lamarck joined the Academy of Sciences. Wanting his son to travel, Buffon arranged for Lamarck to be his companion and tutor. They took a trip through Holland, Germany, and Hungary, where he met Gleditsch in Berlin, Jacquin in Vienna, and Murray in Göttingen.[Pg 238]"
"The 'Encyclopédie méthodique,' begun by Diderot and D'Alembert, was not yet completed. For this work Lamarck wrote four volumes, describing all the then known plants whose names began with the letters from A to P. This great work was completed by Poiret, and comprises twelve volumes, which appeared between the years 1783 and 1817. A still more important work, also part of the Encyclopedia, and continually quoted by botanists, is the 'Illustration des Genres.' In this work Lamarck describes two thousand genera, and illustrates them, according to the title-page, with nine hundred engravings. Only a botanist can form any idea of the research in collections, gardens, and books, which such a work must have involved. But Lamarck's activity was inexhaustible. Sonnerat returned from India in 1781 with a very large number of dried plants; no one except Lamarck thought it worth while to inspect them, and Sonnerat, charmed with his enthusiasm, gave him the whole magnificent collection.
The 'Encyclopédie méthodique,' started by Diderot and D'Alembert, was still a work in progress. For this project, Lamarck wrote four volumes that detailed all the known plants starting with the letters A to P. Poiret later completed this significant work, which consists of twelve volumes published between 1783 and 1817. An even more crucial publication, also part of the Encyclopedia and frequently referenced by botanists, is the 'Illustration des Genres. In this work, Lamarck describes two thousand genera and illustrates them with nine hundred engravings, according to the title page. Only a botanist can truly appreciate the extensive research in collections, gardens, and books that this work must have required. However, Lamarck's energy was boundless. Sonnerat returned from India in 1781 with a vast number of dried plants; no one besides Lamarck thought it was worth examining them, and Sonnerat, impressed by his enthusiasm, gifted him the entire stunning collection.
"In spite, however, of his incessant toil, Lamarck's position continued to be most precarious. He lived by his pen, as a publisher's hack, and it was with difficulty that he obtained even the poorly paid post of keeper of the king's cabinet of dried plants. Like most other naturalists he had thus to contend with incessant difficulties during a period of fifteen years.
"In spite of his constant hard work, Lamarck's situation remained very unstable. He made a living by writing, often working as a publisher’s freelancer, and it was a struggle for him to secure the low-paying position of keeper of the king's collection of dried plants. Like many other naturalists, he faced continuous challenges for fifteen years."
"At length fortune bettered his condition while changing the direction of his labours. France was now under the Convention; what Carnot had done for the army Lakanal undertook to do for the natural sciences. At his suggestion a museum of natural history was[Pg 239] established. Professors had been found for all the chairs save that of Zoology; but in that time of enthusiasm, so different from the present, France could find men of war and men of science wherever and whenever she had need of them. Étienne Geoffroy St. Hilaire was twenty-one years old, and was engaged in the study of mineralogy under Haüy. Daubenton said to him, 'I will undertake the responsibility for your inexperience. I have a father's authority over you. Take this professorship, and let us one day say that you have made zoology a French science.' Geoffroy accepted, and undertook the higher animals. Lakanal knew that a single professor could not suffice for the task of arranging the collections of the entire animal kingdom, and as Geoffroy was to class the vertebrate animals only, there remained the invertebrata—that is to say, insects, molluscs, worms, zoophytes—in a word, what was then the chaos of the unknown. 'Lamarck,' says M. Michelet, 'accepted the unknown.' He had devoted some attention to the study of shells with Bruguières, but he had still everything to learn, or I should perhaps say rather, everything to create in that unexplored territory into which Linnæus had declined to enter, and into which he had thus introduced none of the order he had so well known how to establish among the higher animals.
Eventually, luck improved his situation while changing the focus of his work. France was now under the Convention; just as Carnot had done for the military, Lakanal aimed to do for the natural sciences. At his suggestion, a museum of natural history was[Pg 239] established. Professors had been appointed for all the positions except Zoology; but during that period of enthusiasm, so different from today, France could find both soldiers and scientists whenever she needed them. Étienne Geoffroy St. Hilaire was twenty-one years old and studying mineralogy under Haüy. Daubenton told him, "I'll take responsibility for your lack of experience. I have a fatherly authority over you. Accept this professorship, and let’s say one day that you made zoology a French science." Geoffroy agreed and took on the higher animals. Lakanal realized that one professor wasn’t enough to organize the collections of the entire animal kingdom, so since Geoffroy would focus only on vertebrates, there were still the invertebrates—meaning insects, mollusks, worms, zoophytes—in short, what was then a jumble of the unknown. "Lamarck," says M. Michelet, "accepted the unknown." He had spent some time studying shells with Bruguières, but he still had everything to learn or, perhaps more accurately, everything to create in that uncharted territory that Linnæus had refused to explore, leaving behind none of the order he had so successfully established among the higher animals.
"Lamarck began his course of lectures at the museum in 1794, after a year's preparation, and at once established that great division of animals into vertebrate and invertebrate, which science has ever since recognized.[Pg 240]
"Lamarck started his lecture series at the museum in 1794, following a year of preparation, and immediately established the significant classification of animals into vertebrates and invertebrates, which science has acknowledged ever since.[Pg 240]
"Dividing the vertebrate animals—as Linnæus had already divided them—into mammals, birds, reptiles, and fishes, he divided the invertebrates into molluscs, insects, worms, echinoderms, and polyps. In 1799 he separated the crustacea from the insects, with which they had been classed hitherto; in 1800 he established the arachnids as a class distinct from the insects; in 1802 that of the annelids, a subdivision of the worms, and that of the radiata as distinct from the polyps. Time has approved the wisdom of these divisions, founded all of them upon the organic type of the creatures themselves—that is to say, upon the rational method introduced into zoology by Cuvier, Lamarck, and Geoffroy St. Hilaire.
"Dividing vertebrate animals—just as Linnæus had done—into mammals, birds, reptiles, and fish, he categorized invertebrates into mollusks, insects, worms, echinoderms, and polyps. In 1799, he distinguished crustaceans from insects, with which they had previously been grouped; in 1800, he established arachnids as a separate class from insects; in 1802, he created the annelids category, a subset of worms, and classified radiata as distinct from polyps. Time has shown the value of these classifications, all based on the organic characteristics of the creatures themselves—that is, following the rational approach introduced into zoology by Cuvier, Lamarck, and Geoffroy St. Hilaire."
"This introduction being devoted only to Lamarck's labours as a naturalist, we will pass over certain works in which he treats of physics and chemistry. These attempts—errors of a powerful mind which thought itself able by the help of pure reason to establish truths which rest only upon experience—attempts, moreover, which were some of them but resuscitations of exploded theories, such as that of 'phlogistic'—had not even the honour of being refuted: they did not deserve to be so, and should be a warning to all those who would write upon a subject without the necessary practical knowledge.
"This introduction focuses solely on Lamarck's work as a naturalist, so we will skip over certain writings where he discusses physics and chemistry. These efforts—mistakes from a brilliant mind that believed it could uncover truths based solely on reason—were, in some cases, just reiterations of outdated theories, like 'phlogiston.' They didn't even merit refutation; they weren’t worthy of that, and they should serve as a caution to anyone who attempts to write on a topic without the required practical expertise."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"At the beginning of this century there was not yet any such science as geology. People observed but little, and in lieu of observation made theories to embrace the entire globe. Lamarck made his in 1802,[Pg 241] and twenty-three years later the judicious Cuvier still yielded to the prevailing custom in publishing his 'Discoveries on the Earth's Revolutions.'
"At the start of this century, geology didn't exist as a science yet. People did very little observing and instead created theories to explain the entire planet. Lamarck put forward his theory in 1802,[Pg 241] and twenty-three years later, the sensible Cuvier still followed the common trend by publishing his 'Discoveries on the Earth's Revolutions.'"
"Lamarck's merit was to have discovered that there had been no catastrophes, but that the gradual action of forces during thousands of ages accounted for the changes observable upon the face of the earth, better than any sudden and violent perturbations. 'Nature,' he writes, 'has no difficulty on the score of time; she has it always at command; it is with her a boundless space in which she has room for the greatest as for the smallest operations.'"
"Lamarck's achievement was recognizing that there hadn't been any disasters, but that the slow action of forces over thousands of years explained the changes we see on Earth much better than any sudden and violent disturbances. 'Nature,' he writes, 'doesn't worry about time; she always has it at her disposal; for her, it is an endless space where she has room for both the largest and smallest processes.'"
Here we must not forget Buffon's fine passage, "Nature's great workman is Time," &c. See page 103.
Here we must not forget Buffon's great line, "Nature's main craftsman is Time," etc. See page 103.
"Lamarck," continues M. Martins, "was the first to distinguish littoral from ocean fossils, but no one accepts his theory that oceans make their beds deeper owing to the action of the tides, and distribute themselves differently over the earth's surface without any change of level of the different parts of that surface.
"Lamarck," M. Martins continues, "was the first to distinguish between coastal and deep-sea fossils, but no one accepts his theory that oceans deepen their beds due to tidal action and spread out differently across the earth's surface without any change in the levels of the various parts of that surface."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"Settling down to a single branch of science, in consequence of his professorship, Lamarck now devoted himself to the twofold labour of lecturing and classifying the collections at the museum. In 1802 he published his 'Considerations on the Organization of Living Bodies'; in 1809 his 'Philosophie Zoologique,' a development of the 'Considerations'; and from 1816 to 1822 his Natural History of the invertebrate animals, in seven volumes. This is his great work, and, being entirely a work of description and classification,[Pg 242] was received with the unanimous approbation of the scientific world. His 'Fossil Shells of the Neighbourhood of Paris'—a work in which his profound knowledge of existing shells enabled him to class with certainty the remains of forms that had disappeared thousands of ages ago—met also with a favourable reception.
"After settling on a specific branch of science because of his professorship, Lamarck dedicated himself to the dual tasks of lecturing and organizing the museum's collections. In 1802, he published 'Considerations on the Organization of Living Bodies'; in 1809, his 'Philosophie Zoologique', which expanded on the 'Considerations'; and from 1816 to 1822, his Natural History of Invertebrate Animals in seven volumes. This is his major work and, being solely descriptive and classificatory,[Pg 242] received unanimous praise from the scientific community. His 'Fossil Shells of the Neighbourhood of Paris'—a work that showcased his deep understanding of modern shells, allowing him to confidently categorize the remains of species that had vanished thousands of years ago—was also well received."
"Lamarck was fifty years old before he began to study zoology; and prolonged microscopic examinations first fatigued and at length enfeebled his eyesight. The clouds which obscured it gradually thickened, and he became quite blind. Married four times, the father of seven children, he saw his small patrimony and even his earlier savings swallowed up by one of those hazardous investments with which promoters impose on the credulity of the public. His small endowment as professor alone protected him from destitution. Men of science whom his reputation as a botanist and zoologist had attracted near him, wondered at the manner in which he was neglected.
"Lamarck was fifty when he started studying zoology, and extended microscopic examinations first tired out and eventually weakened his eyesight. The clouds that obscured his vision gradually thickened, and he became completely blind. He was married four times and had seven children, yet he watched his modest inheritance and even his earlier savings get wiped out by one of those risky investments that promoters trick the public into believing. His modest salary as a professor was the only thing keeping him from poverty. Scientists who were drawn to him because of his reputation as a botanist and zoologist were amazed at how neglected he was."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"He passed the last ten years of his laborious life in darkness, tended only by the affectionate care of his two daughters. The eldest wrote from his dictation part of the sixth and seventh volumes of his work on the invertebrate animals. From the time her father became confined to his room his daughter never left the house; and when first she did so after his death, she was distressed by the fresh air to which she had been so long a stranger.
"He spent the last ten years of his hard life in darkness, cared for only by the loving attention of his two daughters. The eldest wrote down parts of the sixth and seventh volumes of his work on invertebrate animals from his dictation. Once her father was confined to his room, she never left the house; and when she finally did after his death, the fresh air upset her, as she had been so long away from it."
"Lamarck died December 18, 1829, at the age of[Pg 243] eighty-five. Latreille and Blainville were his successors at the museum. The incredible activity of the first professor had so greatly increased the number of the known invertebrata that it was found necessary to endow two professors, where one had originally been sufficient.
"Lamarck died on December 18, 1829, at the age of[Pg 243] eighty-five. Latreille and Blainville took over his position at the museum. The remarkable efforts of the first professor had increased the number of known invertebrates so much that it became necessary to appoint two professors instead of just one."
"His two daughters were left penniless. In the year 1832 I myself saw Mlle. Cornélie de Lamarck earning a scanty pittance by fastening dried plants on to paper, in the museum of which her father had been a professor. Many a species named and described by him must have passed under her eyes and increased the bitterness of her regret."[185]
"His two daughters were left broke. In 1832, I personally saw Mlle. Cornélie de Lamarck making a tiny income by gluing dried plants onto paper at the museum where her father had been a professor. Many species that he had named and described must have caught her eye, deepening her sense of loss." [185]
FOOTNOTES:
[184] Paris, 1873.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Paris, 1873.
GENERAL MISCONCEPTION CONCERNING LAMARCK—HIS PHILOSOPHICAL POSITION.
GENERAL MISCONCEPTION CONCERNING LAMARCK—HIS PHILOSOPHICAL POSITION.
"If Cuvier," says M. Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire,[186] "is the modern successor of Linnæus, so is Lamarck of Buffon. But Cuvier does not go so far as Linnæus, and Lamarck goes much farther than Buffon. Lamarck, moreover, took his own line, and his conjectures are not only much bolder, or rather more hazardous, but they are profoundly different from Buffon's.
"If Cuvier," says M. Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire,[186] "is the modern successor to Linnæus, then Lamarck is to Buffon. However, Cuvier doesn’t go as far as Linnæus, whereas Lamarck goes much further than Buffon. Additionally, Lamarck carved out his own path, and his ideas are not just much bolder, or more daring, but they are also fundamentally different from Buffon's."
"It is well known that the vast labours of Lamarck were divided between botany and physical science in the eighteenth century, and between zoology and natural philosophy in the nineteenth; it is, however, less generally known that Lamarck was long a partisan of the immutability of species. It was not till 1801, when he was already old, that he freed himself from the ideas then generally prevailing. But Lamarck, having once made up his mind, never changed it; in his ripe age he exhibits all the ardour of youth in propagating and defending his new convictions.
"It’s well known that Lamarck’s extensive work was split between botany and physical science in the eighteenth century, and between zoology and natural philosophy in the nineteenth. However, it’s less commonly known that Lamarck was a long-time supporter of the idea that species don’t change. It wasn’t until 1801, when he was already an old man, that he broke free from the beliefs that were popular at the time. Once Lamarck made up his mind, he never looked back; in his old age, he showed all the enthusiasm of youth in promoting and defending his new beliefs."
"In the three years, 1801, 1802, 1803, he enounced them twice in his lectures, and three times in his writings.[187] He returns to the subject and states his views[Pg 245] precisely in 1806,[188] and in 1809 he devotes a great part of his principal work, the 'Philosophie Zoologique,' to their demonstration.[189] Here he might have rested and have quietly awaited the judgment of his peers; but he is too much convinced; he believes the future of science to depend so much upon his doctrine that to his dying day he feels compelled to explain it further and insist upon it. When already over seventy years of age he enounces it again, and maintains it as firmly as ever in 1815, in his 'Histoire des Animaux sans Vertèbres,' and in 1820 in his 'Système des Connaissances Positives.'[190]
"In the three years, 1801, 1802, 1803, he presented them twice in his lectures and three times in his writings.[187] He revisits the topic and clearly states his views[Pg 245] in 1806,[188] and in 1809, he dedicates a significant portion of his main work, 'Philosophie Zoologique,' to demonstrating them.[189] At this point, he could have rested and waited for his peers to judge his work; however, he is too convinced. He believes that the future of science hinges on his doctrine, so he feels compelled to keep explaining it and advocating for it until his dying day. Even at over seventy years old, he reiterates his views and stands by them firmly in 1815 in his 'Histoire des Animaux sans Vertèbres,' and again in 1820 in his 'Système des Connaissances Positives.'[190]"
"This doctrine, so dearly cherished by its author, and the conception, exposition, and defence of which so laboriously occupied the second half of his scientific career, has been assuredly too much admired by some, who have forgotten that Lamarck had a precursor, and that that precursor was Buffon. It has, on the other hand, been too severely condemned by others who have involved it in its entirety in broad and sweeping condemnation. As if it were possible that so great labour on the part of so great a naturalist should have led him to 'a fantastic conclusion' only—to a 'flighty error,' and, as has been often said, though not written, to 'one[Pg 246] absurdity the more.' Such was the language which Lamarck heard during his protracted old age, saddened alike by the weight of years and blindness; this was what people did not hesitate to utter over his grave yet barely closed, and what, indeed, they are still saying—commonly, too, without any knowledge of what Lamarck maintained, but merely repeating at second hand bad caricatures of his teaching.
"This idea, deeply valued by its creator, and the explanation, presentation, and defense of which took up so much of the latter part of his scientific career, has certainly been overly praised by some who forgot that Lamarck had a predecessor, and that predecessor was Buffon. On the flip side, it has been too harshly criticized by others who have broadly condemned it as a whole. As if it were possible that such extensive work by such a significant naturalist could have led him to 'a ridiculous conclusion' only—to a 'silly mistake,' and, as has often been said, though not written, to 'one[Pg 246] absurdity more.' This is the kind of language Lamarck heard during his long old age, weighed down by years and blindness; this is what people openly stated over his barely closed grave, and what they are still saying—often without any true understanding of what Lamarck actually argued, merely repeating poorly drawn caricatures of his ideas."
"When will the time come when we may see Lamarck's theory discussed—and, I may as well at once say, refuted in some important points—with at any rate the respect due to one of the most illustrious masters of our science? And when will this theory, the hardihood of which has been greatly exaggerated, become freed from the interpretations and commentaries by the false light of which so many naturalists have formed their opinion concerning it? If its author is to be condemned, let it be, at any rate, not before he has been heard."[191]
"When will we finally see Lamarck's theory discussed—and I should mention, refuted on some key points—with the respect it deserves for being one of the most prominent ideas in our field? And when will this theory, whose boldness has been greatly overstated, be liberated from the misinterpretations that have shaped so many naturalists' views on it? If we are to criticize its author, let’s at least do so after he has had a chance to speak."[191]
It is not necessary for me to give the extracts from Lamarck which M. Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire quotes in order to show what he really maintained, inasmuch as they will be given at greater length in the following chapter; but I may perhaps say that I have not found M. Geoffroy refuting Lamarck in any essential point.
It’s not needed for me to provide the quotes from Lamarck that M. Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire mentions to show what he actually believed, since they will be discussed more thoroughly in the next chapter; however, I can say that I haven’t found M. Geoffroy disproving Lamarck on any major point.
Professor Haeckel says that to Lamarck "will always belong the immortal glory of having for the first time worked out the theory of descent as an independent scientific theory of the first order, and as the philosophical foundation of the whole science of Biology."
Professor Haeckel says that to Lamarck "will always belong the enduring honor of being the first to develop the theory of evolution as an independent scientific theory of the highest significance, and as the philosophical basis of the entire field of Biology."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"The 'Philosophie Zoologique,'" continues Professor Haeckel, "is the first connected exposition of the theory of descent carried out strictly into all its consequences; ... and with the exception of Darwin's work, which appeared exactly half a century later, we know of none which we could in this respect place by the side of the 'Philosophie Zoologique.' How far it was in advance of its time is perhaps best seen from the circumstance that it was not understood by most men, and for fifty years was not spoken of at all."[192]
"The 'Philosophie Zoologique,'" continues Professor Haeckel, "is the first comprehensive explanation of the theory of evolution that fully explores all its implications; ... and aside from Darwin's work, which was published exactly fifty years later, we don't know of any that we could compare to the 'Philosophie Zoologique' in this regard. The extent to which it was ahead of its time is perhaps best illustrated by the fact that most people didn’t understand it, and for fifty years, it was barely mentioned at all."[192]
This is an exaggeration, both as regards the originality of Lamarck's work and the reception it has met with. It is probably more accurate to say with M. Martins that Lamarck's theory has "never yet had the honour of being discussed seriously,"[193] not, at least, in connection with the name of its originators.
This is an exaggeration regarding both the originality of Lamarck's work and the response it has received. It's likely more accurate to agree with M. Martins that Lamarck's theory has "never yet had the honor of being discussed seriously,"[193] at least not in relation to the name of its creators.
So completely has this been so that the author of the 'Vestiges of Creation,' even in the edition of 1860, in which he unreservedly acknowledges the adoption of Lamarck's views, not unfrequently speaks disparagingly of Lamarck himself, and never gives him his due meed of recognition. I am not, therefore, wholly displeased to find this author conceiving himself to have been treated by Mr. Charles Darwin with some of the injustice which he has himself inflicted on Lamarck.
So completely has this been the case that the author of the 'Vestiges of Creation,' even in the 1860 edition where he openly acknowledges adopting Lamarck's views, often speaks negatively about Lamarck and never gives him the recognition he deserves. Therefore, I'm not entirely unhappy to see this author feeling that Mr. Charles Darwin has treated him with some of the same unfairness that he has shown to Lamarck.
In the 1859 edition of the 'Origin of Species,' and in a very prominent place, Mr. Darwin says:—"The author of the 'Vestiges of Creation' would I presume[Pg 248] say, that after a certain number of unknown generations, some bird had given birth to a woodpecker, and some plant to a misseltoe, and that these had been produced perfect as we now see them."[194] This is the only allusion to the 'Vestiges' which I have found in the first edition of the 'Origin of Species.'
In the 1859 edition of the 'Origin of Species,' Mr. Darwin states in a very prominent spot:—"I assume the author of the 'Vestiges of Creation' would say that after a certain number of unknown generations, some bird gave birth to a woodpecker, and some plant gave rise to a mistletoe, and that these appeared just as we see them now."[Pg 248][194] This is the only reference to the 'Vestiges' that I found in the first edition of the 'Origin of Species.'
Those who have read the 1853 edition of the 'Vestiges' will not be surprised to find the author rejoining, in his edition of 1860, that it was to be regretted Mr. Darwin should have read the 'Vestiges' "nearly as much amiss as though, like its declared opponents, he had an interest in misunderstanding it." And a little lower he adds that Mr. Darwin's book in no essential respect contradicts the 'Vestiges'; "on the contrary, while adding to its explanations of nature, it expresses substantially the same general ideas."[195] It is right to say that the passage thus objected to is not to be found in later editions of the 'Origin of Species,' while in the historical sketch we now read as follows:—"In my opinion it (the 'Vestiges of Creation') has done excellent service in this country by calling attention to the subject, removing prejudice, and in thus preparing the ground for the reception of analogous views."
Those who have read the 1853 edition of the 'Vestiges' won’t be surprised to see the author responding in his 1860 edition, expressing regret that Mr. Darwin seemed to have misunderstood the 'Vestiges' "almost as much as if, like its stated opponents, he had a reason to misinterpret it." A bit further down, he notes that Mr. Darwin's book doesn’t fundamentally contradict the 'Vestiges'; "on the contrary, while adding to its explanations of nature, it expresses essentially the same general ideas." [195] It’s worth mentioning that the passage in question doesn’t appear in later editions of the 'Origin of Species,' while in the historical sketch we now read, it states: "In my opinion, it (the 'Vestiges of Creation') has provided great service in this country by bringing attention to the subject, removing bias, and thus preparing the ground for the acceptance of similar views."
Mr. Darwin, the main part of whose work on the 'Origin of Species' is taken up with supporting the theory of descent with modification (which frequently in the recapitulation chapter of the 'Origin of Species' he seems to treat as synonymous with natural selection), has fallen into the common error of thinking[Pg 249] that Lamarck can be ignored or passed over in a couple of sentences. I only find Lamarck's name twice in the 1859 edition of the 'Origin,' once on p. 242, where Mr. Darwin writes: "I am surprised that no one has advanced this demonstrative case of neuter insects, against the well-known doctrine of Lamarck;" and again, p. 427, where Lamarck is stated to have been the first to call attention to the "very important distinction between real affinities and analogical or adaptive resemblances." How far from demonstrative is the particular case which in 1859 Mr. Darwin considered so fatal to "the well-known doctrine of Lamarck"—which should surely, one would have thought, include the doctrine of descent with modification, which Mr. Darwin is himself supporting—I have attempted to show in 'Life and Habit,' but had perhaps better recapitulate briefly here.
Mr. Darwin, whose main focus in the 'Origin of Species' is on supporting the theory of evolution through modification (which he often seems to equate with natural selection in the recap chapter), has made the common mistake of thinking[Pg 249] that Lamarck can be dismissed in just a couple of sentences. I only see Lamarck's name mentioned twice in the 1859 edition of the 'Origin,' once on p. 242, where Mr. Darwin writes: "I am surprised that no one has put forward this clear example of neuter insects against the well-known doctrine of Lamarck;" and again on p. 427, where it's mentioned that Lamarck was the first to highlight the "very important distinction between real affinities and analogical or adaptive resemblances." Just how unconvincing is the specific case that Mr. Darwin considered so damaging to "the well-known doctrine of Lamarck" in 1859—which should logically include the concept of evolution through modification that Mr. Darwin himself supports—I have attempted to explain in 'Life and Habit,' but it may be best to summarize briefly here.
Mr. Darwin writes: "In the simpler case of neuter insects all of one caste, which, as I believe, have been rendered different from the fertile males and females through natural selection...."[196] He thus attributes the sterility and peculiar characteristics, we will say, of the common hive working bees—"neuter insects all of one caste"—to natural selection. Now, nothing is more certain than that these characteristics—sterility, a cavity in the thigh for collecting wax, a proboscis for gathering honey, &c.—are due to the treatment which the eggs laid by the queen bee receive after they have left her body. Take an egg and treat it in a certain way, and it becomes a working bee; treat the same[Pg 250] egg in a certain other way, and it becomes a queen. If the bees are in danger of becoming queenless they take eggs which were in the way of being developed into working bees, and change their food and cells, whereon they develop into queens instead. How Mr. Darwin could attribute the neutralization of the working bees—an act which is obviously one of abortion committed by the body politic of the hive on a balance of considerations—to the action of what he calls "natural selection," and how, again, he could suppose that what he was advancing had any but a confirmatory bearing upon Lamarck's position, is incomprehensible, unless the passage in question be taken as a mere slip. That attention has been called to it is plain, for the words "the well-known doctrine of Lamarck" have been changed in later editions into "the well-known doctrine of inherited habit as advanced by Lamarck,"[197] but this correction, though some apparent improvement on the original text, does little indeed in comparison with what is wanted.
Mr. Darwin writes: "In the simpler case of neuter insects all of one caste, which, as I believe, have been rendered different from the fertile males and females through natural selection...."[196] He attributes the sterility and unique traits of the common hive working bees—"neuter insects all of one caste"—to natural selection. Clearly, these traits—sterility, a cavity in the thigh for collecting wax, a proboscis for gathering honey, etc.—come from how the eggs laid by the queen bee are treated after leaving her body. If you take an egg and treat it a certain way, it becomes a working bee; treat the same[Pg 250] egg differently, and it becomes a queen. If the bees risk becoming queenless, they take eggs that are developing into working bees and change their food and cells, causing them to develop into queens instead. How Mr. Darwin could link the neutralization of working bees—an act that is clearly a sort of abortion performed by the hive on a balance of considerations—to what he calls "natural selection," and how he could think that his argument had any relevance to Lamarck's theory, is baffling unless this passage is regarded as a mere mistake. It’s evident that attention has been drawn to it, as the words "the well-known doctrine of Lamarck" have been updated in later editions to "the well-known doctrine of inherited habit as advanced by Lamarck,"[197] but this correction, while an apparent improvement over the original text, falls short of what is really needed.
Mr. Darwin has since introduced a paragraph concerning Lamarck into the "historical sketch," already more than once referred to in these pages. In this he summarises the theory which I am about to lay before the reader, by saying that Lamarck "upheld the doctrine that all species, including man, are descended from other species." If Lamarck had been alive he would probably have preferred to see Mr. Darwin write that he upheld "the doctrine of descent with modification as the explanation of all differentiations of structure[Pg 251] and instinct." Mr. Darwin continues, that Lamarck "seems" to have been chiefly led to his conclusion on the gradual change of species, "by the difficulty of distinguishing species and varieties, by the almost perfect gradation of forms in certain groups, and by the analogy of domestic productions."
Mr. Darwin has since added a section about Lamarck into the "historical sketch," which has already been mentioned multiple times in these pages. In this section, he summarizes the theory that I am about to present by stating that Lamarck "argued that all species, including humans, are derived from other species." If Lamarck had been alive, he might have preferred Mr. Darwin to say that he supported "the theory of descent with modification as the explanation for all variations in structure[Pg 251] and instinct." Mr. Darwin goes on to say that Lamarck "appears" to have reached his conclusion about the gradual change of species mainly because of the difficulty in distinguishing between species and varieties, the nearly perfect gradation of forms in some groups, and the analogy of domesticated animals.
Lamarck would probably have said that though he did indeed turn—as Mr. Darwin has done, and as Buffon and Dr. Darwin had done before him—to animals and plants under domestication, in illustration and support of the theory of descent with modification; and that though he did also insist, as so many other writers have done, on the arbitrary and artificial nature of the distinction between species and varieties, he was mainly led to agree with Buffon and Dr. Darwin by a broad survey of the animal kingdom, with the details also of which few naturalists have ever been better acquainted.
Lamarck would likely have stated that while he did look to animals and plants in domestication—just like Mr. Darwin, and earlier Buffon and Dr. Darwin—to illustrate and support the theory of evolution through modification; and even though he also emphasized, like many other authors, the arbitrary and artificial distinction between species and varieties, his agreement with Buffon and Dr. Darwin was mainly based on a comprehensive view of the animal kingdom, which few naturalists have been as knowledgeable about as he was.
"Great," says Mr. Darwin, "is the power of steady misrepresentation,"—and greatly indeed has the just fame of Lamarck been eclipsed in consequence; "but," as Mr. Darwin finely continues, "the history of science shows that fortunately this power does not long endure."[198]
"Great," says Mr. Darwin, "is the power of consistent misrepresentation,"—and indeed, the rightful reputation of Lamarck has been greatly overshadowed as a result; "but," as Mr. Darwin wisely adds, "the history of science shows that thankfully this power doesn't last long."[198]
That Lamarck anticipated it, was prepared to face it, and even felt that things were thus, after all, as they should be, will appear from the shrewd and pleasant passage which is to be found near the close of his preface:—
That Lamarck anticipated it, was ready to confront it, and even believed that things were as they should be, will be evident from the clever and enjoyable excerpt found near the end of his preface:—
"So great is the power of preconceived opinion, especially when any personal interest is enlisted on the[Pg 252] same side as itself, that though it is hard to deduce new truths from the study of nature, it is still harder to get them recognized by other people.
"So strong is the influence of preconceived opinions, especially when personal interests align with them, that even though it's difficult to discover new truths through studying nature, it's even harder to get others to accept those truths."
"These difficulties, however, are on the whole more beneficial than hurtful to the cause of science; for it is through them that a number of eccentric, though perhaps plausible speculations, perish in their infancy, and are never again heard of. Sometimes, indeed, valuable ideas are thus lost; but it is better that a truth, when once caught sight of, should have to struggle for a long time without meeting the attention it deserves, than that every outcome of a heated imagination should be readily received.
"These challenges, however, are mostly more helpful than harmful to science; because it's through them that many odd, though maybe reasonable, ideas die off early and are never heard from again. Sometimes, valuable ideas are lost this way; but it's better for a truth, once it's recognized, to have to fight for a long time without getting the attention it deserves than for every product of a heated imagination to be easily accepted."
"The more I reflect upon the numerous causes which affect our judgments, the more convinced I am that, with the exception of such physical and moral facts as no one can now throw doubt upon, all else is matter of opinion and argument; and we know well that there is hardly an argument to be found anywhere, against which another argument cannot plausibly be adduced. Hence, though it is plain that the various opinions of men differ greatly in probability and in the weight which should be attached to them, it seems to me that we are wrong when we blame those who differ from us.
"The more I think about the many things that influence our judgments, the more I'm convinced that, aside from physical and moral truths that no one can dispute, everything else is just a matter of opinion and debate. We know there’s hardly an argument out there that doesn't have a counterargument that sounds credible. So, even though it's clear that people's opinions vary greatly in how likely they are to be true and the importance we should give them, I believe it's wrong to criticize those who have different views from ours."
"Are we then to recognize no opinions as well founded but those which are generally received? Nay—experience teaches us plainly that the highest and most cultivated minds must be at all times in an exceedingly small minority. No one can dispute this. Authority should be told by weight and not by number—but[Pg 253] in good truth authority is a hard thing to weigh.
"Are we really supposed to only accept opinions that are widely accepted? No—experience clearly shows us that the most advanced and educated minds are almost always a tiny minority. No one can argue with that. Authority should be measured by quality, not quantity—but[Pg 253] honestly, it's hard to measure authority."
"Nor again—in spite of the many and severe conditions which a judgment must fulfil before it can be declared good—is it quite certain that those whom public opinion has declared to be authorities, are always right in the conclusions they arrive at.
"Nor again—in spite of the many and severe conditions that a judgment must meet before it can be called good—is it really certain that those whom public opinion has deemed to be authorities are always correct in the conclusions they reach."
"Positive facts are the only solid ground for man; the deductions he draws from them are a very different matter. Outside the facts of nature all is a question of probabilities, and the most that can be said is that some conclusions are more probable than others."
"Positive facts are the only reliable foundation for people; the conclusions they make from those facts are a whole different story. Beyond the facts of nature, everything is a matter of probabilities, and all anyone can really say is that some conclusions are more likely than others."
Lamarck's poverty was perhaps one main reason of the ease with which it was found possible to neglect his philosophical opinions. Science is not a kingdom into which a poor man can enter easily, if he happens to differ from a philosopher who gives good dinners, and has "his sisters and his cousins and his aunts" to play the part of chorus to him. Lamarck's two daughters do not appear to have been the kind of persons who could make effective sisters or cousins or aunts. Men of science are of like passions even with the other holy ones who have set themselves up in all ages as the pastors and prophets of mankind. The saint has commonly deemed it to be for the interests of saintliness that he should strain a point or two in his own favour—and the more so according as his reputation for an appearance of candour has been the better earned. If, then, Lamarck's opponents could keep choruses, while Lamarck had nothing to fall back upon but the merits of his case only, it is not surprising[Pg 254] that he should have found himself neglected by the scientists of his own time. Moreover he was too old to have undertaken such an unequal contest. If he had been twenty years younger when he began it, he would probably have enjoyed his full measure of success before he died.
Lamarck's poverty was likely a big reason why his philosophical views were often overlooked. Science isn't an easy realm for someone without wealth, especially if they disagree with a well-off philosopher who has friends and family to support him. Lamarck's two daughters didn't seem like the type to effectively play the roles of supportive sisters or cousins or aunts. Scientists share similar passions with other "holy" figures who have claimed roles as the leaders and visionaries of society throughout history. Saints often think it's in the best interest of their holiness to bend the truth a little for their own benefit—and they tend to do this more when they've earned a stronger reputation for being honest. So, if Lamarck's rivals had groups backing them while Lamarck only had the merit of his arguments to rely on, it's not surprising[Pg 254] that he was neglected by the scientists of his time. Additionally, he was too old to take on such an uneven battle. If he had started it twenty years earlier, he likely would have seen much greater success before his death.
Not that Lamarck can claim, as a thinker, to stand on the same level with Dr. Darwin, and still less so with Buffon. He attempted to go too fast and too far. Seeing that if we accept descent with modification, the question arises whether what we call life and consciousness may not themselves be evolved from some thing or things which looked at one time so little living and conscious that we call them inanimate—and being anxious to see his theory reach, and to follow it, as far back as possible, he speculates about the origin of life; having formed a theory thereon, he is more inclined to interpret the phenomena of lower animal life so as to make them fit in with his theory, than as he would have interpreted them if there had been no theory at stake.
Not that Lamarck can really compare as a thinker to Dr. Darwin, and even less so to Buffon. He tried to go too fast and too far. If we accept the idea of descent with modification, it raises the question of whether what we call life and consciousness might have evolved from things that once seemed so non-living and non-conscious that we label them as inanimate—and eager to trace his theory as far back as possible, he speculates about the origin of life; having come up with a theory about it, he tends to interpret the phenomena of lower animal life in a way that supports his theory, rather than as he would have interpreted them if there were no theory at play.
Thus his denial that sensation, and much more, intelligence and deliberate action, can exist without a brain and a nervous system, has led him to deny sensation, consciousness, and intelligence to many animals which act in such manner as would certainly have made him say that they feel and know what they are about, if he had formed no theory about brains and nervous systems.
So, his refusal to accept that sensation—and even more so, intelligence and conscious thought—can happen without a brain and a nervous system has led him to claim that many animals lack sensation, awareness, and intelligence. However, these animals behave in ways that would definitely make him assert that they feel and understand their actions if he had never developed a theory about brains and nervous systems.
Nothing can be more different than the manners in which Lamarck and Dr. Darwin wrote on this head.[Pg 255] Lamarck over and over again maintains that where there is no nervous system there can be no sensation. Combating, for example, the assertion of Cabanis, that to live is to feel, he says that "the greater number of the polypi and all the infusoria, having no nervous system, it must be said of them as also of worms, that to live is still not to feel; and so again of plants."[199]
Nothing could be more different than the ways Lamarck and Dr. Darwin wrote about this topic.[Pg 255] Lamarck repeatedly argues that where there is no nervous system, there can be no sensation. For example, challenging Cabanis’s statement that to live is to feel, he says that "the majority of polyps and all infusoria, lacking a nervous system, should be said, like worms, to live without feeling; and the same goes for plants."[199]
How different from this is the un-theory-ridden language of Dr. Darwin, quoted on p. 116 of this work.
How different this is from the straightforward language of Dr. Darwin, quoted on p. 116 of this work.
Lamarck again writes:—
Lamarck writes again:—
"The very imperfect animals of the lowest classes, having no nervous system, are simply irritable, have nothing but certain habits, experience no sensations, and never conceive ideas."
"The very basic animals of the lowest classes, lacking a nervous system, are just reactive, have only certain habits, feel no sensations, and never form ideas."
This, in the face of the performances of the amœba—a minute jelly speck, without any special organ whatever—in making its tests, cannot be admitted. Is it possible that Lamarck was in some measure misled by believing Buffon to be in earnest when he advanced propositions little less monstrous?
This, considering the actions of the amoeba—a tiny jelly-like speck, without any specific organs—cannot be accepted. Is it possible that Lamarck was somewhat misled by thinking Buffon was serious when he put forward ideas that were almost as absurd?
"But," continues Lamarck, "the less imperfect animals which have a nervous system, though they have not the organ of intelligence, have instinct, habits, and proclivities; they feel sensations, and yet form no ideas whatever. I venture to say that where there is no organ for a faculty that faculty cannot exist."[200]
"But," continues Lamarck, "the less advanced animals that have a nervous system, even though they lack an organ for intelligence, still possess instincts, habits, and tendencies; they experience sensations but don’t form any ideas at all. I dare say that without an organ for a specific ability, that ability cannot exist."[200]
Who can tell what ideas a worm does or does not form? We can watch its actions, and see that they are such as involve what we call design and a perception of its own interest. Under these circumstances it seems[Pg 256] better to call the worm a reasonable creature with Dr. Darwin than to say with Lamarck that because worms do not appear to have that organ which he assumes to be the sole means of causing sensation and ideas, therefore they can neither feel nor think. Doubtless they cannot feel and think as many sensations and thoughts as we can, but our ideas of what they can and cannot feel must be formed through consideration of what we see them do, and must be biassed by no theories of what they ought to be able to feel or not feel.
Who can say what ideas a worm might or might not have? We can observe its actions and see that they seem to involve what we call intention and an awareness of its own interests. Given these circumstances, it seems[Pg 256] more reasonable to agree with Dr. Darwin and consider the worm a rational being, rather than following Lamarck's view that since worms don’t have the organ he believes is essential for sensation and ideas, they cannot feel or think at all. Certainly, they might not feel or think in the same way we do, but our ideas about what they can or can't feel should be based on our observations of their behavior, free from any assumptions about what they should or shouldn't be able to feel.
Again Lamarck, shortly after an excellent passage in which he points out that the lower animals gain by experience just as man does (and here probably he had in his mind the passage of Buffon referred to at p. 112 of this work), nevertheless writes:—
Again, Lamarck, shortly after a great section where he notes that lower animals learn from experience just like humans do (and he probably had Buffon’s passage mentioned on p. 112 of this work in mind), still writes:—
"If the facts and considerations put forward in this volume be held worthy of attention, it will follow necessarily that there are some animals which have neither reason nor instinct" (I should be glad to see one of these animals and to watch its movements), "such as those which have no power of feeling; that there are others which have instinct but no degree whatever of reason" (whereas from Dr. Darwin's premises it should follow, and would doubtless be readily admitted by him, that instinct is reason, but reason many times repeated made perfect, and finally repeated by rote; so that far from being prior to reason, as Lamarck here implies, it can only come long afterwards), "such as those which have a system enabling them to feel, but which still lack the organ of intelligence; and finally, that there are those which have not only instinct, but[Pg 257] over and above this a certain degree of reasoning power, such as those creatures which have one system for sensations and another for acts involving intelligence. Instinct is with these last animals the motive power of almost all their actions, and they rarely use what little reason they have. Man, who comes next above them, is also possessed of instincts which inspire some of his actions, but he can acquire much reason, and can use it so as to direct the greater part of his actions."[201]
"If the facts and arguments presented in this book are considered worthy of attention, it necessarily follows that there are some animals that lack both reason and instinct" (I would be curious to see one of these animals and observe its behavior), "such as those that don't have the ability to feel; there are others that possess instinct but have no capacity for reason whatsoever" (whereas, based on Dr. Darwin's arguments, it should follow—and he would probably agree—that instinct is essentially reason, but reason that has been repeated many times to reach perfection, and ultimately memorized; so, rather than existing prior to reason, as Lamarck suggests, it can only come much later), "such as those that have a system allowing them to feel, yet still lack the organ for intelligence; and finally, there are those that not only have instinct, but[Pg 257] also a certain degree of reasoning ability, like creatures that have one system for sensations and another for actions that require intelligence. For these last animals, instinct drives almost all of their actions, and they rarely utilize the little reason they possess. Humans, who come next in the hierarchy, also have instincts that motivate some of their actions, but they can develop significant reasoning ability and use it to guide most of their actions." [201]
All this will be felt to be less satisfactory than the simple directness of Dr. Darwin. It comes in great measure from following Buffon without being en rapport with him. On the other hand, Lamarck must be admitted to have elaborated the theory of "descent with modification" with no less clearness than Dr. Darwin, and with much greater fulness of detail. There is no substantial difference between the points they wish to establish; Dr. Darwin has the advantage in that not content with maintaining that there will be a power of adaptation to the conditions of an animal's existence which will determine its organism, he goes on to say what the principal conditions are, and shows more lucidly than Lamarck has done (though Lamarck adopts the same three causes in a passage which will follow), that struggle, and consequently modification, will be chiefly conversant about the means of subsistence, of reproduction, and of self-protection. Nevertheless, though Dr. Darwin has said enough to show that he had the whole thing clearly before him, and could have elaborated it as finely as or better than[Pg 258] Lamarck himself has done, if he had been so minded, yet the palm must be given to Lamarck on the score of what he actually did, and this I observe to be the verdict of history, for whereas Lamarck's name is still daily quoted, Dr. Darwin's is seldom mentioned, and never with the applause which it deserves.
All this feels less satisfying than the straightforwardness of Dr. Darwin. It largely stems from following Buffon without truly connecting with him. On the other hand, we have to acknowledge that Lamarck clearly developed the theory of "descent with modification" just as effectively as Dr. Darwin, and with much more detail. There's no significant difference between the points they want to make; Dr. Darwin has the edge in that he doesn't just claim there will be an ability to adapt to an animal's living conditions that will shape its organism, but he also specifies what the main conditions are, demonstrating more clearly than Lamarck (though Lamarck includes the same three causes in a passage that follows) that struggle, and thus modification, will mainly focus on the means of survival, reproduction, and self-protection. Still, while Dr. Darwin has provided enough insight to show that he understood the whole idea and could have developed it just as finely, if not better than [Pg 258] Lamarck did, credit has to go to Lamarck for what he actually accomplished. I notice this is the consensus of history, as Lamarck's name is still frequently cited, while Dr. Darwin's is rarely mentioned and never with the recognition it deserves.
The resemblance between the two writers—that is to say, the complete coincidence of their views—is so remarkable that the question is forced upon us how far Lamarck knew the substance of Dr. Darwin's theory. Lamarck knew Buffon personally; he had been tutor to Buffon's son, and Buffon had three of Lamarck's volumes on the French Flora printed at the royal printing press;—how can we account for Lamarck's having had Buffon's theory of descent with modification before him for so many years, and yet remaining a partisan of immutability till 1801? Before this year we find no trace of his having accepted evolution; thenceforward he is one of the most ardent and constant exponents which this doctrine has ever had. What was it that repelled him in Buffon's system? How is it that in the 'Philosophie Zoologique' there is not, so far as I can remember, a single reference to Buffon, from whom, however, as we shall see, many paragraphs are taken with but very little alteration?
The similarity between the two writers—specifically, the complete alignment of their views—is so striking that it raises the question of how well Lamarck understood Dr. Darwin's theory. Lamarck personally knew Buffon; he had been a tutor to Buffon's son, and Buffon had three of Lamarck's volumes on the French Flora published at the royal printing press. How can we explain that Lamarck had Buffon's theory of descent with modification in front of him for so many years, yet remained a supporter of immutability until 1801? Before this year, there's no evidence that he accepted evolution; after that, he became one of the most passionate and consistent advocates for this doctrine. What was it about Buffon's system that turned him away? How is it that in the 'Philosophie Zoologique' there isn't, as far as I can recall, a single mention of Buffon, even though, as we will see, many paragraphs are borrowed from him with very little alteration?
I am inclined to think that the secret of this sudden conversion must be found in a French translation by M. Deleuze of Dr. Darwin's poem, 'The Loves of the Plants' which appeared in 1800. Lamarck—the most eminent botanist of his time—was sure to have heard of and seen this, and would probably know the translator,[Pg 259] who would be able to give him a fair idea of the 'Zoonomia.'
I think the key to this sudden change lies in a French translation by M. Deleuze of Dr. Darwin's poem, 'The Loves of the Plants,' which was published in 1800. Lamarck—the leading botanist of his time—likely heard of and saw this work, and he would probably know the translator,[Pg 259] who could give him a good understanding of the 'Zoonomia.'
I will give a few of the passages which Lamarck would find in this translation. Speaking of Dr. Darwin, M. Deleuze says:—"Il falloit encore qu'un nouvel observateur, entrant dans la route qui venoit de s'ouvrir, s'y frayât des sentiers ignorés; que liant la physique végétale à la botanique il nous montrât dans les plantes, non seulement des corps organisés soumis à des lois constantes, mais des êtres doués sinon de sensibilité, au moins d'une irritabilité particulière, d'un principe de vie qui leur fait exécuter des mouvements analogues à leurs besoins....[202]
I’ll share a few of the passages that Lamarck would come across in this translation. When talking about Dr. Darwin, M. Deleuze states: “It was necessary for a new observer to enter the path that was just beginning to open up, carving out unexplored trails; by linking plant physics with botany, he showed us in plants not only organized bodies governed by constant laws but also beings that, if not sensitive, at least have a particular irritability, a life principle that makes them perform movements similar to their needs....[202]
"Il est des animaux et des plantes qui par le laps du tems paroissent avoir éprouvé des changemens dans leur organisation, pour s'accommoder à de nouveaux genres de nourriture et aux moyens de se la procurer. Peut-être les productions de la nature font elles des progrès vers la perfection. Cette idée appuyée par les observations modernes sur l'accroissement progressif des parties solides du globe, s'accorde avec la dignité et la providence du créateur de l'univers."[203]
"Some animals and plants seem to have changed over time in their structure, to adapt to new types of food and the ways to obtain it. Perhaps nature's creations are making advancements toward perfection. This idea, supported by modern observations on the gradual growth of solid parts of the Earth, aligns with the dignity and providence of the creator of the universe."[203]
"La nature semble s'être fait un jeu d'établir entre tous les êtres organisés une sorte de guerre qui entretient leur activité: si elle a donné aux uns des moyens de défense, elle a donné aux autres des moyens d'attaque."[204]
"Nature seems to have made a game of setting up a kind of war between all organized beings that keeps them active: if it has given some means of defense, it has given others means of attack."[204]
Turning to the 'Botanic Garden' itself, I find that[Pg 260] this admirable sentence belongs to M. Deleuze, and not to Dr. Darwin, who, however, has said what comes to much the same thing,[205] as may be seen p. 227 of this volume. But the authorship is immaterial; whether the passage was by Dr. Darwin or M. Deleuze, it was, in all probability, known to Lamarck before his change of front.
Turning to the 'Botanic Garden' itself, I see that[Pg 260] this excellent sentence is attributed to M. Deleuze, not to Dr. Darwin, who has nonetheless expressed a similar idea,[205] as can be found on p. 227 of this volume. But the authorship doesn't really matter; whether the passage is by Dr. Darwin or M. Deleuze, it's likely that Lamarck was familiar with it before changing his stance.
The note on Trapa Natans again[206] suggests itself as the source from which the passage in the 'Philosophie Zoologique' about the Ranunculus aquatilis is taken,[207] while one of the most important passages in the work, a summary, in fact, of the principal means of modification, seems to be taken, the first half of it from Buffon, and the second from Dr. Darwin. I have called attention to it on pp. 300, 301.
The note on Trapa Natans again[206] appears to be the source of the passage in the 'Philosophie Zoologique' regarding the Ranunculus aquatilis,[207] while one of the key passages in the work, essentially a summary of the main means of modification, seems to be drawn, with the first half from Buffon and the second from Dr. Darwin. I've pointed this out on pp. 300, 301.
We may then suppose that Lamarck failed to understand Buffon, and conceived that he ought either to have gone much farther, or not so far; not being yet prepared to go the whole length himself, he opposed mutability till Dr. Darwin's additions to Buffon's ostensible theory reached him, whereon he at once adopted them, and having received nothing but a few notes and hints, felt himself at liberty to work the theory out independently and claim it. In so original a work as the 'Philosophie Zoologique' must always be considered, this may be legitimate, but I find in it, as Isidore Geoffroy seems also to have found, a little more claim to complete independence than is acceptable to one who is fresh from Buffon and Dr. Darwin.
We might assume that Lamarck didn't fully grasp Buffon's ideas and believed he should have either expanded on them much more or kept them more limited. Not yet ready to fully embrace the concept himself, he pushed back against the idea of change until he learned about Dr. Darwin's contributions to Buffon's apparent theory. After that, he quickly accepted them and, having only received a few notes and suggestions, felt free to develop the theory on his own and take credit for it. In such an original work as the 'Philosophie Zoologique' is always considered, this might be justified, but I notice, as Isidore Geoffroy seems to have noticed as well, that there appears to be a bit more claim to complete independence than is reasonable for someone just coming from Buffon and Dr. Darwin.
FOOTNOTES:
[187] 'Système des Animaux sans Vertèbres,' Paris, in-8, an. ix. (1801); 'Discours d'Ouverture,' p. 12, &c.; 'Recherches sur l'Organisation des Corps Vivants,' Paris, in-8, 1802, p. 50, &c.; 'Discours d'Ouverture d'un Cours de Zoologie pour l'an ix.,' Paris, in-8, 1803. This discourse is entirely devoted to the consideration of the question, "What is Species?"
[187] 'System of Invertebrate Animals,' Paris, 8vo, year IX (1801); 'Opening Speech,' p. 12, etc.; 'Research on the Organization of Living Bodies,' Paris, 8vo, 1802, p. 50, etc.; 'Opening Speech for a Course of Zoology for Year IX,' Paris, 8vo, 1803. This speech focuses entirely on the question, "What is Species?"
[190] 'Hist, des Anim. sans Vertèb.,' tom, i., Introduction, 1re ed., 1815; 'Syst. des Conn. Positives,' Paris, in-8, 1820, 1re part, 2me sect. ch. ii. p. 114, &c.
[190] 'History of Invertebrate Animals,' vol. I, Introduction, 1st ed., 1815; 'System of Positive Knowledge,' Paris, 8vo, 1820, 1st part, 2nd section chap. II p. 114, &c.
[204] Ibid. p. 238.
Ibid. p. 238.
[205] 'Zoonomia,' vol. i. p. 507.
SUMMARY OF THE 'PHILOSOPHIE ZOOLOGIQUE.'
SUMMARY OF THE 'ZOOLOGICAL PHILOSOPHY.'
The first part of the 'Philosophie Zoologique' is the one which deals with the doctrine of evolution or descent with modification. It is to this, therefore, that our attention will be confined. Yet only a comparatively small part of the three hundred and fifty pages which constitute Lamarck's first part are devoted to setting forth the reasons which led him to arrive at his conclusions—the greater part of the volume being occupied with the classification of animals, which we may again omit, as foreign to our purpose.
The first part of the 'Philosophie Zoologique' focuses on the theory of evolution or descent with modification. This is what we will concentrate on. However, only a small portion of the three hundred and fifty pages in Lamarck's first part explains the reasons behind his conclusions—the majority of the volume is taken up with classifying animals, which we can skip since it’s not relevant to our discussion.
I shall condense whenever I can, but I do not think the reader will find that I have left out much that bears upon the argument. I shall also use inverted commas while translating with such freedom as to omit several lines together, where I can do so without suppressing anything essential to the elucidation of Lamarck's meaning. I shall, however, throughout refer the reader to the page of the original work from which I am translating.
I will summarize whenever possible, but I don’t think the reader will notice that I’ve left out much that’s relevant to the argument. I’ll also use quotation marks while translating, and I might skip several lines when it doesn’t take away anything important to clarify Lamarck’s meaning. However, I will constantly refer the reader to the page of the original work that I’m translating from.
"The common origin of bodily and mental phenomena," says Lamarck in his preliminary chapter, "has been obscured, because we have studied them[Pg 262] chiefly in man, who, as the most highly developed of living beings, presents the problem in its most difficult and complicated aspect. If we had begun our study with that of the lowest organisms, and had proceeded from these to the more complex ones, we should have seen the progression which is observable in organization, and the successive acquisition of various special organs, with new faculties for every additional organ. We should thus have seen that sense of needs—originally hardly perceptible, but gradually increasing in intensity and variety—has led to the attempt to gratify them; that the actions thus induced, having become habitual and energetic, have occasioned the development of organs adapted for their performance; that the force which excites organic movements can in the case of the lowest animals exist outside them and yet animate them; that this force was subsequently introduced into the animals themselves, and fixed within them; and, lastly, that it gave rise to sensibility and, in the end, to intelligence."[208] The reader had better be on his guard here, and whenever Lamarck is speculating about the lowest forms of action and sensation. I have thought it well, however, to give enough of these speculations, as occasion arises, to show their tendency.
"The common origin of physical and mental phenomena," Lamarck says in his introductory chapter, "has been clouded because we have mainly studied them[Pg 262] in humans, who, as the most developed living beings, present the issue in its most challenging and complex form. If we had started our study with the simplest organisms and moved on to the more complex ones, we would have observed the progression seen in organization and the gradual acquisition of various specialized organs, along with new abilities for each additional organ. We would see that the sense of needs—initially barely noticeable, but gradually becoming stronger and more diverse—led to efforts to satisfy them; that the actions prompted by these needs, having become habitual and vigorous, caused the development of organs suited for those actions; that the force motivating organic movements could, in the case of the simplest animals, exist externally yet still energize them; that this force was later incorporated into the animals themselves and established within them; and finally, that it resulted in sensitivity and ultimately intelligence." [208] The reader should be cautious here, particularly when Lamarck is speculating about the most basic forms of action and sensation. I thought it important to provide enough of these speculations, as they come up, to illustrate their direction.
"Sensation is not the proximate cause of organic movements. It may be so with the higher animals, but it cannot be shown to be so with plants, nor even with all known animals. At the outset of life there was none of that sensation which could only arise[Pg 263] where organic beings had already attained a considerable development. Nature has done all by slow gradations, both organs and faculties being the outcome of a progressive development.[209]
"Sensation is not the direct cause of physical movements. This may be true for higher animals, but it can't be proven for plants, nor for all known animals. In the beginning of life, there wasn't any sensation that could only develop where living beings had already reached a significant level of development. Nature has accomplished everything through gradual changes, with both organs and abilities resulting from progressive development.[209]
"The mere composition of an animal is but a small part of what deserves study in connection with the animal itself. The effects of its surroundings in causing new wants, the effects of its wants in giving rise to actions, those of its actions in developing habits and tendencies, the effects of use and disuse as affecting any organ, the means which nature takes to preserve and make perfect what has been already acquired—these are all matters of the highest importance.[210]
"The composition of an animal is just a small part of what we should study about it. The way its environment creates new needs, how those needs lead to actions, how those actions shape habits and tendencies, the impact of use and disuse on any organ, and the methods nature uses to preserve and enhance what has already been developed—these are all extremely important topics.[210]
"In their bearing upon these questions the invertebrate animals are more important and interesting than the vertebrate, for they are more in number, and being more in number are more varied; their variations are more marked, and the steps by which they have advanced in complexity are more easily observed.[211]
"In addressing these questions, invertebrate animals are more significant and fascinating than vertebrates because there are more of them, and because they are more numerous, they also exhibit greater diversity. Their variations are more pronounced, and the ways in which they have evolved in complexity are easier to observe.[211]
"I propose, therefore, to divide this work into three parts, of which the first shall deal with the conventions necessary for the treatment of the subject, the importance of analogical structures, and the meaning which should be attached to the word species. I will point out on the one hand the evidence of a graduated descending scale, as existing between the highest and the lowest organisms; and, on the other, the effect of surroundings and habits on the organs of living beings, as the cause of their development or arrest of development. Lastly, I will treat of the natural order of[Pg 264] animals, and show what should be their fittest classification and arrangement."[212]
"I propose to break this work into three parts. The first part will cover the necessary conventions for approaching the subject, the significance of analogical structures, and what we should understand by the term species. I will highlight, on one hand, the evidence of a graduated descending scale that exists between the most advanced and the simplest organisms, and on the other hand, the influence of the environment and habits on the organs of living beings, which leads to either their development or lack of development. Lastly, I will discuss the natural order of[Pg 264] animals and demonstrate what their most suitable classification and arrangement should be." [212]
It seems unnecessary to give Lamarck's intentions with regard to his second and third parts, as they do not here concern us; they deal with the origin of life and mind.
It seems pointless to discuss Lamarck's intentions regarding his second and third parts, as they are not relevant to us here; they focus on the origin of life and consciousness.
The first chapter of the work opens with the importance of bearing in mind the difference between the conventional and the natural, that is to say, between words and things. Here, as indeed largely throughout this part of his work, he follows Buffon, by whom he is evidently influenced.
The first chapter of the work opens with the importance of remembering the difference between the conventional and the natural, that is, between words and things. Here, as he does largely throughout this part of his work, he follows Buffon, who clearly influences him.
"The conventional deals with systems of arrangement, classification, orders, families, genera, and the nomenclature, whether of different sections or of individual objects.
"The conventional involves systems of organization, classification, orders, families, genera, and naming, whether for different sections or individual items."
"An arrangement should be called systematic, or arbitrary, when it does not conform to the genealogical order taken by nature in the development of the things arranged, and when, by consequence it is not founded upon well-considered analogies. There is such a thing as a natural order in every department of nature; it is the order in which its several component items have been successively developed.[213]
"An arrangement is considered systematic or arbitrary when it doesn’t follow the natural order that reflects how things have developed over time, and as a result, it isn’t based on well-thought-out similarities. There is a natural order in every area of nature; it’s the sequence in which its different components have evolved.[213]
"Some lines certainly seem to have been drawn by Nature herself. It was hard to believe that mammals, for example, and birds, were not well-defined classes. Nevertheless the sharpness of definition was an illusion, and due only to our limited knowledge. The ornithorhynchus and the echidna bridge the gulf.[214]
"Some boundaries definitely look like they were created by Nature herself. It’s hard to accept that mammals and birds aren’t distinct categories. However, that clarity is just an illusion, stemming from our limited understanding. The platypus and the echidna connect the gap.[214]
[Pg 265]"Simplicity is the main end of any classification. If all the races, or as they are called, species, of any kingdom were perfectly known, and if the true analogies between each species, and between the groups which species form, were also known, so that their approximations to each other and the position of the several groups were in conformity with the natural analogies between them—then classes, orders, sections, and genera would be families, larger or smaller; for each division would be a greater or smaller section of a natural order or sequence.[215] But in this case it would be very difficult to assign the limits of each division; they would be continually subjected to arbitrary alteration, and agreement would only exist where plain and palpable gaps were manifest in our series. Happily, however, for classifiers there are, and will always probably remain, a number of unknown forms."[216]
[Pg 265]"Simplicity is the primary goal of any classification. If all the races, or what we now call species, of any kingdom were completely understood, and if we also knew the true relationships between each species and the groups they form, so that their similarities and the arrangement of the various groups reflected their natural connections—then classes, orders, sections, and genera would simply be larger or smaller families; each category would be a part of a broader natural order or sequence.[215] But in this scenario, it would be quite challenging to define the boundaries of each category; they would constantly be subject to arbitrary changes, and agreement would only occur where obvious and clear gaps appeared in our classification. Fortunately for classifiers, there are, and will likely always be, many unknown forms."[216]
That the foregoing is still felt to be true by those who accept evolution, may be seen from the following passage, taken from Mr. Darwin's 'Origin of Species':—
That the above is still believed to be true by those who accept evolution can be seen in the following passage from Mr. Darwin's 'Origin of Species':—
"As all the organic beings which have ever lived can be arranged within a few great classes; and as all within each class have, according to our theory, been connected together by fine gradations, the best, and if our collections were nearly perfect, the only possible arrangement would be genealogical: descent being the hidden bond of connection which naturalists have been seeking under the term of the Natural System. On this view, we can understand how it is that in the eyes of most naturalists, the structure of the embryo is[Pg 266] even more important for classifications than that of the adult."[217]
"As all living organisms can be categorized into a few major classes, and as all members within each class have, according to our theory, been linked through subtle variations, the best and, if our collections were nearly perfect, the only feasible arrangement would be genealogical: descent being the underlying connection that naturalists have been trying to define as the Natural System. With this perspective, we can see why most naturalists consider the structure of the embryo to be even more crucial for classifications than that of the adult."[Pg 266][217]
In his second chapter Lamarck deals with the importance of comparative anatomy, and the study of homologous structures. These indicate a sort of blood relationship between the individuals in which they are found, and are our safest guide to any natural system of classification. Their importance is not confined to the study of classes, families, or even species; they must be studied also in the individuals of each species, as it is thus only, that we can recognize either identity or difference of species. The results arrived at, however, are only trustworthy over a limited period, for though the individuals of any species commonly so resemble one another at any given time, as to enable us to generalize from them, at the date of our observing them, yet species are not fixed and immutable through all time: they change, though with such extreme slowness that we do not observe their doing so, and when we come upon a species that has changed, we consider it as a new one, and as having always been such as we now see it.[218]
In his second chapter, Lamarck discusses the significance of comparative anatomy and the study of homologous structures. These structures suggest a sort of familial connection between the individuals in which they appear, and they're our best guide to any natural classification system. Their significance isn't limited to the study of classes, families, or even species; they also need to be examined in individuals of each species because that's the only way we can identify either the sameness or difference of species. However, the conclusions we draw are only reliable for a limited time, because while individuals of a species usually resemble one another closely enough at any given moment to allow for generalizations, species aren't fixed and unchanging over all time: they do evolve, albeit so slowly that we don't notice, and when we encounter a species that has changed, we treat it as something new, assuming it has always appeared as we see it now.[218]
"It is none the less true that when we compare the same kind of organs in different individuals, we can quickly and easily tell whether they are very like each other or not, and hence, whether the animals or plants in which they are found, should be set down as members of the same or of a different species. It is only therefore the general inference drawn from the[Pg 267] apparent immutability of species, that has been too inconsiderately drawn.[219]
"It is still true that when we compare similar organs in different individuals, we can quickly and easily determine whether they are very similar or not, which helps us decide if the animals or plants they belong to should be classified as the same or different species. Therefore, the general conclusion about the apparent unchanging nature of species has been drawn without sufficient consideration."
"The analogies and points of agreement between living organisms, are always incomplete when based upon the consideration of any single organ only. But though still incomplete, they will be much more important according as the organ on which they are founded is an essential one or otherwise.
"The comparisons and commonalities among living organisms are always limited when focused solely on a single organ. However, even though they are still limited, they become significantly more meaningful depending on whether the organ in question is essential or not."
"With animals, those analogies are most important which exist between organs most necessary for the conservation of their life. With plants, between their organs of generation. Hence, with animals, it will be the interior structure which will determine the most important analogies: with plants it will be the manner in which they fructify.[220]
"With animals, the most important analogies are found between the organs essential for their survival. With plants, the focus is on their reproductive organs. Therefore, for animals, it’s the internal structure that reveals the key analogies; for plants, it’s how they reproduce.[220]
"With animals we should look to nerves, organs of respiration, and those of the circulation; with plants, to the embryo and its accessories, the sexual organs of their flowers, &c.[221] To do this, will set us on to the Natural Method, which is as it were a sketch traced by man of the order taken by Nature in her productions.[222] Nevertheless the divisions which we shall be obliged to establish, will still be arbitrary and artificial, though presenting to our view sections arranged in the order which Nature has pursued.[223]
"With animals, we should focus on the nerves, the respiratory organs, and the circulatory system; for plants, we should look at the embryo and its components, the reproductive organs of their flowers, etc.[221] Doing this will guide us to the Natural Method, which is essentially a framework created by humans to reflect the order that Nature follows in her creations.[222] However, the categories we need to create will still be somewhat arbitrary and artificial, even though they will show us sections organized in the order that Nature has chosen.[223]"
"What, then," he asks,[224] "is species—and can we show that species has changed—however slowly?" He now covers some of the ground since enlarged upon in Mr. Darwin's second chapter, in which the arbitrary[Pg 268] nature of the distinction between species and varieties is so well exposed. "I shall show," says Lamarck (in substance, but I am compelled to condense much), "that the habits by which we now recognize any species, are due to the conditions of life [circonstances] under which it has for a long time existed, and that these habits have had such an influence upon the structure of each individual of the species, as to have at length modified this structure, and adapted it to the habits which have been contracted.[225]
"What, then," he asks,[224] "is a species—and can we demonstrate that species has changed—no matter how slowly?" He now covers some of the ground discussed in Mr. Darwin's second chapter, where the arbitrary[Pg 268] nature of the distinction between species and varieties is clearly outlined. "I will demonstrate," says Lamarck (in essence, but I must condense a lot), "that the traits by which we currently recognize any species are a result of the living conditions [circonstances] under which it has existed for a long time, and that these traits have significantly influenced the structure of each individual within the species, ultimately modifying this structure and adapting it to the traits that have developed.[225]
"The individuals of any species," he continues, "certainly resemble their parents; it is a universal law of nature that all offspring should differ but little from its immediate progenitors, but this does not justify the ordinary belief that species never vary. Indeed, naturalists themselves are in continual difficulty as regards distinguishing species from varieties; they do not recognize the fact that species are only constant as long as the conditions in which they are placed are constant. Individuals vary and form breeds which blend so insensibly into the neighbouring species, that the distinctions made by naturalists between species and varieties, are for the most part arbitrary, and the confusion upon this head is becoming day by day more serious.[226]
"The members of any species," he continues, "definitely resemble their parents; it’s a universal law of nature that all offspring should differ only slightly from their immediate ancestors, but this doesn’t support the common belief that species never change. In fact, naturalists often struggle to differentiate species from varieties; they fail to recognize that species remain constant only as long as the conditions they live in remain constant. Individuals vary and create breeds that merge so subtly into neighboring species that the distinctions made by naturalists between species and varieties are mostly arbitrary, and the confusion on this issue is becoming more serious every day.[226]
"Not perceiving that species will not vary as long as the conditions in which they are placed remain essentially unchanged, naturalists have supposed that each species was due to a special act of creation on the part of the Supreme Author of all things. Assuredly, nothing[Pg 269] can exist but by the will of this Supreme Author, but can we venture to assign rules to him in the execution of his will? May not his infinite power have chosen to create an order of things which should evolve in succession all that we know as well as all that we do not know? Whether we regard species as created or evolved, the boundlessness of his power remains unchanged, and incapable of any diminution whatsoever. Let us then confine ourselves simply to observing the facts around us, and if we find any clue to the path taken by Nature, let us say fearlessly that it has pleased her Almighty Author that she should take this path.[227]
"Not realizing that species won't change as long as their conditions stay mostly the same, naturalists have assumed that each species resulted from a special act of creation by the Supreme Author of everything. Of course, nothing can exist except by the will of this Supreme Author, but can we really impose rules on him regarding how his will is executed? Could it be that his infinite power has chosen to create a system that evolves and brings forth everything we know, along with everything we don’t yet understand? Whether we see species as created or evolved, the limitless nature of his power remains intact and cannot be diminished at all. So, let’s simply focus on observing the facts around us, and if we discover any insight into how Nature behaves, let’s confidently state that it has been the intention of her Almighty Author for her to follow this path.[227]"
"What applies to species applies also to genera; the further our knowledge extends, the more difficult do we find it to assign its exact limits to any genus. Gaps in our collections are being continually filled up, to the effacement of our dividing lines of demarcation. We are thus compelled to settle the limits of species and variety arbitrarily, and in a manner about which there will be constant disagreement. Naturalists are daily classifying new species which blend into one another so insensibly that there can hardly be found words to express the minute differences between them. The gaps that exist are simply due to our not having yet found the connecting species.
What applies to species also applies to genera; as our knowledge expands, it becomes harder to pinpoint the exact boundaries of any genus. The gaps in our collections are continually being filled in, blurring our dividing lines. This forces us to define the limits of species and variety in an arbitrary way, leading to ongoing disagreement. Naturalists are constantly discovering new species that blend into each other so seamlessly that it’s hard to find words to describe the subtle differences between them. The existing gaps are simply because we haven’t yet found the connecting species.
"I do not, however, mean to say that animal life forms a simple and continuously blended series. Life is rather comparable to a ramification. In life we should see, as it were, a ramified continuity, if certain species had not been lost. The species which, according[Pg 270] to this illustration, stands at the extremity of each bough, should bear a resemblance, at least upon one side, to the other neighbouring species; and this certainly is what we observe in nature.
"I don't mean to say that animal life is a simple, continuous series. Life is more like a branching structure. If certain species hadn't gone extinct, we would see a sort of branched continuity in life. The species at the end of each branch, according to this idea, should at least share some similarities with the neighboring species, and that’s definitely what we see in nature."
"Having arranged living forms in such an order as this, let us take one, and then, passing over several boughs, let us take another at some distance from it; a wide difference will now be seen between the species which the forms selected represent. Our earliest collections supplied us with such distantly allied forms only; now, however, that we have such an infinitely greater number of specimens, we can see that many of them blend one into the other without presenting noteworthy differences at any step."[228]
"Now that we've organized living forms this way, let’s select one and then, skipping several branches, choose another from a distance. We'll notice a significant difference between the species represented by our selected forms. In our earlier collections, we mostly gathered forms that were quite unrelated; however, now that we have access to an exponentially larger number of specimens, we can observe that many of them transition smoothly into one another without showing any significant differences at any point." [228]
This has been well extended by Mr. Darwin in a passage which begins:—"The affinities of all beings of the same class have sometimes been represented by a great tree. I believe that this simile largely speaks the truth."[229]
This has been well explained by Mr. Darwin in a passage that starts:—"The connections of all beings in the same class have sometimes been illustrated by a large tree. I believe this analogy mostly holds true."[229]
"What, then," continues Lamarck, "can be the cause of all this? Surely the following: namely, that when individuals of any species change their situation, climate, mode of existence, or habits [conditions of life], their structure, form, organization, and in fact their whole being becomes little by little modified, till in the course of time it responds to the changes experienced by the creature."[230]
"What, then," continues Lamarck, "could be causing all of this? It's likely the following: when individuals of any species alter their environment, climate, way of living, or habits [conditions of life], their structure, form, organization, and essentially their entire existence gradually change, until over time it adapts to the changes the creature experiences." [230]
In his preface Lamarck had already declared that "the thread which gives us a clue to the causes of the[Pg 271] various phenomena of animal organization, in the manifold diversity of its developments, is to be found in the fact that Nature conserves in offspring all that their life and environments has developed in parents." Heredity—"the hidden bond of common descent"—tempered with the modifications induced by changed habits—which changed habits are due to new conditions and surroundings—this with Lamarck, as with Buffon and Dr. Darwin, is the explanation of the diversity of forms which we observe in nature. He now goes on to support this—briefly, in accordance with his design—but with sufficient detail to prevent all possibility of mistake about his meaning.
In his preface, Lamarck had already stated that "the thread that helps us understand the causes of the[Pg 271] various phenomena of animal organization, in the wide range of its developments, can be found in the fact that Nature passes down to offspring everything that their life and environment have shaped in their parents." Heredity—"the hidden link of common descent"—along with the changes brought about by new habits—these new habits emerging from different conditions and surroundings—this, for Lamarck just like for Buffon and Dr. Darwin, explains the variety of forms we see in nature. He now continues to support this—briefly, in line with his goals—but with enough detail to eliminate any misunderstanding about his meaning.
"In the same climate differences in situation, and a greater or less degree of exposure, affect simply, in the first instance, the individuals exposed to them; but in the course of time, these repeated differences of surroundings in individuals which reproduce themselves continually under similar circumstances, induce differences which become part of their very nature; so that after many successive generations, these individuals, which were originally, we will say, of any given species, become transformed into a different one."[231]
"In the same climate, differences in circumstances and varying levels of exposure initially impact only the individuals experiencing them. However, over time, these consistent differences in surroundings for individuals that continue to exist under similar conditions lead to changes that become ingrained in their very nature. As a result, after many generations, these individuals, which we might say originally belonged to a particular species, can become transformed into a different one."[231]
"Let us suppose that a grass growing in a low-lying meadow gets carried by some accident to the brow of a neighbouring hill, where the soil is still damp enough for the plant to be able to exist. Let it live here for many generations, till it has become thoroughly accustomed to its position, and let it then gradually find its way to the dry and almost arid soil of a mountain side;[Pg 272] if the plant is able to stand the change and to perpetuate itself for many generations, it will have become so changed that botanists will class it as a new species."[232]
"Imagine a grass growing in a low meadow that accidentally gets transported to the top of a nearby hill, where the soil is still damp enough for it to survive. Let it thrive there for many generations until it becomes completely used to its new environment, and then slowly moves to the dry and nearly barren soil of a mountainside;[Pg 272] if the plant can adapt to this change and continue to reproduce for many generations, it will have changed so much that botanists will categorize it as a new species."[232]
"The same sort of process goes on in the animal kingdom, but animals are modified more slowly than plants."[233]
"The same kind of process happens in the animal kingdom, but animals change more slowly than plants." [233]
The sterility of hybrids, to which Mr. Darwin devotes a great part of the ninth chapter of his 'Origin of Species,'[234] is then touched on—briefly, but sufficiently—as follows:—
The sterility of hybrids, which Mr. Darwin discusses extensively in the ninth chapter of his 'Origin of Species,'[234] is then mentioned—briefly, but adequately—as follows:—
"The idea that species were fixed and immutable involved the belief that distinct species could not be fertile inter se. But unfortunately observation has proved, and daily proves, that this supposition is unfounded. Hybrids are very common among plants, and quite sufficiently so among animals to show that the boundaries of these so-called immutable species are not so well defined as has been supposed. Often, indeed, there is no offspring between the individuals of what are called distinct species, especially when they are widely different, and again, the offspring when produced is generally sterile; but when there is less difference between the parents, both the difficulty of breeding the hybrid, and its sterility when produced, are found to disappear. In this very power of crossing we see a source from which breeds, and ultimately species, may arise."[235]
"The idea that species are fixed and unchangeable came from the belief that distinct species couldn't breed with each other. But unfortunately, observations have shown, and continue to show, that this assumption is incorrect. Hybrids are very common among plants, and quite common among animals too, indicating that the boundaries of these so-called unchangeable species are not as clear as previously thought. Often, there isn't any offspring between individuals of what are called distinct species, especially when they are very different, and also, the offspring, when produced, is usually sterile; however, when the parents are more similar, both the difficulty of producing hybrids and their sterility tend to disappear. This ability to crossbreed is a source from which breeds, and eventually species, can emerge." [235]
Mr. Darwin arrives at the same conclusion. He writes:[Pg 273]—
Mr. Darwin comes to the same conclusion. He writes:[Pg 273]—
"We must, therefore, either give up the belief of the universal sterility of species when crossed, or we must look at this sterility in animals, not as an indelible characteristic, but as one capable of being removed by domestication.
"We must, therefore, either abandon the belief in the universal sterility of species when they interbreed, or we must view this sterility in animals not as a permanent trait, but as something that can be eliminated through domestication."
"Finally, on considering all the ascertained facts on the intercrossing of plants and animals, it may be concluded that some degree of sterility, both in first crosses and in hybrids, is an exceedingly general result, but that it cannot, under our present state of knowledge, be considered as absolutely universal."[236]
"Finally, after looking at all the confirmed facts about the breeding of plants and animals, we can conclude that some level of sterility in initial crosses and hybrids is a very common outcome. However, based on what we currently know, it can't be regarded as completely universal."[236]
Returning to Lamarck, we find him saying:—
Returning to Lamarck, we see him saying:—
"The limits, therefore, of so-called species are not so constant and unvarying as is commonly supposed. Consider also the following. All living forms upon the face of the globe have been brought forth in the course of infinite time by the process of generation only. Nature has directly created none but the lowest organisms; these she is still producing every day, they being, as it were, the first sketches of life, and produced by what is called spontaneous generation. Organs have been gradually developed in these low forms, and these organs have in the course of time increased in diversity and complexity. The power of growth in each living body has given rise to various modes of reproduction, and thus progress, already acquired, has been preserved and handed down to offspring.[237] With sufficient time, favourable conditions of life [circonstances], successive changes in the surface of the globe, and the power of new surroundings and habits to modify the organs of[Pg 274] living bodies, all animal and vegetable forms have been imperceptibly rendered such as we now see them. It follows that species will be constant only in relation to their environments, and cannot be as old as Nature herself.
"The limits of so-called species are not as fixed and unchanging as people often think. Consider this: all living forms on Earth have developed over immense time through the process of generation alone. Nature has directly created only the simplest organisms, which she continues to produce every day. These are, in a way, the initial drafts of life and come from what we call spontaneous generation. Organs have gradually evolved in these simple forms, and over time, these organs have become more diverse and complex. The ability to grow in each living organism has led to various methods of reproduction, allowing advancements to be preserved and passed down to the next generation.[237] Given enough time, favorable living conditions, changes in the Earth's surface, and the influence of new environments and habits on the structure of living beings, all animal and plant forms have gradually transformed into what we observe today. So, it follows that species will remain constant only in relation to their environments and cannot be as ancient as Nature itself."
"But what are we to say of instinct? Can we suppose that all the tricks, cunning, artifices, precautions, patience, and skill of animals are due to evolution only? Must we not see here the design of an all-powerful Creator? No one certainly will assign limits to the Creator's power, but it is a bold thing to say that he did not choose to work in this way or that way, when his own handiwork declares to us that this is the way he chose. I find proof in Nature—meaning by nature the ensemble of all that is,[238] but regarding her as herself the effect of an unknown first cause[239]—that she is the author of organization, life, and even sensation; that she has multiplied and diversified the organs and mental powers of the creatures which she sustains and reproduces; that she has developed in animals, through the sole instrumentality of sense of need as establishing and directing their habits, all actions and all habits, from the simplest up to those which constitute instinct, industry, and finally reason.[240]
"But what can we say about instinct? Can we really assume that all the tricks, cleverness, strategies, precautions, patience, and skills of animals are solely a result of evolution? Shouldn’t we acknowledge here the design of a powerful Creator? No one would definitely limit the Creator's power, but it’s a bold claim to say that he didn’t choose to work in this way or that way, especially when his own creation shows us that this is the way he chose. I find evidence in Nature—meaning by nature the whole of everything,[238] while considering her as the effect of an unknown first cause[239]—that she is the source of organization, life, and even sensation; that she has multiplied and diversified the organs and mental abilities of the creatures she supports and reproduces; that she has developed in animals, solely through the sense of need guiding their habits, all actions and habits, from the simplest to those that form instinct, work ethic, and ultimately reason.[240]
"Against this it is alleged that we have no reason to believe species to have changed within any known era. The skeletons of some Egyptian birds, preserved two or three thousand years ago, differ in no particular from the same kind of creatures at the present day. But this is what we should expect, inasmuch as the position and[Pg 275] climate of Egypt itself do not appear to have changed. If the conditions of life have not varied, why should the species subjected to those conditions have done so? Moreover, birds can move about freely, and if one place does not suit them they can find another that does. All that these Egyptian mummies really prove is, that there were animals in Egypt two or three thousand years ago which are like the animals of to-day; but how short a space is two or three thousand years, as compared with the time which Nature has had at her disposal! A time infinitely great quâ man, is still infinitely short quâ Nature.[241]
"On the contrary, it is argued that we have no reason to believe species have changed at all during any known era. The skeletons of some Egyptian birds, preserved two or three thousand years ago, are no different from those of the same species today. But this is what we would expect since the geography and climate of Egypt itself don’t seem to have changed. If the living conditions haven’t varied, why would the species that live in those conditions? Additionally, birds can move freely, and if one place isn’t suitable for them, they can find another that is. All that these Egyptian mummies really demonstrate is that there were animals in Egypt two or three thousand years ago that are similar to today’s animals; but how brief a period is two or three thousand years when compared to the vast time Nature has had at her disposal! A time which is incredibly long for humans is still incredibly short in the context of Nature."
"If, however, we turn to animals under confinement, we find immediate proof that the most startling changes are capable of being produced after some generations of changed habits. In the sixth chapter we shall have occasion to observe the power of changed conditions [circonstances] to develop new desires in animals, and to induce new courses of action; we shall see the power which these new actions will have, after a certain amount of repetition, to engender new habits and tendencies; and we shall also note the effects of use and disuse in either fortifying and developing an organ, or in diminishing it and causing it to disappear. With plants under domestication, we shall find corresponding phenomena. Species will thus appear to be unchangeable for comparatively short periods only."[242]
"If we look at animals in confinement, we can see clear evidence that significant changes can occur after several generations of altered habits. In the sixth chapter, we will observe how changing conditions can create new desires in animals and lead to new behaviors. We will see how these new actions, when repeated enough, can form new habits and tendencies. We will also examine how use and disuse can strengthen or weaken an organ, leading it to thrive or fade away. With domesticated plants, we will find similar patterns. Thus, species seem to remain unchanged for only relatively short periods."
It is interesting to see that Mr. Darwin lays no less stress on the study of animals and plants under domestication than Buffon, Dr. Darwin, and Lamarck.[Pg 276] Indeed, all four writers appear to have been in great measure led to their conclusions by this very study. "At the commencement of my investigations," writes Mr. Darwin, "it seemed to me probable that a careful study of domesticated animals and of cultivated plants would offer the best chance of making out this obscure problem. Nor have I been disappointed; in this and in all other perplexing cases, I have invariably found that our knowledge, imperfect though it be, of variation under domestication, afforded the best and safest clue. I may venture to express my conviction of the high value of such studies, though they have been very commonly neglected by naturalists."[243]
It's interesting to note that Mr. Darwin emphasizes the study of domesticated animals and plants just as much as Buffon, Dr. Darwin, and Lamarck do.[Pg 276] In fact, all four writers seem to have reached their conclusions largely through this specific study. "At the start of my investigations," Mr. Darwin writes, "I believed that a detailed examination of domesticated animals and cultivated plants would provide the best opportunity to unravel this complex issue. I haven't been let down; in this and all other challenging situations, I've consistently found that our understanding—albeit imperfect—of variation in domestication has provided the best and most reliable insight. I feel confident in expressing my belief in the significant value of such studies, even though they are often overlooked by naturalists."[243]
In justice to the three writers whom I have named, it should be borne in mind that they also ventured to express their conviction of the high value of these studies. Buffon, indeed, as we have seen, gives animals under domestication the foremost place in his work. He does not treat of wild animals till he has said all he has to say upon our most important domesticated breeds,—on whose descent from one or two wild stocks he is never weary of insisting. It was doubtless because of the opportunities they afforded him for demonstrating the plasticity of living organism that the most important position in his work was assigned to them.
In fairness to the three writers I mentioned, it's important to note that they also expressed their strong belief in the significant value of these studies. Buffon, as we've seen, prioritizes domesticated animals in his work. He doesn't discuss wild animals until he fully explores our most important domesticated breeds, emphasizing their descent from one or two wild ancestors. The reason he gave them such a prominent role in his work was likely due to the opportunities they provided for demonstrating the adaptability of living organisms.
Lamarck professes himself unable to make up his mind about extinct species; how far, that is to say, whole breeds must be considered as having died out, or how far the difference between so many now living and[Pg 277] fossil forms is due to the fact that our living species are modified descendants of the fossil ones. Such large parts of the globe were still practically unknown in Lamarck's time, and the recent discovery of the ornithorhynchus has raised such hopes as to what might yet be found in Australia, that he was inclined to think that only such creatures as man found hurtful to him, as, for example, the megatherium and the mastodon, had become truly extinct, nor was he, it would seem, without a hope that these would yet one day be discovered. The climatic and geological changes that have occurred in past ages, would, he believed, account for all the difference which we observe between living and fossil forms, inasmuch as they would have changed the conditions under which animals lived, and therefore their habits and organs would have become correspondingly modified. He therefore rather wondered to find so much, than so little, resemblance between existing and fossil forms.
Lamarck admits that he's unsure about extinct species; specifically, how many whole breeds should be considered completely gone, or how much of the difference between so many living species and[Pg 277] fossil forms is because our living species are modified descendants of the fossil ones. So much of the globe was still largely unexplored during Lamarck's time, and the recent discovery of the platypus sparked such excitement about what else might be found in Australia that he tended to believe that only those creatures that humans found harmful, like the megatherium and the mastodon, had truly gone extinct. He also seemed to hold out hope that these creatures might one day be discovered. He believed that the climatic and geological changes that happened in the past could explain all the differences we see between living and fossil forms, as they would have altered the conditions in which animals lived, thereby modifying their habits and features. Consequently, he was more surprised to see so much resemblance between current and fossil forms rather than finding little of it.
Buffon took a juster view of this matter; it will be remembered that he concluded his remarks upon the mammoth by saying that many species had doubtless disappeared without leaving any living descendants, while others had left descendants which had become modified.
Buffon had a more accurate perspective on this issue; it’s worth noting that he wrapped up his comments on the mammoth by stating that many species had likely vanished without leaving any living descendants, while others had left behind descendants that had changed over time.
Lamarck anticipated Lyell in supposing geological changes to have been due almost entirely to the continued operation of the causes which we observe daily at work in nature: thus he writes:—
Lamarck anticipated Lyell by suggesting that geological changes were mainly caused by the ongoing effects of the factors we see operating in nature every day: so he writes:—
"Every observer knows that the surface of the earth has changed; every valley has been exalted, the[Pg 278] crooked has been made straight, and the rough places plain; not even is climate itself stable. Hence changed conditions; and these involve changed needs and habits of life; if such changes can give rise to modifications or developments, it is clear that every living body must vary, especially in its outward character, though the variation can only be perceptible after several generations.
"Every observer knows that the surface of the earth has changed; every valley has been raised up, the[Pg 278] crooked has been straightened, and the rough areas have become smooth; even the climate is not stable. This leads to changed conditions, which involve changed needs and ways of life; if these changes can lead to modifications or developments, it’s clear that every living being must adapt, especially in its outward appearance, although this variation can only be noticeable after several generations."
"It is not surprising then that so few living species should be represented in the geologic record. It is surprising rather that we should find any living species represented at all.[244]
"It’s not surprising that so few living species are found in the geologic record. What is surprising is that we find any living species at all.[244]
"Catastrophes have indeed been supposed, and they are an easy way of getting out of the difficulty; but unfortunately, they are not supported by evidence. Local catastrophes have undoubtedly occurred, as earthquakes and volcanic eruptions, of which the effects can be sufficiently seen; but why suppose any universal catastrophe, when the ordinary progress of nature suffices to account for the phenomena? Nature is never brusque. She proceeds slowly step by step, and this with occasional local catastrophes will remove all our difficulties."[245]
"Catastrophes have been suggested, and they’re an easy way to escape the problem; but unfortunately, there’s no supporting evidence. Local catastrophes, such as earthquakes and volcanic eruptions, have definitely happened, and their effects can be clearly seen; but why assume a universal catastrophe when the normal progress of nature is enough to explain the phenomena? Nature is never brusque. She moves slowly, step by step, and with occasional local catastrophes, we can solve all our problems."[245]
In his fourth chapter Lamarck points out that animals move themselves, or parts of themselves, not through impulsion or movement communicated to them as from one billiard ball to another, but by reason of a cause which excites their irritability, which cause is within some animals and forms part of them, while it is wholly outside of others.[246]
In his fourth chapter, Lamarck highlights that animals move themselves, or parts of themselves, not due to an impulse or motion transferred to them like one billiard ball hitting another, but because of a cause that stimulates their sensitivity. This cause exists within some animals and is a part of them, while it is completely external to others.[246]
[Pg 279]I should again warn the reader to be on his guard against the opinion that any animals can be said to live if they have no "inward motion" of their own which prompts them to act. We cannot call anything alive which moves only as wind and water may make it move, but without any impulse from within to execute the smallest action and without any capacity of feeling. Such a creature does not look sufficiently like the other things which we call alive; it should be first shown to us, so that we may make up our minds whether the facts concerning it have been truly stated, and if so, what it most resembles; we may then classify it accordingly.
[Pg 279]I should once again remind the reader to be cautious about the belief that any animals can be considered alive if they lack an "inward motion" that drives them to act. We can't call anything alive that only moves due to the influence of wind and water, without any internal urge to perform even the smallest action or any ability to feel. Such a creature doesn't resemble the other things we label as alive; it should first be presented to us so we can determine whether the information about it has been accurately represented, and if so, what it is most similar to; we can then categorize it accordingly.
"Some animals change their place by creeping, some by walking, some by running or leaping; others again fly, while others live in the water and swim.
"Some animals move by crawling, some by walking, some by running or jumping; others can fly, while others live in water and swim."
"The origin of these different kinds of locomotion is to be found in the two great wants of animal life: 1, the means of procuring food; 2, the search after mates with a view to reproduction.
The origin of these different types of movement stems from two main needs of animal life: 1, the way to get food; 2, the pursuit of partners for reproduction.
"Since then the power of locomotion was a matter affecting their individual self-preservation, as well as that of their race, the existence of the want led to the means of its being gratified."[247]
"Since then, the ability to move around became essential for their survival and that of their species, and the need for it led to ways of satisfying that need."[247]
Lamarck is practically at one with Dr. Erasmus Darwin, that modification will commonly travel along three main lines which spring from the need of reproduction, of procuring food, and (Dr. Darwin has added) the power of self-protection; but Dr. Darwin's treatment of this part of his subject is more lucid and[Pg 280] satisfactory than Lamarck's, inasmuch as he immediately brings forward instances of various modifications which have in each case been due to one of the three main desires above specified, namely, reproduction, subsistence, and self-defence.
Lamarck completely agrees with Dr. Erasmus Darwin that changes typically occur along three main paths driven by the needs for reproduction, finding food, and (as Dr. Darwin adds) self-protection. However, Dr. Darwin explains this aspect of his topic more clearly and[Pg 280] effectively than Lamarck does, as he quickly provides examples of different changes that can be attributed to one of these three main needs: reproduction, survival, and self-defense.
Lamarck concludes the chapter with some passages which show that he was alive—as what Frenchman could fail to be after Buffon had written?—to the consequences which must follow from the geometrical ratio of increase, and to the struggle for existence, with consequent survival of the fittest, which must always be one of the conditions of any wild animal's existence. The paragraphs, indeed, on this subject are taken with very little alteration from Buffon's work. As Lamarck's theory is based upon the fact that it is on the nature of these conditions that the habits and consequently the structure of any animal will depend, he must have seen that the shape of many of its organs must vary greatly in correlation to the conditions to which it was subjected in the matter of self-protection. I do not see, then, that there is any substantial difference between the positions taken by Dr. Erasmus Darwin and by Lamarck in this respect.
Lamarck wraps up the chapter with some sections that reveal he was aware—after all, what Frenchman wouldn't be after Buffon's writings?—of the implications of geometric growth and the struggle for survival, which leads to the survival of the fittest, a constant factor for any wild animal's existence. The paragraphs on this topic are largely taken with very few changes from Buffon's work. Since Lamarck's theory hinges on the idea that the nature of these conditions affects an animal's habits and ultimately its structure, he must have recognized that the shape of many of its organs could vary significantly based on the conditions it faced for self-protection. Therefore, I don't see any substantial difference between the views held by Dr. Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck on this matter.
"Let us conclude," he writes, "by showing the means employed by nature to prevent the number of her creatures from injuring the conservation of what has been produced already, and of the general order which should subsist.[248]
"Let’s wrap this up," he writes, "by highlighting the ways nature works to ensure that the population of its creatures does not harm the preservation of what has already been created, as well as the overall order that should exist.[248]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"In consequence of the extremely rapid rate of increase[Pg 281] of the smaller, and especially of the most imperfect, animals, their numbers would become so great as to prove injurious to the conservation of breeds, and to the progress already made towards more perfect organization, unless nature had taken precautions to keep them down within certain fixed limits which she cannot exceed."[249]
"As a result of the extremely fast growth rate of the smaller, especially the least developed animals, their populations could become so large that they would harm the preservation of breeds and the progress already achieved towards more advanced organization, unless nature had taken steps to keep them within certain fixed limits that she cannot surpass."
This seems to contain, and in a nutshell, as much of the essence of what Mr. Herbert Spencer and Mr. Charles Darwin have termed the survival of the fittest in the struggle for existence, as was necessary for Lamarck's purpose.
This seems to capture, in a nutshell, much of what Mr. Herbert Spencer and Mr. Charles Darwin called the survival of the fittest in the struggle for existence, which was necessary for Lamarck's purpose.
To Lamarck, as to Dr. Darwin and Buffon, it was perfectly clear that the facts, that animals have to find their food under varying circumstances, and that they must defend themselves in all manner of varying ways against other creatures which would eat them if they could, were simply some of the conditions of their existence. In saying that the surrounding circumstances—which amount to the conditions of existence—determined the direction in which any plant or animal should be slowly modified, Lamarck includes as a matter of course the fact that the "stronger and better armed should eat the weaker," and thus survive and bear offspring which would inherit the strength and better armour of its parents. Nothing therefore can be more at variance with the truth than to represent Lamarck and the other early evolutionists as ignoring the struggle for existence and the survival of the fittest; these are inevitably implied whenever they use the word "circonstances"[Pg 282] or environment, as I will more fully show later on, and are also expressly called attention to by the greater number of them.[250]
To Lamarck, like Dr. Darwin and Buffon, it was clear that animals must find food under different circumstances and defend themselves in various ways against creatures that would eat them if they had the chance. He argued that these surrounding circumstances—essentially the conditions of existence—determined how any plant or animal would gradually change. Lamarck naturally included the idea that "the stronger and better equipped will prey on the weaker," allowing them to survive and reproduce, passing on the strength and better defenses of their parents. Therefore, it’s completely false to portray Lamarck and other early evolutionists as ignoring the struggle for existence and the survival of the fittest; these concepts are inherently included whenever they talk about "circonstances"[Pg 282] or the environment, as I will explain in more detail later, and are explicitly pointed out by most of them.[250]
"Animals, except those which are herbivorous, prey upon one another; and the herbivorous are exposed to the attacks of the flesh-eating races.
"Animals, except for those that are herbivores, hunt each other; and herbivores are vulnerable to attacks from meat-eating species."
"The strongest and best armed for attack eat the weaker, and the greater kinds eat the smaller. Individuals of the same race rarely eat one another; they war only with other races than their own."[251]
"The strongest and best-equipped for attack prey on the weaker, and the bigger species consume the smaller. Members of the same species rarely harm each other; they only fight against different species." [251]
Dr. Darwin here again has the advantage over Lamarck; for he has pointed out how the males contend with one another for the possession of the females, which I do not find Lamarck to have done, though he would at once have admitted the fact. Lamarck continues:—
Dr. Darwin has the edge over Lamarck here because he highlights how the males compete with each other for access to females, something I don't see Lamarck addressing, even though he would definitely acknowledge the reality of it. Lamarck continues:—
"The smaller kinds of animals breed so numerously and so rapidly that they would people the globe to the exclusion of other forms of life, if nature had not limited their inconceivable multitude. As, however, they are the prey of a number of other creatures, live but a short time, and perish easily with cold, they are kept always within the proportions necessary for the maintenance both of their own and of other races.[252]
"The smaller types of animals reproduce so quickly and in such large numbers that they could overpopulate the planet, pushing out other forms of life, if nature hadn’t kept their astonishing numbers in check. However, since they are prey for many other creatures, have short lifespans, and easily die from the cold, they are always kept in the balance needed to sustain both their own species and others." [252]
"As regards the larger and stronger animals, they would become dominant, and be injurious to the conservation of many other races, if they could multiply in too great numbers. But as it is, they devour one another, and breed but slowly, and few at a birth, so[Pg 283] that equilibrium is duly preserved among them. Man alone is the unquestionably dominant animal, but men war among themselves, so that it may be safely said the world will never be peopled to its utmost capacity."[253]
"As for the larger and stronger animals, they would take over and harm the survival of many other species if they could reproduce in excessive numbers. However, they end up eating each other, reproduce slowly, and have few offspring at a time, so[Pg 283] balance is maintained among them. Humans are the clearly dominant species, but they fight among themselves, so it can be confidently stated that the world will never be populated to its full potential."[253]
In his fifth chapter Lamarck returns to the then existing arrangement and classification of animals.
In his fifth chapter, Lamarck revisits the current organization and classification of animals.
"Naturalists having remarked that many species, and some genera and even families present characters which as it were isolate them, it has been imagined that these approached or drew further from each other according as their points of agreement or difference seemed greater or less when set down as it were on a chart or map. They regard the small well-marked series which have been styled natural families, as groups which should be placed between the isolated species and their nearest neighbours so as to form a kind of reticulation. This idea, which some of our modern naturalists have held to be admirable, is evidently mistaken, and will be discarded on a profounder and more extended knowledge of organization, and more especially when the distinction has been duly drawn between what is due to the action of special conditions and to general advance of organization."[254]
"Naturalists have observed that many species, and some genera and even families, have traits that set them apart. It has been thought that these groups are either getting closer or farther from each other based on how much they agree or differ, as if plotted on a chart or map. They view the small, well-defined series referred to as natural families as groups that should be placed between isolated species and their closest neighbors to create a sort of network. This idea, which some modern naturalists consider wonderful, is clearly misguided and will be abandoned as we gain a deeper and broader understanding of organization, especially once we accurately differentiate between what arises from specific conditions and what results from overall advancements in organization." [254]
[Pg 284]I take it that Lamarck is here attempting to express what Mr. Charles Darwin has rendered much more clearly in the following excellent passage:—
[Pg 284]I assume that Lamarck is trying to convey what Mr. Charles Darwin has articulated much more clearly in the following excellent passage:—
"It should always be borne in mind what sort of intermediate forms must, on the theory [what theory?], have formerly existed. I have found it difficult when looking at any two species to avoid picturing to myself forms directly intermediate between them. But this is a wholly false view; we should always look for forms intermediate between each species and a common but unknown progenitor; and the progenitor will generally have differed in some respects from all its modified descendants. To give a simple illustration: the fantail and pouter pigeons are both descended from the rock pigeon. If we possessed all the intermediate varieties which have ever existed, we should have an extremely close series, between both and the rock pigeon; but we should have no varieties directly intermediate between the fantail and the pouter; none, for instance, combining a tail somewhat expanded with a crop somewhat enlarged, the characteristic features of these two breeds. These two breeds, moreover, have become so much modified that, if we had no historical or indirect evidence regarding their origin, it would not have been possible to have determined, from a mere comparison of their structure with that of the rock[Pg 285] pigeon C. livia, whether they had descended from this species, or from some other allied form, as C. œnas.
It should always be kept in mind what kind of intermediate forms must, according to the theory, have existed in the past. I find it hard, when looking at any two species, to avoid imagining forms directly between them. But that's completely a wrong perspective; we should instead look for forms that are intermediate between each species and a common but unknown ancestor. This ancestor will usually have been different in some ways from all its modified descendants. To give a simple example: the fantail and pouter pigeons both come from the rock pigeon. If we had all the intermediate varieties that have ever existed, we would have a very close series between both and the rock pigeon; but we wouldn’t have any varieties that are directly intermediate between the fantail and the pouter, none that, for example, combine a somewhat expanded tail with a somewhat enlarged crop, which are the key features of these two breeds. Additionally, these two breeds have been modified to such an extent that if we didn't have historical or indirect evidence about their origin, we wouldn't be able to tell, just by comparing their structure with that of the rock pigeon C. livia, whether they descended from this species or from some other related form, like C. œnas.
"So with natural species, if we look to forms very distinct—for instance, to the horse and the tapir—we have no reason to suppose that links directly intermediate between them ever existed, but between each and an unknown common parent. The common parent will have had in its whole organization much general resemblance to the tapir and the horse; but in some points of structure it may have differed considerably from both, even perhaps more than they differ from each other. Hence in all such cases we should be unable to recognize the parent form of any two or more species, even if we closely compared the structure of the parent with that of its modified descendants, unless at the same time we had a nearly perfect chain of the intermediate links.
"So with natural species, if we look at very distinct forms—for example, the horse and the tapir—we have no reason to think that there were direct links between them, only that each has an unknown common ancestor. The common ancestor likely had a lot in common with both the tapir and the horse, but in some structural aspects, it may have differed significantly from both, possibly even more than they differ from each other. Therefore, in these cases, we wouldn't be able to identify the parent form of any two or more species, even if we carefully compared the structure of the parent with that of its modified descendants, unless we also had a nearly complete chain of the intermediate links."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"By the theory of natural selection [surely this is a slip for "by the theory of descent with modification"] all living species have been connected with the parent species of each genus, by differences not greater than we see between the natural and domestic varieties of the same species at the present day; and their parent species, now generally extinct, have in their turn been similarly connected with more ancient forms, and so on backwards, always converging to the common ancestor of each great class; so that the number of intermediate and transitional links between all living and extinct species must have been inconceivably great. But assuredly if this theory [the theory of descent with[Pg 286] modification or that of "natural selection"?] be true, such have lived upon the earth."[255]
"According to the theory of natural selection [this is likely a mistake for "the theory of descent with modification"], all living species are connected to their parent species by differences no greater than those we observe between natural and domesticated varieties of the same species today; and their parent species, which are mostly extinct now, have also been linked to even older forms, and so on back, always tracing back to the common ancestor of each major class; therefore, the number of intermediate and transitional links between all living and extinct species must have been unimaginably large. But if this theory [the theory of descent with[Pg 286] modification or that of "natural selection"?] is true, such species have indeed existed on Earth." [255]
To return, however, to Lamarck.
To get back to Lamarck.
"Though Nature," he continues, "in the course of long time has evolved all animals and plants in a true scale of progression, the steps of this scale can be perceived only in the principal groups of living forms; it cannot be perceived in species nor even in genera. The reason of this lies in the extreme diversity of the surroundings in which each different race of animals and plants has existed. These surroundings have often been out of harmony with the growing organization of the plants and animals themselves; this has led to anomalies, and, as it were, digressions, which the mere development of organization by itself could not have occasioned."[256] Or, in other words, to that divergency of type which is so well insisted on by Mr. Charles Darwin.
"Although Nature," he goes on, "over a long period has developed all animals and plants in a true progression, the stages of this progression can only be seen in the major groups of living things; they can't be seen in individual species or even in genera. This is because of the extreme variety of environments where each different species of animals and plants has lived. These environments have often clashed with the evolving traits of the plants and animals themselves; this has caused irregularities and, in a sense, detours that the simple development of traits alone wouldn’t have caused."[256] In other words, this refers to the divergence in types that Mr. Charles Darwin emphasizes so well.
"It is only therefore the principal groups of animal and vegetable life which can be arranged in a vertical line of descent; species and even genera cannot always be so—for these contain beings whose organization has been dependent on the possession of such and such a special system of essential organs.
"It is only the main groups of animal and plant life that can be arranged in a vertical line of descent; species and even genera cannot always be placed this way—because these include organisms whose structure relies on having specific essential organ systems."
"Each great and separate group has its own system of essential organs, and it is these systems which can be seen to descend, within the limits of the group, from their most complex to their simplest form. But each organ, considered individually, does not descend by equally regular gradation; the gradations are less and[Pg 287] less regular according as the organ is of less importance, and is more susceptible of modification by the conditions which surround it. Organs of small importance, and not essential to existence, are not always either perfected or degraded at an equal rate, so that in observing all the species of any class we find an organ in one species in the highest degree of perfection, while another organ, which in this same species is impoverished or very imperfect, is highly developed in another species of the same group."[257]
"Each major group has its own system of essential organs, and these systems can be seen to progress from their most complex forms to their simplest within the group. However, when looking at each organ individually, the progression isn't always equally consistent; the variations become less regular as the organ's significance decreases and as it becomes more influenced by its surrounding conditions. Organs that are less crucial for survival do not always evolve or decline at the same rate, so when examining all the species within a class, we may find one organ in a particular species is highly advanced, while another organ, which in that same species is underdeveloped or flawed, is very well developed in a different species from the same group." [Pg 287] [257]
The facts maintained in the preceding paragraph are in great measure supported by Mr. Charles Darwin, who, however, assigns their cause to natural selection.
The facts mentioned in the previous paragraph are largely backed by Mr. Charles Darwin, who, however, attributes their cause to natural selection.
Mr. Darwin writes, "Ordinary specific characters are more variable than generic;" and again, a little lower down, "The points in which all the species of a genus resemble each other, and in which they differ from allied genera, are called generic characters; and these characters may be attributed to inheritance from a common progenitor, for it can rarely happen that natural selection will have modified several distinct species fitted to more or less widely different habits, in exactly the same manner; and as these so called generic characters have been inherited from before the period when the several species first branched off from their common progenitor, and subsequently have not varied or come to differ in any degree, or only in a slight degree, it is not probable that they should vary at the present day. On the other hand, the points in which species differ from other species of the same genus are[Pg 288] called specific characters; and as these specific characters have varied and come to differ since the period when the species branched off from a common progenitor, it is probable that they should still often be in some degree variable, or at least more variable than those parts of the organization which have for a very long time remained constant."[258]
Mr. Darwin writes, "Ordinary specific characteristics are more variable than generic ones;" and later, he states, "The traits that all species of a genus share, and that distinguish them from related genera, are called generic characters; these traits can be traced back to inheritance from a common ancestor, since it rarely occurs that natural selection modifies several distinct species suited to varying habits in precisely the same way; and because these so-called generic characters were inherited from the time before the species diverged from their common ancestor, and have not significantly changed or differ only slightly since then, it’s unlikely that they will vary today. On the other hand, the features that differentiate species within the same genus are called specific characters; and because these specific characters have changed and diverged since the time the species split from a common ancestor, it’s likely they will still be somewhat variable, or at least more variable than those parts of the organization that have remained stable for a very long time."[Pg 288][258]
The fact, then, that it is specific characters which vary most is agreed upon by both Lamarck and Mr. Darwin. Lamarck, however, maintains that it is these specific characters which are most capable of being affected by the habits of the creature, and that it is for this reason they will be most variable, while Mr. Darwin simply says they are most variable, and that, this being so, the favourable variations will be preserved and accumulated—an assertion which Lamarck would certainly not demur to.
Both Lamarck and Mr. Darwin agree that specific characters are the ones that vary the most. However, Lamarck argues that these specific characters can be most influenced by the creature's habits, and that's why they will be the most variable. Meanwhile, Mr. Darwin points out that they simply *are* the most variable, and because of this, favorable variations will be preserved and accumulated—something Lamarck would definitely agree with.
"Irregular degrees of perfection," says Lamarck, "and degradation in the less essential organs, are due to the fact that these are more liable than the more essential ones to the influence of external circumstances: these induce corresponding differences in the more outward parts of the animal, and give rise to such considerable and singular difference in species, that instead of being able to arrange them in a direct line of descent, as we can arrange the main groups, these species often form lateral ramifications round about the main groups to which they belong, and in their extreme development are truly isolated."[259]
"Irregular levels of perfection," says Lamarck, "and decline in the less essential organs, occur because these are more susceptible than the more essential ones to the influence of external factors. These influences lead to noticeable differences in the more superficial parts of the animal, resulting in such significant and unique variations in species that, instead of being arranged in a straightforward line of descent like the main groups, these species often branch off laterally around the main groups they belong to, and in their most advanced form, are truly isolated."[259]
In his summary of the second chapter of his 'Origin[Pg 289] of Species,' Mr. Darwin well confirms this when he says, "In large genera the species are apt to be closely, but unequally, allied together, forming little clusters round other species."
In his summary of the second chapter of his 'Origin[Pg 289] of Species,' Mr. Darwin effectively supports this by stating, "In large genera, the species tend to be closely, but unevenly, related to each other, forming small clusters around other species."
"A longer time," says Lamarck, "and a greater influence of surrounding conditions, is necessary in order to modify interior organs. Nevertheless we see that Nature does pass from one system to another without any sudden leap, when circumstances require it, provided the systems are not too far apart. Her method is to proceed from the more simple to the more complex.[260]
"A longer time," says Lamarck, "and a stronger influence from surrounding conditions, is needed to change internal organs. Still, we notice that Nature transitions from one system to another without any abrupt changes when it's necessary, as long as the systems aren't too different. Her approach is to move from the simpler to the more complex.[260]
"She does this not only in the race, but in the individual." Here Lamarck, like Dr. Erasmus Darwin, shows his perception of the importance of embryology in throwing light on the affinities of animals—as since more fully insisted on by the author of the 'Vestiges of Creation,' and by Mr. Darwin,[261] as well as by other writers. "Breathing through gills is nearer to breathing through lungs than breathing through trachea is. Not only do we see Nature pass from gills to lungs in families which are not too far apart, as may be seen by considering the case of fishes and reptiles; but she does so during the existence of a single individual, which may successively make use both of the one and of the other system. The frog while yet a tadpole breathes through gills; on becoming a frog it breathes through lungs; but we cannot find that Nature in any case passes from trachea to lungs."[262]
"She does this not just in the race, but in the individual." Here, Lamarck, similar to Dr. Erasmus Darwin, demonstrates his understanding of how essential embryology is for shedding light on the connections between animals—as has been more extensively discussed by the author of the 'Vestiges of Creation' and by Mr. Darwin,[261] along with other writers. "Breathing through gills is more similar to breathing through lungs than breathing through trachea is. Not only do we observe Nature transitioning from gills to lungs in families that are not too distantly related, as can be seen in the cases of fish and reptiles, but she also does so within the lifespan of a single individual, which may use both systems successively. The frog, while still a tadpole, breathes through gills; upon becoming a frog, it breathes through lungs; however, we cannot find any instance where Nature transitions from trachea to lungs."[262]
[Pg 290]Lamarck now rapidly reviews previous classifications, and propounds his own, which stands thus:—I. Vertebrata, consisting of Mammals, Birds, Fishes, and Reptiles. II. Invertebrata, consisting of Molluscs, Centipedes, Annelids, Crustacea, Arachnids, Insects, Worms, Radiata, Polyps, Infusoria.
[Pg 290]Lamarck quickly goes over earlier classifications and presents his own, which is structured as follows: I. Vertebrates, including Mammals, Birds, Fishes, and Reptiles. II. Invertebrates, including Mollusks, Centipedes, Annelids, Crustaceans, Arachnids, Insects, Worms, Radiates, Polyps, Infusoria.
"The degradation of organism," he concludes, "in this descending scale is not perfectly even, and cannot be made so by any classification, nevertheless there is such evidence of sustained degradation in the principal groups as must point in the direction of some underlying general principle."[263]
"The decline of organisms," he concludes, "in this descending scale is not perfectly uniform, and no classification can make it so; however, there is enough evidence of ongoing decline in the main groups that suggests an underlying general principle."[263]
Lamarck's sixth chapter is headed "Degradation and Simplification of the Animal Chain as we proceed downwards from the most complex to the most simple Organisms."
Lamarck's sixth chapter is titled "Degradation and Simplification of the Animal Chain as we move downwards from the most complex to the simplest Organisms."
"This is a positive fact, and results from the operation of a constant law of nature; but a disturbing cause, which can be easily recognized, varies the regular operation of the law from one end to the other of the chain of life.[264]
"This is a good thing, and it happens because of a constant natural law; however, a noticeable factor, which is easy to identify, disrupts the consistent function of the law throughout the entire chain of life.[264]
"We can see, nevertheless, that special organs become more and more simple the lower we descend; that they become changed, impoverished, and attenuated little by little; that they lose their local centres, and finally become definitely annihilated before we reach the lowest extremity of the chain.[265]
"We can see, however, that specialized organs become simpler the lower we go; that they gradually change, become less complex, and shrink bit by bit; that they lose their specific local functions, and eventually are completely destroyed before we reach the very bottom of the chain.[265]
"As has been said already, the degradation of organism is not always regular; such and such an organ often fails or changes suddenly, and sometimes[Pg 291] in its changes assumes forms which are not allied with any others by steps that we can recognize. An organ may disappear and reappear several times before being entirely lost: but this is what we might expect, for the cause which has led to the evolution of living organisms has evolved many varieties, due to external influences. Nevertheless, looking at organization broadly, we observe a descending scale."[266]
"As mentioned before, the decline of organisms isn't always consistent; certain organs can suddenly stop functioning or change, and sometimes[Pg 291] during these changes, they take on forms that don’t relate to others in a way we can identify. An organ might disappear and then reappear multiple times before it's completely gone: this is what we might expect, as the processes that led to the evolution of living organisms have produced many variations due to external factors. However, when we look at organization as a whole, we see a descending scale."[266]
"If the tendency to progressive development was the only cause which had influenced the forms and organs of animals, development would have been regular throughout the animal chain; but it has not been so: Nature is compelled to submit her productions to an environment which acts upon them, and variation in environment will induce variation in organism: this is the true cause of the sometimes strange deviations from the direct line of progression which we shall have to observe.[267]
"If the tendency for progress to develop was the only factor affecting the forms and organs of animals, development would have been consistent throughout the animal kingdom; but that hasn’t happened: Nature has to adapt her creations to an environment that impacts them, and changes in the environment will lead to changes in organisms: this is the real reason for the often unusual deviations from the straightforward path of progression that we will see." [267]
"If Nature had only called aquatic beings into existence, and if these beings had lived always in the same climate, in the same kind of water, and at the same depth, the organization of these animals would doubtless have presented an even and regular scale of development. But there has been fresh water, salt water, running and stagnant water, warm and cold climates, an infinite variety of depth: animals exposed to these and other differences in their surroundings have varied in accordance with them.[268] In like manner those animals which have been gradually fitted for living in air instead of water have been subjected to[Pg 292] an endless diversity in their surroundings. The following law, then, may be now propounded, namely:—
"If nature had only created aquatic beings and if they had always lived in the same climate, in the same kind of water, and at the same depth, the structure of these animals would likely have shown a consistent and regular scale of development. However, there has been fresh water, salt water, flowing and stagnant water, warm and cold climates, and an endless variety of depths: animals facing these and other changes in their environment have adapted accordingly.[268] Similarly, those animals that have gradually adapted to living in air instead of water have experienced countless differences in their surroundings. Therefore, the following principle can now be stated:—
"That anomalies in the development of organism are due to the influences of the environment and to the habits of the creature.[269]
That irregularities in the development of an organism are caused by environmental influences and the habits of the creature.[269]
"Some have said that the anomalies above mentioned are so great as to disprove the existence of any scale which should indicate descent; but the nearer we approach species, the smaller we see differences become, till with species itself we find them at times almost imperceptible."[270]
"Some have argued that the mentioned anomalies are so significant that they disprove any scale that would show descent; however, as we get closer to species, we notice that the differences become smaller, until with the species itself, we sometimes find them almost undetectable." [270]
Lamarck here devotes about seventy pages to a survey of the animal kingdom in its entirety, beginning with the mammals and ending with the infusoria. He points out the manner in which organ after organ disappears as we descend the scale, till we are left with a form which, though presenting all the characteristics of life, has yet no special organ whatever. I am obliged to pass this classification over, but do so very unwillingly, for it is illustrative of Lamarck, both at his best and at his worst.
Lamarck spends around seventy pages surveying the whole animal kingdom, starting with mammals and ending with infusoria. He shows how each organ disappears as we move down the scale until we reach a form that, while it has all the signs of life, lacks any specific organ. I have to skip over this classification, but I do so reluctantly, as it reflects Lamarck at both his best and his worst.
The seventh chapter is headed—
Chapter seven is titled—
"On the influence of their surroundings on the actions and habits of animals, and on the effect of these habits and actions in modifying their organization."
"On how their environment affects the behaviors and habits of animals, and how these habits and behaviors change their physical structure."
"The effect of different conditions of our organization upon our character, tendencies, actions, and even our ideas, has been often remarked, but no attention has yet been paid to that of our actions and habits upon our organization itself. These actions and habits depend[Pg 293] entirely upon our relations to the surroundings in which we habitually exist; we shall have occasion, therefore, to see how great is the effect of environment upon organization.
"The impact of various conditions within our organization on our character, tendencies, actions, and even our ideas has been noted many times, but no one has really looked into how our actions and habits affect the organization itself. These actions and habits depend[Pg 293] entirely on our relationships with the environments we regularly inhabit; therefore, we will explore just how significant the effect of our surroundings is on our organization."
"But for our having domesticated plants and animals we should never have arrived at the perception of this truth; for though the influence of the environment is at all times and everywhere active upon all living bodies, its effects are so gradual that they can only be perceived over long periods of time.[271]
"But if we hadn't domesticated plants and animals, we would never have realized this truth; because while the environment constantly affects all living beings, its effects are so gradual that they can only be seen over long stretches of time.[271]
"Taking the chain of life in the inverse order of nature—that is to say, from man downwards—we certainly perceive a sustained but irregular degradation of organism, with an increasing simplicity both in organism and faculties.
"Looking at the chain of life in the opposite order of nature—that is, from humans downwards—we definitely see a steady but uneven decline in organisms, along with a growing simplicity in both their structure and abilities."
"This fact should throw light upon the order taken by nature, but it does not show us why the gradation is so irregular, nor why throughout its extent we find so many anomalies or digressions which have apparently no order at all in their manifold varieties.[272] The explanation of this must be sought for in the infinite diversity of circumstances under which organisms have been developed. On the one hand, there is a tendency to a regular progressive development; on the other, there is a host of widely different surroundings which tend continually to destroy the regularity of development.
"This fact should clarify the order found in nature, but it doesn’t explain why the gradation is so uneven, nor why there are so many anomalies or deviations that seem to lack any order in their numerous variations.[272] The reason for this must be found in the endless variety of conditions in which organisms have developed. On one hand, there is a tendency for regular progressive development; on the other hand, there are numerous differing environments that constantly disrupt the regularity of development."
"It is necessary to explain what is meant by such expressions as 'the effect of its environment upon the form and organization of an animal.' It must not be[Pg 294] supposed that its surroundings directly effect any modification whatever in the form and organization of an animal.[273] Great changes in surroundings involve great changes in the wants of animals, and these changes in their wants involve corresponding changes in their actions. If these new wants become permanent, or of very long duration, the animals contract new habits, which last as long as the wants which gave rise to them.[274] A great change in surroundings, if it persist for a long time, must plainly, therefore, involve the contraction of new habits. These new habits in their turn involve a preference for the employment of such and such an organ over such and such another organ, and in certain cases the total disuse of an organ which is no longer wanted. This is perfectly self-evident.[275]
"It is necessary to clarify what is meant by expressions like 'the effect of its environment on the form and organization of an animal.' It should not be assumed that its surroundings directly cause any changes in the form and organization of an animal.[Pg 294] Significant changes in the environment lead to significant changes in the needs of animals, and these shifts in their needs result in corresponding changes in their behaviors. If these new needs become permanent or last for a long time, the animals develop new habits that last as long as the needs that created them.[273] A major change in the environment, if it continues for a long time, will clearly lead to the development of new habits. These new habits, in turn, create a preference for using certain organs over others, and in some cases, complete disuse of an organ that is no longer needed. This is completely obvious.[274]"
"On the one hand, new wants have rendered a part necessary, which part has accordingly been created by a succession of efforts: use has kept it in existence, gradually strengthening and developing it till in the end it attains a considerable degree of perfection. On the other, new circumstances having in some cases rendered such or such a part useless, disuse has led to its gradually ceasing to receive the development which the other parts attain to; on this it becomes reduced, and in time disappears.[276]
"On one hand, new desires have made certain parts necessary, and these have been created through a series of efforts: their use has kept them alive, gradually strengthening and developing them until they achieve a significant level of perfection. On the other hand, new circumstances have made some parts unnecessary, and their lack of use has caused them to stop developing like the other parts; as a result, they deteriorate and eventually disappear.[276]"
"Plants have neither actions nor habits properly so called, nevertheless they change in a changed environment as much as animals do. This is due to changes in nutrition, absorption and transpiration, to degrees of[Pg 295] heat, light, and moisture, and to the preponderance over others which certain of the vital functions attain to."
"Plants don’t have actions or habits in the traditional sense, but they adapt to their environment just like animals do. This is because of changes in their nutrition, absorption, and transpiration, as well as variations in heat, light, and moisture, and the dominance of certain vital functions over others."
Lamarck is led into the statement that plants have neither actions nor habits, by his theories about the nervous system and the brain. Plain matter-of-fact people will prefer the view taken by Buffon, Dr. Darwin, and, more recently, by Mr. Francis Darwin, that there is no radical difference between plants and animals.
Lamarck arrives at the conclusion that plants have neither actions nor habits because of his theories regarding the nervous system and the brain. Practical, straightforward individuals are more likely to agree with Buffon, Dr. Darwin, and, more recently, Mr. Francis Darwin, who argue that there is no fundamental difference between plants and animals.
"The differences between well-nourished and ill-nourished plants become little by little very noticeable. If individuals, whether animal or vegetable, are continually ill-fed and exposed to hardships for several generations, their organization becomes eventually modified, and the modification is transmitted until a race is formed which is quite distinct from those descendants of the common parent stock which have been placed in favourable circumstances.[277] In a dry spring the meagre and stunted herbage seeds early. When, on the other hand, the spring is warm but with occasional days of rain, there is an excellent hay-crop. If, however, any cause perpetuates unfavourable circumstances, plants will vary correspondingly, first in appearance and general conditions, and then in several particulars of their actual character, certain organs having received more development than others, these differences will in the course of time become hereditary.[278]
The differences between well-nourished and poorly-nourished plants gradually become quite obvious. If organisms, whether animals or plants, are consistently underfed and face hardships over several generations, their structure eventually changes, and these changes are passed down until a distinct breed forms, separate from those descendants of the common ancestors that have been in favorable conditions.[277] In a dry spring, the thin and stunted grass seeds early. However, if the spring is warm but has occasional rainy days, there is a great hay crop. If, for any reason, unfavorable conditions persist, plants will correspondingly change, initially in appearance and general state, and later in various specific characteristics, with certain parts developing more than others; these differences will eventually become hereditary.[278]
"Nature changes a plant or animal's surroundings gradually—man sometimes does so suddenly. All botanists know that plants vary so greatly under[Pg 296] domestication that in time they become hardly recognizable. They undergo so much change that botanists do not at all like describing domesticated varieties. Wheat itself is an example. Where can wheat be found as a wild plant, unless it have escaped from some neighbouring cultivation? Where are our cauliflowers, our lettuces, to be found wild, with the same characters as they possess in our kitchen gardens?
"Nature slowly alters a plant or animal's environment, while humans can make changes abruptly. All botanists know that plants change so much under[Pg 296] domestication that eventually they become almost unrecognizable. They transform to such an extent that botanists really dislike describing domesticated varieties. Wheat is a prime example. Where can you find wild wheat unless it has escaped from nearby farming? Where can we find wild versions of our cauliflowers or lettuces that have the same traits as the ones we grow in our gardens?"
"The same applies to our domesticated breeds of animals. What a variety of breeds has not man produced among fowls and pigeons, of which we can find no undomesticated examples!"[279]
"The same goes for our domesticated animal breeds. Look at the countless breeds of birds and pigeons that humans have created, for which we can't find any wild counterparts!"[279]
The foregoing remarks on the effects of domestication seem to have been inspired by those given p. 123 and pp. 168, 169 of this volume.[280]
The earlier comments on the effects of domestication appear to have been influenced by those found on p. 123 and pp. 168, 169 of this volume.[280]
"Some, doubtless, have changed less than others, owing to their having undergone a less protracted domestication, and a less degree of change in climate; nevertheless, though our ducks and geese, for example, are of the same type as their wild progenitors, they have lost the power of long and sustained flight, and have become in other respects considerably modified.[281]
"Some have definitely changed less than others, because they have been domesticated for a shorter time and experienced less change in their environment. Still, even though our ducks and geese, for instance, resemble their wild ancestors, they have lost the ability for long and sustained flight and have significantly changed in other ways.[281]
"A bird, after having been kept five or six years in a cage, cannot on being liberated fly like its brethren which have been always free. Such a change in a single lifetime has not effected any transmissible modification of type; but captivity, continued during many[Pg 297] successive generations, would undoubtedly do so. If to the effects of captivity there be added also those of changed climate, changed food, and changed actions for the purpose of laying hold of food, these, united together and become constant, would in the course of time develop an entirely new breed."
"A bird that has been kept in a cage for five or six years can't fly like its wild counterparts when it's finally set free. This change within a single lifetime hasn’t caused any lasting changes in its kind; however, long-term captivity over many[Pg 297] generations would certainly lead to changes. If you also consider the effects of a different climate, different food, and new behaviors developed for getting food, all these factors combined and made consistent could eventually create an entirely new breed over time."
This, again, is almost identical with the passage from Buffon,[282] p. 148 of this volume. See also pp. 169, 170.
This is pretty much the same as the passage from Buffon,[282] p. 148 of this volume. Check out pp. 169, 170 as well.
"Where can our many domestic breeds of dogs be found in a wild state? Where are our bulldogs, greyhounds, spaniels, and lapdogs, breeds presenting differences which, in wild animals, would be certainly called specific? These are all descended from an animal nearly allied to the wolf, if not from the wolf itself. Such an animal was domesticated by early man, taken at successive intervals into widely different climates, trained to different habits, carried by man in his migrations as a precious capital into the most distant countries, and crossed from time to time with other breeds which had been developed in similar ways. Hence our present multiform breeds."[283]
"Where can we find our many domestic dog breeds in the wild? Where are our bulldogs, greyhounds, spaniels, and lapdogs, which have differences that would definitely be considered distinct species in wild animals? All of these breeds come from an animal closely related to the wolf, if not directly from the wolf itself. This animal was domesticated by early humans, moved across various climates, adapted to different lifestyles, carried by people as valuable companions to far-off lands, and occasionally mixed with other breeds that developed in similar ways. That's how we ended up with our diverse dog breeds." [283]
Here, also, it is impossible to forget Buffon's passages on the dog, given pp. 121, 122. See also p. 223.
Here, it's also impossible to forget Buffon's sections about the dog, see pp. 121, 122. Also, check p. 223.
"Observe the gradations which are found between the ranunculus aquatilis and the ranunculus hederaceus: the latter—a land plant—resembles those parts of the former which grow above the surface of the water, but not those that grow beneath it.[284]
"Look at the differences between the ranunculus aquatilis and the ranunculus hederaceus: the latter—a land plant—looks like the parts of the former that grow above the water's surface, but not the parts that grow below it.[284]
[Pg 298]"The modifications of animals arise more slowly than those of plants; they are therefore less easily watched, and less easily assignable to their true causes, but they arise none the less surely. As regards these causes, the most potent is diversity of the surroundings in which they exist, but there are also many others.[285]
[Pg 298]"Changes in animals happen more slowly than in plants; therefore, they are not as easy to observe and link to their actual causes, but they still occur reliably. The main factor behind these changes is the different environments in which they live, but there are many other factors as well.[285]
"The climate of the same place changes, and the place itself changes with changed climate and exposure, but so slowly that we imagine all lands to be stable in their conditions. This, however, is not true; climatic and other changes induce corresponding changes in environment and habit, and these modify the structure of the living forms which are subjected to them. Indeed, we see intermediate forms and species corresponding to intermediate conditions.
"The climate of a specific area changes, and the area itself changes with the shifting climate and exposure, but so gradually that we tend to believe all lands remain stable in their conditions. This, however, isn't accurate; climate and other changes lead to corresponding changes in the environment and behavior, which in turn modify the structure of the living forms that experience them. In fact, we observe intermediate forms and species that correspond to intermediate conditions."
"To the above causes must be ascribed the infinite variety of existing forms, independently of any tendency towards progressive development."[286]
"These factors account for the countless different forms we see, regardless of any inclination toward progress." [286]
The reader has now before him a fair sample of "the well-known doctrine of inherited habit as advanced by Lamarck."[287] In what way, let me ask in passing, does "the case of neuter insects" prove "demonstrative" against it, unless it is held equally demonstrative against Mr. Darwin's own position? Lamarck continues:—
The reader now has a good example of "the well-known doctrine of inherited habit as presented by Lamarck."[287] How, I ask casually, does "the case of neuter insects" serve as "demonstrative" evidence against it, unless it is also considered equally demonstrative against Mr. Darwin's own stance? Lamarck goes on:—
"The character of any habitable quarter of the globe is quâ man constant: the constancy of type in species is therefore also quâ man persistent. But this is an[Pg 299] illusion. We establish, therefore, the three following propositions:—
"The nature of any livable part of the world is as man remains constant: the consistency of type in species is thus also as man continues. However, this is an[Pg 299] illusion. We therefore establish the following three propositions:—"
"1. That every considerable and sustained change in the surroundings of any animal involves a real change in its needs.
"1. Any significant and lasting change in an animal's environment brings about a true change in its needs."
"2. That such change of needs involves the necessity of changed action in order to satisfy these needs, and, in consequence, of new habits.[288]
"2. That such a change in needs requires a change in actions to meet those needs, and as a result, new habits."
"3. It follows that such and such parts, formerly less used, are now more frequently employed, and in consequence become more highly developed; new parts also become insensibly evolved in the creature by its own efforts from within.
"3. This means that certain parts, which were previously used less often, are now used more frequently, and as a result, they become more developed; new parts also gradually evolve in the creature through its own internal efforts."
"From the foregoing these two general laws may be deduced:—
"From the above, we can conclude these two general principles:—"
"Firstly. That in every animal which has not passed its limit of development, the more frequent and sustained employment of any organ develops and aggrandizes it, giving it a power proportionate to the duration of its employment, while the same organ in default of constant use becomes insensibly weakened and deteriorated, decreasing imperceptibly in power until it finally disappears.[289]
Firstly, in every animal that hasn't reached its full development, the more often and consistently an organ is used, the more it develops and strengthens, gaining power in line with how long it's used. Conversely, if an organ isn't used regularly, it gradually weakens and deteriorates, losing power little by little until it eventually disappears.[289]
"Secondly. That these gains or losses of organic development, due to use or disuse, are transmitted to offspring, provided they have been common to both sexes, or to the animals from which the offspring have descended."[290]
"Secondly. That these gains or losses in physical development, resulting from use or disuse, are passed down to offspring, as long as they have been shared by both sexes, or by the animals from which the offspring are descended."[290]
Lamarck now sets himself to establish the fact that animals have developed modifications which have been transmitted to their offspring.[Pg 300]
Lamarck now focuses on proving that animals have developed changes that have been passed down to their offspring.[Pg 300]
"Naturalists," he says, "have believed that the possession of certain organs has led to their employment. This is not so: it is need and use which have developed the organs, and even called them into existence." [I have already sufficiently insisted that it is impossible to dispense with either of these two views. Demand and Supply have gone hand in hand, each reacting upon the other.] "Otherwise a special act of creation would be necessary for every different combination of conditions; and it would be also necessary that the conditions should remain always constant.
"Naturalists," he says, "have thought that having certain organs has led to their use. That's not true: it's the need and use that have developed the organs and even brought them into existence." [I have already stressed enough that we can't ignore either of these two perspectives. Demand and Supply have worked together, each influencing the other.] "Otherwise, we would need a special act of creation for every different combination of conditions, and the conditions would also have to stay constant."
"If this were really so we should have no racehorses like those of England, nor drayhorses so heavy in build and so unlike the racehorse; for there are no such breeds in a wild state. For the same reason, we should have no turnspit dogs with crooked legs, no greyhounds nor water-spaniels; we should have no tailless breed of fowls nor fantail pigeons, &c. Nor should we be able to cultivate wild plants in our gardens, for any length of time we please, without fear of their changing.
"If this were really true, we wouldn't have racehorses like those in England, or heavy-built draught horses that are so different from racehorses; because there are no such breeds in the wild. For the same reason, we wouldn't have turnspit dogs with crooked legs, greyhounds, or water spaniels; we wouldn't have tailless chickens or fantail pigeons, etc. We also wouldn't be able to grow wild plants in our gardens for as long as we want, without worrying about them changing."
"'Habit,' says the proverb, 'is a second nature'; what possible meaning can this proverb have, if descent with modification is unfounded?[291]
"'Habit,' says the proverb, 'is a second nature'; what possible meaning can this proverb have, if descent with modification is unfounded?[291]
"As regards the circumstances which give rise to variation, the principal are climatic changes, different temperatures of any of a creature's environments, differences of abode, of habit, of the most frequent actions; and lastly, of the means of obtaining food, self-defence, reproduction, &c., &c."[292]
"As for the circumstances that cause variation, the main ones are climate changes, different temperatures in a creature's surroundings, variations in habitat, habits, and the most common activities; and finally, the methods of getting food, self-defense, reproduction, etc., etc." [292]
"In consequence of change in any of these respects, the faculties of an animal become extended and enlarged by use: they become diversified through the long continuance of the new habits, until little by little their whole structure and nature, as well as the organs originally affected, participate in the effects of all these influences, and are modified to an extent which is capable of transmission to offspring."[294]
"As a result of changes in any of these areas, an animal's abilities increase and develop through use. They become varied over time due to the lasting effects of these new habits, until gradually their entire structure and nature, along with the originally impacted organs, reflect all these influences and are altered to a degree that can be passed down to their offspring." [294]
This sentence alone would be sufficient to show that Lamarck was as much alive as Buffon and Dr. Darwin were before him, to the fact that one of the most important conditions of an animal's life, is the relation in which it stands to the other inhabitants of the same neighbourhood—from which the survival of the fittest follows as a self-evident proposition. Nothing, therefore, can be more unfounded than the attempt, so frequently made by writers who have not read Lamarck, or who think others may be trusted not to do so, to represent him as maintaining something perfectly different from what is maintained by modern writers on evolution. The difference, in so far as there is any difference, is one of detail only. Lamarck would not have hesitated to admit, that, if animals are modified in a direction which is favourable to them, they will have a better chance of surviving and transmitting their favourable[Pg 302] modifications. In like manner, our modern evolutionists should allow that animals are modified not because they subsequently survive, but because they have done this or that which has led to their modification, and hence to their surviving.
This sentence alone is enough to show that Lamarck was just as aware as Buffon and Dr. Darwin before him that one of the most important conditions for an animal's life is its relationship with other inhabitants in the same area—leading to the obvious conclusion of survival of the fittest. Therefore, nothing is more unfounded than the common attempt by writers who haven’t read Lamarck or believe others won’t, to claim he argued something completely different from what modern evolutionists propose. The difference, if there is any, is only in the details. Lamarck would have readily accepted that if animals are changed in a way that benefits them, they will have a better chance of surviving and passing on their beneficial[Pg 302] traits. Similarly, modern evolutionists should recognize that animals are modified not because they merely survive, but because of specific actions that led to their modification, which in turn contributes to their survival.
Having established that animals and plants are capable of being materially changed in the course of a few generations, Lamarck proceeds to show that their modification is due to changed distribution of the use and disuse of their organs at any given time.
Having established that animals and plants can undergo significant changes in just a few generations, Lamarck goes on to explain that these changes are caused by the varying use and disuse of their organs over time.
"The disuse of an organ," he writes, "if it becomes constant in consequence of new habits, gradually reduces the organ, and leads finally to its disappearance."[295]
"The disuse of an organ," he writes, "if it becomes constant because of new habits, gradually weakens the organ, and ultimately leads to its disappearance."[295]
"Thus whales have lost their teeth, though teeth are still found in the embryo. So, again, M. Geoffroy has discovered in birds the groove where teeth were formerly placed. The ant-eater, which belongs to a genus that has long relinquished the habit of masticating its food, is as toothless as the whale."[296]
"Whales have lost their teeth, even though teeth are still present in the embryo. Similarly, M. Geoffroy has found a groove in birds where teeth used to be. The anteater, which is part of a genus that has long stopped chewing its food, is just as toothless as the whale."[296]
Then are adduced further examples of rudimentary organs, which will be given in another place, and need not be repeated here. Speaking of the fact, however, that serpents have no legs, though they are higher in the scale of life than the batrachians, Lamarck attributes this "to the continued habit of trying to squeeze through very narrow places, where four feet would be in the way, and would be very little good to them, inasmuch as more than four would be wanted in order to turn bodies that were already so much elongated."[297]
Then additional examples of basic organs are mentioned, which will be covered elsewhere and don’t need to be repeated here. Regarding the fact that snakes have no legs, even though they are higher on the evolutionary scale than amphibians, Lamarck suggests this is "due to the continuous habit of trying to squeeze through very narrow spaces, where four feet would just be in the way and wouldn't be very useful, since more than four would be needed to maneuver bodies that are already so elongated."[297]
If it be asked why, on Lamarck's theory, if serpents[Pg 303] wanted more legs they could not have made them, the answer is that the attempt to do this would be to unsettle a question which had been already so long settled, that it would be impossible to reopen it. The animal must adapt itself to four legs, or must get rid of all or some of them if it does not like them; but it has stood so long committed to the theory that if there are to be legs at all, there are to be not more than four, that it is impossible for it now to see this matter in any other light.
If you ask why, according to Lamarck's theory, serpents[Pg 303] can’t simply grow more legs if they wanted to, the answer is that trying to do so would shake up a question that has been settled for so long, it’s impossible to revisit it. The animal has to adapt to having four legs, or get rid of all or some of them if it doesn't want them; but it's been so long committed to the idea that if it’s going to have legs at all, there can be no more than four, that it can't see the situation any differently now.
The experiments of M. Brown Séquard on guinea pigs, quoted by Mr. Darwin,[298] suggest that the form of the serpent may be due to its having lost its legs by successive accidents in squeezing through narrow places, and that the wounds having been followed by disease, the creature may have bitten the limbs off, in which case the loss might have been very readily transmitted to offspring; the animal would accordingly take to a sinuous mode of progression that would doubtless in time elongate the body still further. M. Brown Séquard "carefully recorded" thirteen cases, and saw even a greater number, in which the loss of toes by guinea pigs which had gnawed their own toes off, was immediately transmitted to offspring. Accidents followed by disease seem to have been somewhat overlooked as a possible means of modification. The missing forefinger to the hand of the potto[299] would appear at first sight to have been lost by some such mishap. Returning to Lamarck, we find him saying:[Pg 304]—
The experiments by M. Brown Séquard on guinea pigs, mentioned by Mr. Darwin,[298] indicate that the shape of the serpent may have come from it losing its legs due to repeated accidents while squeezing through tight spaces. The resulting injuries could have led to disease, causing the creature to bite off its limbs, which could then easily be passed down to its offspring. Consequently, the animal would adopt a squiggly way of moving that would likely further lengthen its body over time. M. Brown Séquard “carefully recorded” thirteen cases and observed even more instances where guinea pigs that chewed off their own toes immediately transmitted this loss to their offspring. The role of accidents followed by disease seems to have been somewhat overlooked as a potential means of change. The missing forefinger on the hand of the potto[299] might initially seem to have been lost due to a similar incident. Going back to Lamarck, we find him stating:[Pg 304]—
"Even in the lifetime of a single individual we can see organic changes in consequence of changed habits. Thus M. Tenon has constantly found the intestinal canal of drunkards to be greatly shorter than that of people who do not drink. This is due to the fact that habitual drunkards eat but little solid food, so that the stomach and intestines are more rarely distended. The same applies to people who lead studious and sedentary lives. The stomachs of such persons and of drunkards have little power, and a small quantity will fill them, while those of men who take plenty of exercise remain in full vigour and are even increased."[300]
"Even within a single person's lifetime, we can see physical changes resulting from altered habits. M. Tenon consistently found that the intestines of alcoholics are significantly shorter than those of non-drinkers. This happens because regular drinkers consume very little solid food, leading to less frequent stretching of the stomach and intestines. The same is true for individuals who lead academic and sedentary lifestyles. The stomachs of these people and alcoholics have less strength, and only a small amount of food will satisfy them, while those of physically active individuals remain strong and even increase in capacity."[300]
It becomes now necessary to establish the converse proposition, namely that:—
It is now necessary to establish the opposite proposition, which is:—
"The frequent use of an organ increases its power; it even develops the organ itself, and makes it acquire dimensions and powers which it is not found to have in animals which make no use of such an organ.
Using an organ often strengthens it; it even develops the organ itself, allowing it to grow in size and ability that you don't see in animals that don't use that organ.
"In support of this we see that the bird whose needs lead it to the water, in which to find its prey, extends the toes of its feet when it wants to strike the water, and move itself upon the surface. The skin at the base of the toes of such a bird contracts the habit of extending itself from continual practice. To this cause, in the course of time, must be attributed the wide membrane which unites the toes of ducks, geese, &c. The same efforts to swim, that is to say, to push the water for the purpose of moving itself forward, has extended the membrane between the toes of frogs, turtles, the otter, and the beaver."[301]
"In support of this, we see that the bird that needs to reach the water to find its prey spreads its toes when it wants to hit the water and move along the surface. The skin at the base of the toes of such a bird tightens due to the repeated action of spreading them. This, over time, leads to the development of the webbed feet that connect the toes of ducks, geese, and similar birds. The same swimming actions, meaning pushing the water to move forward, have resulted in the webbing between the toes of frogs, turtles, otters, and beavers." [301]
[Pg 305][This is taken, I believe, from Dr. Darwin or Buffon, but I have lost the passage, if, indeed, I ever found it. It had been met by Paley some years earlier (1802) in the following:—
[Pg 305][I think this is from Dr. Darwin or Buffon, but I've lost the quote, if I ever had it. Paley encountered it a few years earlier (1802) as follows:—
"There is nothing in the action of swimming as carried on by a bird upon the surface of the water that should generate a membrane between the toes. As to that membrane it is an action of constant resistance.... The web feet of amphibious quadrupeds, seals, otters, &c., fall under the same observation."[302]]
"There’s nothing in the way a bird swims on the water’s surface that would create a membrane between its toes. That membrane is a result of constant resistance... The webbed feet of amphibious mammals, like seals and otters, follow the same principle."[302]]
"On the other hand those birds whose habits lead them to perch on trees, and which have sprung from parents that have long contracted this habit, have their toes shaped in a perfectly different manner. Their claws become lengthened, sharpened, and curved, so as to enable the creature to lay hold of the boughs on which it so often rests. The shore bird again, which does not like to swim, is nevertheless continually obliged to enter the water when searching after its prey. Not liking to plunge its body in the water, it makes every endeavour to extend and lengthen its lower limbs. In the course of long time these birds have come to be elevated, as it were, on stilts, and have got long legs bare of feathers as far as their thighs, and often still higher. The same bird is continually trying to extend its neck in order to fish without wetting its body, and in the course of time its neck has become modified accordingly.[303]
"On the other hand, birds that have developed the habit of perching on trees, which has been passed down from their ancestors, have toes shaped in a completely different way. Their claws become longer, sharper, and curved, allowing them to grip the branches where they often rest. The shorebird, which doesn’t like to swim, is still constantly forced to wade into the water while searching for food. Since it prefers not to immerse its body, it works hard to extend and lengthen its legs. Over a long period, these birds have effectively become elevated on stilts, acquiring long legs that are bare of feathers up to their thighs, and often even higher. This bird is also continuously trying to stretch its neck to catch fish without getting its body wet, and over time, its neck has adapted to this need.[303]"
"Swans, indeed, and geese have short legs and very[Pg 306] long necks, but this is because they plunge their heads as low in the water as they can in their search for aquatic larvæ and other animalcules, but make no effort to lengthen their legs."[304]
"Swans and geese have short legs and long necks, but that's because they dip their heads as low as possible in the water while searching for aquatic larvae and other tiny organisms, and they don't try to make their legs longer."
This too is taken from some passage which I have either never seen or have lost sight of. Paley never gives a reference to an opponent, though he frequently does so when quoting an author on his own side, but I can hardly doubt that he had in his mind the passage from which Lamarck in 1809 derived the foregoing, when in 1802 he wrote § 5 of chapter xv. and the latter half of chapter xxiii. of his 'Natural Theology.'
This is also taken from some passage that I either haven't seen or have forgotten about. Paley never references an opponent, even though he often cites authors on his own side, but I can hardly doubt that he was thinking of the passage from which Lamarck took the previous content when he wrote § 5 of chapter xv. and the second half of chapter xxiii. of his 'Natural Theology' in 1802.
"The tongues of the ant-eater and the woodpecker," continues Lamarck, "have become elongated from similar causes. Humming birds catch hold of things with their tongues; serpents and lizards use their tongues to touch and reconnoitre objects in front of them, hence their tongues have come to be forked.
"The tongues of the anteater and the woodpecker," continues Lamarck, "have become longer for similar reasons. Hummingbirds grab onto things with their tongues; snakes and lizards use their tongues to feel and explore objects in front of them, which is why their tongues have become forked."
"Need—always occasioned by the circumstances in which an animal is placed, and followed by sustained efforts at gratification—can not only modify an organ, that is to say, augment or reduce it, but can change its position when the case requires its removal.[305]
"Need—always driven by the situation in which an animal finds itself, and followed by ongoing attempts to satisfy that need—can not only alter an organ, meaning it can increase or decrease its size, but can also shift its position when a change is necessary.[305]
"Ocean fishes have occasion to see what is on either side of them, and have their eyes accordingly placed on either side their head. Some fishes, however, have their abode near coasts on submarine banks and inclinations, and are thus forced to flatten themselves as much as possible in order to get as near as they can to the shore. In this situation they receive more light[Pg 307] from above than from below, and find it necessary to pay attention to whatever happens to be above them; this need has involved the displacement of their eyes, which now take the remarkable position which we observe in the case of soles, turbots, plaice, &c. The transfer of position is not even yet complete in the case of these fishes, and the eyes are not, therefore, symmetrically placed; but they are so with the skate, whose head and whole body are equally disposed on either side a longitudinal section. Hence the eyes of this fish are placed symmetrically upon the uppermost side.[306]
"Ocean fish can see what's on both sides of them because their eyes are positioned on either side of their head. However, some fish live close to the shore on underwater banks and slopes, which forces them to flatten themselves as much as possible to get nearer to the land. In this position, they receive more light from above than from below and need to be aware of whatever is above them; this necessity has led to the shifting of their eyes, which now have the unusual placement seen in soles, turbots, plaice, and others. The shift isn’t fully complete in these fish, so their eyes aren't symmetrically placed. In contrast, the skate has a head and body that are evenly shaped on either side of a longitudinal line, so its eyes are symmetrically located on the upper side."
"The eyes of serpents are placed on the sides and upper portions of the head, so that they can easily see what is on one side of them or above them; but they can only see very little in front of them, and supplement this deficiency of power with their tongue, which is very long and supple, and is in many kinds so divided that it can touch more than one object at a time; the habit of reconnoitring objects in front of them with their tongues has even led to their being able to pass it through the end of their nostrils without being obliged to open their jaws.[307]
The eyes of snakes are located on the sides and top of their heads, allowing them to easily see what’s beside them or above them; however, they can only see a small amount directly in front of them. They make up for this limitation with their long, flexible tongues, which in many species are split so they can touch multiple objects at once. Their tendency to explore objects in front of them with their tongues has even enabled them to stick their tongues through the ends of their nostrils without having to open their mouths.[307]
"Herbivorous mammals, such as the elephant, rhinoceros, ox, buffalo, horse, &c., owe their great size to their habit of daily distending themselves with food and taking comparatively little exercise. They employ their feet for standing, walking, or running, but not for climbing trees. Hence the thick horn which covers their toes. These toes have become useless to them, and are now in many cases rudimentary only. Some [Pg 308]pachyderms have five toes covered with horn; some four, some three. The ruminants, which appear to be the earliest mammals that confined themselves to a life upon the ground, have but two hooves, while the horse has only one.[308]
Herbivorous mammals, like elephants, rhinos, oxen, buffalo, and horses, have their massive size due to their habit of stuffing themselves with food every day and exercising very little. They use their feet to stand, walk, or run, but not to climb trees, which is why they have thick horns on their toes. These toes have become mostly useless and are now just remnants in many cases. Some [Pg 308]pachyderms have five toes covered with horn; some have four, and some have three. Ruminants, which seem to be the first mammals that stuck to life on land, have just two hooves, while horses have only one.[308]
"Some herbivorous animals, especially among the ruminants, have been incessantly preyed upon by carnivorous animals, against which their only refuge is in flight. Necessity has therefore developed the light and active limbs of antelopes, gazelles, &c. Ruminants, only using their jaws to graze with, have but little power in them, and therefore generally fight with their heads. The males fight frequently with one another, and their desires prompt an access of fluids to the parts of their heads with which they fight; thus the horns and bosses have arisen with which the heads of most of these animals are armed.[309] The giraffe owes its long neck to its continued habit of browsing upon trees, whence also the great length of its fore legs as compared with its hinder ones. Carnivorous animals, in like manner, have had their organs modified in correlation with their desires and habits. Some climb, some scratch in order to burrow in the earth, some tear their prey; they therefore have need of toes, and we find their toes separated and armed with claws. Some of them are great hunters, and also plunge their claws deeply into the bodies of their victims, trying to tear out the part on which they have seized; this habit has developed a size and curvature of claw which would impede them greatly in travelling over stony ground;[Pg 309] they have therefore been obliged to make efforts to draw back their too projecting claws, and so, little by little, has arisen the peculiar sheath into which cats, tigers, lions, &c., withdraw their claws when they no longer wish to use them.[310]
Some herbivorous animals, especially ruminants, have constantly been hunted by carnivorous animals, and their only escape is to run away. As a result, the light and agile limbs of antelopes, gazelles, etc., have evolved. Ruminants mainly use their jaws for grazing, which gives them little power, so they generally fight with their heads. Males often engage in fights with one another, and their desires lead to an increase in blood flow to the head areas they use in combat; this is how the horns and other head structures have developed in most of these animals.[309] The giraffe's long neck comes from its habit of reaching for leaves high up in trees, which also explains why its front legs are much longer than its back legs. Similarly, carnivorous animals have adapted their bodies in line with their instincts and behaviors. Some climb, some dig with their claws, and some tear into their prey; thus, they need strong toes, which have evolved to be separated and equipped with claws. Some are powerful hunters that dig their claws deep into their victims, trying to rip out the flesh where they latch on; this behavior has led to the development of large, curved claws that would hinder their movement on rocky terrain.[Pg 309] To address this, they have gradually adapted to retract their overly prominent claws, resulting in the unique sheaths into which cats, tigers, lions, etc., retract their claws when they’re not using them.[310]
"We see then that the long-sustained and habitual exercise of any part of a living organism, in consequence of the necessities engendered by its environment, develops such part, and gives it a form which it would never have attained if the exercise had not become an habitual action. All known animals furnish us with examples of this.[311] If anyone maintains that the especially powerful development of any organ has had nothing to do with its habitual use—that use has added nothing, and disuse detracted nothing from its efficiency, but that the organ has always been as we now see it from the creation of the particular species onwards—I would ask why cannot our domesticated ducks fly like wild ducks? I would also quote a multitude of examples of the effects of use and disuse upon our own organs, effects which, if the use and disuse were constant for many generations, would become much more marked.
We can see that the long-term and regular use of any part of a living organism, driven by the needs created by its environment, develops that part and shapes it in ways it would never have reached without this habitual activity. All known animals provide us with examples of this.[311] If anyone argues that the significant growth of any organ has nothing to do with its regular use—that use hasn’t contributed anything, and disuse hasn’t taken anything away from its function, suggesting that the organ has always looked the way it does since the creation of that species—I would ask why our domesticated ducks can’t fly like wild ducks? I could also provide numerous examples of how use and disuse affect our own organs, effects that would become much more pronounced if the patterns of use and disuse continued over many generations.
"A great number of facts show, as will be more fully insisted on, that when its will prompts an animal to this or that action, the organs which are to execute it receive an excess of nervous fluid, and this is the determinant cause of the movements necessary for the required action. Modifications acquired in this way eventually become permanent in the breed that has[Pg 310] acquired them, and are transmitted to offspring, without the offspring's having itself gone through the processes of acquisition which were necessary in the case of the ancestor.[312] Frequent crosses, however, with unmodified individuals, destroy the effect produced. It is only owing to the isolation of the races of man through geographical and other causes, that man himself presents so many varieties, each with a distinctive character.
A lot of evidence shows, as we will explain in more detail, that when an animal's will drives it to perform a certain action, the organs responsible for carrying it out get a surge of nervous energy, which is the main reason behind the movements needed for that action. Changes gained this way eventually become permanent in the breed that has[Pg 310] adapted these traits and are passed on to their offspring, without the offspring having to go through the same learning processes that the ancestor did.[312] However, frequent breeding with unmodified individuals wipes out the effects produced. It’s only because of the isolation of human races due to geographical and other factors that humanity shows so many varieties, each with its own unique characteristics.
"A review of all existing classes, orders, genera, and species would show that their structure, organs, and faculties, are in all cases solely attributable to the surroundings to which each creature has been subjected by nature, and to the habits which individuals have been compelled to contract; and that they are not at all the result of a form originally bestowed, which has imposed certain habits upon the creature.[313]
A review of all existing classes, orders, genera, and species would show that their structure, organs, and abilities are all a result of the environments they’ve been exposed to by nature, and the habits they’ve had to adopt. They are not the outcome of an originally given form that has dictated certain behaviors for the creature.[313]
"It is unnecessary to multiply instances; the fact is simply this, that all animals have certain habits, and that their organization is always in perfect harmony with these habits.[314] The conclusion hitherto accepted is that the Author of Nature, when he created animals, foresaw all the possible circumstances in which they would be placed, and gave an unchanging organism to each creature, in accordance with its future destiny. The conclusion, on the other hand, here maintained is that nature has evolved all existing forms of life successively, beginning with the simplest organisms and gradually proceeding to those which are more complete. Forms of life have spread themselves throughout all the habitable parts of the earth, and[Pg 311] each species has received its habits and corresponding modification of organs, from the influence of the surroundings in which it found itself placed.[315]
"It isn’t necessary to provide more examples; the reality is that all animals have specific habits, and their biological structure is always perfectly aligned with these habits.[314] The prevailing conclusion has been that the Creator, when making animals, anticipated all the possible situations they might encounter and designed each creature with a fixed structure suited to its future role. However, the argument presented here is that nature has developed all existing life forms over time, starting with the simplest organisms and gradually evolving into more complex ones. Life forms have distributed themselves across all the habitable regions of the earth, and[Pg 311] each species has adapted its habits and corresponding physical traits due to the influences of its environment.[315]"
"The first conclusion supposes an unvarying organism and unvarying conditions. The second, which is my theory (la mienne propre), supposes that each animal is capable of modifications which in the course of generations amount to a wide divergence of type.
"The first conclusion assumes a constant organism and constant conditions. The second, which is my theory (la mienne propre), assumes that each animal can undergo changes that, over generations, lead to significant differences in type."
"If a single animal can be shown to have varied considerably under domestication, the first conclusion is proved to be inadmissible, and the second to be in conformity with the laws of nature."
"If one animal can be demonstrated to have changed significantly through domestication, the first conclusion is shown to be unacceptable, and the second conforms to the laws of nature."
"Animal forms then are the result of conditions of life and of the habits engendered thereby. With new forms new faculties are developed, and thus nature has little by little evolved the existing differentiations of animal and vegetable life."[316]
"Animal forms are the outcome of living conditions and the habits that arise from them. As new forms emerge, new abilities are developed, and in this way, nature has gradually evolved the current distinctions between animal and plant life."[316]
Lamarck makes no exception in man's favour to the rule of descent with modification. He supposes that a race of quadrumanous apes gradually acquired the upright position in walking, with a corresponding modification of the feet and facial angle. Such a race having become master of all the other animals, spread itself over all parts of the world that suited it. It hunted out the other higher races which were in a condition to dispute with it for enjoyment of the[Pg 312] world's productions, and drove them to take refuge in such places as it did not desire to occupy. It checked the increase of the races nearest itself, and kept them exiled in woods and desert places, so that their further development was arrested, while itself, able to spread in all directions, to multiply without opposition, and to lead a social life, it developed new requirements one after another, which urged it to industrial pursuits, and gradually perfected its capabilities. Eventually this pre-eminent race, having acquired absolute supremacy, came to be widely different from even the most perfect of the lower animals.
Lamarck doesn't make any exceptions for humans in the rule of descent with modification. He suggests that a group of four-handed apes gradually developed the ability to walk upright, which led to changes in their feet and facial structure. This group, having mastered all other animals, spread to all parts of the world that suited them. They hunted down other higher species that could compete with them for the world's resources and forced them into areas they didn't want to inhabit. They limited the population of the nearest races, pushing them to live in forests and deserts, which halted their further development. Meanwhile, this dominant race, able to expand in all directions, multiply freely, and live socially, developed new needs that drove them toward industrial activities, gradually enhancing their skills. Eventually, this superior race, having achieved total dominance, became quite different from even the most advanced of the lower animals.
"Certain apes approach man more nearly than any other animal approaches him; nevertheless, they are far inferior to him, both in bodily and mental capacity. Some of them frequently stand upright, but as they do not habitually maintain this attitude, their organization has not been sufficiently modified to prevent it from being irksome to them to stand for long together. They fall on all fours immediately at the approach of danger. This reveals their true origin.[317]
Certain apes are closer to humans than any other animal, but they are still much less advanced, both physically and mentally. Some of them often stand on two legs, but since they don’t do this regularly, their bodies haven’t adapted enough to make it comfortable for them to stand for long periods. They drop back to all fours as soon as they sense danger. This shows where they really come from.[317]
"But is the upright position altogether natural, even to man? He uses it in moving from place to place, but still standing is a fatiguing position, and one which can only be maintained for a limited time, and by the aid of muscular contraction. The vertebrate column does not pass through the axis of the head so as to maintain it in like equilibrium with other limbs. The head, chest, stomach, and intestines weigh almost entirely on the anterior part of the vertebrate column, and this[Pg 313] column itself is placed obliquely, so that, as M. Richerand has observed, continual watchfulness and muscular exertion are necessary to avoid the falls towards which the weight and disposition of our parts are continually inclining us. 'Children,' he remarks, 'have a constant tendency to assume the position of quadrupeds.'"[318]
"But is standing up completely natural for humans? We use it to move around, but standing can be tiring and can only be sustained for a limited time with muscle effort. The spine doesn’t align with the head in a way that keeps it balanced with the other limbs. The head, chest, stomach, and intestines mostly rest on the front part of the spine, which is positioned at an angle. As M. Richerand noted, we need constant vigilance and muscle strength to prevent ourselves from tipping over due to how our weight is distributed. 'Children,' he points out, 'tend to naturally take on a four-legged stance.'"[Pg 313]
"Surely these facts should reveal man's origin as analogous to that of the other mammals, if his organization only be looked to. But the following consideration must be added. New wants, developed in societies which had become numerous, must have correspondingly multiplied the ideas of this dominant race, whose individuals must have therefore gradually felt the need of fuller communication with each other. Hence the necessity for increasing and varying the number of the signs suitable for mutual understanding. It is plain therefore that incessant efforts would be made in this direction.[319]
"These facts should clearly show that humans originated similarly to other mammals, considering their biological structure. However, we must also take into account another factor. As societies grew larger, new needs arose, which would have correspondingly expanded the ideas of this dominant group. As a result, individuals would gradually realize the necessity for better communication with one another. This created a need to increase and diversify the signs used for mutual understanding. Therefore, it’s evident that continuous efforts would be made in this area.[319]"
"The lower animals, though often social, have been kept in too great subjection for any such development of power. They continue, therefore, stationary as regards their wants and ideas, very few of which need be communicated from one individual to another. A few movements of the body, a few simple cries and whistles, or inflexions of voice, would suffice for their purpose. With the dominant race, on the other hand, the continued multiplication of ideas which it was desirable to communicate rapidly, would exhaust the power of pantomimic gesture and of all possible[Pg 314] inflexions of the voice—therefore by a succession of efforts this race arrived at the utterance of articulate sounds. A few only would be at first made use of, and these would be supplemented by inflexions of the voice: presently they would increase in number, variety, and appropriateness, with the increase of needs and of the efforts made to speak. Habitual exercise would increase the power of the lips and tongue to articulate distinctly.
The lower animals, while often social, have been kept in too much subjection for any significant development of their capabilities. As a result, they remain static in their needs and ideas, with very few of these needing to be shared between individuals. A few body movements, some simple cries and whistles, or changes in tone would be enough for their communication. In contrast, the dominant species has seen a continual growth of ideas that needed to be communicated quickly, which would exceed the limits of gestures and all possible[Pg 314] changes in tone—so through various efforts, this species developed the ability to produce articulate sounds. Initially, only a few would be used, and these would be enhanced by changes in tone; over time, their number, variety, and relevance would grow alongside an increase in needs and the efforts to communicate. Regular practice would enhance the ability of the lips and tongue to articulate clearly.
"The diversity of language is due to geographical distribution, with consequent greater or less isolation of certain races, and corruption of the signs originally agreed upon for each idea. Man's own wants, therefore, will have achieved the whole result. They will have given rise to endeavour, and habitual use will have developed the organs of articulation."[320]
"The variety of languages comes from where people live, leading to different levels of isolation among certain groups and changes to the symbols originally used for each idea. Ultimately, it's people's needs that create this diversity. Those needs drive efforts to communicate, and regular use shapes the way we speak."[320]
How, let me ask again, is "the case of neuter insects" "demonstrative" against the "well-known" theory put forward in the foregoing chapter?
How, let me ask again, is "the case of neuter insects" "demonstrative" against the "well-known" theory presented in the previous chapter?
FOOTNOTES:
[210] Page 28.
[211] Pages 28-31.
[213] Page 42.
[214] Page 46.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Page 46.
[216] Pages 50, 51.
[220] Page 63.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Page 63.
[221] Page 64.
[222] Page 65.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Page 65.
[223] Page 67.
[224] Chap. iii.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Chap. 3.
[226] Pages 71-73.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Pages 71-73.
[233] Page 80.
[234] Ed. 1876.
[236] 'Origin of Species,' p. 241.
'Origin of Species,' p. 241.
[237] 'Phil. Zool.,' p. 82.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 'Phil. Zool.', p. 82.
[239] Pages 349-351.
[240] Page 84.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ P. 84.
[242] Page 90.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Page 90.
[243] 'Origin of Species,' p. 3.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 'Origin of Species,' p. 3.
[245] Pages 95-96.
[246] Page 97.
[252] Page 113.
[254] This passage is rather obscure. I give it therefore in the original:—
[254] This passage is pretty unclear. So, I'm sharing it in its original form:—
"Ainsi les naturalistes ayant remarqué que beaucoup d'espèces, certains genres, et même quelques familles paraissent dans une sorte d'isolement, quant à leurs caractères, plusieurs se sont imaginés que les êtres vivants, dans l'un ou l'autre règne, s'avoisinaient, ou s'éloignaient entre eux, relativement à leurs rapports naturels, dans une disposition semblable aux differents points d'une carte de géographie ou d'une mappemonde. Ils regardent les petites séries bien prononcées qu'on a nommées familles naturelles, comme devant être disposées entre elles de manière à former une réticulation. Cette idée qui a paru sublime à quelques modernes, est évidemment une erreur, et, sans doute, elle se dissipera dès qu'on aura des connaissances plus profondes et plus générales de l'organisation, et surtout lorsqu'on distinguera ce qui appartient à l'influence des lieux d'habitation et des habitudes contractées, de ce qui résulte des progrès plus ou moins avancés dans la composition ou le perfectionnement de l'organisation."—(p. 120).
"Many naturalists have noticed that a lot of species, certain genera, and even some families seem to exist in a sort of isolation regarding their characteristics. Some have imagined that living beings, within either kingdom, are either close to or distant from each other based on their natural relationships, in a way similar to the different points on a geographic map or globe. They see the clearly defined small series called natural families as needing to be arranged in a way that forms a network. This idea, which has seemed grand to some modern thinkers, is clearly a mistake, and it will likely fade away as we gain deeper and broader knowledge of organization, especially when we distinguish what comes from the influence of habitats and developed habits from what results from more or less advanced progress in the composition or improvement of organization."—(p. 120).
[261] 'Origin of Species,' chap. xiv.
[264] Page 142.
[265] Page 143.
[267] Page 144.
[268] Ibid.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source.
[270] Page 146.
[272] Page 222.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Page 222.
[274] Page 224.
[275] Page 223.
[276] Page 225.
[278] Page 226.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Page 226.
[289] Page 235.
[290] Page 236.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ p. 236.
[292] Page 238.
[293] See ante, pp. 220-228.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See above, pp. 220-228.
[296] Page 241.
[297] Page 245.
[301] Page 248.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Page 248.
[305] Page 250.
[307] Page 252.
[309] Page 254.
[311] Page 257.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Page 257.
[313] Page 260.
[314] Page 263.
[316] Page 265.
[319] Page 346.
MR. PATRICK MATTHEW, MM. ÉTIENNE AND ISIDORE GEOFFROY ST. HILAIRE, AND MR. HERBERT SPENCER.
MR. PATRICK MATTHEW, MM. ÉTIENNE AND ISIDORE GEOFFROY ST. HILAIRE, AND MR. HERBERT SPENCER.
The same complaint must be made against Mr. Matthew's excellent survey of the theory of evolution, as against Dr. Erasmus Darwin's original exposition of the same theory, namely, that it is too short. It may be very true that brevity is the soul of wit, but the leaders of science will generally succeed in burking new-born wit, unless the brevity of its soul is found compatible with a body of some bulk.
The same criticism applies to Mr. Matthew's great overview of the theory of evolution as it does to Dr. Erasmus Darwin's original explanation of the same theory: it's too brief. While it’s true that brevity is the soul of wit, the leaders in science generally manage to suppress new ideas unless the concise nature of those ideas is supported by a substantial foundation.
Mr. Darwin writes thus concerning Mr. Matthew in the historical sketch to which I have already more than once referred.
Mr. Darwin writes this about Mr. Matthew in the historical sketch I have mentioned several times before.
"In 1831 Mr. Patrick Matthew published his work on 'Naval Timber and Arboriculture,' in which he gives precisely the same view on the origin of species as that (presently to be alluded to) propounded by Mr. Wallace and myself in the 'Linnean Journal,' and as that enlarged in the present volume. Unfortunately the view was given by Mr. Matthew very briefly, in scattered passages in an appendix to a work on a different subject, so that it remained unnoticed until Mr. Matthew himself drew attention to it in the 'Gardener's Chronicle' for April 7, 1860. The differences of Mr. Matthew's[Pg 316] view from mine are not of much importance; he seems to consider that the world was nearly depopulated at successive periods, and then re-stocked, and he gives as an alternative, that new forms may be generated 'without the presence of any mould or germ of former aggregates.' I am not sure that I understand some passages; but it seems that he attributes much influence to the direct action of the conditions of life. He clearly saw, however, the full force of the principle of natural selection."[321]
In 1831, Mr. Patrick Matthew published his work titled 'Naval Timber and Arboriculture,' where he presented the same idea about the origin of species that Mr. Wallace and I later discussed in the 'Linnean Journal,' and that is further expanded in this volume. Unfortunately, Mr. Matthew’s view was only briefly mentioned in scattered sections of an appendix to a work on a different topic, so it went largely unnoticed until Mr. Matthew himself highlighted it in the 'Gardener's Chronicle' on April 7, 1860. The differences between Mr. Matthew’s views and mine aren’t very significant; he seems to believe that the world experienced near-total depopulation during certain periods and was then restocked, and he also suggests that new forms could arise “without any mold or germ of former aggregates.” I’m not sure I grasp all parts of his argument, but it seems that he placed a lot of importance on the direct impact of the conditions of life. However, he clearly recognized the full significance of the principle of natural selection.[Pg 316][321]
Nothing could well be more misleading. If Mr. Matthew's view of the origin of species is "precisely the same as that" propounded by Mr. Darwin, it is hard to see how Mr. Darwin can call those of Lamarck and Dr. Erasmus Darwin "erroneous"; for Mr. Matthew's is nothing but an excellent and well-digested summary of the conclusions arrived at by these two writers and by Buffon. If, again, Mr. Darwin is correct in saying that Mr. Matthew "clearly saw the full force of the principle of natural selection," he condemns the view he has himself taken of it in his 'Origin of Species,' for Mr. Darwin has assigned a far more important and very different effect to the fact that the fittest commonly survive in the struggle for existence, than Mr. Matthew has done. Mr. Matthew sees a cause underlying all variations; he takes the most teleological or purposive view of organism that has been taken by any writer (not a theologian) except myself, while Mr. Darwin's view, if not the least teleological, is certainly nearly so, and his confession of inability to detect any[Pg 317] general cause underlying variations, leaves, as will appear presently, less than common room for ambiguity. Here are Mr. Matthew's own words:—
Nothing could be more misleading. If Mr. Matthew's perspective on the origin of species is "exactly the same as that" proposed by Mr. Darwin, it’s hard to understand how Mr. Darwin can label the views of Lamarck and Dr. Erasmus Darwin as "incorrect"; because Mr. Matthew's take is simply an excellent and well-organized summary of the conclusions reached by these two authors and by Buffon. Additionally, if Mr. Darwin is right in saying that Mr. Matthew "clearly recognized the full impact of the principle of natural selection," he undermines his own position on it in his 'Origin of Species,' since Mr. Darwin has attributed a much greater and different significance to the survival of the fittest in the struggle for existence than Mr. Matthew has. Mr. Matthew identifies a cause behind all variations; he adopts the most purposeful view of organisms that has been presented by any writer (not a theologian) except for myself, while Mr. Darwin's perspective, if not entirely averse to teleology, is certainly close to it, and his admission of being unable to identify any[Pg 317] general cause driving variations leaves, as will soon be evident, little room for confusion. Here are Mr. Matthew's own words:—
"There is a law universal in nature, tending to render every reproductive being the best possibly suited to the condition that its kind, or that organized matter is susceptible of, and which appears intended to model the physical and mental or instinctive, powers to their highest perfection, and to continue them so. This law sustains the lion in his strength, the hare in her swiftness, and the fox in his wiles. As nature in all her modifications of life has a power of increase far beyond what is needed to supply the place of what falls by Time's decay, those individuals who possess not the requisite strength, swiftness, hardihood, or cunning, fall prematurely without reproducing—either a prey to their natural devourers, or sinking under disease, generally induced by want of nourishment, their place being occupied by the more perfect of their own kind, who are pressing on the means of existence.
There’s a universal law in nature that causes every reproductive being to adapt as well as possible to the conditions their kind, or organized matter, can handle. This law seems aimed at developing their physical and mental or instinctive abilities to their highest potential and maintaining them that way. This law supports the lion in its strength, the hare in her speed, and the fox in its cleverness. Since nature, in all its forms of life, has a capacity for growth that far exceeds what’s necessary to replace what is lost over time, individuals lacking the necessary strength, speed, toughness, or cunning tend to perish early without reproducing. They either become prey for their natural enemies or succumb to diseases, often caused by lack of nourishment, while the more capable individuals of their kind take their place and compete for resources.
"Throughout this volume, we have felt considerable inconvenience from the adopted dogmatical classification of plants, and have all along been floundering between species and variety, which certainly under culture soften into each other. A particular conformity, each after its own kind, when in a state of nature, termed species, no doubt exists to a considerable degree. This conformity has existed during the last forty centuries; geologists discover a like particular conformity—fossil species—through the deep deposition of each great epoch; but they also discover an almost complete difference to exist[Pg 318] between the species or stamp of life of one epoch from that of every other. We are therefore led to admit either a repeated miraculous conception, or a power of change under change of circumstances to belong to living organized matter, or rather to the congeries of inferior life which appears to form superior." (By this I suppose Mr. Matthew to imply his assent to the theory, that our personality or individuality is but as it were "the consensus, or full flowing river of a vast number of subordinate individualities or personalities, each one of which is a living being with thoughts and wishes of its own.") "The derangements and changes in organized existence, induced by a change of circumstances from the interference of man, afford us proof of the plastic quality of superior life; and the likelihood that circumstances have been very different in the different epochs, though steady in each, tend strongly to heighten the probability of the latter theory.
"Throughout this book, we've experienced a lot of frustration from the rigid dogmatic classification of plants, and we've been struggling to differentiate between species and variety, which definitely blend together when cultivated. A specific consistency, each according to its type, exists in nature, referred to as species, to a notable extent. This consistency has been present for the past forty centuries; geologists find a similar specific consistency—fossil species—through the extensive deposits of each major era; however, they also find nearly complete differences in the species or forms of life from one era to another. Thus, we are led to accept either a repeated miraculous creation or a power of change in response to changing circumstances in living organized matter, or more accurately, in the collection of lower life forms that seem to give rise to higher forms." (By this, I believe Mr. Matthew is agreeing with the theory that our personality or individuality is essentially "the consensus, or full flowing river of a vast number of subordinate individualities or personalities, each of which is a living being with its own thoughts and desires.") "The disruptions and changes in organized life caused by human interference provide evidence of the flexible nature of higher life; and the idea that circumstances have varied significantly across different eras, even though stable within each, strongly supports the likelihood of the latter theory.[Pg 318]"
"When we view the immense calcareous and bituminous formations, principally from the waters and atmosphere, and consider the oxidations and depositions which have taken place, either gradually or during some of the great convulsions, it appears at least probable that the liquid elements containing life have varied considerably at different times in composition and weight; that our atmosphere has contained a much greater proportion of carbonic acid or oxygen; and our waters, aided by excess of carbonic acid, and greater heat resulting from greater density of atmosphere, have contained a greater quantity of lime, and other mineral solutions. Is the inference, then, unphilosophic that[Pg 319] living things which are proved to have a circumstance-suiting power (a very slight change of circumstance by culture inducing a corresponding change of character), may have gradually accommodated themselves to the variations of the elements containing them, and without new creation, have presented the diverging changeable phenomena of past and present organized existence?
"When we look at the vast limestone and tar-like formations, mainly from the water and the atmosphere, and consider the oxidizations and deposits that have occurred, either slowly or during major upheavals, it seems likely that the liquid elements that support life have changed a lot over time in terms of composition and weight. Our atmosphere may have had a much higher proportion of carbon dioxide or oxygen, and our waters, influenced by excess carbon dioxide and higher temperatures due to a denser atmosphere, could have contained more lime and other mineral solutions. So, is it unreasonable to conclude that[Pg 319] living things, which have shown a capacity to adapt to circumstances (where even a small change in environment through cultivation leads to a corresponding change in characteristics), may have gradually adjusted to the changes in their environment, and without any new creation, exhibited the varying and evolving phenomena of both past and present life?"
"The destructive liquid currents before which the hardest mountains have been swept and comminuted into gravel, sand, and mud, which intervened between and divided these epochs, probably extending over the whole surface of the globe and destroying nearly all living things, must have reduced existence so much that an unoccupied field would be formed for new diverging ramifications of life, which from the connected sexual system of vegetables, and the natural instinct of animals to herd and combine with their own kind, would fall into specific groups—these remnants in the course of time moulding and accommodating their being anew to the change of circumstances, and to every possible means of subsistence—and the millions of ages of regularity which appear to have followed between the epochs, probably after this accommodation was completed, affording fossil deposit of regular specific character.
"The destructive liquid currents that have worn down even the toughest mountains into gravel, sand, and mud, which separated and divided these eras, likely spread across the entire surface of the Earth and wiped out nearly all living things. This must have created a blank slate for new, diverse forms of life to emerge. From the interconnected reproductive systems of plants and the natural instinct of animals to group together with their own kind, they would form distinct categories. Over time, these remnants would adapt and reshape themselves to new conditions and various ways to survive. The millions of years of stability that seem to follow these periods likely resulted from this adaptation, leading to fossil deposits with consistent characteristics."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"In endeavouring to trace ... the principle of these changes of fashion which have taken place in the domiciles of life the following questions occur: Do they arise from admixture of species nearly allied producing intermediate species? Are they the diverging ramifications[Pg 320] of the living principle under modification of circumstance? or have they resulted from the combined agency of both?
"In trying to understand the principle behind the changes in fashion that have occurred in our living spaces, the following questions arise: Do they come from the mixing of closely related species producing intermediate forms? Are they the diverging branches[Pg 320] of the living principle adapting to changes in circumstances? Or are they the result of both factors working together?"
"Is there only one living principle? Does organized existence, and perhaps all material existence, consist of one Proteus principle of life capable of gradual circumstance-suited modifications and aggregations without bound, under the solvent or motion-giving principle of heat or light? There is more beauty and unity of design in this continual balancing of life to circumstance, and greater conformity to those dispositions of nature that are manifest to us, than in total destruction and new creation. It is improbable that much of this diversification is owing to commixture of species nearly allied; all change by this appears very limited and confined within the bounds of what is called species; the progeny of the same parents under great difference of circumstance, might in several generations even become distinct species, incapable of co-reproduction.
Is there just one living principle? Does organized existence, and maybe all material existence, consist of one Proteus principle of life that can gradually change and adapt based on circumstances, without limits, under the driving forces of heat or light? There’s more beauty and unity in this constant adjustment of life to its surroundings, and a greater alignment with those natural tendencies we can observe, than in total destruction and new creation. It seems unlikely that much of this diversity is due to the mixing of closely related species; all the changes that come from this seem very limited and contained within what we call species; the offspring of the same parents under significantly different circumstances might, over many generations, even evolve into distinct species that can’t reproduce with each other.
"The self-regulating adaptive disposition of organized life may, in part, be traced to the extreme fecundity of nature, who, as before stated, has in all the varieties of her offspring a prolific power much beyond (in many cases a thousand fold) what is necessary to fill up the vacancies caused by senile decay. As the field of existence is limited and preoccupied, it is only the hardier, more robust, better suited to circumstance individuals, who are able to struggle forward to maturity, these inhabiting only the situations to which they have superior adaptation and greater power of occupancy[Pg 321] than any other kind; the weaker and less circumstance-suited being prematurely destroyed. This principle is in constant action; it regulates the colour, the figure, the capacities, and instincts; those individuals in each species whose colour and covering are best suited to concealment or protection from enemies, or defence from inclemencies and vicissitudes of climate, whose figure is best accommodated to health, strength, defence, and support; whose capacities and instincts can best regulate the physical energies to self-advantage according to circumstances—in such immense waste of primary and youthful life those only come forward to maturity from the strict ordeal by which nature tests their adaptation to her standard of perfection and fitness to continue their kind by reproduction.
The self-regulating adaptive nature of organized life can be partly traced back to the incredible fertility of nature, which, as mentioned before, has the ability to produce far more offspring (in many cases, a thousand times more) than necessary to replace those lost to aging. Since the realm of existence is limited and occupied, only the hardiest, most robust, and best-suited individuals can manage to reach maturity. These individuals thrive only in environments to which they have superior adaptation and greater ability to occupy than any others; the weaker and less adaptable are eliminated prematurely. This principle is always at work; it governs color, shape, abilities, and instincts. Those individuals within each species whose coloration and covering are best suited for concealment or protection from predators, or for defense against harsh weather and environmental changes, whose form promotes health, strength, protection, and support; whose abilities and instincts effectively manage physical energy to their advantage depending on the situation—only they survive to maturity amid the significant loss of young life, as nature rigorously tests their adaptation to her standards of perfection and suitability for reproduction.
"From the unremitting operation of this law acting in concert with the tendency which the progeny have to take the more particular qualities of the parents, together with the connected sexual system in vegetables and instinctive limitation to its own kind in animals, a considerable uniformity of figure, colour, and character is induced constituting species; the breed gradually acquiring the very best possible adaptation of these to its condition which it is susceptible of, and when alteration of circumstance occurs, thus changing in character to suit these, as far as its nature is susceptible of change.
"Because of the constant operation of this law working alongside the tendency for offspring to inherit specific traits from their parents, along with the related reproductive systems in plants and the instinctual limitations in animals to their own species, a significant consistency in shape, color, and characteristics arises that defines species. Each breed gradually develops the best possible adaptation to its environment and, when circumstances change, it alters its traits to adjust to these new conditions, as much as its nature allows."
"This circumstance-adaptive law operating upon the slight but continued natural disposition to sport in the progeny (seedling variety) does not preclude the supposed influence which volition or sensation may have had over[Pg 322] the configuration of the body. To examine into the disposition to sport in the progeny, even when there is only one parent as in many vegetables, and to investigate how much variation is modified by the mind or nervous sensation of the parents, or of the living thing itself during its progress to maturity; how far it depends upon external circumstance, and how far on the will, irritability, and muscular exertion, is open to examination and experiment. In the first place, we ought to examine its dependency upon the preceding links of the particular chain of life, variety being often merely types or approximations of former parentage; thence the variation of the family as well as of the individual must be embraced by our experiments.
"This law that adapts to circumstances and affects the slight but ongoing natural tendency to vary in offspring (seedling variety) does not eliminate the potential impact that will or sensation may have had on[Pg 322] the body's structure. We need to investigate the tendency to vary in offspring, even when there’s only one parent, as seen in many plants, and explore how much variation is influenced by the mind or nervous sensations of the parents, or of the living organism itself as it grows; how much is based on external factors, and how much is influenced by will, irritability, and physical exertion, is open to investigation and experimentation. First, we should look into its reliance on the previous links in the specific chain of life, since variety often represents merely types or approximations of past ancestry; thus, the variation within the family as well as the individual must be included in our experiments."
"This continuation of family type, not broken by casual particular aberration, is mental as well as corporeal, and is exemplified in many of the dispositions or instincts of particular races of men. These innate or continuous ideas or habits seem proportionally greater in the insect tribes, and in those especially of shorter revolution; and forming an abiding memory, may resolve much of the enigma of instinct, and the foreknowledge which these tribes have of what is necessary to completing their round of life, reducing this to knowledge or impressions and habits acquired by a long experience.
"This ongoing family pattern, not disrupted by random specific differences, is both mental and physical, and is shown in many traits or instincts of specific human races. These inherent or persistent ideas or habits appear to be more pronounced in insect species, particularly those with shorter life cycles; and by creating a lasting memory, they may explain much of the mystery of instinct and the awareness these species have of what is needed to complete their life cycle, simplifying it to knowledge or impressions and habits gained through long experience.
"This greater continuity of existence, or rather continuity of perceptions and impressions in insects, is highly probable; it is even difficult in some to ascertain the particular steps when each individual commences, under the different phases of egg, larva, pupa, or if much consciousness of individuality exists. The continuation[Pg 323] of reproduction for several generations by the females alone in some of these tribes, tends to the probability of the greater continuity of existence; and the subdivisions of life by cuttings (even in animal life), at any rate, must stagger the advocate of individuality.
"This greater continuity of existence, or rather the continuity of perceptions and impressions in insects, is very likely; it’s even hard in some cases to determine the specific point when each one starts, during the various stages of egg, larva, pupa, or whether there's much awareness of individuality present. The continuation[Pg 323] of reproduction over several generations solely by females in some of these groups, supports the idea of greater continuity of existence; and the way life is subdivided by splitting (even in animals) is bound to challenge the notion of individuality.
"Among the millions of specific varieties of living things which occupy the humid portions of the surface of our planet, as far back as can be traced, there does not appear, with the exception of man, to have been any particular engrossing race, but a pretty fair balance of power of occupancy—or rather most wonderful variation of circumstance parallel to the nature of every species, as if circumstance and species had grown up together. There are, indeed, several races which have threatened ascendancy in some particular regions; but it is man alone from whom any general imminent danger to the existence of his brethren is to be dreaded.
"Among the millions of specific varieties of living things that inhabit the humid areas of our planet, as far back as we can trace, there doesn’t seem to be, except for humans, any particularly dominant race. Instead, there’s a pretty good balance of occupancy—or rather, a fascinating variation of conditions that align with the nature of each species, as if circumstances and species evolved together. Indeed, there are several races that have threatened to dominate in certain regions, but it is only humans from whom we should fear any widespread threat to the existence of their fellow beings."
"As far back as history reaches, man had already had considerable influence, and had made encroachments upon his fellow denizens, probably occasioning the destruction of many species, and the production and continuation of a number of varieties, and even species, which he found more suited to supply his wants, but which from the infirmity of their condition—not having undergone selection by the law of nature, of which we have spoken—cannot maintain their ground without culture and protection.
"As far back as history goes, humans have already had a significant impact, encroaching on their fellow inhabitants and likely causing the extinction of many species. They've also created and sustained several varieties and even species that fit their needs better. However, due to the weaknesses of these organisms—not having been shaped by natural selection as we've discussed—they can't survive without cultivation and protection."
"It is only however in the present age that man has begun to reap the fruits of his tedious education, and has proven how much 'knowledge is power.' He[Pg 324] has now acquired a dominion over the material world, and a consequent power of increase, so as to render it probable that the whole surface of the earth may soon be overrun by this engrossing anomaly, to the annihilation of every wonderful and beautiful variety of animal existence which does not administer to his wants, principally as laboratories of preparation to befit cruder elemental matter for assimilation by his organs.
"It’s only in the current age that people have started to enjoy the benefits of their long education, proving how much 'knowledge is power.' He[Pg 324] has now gained control over the material world, and as a result, the potential for growth is so great that it’s likely the entire surface of the earth could soon be dominated by this overwhelming phenomenon, leading to the destruction of every amazing and beautiful type of animal life that doesn’t serve his needs, mainly as sources of resources to prepare raw materials for his consumption."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"The consequences are being now developed of our deplorable ignorance of, or inattention to, one of the most evident traits of natural history—that vegetables, as well as animals, are generally liable to an almost unlimited diversification, regulated by climate, soil, nourishment, and new commixture of already-formed varieties. In those with which man is most intimate, and where his agency in throwing them from their natural locality and disposition has brought out this power of diversification in stronger shades, it has been forced upon his notice, as in man himself, in the dog, horse, cow, sheep, poultry,—in the apple, pear, plum, gooseberry, potato, pea, which sport in infinite varieties, differing considerably in size, colour, taste, firmness of texture, period of growth, almost in every recognizable quality. In all these kinds man is influential in preventing deterioration, by careful selection of the largest or most valuable as breeders."[322]
The consequences of our unfortunate ignorance or negligence regarding one of the most obvious aspects of natural history are unfolding now—that both plants and animals are generally subject to nearly limitless variation, affected by climate, soil, nutrients, and new combinations of existing varieties. In those species that humans are most closely connected to, where our actions in moving them from their natural environment have emphasized this capacity for change, it has become clear, just like in humans, dogs, horses, cows, sheep, and poultry—as well as in apples, pears, plums, gooseberries, potatoes, and peas, which display endless variations in size, color, flavor, texture, growth period, and almost every identifiable trait. In all these cases, humans play a key role in preventing decline by carefully selecting the largest or most valuable individuals for breeding.[322]
Étienne and Isidore Geoffroy.
Étienne and Isidore Geoffroy.
"Both Cuvier and Étienne Geoffroy," says Isidore Geoffroy, "had early perceived the philosophical importance of a question (evolution) which must be admitted as—with that of unity of composition—the greatest in natural history. We find them laying it down in the year 1795 in one of their joint 'Memoirs' (on the Orangs), in the very plainest terms, in the following question, 'Must we see,' they inquire, 'what we commonly call species, as the modified descendants of the same original form?'
"Both Cuvier and Étienne Geoffroy," says Isidore Geoffroy, "recognized early on the philosophical significance of a question (evolution) that must be considered one of the most important in natural history, alongside the concept of unity of composition. We see them stating this clearly in 1795 in one of their joint 'Memoirs' (on the Orangs) with the straightforward question, 'Should we view what we commonly refer to as species as the modified descendants of the same original form?'"
"Both were at that time doubtful. Some years afterwards Cuvier not only answered this question in the negative, but declared, and pretended to prove, that the same forms have been perpetuated from the beginning of things. Lamarck, his antagonist par excellence on this point, maintained the contrary position with no less distinctness, showing that living beings are unceasingly variable with change of their surroundings, and giving with some boldness a zoological genesis in conformity with this doctrine.
"Both were uncertain at that time. A few years later, Cuvier not only answered this question negatively but also claimed, and tried to prove, that the same forms have been maintained since the beginning of time. Lamarck, his main opponent on this issue, argued the opposite position just as clearly, demonstrating that living beings are constantly changing with changes in their environment, and boldly proposing a zoological origin that aligns with this idea."
"Geoffroy St. Hilaire had long pondered over this difficult subject. The doctrine which in his old age he so firmly defended, does not seem to have been conceived by him till after he had completed his 'Philosophie Anatomique,' and except through lectures delivered orally to the museum and the faculty, it was not published till 1828; nor again in the work then published do we find his theory in its neatest expression and fullest development."[Pg 326]
"Geoffroy St. Hilaire had spent a long time thinking about this tough topic. The theory he strongly defended in his later years doesn’t appear to have been developed until after he finished his 'Philosophie Anatomique,' and it wasn’t published until 1828, except for lectures he gave at the museum and the faculty. Moreover, this work didn’t present his theory in its clearest expression and most complete form." [Pg 326]
Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire tells us in a note that the work referred to as first putting his father's views before the public in a printed form, was a report to the Academy of Sciences on a memoir by M. Roulin; but that before this report some indications of them are to be found in a paper on the Gavials, published in 1825. Their best rendering, however, and fullest development is in several memoirs, published in succession, between the years 1828 and 1837.
Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire notes that the work considered the first to present his father's views to the public in print was a report to the Academy of Sciences on a paper by M. Roulin; however, before this report, there are some hints of these ideas in a paper on the Gavials, published in 1825. Their clearest expression and most complete development can be found in several papers published in succession between 1828 and 1837.
"This doctrine," he continues, "is diametrically opposed to that of Cuvier, and is not entirely the same as Lamarck's. Geoffroy St. Hilaire refutes the one, he restrains and corrects the other. Cuvier, according to him, sums up against the facts, while Lamarck goes further than they will bear him out. Essentially however on questions of this nature he is a follower of Lamarck, and took pleasure on several occasions in describing himself as the disciple of his illustrious confrère."[323]
"This idea," he goes on, "is completely opposite to Cuvier's, and it’s not exactly the same as Lamarck's either. Geoffroy St. Hilaire challenges one and moderates the other. According to him, Cuvier’s conclusions clash with the facts, while Lamarck goes beyond what the evidence can support. Ultimately, on these kinds of issues, he aligns more with Lamarck, even enjoying describing himself at times as a student of his renowned peer." [323]
I have been unable to detect any substantial difference of opinion between Geoffroy St. Hilaire and Lamarck, except that the first maintained that a line must be drawn somewhere—and did not draw it—while the latter said that no line could be drawn, and therefore drew none. Mr. Darwin is quite correct in saying that Geoffroy St. Hilaire "relied chiefly on the conditions of life, or the 'monde ambiant,' as the cause of change." But this is only Lamarck over again, for though Lamarck attributes variation directly to[Pg 327] change of habits in the creature, he is almost wearisome in his insistence on the fact that the habit will not change, unless the conditions of life also do so. With both writers then it is change in the relative positions of the exterior circumstances, and of the organism, which results in variation, and finally in specific modification.
I haven't been able to find any significant disagreement between Geoffroy St. Hilaire and Lamarck, except that Geoffroy believed a line had to be drawn somewhere—but didn't actually draw it—while Lamarck argued that no line could be drawn at all, so he didn't draw one. Mr. Darwin is absolutely right when he says that Geoffroy St. Hilaire "mainly relied on the conditions of life, or the 'monde ambiant,' as the cause of change." But that's just a repeat of Lamarck because, even though Lamarck directly attributes variation to changes in an organism's habits, he keeps stressing that habits won’t change unless the conditions of life change too. So, for both writers, it’s the change in the relative positions of external circumstances and the organism that leads to variation and ultimately to specific modifications.
Here is another sketch of Étienne Geoffroy, also by his son Isidore.
Here’s another drawing of Étienne Geoffroy, also by his son Isidore.
In 1795, while Lamarck was still a believer in immutability, Étienne Geoffroy St. Hilaire "had ventured to say that species might well be 'degenerations from a single type,'" but, though he never lost sight of the question, he waited more than a quarter of a century before passing from meditation to action. "He at length put forward his opinion in 1825, he returned to it, but still briefly, in 1828 and 1829, and did not set himself to develop and establish it till the year 1831—the year following the memorable discussion in the Academy, on the unity of organic composition."[324]
In 1795, while Lamarck still believed in the idea that species don’t change, Étienne Geoffroy St. Hilaire "had boldly suggested that species could be 'degenerations from a single type.'" However, he kept thinking about it for over twenty-five years before moving from thought to action. "Eventually, he presented his opinion in 1825, revisited it briefly in 1828 and 1829, and didn’t really work to develop and establish it until 1831—the year after the important discussion in the Academy about the unity of organic composition."[324]
"If," says his son, "he began by paying homage to his illustrious precursor, and by laying it down as a general axiom, that there is no such thing as fixity in nature, and especially in animated nature, he follows this adhesion to the general doctrine of variability by a dissent which goes to the very heart of the matter. And this dissent becomes deeper and deeper in his later works. Not only is Geoffroy St. Hilaire at pains to deny the unlimited extension of variability which[Pg 328] is the foundation of the Lamarckian system, but he moreover and particularly declines to explain those degenerations which he admits as possible, by changes of action and habit on the part of the creature varying—Lamarck's favourite hypothesis, which he laboured to demonstrate without even succeeding in making it appear probable."[325]
"If," says his son, "he started by honoring his famous predecessor and stating as a general principle that nothing in nature is fixed, especially in living things, he then contrasts this commitment to the idea of change with a disagreement that strikes at the core of the issue. This disagreement deepens in his later works. Not only does Geoffroy St. Hilaire make it clear that he rejects the limitless idea of variability that is the basis of the Lamarckian system, but he also specifically refuses to explain the degenerations he accepts as possible through changes in actions and habits of the creature undergoing variation—Lamarck's preferred theory, which he tried to prove without even managing to make it seem plausible."
Isidore Geoffroy then declares that his father, "though chronologically a follower of Lamarck, should be ranked philosophically as having continued the work of Buffon, to whom all his differences of opinion with Lamarck serve to bring him nearer."[326] If he had understood Buffon he would not have said so.
Isidore Geoffroy then states that his father, "even though he came after Lamarck in time, should be considered philosophically as having carried on the work of Buffon, as all his disagreements with Lamarck actually bring him closer to Buffon."[326] If he had truly understood Buffon, he wouldn't have expressed it that way.
His conclusions are thus summed up:—"Geoffroy St. Hilaire maintains that species are variable if the environment varies in character; differences, then, more or less considerable according to the power of the modifying causes may have been produced in the course of time, and the living forms of to-day may be the descendants of more ancient forms."[327]
His conclusions can be summarized as follows:—"Geoffroy St. Hilaire argues that species can change if their environment changes; differences, therefore, which can vary in significance depending on the influence of modifying factors, have likely developed over time, and today’s living forms might be the descendants of more ancient forms."[327]
It is not easy to see that much weight should be attached to Geoffroy St. Hilaire's opinion. He seems to have been a person of hesitating temperament, under an impression that there was an opening just then through which a judicious trimmer might pass himself in among men of greater power. If his son has described his teaching correctly, it amounts practically to a bonâ fide endorsement of what Buffon can only be considered to have pretended to believe. The same objection that must be fatal to the view pretended by[Pg 329] Buffon, is so in like manner to those put forward seriously of both the Geoffroys—for Isidore Geoffroy followed his father, but leant a little more openly towards Lamarck. He writes:—
It’s not easy to see why so much importance should be placed on Geoffroy St. Hilaire's opinion. He seems to have had a hesitant personality, believing there was a chance to position himself among more powerful individuals. If his son accurately portrayed his teaching, it essentially amounts to a genuine endorsement of what Buffon only pretended to believe. The same objection that would undermine Buffon's argument also applies to those put forward by both Geoffroys—since Isidore Geoffroy followed in his father’s footsteps but leaned a bit more openly towards Lamarck. He writes:—
"The characters of species are neither absolutely fixed, as has been maintained by some; nor yet, still more, indefinitely variable as according to others. They are fixed for each species as long as that species continues to reproduce itself in an unchanged environment; but they become modified if the environment changes."[328]
"The characteristics of species aren't completely unchanging, as some have claimed; nor are they endlessly variable, as others suggest. They remain stable for each species as long as that species continues to reproduce in a consistent environment; however, they do change if the environment shifts." [328]
This is all that Lamarck himself would expect, as no one could be more fully aware than M. Geoffroy, who, however, admits that degeneration may extend to generic differences.[329]
This is exactly what Lamarck would expect, since no one understood this better than M. Geoffroy, who does acknowledge that degeneration can apply to generic differences.[329]
I have been unable to find in M. Isidore Geoffroy's work anything like a refutation of Lamarck's contention that the modifications in animals and plants are due to the needs and wishes of the animals and plants themselves; on the contrary, to some extent he countenances this view himself, for he says, "hence arise notable differences of habitation and climate, and these in their turn induce secondary differences in diet and even in habits."[330] From which it must follow, though I cannot find it said expressly, that the author attributes modification in some measure to changed habits, and therefore to the changed desires from which the change of habits has arisen; but in the main he appears[Pg 330] to refer modification to the direct action of a changed environment.
I haven't been able to find anything in M. Isidore Geoffroy's work that directly refutes Lamarck's claim that changes in animals and plants come from their own needs and desires. In fact, to some extent, he seems to support this idea himself, as he states, "hence arise notable differences of habitation and climate, and these in their turn induce secondary differences in diet and even in habits."[330] This implies, although it isn’t stated outright, that the author believes changes are partly due to altered habits, which relate to the changed desires that prompted those habits. However, overall he seems[Pg 330] to attribute changes mainly to the direct impact of a changed environment.
Mr. Herbert Spencer.
Mr. Herbert Spencer.
"Those who cavalierly reject the theory of Lamarck and his followers as not adequately supported by facts," wrote Mr. Herbert Spencer,[331] "seem quite to forget that their own theory is supported by no facts at all"—inasmuch as no one pretends to have seen an act of direct creation. Mr. Spencer points out that, according to the best authorities, there are some 320,000 species of plants now existing, and about 2,000,000 species of animals, including insects, and that if the extinct forms which have successively appeared and disappeared be added to these, there cannot have existed in all less than some ten million species. "Which," asks Mr. Spencer, "is the most rational theory about these ten millions of species? Is it most likely that there have been ten millions of special creations? or, is it most likely that by continual modification due to change of circumstances, ten millions of varieties may have been produced as varieties are being produced still?"
"Those who dismiss the theory of Lamarck and his followers without strong evidence," wrote Mr. Herbert Spencer,[331] "seem to overlook the fact that their own theory lacks any evidence whatsoever"—since no one claims to have witnessed an act of direct creation. Mr. Spencer points out that, according to the best experts, there are about 320,000 species of plants currently existing, and around 2,000,000 species of animals, including insects. When you factor in the extinct forms that have come and gone, there have likely been at least ten million species in total. "Which," asks Mr. Spencer, "is the most reasonable explanation for these ten million species? Is it more probable that there have been ten million separate creations? Or is it more likely that through continuous modification due to changes in circumstances, ten million varieties have developed, just as new varieties are still being produced today?"
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"Even could the supporters of the development hypothesis merely show that the production of species by the process of modification is conceivable, they would be in a better position than their opponents. But they can do much more than this; they can show that the process of modification has effected and is effecting great changes in all organisms, subject to[Pg 331] modifying influences ... they can show that any existing species—animal or vegetable—when placed under conditions different from its previous ones, immediately begins to undergo certain changes of structure fitting it for the new conditions. They can show that in successive generations these changes continue until ultimately the new conditions become the natural ones. They can show that in cultivated plants and domesticated animals, and in the several races of men, these changes have uniformly taken place. They can show that the degrees of difference, so produced, are often, as in dogs, greater than those on which distinctions of species are in other cases founded. They can show that it is a matter of dispute whether some of these modified forms are varieties or modified species. They can show too that the changes daily taking place in ourselves; the facility that attends long practice, and the loss of aptitude that begins when practice ceases; the strengthening of passions habitually gratified, and the weakening of those habitually curbed; the development of every faculty, bodily, moral or intellectual, according to the use made of it, are all explicable on this same principle. And thus they can show that throughout all organic nature there is at work a modifying influence of the kind they assign as the cause of these specific differences, an influence which, though slow in its action, does in time, if the circumstances demand it, produce marked changes; an influence which, to all appearance, would produce in the millions of years, and under the great varieties of condition which geological records imply, any amount of change."[Pg 332]
Even if the supporters of the development hypothesis could only demonstrate that species can change through modification, they would have an advantage over their opponents. But they can do much more than that; they can show that modification has caused and is causing significant changes in all organisms, influenced by[Pg 331] various factors... They can show that any existing species—whether animal or plant—when exposed to different conditions from before, immediately starts to undergo specific structural changes that adapt it to the new conditions. They can show that these changes continue over successive generations until the new conditions become the norm. They can show that in cultivated plants, domesticated animals, and various human races, these changes have consistently occurred. They can show that the degree of difference produced is often, as in dogs, greater than the distinctions used to classify species in other cases. They can also show that there’s debate over whether some of these modified forms are varieties or modified species. Furthermore, they can show that the changes happening in ourselves daily; the ease that comes with long practice, and the decline in skill when practice stops; the strengthening of desires that are regularly satisfied, and the weakening of those that are typically suppressed; the development of every ability, whether physical, moral, or intellectual, based on how it’s used, all can be explained by this same principle. And so they can show that throughout all of organic nature, there is a modifying influence working in the way they identify as the cause of these specific differences, an influence which, although slow, can produce significant changes over time when circumstances demand it; an influence that, given millions of years and the vast variety of conditions indicated by geological records, could lead to any extent of change.[Pg 332]
This leaves nothing to be desired. It is Buffon, Dr. Darwin, and Lamarck, well expressed. Those were the days before "Natural Selection" had been discharged into the waters of the evolution controversy, like the secretion of a cuttle fish. Changed circumstances immediately induce changed habits, and hence a changed use of some organs, and disuse of others: as a consequence of this, organs and instincts become changed, "and these changes continue in successive generations, until ultimately the new conditions become the natural ones." This is the whole theory of "development," "evolution," or "descent with modification." Volumes may be written to adduce the details which warrant us in accepting it, and to explain the causes which have brought it about, but I fail to see how anything essential can be added to the theory itself, which is here so well supported by Mr. Spencer, and which is exactly as Lamarck left it. All that remains is to have a clear conception of the oneness of personality between parents and offspring, of the eternity, and latency, of memory, and of the unconsciousness with which habitual actions are repeated, which last point, indeed, Mr. Spencer has himself touched upon.
This leaves nothing to be desired. It captures Buffon, Dr. Darwin, and Lamarck perfectly. Those were the days before "Natural Selection" had been thrown into the mix of the evolution debate, like the ink of a cuttlefish. Changed circumstances immediately lead to changed habits, which means some organs are used differently while others are not used at all. As a result, organs and instincts evolve, "and these changes carry on in successive generations until the new conditions become the norm." This is the entire theory of "development," "evolution," or "descent with modification." Many volumes could be written to provide the details that justify our acceptance of it, and to explain the causes that led to it, but I don't see how anything essential can be added to the theory itself, which is so well supported by Mr. Spencer and remains just as Lamarck stated it. What’s left is to clearly understand the unity of personality between parents and their offspring, the permanence and hidden nature of memory, and the unconscious way in which habitual actions are repeated—this last point is something Mr. Spencer has also addressed.
Mr. Spencer continues—"That by any series of changes a zoophyte should ever become a mammal, seems to those who are not familiar with zoology, and who have not seen how clear becomes the relationship between the simplest and the most complex forms, when all intermediate forms are examined, a very grotesque notion ... they never realize the fact that by small increments of modification, any amount of[Pg 333] modification may in time be generated. That surprise which they feel on finding one whom they last saw as a boy, grown into a man, becomes incredulity when the degree of change is greater. Nevertheless, abundant instances are at hand of the mode in which we may pass to the most diverse forms by insensible gradations."
Mr. Spencer continues—"The idea that a zoophyte could eventually evolve into a mammal seems ridiculous to those who aren't familiar with zoology and haven't examined how clear the connections become between the simplest and the most complex forms when all the intermediate stages are looked at. They fail to realize that, through small, gradual changes, significant amounts of modification can accumulate over time. That surprise people feel when they see someone they last knew as a boy now grown into a man turns into disbelief when the change is more pronounced. However, there are plenty of examples showing how we can transition to various forms through subtle gradations."
Nothing can be more satisfactory and straightforward. I will make one more quotation from this excellent article:—
Nothing could be more satisfying and straightforward. I’ll share one more quote from this excellent article:—
"But the blindness of those who think it absurd to suppose that complex organic forms may have arisen by successive modifications out of simple ones, becomes astonishing when we remember that complex organic forms are daily being thus produced. A tree differs from a seed immeasurably in every respect—in bulk, in structure, in colour, in form, in specific gravity, in chemical composition—differs so greatly that no visible resemblance of any kind can be pointed out between them. Yet is the one changed in the course of a few years into the other—changed so gradually that at no moment can it be said, 'Now the seed ceases to be, and the tree exists.' What can be more widely contrasted than a newly-born child, and the small, semi-transparent gelatinous spherule constituting the human ovum? The infant is so complex in structure that a cyclopædia is needed to describe its constituent parts. The germinal vesicle is so simple, that a line will contain all that can be said of it. Nevertheless, a few months suffices to develop the one out of the other, and that too by a series of modifications so small, that were the[Pg 334] embryo examined at successive minutes, not even a microscope would disclose any sensible changes. That the uneducated and ill-educated should think the hypothesis that all races of beings, man inclusive, may in process of time have been evolved from the simplest monad a ludicrous one is not to be wondered at. But for the physiologist, who knows that every individual being is so evolved—who knows further that in their earliest condition the germs of all plants and animals whatsoever are so similar, 'that there is no appreciable distinction among them which would enable it to be determined whether a particular molecule is the germ of a conferva or of an oak, of a zoophyte or of a man'[332]—for him to make a difficulty of the matter is inexcusable. Surely, if a single structureless cell may, when subjected to certain influences, become a man in the space of twenty years, there is nothing absurd in the hypothesis that under certain other influences a cell may, in the course of millions of years, give origin to the human race. The two processes are generically the same, and differ only in length and complexity."
"But the ignorance of those who find it ridiculous to think that complex organic forms could have evolved from simple ones through gradual changes is remarkable, especially when we consider that complex organic forms are being created every day. A tree is vastly different from a seed in every way—in size, structure, color, shape, density, and chemical makeup—so much so that there’s no visible similarity between them. Yet one transforms into the other over just a few years—changing so slowly that at no point can we say, 'Now the seed is gone, and the tree has appeared.' What could contrast more than a newborn baby and the tiny, clear, gel-like sphere that makes up the human egg? The baby is so complex that it takes an encyclopedia to describe its parts, while the egg is so simple that it can be fully described in a single sentence. Still, it only takes a few months to develop one from the other, and the changes are so minor that if we examined the embryo minute by minute, even a microscope wouldn’t reveal any noticeable differences. It's not surprising that those who are uneducated or poorly educated would find the idea that all species, including humans, could eventually evolve from the simplest single-celled organisms to be laughable. But for a physiologist, who understands that every individual organism is indeed evolved—who also knows that in their earliest stages, the seeds of all plants and animals are so similar that there’s no noticeable difference to tell whether a particular molecule is the seed of a filamentous algae or an oak, a sea creature or a human—for him to struggle with the concept is inexcusable. Surely, if a single, structureless cell can, under certain conditions, become a human in twenty years, it’s not absurd to think that under different conditions, a cell could, over millions of years, give rise to humanity. The two processes are fundamentally the same and differ only in duration and complexity."
The very important extract from Professor Hering's lecture should perhaps have been placed here. The reader will, however, find it on page 199.
The important excerpt from Professor Hering's lecture should probably be included here. However, you can find it on page 199.
FOOTNOTES:
[322] See 'Naval Timber and Arboriculture,' by Patrick Matthew, published by Adam and C. Black, Edinburgh, and Longmans and Co., London, 1831, pp. 364, 365, 381-388, and also 106-108, 'Gardeners' Chronicle,' April 7, 1860.
[322] See 'Naval Timber and Arboriculture,' by Patrick Matthew, published by Adam and C. Black, Edinburgh, and Longmans and Co., London, 1831, pp. 364, 365, 381-388, and also 106-108, 'Gardeners' Chronicle,' April 7, 1860.
[326] Ibid.
Ibid.
[327] Ibid. p. 421.
Ibid. p. 421.
MAIN POINTS OF AGREEMENT AND OF DIFFERENCE BETWEEN THE OLD AND NEW THEORIES OF EVOLUTION.
MAIN POINTS OF AGREEMENT AND DIFFERENCE BETWEEN OLD AND NEW THEORIES OF EVOLUTION.
Having put before the reader with some fulness the theories of the three writers to whom we owe the older or teleological view of evolution, I will now compare that view more closely with the theory of Mr. Darwin and Mr. Wallace, to whom, in spite of my profound difference of opinion with them on the subject of natural selection, I admit with pleasure that I am under deep obligation. For the sake of brevity, I shall take Lamarck as the exponent of the older view, and Mr. Darwin as that of the one now generally accepted.
Having thoroughly presented the theories of the three writers who contributed to the older or teleological view of evolution, I will now closely compare that view with the theory proposed by Mr. Darwin and Mr. Wallace. Even though I have significant disagreements with them regarding natural selection, I must acknowledge my deep appreciation for their work. To keep it concise, I will use Lamarck to represent the older view and Mr. Darwin for the currently accepted perspective.
We have seen, that up to a certain point there is very little difference between Lamarck and Mr. Darwin. Lamarck maintains that animals and plants vary: so does Mr. Darwin. Lamarck maintains that variations having once arisen have a tendency to be transmitted to offspring and accumulated: so does Mr. Darwin. Lamarck maintains that the accumulation of variations, so small, each one of them, that it cannot be, or is not noticed, nevertheless will lead in the course of that almost infinite time during which life has existed upon earth, to very wide differences in form, structure, and instincts: so does Mr. Darwin.[Pg 336] Finally, Lamarck declares that all, or nearly all, the differences which we observe between various kinds of animals and plants are due to this exceedingly gradual and imperceptible accumulation, during many successive generations, of variations each one of which was in the outset small: so does Mr. Darwin. But in the above we have a complete statement of the fact of evolution, or descent with modification—wanting nothing, but entire, and incapable of being added to except in detail, and by way of explanation of the causes which have brought the fact about. As regards the general conclusion arrived at, therefore, I am unable to detect any difference of opinion between Lamarck and Mr. Darwin. They are both bent on establishing the theory of evolution in its widest extent.
We've seen that, up to a certain point, there's very little difference between Lamarck and Mr. Darwin. Lamarck argues that animals and plants vary; Mr. Darwin does too. Lamarck asserts that once variations occur, they have a tendency to be passed on to offspring and accumulate; Mr. Darwin agrees. Lamarck holds that the accumulation of these variations, each so small that they’re not noticeable, will eventually lead, over the almost infinite time life has existed on Earth, to significant differences in form, structure, and instincts; Mr. Darwin shares this view. Finally, Lamarck claims that all, or nearly all, the differences we see between different types of animals and plants are due to this extremely gradual and imperceptible accumulation of variations over many generations, each initially small; Mr. Darwin concurs. In this, we have a complete statement of the fact of evolution, or descent with modification—it's comprehensive, needing nothing more except details and explanations of the causes that brought this about. Therefore, regarding the general conclusion reached, I can't find any difference of opinion between Lamarck and Mr. Darwin. Both are committed to establishing the theory of evolution in its broadest sense.[Pg 336]
The late Sir Charles Lyell, in his 'Principles of Geology,' bears me out here. In a note to his résumé of the part of the 'Philosophie Zoologique' which bears upon evolution, he writes:—
The late Sir Charles Lyell, in his 'Principles of Geology,' supports my point here. In a note to his summary of the section of the 'Philosophie Zoologique' that relates to evolution, he writes:—
"I have reprinted in this chapter word for word my abstract of Lamarck's doctrine of transmutation, as drawn up by me in 1832 in the first edition of the 'Principles of Geology.'[333] I have thought it right to do this in justice to Lamarck, in order to show how nearly the opinions taught by him at the commencement of this century resembled those now in vogue amongst a large body of naturalists respecting the infinite variability of species, and the progressive development in past time of the organic world. The reader[Pg 337] must bear in mind that when I made this analysis of the 'Philosophie Zoologique' in 1832, I was altogether opposed to the doctrine that the animals and plants now living were the lineal descendants of distinct species, only known to us in a fossil state, and ... so far from exaggerating, I did not do justice to the arguments originally adduced by Lamarck and Geoffroy St. Hilaire, especially those founded on the occurrence of rudimentary organs. There is therefore no room for suspicion that my account of the Lamarckian hypothesis, written by me thirty-five years ago, derived any colouring from my own views tending to bring it more into harmony with the theory since propounded by Darwin."[334] So little difference did Sir Charles Lyell discover between the views of Lamarck and those of his successors.
"I have reprinted in this chapter word for word my summary of Lamarck's doctrine of transmutation, as I wrote it in 1832 in the first edition of the 'Principles of Geology.'[333] I felt it was important to do this in fairness to Lamarck, to show how closely his ideas at the beginning of this century resembled those currently held by many naturalists regarding the endless variability of species and the gradual development of the organic world over time. The reader[Pg 337] should keep in mind that when I analyzed the 'Philosophie Zoologique' in 1832, I was completely against the idea that living animals and plants are direct descendants of distinct species that we only know from fossils, and... far from exaggerating, I did not fully acknowledge the arguments originally put forth by Lamarck and Geoffroy St. Hilaire, particularly those based on the presence of rudimentary organs. Therefore, there is no reason to suspect that my account of the Lamarckian hypothesis, written thirty-five years ago, was influenced by my own views that aimed to align it more closely with the theory later proposed by Darwin."[334] Sir Charles Lyell found very little difference between the views of Lamarck and those of his followers.
With the identity, however, of the main proposition which, both Lamarck and Mr. Darwin alike endeavour to establish, the points of agreement between the two writers come to an end. Lamarck's great aim was to discover the cause of those variations whose accumulation results in specific, and finally in generic, differences. Not content with establishing the fact of descent with modification, he, like his predecessors, wishes to explain how it was that the fact came about. He finds its explanation in changed surroundings—that is to say, in changed conditions of existence—as the indirect cause, and in the varying needs arising from these changed conditions as the direct cause.
With the identity of the main proposition that both Lamarck and Mr. Darwin are trying to establish, the agreement between the two writers ends. Lamarck's primary goal was to discover the reason behind the variations that accumulate and lead to specific, and eventually generic, differences. Not satisfied with just establishing the fact of descent with modification, he, like his predecessors, wants to explain how this fact came to be. He attributes its explanation to changing environments—that is, to changing conditions of existence—as the indirect cause, and to the varying needs that arise from these changed conditions as the direct cause.
According to Lamarck, there is a broad principle[Pg 338] which underlies variation generally, and this principle is the power which all living beings possess of slightly varying their actions in accordance with varying needs, coupled with the fact observable throughout nature that use develops, and disuse enfeebles an organ, and that the effects, whether of use or disuse, become hereditary after many generations.
According to Lamarck, there’s a general principle[Pg 338] that explains variation in living things. This principle is the ability of all living beings to slightly change their behavior based on different needs, along with the observation in nature that using an organ strengthens it, while not using it weakens it. These effects, whether from use or disuse, can be passed down through generations.
This resolves itself into the effect of the mutual interaction of mind on body and of body on mind. Thus he writes:—
This comes down to how the mind and body affect each other. So he writes:—
"The physical and the mental are to start with undoubtedly one and the same thing; this fact is most easily made apparent through study of the organization of the various orders of known animals. From the common source there proceeded certain effects, and these effects, in the outset hardly separated, have in the course of time become so perfectly distinct, that when looked at in their extremest development they appear to have little or nothing in common.
"The physical and mental aspects are, to begin with, undoubtedly the same thing; this fact is most clearly demonstrated through the study of the organization of different groups of known animals. From a common source, certain effects emerged, and these effects, initially hardly distinguishable, have over time become so completely separate that when observed in their most developed forms, they seem to have very little or nothing in common."
"The effect of the body upon the mind has been already sufficiently recognized; not so that of the mind upon the body itself. The two, one in the outset though they were, interact upon each other more and more the more they present the appearance of having become widely sundered, and it can be shown that each is continually modifying the other and causing it to vary."[335]
"The influence of the body on the mind is already well acknowledged; however, the opposite—how the mind affects the body—is not as widely recognized. Although they were initially connected, the two influence each other increasingly as they seem to be more separated. It's clear that each one is constantly changing the other and causing it to adapt." [335]
And again, later:—
And again, later:—
"I shall show that the habits by which we now[Pg 339] recognize any creature are due to the environment (circonstances) under which it has for a long while existed, and that these habits have had such an influence upon the structure of each individual of the species as to have at length" (that is to say, through many successive slight variations, each due to habit engendered by the wishes of the animal itself), "modified this structure and adapted it to the habits contracted."[336]
"I will demonstrate that the ways we currently recognize any creature are influenced by the environment it has lived in for a long time, and that these habits have significantly impacted the structure of each individual in the species, eventually modifying this structure and adapting it to the habits formed."
These quotations must suffice, for the reader has already had Lamarck's argument sufficiently put before him.
These quotes have to be enough, since the reader has already been presented with Lamarck's argument thoroughly.
Variation, and consequently modification, are, according to Lamarck, the outward and visible signs of the impressions made upon animals and plants in the course of their long and varied history, each organ chronicling a time during which such and such thoughts and actions dominated the creature, and specific changes being the effect of certain long-continued wishes upon the body, and of certain changed surroundings upon the wishes. Plants and animals are living forms of faith, or faiths of form, whichever the reader pleases.
Variation, and as a result modification, are, according to Lamarck, the visible signs of the impressions made on animals and plants throughout their long and diverse history. Each organ reflects a period when certain thoughts and actions were dominant in the creature, and specific changes are the result of certain long-held desires affecting the body, as well as changes in the environment influencing those desires. Plants and animals are living representations of beliefs, or beliefs represented in their form, depending on what the reader prefers.
Mr. Darwin, on the other hand, repeatedly avows ignorance, and profound ignorance, concerning the causes of those variations which, or nothing, must be the fountain-heads of species. Thus he writes of "the complex and little known laws of variation."[337] "There is also some probability in the view propounded by Andrew Knight, that variability may be partly connected with excess of food."[338] "Many laws regulate variation, some[Pg 340] few of which can be dimly seen."[339] "The results of the unknown, or but dimly understood, laws of variation are infinitely complex and diversified."[340] "We are profoundly ignorant of the cause of each slight variation or individual difference."[341] "We are far too ignorant to speculate on the relative importance of the several known and unknown causes of variation."[342] He admits, indeed, the effects of use and disuse to have been important, but how important we have no means of knowing; he also attributes considerable effect to the action of changed conditions of life—but how considerable again we know not; nevertheless, he sees no great principle underlying the variations generally, and tending to make them appear for a length of time together in any definite direction advantageous to the creature itself, but either expressly, as at times, or by implication, as throughout his works, ascribes them to accident or chance.
Mr. Darwin, on the other hand, openly admits to having little to no understanding of the causes of the variations that are essential to the origins of species. He describes "the complex and little known laws of variation."[337] "There is also some probability in the idea proposed by Andrew Knight that variability may be partly related to having too much food."[338] "Many laws influence variation, some[Pg 340] few of which can be dimly seen."[339] "The results of the unknown or only partially understood laws of variation are incredibly complex and diverse."[340] "We are profoundly ignorant of the cause of each small variation or individual difference."[341] "We are far too ignorant to speculate on how important the various known and unknown causes of variation are."[342] He acknowledges that the effects of use and disuse have been significant, but we have no way of knowing exactly how significant; he also points out that changes in living conditions have a notable impact, though we don’t know how much. Still, he does not see any major principle that underlies the variations or guides them to be consistently beneficial to the organism, instead attributing them to accident or chance, either directly at times or implicitly throughout his work.
In other words, he admits his ignorance concerning them, and dwells only on the accumulation of variations the appearance of which for any length of time in any given direction he leaves unaccounted for.
In other words, he acknowledges that he doesn't know much about them and focuses solely on the collection of variations, leaving unexplained their appearance for any length of time in any specific direction.
Lamarck, again, having established his principle that sense of need is the main direct cause of variation, and having also established that the variations thus engendered are inherited, so that divergences accumulate and result in species and genera, is comparatively indifferent to further details. His work is avowedly an outline. Nevertheless, we have seen that he was[Pg 341] quite alive to the effects of the geometrical ratio of increase, and of the struggle for existence which thence inevitably follows.
Lamarck, once again, has established his principle that the sense of need is the main reason for variation, and he has also shown that the variations resulting from this are inherited, allowing divergences to build up and lead to the formation of species and genera. He is relatively unconcerned with the finer details. His work is clearly a broad overview. However, we have noted that he was[Pg 341] well aware of the effects of the geometric ratio of increase and the struggle for existence that naturally follows from it.
Mr. Darwin, on the other hand, comparatively indifferent to, or at any rate silent concerning the causes of those variations which appeared so all-important to Lamarck, inasmuch as they are the raindrops which unite to form the full stream of modification, goes into very full detail upon natural selection, or the survival of the fittest, and maintains it to have been "the most important but not the exclusive means of modification."[343]
Mr. Darwin, on the other hand, seems relatively unconcerned with, or at least quiet about, the reasons behind the variations that were so crucial to Lamarck, since they are the small changes that come together to create the bigger picture of evolution. He goes into great detail about natural selection, or the survival of the fittest, and argues that it has been "the most important but not the only means of modification." [343]
It will be readily seen that, according to Lamarck, the variations which when accumulated amount to specific and generic differences, will have been due to causes which have been mainly of the same kind for long periods together. Conditions of life change for the most part slowly, steadily, and in a set direction; as in the direction of steady, gradual increase or decrease of cold or moisture; of the steady, gradual increase of such and such an enemy, or decrease of such and such a kind of food; of the gradual upheaval or submergence of such and such a continent, and consequent drying up or encroachment of such and such a sea, and so forth. The thoughts of the creature varying will thus have been turned mainly in one direction for long together; and hence the consequent modifications will also be mainly in fixed and definite directions for many successive generations; as in the direction of a warmer or cooler covering; of a better means of defence[Pg 342] or of attack in relation to such and such another species; of a longer neck and longer legs, or of whatever other modification the gradually changing circumstances may be rendering expedient. It is easy to understand the accumulation of slight successive modifications which thus make their appearance in given organs and in a set direction.
It’s clear that, according to Lamarck, the variations that accumulate to create specific and general differences are primarily caused by factors that have been similar over long periods. Life conditions mostly change slowly, steadily, and in a specific direction; like a steady gradual increase or decrease in cold or moisture; the steady, gradual increase of certain predators or decrease in certain food sources; the gradual rise or sinking of specific continents, leading to the drying up or encroachment of particular seas, and so on. The creature’s thoughts will have mostly focused on one direction for a long time, resulting in corresponding modifications that will also generally follow fixed and definite paths over many generations; like developing warmer or cooler coverings; better means of defense or attack against other species; longer necks and legs, or other adaptations that the slowly changing circumstances may require. It’s easy to grasp how slight successive modifications accumulate in specific organs and a designated direction.
With Mr. Darwin, on the contrary, the variations being accidental, and due to no special and uniform cause, will not appear for any length of time in any given direction, nor in any given organ, but will be just as liable to appear in one organ as in another, and may be in one generation in one direction, and in another in another.
With Mr. Darwin, however, the variations are random and not caused by any specific or consistent factor, so they won't show up for any extended period in any particular direction or in any specific organ. Instead, they can just as easily occur in one organ as in another, and may appear in one generation going one way, and in the next generation going a different way.
In confirmation of the above, and in illustration of the important consequences that will follow according as we adopt the old or the more recent theory, I would quote the following from Mr. Mivart's 'Genesis of Species.'
In confirmation of the above, and to illustrate the important consequences that will follow depending on whether we adopt the old theory or the newer one, I would like to quote the following from Mr. Mivart's 'Genesis of Species.'
Shortly before maintaining that two similar structures have often been developed independently of one another, Mr. Mivart points out that if we are dependent upon indefinite variations only, as provided for us by Mr. Darwin, this would be "so improbable as to be practically impossible."[344] The number of possible variations being indefinitely great, "it is therefore an indefinitely great number to one against a similar series of variations occurring and being similarly preserved in any two independent instances." It will be felt (as Mr. Mivart presently insists) that this objection does[Pg 343] not apply to a system which maintains that in case an animal feels any given want it will gradually develop the structure which shall meet the want—that is to say, if the want be not so great and so sudden as to extinguish the creature to which it has become a necessity. For if there be such a power of self-adaptation as thus supposed, two or more very widely different animals feeling the same kind of want might easily adopt similar means to gratify it, and hence develop eventually a substantially similar structure; just as two men, without any kind of concert, have often hit upon like means of compassing the same ends. Mr. Spencer's theory—so Mr. Mivart tells us—and certainly that of Lamarck, whose disciple Mr. Spencer would appear to be,[345] admits "a certain peculiar, but limited power of response and adaptation in each animal and plant"—to the conditions of their existence. "Such theories," says Mr. Mivart, "have not to contend against the difficulty proposed, and it has been urged that even very complex extremely similar structures have again and again been developed quite independently one of the other, and this because the process has taken place not by merely haphazard, indefinite variations in all directions, but by the concurrence of some other internal natural law or laws co-operating with external influences and with Natural Selection in the evolution of organic forms.
Shortly before claiming that two similar structures have often developed independently from one another, Mr. Mivart points out that if we are relying solely on indefinite variations as explained by Mr. Darwin, this would be "so improbable as to be practically impossible."[344] Since the number of possible variations is indefinitely vast, "it is therefore an indefinitely great number to one against a similar series of variations occurring and being similarly preserved in any two independent instances." It will be understood (as Mr. Mivart soon asserts) that this objection does[Pg 343] not apply to a system suggesting that if an animal experiences a specific need, it will gradually develop the structure that satisfies that need—provided that the need is not so urgent and sudden that it overwhelms the creature for whom it has become essential. For if there exists such a capacity for self-adaptation as proposed, two or more very different animals experiencing the same type of need might easily adopt similar methods to fulfill it, thereby eventually developing a similar structure; just as two individuals, without any coordination, have often discovered similar ways to achieve the same goals. Mr. Spencer's theory—so Mr. Mivart tells us—and certainly that of Lamarck, whose follower Mr. Spencer seems to be,[345] acknowledges "a certain peculiar, but limited power of response and adaptation in each animal and plant"—to their environmental conditions. "Such theories," says Mr. Mivart, "do not face the difficulty mentioned, and it has been pointed out that even very complex and extremely similar structures have repeatedly developed completely independently of one another, and this is because the process has not occurred through random, indefinite variations in all directions, but through the interaction of some other internal natural laws working alongside external influences and Natural Selection in the evolution of living forms.
"It must never be forgotten that to admit any such constant operation of any such unknown natural cause is to deny the purely Darwinian theory which relies upon[Pg 344] the survival of the fittest by means of minute fortuitous indefinite variations.
We must always remember that accepting any ongoing effect from an unknown natural cause undermines the purely Darwinian theory, which is based on[Pg 344] the survival of the fittest through small, random, and indefinite variations.
"Among many other obligations which the author has to acknowledge to Professor Huxley, are the pointing out of this very difficulty, and the calling his attention to the striking resemblance between certain teeth of the dog, and of the thylacine, as one instance, and certain ornithic peculiarities of pterodactyles as another."[346]
"Among the many debts the author owes to Professor Huxley are highlighting this particular difficulty and drawing his attention to the remarkable similarity between certain teeth of the dog and those of the thylacine in one case, and certain bird-like features of pterodactyls in another."[346]
In brief then, changed distribution of use and disuse in consequence of changed conditions of the environment is with Lamarck the main cause of modification. According to Mr. Darwin natural selection, or the survival of favourable but accidental variations, is the most important means of modification. In a word, with Lamarck the variations are definite; with Mr. Darwin indefinite.
In short, according to Lamarck, the changed distribution of use and disuse due to changes in environmental conditions is the main cause of modification. Mr. Darwin, on the other hand, believes that natural selection, or the survival of beneficial but random variations, is the most important means of modification. To sum it up, for Lamarck, the variations are specific; for Mr. Darwin, they are not.
FOOTNOTES:
[333] Vol. ii. chap. i.
[337] 'Origin of Species,' p. 3.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 'Origin of Species,' p. 3.
[338] Ibid. p. 5.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 5.
[339] 'Origin of Species,' p. 8.
[340] Ibid. p. 9.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 9.
[341] Ibid. p. 158.
Ibid. p. 158.
[342] Ibid. p. 159.
Ibid. p. 159.
[343] 'Origin of Species,' p. 4.
NATURAL SELECTION CONSIDERED AS A MEANS OF MODIFICATION. THE CONFUSION WHICH THIS EXPRESSION OCCASIONS.
NATURAL SELECTION VIEWED AS A WAY OF CHANGE. THE CONFUSION THIS PHRASE CREATES.
When Mr. Darwin says that natural selection is the most important "means" of modification, I am not sure that I understand what he wishes to imply by the word "means." I do not see how the fact that those animals which are best fitted for the conditions of their existence commonly survive in the struggle for life, can be called in any special sense a "means" of modification.
When Mr. Darwin says that natural selection is the most important "means" of change, I'm not sure I understand what he means by the word "means." I don't see how the fact that animals best suited to their environment usually survive in the fight for life can be considered a specific "means" of change.
"Means" is a dangerous word; it slips too easily into "cause." We have seen Mr. Darwin himself say that Buffon did not enter on "the causes or means"[347] of modification, as though these two words were synonymous, or nearly so. Nevertheless, the use of the word "means" here enables Mr. Darwin to speak of Natural Selection as if it were an active cause (which he constantly does), and yet to avoid expressly maintaining that it is a cause of modification. This, indeed, he has not done in express terms, but he does it by implication when he writes, "Natural Selection might be most effective in giving the proper colour to each kind of[Pg 346] grouse, and in keeping that colour when once acquired." Such language, says the late Mr. G. H. Lewes, "is misleading;" it makes "selection an agent."[348]
"Means" is a tricky word; it easily turns into "cause." We’ve seen Mr. Darwin himself say that Buffon didn't touch on "the causes or means"[347] of modification, as if these two words were the same, or nearly so. Still, using the word "means" here lets Mr. Darwin talk about Natural Selection as if it were an active cause (which he often does), while avoiding the outright claim that it causes modification. He hasn’t done this explicitly, but he implies it when he writes, "Natural Selection might be most effective in giving the proper color to each type of[Pg 346] grouse, and in keeping that color once it’s acquired." Such language, according to the late Mr. G. H. Lewes, "is misleading;" it makes "selection an agent."[348]
It is plain that natural selection cannot be considered a cause of variation; and if not of variation, which is as the rain drop, then not of specific and generic modification, which are as the river; for the variations must make their appearance before they can be selected. Suppose that it is an advantage to a horse to have an especially hard and broad hoof, then a horse born with such a hoof will indeed probably survive in the struggle for existence, but he was not born with the larger and harder hoof because of his subsequently surviving. He survived because he was born fit—not, he was born fit because he survived. The variation must arise first and be preserved afterwards.
It's clear that natural selection can't be seen as a cause of variation; and if it doesn't cause variation, which is like a raindrop, then it also doesn't cause specific and generic changes, which are like a river. The variations need to appear before they can be selected. For example, if having a particularly hard and wide hoof benefits a horse, then a horse born with that kind of hoof will likely survive in the struggle for existence. But he wasn't born with the larger and harder hoof because he later survived. He survived because he was born well-suited—not he was born well-suited because he survived. The variation needs to occur first and then be preserved later.
Mr. Darwin therefore is in the following dilemma. If he does not treat natural selection as a cause of variation, the 'Origin of Species' will turn out to have no raison d'être. It will have professed to have explained to us the manner in which species has originated, but it will have left us in the dark concerning the origin of those variations which, when added together, amount to specific and generic differences. Thus, as I said in 'Life and Habit,' Mr. Darwin will have made us think we know the whole road, in spite of his having almost ostentatiously blindfolded us at every step in the journey. The 'Origin of Species' would thus prove to be no less a piece of intellectual sleight-of-hand than Paley's 'Natural Theology.'[Pg 347]
Mr. Darwin faces a dilemma. If he doesn’t consider natural selection as a source of variation, the 'Origin of Species' will lack a purpose. It would claim to explain how species originated but leave us confused about where those variations come from that, together, create specific and general differences. So, as I mentioned in 'Life and Habit,' Mr. Darwin would have made us believe we understand the entire process, even though he's essentially kept us in the dark at every turn. The 'Origin of Species' would thus be no different from Paley's 'Natural Theology' in terms of being an intellectual trick.[Pg 347]
If, on the other hand, Mr. Darwin maintains natural selection to be a cause of variation, this comes to saying that when an animal has varied in an advantageous direction, the fact of its subsequently surviving in the struggle for existence is the cause of its having varied in the advantageous direction—or more simply still—that the fact of its having varied is the cause of its having varied.
If, on the other hand, Mr. Darwin believes that natural selection is a reason for variation, it means that when an animal changes in a helpful way, the fact that it survives later in the competition for existence is what caused it to change in that helpful way—or even more straightforwardly—that the fact it changed is the reason it changed.
And this is what we have already seen Mr. Darwin actually to say, in a passage quoted near the beginning of this present book. When writing of the eye he says, "Variation will cause the slight alterations;"[349] but the "slight alterations" are the variations; so that Mr. Darwin's words come to this—that "variation will cause the variations."
And this is what we've already seen Mr. Darwin actually say in a passage quoted near the start of this book. When discussing the eye, he states, "Variation will cause the slight alterations;"[349] but the "slight alterations" are the variations; so that Mr. Darwin's words boil down to this—that "variation will cause the variations."
There does not seem any better way out of this dilemma than that which Mr. Darwin has adopted—namely, to hold out natural selection as "a means" of modification, and thenceforward to treat it as an efficient cause; but at the same time to protest again and again that it is not a cause. Accordingly he writes that "Natural Selection acts only by the preservation and accumulation of small inherited modifications,"[350]—that is to say, it has had no share in inducing or causing these modifications. Again, "What applies to one animal will apply throughout all time to all animals—that is, if they vary, for otherwise natural selection can effect nothing"[351]; and again, "for natural selection only takes advantage of such variations as[Pg 348] arise"[352]—the variations themselves arising, as we have just seen, from variation.
There doesn’t seem to be a better way out of this dilemma than the one Mr. Darwin has chosen—specifically, to present natural selection as "a means" of modification, and then to treat it as an effective cause; but at the same time, he insists repeatedly that it is not a cause. He writes that "Natural Selection acts only by the preservation and accumulation of small inherited modifications,"[350]—which means it has no role in causing or inducing these modifications. He also states, "What applies to one animal will apply throughout all time to all animals—that is, if they vary, for otherwise natural selection can effect nothing"[351]; and again, "for natural selection only takes advantage of such variations as[Pg 348] arise"[352]—the variations themselves arising, as we have just seen, from variation.
Nothing, then, can be clearer from these passages than that natural selection is not a cause of modification; while, on the other hand, nothing can be clearer, from a large number of such passages, as, for instance, "natural selection may be effective in giving and keeping colour,"[353] than that natural selection is an efficient cause; and in spite of its being expressly declared to be only a "means" of modification, it will be accepted as cause by the great majority of readers.
Nothing is clearer from these passages than that natural selection isn't a cause of change; however, it's also very clear from many passages, such as "natural selection may be effective in giving and keeping colour,"[353] that natural selection is an effective cause. Even though it's explicitly stated to be only a "means" of change, most readers will see it as a cause.
Mr. Darwin explains this apparent inconsistency thus:—He maintains that though the advantageous modification itself is fortuitous, or without known cause or principle underlying it, yet its becoming the predominant form of the species in which it appears is due to the fact that those animals which have been advantageously modified commonly survive in times of difficulty, while the unmodified individuals perish: offspring therefore is more frequently left by the favourably modified animal, and thus little by little the whole species will come to inherit the modification. Hence the survival of the fittest becomes a means of modification, though it is no cause of variation.
Mr. Darwin explains this apparent inconsistency like this: He argues that even though the advantageous changes happen by chance, without a known cause or principle behind them, their dominance in the species occurs because the animals that have these beneficial changes tend to survive during tough times, while those that don’t change often do not. As a result, the modified animals leave behind more offspring, and over time, the entire species will start to inherit these changes. Therefore, survival of the fittest acts as a way for modifications to spread, even though it doesn’t cause variations.
It will appear more clearly later on how much this amounts to. I will for the present content myself with the following quotation from the late Mr. G. H. Lewes in reference to it. Mr. Lewes writes:—
It will become clearer later how significant this is. For now, I'll just share a quote from the late Mr. G. H. Lewes about it. Mr. Lewes writes:—
"Mr. Darwin seems to imply that the external conditions which cause a variation are to be distinguished[Pg 349] from the conditions which accumulate and perfect such variation, that is to say, he implies a radical difference between the process of variation and the process of selection. This I have already said does not seem to me acceptable; the selection I conceive to be simply the variation which has survived."[354]
"Mr. Darwin seems to suggest that the external factors causing a variation should be distinguished[Pg 349] from the factors that build up and refine that variation. In other words, he indicates a fundamental difference between the process of variation and the process of selection. I have already mentioned that this doesn’t seem acceptable to me; I believe that selection is simply the variation that has survived."[354]
Certainly those animals and plants which are best fitted for their environment, or, as Lamarck calls it, "circonstances"—those animals, in fact, which are best fitted to comply with the conditions of their existence—are most likely to survive and transmit their especial fitness. No one would admit this more readily than Lamarck. This is no theory; it is a commonly observed fact in nature which no one will dispute, but it is not more "a means of modification" than many other commonly observed facts concerning animals.
Certainly, the animals and plants that are best suited to their environment, or, as Lamarck refers to it, "circumstances"—those animals that are most capable of adapting to their living conditions—are the ones most likely to survive and pass on their particular traits. No one would agree with this more readily than Lamarck. This isn't just a theory; it's a widely observed fact in nature that no one can dispute, but it's not any more "a means of modification" than many other widely recognized facts about animals.
Why is "the survival of the fittest" more a means of modification than, we will say, the fact that animals live at all, or that they live in successive generations, being born, continuing their species, and dying, instead of living on for ever as one single animal in the common acceptation of the term; or than that they eat and drink?
Why is "the survival of the fittest" more about adaptation than, let's say, the fact that animals exist at all, or that they live through generations, being born, continuing their species, and dying, instead of living forever as a single creature in the usual sense of the term; or that they eat and drink?
The heat whereby the water is heated, the water which is turned into steam, the piston on which the steam acts, the driving wheel, &c., &c., are all one as much as another a means whereby a train is made to go from one place to another; it is impossible to say that any one of them is the main means. So (mutatis mutandis) with modification. There is no reason therefore[Pg 350] why "the survival of the fittest" should claim to be an especial "means of modification" rather than any other necessary adjunct of animal or vegetable life.
The heat that warms the water, the water that turns into steam, the piston affected by the steam, the driving wheel, etc., are all equally important in making a train move from one place to another; it's impossible to pinpoint any single one as the most crucial. Similarly, with changes taken into account. There's no reason, therefore[Pg 350] why "the survival of the fittest" should be considered a special "means of modification" over any other essential aspect of animal or plant life.
I find that the late Mr. G. H. Lewes has insisted on this objection in his 'Physical Basis of Mind.' I observe, also, that in the very passage in which he does so, Mr. Lewes appears to have been misled by Mr. Darwin's use of that dangerous word "means," and, at the same time, by his frequent treatment of natural selection as though it were an active cause; so that Mr. Lewes supposes Mr. Darwin to have fallen into the very error of which, as I have above shown, he is evidently struggling to keep clear—namely, that of maintaining natural selection to be a "cause" of variation. Mr. Lewes then continues:—
I notice that the late Mr. G. H. Lewes has strongly emphasized this objection in his 'Physical Basis of Mind.' I also see that in the very section where he does this, Mr. Lewes seems to be misled by Mr. Darwin's use of the tricky word "means," and at the same time, by his frequent portrayal of natural selection as if it were an active cause. As a result, Mr. Lewes believes that Mr. Darwin has fallen into the exact mistake that, as I have pointed out earlier, he is clearly trying to avoid—specifically, the idea that natural selection is a "cause" of variation. Mr. Lewes then goes on:—
"He [Mr. Darwin] separates Natural Selection from all the primary causes of variation either internal or external—either as results of the laws of growth, of the correlations of variation, of use and disuse, &c., and limits it to the slow accumulation of such variations as are profitable in the struggle with competitors. And for his purpose this separation is necessary. But biological philosophy must, I think, regard the distinction as artificial, referring only to one of the great factors in the production of species."[355]
"He [Mr. Darwin] distinguishes Natural Selection from all the main causes of variation, whether they are internal or external—whether as results of growth laws, correlations of variation, the effects of use and disuse, etc.—and restricts it to the gradual buildup of variations that are advantageous in the competition for survival. This distinction is essential for his argument. However, I believe that biological philosophy should view this differentiation as artificial, referring only to one of the major factors in the emergence of species."[355]
The fact that one in a brood or litter is born fitter for the conditions of its existence than its brothers and sisters, and, again, the causes that have led to this one's having been born fitter—which last is what the older[Pg 351] evolutionists justly dwelt upon as the most interesting consideration in connection with the whole subject—are more noteworthy factors of modification than the factor that an animal, if born fitter for its conditions, will commonly survive longer in the struggle for existence. If the first of these can be explained in such a manner as to be accepted as true, or highly probable, we have a substantial gain to our knowledge. The second is little—if at all—better than a truism. Granted, if it were not generally the case that those forms are most likely to survive which are best fitted for the conditions of their existence, no adaptation of form to conditions of existence could ever have come about. "The survival of the fittest" therefore, or, perhaps better, "the fertility of the fittest," is thus a sine quâ non for modification. But, as we have just insisted, this does not render "the fertility of the fittest" an especial "means of modification," rather than any other sine quâ non for modification.
The fact that one in a group of offspring is born better suited to its environment than its siblings, and the reasons why this specific individual is better adapted—these are the aspects that older evolutionists focused on as the most intriguing part of the topic. These factors of modification are more significant than the idea that an animal born better suited to its environment will usually survive longer in the struggle for existence. If we can explain the first point in a way that is accepted as true or highly likely, we gain significant knowledge. The second point is hardly more than a simple truth. It's accepted that the forms most likely to survive are those best adapted to their environments; otherwise, adaptations wouldn’t occur. So, "the survival of the fittest," or maybe more accurately, "the fertility of the fittest," is essential for modification. However, as we've just emphasized, this doesn't mean that "the fertility of the fittest" is a unique way of achieving modification, just that it's one of the necessary conditions for it.
But, to look at the matter in another light. Mr. Darwin maintains natural selection to be "the most important but not the exclusive means of modification."
But, looking at it differently, Mr. Darwin argues that natural selection is "the most important but not the only means of modification."
For "natural selection" substitute the words "survival of the fittest," which we may do with Mr. Darwin's own consent abundantly given.
For "natural selection," use the phrase "survival of the fittest," which we can do with Mr. Darwin's full permission.
To the words "survival of the fittest" add what is elided, but what is, nevertheless, unquestionably as much implied as though it were said openly whenever these words are used, and without which "fittest" has no force—I mean, "for the conditions of their existence."
To the phrase "survival of the fittest," add what is left out but is still clearly implied whenever these words are used, and without which "fittest" has no meaning—I mean, "for the conditions of their existence."
We thus find that when Mr. Darwin says that natural[Pg 352] selection is the most important, but not exclusive means of modification, he means that the survival in the struggle for existence of those creatures which are best fitted to comply with the conditions of their existence is the most important, but not exclusive means whereby the descendants of a creature, we will say, A, have become modified, so as to be now represented by a creature, we will say, B.
We see that when Mr. Darwin says that natural[Pg 352] selection is the most important, but not the only way of change, he means that the survival of those beings best suited to their living conditions is the most important, but not the only means by which the descendants of a creature, let's call it A, have changed to become what we now refer to as a creature, let's call it B.
But the word "circonstances," so frequently used by Lamarck for the conditions of an animal's existence, contains, by implication, the idea of animals which shall exist or not according as they fulfil those conditions or fail to fulfil them. Conditions of existence are conditions which something capable of existing must fulfil if it would exist at all, and nothing is a condition of an animal's existence which that animal need not comply with and may yet continue to exist. Again, the words "animals" and "plants" comprehend the ideas of "fit," "fitter," and "fittest," "unfit," "unfitter," and "unfittest" for certain conditions, for we know of no animals or plants in which we do not observe degrees of fitness or unfitness for their "circonstances" or environment, or conditions of existence.
But the word "circonstances," which Lamarck often used to refer to the conditions of an animal's existence, implies that there are animals that will exist or not depending on whether they meet those conditions or fail to meet them. Conditions of existence are requirements that something capable of existing must meet in order to exist at all, and nothing can be considered a condition of an animal's existence if that animal doesn't have to meet it and can still exist. Additionally, the terms "animals" and "plants" include the concepts of "fit," "fitter," and "fittest," as well as "unfit," "unfitter," and "unfittest" for certain conditions. We observe that there are degrees of fitness or unfitness in all animals and plants regarding their "circonstances" or environment, or conditions for existence.
The use, therefore, of the term "conditions of existence" is sufficient to show that the person using it intends to imply that those animals and plants will live longest (or survive) and thrive best which are best able to fulfil those conditions. Hence it implies neither more nor less than what is implied by the words "struggle for existence, with consequent survival of the fittest"—that is to say, if we hold the complying[Pg 353] with any condition of life to which difficulty is attached to be part of "the struggle" for life, and this we should certainly do.
The term "conditions of existence" clearly indicates that the person using it means that the animals and plants that will live the longest (or survive) and thrive best are the ones that can best meet those conditions. This suggests exactly what is meant by "struggle for existence, leading to the survival of the fittest." In other words, if we consider meeting any challenging life condition to be part of "the struggle" for life, then we are definitely correct in doing so.
The words "conditions of existence" may, then, be used instead of the "struggle for existence with consequent survival of the fittest," for as they cannot imply any less than the "struggle, &c.," when they are set out in full, and without suppression, so neither do they imply more; for nothing is a condition of existence, in so far as its power of effecting the modification of any animal is concerned, which does not also involve more or less difficulty or struggle; for if there is no difficulty or struggle there will be nothing to bring about change of habit, and hence of structure. This identity of meaning may be also seen if we call to mind that the conditions of existence can be only a synonym for "the conditions of continuing to live," and "the conditions of continuing to live" a synonym for "the conditions of continuing to live a longer time," and "the conditions of continuing to live a longer time," for "the conditions of survival," and "the conditions of survival," for "the survival of the fittest," inasmuch as the being fittest is the condition of being the longest survivor.
The phrase "conditions of existence" can be used instead of the "struggle for existence with the resulting survival of the fittest," because when fully explained, it implies no less than the "struggle," and it doesn't imply more either; nothing can be a condition of existence concerning its ability to cause changes in any animal that doesn't also involve some degree of difficulty or struggle. If there's no difficulty or struggle, there won’t be anything to trigger changes in behavior, and therefore structure. This similarity in meaning is also clear if we remember that the conditions of existence are simply another way to say "the conditions for continuing to live," and "the conditions for continuing to live" can be thought of as synonymous with "the conditions for living longer," which in turn is synonymous with "the conditions for survival," and "the conditions for survival" relate to "the survival of the fittest," since being the fittest is what allows one to be the longest survivor.
But we have already seen that "the survival of the fittest," is, according to Mr. Darwin, a synonym for "natural selection"; hence it follows that "the conditions of existence" imply neither more nor less than what is implied by "natural selection" when this expression is properly explained, and may be used instead of it; so that when Mr. Darwin says that "natural selection" is the main but not exclusive means of modification,[Pg 354] he must mean, consciously or unconsciously, that "the conditions of existence" are the main but not exclusive means of modification. But this is only falling in with "the views and erroneous grounds of opinion," as Mr. Darwin briefly calls them, of Lamarck himself; a fact which Mr. Darwin's readers would have seen more readily if he had kept to the use of the words "survival of the fittest" instead of "natural selection." Of that expression Mr. Darwin says[356] that it is "more accurate" than natural selection, but naively adds, "and sometimes equally convenient."
But we've already seen that "the survival of the fittest" is, according to Mr. Darwin, another way of saying "natural selection"; therefore, it follows that "the conditions of existence" mean exactly what is meant by "natural selection" when this term is properly defined, and can be used in its place. So when Mr. Darwin states that "natural selection" is the primary but not the only means of change,[Pg 354] he must be implying, either consciously or unconsciously, that "the conditions of existence" are the primary but not the only means of change. However, this aligns with what Mr. Darwin refers to as "the views and erroneous grounds of opinion" of Lamarck himself; a point that Mr. Darwin's readers might have grasped more easily if he had stuck with the phrase "survival of the fittest" instead of "natural selection." Regarding that phrase, Mr. Darwin states[356] that it is "more accurate" than natural selection but somewhat amusingly adds, "and sometimes equally convenient."
I have said that there is a practical identity of meaning between "natural selection" and "the conditions of existence," when both expressions are fully extended. I say this, however, without prejudice to my right of maintaining that, of the two expressions, the one is accurate, lucid, and calculated to keep the thread of the argument well in sight of the reader, while the other is inaccurate, and always, if I may say so, less "convenient," as being always liable to lead the reader astray. Nor should it be lost sight of that Lamarck and Dr. Erasmus Darwin maintain that species and genera have arisen because animals can fashion themselves into accord with their conditions, so that, as Lamarck is so continually insisting, the action of the conditions is indirect only—changed use and disuse being the direct causes; while, according to Mr. Darwin, it is natural selection itself (which, as we have seen, is but another way of saying conditions of existence) that is the most important means of modification.[Pg 355]
I have stated that "natural selection" and "the conditions of existence" essentially mean the same thing when you consider both terms fully. However, I assert this without losing my right to argue that one of these terms is precise, clear, and helpful in keeping the reader focused on the main argument, while the other is inaccurate and tends to mislead the reader. It's also important to note that Lamarck and Dr. Erasmus Darwin argue that species and genera have developed because animals can adapt to their environments, so that, as Lamarck frequently emphasizes, the influence of conditions is only indirect—changes in use and disuse being the direct causes; whereas, according to Mr. Darwin, it is natural selection itself (which, as we've noted, is just another way of referring to the conditions of existence) that is the key factor in modification.[Pg 355]
The identity of meaning above insisted on was, on the face of it, almost as obscure as that between "evêque and bishop." Yet we know that "evêque" is "episc" and "bishop" "piscop," and that "episcopus" is the Latin for bishop; the words, therefore, are really one and the same, in spite of the difference in their appearance. I think I can show, moreover, that Mr. Darwin himself holds natural selection and the conditions of existence to be one and the same thing. For he writes, "in one sense," and it is hard to see any sense but one in what follows, "the conditions of life may be said not only to cause variability" (so that here Mr. Darwin appears to support Lamarck's main thesis) "either directly or indirectly, but likewise to include natural selection; for the conditions determine whether this or that variety shall survive."[357] But later on we find that "the expression of conditions of existence, so often insisted upon by the illustrious Cuvier" (and surely also by the illustrious Lamarck, though he calls them "circonstances") "is fully embraced by the principle of natural selection."[358] So we see that the conditions of life "include" natural selection, and yet the conditions of existence "are fully embraced by" natural selection, which, I take it, is an enigmatic way of saying that they are one and the same thing, for it is not until two bodies absolutely coincide and occupy the same space that the one can be said both to include and to be embraced by the other.
The identity of the meaning insisted upon above was, at first glance, nearly as unclear as the difference between "evêque and bishop." However, we know that "evêque" translates to "episc" and "bishop" to "piscop," and that "episcopus" is the Latin term for bishop; thus, these words are essentially identical, despite their different appearances. I believe I can demonstrate that Mr. Darwin himself considers natural selection and the conditions of existence to be the same. He writes, "in one sense," and it's difficult to interpret his following statements in any way other than this, "the conditions of life may be said not only to cause variability" (which suggests that Mr. Darwin supports Lamarck's main point) "either directly or indirectly, but also to include natural selection; for the conditions determine whether this or that variety shall survive."[357] Later, we see that "the expression of conditions of existence, so often emphasized by the renowned Cuvier" (and surely also by the renowned Lamarck, though he calls them "circonstances") "is fully included by the principle of natural selection."[358] Therefore, we observe that the conditions of life "include" natural selection, and yet the conditions of existence "are fully embraced by" natural selection, which, I take to mean, is a complex way of stating that they are the same thing, as it is only when two entities completely coincide and occupy the same space that one can be said to both include and be embraced by the other.
The difficulty, again, of understanding Mr. Darwin's meaning is enhanced by his repeatedly writing of[Pg 356] "natural selection," or the fact that the fittest survive in the struggle for existence, as though it were the same thing as "evolution" or the descent, through the accumulation of small modifications in many successive generations, of one species from another and different one. In the concluding and recapitulatory chapter of the 'Origin of Species,' he writes:—
The challenge of grasping Mr. Darwin's meaning is complicated by his frequent references to[Pg 356] "natural selection," or the idea that the strongest survive in the fight for existence, as if it's the same as "evolution" or the process of one species gradually changing into another over many generations through small modifications. In the final and summarizing chapter of the 'Origin of Species,' he writes:—
"Turning to geographical distribution, the difficulties encountered on the theory of descent with modification are serious enough;"[359] and in the next paragraph, "As, according to the theory of natural selection, &c.," the context showing that in each case descent with modification is intended.
"Looking at geographical distribution, the challenges faced on the theory of descent with modification are quite significant;"[359] and in the following paragraph, "As, according to the theory of natural selection, &c.," the context makes it clear that in each instance descent with modification is intended.
Again:—
Again:—
"On the theory of the natural selection of successive, slight, but profitable, modifications,"[360] that is to say, on the theory of the survival of the fittest; while on the next page we find "the theory of descent with modification," and "the principle of natural selection," used as though they were convertible terms.
"On the idea of natural selection of gradual, small, but beneficial changes,"[360] meaning, on the concept of the survival of the fittest; while on the following page we see "the theory of descent with modification," and "the principle of natural selection," treated as if they were the same thing.
Again:—
Again:—
"The existence of closely allied or representative species in any two areas implies, on the theory of descent with modification, &c.;"[361] and, in the next paragraph, "the theory of natural selection, with its contingencies of extinction and divergence of character," is substituted as though the two expressions were identical.
"The presence of similar or representative species in any two regions suggests, based on the theory of descent with modification, etc.;"[361] and, in the following paragraph, "the theory of natural selection, along with the risks of extinction and variation in traits," is used interchangeably as if the two concepts were the same.
This is calculated to mislead. Independently of the fact that "natural selection," or "the survival of the[Pg 357] fittest," is in no sense a theory, but simply an observed fact, yet even if the words are allowed to stand for "descent with modification by means of natural selection," it is still misleading to write as though this were synonymous with "the theory of evolution," or "the theory of descent with modification." To do this prevents the reader from bearing in mind that "evolution by means of the circumstance-suiting power of plants and animals" as advanced by the earlier evolutionists; and "evolution by means of lucky accidents" with comparatively little circumstance-suiting power, are two very different things, of which the one may be true and the other untrue. It leads the reader to forget that evolution by no means stands or falls with evolution by means of natural selection, and makes him think that if he accepts evolution at all, he is bound to Mr. Darwin's view of it. Hence, when he falls in with such writers as Professor Mivart and the Rev. J. J. Murphy, who show, and very plainly, that the survival of the fittest, unsupplemented by something which shall give a definite aim to the variations which successively occur, fails to account for the coadaptations of need and structure, he imagines that evolution has much less to say for itself than it really has. If Mr. Darwin, instead of taking the line which he has thought fit to adopt towards Buffon, Dr. Erasmus Darwin, Lamarck, and the author of the 'Vestiges,' had shown us what these men taught, why they taught it, wherein they were wrong, and how he proposed to set them right, he would have taken a course at once more agreeable with ordinary practice, and more likely[Pg 358] to clear misconception from his own mind and from those of his readers.
This is designed to mislead. Apart from the fact that "natural selection," or "the survival of the fittest," is not a theory but just an observed fact, even if we accept the phrase as meaning "descent with modification through natural selection," it's still misleading to suggest that this is the same as "the theory of evolution" or "the theory of descent with modification." Doing so prevents the reader from recognizing that "evolution through the adaptable abilities of plants and animals," as proposed by earlier evolutionists, and "evolution through random accidents" with relatively little adaptability are two very different ideas, where one can be true and the other false. It leads the reader to forget that evolution doesn't solely depend on evolution through natural selection, making them think that accepting evolution means they have to agree with Mr. Darwin's perspective on it. Therefore, when they encounter writers like Professor Mivart and the Rev. J. J. Murphy, who clearly argue that the survival of the fittest, without something to give a clear purpose to the variations that happen, fails to explain the adaptations of needs and structures, they might believe that evolution has much less validity than it actually does. If Mr. Darwin, instead of taking his chosen approach towards Buffon, Dr. Erasmus Darwin, Lamarck, and the author of the 'Vestiges,' had explained what these individuals theorized, why they held their views, where they were mistaken, and how he intended to correct them, he would have taken a path that was not only more in line with typical practice but also more likely to clear up misconceptions for himself and his readers.
Mr. Darwin says,[362] "it is easy to hide our ignorance under such expressions as 'the plan of creation' and 'unity of design.'" Surely, also, it is easy to hide want of precision of thought, and the absence of any fundamental difference between his own main conclusion and that of Dr. Darwin and Lamarck whom he condemns, under the term "natural selection."
Mr. Darwin says,[362] "it’s easy to mask our ignorance with phrases like 'the plan of creation' and 'unity of design.'" It's also quite easy to cover up a lack of clear thinking and the absence of any real difference between his main conclusion and those of Dr. Darwin and Lamarck, whom he criticizes, by using the term "natural selection."
I assure the reader that I find the task of forming a clear, well-defined conception of Mr. Darwin's meaning, as expressed in his 'Origin of Species,' comparable only to that of one who has to act on the advice of a lawyer who has obscured the main issue as far as he can, and whose chief aim has been to make as many loopholes as possible for himself to escape through in case of his being called to account. Or, again, to that of one who has to construe an Act of Parliament which was originally framed so as to throw dust in the eyes of those who would oppose the measure, and which, having been since found unworkable, has had clauses repealed and inserted up and down it, till it is in an inextricable tangle of confusion and contradiction.
I assure the reader that trying to form a clear, well-defined understanding of Mr. Darwin's meaning in his 'Origin of Species' is like dealing with a lawyer who has muddled the main issue as much as possible, just to create as many escape routes for himself if he gets called to explain. It's also like trying to interpret a law that was originally designed to mislead those who would oppose it, and which, after being found unworkable, has had clauses removed and added in such a way that it has become a complete mess of confusion and contradiction.
As an example of my meaning, I will quote a passage to which I called attention in 'Life and Habit.' It runs:—
As an example of what I mean, I’ll quote a passage that I pointed out in 'Life and Habit.' It says:—
"In the earlier editions of this work I underrated, as now seems probable, the frequency and importance of modifications due to spontaneous variability. But it is impossible to attribute to this cause" (i. e. spontaneous[Pg 359] variability, which is itself only an expression for unknown causes) "the innumerable structures which are so well adapted to the habits of life of each species. I can no more believe in this" (i. e. that the innumerable structures, &c., can be due to unknown causes) "than that the well adapted form of a racehorse or greyhound, which, before the principle of selection by man was well understood, excited so much surprise in the minds of the older naturalists, can thus" (i. e. by attributing them to unknown causes) "be explained."[363]
"In the earlier editions of this work, I underestimated, as now seems likely, the frequency and significance of changes caused by spontaneous variability. However, it's impossible to attribute to this cause" (i.e., spontaneous[Pg 359] variability, which is just a term for unknown causes) "the countless structures that are so well suited to the lifestyles of each species. I cannot believe that this" (i.e., that these countless structures, etc., can be attributed to unknown causes) "is true any more than I can believe that the well-suited form of a racehorse or greyhound, which, before the principle of selection by humans was fully understood, surprised earlier naturalists, can thus" (i.e., by linking them to unknown causes) "be explained."[363]
This amounts to saying that unknown causes can do so much, but cannot do so much more. On this passage I wrote, in 'Life and Habit':—
This means that unknown causes can have a significant impact, but their influence has limits. In this section, I wrote in 'Life and Habit':—
"It is impossible to believe that, after years of reflection upon his subject, Mr. Darwin should have written as above, especially in such a place, if his mind was clear about his own position. Immediately after the admission of a certain amount of miscalculation there comes a more or less exculpatory sentence, which sounds so right that ninety-nine people out of a hundred would walk through it, unless led by some exigency of their own position to examine it closely, but which yet, upon examination, proves to be as nearly meaningless as a sentence can be."[364]
"It’s hard to believe that, after years of thinking about his topic, Mr. Darwin would have written like this, especially in such a prominent place, if he was clear about his own stance. Right after he admits to a certain level of miscalculation, there’s a more or less justifying statement that sounds so correct that ninety-nine out of a hundred people wouldn’t think twice about it unless they were pushed by their own situation to examine it closely, but which, upon closer inspection, turns out to be nearly meaningless."[364]
No one, to my knowledge, has impugned the justice of this criticism, and I may say that further study of Mr. Darwin's works has only strengthened my conviction of the confusion and inaccuracy of thought, which detracts so greatly from their value.[Pg 360]
No one, as far as I know, has challenged the fairness of this criticism, and I can say that looking more closely at Mr. Darwin's works has only reinforced my belief in the confusion and inaccuracy in his thinking, which significantly reduces their value.[Pg 360]
So little is it generally understood that "evolution" and what is called "Darwinism" convey indeed the same main conclusion, but that this conclusion has been reached by two distinct roads, one of which is impregnable, while the other has already fallen into the hands of the enemy, that in the last November number of the 'Nineteenth Century' Professor Tyndall, while referring to descent with modification or evolution, speaks of it as though it were one and inseparable from Mr. Darwin's theory that it has come about mainly by means of natural selection. He writes:—
So little is generally understood that "evolution" and what we call "Darwinism" actually convey the same main conclusion, but this conclusion has been reached through two different paths, one of which is solid, while the other has already been taken over by critics. In the November issue of the 'Nineteenth Century,' Professor Tyndall, while discussing descent with modification or evolution, treats it as if it’s one and the same with Mr. Darwin's theory that it mainly happens through natural selection. He writes:—
"Darwin's theory, as pointed out nine or ten years ago by Helmholtz and Hooker, was then exactly in this condition of growth; and had they to speak of the subject to-day they would be able to announce an enormous strengthening of the theoretic fibre. Fissures in continuity which then existed, and which left little hope of being ever spanned, have been since bridged over, so that the further the theory is tested the more fully does it harmonize with progressive experience and discovery. We shall never probably fill all the gaps; but this will not prevent a profound belief in the truth of the theory from taking root in the general mind. Much less will it justify a total denial of the theory. The man of science, who assumes in such a case the position of a denier, is sure to be stranded and isolated."
"Darwin's theory, as noted nine or ten years ago by Helmholtz and Hooker, was in a state of development then; and if they were to discuss the topic today, they could announce a significant strengthening of the theoretical framework. Gaps in continuity that existed at the time, which seemed unlikely to ever be bridged, have since been connected, so that the more the theory is examined, the more it aligns with ongoing experience and discovery. We may never completely fill all the gaps; however, this will not stop a deep belief in the validity of the theory from taking hold in the general consciousness. It certainly won't justify a complete rejection of the theory. A scientist who takes the stance of a denier in such a case is bound to end up stranded and isolated."
This is in the true vein of the professional and orthodox scientist; of that new orthodoxy which is clamouring for endowment, and which would step into the Pope's shoes to-morrow, if we would only let it. If[Pg 361] Professor Tyndall means that those who deny evolution will find themselves presently in a very small minority, I agree with him; but if he means that evolution is Mr. Darwin's theory, and that he who rejects what Mr. Darwin calls "the theory of natural selection" will find himself stranded, his assertion will pass muster with those only who know little of the history and literature of evolution.
This reflects the mindset of the professional and traditional scientist; of that new orthodoxy that is demanding funding and would take the Pope's place tomorrow if we allowed it. If[Pg 361] Professor Tyndall means that those who reject evolution will soon become a very small minority, I agree with him; but if he implies that evolution is just Mr. Darwin's theory, and that anyone who dismisses what Mr. Darwin calls "the theory of natural selection" will find themselves isolated, his claim will only be accepted by those who know little about the history and literature of evolution.
FOOTNOTES:
[349] 'Origin of Species,' p. 146.
'Origin of Species,' p. 146.
[350] Ibid. p. 75.
Ibid. p. 75.
[351] Ibid. p. 88.
Ibid. p. 88.
[352] 'Origin of Species,' p. 98.
'Origin of Species,' p. 98.
[353] Ibid. p. 66.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 66.
[356] 'Origin of Species,' p. 49.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 'Origin of Species,' p. 49.
[357] 'Origin of Species,' p. 107.
[358] Ibid. p. 166.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source, p. 166.
[359] 'Origin of Species,' p. 406.
[360] Ibid, p. 416.
Ibid, p. 416.
[361] Ibid. p. 419.
[362] 'Origin of Species,' p. 422.
[364] 'Life and Habit,' p. 260.
'Life and Habit,' p. 260.
MR. DARWIN'S DEFENCE OF THE EXPRESSION, NATURAL SELECTION—PROFESSOR MIVART AND NATURAL SELECTION.
MR. DARWIN'S DEFENSE OF THE TERM, NATURAL SELECTION—PROFESSOR MIVART AND NATURAL SELECTION.
So important is it that we should come to a clear understanding upon the positions taken by Mr. Darwin and Lamarck respectively, that at the risk of wearying the reader I will endeavour to exhaust this subject here. In order to do so, I will follow Mr. Darwin's answer to those who have objected to the expression, "natural selection."
So important is it that we come to a clear understanding of the positions taken by Mr. Darwin and Lamarck that, even if it risks boring the reader, I will try to cover this topic thoroughly here. To do this, I will follow Mr. Darwin's response to those who have criticized the term "natural selection."
Mr. Darwin says:—
Mr. Darwin says:—
"Several writers have misapprehended or objected to the term 'natural selection.' Some have even imagined that natural selection induces variability."[365]
"Many writers have misunderstood or disagreed with the term 'natural selection.' Some have even thought that natural selection causes variability."[365]
And small wonder if they have; but those who have fallen into this error are hardly worth considering. The true complaint is that Mr. Darwin has too often written of "natural selection" as though it does induce variability, and that his language concerning it is so confusing that the reader is not helped to see that it really comes to nothing but a cloak of difference from his predecessors, under which there lurks a concealed[Pg 363] identity of opinion as to the main facts. The reader is thus led to look upon it as something positive and special, and, in spite of Mr. Darwin's disclaimer, to think of it as an actively efficient cause.
And it's no surprise if they have; but those who have made this mistake aren't worth considering. The real issue is that Mr. Darwin has too often talked about "natural selection" as if it actually causes variability, and his wording is so unclear that readers struggle to understand that it really amounts to nothing more than a mask of difference from his predecessors, behind which hides a hidden[Pg 363] agreement about the main facts. As a result, readers are led to see it as something concrete and unique, and despite Mr. Darwin's denial, they end up viewing it as an actively effective cause.
Few will deny that this complaint is a just one, or that ninety-nine out of a hundred readers of average intelligence, if asked, after reading Mr. Darwin's 'Origin of Species,' what was the most important cause of modification, would answer "natural selection." Let the same readers have read the 'Zoonomia' of Dr. Erasmus Darwin, or the 'Philosophie Zoologique' of Lamarck, and they would at once reply, "the wishes of an animal or plant, as varying with its varying conditions," or more briefly, "sense of need."
Few would argue that this complaint is fair, or that ninety-nine out of a hundred average readers, if asked what they think is the most important factor in change after reading Mr. Darwin’s 'Origin of Species,' would respond with "natural selection." If the same readers had also read Dr. Erasmus Darwin’s 'Zoonomia' or Lamarck’s 'Philosophie Zoologique,' they would quickly say, "the desires of an animal or plant, which change with its changing conditions," or more simply, "sense of need."
"Whereas," continues Mr. Darwin, "it" (natural selection) "implies only the preservation of such variations as arise, and are beneficial to the being under its conditions of life. No one objects to agriculturists speaking of the potent effects of man's selection."
"Whereas," continues Mr. Darwin, "it" (natural selection) "only involves the preservation of beneficial variations that occur and help the organism survive in its environment. No one disagrees with farmers discussing the powerful impact of human selection."
Of course not; for there is an actual creature man, who actually does select with a set purpose in order to produce such and such a result, which result he presently produces.
Of course not; because there is a real being called man, who actually chooses with a specific intent to achieve a certain outcome, which he currently creates.
"And in this case the individual differences given by nature, which man for some object selects, must first occur."
"And in this case, the individual differences provided by nature, which a person chooses for some purpose, must first exist."
This shows that the complaint has already reached Mr. Darwin, that in not showing us how "the individual differences first occur," he is really leaving us absolutely in the dark as to the cause of all modification—giving us an 'Origin of Species' with "the origin" cut[Pg 364] out; but I do not think that any reader who has not been compelled to go somewhat deeply into the question would find out that this is the real gist of the objection which Mr. Darwin is appearing to combat. A general impression is left upon the reader that some very foolish objectors are being put to silence, that Mr. Darwin is the most candid literary opponent in the world, and as just as Aristides himself; but if the unassisted reader will cross-question himself what it is all about, I shall be much surprised if he is ready with his answer.
This shows that Mr. Darwin is aware of the complaint, and by not explaining how "individual differences first occur," he is really leaving us completely in the dark about the cause of all modification—presenting us with an 'Origin of Species' with "the origin" cut[Pg 364] out. However, I doubt that any reader who hasn't delved somewhat deeply into the issue would realize that this is the core of the objection Mr. Darwin seems to be addressing. A general impression is left that some very unreasonable critics are being silenced, and that Mr. Darwin is the most honest literary opponent in the world, as just as Aristides himself; but if the average reader reflects on what it's all about, I would be quite surprised if they have a ready answer.
"Others"—to resume our criticism on Mr. Darwin's defence—"have objected that the term implies conscious choice in the animals which become modified, and it has been even urged that as plants have no volition, natural selection is not applicable to them!"
"Others"—to continue our critique of Mr. Darwin's defense—"have argued that the term suggests deliberate choice in the animals that undergo modification, and it has even been claimed that since plants lack will, natural selection doesn't apply to them!"
This—unfortunately—must have been the objection of a slovenly, or wilfully misapprehending reader, and was unworthy of serious notice. But its introduction here tends to draw the reader from the true ground of complaint, which is that at the end of Mr. Darwin's book we stand much in the same place as we did when we started, as regards any knowledge of what is the "origin of species."
This—unfortunately—was probably the criticism of a careless or willfully misunderstanding reader, and it wasn't worth serious attention. But bringing it up here distracts from the real issue, which is that by the end of Mr. Darwin's book, we find ourselves in pretty much the same position as we were at the beginning in terms of understanding the "origin of species."
"In the literal sense of the word, no doubt, natural selection is a false term."
"In the strict sense of the term, it's clear that natural selection is a misleading phrase."
Then why use it when another, and, by Mr. Darwin's own admission, a "more accurate" one is to hand in "the survival of the fittest"?[366] This term is not appreciably longer than natural selection. Mr. Darwin may[Pg 365] say, indeed, that it is "sometimes" as convenient a term as natural selection; but the kind of men who exercise permanent effect upon the opinions of other people will bid such a passage as this stand aside somewhat sternly. If a term is not appreciably longer than another, and if at the same time it more accurately expresses the idea which is intended to be conveyed, it is not sometimes only, but always, more convenient, and should immediately be substituted for the less accurate one.
Then why use it when another term, which Mr. Darwin himself says is "more accurate," is available in "the survival of the fittest"?[366] This term isn't significantly longer than natural selection. Mr. Darwin might say that it is "sometimes" as convenient as natural selection; however, those who have a lasting impact on the opinions of others will view such a comment rather critically. If a term isn’t much longer than another and at the same time expresses the intended idea more accurately, it’s not just sometimes but always more convenient, and should be used to replace the less accurate term right away.
No one complains of the use of what is, strictly speaking, an inaccurate expression, when it is nevertheless the best that we can get. It may be doubted whether there is any such thing possible as a perfectly accurate expression. All words that are not simply names of things are apt to turn out little else than compendious false analogies; but we have a right to complain when a writer tells us that he is using a less accurate expression when a more accurate one is ready to his hand. Hence, when Mr. Darwin continues, "Who ever objected to chemists speaking of the elective affinities of the various elements? and yet an acid cannot strictly be said to elect the base with which it by preference combines," he is beside the mark. Chemists do not speak of "elective affinities" in spite of there being a more accurate and not appreciably longer expression at their disposal.
No one really complains about using what is technically an inaccurate term when it’s still the best option we have. It's debatable whether a perfectly accurate expression is even possible. Most words that go beyond simple naming tend to be little more than misleading analogies. However, we can justifiably complain when a writer tells us they’re opting for a less accurate term when a more precise one is available. So, when Mr. Darwin says, "Who ever objected to chemists speaking of the elective affinities of the various elements? And yet, an acid cannot strictly be said to elect the base with which it by preference combines," he misses the point. Chemists don’t use "elective affinities" when a more accurate and not significantly longer term is at their disposal.
"It has been said," continues Mr. Darwin, "that I speak of natural selection as an active power or deity. But who objects to an author speaking of the attraction of gravity? Everyone knows what is meant and implied[Pg 366] by such metaphorical expressions, and they are almost necessary for brevity."
"It’s been said," Mr. Darwin goes on, "that I talk about natural selection as if it's an active force or a god. But who complains when an author refers to gravity’s pull? Everyone understands what is meant and suggested by such figurative language, and they’re almost essential for being concise."
Mr. Darwin certainly does speak of natural selection "acting," "accumulating," "operating"; and if "every-one knew what was meant and implied by this metaphorical expression," as they now do, or think they do, in the case of the attraction of gravity, there might be less ground of complaint; but the expression was known to very few at the time Mr. Darwin introduced it, and was used with so much ambiguity, and with so little to protect the reader from falling into the error of supposing that it was the cause of the modifications which we see around us, that we had a just right to complain, even in the first instance; much more should we do so on the score of the retention of the expression when a more accurate one had been found.
Mr. Darwin definitely talks about natural selection "acting," "accumulating," and "operating"; and if "everyone knew what was meant and implied by this metaphorical expression," as they think they do now with the concept of gravity, there might be fewer reasons to complain. However, at the time Mr. Darwin introduced this term, very few people understood it, and it was used with so much ambiguity, leaving little to stop the reader from thinking it caused the changes we observe around us. We had every right to complain back then, and we have even more reason to do so now, especially since a more accurate term has been found.
If the "survival of the fittest" had been used, to the total excision of "natural selection" from every page in Mr. Darwin's book—it would have been easily seen that "the survival of the fittest" is no more a cause of modification, and hence can give no more explanation concerning the origin of species, than the fact of a number of competitors in a race failing to run the whole course, or to run it as quickly as the winner, can explain how the winner came to have good legs and lungs. According to Lamarck, the winner will have got these by means of sense of need, and consequent practice and training, on his own part, and on that of his forefathers; according to Mr. Darwin, the "most important means" of his getting them is his "happening" to be born with them, coupled, with the fact that his uncles and aunts for[Pg 367] many generations could not run so well as his ancestors in the direct line. But can the fact of his uncles and aunts running less well than his fathers and mothers be a means of his fathers and mothers coming to run better than they used to run?
If "survival of the fittest" had been used, completely eliminating "natural selection" from every page in Mr. Darwin's book—it would have been clear that "survival of the fittest" isn’t any more a cause of change, and therefore can’t explain the origin of species, than the fact that a number of competitors in a race didn’t finish the race or run as fast as the winner can explain how the winner ended up having good legs and lungs. According to Lamarck, the winner got those traits through a sense of need and consistent practice and training, both on his part and that of his ancestors; according to Mr. Darwin, the "most important means" of getting them is just that he "happened" to be born with them, along with the fact that his aunts and uncles for[Pg 367] many generations weren’t as fast as his direct ancestors. But can the fact that his aunts and uncles ran slower than his parents really explain how his parents became better runners than they used to be?
If the reader will bear in mind the idea of the runners in a race, it will help him to see the point at issue between Mr. Darwin and Lamarck. Perhaps also the double meaning of the word race, as expressing equally a breed and a competition, may not be wholly without significance. What we want to be told is, not that a runner will win the prize if he can run "ever such a little" faster than his fellows—we know this—but by what process he comes to be able to run ever such a little faster.
If the reader keeps in mind the concept of runners in a race, it will help them understand the disagreement between Mr. Darwin and Lamarck. The dual meaning of the word race, representing both a breed and a competition, might also hold some significance. What we want to know is not that a runner will win the prize if he can run just a little faster than his peers—we already know that—but rather how he becomes able to run just a little faster.
"So, again," continues Mr. Darwin, "it is difficult to avoid personifying nature, but I mean by nature only the aggregate action and product of many natural laws, and by laws the sequence of events as ascertained by us."
"Once more," Mr. Darwin goes on, "it's hard to not give nature human traits, but when I say nature, I only mean the combined effects and results of various natural laws, and by laws, I mean the order of events as we have discovered."
This, again, is raising up a dead man in order to knock him down. Nature has been personified for more than two thousand years, and every one understands that nature is no more really a woman than hope or justice, or than God is like the pictures of the mediæval painters; no one whose objection was worth notice could have objected to the personification of nature.
This is once again bringing a dead man back to life just to take him down. Nature has been personified for over two thousand years, and everyone understands that nature isn't really a woman any more than hope or justice is, or than God is like the images created by medieval artists; no one with a valid objection could have opposed the personification of nature.
Mr. Darwin concludes:—
Mr. Darwin concludes:—
"With a little familiarity, such superficial objections will be forgotten."[367]
"With a bit of familiarity, those shallow objections will be forgotten."[367]
[Pg 368]As a matter of fact, I do not see any greater tendency to acquiesce in Mr. Darwin's claim on behalf of natural selection than there was a few years ago, but on the contrary, that discontent is daily growing. To say nothing of the Rev. J. J. Murphy and Professor Mivart, the late Mr. G. H. Lewes did not find the objection a superficial one, nor yet did he find it disappear "with a little familiarity"; on the contrary, the more familiar he became with it the less he appeared to like it. I may even go, without fear, so far as to say that any writer who now uses the expression "natural selection," writes himself down thereby as behind the age. It is with great pleasure that I observe Mr. Francis Darwin in his recent lecture[368] to have kept clear of it altogether, and to have made use of no expression, and advocated no doctrine to which either Dr. Erasmus Darwin or Lamarck would not have readily assented. I think I may affirm confidently that a few years ago any such lecture would have contained repeated reference to Natural Selection. For my own part I know of few passages in any theological writer which please me less than the one which I have above followed sentence by sentence. I know of few which should better serve to show us the sort of danger we should run if we were to let men of science get the upper hand of us.
[Pg 368]In fact, I don't see any greater tendency to accept Mr. Darwin's claims about natural selection than there was a few years ago; on the contrary, that discontent seems to be increasing every day. Not to mention Rev. J. J. Murphy and Professor Mivart, the late Mr. G. H. Lewes didn’t find the objection trivial, nor did he find it go away "with a little familiarity"; in fact, the more he got to know it, the less he seemed to like it. I can confidently say that any writer who currently uses the term "natural selection" shows themselves to be out of touch. I’m pleased to see that Mr. Francis Darwin, in his recent lecture[368], completely avoided it and used no terminology or supported no theories that either Dr. Erasmus Darwin or Lamarck wouldn’t have accepted. I can assert confidently that just a few years ago, any such lecture would have made frequent references to Natural Selection. Personally, I know of few passages from any theological writer that bother me more than the one I have just dissected sentence by sentence. There are few that illustrate better the kind of danger we would face if we allowed scientists to take control over us.
Natural Selection, then, is only another way of saying "Nature." Mr. Darwin seems to be aware of this when he writes, "Nature, if I may be allowed to personify the natural preservation or survival of the[Pg 369] fittest." And again, at the bottom of the same page, "It may metaphorically be said that natural selection is daily and hourly scrutinizing throughout the world the slightest variations."[369] It may be metaphorically said that Nature is daily and hourly scrutinizing, but it cannot be said consistently with any right use of words, metaphorical or otherwise, that natural selection scrutinizes, unless natural selection is merely a somewhat cumbrous synonym for Nature. When, therefore, Mr. Darwin says that natural selection is the "most important, but not the exclusive means" whereby any modification has been effected, he is really saying that Nature is the most important means of modification—which is only another way of telling us that variation causes variations, and is all very true as far as it goes.
Natural Selection is just another way of saying "Nature." Mr. Darwin seems to recognize this when he writes, "Nature, if I may be allowed to personify the natural preservation or survival of the[Pg 369] fittest." And again, at the bottom of the same page, "It may metaphorically be said that natural selection is daily and hourly scrutinizing throughout the world the slightest variations."[369] It can be metaphorically said that Nature is continually scrutinizing, but it wouldn’t be correct to say that natural selection scrutinizes, unless natural selection is just a bit of a clumsy synonym for Nature. So, when Mr. Darwin states that natural selection is the "most important, but not the exclusive means" by which any modifications occur, he is really saying that Nature is the most important means of modification—which is essentially another way of telling us that variation leads to variations, and that’s true as far as it goes.
I did not read Professor Mivart's 'Lessons from Nature,' until I had written all my own criticism on Mr. Darwin's position. From that work, however, I now quote the following:—
I didn't read Professor Mivart's 'Lessons from Nature' until I had finished all my own critiques on Mr. Darwin's views. However, from that work, I now quote the following:—
"It cannot then be contested that the far-famed 'Origin of Species,' that, namely, by 'Natural Selection,' has been repudiated in fact, though not expressly even by its own author. This circumstance, which is simply undeniable, might dispense us from any further consideration of the hypothesis itself. But the "conspiracy of silence," which has accompanied the repudiation tends to lead the unthinking many to suppose that the same importance still attaches to it as at first. On this account it may be well to ask the question, what, after all, is 'Natural Selection'?[Pg 370]
"It can't be argued that the famous 'Origin of Species,' specifically the idea of 'Natural Selection,' has actually been rejected, even if not directly by its own author. This fact, which is simply undeniable, could allow us to skip any further discussion of the hypothesis itself. However, the 'conspiracy of silence' surrounding this rejection tends to cause many people to mistakenly believe that it still holds the same significance as it once did. Therefore, it might be useful to ask the question, what is 'Natural Selection' after all?[Pg 370]
"The answer may seem surprising to some, but it is none the less true, that 'Natural Selection' is simply nothing. It is an apparently positive name for a really negative effect, and is therefore an eminently misleading term. By 'Natural Selection' is meant the result of all the destructive agencies of Nature, destructive to individuals and to races by destroying their lives or their powers of propagation. Evidently, the cause of the distinction of species (supposing such distinction to be brought about in natural generation) must be that which causes variation, and variation in one determinate direction in at least several individuals simultaneously." I should like to have added here the words "and during many successive generations," but they will go very sufficiently without saying.
"The answer may surprise some, but it’s still true that 'Natural Selection' is essentially meaningless. It’s a seemingly positive term for an actually negative effect, making it quite misleading. 'Natural Selection' refers to the result of all the destructive forces in Nature, which harm individuals and species by taking away their lives or their ability to reproduce. Clearly, the cause of the distinction of species (assuming such distinctions arise through natural processes) must be what triggers variation, and that variation must occur in a specific direction in at least several individuals at the same time. I would have liked to add "and over many successive generations," but that is quite clear without stating it."
"At the same time," continues Professor Mivart, "it is freely conceded that the destructive agencies in nature do succeed in preventing the perpetuation of monstrous, abortive, and feeble attempts at the performance of the evolutionary process, that they rapidly remove antecedent forms when new ones are evolved more in harmony with surrounding conditions, and that their action results in the formation of new characters when these have once attained sufficient completeness to be of real utility to their possessor.
"At the same time," Professor Mivart continues, "it's widely acknowledged that the destructive forces in nature effectively stop the continuation of bizarre, failed, and weak attempts at evolution. They quickly eliminate earlier forms when new ones emerge that better suit their environment, and their actions lead to the development of new traits once those traits reach a level of completeness that truly benefits their owner."
"Continued reflection, and five years further pondering over the problems of specific origin have more and more convinced me that the conception, that the origin of all species 'man included' is due simply to conditions which are (to use Mr. Darwin's own words) 'strictly accidental,' is a conception utterly irrational."[Pg 371]
"After a lot of thinking and five more years contemplating the issues of specific origins, I'm increasingly convinced that the idea that the origin of all species, including humans, is purely the result of conditions that are, in Mr. Darwin's own words, 'strictly accidental,' is completely irrational."[Pg 371]
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"With regard to the conception as now put forward by Mr. Darwin, I cannot truly characterize it but by an epithet which I employ only with much reluctance. I weigh my words and have present to my mind the many distinguished naturalists who have accepted the notion, and yet I cannot hesitate to call it a 'puerile hypothesis.'"[370]
"About the idea being proposed by Mr. Darwin, I can only describe it with a term I use very reluctantly. I choose my words carefully and I'm aware of the many respected naturalists who have embraced this idea, but I still can't help but call it a 'childish hypothesis.'"[370]
I am afraid I cannot go with Professor Mivart farther than this point, though I have a strong feeling as though his conclusion is true, that "the material universe is always and everywhere sustained and directed by an infinite cause, for which to us the word mind is the least inadequate and misleading symbol." But I feel that any attempt to deal with such a question is going far beyond that sphere in which man's powers may be at present employed with advantage: I trust, therefore, that I may never try to verify it, and am indifferent whether it is correct or not.
I’m afraid I can’t go with Professor Mivart any further than this point, even though I strongly feel his conclusion is likely true: that "the material universe is always and everywhere sustained and directed by an infinite cause, for which to us the word mind is the least inadequate and misleading symbol." However, I believe that trying to tackle such a question goes beyond what we can currently explore with any benefit. Therefore, I hope I never feel the need to verify it, and I don’t really care whether it’s right or wrong.
Again, I should probably differ from Professor Mivart in finding this mind inseparable from the material universe in which we live and move. So that I could neither conceive of such a mind influencing and directing the universe from a point as it were outside the universe itself, nor yet of a universe as existing without there being present—or having been present—in its every particle something for which mind should be the least inadequate and misleading symbol. But the subject is far beyond me.
Again, I should probably disagree with Professor Mivart in seeing the mind as inseparable from the material universe we inhabit. I can't imagine a mind influencing and guiding the universe from a point outside of it, nor can I envision a universe existing without some aspect of mind being present—or having been present—in every particle, for which the mind would be at least an imperfect and misleading representation. But the topic is well beyond my understanding.
As regards Professor Mivart's denunciations of[Pg 372] natural selection, I have only one fault to find with them, namely, that they do not speak out with sufficient bluntness. The difficulty of showing the fallacy of Mr. Darwin's position, is the difficulty of grasping a will-o'-the-wisp. A concluding example will put this clearly before the reader, and at the same time serve to illustrate the most tangible feature of difference between Mr. Darwin and Lamarck.
As for Professor Mivart's criticisms of[Pg 372] natural selection, I only have one issue with them: they aren't direct enough. The challenge of disproving Mr. Darwin's argument is like trying to catch a will-o'-the-wisp. A final example will clarify this for the reader while also highlighting the most noticeable difference between Mr. Darwin and Lamarck.
FOOTNOTES:
[365] 'Origin of Species,' p. 62.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 'Origin of Species,' p. 62.
[366] 'Origin of Species,' p. 49.
[367] 'Origin of Species,' p. 63.
[369] 'Origin of Species,' p. 65.
[370] 'Lessons from Nature,' p. 300.
THE CASE OF THE MADEIRA BEETLES AS ILLUSTRATING THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN THE EVOLUTION OF LAMARCK AND OF MR. CHARLES DARWIN—CONCLUSION.
THE CASE OF THE MADEIRA BEETLES AS ILLUSTRATING THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN THE EVOLUTION OF LAMARCK AND OF MR. CHARLES DARWIN—CONCLUSION.
An island of no very great extent is surrounded by a sea which cuts it off for many miles from the nearest land. It lies a good deal exposed to winds, so that the beetles which live upon it are in continual danger of being blown out to sea if they fly during the hours and seasons when the wind is blowing. It is found that an unusually large proportion of the beetles inhabiting this island are either without wings or have their wings in a useless and merely rudimentary state; and that a large number of kinds which are very common on the nearest mainland, but which are compelled to use their wings in seeking their food, are here entirely wanting. It is also observed that the beetles on this island generally lie much concealed until the wind lulls and the sun shines. These are the facts; let us now see how Lamarck would treat them.
An island of relatively small size is surrounded by a sea that cuts it off for many miles from the nearest land. It is quite exposed to winds, so the beetles that live there are constantly at risk of being blown out to sea if they fly during windy hours and seasons. It turns out that a surprisingly high number of the beetles on this island either lack wings or have wings that are useless and only partially developed; many types that are very common on the nearest mainland—where they need to fly to find food—are completely absent here. It’s also noted that the beetles on this island typically stay hidden until the wind dies down and the sun comes out. Those are the facts; let’s now see how Lamarck would interpret them.
Lamarck would say that the beetles once being on this island it became one of the conditions of their existence that they should not get blown out to sea. For once blown out to sea, they would be quite certain to be drowned. Beetles, when they fly, generally fly for[Pg 374] some purpose, and do not like having that purpose interfered with by something which can carry them all-whithers, whether they like it or no. If they are flying and find the wind taking them in a wrong direction, or seaward—which they know will be fatal to them—they stop flying as soon as may be, and alight on terra firma. But if the wind is very prevalent the beetles can find but little opportunity for flying at all: they will therefore lie quiet all day and do as best they can to get their living on foot instead of on the wing. There will thus be a long-continued disuse of wings, and this will gradually diminish the development of the wings themselves, till after a sufficient number of generations these will either disappear altogether, or be seen in a rudimentary condition only. For each beetle which has made but little use of its wings will be liable to leave offspring with a slightly diminished wing, some other organ which has been used instead of the wing becoming proportionately developed. It is thus seen that the conditions of existence are the indirect cause of the wings becoming rudimentary, inasmuch as they preclude the beetles from using them; the disuse however on the part of the beetles themselves is the direct cause.
Lamarck would argue that once beetles arrived on this island, it became essential for their survival not to get blown out to sea. If they did, they would surely drown. When beetles take flight, they usually have a specific intention and dislike having that purpose interrupted by anything that could carry them off, whether they want it to or not. If they’re flying and feel the wind pushing them in the wrong direction, especially toward the ocean—which they know could be deadly—they try to land as quickly as possible on solid ground. However, if the wind is too strong, the beetles may find it hard to take to the skies at all; as a result, they'll stay grounded all day and do their best to find food on foot rather than flying. This extended period of not using their wings will gradually lead to a decline in their development, and after several generations, the wings may either completely disappear or be reduced to a basic state. Each beetle that uses its wings less is likely to produce offspring with slightly smaller wings, while some other organ that’s used instead becomes more developed. This demonstrates that the conditions of their environment indirectly cause the wings to become rudimentary, as they prevent the beetles from using them; however, the beetles' own disuse of the wings is the direct cause.
Now let us see how Mr. Darwin deals with the same case. He writes:—
Now let's see how Mr. Darwin addresses the same situation. He writes:—
"In some cases we might easily set down to disuse, modifications of structure which are wholly or mainly due to natural selection." Then follow the facts about the beetles of Madeira, as I have given them above. While we are reading them we naturally make up our[Pg 375] minds that the winglessness of the beetles will prove due either wholly, or at any rate mainly, to natural selection, and that though it would be easy to set it down to disuse, yet we must on no account do so. The facts having been stated, Mr. Darwin continues:—"These several considerations make me believe that the wingless condition of so many Madeira beetles is mainly due to the action of natural selection," and when we go on to the words that immediately follow, "combined probably with disuse," we are almost surprised at finding that disuse has had anything to do with the matter. We feel a languid wish to know exactly how much and in what way it has entered into the combination; but we find it difficult to think the matter out, and are glad to take it for granted that the part played by disuse must be so unimportant that we need not consider it. Mr. Darwin continues:—
"In some cases, we might easily dismiss changes in structure that are entirely or primarily due to natural selection." Then come the facts about the beetles of Madeira, as I've mentioned earlier. While reading them, we naturally conclude that the winglessness of the beetles is either entirely or mostly due to natural selection, and although it would be easy to attribute it to disuse, we must not do so. After stating the facts, Mr. Darwin goes on:—"These several considerations lead me to believe that the wingless condition of many Madeira beetles is mainly caused by natural selection," and when we continue to the following words, "probably combined with disuse," we are almost surprised to see that disuse has had any role in this. We feel a vague curiosity to understand exactly how much and in what way it has contributed, but we find it challenging to figure it out and prefer to assume that disuse is so minor that we don’t need to consider it. Mr. Darwin continues:—
"For during many successive generations each individual beetle which flew least, either from its wings having been ever so little less perfectly developed, or from indolent habit, will have had the best chance of surviving from not having been blown out to sea; and on the other hand those beetles which most readily took to flight would oftenest be blown out to sea and perish."[371]
"Over many generations, each beetle that flew the least—whether due to slightly underdeveloped wings or laziness—has had a better chance of surviving because it wasn’t blown out to sea. Conversely, the beetles that were quickest to take flight were often blown out to sea and died." [371]
So apt are we to believe what we are told, when it is told us gravely and with authority, and when there is no statement at hand to contradict it, that we fail to see that Mr. Darwin is all the time really attributing the winglessness of the Madeira beetles either to the quâ him unknown causes which have led[Pg 376] to the "ever so little less perfect development of wing" on the part of the beetles that leave offspring—that is to say, is admitting that he can give no account of the matter—or else to the "indolent habit" of the parent beetles which has led them to disuse their wings, and hence gradually to lose them—which is neither more nor less than the "erroneous grounds of opinion," and "well-known doctrine" of Lamarck.
We’re so quick to believe what we’re told, especially when it’s presented seriously and with authority, and when there’s no evidence to contradict it, that we overlook the fact that Mr. Darwin is actually attributing the winglessness of the Madeira beetles either to the quâ him unknown causes that have led[Pg 376] to the “slightly less perfect development of wing” in the beetles that produce offspring—that is, he’s admitting he can’t explain it—or to the “lazy behavior” of the parent beetles, which has caused them to stop using their wings, and thus gradually lose them. This idea is no different from the “misguided reasons” and “well-known theory” of Lamarck.
For Mr. Darwin cannot mean that the fact of some beetles being blown out to sea is the most important means whereby certain other beetles come to have smaller wings—that the Madeira beetles in fact come to have smaller wings mainly because their large winged uncles and aunts—go away.
For Mr. Darwin can't really mean that the fact that some beetles are blown out to sea is the main reason why certain other beetles end up with smaller wings—that the Madeira beetles actually end up with smaller wings mostly because their large-winged relatives just leave.
But if he does not mean this, what becomes of natural selection?
But if he doesn't mean this, what happens to natural selection?
For in this case we are left exactly where Lamarck left us, and must hold that such beetles as have smaller wings have them because the conditions of life or "circumstances" in which their parents were placed, rendered it inconvenient to them to fly, and thus led them to leave off using their wings.
For in this case, we find ourselves exactly where Lamarck left off, and we have to conclude that beetles with smaller wings have them because the living conditions or "circumstances" their parents experienced made it difficult for them to fly, which resulted in them stopping the use of their wings.
Granted, that if there had been nothing to take unmodified beetles away, there would have been less room and scope for the modified beetles; also that unmodified beetles would have intermixed with the modified, and impeded the prevalence of the modification. But anything else than such removal of unmodified individuals would be contrary to our hypothesis. The very essence of conditions of existence is that there shall be something to take away[Pg 377] those which do not comply with the conditions; if there is nothing to render such and such a course a sine quâ non for life, there is no condition of existence in respect of this course, and no modification according to Lamarck could follow, as there would be no changed distribution of use.
If there hadn't been anything to remove unmodified beetles, there would have been less space and opportunity for the modified beetles. Unmodified beetles would have mixed with the modified ones and hindered the spread of the modification. However, anything other than the removal of unmodified individuals would contradict our hypothesis. The very essence of living conditions is that there must be something to remove those that don't fit the conditions; if there's nothing to make a certain path essential for life, then there are no living conditions related to that path, and no modification according to Lamarck could happen, as there would be no change in usage distribution.[Pg 377]
I think that if I were to leave this matter here I should have said enough to make the reader feel that Lamarck's system is direct, intelligible and sufficient—while Mr. Darwin's is confused and confusing. I may however quote Mr. Darwin himself as throwing his theory about the Madeira beetles on one side in a later passage, for he writes:—
I think that if I were to leave this matter here, I would have said enough to make the reader feel that Lamarck's system is straightforward, clear, and adequate—while Mr. Darwin's is unclear and perplexing. However, I can quote Mr. Darwin himself as he dismisses his theory about the Madeira beetles in a later passage, as he writes:—
"It is probable that disuse has been the main agent in rendering organs rudimentary," or in other words that Lamarck was quite right—nor does one see why if disuse is after all the main agent in rendering an organ rudimentary, use should not have been the main agent in developing it—but let that pass. "It (disuse) would at first lead," continues Mr. Darwin, "by slow steps to the more and more complete reduction of a part, until at last it became rudimentary—as in the case of the eyes of animals inhabiting dark caverns, and of the wings of birds inhabiting oceanic islands, which have seldom been forced by beasts of prey to take flight, and have ultimately lost the power of flying. Again, an organ useful under certain conditions, might become injurious under others, as with the wings of beetles living on small and exposed islands;"[372] so that the rudimentary condition of the Madeira beetles' wings is here set down[Pg 378] as mainly due to disuse—while above we find it mainly due to natural selection—I should say that immediately after the word "islands" just quoted, Mr. Darwin adds "and in this case natural selection will have aided in reducing the organ, until it was rendered harmless and rudimentary," but this is Mr. Darwin's manner, and must go for what it is worth.
"It’s likely that disuse has been the main factor in making organs rudimentary,” or in other words, Lamarck was pretty much right—there's no reason to think that if disuse is indeed the main factor in making an organ rudimentary, then use couldn't have been the main factor in developing it—but let’s not dwell on that. “It (disuse) would initially lead,” continues Mr. Darwin, “by gradual steps to the more and more complete reduction of a part, until eventually, it became rudimentary—like the eyes of animals living in dark caves, and the wings of birds on oceanic islands that have rarely faced predators, leading them to lose their ability to fly. Additionally, an organ useful under certain conditions might become harmful under others, like the wings of beetles living on small and exposed islands;”[372] thus, the rudimentary condition of the Madeira beetles' wings is noted here as primarily due to disuse—while previously it was mainly attributed to natural selection—I would point out that right after the word “islands” in that quote, Mr. Darwin adds, “and in this case natural selection will have helped reduce the organ until it became harmless and rudimentary,” but that’s just Mr. Darwin's style and should be taken for what it is worth.[Pg 378]
How refreshing to turn to the simple straightforward language of Lamarck.
How refreshing to read the clear and direct language of Lamarck.
"Long continued disuse," he writes, "in consequence of the habits which an animal has contracted, gradually reduces an organ, and leads to its final disappearance....
"Extended periods of not using an organ," he writes, "because of the habits an animal has developed, gradually diminishes that organ and ultimately leads to its disappearance..."
"Eyes placed in the head form an essential part of that plan on which we observe all vertebrate organisms to be constructed. Nevertheless the mole which uses its vision very little, has eyes which are only very small and hardly apparent.
"Eyes located in the head are a crucial aspect of the structure that we see in all vertebrate organisms. However, the mole, which relies on its vision very little, has eyes that are tiny and barely noticeable."
"The aspalax of Olivier, which lives underground like the mole, and exposes itself even less than the mole to the light of day, has wholly lost the use of its sight, nor does it retain more than mere traces of visual organs, these traces again being hidden under the skin and under certain other parts which cover them up and leave not even the smallest access to the light. The Proteus, an aquatic reptile akin to the Salamander and living in deep and obscure cavities under water, has, like the aspalax, no longer anything but traces of eyes remaining—traces which are again entirely hidden and covered up.[373]
The aspalax from Olivier, which lives underground like a mole and is even more reclusive when it comes to sunlight, has completely lost its ability to see. It barely has any remnants of eyes left, and those are concealed beneath the skin and other layers that block any light from reaching them. Similarly, the Proteus, an aquatic reptile related to the Salamander that resides in deep, dark underwater spaces, has also lost its eyesight, leaving only traces of eyes that are fully hidden and covered. [373]
"The following consideration should be decisive.[Pg 379]
The following consideration should be decisive.[Pg 379]
"Light cannot penetrate everywhere, and as a consequence, animals which live habitually in places which it cannot reach, do not have an opportunity of using eyes, even though they have got them; but animals which form part of a system of organization which comprises eyes as an invariable rule among its organs, must have had eyes originally. Since then we find among these animals some which have lost their eyes, and which have only concealed traces of these organs, it is evident that the impoverishment, and even disappearance of the organs in question, must be the effect of long-continued disuse.
"Light can't reach everywhere, so animals that live in places it can't penetrate don't get to use their eyes, even if they have them; however, animals that are part of a system that consistently includes eyes must have originally had them. Since we observe some of these animals have lost their eyes and only show faint traces of these organs, it's clear that the reduction and even loss of these organs is a result of long-term disuse."
"A proof of this is to be found in the fact that the organ of hearing is never in like case with that of sight; we always find it in animals of whose system of organization hearing is a component part; and for the following reason, namely, that sound, which is the effect of vibration upon the ear, can penetrate everywhere, and pass even through massive intermediate bodies. Any animal, therefore, with an organic system of which the ear is an essential part, can always find a use for its ears, no matter where it inhabits. We never, therefore, come upon rudimentary ears among the vertebrata, and when, going down the scale of life lower than the vertebrata, we come to a point at which the ear is no longer to be found; we never come upon ears again in any lower class.
A proof of this is found in the fact that the hearing organ is never quite the same as the sight organ; we always see it in animals whose biological systems include hearing as a key component. The reason for this is that sound, which results from vibrations hitting the ear, can travel everywhere and even go through thick obstacles. Therefore, any animal whose organic system includes the ear can always find a purpose for its ears, regardless of its environment. We never find rudimentary ears among vertebrates, and when we move down the scale of life past vertebrates, reaching a point where ears are absent, we never see ears again in any lower category.
"Not so with the organ of sight: we see this organ disappear, reappear, and disappear again with the possibility or impossibility of using eyes on the part of the creature itself.[374]
"Not so with the organ of sight: we see this organ vanish, return, and vanish again depending on whether the creature can use its eyes or not.[374]
[Pg 380]"The great development of mantle in the acephalous molluscs has rendered eyes, and even a head, entirely useless to them. These organs, though belonging to the type of the organism, and by rights included in it, have had to disappear and become annihilated owing to continued default of use.
[Pg 380]"The significant growth of the mantle in headless mollusks has made eyes, and even a head, completely unnecessary for them. These organs, although they are part of the organism's structure and should logically be present, have had to vanish and be eliminated due to their ongoing lack of use.
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"Many insects which, by the analogy of their order and even genus, should have wings, have nevertheless lost them more or less completely through disuse. A number of coleoptera, orthoptera, hymenoptera, and hemiptera give us examples, the habits of these animals never leading them to use their wings."[375]
"Many insects that, by analogy of their classification and even genus, should have wings, have nonetheless lost them more or less completely due to not using them. Several beetles, grasshoppers, wasps, and true bugs provide examples, as their habits do not require them to use their wings."[375]
I will here bring this present volume to a conclusion, hoping, however, to return to the same subject shortly, but to that part of it which bears upon longevity and the phenomena of old age. In 'Life and Habit' I pointed out that if differentiations of structure and instinct are considered as due to the different desires under different circumstances of an organism, which must be regarded as a single creature, though its development has extended over millions of years, and which is guided mainly by habit and memory until some disturbing cause compels invention—then the longevity of each generation or stage of this organism should depend upon the lateness of the average age of reproduction in each generation; so that an organism (using the word in its usual signification) which did not upon the average begin to reproduce itself till it was[Pg 381] twenty, should be longer lived than one that on the average begins to reproduce itself at a year old. I also maintained that the phenomena of old age should be referred to failure of memory on the part of the organism, which in the embryonic stages, infancy, youth, and early manhood, leans upon the memory of what it did when it was in the persons of its ancestors; in middle life, carries its action onward by means of the impetus, already received, and by the force of habit; and in old age becomes puzzled, having no experience of any past existence at seventy-five, we will say, to guide it, and therefore forgetting itself more and more completely till it dies. I hope to extend this, and to bring forward arguments in support of it in a future work.
I will conclude this current volume here, but I hope to revisit this topic soon, focusing specifically on longevity and the effects of aging. In 'Life and Habit,' I pointed out that if we view changes in structure and instinct as responses to different desires in various situations of an organism—which should be considered as a single entity, despite its development over millions of years—and if it's mainly driven by habit and memory until something disrupts it and sparks innovation—then each generation's lifespan should depend on how late the average age of reproduction occurs within that generation. Therefore, an organism (using the term in its usual sense) that typically starts reproducing at around[Pg 381] twenty years old should live longer than one that begins to reproduce at one year old. I also argued that the effects of aging should be linked to the organism's failing memory. In its early stages—embryonic, infant, youth, and early adulthood—it relies on the memories of its ancestors. During middle age, it continues to act based on the momentum it has gained, fueled by habit. However, in old age, it becomes confused, having no past experiences at seventy-five, for example, to guide it, leading to an increasing forgetfulness until death. I plan to elaborate on this and present supporting arguments in a future work.
Of the importance of the theory put forward in 'Life and Habit'—I am daily more and more convinced. Unless we admit oneness of personality between parents and offspring, memory of the often repeated facts of past existences, the latency of that memory until it is rekindled by the presence of the associated ideas, or of a sufficient number of them, and the far-reaching consequences of the unconsciousness which results from habitual action, evolution does not greatly add to our knowledge as to how we shall live here to the best advantage. Add these considerations, and its value as a guide becomes immediately apparent; a new light is poured upon a hundred problems of the greatest delicacy and difficulty. Not the least interesting of these is the gradual extension of human longevity—an extension, however, which cannot be effected till many[Pg 382] many generations as yet unborn have come and gone. There is nothing, however, to prevent man's becoming as long lived as the oak if he will persevere for many generations in the steps which can alone lead to this result. Another interesting achievement which should be more quickly attainable, though still not in our own time, is the earlier maturity of those animals whose rapid maturity is an advantage to us, but whose longevity is not to our purpose.
Of the importance of the theory presented in 'Life and Habit'—I am becoming more and more convinced every day. Unless we acknowledge a connection between the personalities of parents and their children, the memory of repeated events from previous lives, the dormant nature of that memory until sparked by related ideas—or enough of them—and the significant effects of the unconsciousness that comes from habitual actions, evolution doesn’t really improve our understanding of how to live our best lives here. Take these points into account, and its value as a guide becomes clear; a new perspective is shed on numerous complex and challenging issues. One particularly intriguing topic is the gradual increase in human lifespan—although this won’t happen until many, many generations yet to be born have lived and passed away. However, there’s nothing stopping humans from living as long as oak trees if we persist, across many generations, in the practices that can lead to this outcome. Another fascinating goal that should be achievable sooner, though still not in our lifetime, is the earlier maturity of those animals whose rapid growth benefits us, although their long lifespan is not in our interest.
The question—Evolution or Direct Creation of all species?—has been settled in favour of Evolution. A hardly less interesting and important battle has now to be fought over the question whether we are to accept the evolution of the founders of the theory—with the adjuncts hinted at by Dr. Darwin and Mr. Matthew, and insisted on, so far as I can gather, by Professor Hering and myself—or the evolution of Mr. Darwin, which denies the purposiveness or teleology inherent in evolution as first propounded. I am assured that such of my readers as I can persuade to prefer the old evolution to the new will have but little reason to regret their preference.
The question—Evolution or Direct Creation of all species?—has been decided in favor of Evolution. There's an equally fascinating and significant debate that now needs to be addressed regarding whether we should accept the evolution of the founders of the theory—with the ideas suggested by Dr. Darwin and Mr. Matthew, and emphasized, as far as I understand, by Professor Hering and myself—or the evolution proposed by Mr. Darwin, which rejects the purposefulness or teleology originally associated with evolution. I'm confident that those readers I can convince to favor the old evolution over the new will have little reason to regret their choice.
P.S.—As these sheets leave my hands, my attention is called to a review of Professor Haeckel's 'Evolution of Man,' by Mr. A. E. Wallace, in the 'Academy' for April 12, 1879. "Professor Haeckel maintains," says Mr. Wallace, "that the struggle for existence in nature evolves new forms without design, just as the will of man produces new varieties in cultivation with design." I[Pg 383] maintain in preference with the older evolutionists, that in consequence of change in the conditions of their existence, organisms design new forms for themselves, and carry those designs out in additions to, and modifications of, their own bodies.
P.S.—As these sheets leave my hands, I'm reminded of a review of Professor Haeckel's 'Evolution of Man' by Mr. A. E. Wallace in the 'Academy' from April 12, 1879. "Professor Haeckel argues," says Mr. Wallace, "that the struggle for existence in nature creates new forms without any plan, just as human will creates new varieties through cultivation intentionally." I[Pg 383] argue, following the older evolutionists, that due to changes in their living conditions, organisms create new forms for themselves and implement those designs through additions and modifications of their own bodies.
"The science of rudimentary organs," continues Mr. Wallace, "which Haeckel terms 'dysteleology, or the doctrine of purposelessness,' is here discussed, and a number of interesting examples are given, the conclusion being that they prove the mechanical or monistic conception of the origin of organisms to be correct, and the idea of any 'all-wise creative plan an ancient fable.'" I see no reason to suppose, or again not to suppose, an all-wise creative plan. I decline to go into this question, believing it to be not yet ripe, nor nearly ripe, for consideration. I see purpose, however, in rudimentary organs as much as in useful ones, but a spent or extinct purpose—a purpose which has been fulfilled, and is now forgotten—the rudimentary organ being repeated from force of habit, indolence, and dislike of change, so long as it does not, to use the words of Buffon, "stand in the way of the fair development" of other parts which are found useful and necessary. I demur, therefore, to the inference of "purposelessness" which I gather that Professor Haeckel draws from these organs.
"The science of rudimentary organs," Mr. Wallace continues, "which Haeckel calls 'dysteleology, or the doctrine of purposelessness,' is discussed here, along with several interesting examples. The conclusion drawn is that these examples support the mechanical or monistic view of the origin of organisms, and that the notion of any 'all-wise creative plan' is merely an ancient myth." I see no reason to believe or disbelieve in an all-wise creative plan. I choose not to delve into this issue, as I think it isn’t ready for consideration yet. However, I see purpose in rudimentary organs just as much as in useful ones, but it's a spent or outdated purpose—a purpose that has been fulfilled and is now forgotten. The rudimentary organ is repeated out of habit, laziness, and a reluctance to change, as long as it doesn’t, to use Buffon’s words, "hinder the fair development" of other parts that are useful and necessary. Therefore, I disagree with the conclusion of "purposelessness" that I understand Professor Haeckel draws from these organs.
In the 'Academy' for April 19, 1879, Mr. Wallace quotes Professor Haeckel as saying that our "highly purposive and admirably-constituted sense-organs have developed without premeditated aim; that they have originated by the same mechanical process of Natural[Pg 384] Selection, by the same constant interaction of Adaptation and Heredity [what is Heredity but another word for unknown causes, unless it is explained in some such manner as in 'Life and Habit'?] by which all the other purposive contrivances of the animal organization have been slowly and gradually evolved during the struggle for existence."
In the 'Academy' for April 19, 1879, Mr. Wallace quotes Professor Haeckel as saying that our "highly purposeful and well-designed sense organs have developed without any specific intent; that they have come about through the same mechanical process of Natural[Pg 384] Selection, by the same ongoing interaction of Adaptation and Heredity [what is Heredity but another term for unknown causes, unless it is explained in some way like in 'Life and Habit'?] through which all the other purposeful designs of animal organization have been slowly and gradually evolved during the struggle for survival."
I see no evidence for "premeditated aim" at any modification very far in advance of an existing organ, any more than I do for "premeditated aim" on man's part at any as yet inconceivable mechanical invention; but as in the case of man's inventions, so also in that of the organs of animals and plants, modification is due to the accumulation of small, well-considered improvements, as found necessary in practice, and the conduct of their affairs. Each step having been purposive, the whole road has been travelled purposively; nor is the purposiveness of such an organ, we will say, as the eye, barred by the fact that invention has doubtless been aided by some of those happy accidents which from time to time happen to all who keep their wits about them, and know how to turn the gifts of Fortune to account.
I see no evidence of a "premeditated goal" for any changes well before the development of an existing organ, just like I don’t see any "premeditated goal" on humanity's part for any yet-to-be-imagined mechanical invention. But just like with human inventions, the changes in the organs of animals and plants come from small, thoughtful improvements made as needed in real life and in how they manage their existence. Each step has been intentional, so the entire journey has been taken with purpose. The purposefulness of an organ, like the eye, isn’t diminished by the fact that some of these inventions have likely benefited from those lucky accidents that happen to anyone who stays alert and knows how to make the most of fortunate situations.
FOOTNOTES:
[371] 'Origin of Species,' p. 109.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 'Origin of Species,' p. 109.
[372] 'Origin of Species, p. 401.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 'On the Origin of Species, p. 401.
CHAPTER I.
Chapter 1.
REVIEWS OF 'EVOLUTION, OLD AND NEW.'
REVIEWS OF 'EVOLUTION, OLD AND NEW.'
Those who have been at the pains to read the foregoing book will, perhaps, pardon me if I put before them a short account of the reception it has met with: I will not waste time by arguing with my critics at any length; it will be enough if I place some of their remarks upon my book under the same cover as the book itself, with here and there a word or two of comment.
Those who have taken the time to read the previous book might forgive me for sharing a brief overview of the feedback it has received: I won’t spend much time debating with my critics; it will suffice to include some of their comments on my book alongside the book itself, with a few words of my own here and there.
The only reviews which have come under my notice appeared in the 'Academy' and the 'Examiner,' both of May 17, 1879; the 'Edinburgh Daily Review,' May 23, 1879; 'City Press,' May 21, 1879; 'Field,' May 26, 1879; 'Saturday Review,' May 31, 1879; 'Daily Chronicle,' May 31, 1879; 'Graphic' and 'Nature,' both June 12, 1879; 'Pall Mall Gazette,' June 18, 1879; 'Literary World,' June 20, 1879; 'Scotsman,' June 24, 1879; 'British Journal of Homœopathy' and 'Mind,' both July 1, 1879; 'Journal of Science,' July 18, 1879; 'Westminster Review,' July, 1879; 'Athenæum,' July 26, 1879; 'Daily News,' July 29, 1879; 'Manchester City[Pg 386] News,' August 16, 1879; 'Nonconformist,' November 26, 1879; 'Popular Science Review,' Jan. 1, 1880; 'Morning Post,' Jan. 12, 1880.
The only reviews I've noticed appeared in the 'Academy' and the 'Examiner,' both dated May 17, 1879; the 'Edinburgh Daily Review,' May 23, 1879; 'City Press,' May 21, 1879; 'Field,' May 26, 1879; 'Saturday Review,' May 31, 1879; 'Daily Chronicle,' May 31, 1879; 'Graphic' and 'Nature,' both on June 12, 1879; 'Pall Mall Gazette,' June 18, 1879; 'Literary World,' June 20, 1879; 'Scotsman,' June 24, 1879; 'British Journal of Homœopathy' and 'Mind,' both on July 1, 1879; 'Journal of Science,' July 18, 1879; 'Westminster Review,' July, 1879; 'Athenæum,' July 26, 1879; 'Daily News,' July 29, 1879; 'Manchester City[Pg 386] News,' August 16, 1879; 'Nonconformist,' November 26, 1879; 'Popular Science Review,' Jan. 1, 1880; 'Morning Post,' Jan. 12, 1880.
Some of the most hostile passages in the reviews above referred to are as follows:—
Some of the most aggressive sections in the reviews mentioned above are as follows:—
"From beginning to end, our eccentric author treats us to a dazzling flood of epigram, invective, and what appears to be argument; and finally leaves us without a single clear idea as to what he has been driving at."
"From start to finish, our quirky author bombards us with a brilliant mix of witty remarks, harsh criticism, and what seems like debate; and ultimately leaves us without a single clear idea of what he’s been aiming for."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"Mr. Butler comes forward, as it were, to proclaim himself a professional satirist, and a mystifier who will do his best to leave you utterly in the dark with regard to his system of juggling. Is he a teleological theologian making fun of evolution? Is he an evolutionist making fun of teleology? Is he a man of letters making fun of science? Or is he a master of pure irony making fun of all three, and of his audience as well? For our part we decline to commit ourselves, and prefer to observe, as Mr. Butler observes of Von Hartmann, that if his meaning is anything like what he says it is, we can only say that it has not been given us to form any definite conception whatever as to what that meaning may be."—'Academy,' May 17, 1879, Signed Grant Allen.
"Mr. Butler steps up to announce himself as a professional satirist and a mystifier who will do his best to keep you completely in the dark about his juggling tricks. Is he a theologian poking fun at evolution? Is he an evolutionist ridiculing teleology? Is he a writer mocking science? Or is he a master of pure irony humorously critiquing all three, along with his audience? We choose not to take a stance on this and prefer to echo Mr. Butler's comments about Von Hartmann, that if his meaning resembles what he claims it is, we can only say that we have not been able to form any clear idea of what that meaning might be."—'Academy,' May 17, 1879, Signed Grant Allen.
Here is another criticism of "Evolution, Old and New"—also, I believe I am warranted in saying, by Mr. Grant Allen. These two criticisms appeared on the same day; how many more Mr. Allen may have written later on I do not know.[Pg 387]
Here’s another critique of "Evolution, Old and New"—and I think I can say this is backed by Mr. Grant Allen. These two critiques were published on the same day; I'm not sure how many more Mr. Allen may have written later on.[Pg 387]
We find the writer who in the 'Academy' declares that he has been left without "a single clear idea" as to what 'Evolution, Old and New,' has been driving at saying on the same day in the 'Examiner' that 'Evolution, Old and New,' "has a more evident purpose than any of its predecessors." If so, I am afraid the predecessors must have puzzled Mr. Allen very unpleasantly. What the purpose of 'Evolution, Old and New,' is, he proceeds to explain:—
We see the writer who in the 'Academy' states that he has been left without "a single clear idea" about what 'Evolution, Old and New' is aiming for, saying on the same day in the 'Examiner' that 'Evolution, Old and New' "has a more evident purpose than any of its predecessors." If that's the case, I’m afraid the predecessors must have confused Mr. Allen quite a bit. He goes on to explain what the purpose of 'Evolution, Old and New' is:—
"As to his (Mr. Butler's) main argument, it comes briefly to this: natural selection does not originate favourable varieties, it only passively permits them to exist; therefore it is the unknown cause which produced the variations, not the natural selection which spared them, that ought to count as the mainspring of evolution. That unknown cause Mr. Butler boldly declares to be the will of the organism itself. An intelligent ascidian wanted a pair of eyes,[376] so set to work and made itself a pair, exactly as a man makes a microscope; a talented fish conceived the idea of walking on dry land, so it developed legs, turned its swim bladder into a pair of lungs, and became an amphibian; an æsthetic guinea-fowl admired bright colours, so it bought a paint-box, studied Mr. Whistler's ornamental designs, and, painting itself a gilded and ocellated tail, was thenceforth a peacock. But how about plants? Mr. Butler does not shirk even this difficulty. The theory must be maintained at all hazards....[Pg 388] This is the sort of mystical nonsense from which we had hoped Mr. Darwin had for ever saved us."—'Examiner,' May 17, 1879.
"As for Mr. Butler's main argument, it essentially boils down to this: natural selection doesn't create favorable variations; it just passively allows them to survive. Therefore, the true driving force behind evolution should be considered the unknown cause that created these variations, not the natural selection that merely spared them. Mr. Butler boldly claims that this unknown cause is the will of the organism itself. An intelligent ascidian wanted a pair of eyes, so it got to work and made itself a pair, just like a person makes a microscope; a clever fish imagined walking on dry land, so it developed legs, transformed its swim bladder into lungs, and became an amphibian; an artistic guinea-fowl admired bright colors, so it got a paintbox, studied Mr. Whistler's decorative designs, and by painting itself a gilded and ocellated tail, it became a peacock. But what about plants? Mr. Butler doesn't shy away from this challenge either. The theory must hold strong no matter what... This is the kind of mystical nonsense we thought Mr. Darwin had freed us from."—'Examiner,' May 17, 1879.
In this last article, Mr. Allen has said that I am a man of genius, "with the unmistakable signet-mark upon my forehead." I have been subjected to a good deal of obloquy and misrepresentation at one time or another, but this passage by Mr. Allen is the only one I have seen that has made me seriously uneasy about the prospects of my literary reputation.
In this final article, Mr. Allen has claimed that I am a man of genius, "with the unmistakable signet-mark upon my forehead." I've faced a lot of criticism and misrepresentation over time, but this statement by Mr. Allen is the only one I've come across that has genuinely made me anxious about the future of my literary reputation.
I see Mr. Allen has been lately writing an article in the 'Fortnightly Review' on the decay of criticism. Looking over it somewhat hurriedly, my eye was arrested by the following:—
I see Mr. Allen has recently been writing an article in the 'Fortnightly Review' about the decline of criticism. Glancing over it quickly, I was caught by the following:—
"Nowadays any man can write, because there are papers enough to give employment to everybody. No reflection, no deliberation, no care; all is haste, fatal facility, stock phrases, commonplace ideas, and a ready pen that can turn itself to any task with equal ease, because supremely ignorant of all alike."
"These days, anyone can write because there are enough platforms to employ everyone. There's no thought, no consideration, no effort; everything is rushed, dangerously easy, filled with clichés, ordinary ideas, and a quick pen that can adapt to any task effortlessly, due to a complete lack of understanding of any of it."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"The writer takes to his craft nowadays, not because he has taste for literature, but because he has an incurable faculty for scribbling. He has no culture, and he soon loses the power of taking pains, if he ever possessed it. But he can talk with glib superficiality and imposing confidence about every conceivable subject, from a play or a picture to a sermon or a metaphysical essay. It is the utter indifference to subject-matter, joined with the vulgar unscrupulousness of pretentious[Pg 389] ignorance, that strikes the keynote of our existing criticism. Men write without taking the trouble to read or think."[377]
"The writer today takes up his craft not because he has a love for literature, but because he has an unstoppable urge to write. He lacks culture, and he quickly loses the ability to put in effort, if he ever had it. But he can chat with slick superficiality and false confidence about every imaginable topic, from a play or a painting to a sermon or a philosophical essay. It is the complete indifference to the subject matter, combined with the rude lack of scruples of pretentious ignorance, that defines our current criticism. People write without bothering to read or think."
The 'Saturday Review' attacked 'Evolution, Old and New,' I may almost say savagely. It wrote: "When Mr. Butler's 'Life and Habit' came before us, we doubted whether his ambiguously expressed speculations belonged to the regions of playful but possibly scientific imagination, or of unscientific fancies; and we gave him the benefit of the doubt. In fact, we strained a point or two to find a reasonable meaning for him. He has now settled the question against himself. Not professing to have any particular competence in biology, natural history, or the scientific study of evidence in any shape whatever, and, indeed, rather glorying in his freedom from any such superfluities, he undertakes to assure the overwhelming majority of men of science, and the educated public who have followed their lead, that, while they have done well to be converted to the doctrine of the evolution and transmutation of species, they have been converted on entirely wrong grounds."
The 'Saturday Review' sharply criticized 'Evolution, Old and New.' It stated: "When Mr. Butler's 'Life and Habit' first appeared, we were unsure if his vaguely expressed ideas were part of playful yet possibly scientific thought or just unscientific whims; we decided to give him the benefit of the doubt. In fact, we bent over backwards a bit to find a reasonable interpretation of his work. He has now made it clear that he does not have the expertise in biology, natural history, or scientific evidence in any form, and he seems to take pride in not having such unnecessary knowledge. He now claims that the vast majority of scientists and the educated public, who have followed their insights, may have embraced the idea of evolution and the change of species, but they have done so based on completely misguided principles."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"When a writer who has not given as many weeks to the subject as Mr. Darwin has given years [as a matter of fact, it is now twenty years since I began to publish on the subject of Evolution] is not content to air his own crude, though clever, fallacies, but presumes to criticize Mr. Darwin with the superciliousness of a young schoolmaster looking over a boy's theme, it is[Pg 390] difficult not to take him more seriously than he deserves or perhaps desires. One would think that Mr. Butler was the travelled and laborious observer of Nature, and Mr. Darwin the pert speculator, who takes all his facts at secondhand."
"When a writer who has spent fewer weeks on the topic than Mr. Darwin has spent years—it's actually been twenty years since I started publishing about Evolution—can't just share his own raw, albeit clever, misconceptions but also feels the need to criticize Mr. Darwin with the arrogance of a young teacher reviewing a student's essay, it’s[Pg 390] hard not to take him more seriously than he deserves or maybe even wants. One might think that Mr. Butler is the experienced and diligent observer of Nature, while Mr. Darwin is the cocky theorist who relies on secondhand information."
. . . . . . . . . . .
. . . . . . . . . . .
"Let us once more consider how matters stood a year or two before the 'Origin of Species' first appeared. The continuous evolution of animated Nature had in its favour the difficulty of drawing fixed lines between species and even larger divisions, all the indications of comparative anatomy and embryology, and a good deal of general scientific presumption. Several well-known writers, and some eminent enough to command respect, had expressed their belief in it. One or two far-seeing thinkers, among whom the place of honour must be assigned to Mr. Herbert Spencer, had done more. They had used their philosophic insight, which, to science, is the eye of faith, to descry the promised land almost within reach; they knew and announced how rich and spacious the heritage would be, if once the entry could be made good. But on that 'if' everything hung. Nature was not bound to give up her secret, or was bound only in a mocking covenant with an impossible condition: Si cælum digito tetigeris; if only some fortunate hand could touch the inaccessible firmament, and bring down the golden chain to earth! But fruition seemed out of sight. Even those who were most willing to advance in this direction, could only regret that they saw no road clear. There was a tempting vision, but nothing proven—many would have said nothing provable. A few years[Pg 391] passed, and all this was changed. The doubtful speculation had become a firm and connected theory. In the room of scattered foragers and scouts, there was an irresistibly advancing column. Nature had surrendered her stronghold, and was disarmed of her secret. And if we ask who were the men by whom this was done, the answer is notorious, and there is but one answer possible: the names that are for ever associated with this great triumph are those of Charles Darwin and Wallace."[378]
"Let’s take a moment to reflect on how things were a year or two before the 'Origin of Species' was published. The ongoing evolution of living Nature faced the challenge of drawing definitive lines between species and even broader categories, all the evidence from comparative anatomy and embryology, and a considerable amount of general scientific reasoning. Several well-known authors, including some highly respected figures, shared their belief in it. A couple of visionary thinkers, prominently including Mr. Herbert Spencer, went even further. They used their philosophical insight, which serves science as a sort of faith, to glimpse the promised land that was almost within reach; they understood and communicated how rich and expansive the legacy would be if they could just gain access. But that 'if' was crucial. Nature wasn’t obligated to reveal her secrets or only did so under a mocking agreement with an impossible condition: Si cælum digito tetigeris; if only some lucky hand could touch the unreachable sky and bring the golden chain down to earth! But realization seemed far off. Even those most eager to pursue this path could only lament that they saw no clear way forward. There was an alluring vision, but nothing concrete—many would have argued nothing provable. A few years[Pg 391] passed, and everything changed. The uncertain speculation transformed into a solid, coherent theory. In place of scattered foragers and scouts, there emerged an unstoppable advancing force. Nature had relinquished her stronghold and revealed her secret. And if we ask who accomplished this, the answer is well known, and there's only one answer possible: the names forever linked to this great achievement are those of Charles Darwin and Wallace."[378]
I gave the lady or gentleman who wrote this an opportunity of acknowledging the authorship; but she or he preferred, not I think unnaturally, to remain anonymous.
I gave the person who wrote this a chance to admit they were the author, but they chose, and I don't think it's unusual, to stay anonymous.
The only other criticism of 'Evolution, Old and New,' to which I would call attention, appeared in 'Nature,' in a review of 'Unconscious Memory,' by Mr. Romanes, and contained the following passages:—
The only other criticism of 'Evolution, Old and New,' that I want to highlight appeared in 'Nature,' in a review of 'Unconscious Memory' by Mr. Romanes, and included the following passages:—
"But to be serious, if in charity we could deem Mr. Butler a lunatic, we should not be unprepared for any aberration of common sense that he might display.... A certain nobody writes a book ['Evolution, Old and New'] accusing the most illustrious man in his generation of burying the claims of certain illustrious predecessors out of the sight of all men. In the hope of gaining some notoriety by deserving, and perhaps receiving a contemptuous refutation from the eminent man in question, he publishes this book which, if it deserved serious consideration, would be not more of an insult to the particular man of science whom it accuses of conscious and wholesale plagiarism [there is no such[Pg 392] accusation in 'Evolution, Old and New'] than it would be to men of science in general for requiring such elementary instruction on some of the most famous literature in science from an upstart ignoramus, who, until two or three years ago, considered himself a painter by profession."—'Nature,' Jan. 27, 1881.
"But to be serious, if we were to consider Mr. Butler a lunatic out of charity, we wouldn’t be surprised by any lapses in common sense he might show.... A certain nobody writes a book ['Evolution, Old and New'] accusing one of the most respected men of his time of making the achievements of some notable predecessors disappear from public view. In hopes of gaining some fame by provoking a perhaps scornful response from the distinguished individual he targets, he publishes this book, which, if it warranted serious attention, would be no more an insult to the specific scientist he accuses of blatant and widespread plagiarism [there is no such[Pg 392] accusation in 'Evolution, Old and New'] than it would be to scientists as a whole for requiring such basic explanations of some of the most well-known literature in science from a pretentious ignoramus who, until just a couple of years ago, thought of himself as a painter by trade."—'Nature,' Jan. 27, 1881.
In a subsequent letter to 'Nature,' Mr. Romanes said he had been "acting the part of policeman" by writing as he had done. Any unscrupulous reviewer may call himself a policeman if he likes, but he must not expect those whom he assails to recognize his pretensions. 'Evolution, Old and New,' was not written for the kind of people whom Mr. Romanes calls men of science; if "men of science" means men like Mr. Romanes, I trust they say well who maintain that I am not a man of science; I believe the men to whom Mr. Romanes refers to be men, not of that kind of science which desires to know, but of that kind whose aim is to thrust itself upon the public as actually knowing. 'Evolution, Old and New,' could be of no use to these; certainly, it was not intended as an insult to them, but if they are insulted by it, I do not know that I am sorry, for I value their antipathy and opposition as much as I should dislike their approbation: of one thing, however, I am certain—namely, that before 'Evolution, Old and New,' was written, Professors Huxley and Tyndall, for example, knew very little of the earlier history of Evolution. Professor Huxley, in his article on Evolution in the ninth edition of the 'Encyclopædia Britannica,' published in 1878, says of the two great pioneers of[Pg 393] Evolution, that Buffon "contributed nothing to the general doctrine of Evolution,"[379] and that Erasmus Darwin "can hardly be said to have made any real advance on his predecessors."[380]
In a later letter to 'Nature,' Mr. Romanes mentioned that he had been "acting as a policeman" by writing as he did. Any dishonest reviewer can call themselves a policeman if they want, but they shouldn't expect those they criticize to accept their claims. 'Evolution, Old and New,' wasn't written for the kind of people Mr. Romanes refers to as men of science; if "men of science" means people like Mr. Romanes, I hope it's true that those who say I'm not a man of science are correct; I believe the people Mr. Romanes talks about are not engaged in the kind of science that seeks knowledge, but rather in the kind whose goal is to present themselves to the public as if they actually know. 'Evolution, Old and New,' wouldn’t benefit them; definitely, it wasn't meant as an insult to them, but if they feel insulted by it, I'm not sure that I'm sorry, because I value their hostility and resistance as much as I'd dislike their approval: however, I am sure of one thing—that before 'Evolution, Old and New,' was written, Professors Huxley and Tyndall, for example, knew very little about the earlier history of Evolution. Professor Huxley, in his article on Evolution in the ninth edition of the 'Encyclopædia Britannica,' published in 1878, states about the two great pioneers of Evolution that Buffon "contributed nothing to the general doctrine of Evolution," and that Erasmus Darwin "can hardly be said to have made any real advance on his predecessors."
Since 'Evolution, Old and New,' was published, I have observed several of the so-called men of science—among them Professor Huxley and Mr. Romanes—airing Buffon; but I never observed any of them do this till within the last three years. I maintain that "men of science" were, and still are, very ignorant concerning the history of Evolution; but, whether they were or were not, I did not write 'Evolution, Old and New,' for them; I wrote for the general public, who have been kind enough to testify their appreciation of it in a sufficiently practical manner.
Since 'Evolution, Old and New' was published, I've noticed several so-called scientists—like Professor Huxley and Mr. Romanes—talking about Buffon; but I hadn't seen any of them do this until the last three years. I believe that "scientists" were, and still are, quite ignorant about the history of Evolution; however, whether they were or weren't, I didn't write 'Evolution, Old and New' for them; I wrote it for the general public, who have been generous enough to show their appreciation in a practical way.
The way in which Mr. Charles Darwin met 'Evolution, Old and New,' has been so fully dealt with in my book, 'Unconscious Memory;' in the 'Athenæum,' Jan. 31, 1880; the 'St. James's Gazette,' Dec. 8, 1880; and 'Nature,' Feb. 3, 1881, that I need not return to it here, more especially as Mr. Darwin has, by his silence, admitted that he has no defence to make.[Pg 394]
The way Mr. Charles Darwin addressed 'Evolution, Old and New' has been thoroughly covered in my book, 'Unconscious Memory'; in the 'Athenæum,' Jan. 31, 1880; the 'St. James's Gazette,' Dec. 8, 1880; and 'Nature,' Feb. 3, 1881, so I won’t revisit it here, especially since Mr. Darwin has, through his silence, acknowledged that he has no defense to offer.[Pg 394]
I have quoted by no means the moat exceptionable parts of Mr. Romanes' article, and have given them a permanence they would not otherwise attain, inasmuch as nothing can better show the temper of the kind of men who are now—as I said in the body of the foregoing work—clamouring for endowment, and who would step into the Pope's shoes to-morrow if we would only let them.
I have by no means quoted the most objectionable parts of Mr. Romanes' article, and I have given them a permanence they wouldn't otherwise achieve, since nothing can better illustrate the attitude of the type of men who are now—as I mentioned in the main part of the previous work—clamoring for funding, and who would take the Pope's place tomorrow if we would only allow them.
FOOTNOTES:
[379] P. 748.
[380] Ibid.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Ibid.
[383] 'Fortnightly Review,' March, 1882.
'Fortnightly Review,' March 1882.
CHAPTER II.
CHAPTER 2.
ROME AND PANTHEISM.
Rome and Pantheism.
Evolution would after all be a poor doctrine if it did not affect human affairs at every touch and turn. I propose to devote the second chapter of this Appendix to the consideration of an aspect of Evolution which will always interest a very large number of people—the development of the relation that may exist between religion and science.
Evolution would be a weak theory if it didn't impact human affairs at every turn. I plan to dedicate the second chapter of this Appendix to exploring an aspect of Evolution that will always capture the interest of many people—the relationship between religion and science.
If the Church of Rome would only develop some doctrine or, I know not how, provide some means by which men like myself, who cannot pretend to believe in the miraculous element of Christianity, could yet join her as a conservative stronghold, I, for one, should gladly do so. I believe the difference between her faith and that of all who can be called gentlemen to be one of words rather than things. Our practical working ideal is much the same as hers; when we use the word "gentleman" we mean the same thing that the Church of Rome does; so that, if we get down below the words that formulate her teaching, there are few points upon which we should not agree. But, alas! words are often so very important.
If the Catholic Church could just develop some doctrine or, I don’t know how, find a way for people like me, who can’t pretend to believe in the miraculous aspects of Christianity, to still join her as a conservative stronghold, I would gladly do so. I think the difference between her beliefs and those of people who can be called gentlemen is mostly a matter of words rather than substance. Our practical ideals are quite similar; when we use the term "gentleman," we mean the same thing that the Catholic Church does. So, if we dig beneath the words that shape her teachings, there are few points on which we wouldn’t agree. But, sadly, words often carry a lot of weight.
How is it possible for myself, for example, to give people to understand that I believe in the doctrine of the Immaculate Conception or in the Lourdes miracles?[Pg 396] If the Pope could spare time to think about so insignificant a person, would he wish me to pretend such beliefs or think better of me if I did pretend them? I should be sorry to see him turn suddenly round and deny his own faith, and I am persuaded that, in like manner, he would have me continue to hold my own in peace; nevertheless, the duty of subordinating private judgment to the avoidance of schism is so obvious that, if we could see a practicable way of bridging the gulf between ourselves and Rome, we should be heartily glad to bridge it.
How can I, for example, make people understand that I believe in the doctrine of the Immaculate Conception or in the Lourdes miracles?[Pg 396] If the Pope had the time to think about someone as insignificant as me, would he want me to pretend to have such beliefs or think better of me if I did? I would hate to see him suddenly turn around and deny his own faith, and I believe he would want me to keep my beliefs in peace; however, the obligation to set aside personal judgment to avoid schism is so clear that if we could find a workable way to bridge the gap between us and Rome, we would be more than happy to do so.
I speak as though the Church of Rome was the only one we can look to. I do not see how it is easy to dispute this. Protestantism has been tried and failed; it has long ceased to grow, but it has by no means ceased to disintegrate. Note the manner in which it is torn asunder by dissensions, and the rancour which these dissensions engender—a rancour which finds its way into the political and social life of Europe, with incalculable damage to the health and well-being of the world. Who can doubt but that there will be a split even in the Church of England ere so many years are over? Protestantism is like one of those drops of glass which tend to split up into minuter and minuter fragments the moment the bond that united them has been removed. It is as though the force of gravity had lost its hold, and a universal power of repulsion taken the place of attraction. This may, perhaps, come about some day in the material as well as in the spiritual and political world, but the spirit of the age is as yet one of aggregation;[Pg 397] the spirit of Protestantism is one of disintegration. I maintain, therefore, that it is not likely to be permanent.
I talk as if the Catholic Church is the only option we have. I don't see how anyone can argue against this. Protestantism has been tried and it hasn't worked; it has stopped growing a long time ago, but it definitely hasn't stopped falling apart. Just look at how it's being torn apart by conflicts, and the bitterness these conflicts create—a bitterness that seeps into the political and social life of Europe, causing untold harm to the health and well-being of the world. Who can doubt that there will be a split even in the Church of England before long? Protestantism is like one of those glass shards that keeps breaking into smaller and smaller pieces the moment the force that holds them together is gone. It's as if gravity has let go, and a universal force of repulsion has taken over instead of attraction. This might eventually happen in both the material and spiritual or political worlds, but for now, the spirit of the age is about coming together; the spirit of Protestantism is about falling apart. Therefore, I argue that it is unlikely to last.
All the great powers of Europe have from numberless distinct tribes become first a few kingdoms or dukedoms, then two or three nations, and now homogeneous wholes, so that there is no chance of their further dismemberment through internal discontent; a process which has been going on for so many hundreds of years all over Europe is not likely to be arrested without ample warning. True, during the Roman Empire the world was practically bonded together, yet broke in pieces again; but this, I imagine, was because the bonding was prophetic and superficial rather than genuine. Nature very commonly makes one or two false starts, and misses her aim a time or two before she hits it. She nearly hit it in the time of Alexander the Great, but this was a short-lived success; in the case of the Roman Empire she succeeded better and for longer together. Where Nature has once or twice hit her mark as near as this she will commonly hit it outright eventually; the disruption of the Roman Empire, therefore, does not militate against the supposition that the normal condition of right-minded people is one which tends towards aggregation, or, in other words, towards compromise and the merging of much of one's own individuality for the sake of union and concerted action.
All the major powers in Europe have evolved from countless distinct tribes into a few kingdoms or duchies, then into two or three nations, and now into unified entities. There’s little chance of them breaking apart again due to internal unrest; this process, which has been happening for hundreds of years across Europe, is unlikely to stop without significant warning. It's true that during the Roman Empire, the world was largely connected, but it fell apart again. I think this happened because the connection was more of a prediction than a genuine bond. Nature often makes one or two missteps and misses its goal before finally succeeding. It almost succeeded during Alexander the Great's time, but that success was short-lived; in the case of the Roman Empire, it was more successful and for a longer period. When nature has come close to hitting its target this way, it usually eventually hits it dead on; thus, the breakdown of the Roman Empire doesn’t contradict the idea that the natural state of rational people tends toward unity, or in other words, towards compromise and giving up some of their own individuality for the sake of collaboration and collective action.
See, again, how Rome herself, within the limits of Italy, was an aggregation, an aggregation which has now within these last few years come together again after centuries of disruption; all middle-aged men have[Pg 398] seen many small countries come together in their own lifetime, while in America a gigantic attempt at disruption has completely failed. Success will, of course, sometimes attend disruption, but on the whole the balance inclines strongly in favour of aggregation and homogeneity; analogy points in the direction of supposing that the great civilized nations of Europe, as they are the coalition of subordinate provinces, so must coalesce themselves also to form a larger, but single empire. Wars will then cease, and surely anything that seems likely to tend towards so desirable an end deserves respectful consideration.
Look again at how Rome itself, within Italy’s borders, was a collection, a collection that has recently come together again after centuries of chaos; all middle-aged individuals have[Pg 398] witnessed many small nations unite in their own lifetime, while in America a massive attempt at division has completely failed. Success might, of course, sometimes accompany division, but overall, the trend leans heavily towards unity and sameness; it suggests that the great civilized nations of Europe, while they are a coalition of smaller regions, must also merge to create a larger, single empire. Wars would then end, and anything that seems likely to lead to such a desirable outcome deserves our serious thought.
The Church of Rome is essentially a unifier. It is a great thing that nations should have so much in common as the acknowledgment of the same tribunal for the settlement of spiritual and religious questions, and there is no head under which Christendom can unite with as little disturbance as under Rome. Nothing more tends to keep men apart than religious differences; this certainly ought not to be the case, but it no less certainly is, and therefore we should strain many points and subordinate our private judgment to a very considerable extent if called upon to do so. A man, under these circumstances, is right in saying he believes in much that he does not believe in. Nevertheless there are limits to this, and the Church of Rome requires more of us at present than we can by any means bring ourselves into assenting to.
The Church of Rome is fundamentally a unifier. It's a great thing that nations share so much in common, like recognizing the same authority for resolving spiritual and religious issues, and there’s no leader under whom Christianity can come together with as little disturbance as under Rome. Nothing keeps people apart more than religious differences; this really shouldn't be the case, but it definitely is. Therefore, we should try to stretch our beliefs and set aside our personal views to a significant degree if asked to do so. In this situation, it’s understandable for someone to say they believe in much that they don’t actually believe in. However, there are limits to this, and the Church of Rome currently asks more from us than we can realistically agree to.
It may be asked, Why have a Church at all? Why not unite in community of negation rather than of assertion? When I wrote 'Evolution, Old and New,' three[Pg 399] years ago, I thought, as now, that the only possible Church must be a development of the Church of Rome; and seeing no chance of agreement between avowed free-thinkers, like myself, and Rome (for I believed Rome immovable), I leaned towards absolute negation as the best chance for unity among civilized nations; but even then, I expressed myself as "having a strong feeling as though Professor Mivart's conclusion is true, that 'the material universe is always and everywhere sustained and directed by an infinite cause, for which to us the word mind is the least inadequate and misleading symbol.'"[384]
It might be asked, why even have a Church? Why not come together in a community that’s based on what we don’t believe rather than what we do? When I wrote 'Evolution, Old and New,' three[Pg 399] years ago, I thought, just like I do now, that the only possible Church has to come from the development of the Church of Rome; and seeing no chance for agreement between open-minded free-thinkers like myself and Rome (since I believed Rome wouldn't change), I leaned towards complete negation as the best way to unite civilized nations; but even back then, I expressed that I had a strong feeling that Professor Mivart's conclusion is true, that 'the material universe is always and everywhere sustained and directed by an infinite cause, which to us, the word mind is the least inadequate and misleading symbol.'[384]
I had hardly finished 'Evolution, Old and New,' before I began to deal with this question according to my lights, in a series of articles upon God[385] which appeared in the 'Examiner' during the summer of 1879, and I returned to the same matter more than once in 'Unconscious Memory,' my next succeeding work. The articles I intend recasting and rewriting, as they go upon a false assumption; but subsequent reflection has only confirmed me in the general result I arrived at—namely, the omnipresence of mind in the universe.
I had barely finished 'Evolution, Old and New' when I started tackling this question based on my perspective, in a series of articles about God[385] that were published in the 'Examiner' during the summer of 1879. I revisited the same topic more than once in 'Unconscious Memory,' my next book. I plan to revise and rewrite those articles since they’re based on a false assumption, but my later reflections have only reinforced the overall conclusion I reached—specifically, the omnipresence of mind in the universe.
I have therefore come to see that we can go farther than negation, and in this case—a positive expression of faith as regards an invisible universe of some sort being possible—a Church of some sort is also possible, which shall formulate and express the general convictions as regards man's position in respect of this faith. I think[Pg 400] the instinct which has led so many countries towards a double legislative chamber, and ourselves, till at any rate quite recently, to a double system of jurisprudence, law and equity, was not arrived at without having passed through the stages of reason and reflection. There are a variety of delicate, almost intangible, questions which belong rather to conscience than to law, and for which a Church is a fitter tribunal—at any rate for many ages hence—than a parliament or law court. There is room, therefore, for both a State and a Church, each of which should be influenced by the action of the other.
I’ve come to realize that we can go beyond just saying what we don’t believe, and in this case—a positive expression of faith in the possibility of some kind of invisible universe—there’s also the potential for some sort of Church. This Church would define and express the shared beliefs about humanity’s relationship to this faith. I believe[Pg 400] the instinct that has driven so many countries to adopt a bicameral legislature, and us, until fairly recently, to a dual system of law and equity, didn’t just happen randomly; it came after careful reasoning and reflection. There are many subtle, almost intangible, issues that relate more to conscience than to the law, and a Church is a more appropriate body to address them—at least for many generations to come—than a parliament or a courtroom. Therefore, there’s a place for both a State and a Church, with each one able to influence the other.
I do not say that I personally should like to see the Church of Rome as at present constituted in the position which I should be glad to see attained by an ideal Church. If it were in that position I would attack it to the utmost of my power; but I have little hesitation in thinking that the world with a very possible feasible Church, would be better than the world with no Church at all; and, if so, I have still less hesitation in concluding, for the reasons already given, that it is to Rome we must turn as the source from which the Church of the future is to be evolved, if it is to come at all.
I’m not saying that I personally want the Church of Rome as it currently exists to be in the position that I would love to see an ideal Church achieve. If it were in that position, I would challenge it with all my strength; but I have little doubt that a world with a feasible Church would be better than one with no Church at all. And if that’s the case, I have even less doubt, for the reasons I've already mentioned, that we must look to Rome as the source from which the Church of the future will emerge, if it’s going to emerge at all.
For the new, if it is to strike deep root and be permanent, must grow out of the old, without too violent a transition. Some violence there will always be, even in the kindliest birth; but the less the better, and a leap greater than the one from Judaism to Christianity is not desirable, even if it were possible. As a free-thinker, therefore, but also as one who wishes to take a practical view of the manner in which things will, and ought to go, I[Pg 401] neither expect to see the religions of the world come once for all to an end with the belief in Christianity—which to me is tantamount to saying with Rome—nor am I at all sure that such a consummation is more desirable than likely to come about. The ultimate fight will, I believe, be between Rome and Pantheism; and the sooner the two contending parties can be ranged into their opposite camps by the extinction of all intermediate creeds, the sooner will an issue of some sort be arrived at. This will not happen in our time, but we should work towards it.
For something new to really take root and be lasting, it has to grow out of what’s old, without a drastic shift. There will always be some level of conflict, even in the kindest of beginnings; but the less, the better. A jump larger than the one from Judaism to Christianity is not ideal, even if it were possible. So, as someone who thinks freely and also wants to have a practical view of how things will and should progress, I[Pg 401] don’t expect to see all the religions of the world come to an end because of a belief in Christianity—which for me is like saying because of Rome—nor am I certain that such an outcome is more desirable than likely. I believe the ultimate struggle will be between Rome and Pantheism; and the sooner the two sides can be divided into their opposing camps by getting rid of all the beliefs in between, the sooner we will reach some sort of resolution. This won’t happen in our lifetime, but we should work towards it.
When it arrives, what is to happen? Is Pantheism to absorb Rome, and, if so, what sort of a religious formula is to be the result? or is Rome so to modify her dogmas that the Pantheist can join her without doing too much violence to his convictions? We who are outside the Church's pale are in the habit of thinking that she will make little if any advances in our direction. The dream of a Pantheistic Rome seems so wild as hardly to be entertained seriously; nevertheless I am much mistaken if I do not detect at least one sign as though more were within the bounds of possibility than even the most sanguine of us could have hoped for a few years back. We do not expect the Church to go our whole length; it is the business of some to act as pioneers, but this is the last function a Church should assume. A Church should be as the fly-wheel of a steam-engine, which conserves, regulates and distributes energy, but does not originate it. In all cases it is more moral and safer to be a little behind the age than a little in front of it; a Church, therefore, ought to cling[Pg 402] to an old-established belief, even though her leaders know it to be unfounded, so long as any considerable number of her members would be shocked at its abandonment. The question is whether there are any signs as though the Church of Rome thought the time had come when she might properly move a step forward, and I rejoice to think, as I have said above, that at any rate one such sign—and a very important one—has come under my notice.
When it arrives, what will happen? Will Pantheism take over Rome, and if so, what kind of religious approach will emerge from it? Or will Rome change her beliefs enough so that Pantheists can join without compromising too much of their own beliefs? Those of us outside the Church tend to think she won't make much, if any, effort to reach out to us. The idea of a Pantheistic Rome seems so far-fetched that it’s hardly worth considering, yet I'm quite sure I see at least one sign suggesting that more is possible than even the most optimistic among us could have hoped for a few years ago. We don’t expect the Church to fully embrace our views; it's up to some to lead the way, but that's the last thing a Church should really take on. A Church should be like the flywheel of a steam engine, conserving, regulating, and distributing energy, but not creating it. In any case, it's generally more moral and safer to be a bit behind the times than to be a bit ahead of them; thus, a Church should hold onto well-established beliefs, even if its leaders know they're unfounded, as long as a significant number of members would be upset by their removal. The question is whether there are any signs that the Church of Rome thinks the time has come to take a step forward, and I’m glad to think, as I mentioned earlier, that at least one such sign—which is quite significant—has caught my attention.
In his Encyclical of August 4, 1879, the Pope desires the Bishops and Clergy to restore the golden wisdom of St. Thomas Aquinas, and to spread it far and wide. "Vos omnes," he writes, "Venerabiles Fratres, quam enixe hortamur ut ad Catholicæ fidei tutelam et decus, ad societatis bonum, ad scientiarum omnium incrementum auream Sancti Thomæ sapientiam restituatis, et quam latissime propagetis." He proceeds then with the following remarkable passage: "We say the wisdom of St. Thomas. For whatever has been worked out with too much subtleness by the doctors of the schools, or handed down inconsiderately, whatever is not consistent with the teachings of a later age, or finally, is in any way not probable, We in no wise intend to propose for acceptance in these days."[386]
In his Encyclical of August 4, 1879, the Pope urges the Bishops and Clergy to revive the valuable teachings of St. Thomas Aquinas and to share them widely. "You all," he writes, "Venerable Brothers, we strongly encourage you to restore the golden wisdom of St. Thomas for the protection and honor of the Catholic faith, for the good of society, and for the advancement of all knowledge, and to spread it as widely as possible." He then continues with the following noteworthy statement: "We refer to the wisdom of St. Thomas. For anything that has been overly complicated by the scholars of the schools, or carelessly passed down, anything that doesn't align with the teachings of later times, or is in any way unlikely, we do not intend to propose for acceptance in these days." [386]
It would be almost possible to suppose that these words had been written inadvertently, so the Pope practically repeats them thus: "We willingly and[Pg 403] gratefully declare that whatsoever can be excepted with advantage, is to be excepted, no matter by whom it has been invented."[387]
It might be easy to think that these words were written by accident, since the Pope nearly repeats them like this: "We gladly and gratefully declare that anything that can be exempted to our benefit should be exempted, regardless of who came up with it."
The passage just quoted is so pregnant that a few words of comment may be very well excused. In the first place, I cannot but admire the latitude which the Pope not only tolerates, but enjoins: he defines nothing, but declares point blank that if we find anything in St. Thomas Aquinas "not consistent with the assured teachings of a later age, or finally in any way not probable"—(what is not involved here?)—we are "in no wise to suppose" that it is being proposed for our acceptance. But it is a small step from allowing latitude in accepting or rejecting the parts of St. Thomas Aquinas which conflict with the assured result of later discoveries to allowing a similar latitude in respect, we will say, of St. Jude; and if of St. Jude, then of St. James the Less; and if of St. James the Less, then surely ere very long of St. James the Greater and St. John and St. Paul; nor will the matter stop there. How marvellously closely are the two extremes of doctrine approaching to one another! We, on the one hand, who begin with tabulæ rasæ having made a clean sweep of every shred of doctrine, lay hold of the first thing we can grasp with any firmness, and work back from it. We grope our way to evolution; through this to purposive evolution; through this to the omnipresence of mind and design throughout the universe; what is this but God? So that we can say with absolute freedom from[Pg 404] équivoque that we are what we are through the will of God. The theologian, on the other hand, starts with God, and finds himself driven through this to evolution, as surely as we found ourselves driven through evolution to the omnipresence of God.
The quoted passage is so rich that a little commentary is probably warranted. First of all, I can’t help but admire the open-mindedness that the Pope not only permits but encourages: he doesn’t define anything explicitly, but states clearly that if we find something in St. Thomas Aquinas that is "not consistent with the assured teachings of a later age, or finally in any unlikely way"—(what isn't included here?)—we are "in no wise to suppose" that it's being put forward for our acceptance. However, it’s a small leap from allowing flexibility in accepting or rejecting parts of St. Thomas Aquinas that contradict later discoveries to allowing similar flexibility regarding, say, St. Jude; and if for St. Jude, then also for St. James the Less; and if for St. James the Less, then surely soon for St. James the Greater, St. John, and St. Paul; and it won’t stop there. How incredibly close the two extremes of doctrine are becoming! We, on one side, who start with tabulæ rasæ having cleared out every bit of doctrine, grab whatever we can hold on to and work our way back from it. We feel our way to evolution; from this to purposeful evolution; from there to the presence of mind and design throughout the universe; what is that but God? So we can confidently say, without any [Pg 404] équivoque, that we are who we are through the will of God. The theologian, on the other hand, begins with God and finds himself led through evolution, just as we were led through evolution to recognize the omnipresence of God.
Let us look a little more closely at the ground which the Church of Rome and the Evolutionist hold in common. St. Paul speaks of there being "one body and one spirit," and of one God as being "above all, and through all, and in you all."[388] Again, he tells us that we are members of God's body, "of his flesh and of his bones;"[389] in another place he writes that God has reconciled us to himself, "in the body of his flesh,"[390] and in yet another of the Spirit of God "dwelling in us."[391] St. Paul indeed is continually using language which implies the closest physical as well as spiritual union between God and those at any rate of mankind who were Christians. Then he speaks of our "being builded together for an habitation of God through the spirit,"[392] and of our being "filled with the fulness of God."[393] He calls Christian men's bodies "temples of the Holy Spirit,"[394] in fact it is not too much to say that he regarded Christian men's limbs as the actual living organs of God himself, for the expressions quoted above—and many others could be given—come to no less than this. It follows that since any man could unite himself to "the flesh and bones" of God by becoming a Christian, Paul had a perception of the unity at any rate of human life; and what Paul[Pg 405] admitted I am persuaded the Church of Rome will not deny.
Let’s take a closer look at the common ground shared by the Church of Rome and Evolutionists. St. Paul mentions that there is "one body and one spirit," and one God who is "above all, through all, and in all."[388] He also says that we are members of God's body, "of his flesh and bones;"[389] in another passage, he writes that God has reconciled us to himself, "in the body of his flesh,"[390] and in yet another that the Spirit of God "dwells in us."[391] St. Paul consistently uses language that suggests a close physical as well as spiritual connection between God and those who are Christians. He mentions our "being built together for a habitation of God through the spirit,"[392] and being "filled with the fullness of God."[393] He refers to Christian bodies as "temples of the Holy Spirit,"[394] and in fact, it’s fair to say that he viewed the limbs of Christians as the actual living organs of God himself, as the expressions quoted above—and many others—suggest. Therefore, since any person could connect themselves to "the flesh and bones" of God by becoming a Christian, Paul had an understanding of the unity of human life; and what Paul[Pg 405] admitted, I am convinced the Church of Rome will not deny.
Granted that Paul's notion of the unity of all mankind in one spirit animating, or potentially animating the whole was mystical, I submit that the main difference between him and the Evolutionist is that the first uses certain expressions more or less prophetically, and without perhaps a full perception of their import; while the second uses the same expressions literally, and with the ordinary signification attached to the words that compose them. It is not so much that we do not hold what Paul held, but that we hold it with the greater definiteness and comprehension which modern discovery has rendered possible. We not only accept his words, but we extend them, and not only accept them as articles of faith to be taken on the word of others, but as so profoundly entering into our views of the world around us that that world loses the greater part of its significance if we may not take such sayings as that "we are God's flesh and his bones" as meaning neither more nor less than what appears upon the face of them. We believe that what we call our life is part of the universal life of the Deity—which is literally and truly made manifest to us in flesh that can be seen and handled—ever changing, but the same yesterday, and to-day, and for ever.
Granted that Paul's idea of the unity of all humanity in one spirit that motivates or could potentially motivate everyone is mystical, I suggest that the main difference between him and the Evolutionist is that Paul uses certain expressions somewhat prophetically, perhaps without fully grasping their meaning, while the Evolutionist uses the same expressions literally, with their usual definition. It’s not so much that we don’t share Paul’s beliefs, but rather that we approach them with greater clarity and understanding made possible by modern discoveries. We not only accept his words but also expand on them, and we don't just take them as articles of faith based on others’ word, but as concepts that deeply influence our understanding of the world around us; without these ideas, the world loses much of its meaning. We believe that what we call our life is part of the universal life of the Deity—which is literally and truly revealed to us in the physical, tangible flesh—constantly changing, yet the same yesterday, today, and forever.
So much for the closeness with which we have come together on matters of fact, and now for the rapprochement between us in respect of how much conformity is required for the sake of avoiding schism. We find ourselves driven through considerations of great obviousness[Pg 406] and simplicity to the conclusion that a man both may and should keep no small part of his opinions to himself, if they are too widely different from those of other people for the sake of union and the strength gained by concerted action; and we also find the Pope declaring of one of the brightest saints and luminaries of the Church that we need not follow him when it is plainly impossible for us to do so. Is it so very much to hope that ere many years are over the approximation will become closer still?
We've come together on facts, and now let's talk about the compromise we need to avoid division. It's pretty clear and simple that a person can and should keep some opinions to themselves if they differ too much from others, in order to maintain unity and the strength that comes from working together. The Pope has even stated that we don't have to follow one of the Church's greatest saints and leaders when it's clearly impossible for us to do so. Is it too much to hope that in a few years we'll get even closer?
I have sometimes imagined that the doctrine of Papal Infallibility may be the beginning of a way out of the difficulty, and that its promoters were so eager for it, rather for the facilities it afforded for the repealing of old dogmas than for the imposition of new ones. The Pope cannot, even now, under any circumstances, declare a dogma of the Church to be obsolete or untrue, but I should imagine he can, in council, ex cathedra, modify the interpretation to be put upon any dogma, if he should find the interpretation commonly received to be prejudicial to the good of the Church: and if so, the manner in which Rome can put herself more in harmony with the spirit of recent discoveries, without putting herself in an illogical position, is not likely to escape eyes so keen as those of the Catholic hierarchy. No sensible man will hesitate to admit that many an interpretation which was natural to and suitable for one age is unnatural to and unsuitable for another; as circumstances are always changing, so men's moods and the meanings they attach to words, and the state of their knowledge changes; and hence, also, the interpretation[Pg 407] of the dogmas in which their conclusions are summarized. There is nothing to be ashamed of or that needs explaining away in this; nothing can remain changeless under changed conditions; and that institution is most likely to be permanent which contains provision for such changes as time may prove to be expedient, with the least disturbance. I can see nothing, therefore, illogical or that needs concealment in the fact of an infallible Pope putting a widely different interpretation upon a dogma now, to what a no less infallible Pope put upon the same dogma fifteen hundred, or even fifteen years ago; it is only right, reasonable, and natural that this should be so. The Church of England may have made no provision for the virtual pruning off of dogmas that have become rudimentary, but the Encyclical from which I have just quoted leads me to think that the Church of Rome has found one, and, in her own cautious way, is proceeding to make use of it. If so, she may possibly in the end get rid of Protestantism by putting herself more in harmony with the spirit of the age than Protestantism can do. In this case, the spiritual reunion of Christendom under Rome ceases to be impossible, or even, I should think improbable. I heartily wish that my conjecture concerning future possibilities is not unfounded.
I have sometimes thought that the idea of Papal Infallibility could be a way out of the problem and that its supporters were more interested in repealing old doctrines than imposing new ones. Even now, the Pope can't declare a Church doctrine to be outdated or false, but I believe he can, in council, ex cathedra, change how any doctrine is interpreted if he sees that the current interpretation is harmful to the Church. If that's the case, the way Rome can align itself more with modern understandings, without creating contradictions, is likely to catch the attention of the Catholic leadership. No reasonable person would deny that many interpretations that made sense in one era might be out of place in another; as circumstances change, so do people's attitudes, the meanings they assign to words, and their level of knowledge, and this affects how they interpret[Pg 407] the doctrines that summarize their beliefs. There's no shame or need for justification in this; nothing can stay the same under different conditions; the institution most likely to endure is one that allows for necessary changes with minimal disruption. Therefore, I see nothing illogical or needing concealment in the fact that an infallible Pope today could interpret a doctrine very differently than another infallible Pope did fifteen hundred or even fifteen years ago; it simply makes sense and is natural. The Church of England may not have provisions for the gradual removal of outdated doctrines, but the Encyclical I just quoted suggests that the Church of Rome has found a way to do this and is cautiously beginning to implement it. If that’s true, she might ultimately overcome Protestantism by aligning herself more closely with the spirit of the times than Protestantism can. In this scenario, a spiritual reunion of Christendom under Rome becomes possible, or even, I would say, likely. I sincerely hope my speculations about future possibilities are not unfounded.
Scientists have been right in preaching evolution, but they have preached it in such a way as to make it almost as much of a stumbling-block as of an assistance. For though the fact that animals and plants are descended from a common stock is accepted by the greater and more reasonable part of mankind, these same people[Pg 408] feel that the evidence in favour of design in the universe is no less strong than that in favour of evolution, and our scientists, for the most part, uphold a theory of evolution of which the cardinal doctrine is that design and evolution have nothing to do with one another; the jar they raise, therefore, is as bad as the jar they have allayed.
Scientists have been correct in advocating for evolution, but they have approached it in a way that often creates as many obstacles as it removes. While most reasonable people accept that animals and plants share a common ancestry, these same individuals[Pg 408] believe that the evidence for design in the universe is just as compelling as the evidence for evolution. However, most scientists promote a theory of evolution that claims design and evolution are unrelated; thus, the confusion they cause is just as problematic as the confusion they attempt to resolve.
It has been the object of the foregoing work to show that those who take this line are wrong, and that evolution not only tolerates design, but cannot get on without it. The unscrupulousness with which I have been attacked, together with the support given me by the general public, are sufficient proofs that I have not written in vain.
It has been the goal of the earlier work to demonstrate that those who follow this path are mistaken, and that evolution not only accepts design but also cannot function without it. The harsh criticism I have faced, along with the support I’ve received from the general public, are strong evidence that I have not written in vain.
FOOTNOTES:
[386] "Sapientiam Sancti Thomæ dicimus: si quid enim est a doctoribus scholasticis vel nimia subtilitate quæsitum, vel parum considerate traditum, si quid cum exploratis posterioris ævi doctrinis minus cohærens, vel denique quoque modo non probabile, id nullo pacto in animo est ætate nostra ad imitandum proponi."
[386] "We talk about the wisdom of Saint Thomas: if there’s something questioned by the scholastic teachers with too much subtlety, or presented without enough consideration, if something doesn’t align well with established teachings from the later times, or in any other way seems questionable, we definitely do not intend to adopt that in our time."
[388] Eph. iv. 3, 4, 5.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Eph. 4:3-5.
[389] Eph. v. 30.
[390] Col. i. 22.
[391] Rom. viii. 2.
[392] Eph. ii. 22.
[393] Eph. iii. 19.
[394] 1 Cor. vii. 19.
ABORTION, neutralization of working bees an act of, 250
Accessory touches, varying Buffon on, 92
Accident, many of our best thoughts come thoughtlessly, 48, 384
—— profiting by, 51, 53
—— and discovery of theory connecting meteors with comets, 53
—— shaking the bag to see what will come out, 53
—— effects of, transmitted to offspring, Dr. Erasmus Darwin, 224
—— and design, the line between these hard to draw, 384
Accidental variations thrown for as with dice, 3
Accumulation of variations, C. Darwin deals with the, and not with the origin of, 340, 341
—— of small divergencies, Buffon on the, 103
Accurate, survival of fittest more accurate than Nat. Sel. and sometimes equally convenient, 9, 354, 365
Act of Parliament, Natural Selection compared to a certain kind of, 358
Age, old, the phenomena of, 67, 204, 381
Aggregation, the spirit of the age tends towards, 397, 398
Ahead, no organism sees very far, 44, 48, 54, 384
Aldrovandus, Buffon on the learned, 93
Alive, when we must not say that an animal is alive (to be retracted), 279
Allen, Grant, on 'Evolution, Old and New,' 386-388
—— on the decay of criticism, 388
—— calls Evolutionism "an almost exclusively English impulse," 393
Alternations of fat and lean years, Buffon on, 125
Amœba, the, did not conceive the idea of an eye and work towards it, 43, 44, 384
Analogies, false, all words are apt to turn out to be, 365
Animals, contracts among, Dr. E. Darwin on, 205
Ape, the, and man, 90
Apes and monkeys, Buffon on, 153
—— and children fall on all-fours at the approach of danger, 312
Apparentibus, de non, et non existentibus, &c., 36
Appearances, rather superficial, our only guide to classification, 34, 35, 36, 198, 204
Appetency, Paley's argument against the view that structures have been developed through, 22, 45
Aristides, C. Darwin as just as, 363
Aristotle denied teleology, 4
Artificial and real foot, differences between, 25
Asceticism, virtue errs on the side of excess rather than on that of, 35
Ass, the, and horse, Buffon's pregnant passage on their relationship, 80, 90, 91, 100, 101, 142, 143, 155, 164, 311
[Pg 410]Authority, a hard thing to weigh, 253
BACON, F., on evolution, 69
Balzac, quotation from, on memory and instinct, 67
Bark, Erasmus Darwin's theory of, 208
Beaver, trowel incorporated into the beaver's organism, 8
Bees, neutralization of working, an act of abortion, 250
Beetles, Madeira, Lamarck and C. Darwin's views of their winglessness compared, 373, 380
Begin, How could the eye begin? 46, 47
Beginnings, of complex structures, a difficulty in the way of natural selection, 21, 22
—— difficulty of accounting for, 46, 47
—— a matter of conjecture and inference, 48
Behind, more moral to be behind the age than in front of it, 401
Best, making the best of whatever power one has, 50
Bird, how birds became web-footed, 48, 49, 51
—— a, will modify its nest a little, under altered circumstances, 55
—— Buffon on, 170, &c.
—— nests, Dr. Erasmus Darwin's failure to connect the power to make them with memory, 201, 203
—— aquatic and wading, Lamarck on, 305
Bishop, and Evêque, common derivation of, 355
Blindfolded, we are so far, that we can see a few steps in front, but no more, 44
—— us, C. Darwin has almost ostentatiously, 346
Blindly, forces interacting blindly, 59
Body and mind, Lamarck on, 338, 339, 341
Brain, Lamarck had brain upon the brain, 36
—— Buffon on the, 131, 133, &c.
Brevity may be the soul of wit, but, &c., 315
Breeding, and feeding, 222
Brown-Séquard, his experiments on guinea-pigs' legs, 303
Buds, individuality of, Dr. Erasmus Darwin on the, 207, 208
Buffalo, Buffon on the, 148, &c.
Buffon, profoundly superficial, 34
—— plus il a su, plus il a pu, &c., 44
—— dans l'animal il y a moins de jugement que de sentiment, 51
—— ignorance concerning, 61
—— memoir of, 74, &c.
—— on glory, genius, and style, 76, 77
—— ironical character of his work and method (see Irony), 78, &c., 171
—— on the ass, horse, and zebra, 80, 90, 91, 100, 101, 142, 143, 155, 164, 311
—— would not play the part of Rousseau or Voltaire, 81
—— Sir W. Jardine on, and the Sorbonne, 82
—— regards all animal and vegetable life as from one common source, 90
—— if a single species has ever been found under domestication, &c., 91
—— on plaisanterie, and the learned Aldrovandus, 93, &c.
—— his compromise, 92
—— accessory touches, 92
—— "especially" the same, 96
—— fluctuation of opinion an unfounded charge, 97, &c., 164
—— on the accumulation of small divergencies, 103
—— began preaching evolution almost on his first page, 104
—— chapter on the dégénération des animaux, equivalent to "on descent with modification," 104, &c.
—— difference of opinion between him and Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck, 105
—— probably did not differ from Lamarck, 105
[Pg 411]—— on direct action of changed conditions, 105, 145, 147
—— on man and the lower animals, 108
—— on classification, 108, 109, 141
—— on animals and plants, 109, 110
—— on reason and instinct, 110, 115
—— on final causes (the pig), 118, &c.
—— on hybridism, 117, 118
—— rudimentary organs, 120
—— on animals under domestication, 121, &c., 148
—— deals with these early, as giving him the best opportunities for illustrating the theory of evolution, 276
—— approaches natural selection in his "by some chance common enough in Nature," 122
—— preaching on the hare when he should have preached on the rabbit out of pure love of mischief, 123
—— resumption of feral characteristics, 123
—— on the geometrical ratio of increase, 123, &c.
—— alternation of fat and lean years, 125
—— equilibrium of Nature, 125
—— "au réel," 126
—— on violent death, 126
—— on sensation, 126, &c.
—— on the interaction of organ and sense, 127
—— the carnivora, 126
—— his criterion of what name a thing is to bear, 127
—— his criterion of perception and sensation, 127
—— on the unity of the individual, 127, 128
—— satirizes our habit of judging all things by our own standards, 129
—— the diaphragm, 129
—— on the stock and the diaphragm, 130
—— distinction between perception and sensation, 129, 130
—— on the meninges, 132
—— on the brain, 131, 133, &c.
—— on scientific orthodoxy and mystification, 138
—— on the relativity of science, 140
—— on nomenclature and knowledge, 141
—— on the genus felis, 143
—— on the lion and the tiger, 143, 145
—— on the animals of the old and new world, 145, &c.
—— on changed geographical distribution of land and water, 145, 164
—— on extinct species, 146
—— hates the new world, 146
—— on heredity and habit, 148, 159, 160, 161, 162
—— approaches Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck, re the Buffalo, Camel, and Llama, 148, 160, 161
—— on oneness of personality between parents and offspring, 151
—— on the organic and inorganic, 153, &c.
—— on apes and monkeys, 153, &c.
—— on the causes or means of the transformation of species, 159, &c.
—— on generic (as well as specific) differences, 164
—— on plants under domestication, 167
—— on pigeons and fowls, 169
—— on birds, 170, &c.
—— the assistance he rendered to Lamarck, 237, 258
—— Isidore Geoffroy's failure to understand, 328
—— Colonel, 75
Bulk, a sine quâ non for success in literature or science, 315
Bull running, Tutbury, and Erasmus Darwin, 187
CAMEL, Buffon on the hereditary ills of the, 161
Cant, and rudimentary organs, 38
[Pg 412]Captandum, all good things are done ad, 85
Carnivora, Buffon on the, 126
Carriage, Dr. Erasmus Darwin's, 181
Cat, family, Buffon on the, 142, &c.
—— with a mane and long tail, 143
Cataclysms, the good cells that get exterminated during the cataclysms of our own development, 75
Catastrophes, Lamarck on, 277
Causes, or "means," of modification, 301
—— C. Darwin says that Buffon has not entered on the, 104, &c.
—— C. Darwin gets us into a fog about, 345, &c.
Change, under changed circumstances, Mr. Patrick Matthew on, 318
Charity, the greatest of these is, 77
Church, a, like a second chamber, 400
—— the world better with than without, 400
—— should be like the fly-wheel of a steam engine, 104
Circonstances (see Conditions of Existence), Lamarck on, 268, 281
Circumstance, suiting power, a, Mr. Patrick Matthew on, 318-321
Classification, rather superficial appearances our best guide to, 34, 35, 36, 198, 204
—— Buffon on, 108, 109, 141
Clear, an ineradicable tendency to make things, 92
Clifford, Professor, on "Design," 6, 7
Climbing plants, the movements of, Dr. Erasmus Darwin on, 209
Coherency, the persistency of ideas the best argument in support of their legitimate connection, 23
Coleridge, on "Darwinising," 21
Common terms, our, involve the connection between memory and heredity, 201, 205
—— descent, the "hidden bond" of Lamarck, as also of C. Darwin, 271
Comparative anatomy, Lamarck on, 266, &c.
Complex structures, the incipiency of, a difficulty in the way of the natural selection view of evolution, 21, 22
Compromise, Buffon's, 92
Conditions of existence, the very essence of condition involves that there shall be penalty in case of non-fulfilment, 352, 376, 377
—— and the winglessness of Madeira beetles, 373, &c.
—— according to C. Darwin, "include" and yet "are fully embraced by" natural selection, 355
—— identical with "natural selection," 351-354
—— Étienne Geoffroy, and Lamarck on, 326, 327, 328
—— Buffon on the, 103;
difference between Buffon's and Lamarck's view of their action, 105
—— direct action of changed, Buffon on the, 145, 147, 160
—— Lamarck on, 105, 268, 270, 271, 275, 277, 278, 281, 291, 292, 294, 295, 298, 299, 300, &c.
Continuity in discontinuity, and vice versâ, 47
Contracts of animals, Dr. E. Darwin on the, 205
Contrivance, does organism show signs of this? 2
Convenient, not only sometimes, but always, more, 365
Corkscrew for corks, and lungs for respiration, Prof. Clifford on, 7. See also p. 58
—— we should have grown a, if drawing corks had been important to us, 7
Creator, a, who is not an organism, unintelligible, 6, 11, 24
Criticising, difficulty of, without knowing more than the mere facts which are to be criticised, 172
Criticism, Miss Seward's, on Dr. Darwin's "Elegy," 189
[Pg 413]—— Grant Allen on the decay of, 388
Crux, the, of the early evolutionist, 35
Cuttle-fish, natural selection like the secretion of a, 332
DAMNATION, praising with faint, 111
Darwin, Charles, on the eye, denies design, 8
—— declares variation to be the cause of variation, 8, 347, 369
—— and blind chance working on whither; the accumulation of innumerable lucky accidents, 41, 42
—— our indebtedness to, 62, 66, 335
—— has adopted one half of Isidore Geoffroy's conclusion without verifying either, 83
—— on Buffon's fluctuation of opinion, 97
—— on Isidore Geoffroy, 97
—— his assertion that Buffon has not entered on the "causes or means" of transformation, 104
—— his meagre notice of his grandfather, 196
—— his treatment of the author of the "Vestiges of Creation," 65, 247, 248
—— attributes the characteristics of neuter insects to natural selection, 249
—— his treatment of Lamarck, 249, 250, 251, 298, 314, 376
—— "great is the power of steady misrepresentation," 251
—— his "happy simplicity" about animals and plants under domestication, 276
—— his notice of Mr. Patrick Matthew in the imperfect historical sketch which he has prefaced to the "Origin of Species,"
315, 316
—— points of agreement between him and Lamarck, 335-337
—— sees no broad principle underlying variation, 339
—— dwells on the accumulation of variations, the origination of which he leaves unaccounted for, 340, 341
—— his variations being due to no general underlying principle, will not tend to appear in definite directions, nor to many individuals at a time, nor to be constant for long together, 342
—— speaks of natural selection as a cause of modification, while declaring it to be a means only, 345, &c.
—— his explanation of this, 384, &c.
—— his dilemma, as regards the "Origin of Species," 346
—— declares the fact of variation to be the cause of variation, 8, 347, 369
—— if he had told us more of what Buffon, &c., said, and where they were wrong, he would have taken a course, &c., 357
—— on the ease with which we can hide our ignorance under a cloud of words, 358
—— apologizes for having underrated the frequency and importance of variation due to spontaneous variability, 358
—— his "Origin of Species" like the opinion of a lawyer who wanted to leave loopholes, or an Act of Parliament full of repealed and inserted clauses, 358
—— accused of confusion and inaccuracy of thought, 359
—— as just as Aristides himself, 364
—— most candid literary opponent in the world, 364
—— declares Nature to be the most important means of modification, and variation to be the cause of variations, 369
—— like a will-o'-the-wisp, 372
[Pg 414]—— disuse, the main agent in reducing wings of Madeira beetles, 377
—— how he and Lamarck treat the winglessness of Madeira beetles respectively, 373-380
—— an example of his "manner," 378
—— the way in which he met "Evolution, Old and New," 393
Darwin, Erasmus, never quite recognized design, 39
—— ignorance concerning, 61
—— on reason and instinct, 115, &c.
—— life of, 173, &c.
—— in Nottingham market-place, 182, 184, 197
—— and Dr. Johnson, 184, 185
—— and Tutbury bull running, 187
—— his poetry about the pump, and illustration, 84, 193
—— should have given his evolution theory a book to itself, 197
—— had no wish to see far beyond the obvious, 197
—— must be admitted to have missed detecting Buffon's humour, 83, 84, 197
—— did not attribute instincts and structures to memory pure and simple, 198
—— on the reasoning powers of animals, and on instinct, 201, 205
—— his failure to connect memory and instinct, as with birds' nests, 201-203
—— failed to see the four main propositions which I contended for in "Life and Habit," 37, 203, 204
—— on the analogies between animal and vegetable life, 206, &c.
—— on sensitive plants, 206, 210
—— on the individuality of buds, and his theory of bark, 207, 208
—— on the movements of climbing plants, 209
—— on the oneness of personality between parents and offspring, 214;
the embryo not a new animal, 215
—— on animals under domestication, 223
—— on the effects of accidents transmitted to offspring, 224
—— sees struggle, and hence modification, turn mainly round three great wants, 226, 229, 257, 279
—— on desire as a means of modification, 226, 228, 259
—— by a slip approaches the error of his grandson, 227, 228
—— on embryonic metamorphoses, 230, 231
—— believed animals and plants to be descended from a common stock, 233
—— and Lamarck compared, 257
—— on the struggle of existence, and the survival of the fittest, 227, 232, 259
Darwin, Mrs. Erasmus, death-bed of, 178
Darwin, Francis, mentioned, 109
—— his interesting lecture, 206
—— does not use the expression "natural selection," 368
Darwinising, Coleridge on, 21
Darwinism, the old Darwinism involves desire, invention, and design, 58
—— modern, falling into disfavour, 60
—— and evolution not to be confounded, 360, 361
Day, the portrait of, by Wright of Derby, 180
Death, violent, Buffon on, 126
—— of Dr. Erasmus Darwin, 193, 194
Death-bed of Mrs. Erasmus Darwin, 178
Deed, illustration drawn from a very intricate, 28
Definite, with Lamarck the variations are, 341, 344
Dégénérations, 87
Demand and supply, like power and desire, 222, 300
[Pg 415]Demonstrative case, "this demonstrative case of neuter insects, &c.," 249, 298, 314
Descent, with modification, spoken of as though synonymous with natural selection, 248, 356
Design, and organism, shall we or shall we not connect these ideas? 2
—— Aristotle denied, Plato upheld, Haeckel on, 4
—— Prof. Clifford's denial of, 6, 7
—— does certainly involve a designer who has an organism, who can think, and make mistakes, 6, 24
—— a belief in both design and evolution, commonly held to be incompatible, 9
—— Sir W. Thomson and Sir J. Herschel on, 11
—— Paley on, 12, &c.
—— light thrown by embryology on the method of, 25
—— G. H. Lewes opposes, 26
—— the three positions in respect to, taken by Charles Darwin, Paley, and the earlier evolutionists, 31
—— the first evolutionists did not see that their view of evolution involved design, 34
—— from within as much design as from without, 36
—— was equivalent to theological design, with the early evolutionists, 36
—— if each step is taken designedly, the whole is done designedly, 52, 384
—— and accident, the line between them hard to draw; shaking the bag, &c., 53, 384
—— instinct originated in, 54
—— as much lost sight of with old-established forms of the steam-engine as with birds' nests or the wheel, 55
—— Dr. E. Darwin's failure to see that evolution involves design, 195
—— we feel the want of, as much as we do of evolution, 407
—— evolution not only tolerates, but cannot get on without, 408
Designer, "I believe in an organic and tangible designer of every complex structure," 6
—— "where is he? show him to us," &c., 29, 30
—— the, of any organism, the organism itself, 30, 31, 40
Desire and power, interaction of, 44, 45, 47, 127, 217, 221, 300, 322
—— and power, like wealth, 222
—— as a means of modification, Dr. Erasmus Darwin on, 226, 228, 259
Development, the history of organic, the history of a moral struggle, 45
—— always due to making the best of the present, 50
Devils, 20,000, dancing a saraband on the point of a needle, 216
Dew drop, or lens, the, and Lord Rosse's telescope, 44, 47
Diaphragm, Buffon on the, 129
Dice, accidental variations thrown for as with, 3
Difference between animal and ordinary mechanism, 24
—— the main, between the manufacture of tools and that of organs, 39
Dilemma, C. Darwin's, 346
Direct action of changed conditions, Buffon on the, 105, 145, 147, 160
Discontinuity in continuity, 47
Disease, accidents followed by, 303
Disintegration, Protestantism tends towards, 397
Distribution, geographical, changed, Buffon on, 145, 164
Disuse, and the winglessness of Madeira beetles, we are almost surprised to find that they are connected at all, 375
—— the main agent in reducing the wings of Madeira beetles, 377
[Pg 416]—— some examples of the effect of, adduced by Lamarck, 378
Dog, Buffon on the, 120
—— Lamarck on the various breeds of the, 297
Domestication, a single case of a species formed under domestication sufficient to remove the à priori difficulty from a comprehensive theory of evolution, 90, 91, 311
—— plants under, Buffon on, 167, &c.
—— Buffon on animals under, 103, 120, &c., 148, &c., 159, &c., 276
—— animals under, Dr. Erasmus Darwin on, 223
—— animals under, Buffon on, 121, &c., 148, 276
—— C. Darwin on, 276
—— animals and plants under, Lamarck on, 275, 293, 296, 297, 300
—— animals and plants under, Mr. Patrick Matthew on, 324
Door, the doing anything well will open the door for doing something else, 51
Ducks, our domesticated, why they cannot fly like wild ones, 296, 309
EARN, "you are but doing your best to earn an honest living," 29
Ears are never found in a rudimentary condition, 379
Eat, or be eaten, 177
Effort, Paley's argument that structures have not been developed through, 22, 45
—— too much, as vicious as indolence, 35
—— "neither too much nor too little," 50
—— Herculean, condemned, 197
Egyptian mummies, Lamarck on, 274, 275
Embryology, the light it throws upon the mode in which organisms have been designed, 25
Embryonic metamorphoses, Erasmus Darwin on, 230, 231
Embryonic development, Lamarck on, 289
Encyclical, the Pope's, on St. Thomas Aquinas, 402, &c.
Endeavour, Paley's argument against the view that structures have been developed through, 22, 45
Endowment, the new orthodoxy, which is clamouring for, 360
English wines, Dr. Erasmus Darwin's preference for, 175
Environment. See Conditions of Existence
Equilibrium, the, of Nature, Buffon on the, 125
Err, the power to, rated highly, 29
—— "it is on this margin that we may err or wander," 50
—— virtue ever errs on the side of excess, 35
Error, importance of, dependent on the distance, rather than the direction, 50
"Especially" the same, 92, 96
Ethiopian, the, can change his skin, if it becomes worth his while to try long enough, 40
Evêque and bishop, common derivation of, 355
Everlasting, God, how far, 32
Evolution, commonly held incompatible with design, 9
—— Paley, its first serious opponent in England, 21
—— Sir Walter Raleigh on, 21, 70
—— must stand or fall according as it rests on a purposive foundation or no, 60
—— brief summary of its six principal stages, 62, &c.
—— Bacon on, 69
—— the theory of, as apart from the evidence in support of it, 332
—— C. Darwin and Lamarck are equally intent upon establishing the same theory of evolution, 335-337
—— and Darwinism, not to be confounded, 360, 361
[Pg 417]—— Rome and Pantheism meet in, 403
Evolutionists, the early, did not know that they accepted teleology, 34
—— the early, saw design, only as design by the God of theologians, 36
Experience and instinct, Mr. Patrick Matthew on, 322
Extinct species, Lamarck on, 277
—— Buffon on, 146, 277
Eye, no creature that had nothing like an eye ever set itself to conceive one and grow one, 44, 387
—— Paley asks "how will our philosopher get an eye?" 46
—— of flat fish, Lamarck on the, 307
—— Lamarck on the, of underground and cave-inhabiting animals, 378
—— disappear and reappear in the scale of organism according to the power of using them, 379
FAITH, forms of, or faiths of form, &c., 339
Familiarity, with a little, such superficial objections will be forgotten, 367
Far ahead, no organism ever saw an improvement a long way off and made towards it, 43, 44, 48, 49, 54, 384
Father, the man who could be father of such a son and retain his affection, &c., 76
Factors, there have been two, of modification, one producing and the other accumulating variations, 227
Fecundity, alternate years of, Buffon on, 125
Feeding and breeding, 222
Feel, if plants and animals look as if they feel, let us say they feel, 198
Feeling, there is more feeling than reason in animals, 51
Feral characteristics, resumption of, Buffon on, 123
Final causes, the doctrine of, as commonly held in the time of the early evolutionists, 34, 36
—— Buffon on, 118, &c.
Fitness, the cause of, more important than the fact that fitness is commonly fit, and therefore successful, 351
Flat fish, Lamarck on the eyes of, 307
Fluctuation of opinion, C. Darwin on Buffon's, the charge refuted, 97, &c., 164, 166
Fontenelle, on theories, 22
Foot, and model of foot, differences between, 24
Forms of faith, or faiths of form, &c., 339
Four main points which the early evolutionists failed to see in their connection and bearing on each other, 37, 203
Four main principles, the, which I contended for in "Life and Habit," 37, 203, 380, 381
Fowls and pigeons, Buffon on, 169
GARNETT, Mr. R., and "Darwinising," 21
Genius, Mr. Allen says I am a, 388
Gentleman, the Church of Rome means the same by the word as we do, 395
Geoffroy, Étienne, how small a way he goes, 196
—— and Isidore, trimmers, 328
—— on Buffon, 328
—— on conditions of existence, 326, 327
—— declares against Lamarck's hypothesis, 328
—— his position, 325-328
Geoffroy, Isidore, on evolution and final causes, 9
—— on Buffon's fluctuation of opinion, 98, &c., 164, 166
—— points out the difference between the views of Buffon and Lamarck, 105
[Pg 418]—— statement that Buffon's opinions fluctuated again refuted, 166
—— and Lamarck's hypothesis, 244-246, 329
—— on Buffon, 328
—— his position, 329
Genealogical order, Lamarck on, 264
—— C. Darwin on, 265
Generation more remarkable than reason, Hume on, 233
Generic differences (as well as specific), Buffon on, 164
Genius, a supreme capacity for taking pains, 76
Geographical distribution, changed, Buffon on, 145, &c., 164
Geometrical ratio of increase, Buffon on, 123
—— Lamarck, on, 280
—— Patrick Matthew on, 320, 321
Germ of oak indistinguishable from that of a man, 334
Germans, Buffon on the, 93
Glory "comes after labour if she can," &c., 76
Go away, because their uncles, aunts, 376
God, embodied in living forms, and dwelling in them, 31
—— how far everlasting, invisible, imperishable, omnipotent, &c., 32
—— the unseen parts of, are as a deep-buried history, 33
Goethe, as an evolutionist, 71
Gradations infinitely subtle, 87
Grant Allen, on "Evolution, Old and New," 386-388
—— on the decay of criticism, 388
—— says that "Evolutionism is an almost exclusively English impulse," 393
Greyhound or racehorse, the well-adapted form of the, 359
Growth attended at each step by a felicitous tempering of two antagonistic principles, 35
Gueneau de Montbeillard, 172, 173
HABIT," "Life and. See "Life and Habit."
—— rudimentary organs repeated through mere force of, 38, 39
—— Buffon on, 148, 159, 160, 161, 162
—— a second Nature, Lamarck on, 300
Habits, or use, and organ, Lamarck on the interaction of, 292, 311
Haeckel, on design, 4, 5
—— on Goethe as an evolutionist, 71
—— does not appear to know of Buffon as an evolutionist, 71, 393
—— his surprising statement concerning Lamarck, 73
—— his ignorance concerning Erasmus Darwin, 73, 393
—— on Lamarck, 246, 247
—— A. R. Wallace's review of his "Evolution of Man," 382, 384
Hamlet, the "Origin of Species" like "Hamlet" without Hamlet, 363
Handiest, a man should do whatever comes handiest, 51, 52
Hare, Buffon on the, 123, &c.
Hartmann's philosophy of the unconscious, and "Life and Habit," 56, 57
Hearing, when we once reach animals so low as to have no organ of, we lose this organ for good and all, 379
Heredity and habit, Buffon on, 148, 159, 160, 161, 162
—— only another term for unknown causes, unless the "Life and Habit" theory be adopted, 384
Hering, Professor, referred to, 66, 67
—— his theory as given in "Nature" by Ray Lankester, 198-200
Herschel, Sir John, compares natural selection to the Laputan method of making books, 10
Higgling and haggling of the market, 50
[Pg 419]History of the universe, each organism is a, from its own point of view, 31
Horse and ass, Buffon's most pregnant passage on the, 80, 90, 91, 100, 101, 142, 143, 155, 164, 311
—— and man, skeleton of the, 88, 89
—— and zebra, Buffon on the, example of irony, 80, 155, 164
Hume, his saying that generation is more remarkable than reason, 233
Huxley, Professor, referred to, 93
—— pointed out to Professor Mivart the difficulty in the way of natural selection, 344
—— his ignorance concerning the earlier history of evolution, 392, 393
Hybridism, Buffon on, 117, 118
Hybrids, sterility of, Lamarck on, and C. Darwin on, 272, 273
IDEAS, the bond or nexus of our, 23, 29, 30
Ignorance, the prevailing, concerning the earlier evolutionists, 61
—— it is easy to hide our, under such expressions as "plan of creation," or natural selection, 358
Imitation, instinct not referable to, as maintained by Erasmus Darwin, 202
Immutability of species and design commonly accepted together, 9, 10
Improvements, small successive, in man's inventions, 44, 46, 47, 54, 55, 384
Inaccuracy of thought, C. Darwin accused of, 359
Incipiency, of complex structures, a difficulty in the way of the Natural selection view of evolution, 21, 22
Incorporate, the designer is, with the organism, 30
Increase, geometrical ratio of Buffon on the, 123
—— Lamarck on, 280
—— Patrick Matthew on, 320, 321
Indefinite, with C. Darwin the variations are, 342, 344
Indifference, I say I am more indifferent than I think I am, whether mind is or is not the least misleading symbol for the cause that sustains the universe, 371
Indirect action of conditions of existence according to Lamarck, 294, 299, 306. (See "Conditions of Existence")
Individuality, Buffon on, 128
—— of buds, Erasmus Darwin on the, 207, 208
—— our, a consensus, or full-flowing river, 318
Infallibility, possible results of the doctrine of Papal, 406
Insectivorous plants, Erasmus Darwin on, 206
Instep, ligament that binds the tendons of the, Paley on the, 22
Instinct, present, does not bar its having arisen in reason and reflection, 53, 54
—— returns to its earlier phase, i. e. to reason on the presence of the unfamiliar, 54, 55, 56
—— and reason, Buffon on, 110-116
—— Darwin, Erasmus, on, 115, 116, 204
—— not referable to imitation, as maintained by Erasmus Darwin, 202
—— is reason become habitual, 203
—— reason perfected and got by rote, 256
—— and reason, Lamarck on, 256, 257, 274
—— referred to experience and memory, by Patrick Matthew, 322
Insult, "Evolution, Old and New," not intended as an insult to men of science, 392
Interaction of want and power, 44, 45, 47, 217, 218, 221, 300, 323
—— of body and mind, Lamarck on the, 338, 339, 341
[Pg 420]Interesting, the more interesting the animal the more evolution Buffon puts into his account of it, 84
Intermediate forms, Lamarck on, 283, 286
—— C. Darwin, 284, 285
Inventions, small successive improvements in man's, and development of, analogous to that of organism, 44, 46, 47, 54, 55, 384
Irony, good-natured and the reverse, 91
—— an apology for, and explanation how far it is legitimate, 111, 112
—— Buffon's, 78, &c., 91, 92, 93, 155, 157, 163, 164
JARDINE, Sir W., on Buffon's character, 82
Johnson, Dr., and Erasmus Darwin, 184, 185
Joints, Paley on the human, 19, 20
Juggle, Paley's argument a juggle, unless man has had a bonâ fide personal, and therefore organic designer, 14, 16
KNEE-PAN, Paley on the human, 18
Knowledge, nomenclature mistaken for, 141
LABOUR, glory comes after, if she can, 76
Lamarck, had brain upon the brain, 36
—— never quite recognized design, 39
—— Haeckel's surprising statement concerning, 73
—— wherein he mainly differs from Buffon, 105
—— memoir of, 235
—— his connection with Buffon, as tutor to his son, &c., 237, 258
—— his daughters, 242, 253
—— his poverty and blindness, 242, 253
—— Isidore Geoffroy on, bad caricature of his teaching, 244-246
—— Haeckel on, 246, 247
—— never seriously discussed, 247
—— "the well-known doctrine of," C. Darwin's reference to, 249, 250, 251, 298, 314, 376
—— on the opposition his theory met with, 252
—— too old to have begun his unequal contest, 253
—— on the feeling of animals, 254, 255
—— too theory-ridden, 254
—— misled by Buffon (query), 255
—— took from Buffon without sufficient acknowledgment, 255, 258, 260, 311
—— as compared with Dr. Erasmus Darwin, 257
—— like Dr. E. Darwin, sees struggle and modification turn mainly round three great wants, 257, 279, 300, 309
—— when and how he came over to the side of mutability, 258
—— and the French translation of the "Loves of the Plant," 259
—— on comparative anatomy, 266
—— on species, 267, &c.
—— on conditions of existence (circonstances), 105, 268, 270, 271, 275, 277, 278, 281, 291, 292, 294, 295, 298, 299, 300, &c.
—— on instinct, 274
—— on animals and plants under domestication, 275, 293, 296, 297, 300
—— on extinct species, 277
—— anticipated Lyell in rejecting catastrophes, 277
—— on the geometrical ratio of increase and struggle for existence, 280-282
—— on embryonic development, 289
—— the main principles which he supposes to underlie variations, 292, 299, 338, 339
—— his contention that plants have neither actions nor habits, 295
—— on use and disuse, 294, 296, 299, 301, 302, 304, 305, 307-309
—— on the various breeds of the dog, 297
[Pg 421]—— habit a second nature, 300
—— like Erasmus Darwin and Buffon, understood the survival of the fittest, 301
—— on the way in which serpents have lost their legs, 303
—— on wading and aquatic birds, 305
—— on the eyes of flat fish, 307
—— on man, 311, &c.
—— on a single instance of considerable variation under domestication, 311
—— on speech, 313, 314
—— on the upright position of man and certain apes, 313
—— his, and Étienne Geoffroy's views on conditions of existence, 326, 327, 328
—— his hypothesis, and Isidore Geoffroy, 329
—— Herbert Spencer on, 330, 331
—— desired to discover the law underlying variations, 337
—— the extent to which he and C. Darwin take common ground, 335-337
—— on body and mind, 338, 339, 341
—— on his theory variations will be definite, will appear in large numbers of individuals at the same time, for long periods together, 341
—— how he and C. Darwin treat the winglessness of Madeira beetles respectively, 373-380
—— on the eyes and ears of cave-inhabiting animals, 378, 379
Laputan method of making books, the, and natural selection, 11
Lawyer's deed, if we come across a very intricate, &c., 27
Leopard, the, can change his spots if it becomes worth his while to try long enough, 40
Lewes, G. H., on embryology, 25
—— his objection to the tentativeness with which the same errors are repeated generation after generation, 26
—— his objection to C. Darwin's language concerning natural selection, 346
Lewes, G. H., on natural selection, 348, 349, 359
Life, some remarks about the criterion of, that I must retract, 279
—— one Proteus principal of, 320
"Life and Habit," what I believe to have been its most important features, 67, 203, 204
—— recapitulation of the main principle insisted on, 37, 56, 203, 380, 381, 384
—— and Hartmann's philosophy of the unconscious, German review, 56, 57
Lifetime, considerable modifications effected during a single, 304
—— the changes undergone by organisms during a single, Herbert Spencer, on, 332-334
Ligament, the, which binds down the tendons of the instep, 21
Living, Paley is but doing his best to earn an honest, 29
—— forms of faith, or faiths of form, 339
Lines, no sharp can be drawn, 47
Lion and tiger, Buffon on the, 143, 145
Llama, Buffon on the hereditary ills of the, 161
Longevity, the principle underlying, 67, 380, 381
Loopholes for escape, the "Origin of Species" full of, 358
"Loves of the Plants," French translation of the, 63, 259
Lungs for respiration, and corkscrew for corks, Professor Clifford on, 7. (See also p. 58)
Lyell, Sir C., and Lamarck, 277
—— on the similarity between Lamarck's theory and Mr. Darwin's, 336, 337
MACHINE, Paley declares animals to be neither wholly machines nor wholly not machines, 14
Madeira beetles, the ways in which Lamarck and C. Darwin would treat their winglessness, 373-380
[Pg 422]Maillet, de, referred to, 70
Mainspring, the true, of our existence lies not in these muscles, &c., 32
Man, the designer of man, 30
—— and horse, skeleton of the, 88, 89
—— and the ape, 90
—— and the lower animals, Buffon on, 107, 108
—— Lamarck on, 311, &c.
Manner, the, is the man himself, 77
—— "but this is Mr. Darwin's", 378
Manufacture, the, of tools and of organs, two species of the same genus, 39
Margin, there is a margin in every organic structure, &c., 49, 50
—— on the margin of the self-evident the greatest purchase is obtainable, 197
Market, the higgling and haggling of the, 50
Martins, M., his life of Lamarck, 235, &c.
Matter less important than the manner, 77
—— and mind, inseparable, 371
Matthew, Mr. Patrick, his work on naval timber and arboriculture, 64, 65
—— extracts from, 315, &c.
—— Mr. C. Darwin on, 315
—— on animals and plants under domestication, 324
—— on will as influencing organism, 320, 321, 322
—— on the struggle for existence with survival of the fittest, 320, 322
—— and natural selection, 323
—— on instinct and memory, and on the continued personality of parents in offspring, 321, 322, 323
Means, C. Darwin's dangerous use of this word, 345
—— one sine quâ non for a thing is as much a means of that thing's coming about as anything else is, 349
Mechanism of animals, Paley on the, 14
Mechanism of animals, evidence of design in any ordinary, 15
Memory, and life and heredity, 37, 38, 39, 56, 67, 198-203, 332, 380, 381
—— Professor Hering on, 198-200
—— Patrick Matthew on, 322
Meteoric, both want and power are, 44, 45
Meninges, Buffon on the, 132
Microcosm, each organism a history of the universe from its own point of view, 31
Microscope, illustration from successive improvements in the, 46, 47
Mind, "the least inadequate and misleading symbol," for the power that has designed organism, 3, 371
—— and body, Lamarck on, 338, 339, 341
—— and matter inseparable, 371
Misfortune, take advantage of, 51
Misrepresentation, "great is the power of steady," 251
Missionaries should avoid trying to effect sudden modifications, 183
Mistake, the power to make, rated highly, 29
—— importance of, depends on magnitude rather than on the direction, 50
Mivart, Professor, says that, "Mind is the least adequate and misleading symbol," &c., 3, 371
—— referred to, 22, 66, 67
—— admits that his objection does not tell against the Lamarckian theory of evolution, 343
—— points out that the admission of a principle underlying variations is fatal to C. Darwin's theory concerning natural selection, 343
—— on C. Darwin's "haphazard, indefinite variations," 343
—— how Professor Huxley pointed out to him the objection to C. Darwin's theory concerning natural selection, 344
[Pg 423]—— asks what is natural selection? and declares it to be repudiated by its propounder, 369
—— declares it to be "nothing," and a puerile hypothesis, 370, 371
—— declares the causes of variation to be the causes of the distinction of species, 370
Model, artificial, of a foot, and true foot, difference between, 24
Modification. It is only on modification that reason reasserts itself, 55
—— there have been two factors of, one producing variations, and the other accumulating them, 227
—— arrived at by struggle round three great wants, Erasmus Darwin on, 226-229
—— Lamarck on the same, 257, 279, 300, 301
—— the cause of survival, not survival the cause of modification, 302
Moral, an organism is most, when looking a little ahead, but not too far, 44
—— struggle, the history of organic development, the history of a, 45
—— more, and safer, to be behind the age than in front of it, 401
Movement, Buffon's great criterion of sensation, 127
Mummies, Egyptian, Lamarck on, 274, 275
Murphy, Rev. J. J., mentioned, 22
—— referred to, 66, 67
Mutability of species commonly held to be incompatible with a belief in design, 9, 10
Mystery-mongering, that Buffon wished to protest against, 81, 171
Mystification, scientific, and orthodoxy, Buffon on, 138
NAIVELY, as Mr. Darwin naively adds, "sometimes equally convenient," 354
Natural selection, the essence of the theory is that the variations shall have been mainly accidental, 7
Natural selection, the unerring skill of, 9
—— Sir William Thomson and Sir John Herschel on, 10
—— Button, and, "by some chance common enough with Nature," 122
—— spoken of as though synonymous with descent with modification, 248, 285, 356
—— C. Darwin attributes the instincts of neuter insects to, 249
—— Mr. Patrick Matthew and, 323
—— like the secretion of a cuttle-fish, 332
—— G. H. Lewes's objection to C. Darwin's language concerning, 346
—— if this is declared to be a cause, the fact of variation is declared to be the cause of variation, 347
—— declared by C. Darwin to be a means of variation, 347
—— treated as a cause, 348
—— G. H. Lewes on, 348, 349, 350
—— identity with "conditions of existence," 351-354
—— according to C. Darwin, "fully embraces" and yet "is included in" conditions of existence, 355
—— a cloak for want of precision of thought, and of substantial difference from Lamarck, 358
—— "some have even imagined that it induces variability;" and small wonder, considering C. Darwin's language concerning it, 362
—— C. Darwin's reply to those who have objected to the term, 362-368
—— a cloak of difference from C. Darwin's predecessors, under which there lurks a concealed identity of opinion as to main facts, 362, 363
[Pg 424]—— "implies only the preservation of such variations as arise," &c., 363
—— admitted by C. Darwin to be a false term, 364
—— the complaint is that the expression has been retained when an avowedly more accurate one is to hand, 365, 366
—— only another way of saying Nature, 368, 369
—— the dislike of it is increasing, 368, 369
—— Francis Darwin does not use the expression, 368, 369
—— daily and hourly scrutinizing throughout the world, &c., 369
—— practically repudiated by C. Darwin himself, 369
—— Professor Mivart declares it to be "simply nothing," 370
—— a "puerile hypothesis," 371
—— and not disuse, the true main cause of the winglessness of Madeira beetles, according to C. Darwin, 374
—— not the main cause of the winglessness of Madeira beetles, according to C. Darwin, 377
—— "combined probably with disuse," will account, according to C. Darwin, for the winglessness of Madeira beetles, 375
Naturalistes, le peuple des, 80, 171
Nature, the personification of comparatively venial, 367
—— and natural selection the same thing, 368, 369
—— the most important means of modification, and variation the cause of variation, 369
Neck, Paley on the human, 17, 18
Need, sense of, the main idea in connection with evolution that is left with the reader by the "Zoonomia," or "Philosophie Zoologique,"
363
Needle, 20,000 devils dancing a saraband on the point of a, 216
Nest, a bird will alter its nest a little, to meet altered circumstances, 55
Nests, birds', Dr. E. Darwin on, 201
Neuter insects, "the demonstrative case of neuter insects," &c., 249, 298, 314
New countries, Buffon a hater of, 146
Nomenclature, mistaken for knowledge, 141
Nottingham market-place, Erasmus Darwin in, 182, 184, 197
OAK and man, the germs of, indistinguishable, 334
—— man may become as long-lived as the, 382
Obvious, Erasmus Darwin had no wish to see far beyond the, 197
Oken, alluded to, 72
Old age, the phenomena of, 67, 204, 381
—— and new worlds, Buffon on the fauna of, 145, &c.
One source for all life, Buffon on, 91
—— Erasmus Darwin on, 109, 233
Oneness of personality between parents and offspring, 37, 38, 39
—— Buffon on the, 151
—— Erasmus Darwin and Professor Hering on the, 198-200
—— Dr. E. Darwin's failure to grasp the whole facts in connection with this, 198, 201, 203
—— Dr. E. Darwin on, 214, 215
—— Patrick Matthew on, 322, 323
—— mentioned, 332, 380, 381
Orang-outang, Buffon on the, 156-159
Organ and use. See "Use."
—— and sense, interaction of the, Buffon on, 127
—— and faculty, Lamarck on, 255
Organs are living tools, 2
—— the manufacture of, and that of tools, two species of the same genus, 39, 43, &c.
—— are the expressions of mental phases, 339, 341
[Pg 425]Organic structures have a margin, 49, 50
Organic strictures and inorganic, Buffon on the, 153, &c.
Organisms, have been developed as man's inventions have, 44, 46, 47, 384
"Origin of Species," the, cannot take permanent rank in the literature of evolution, 62
—— has no raison d'être, if natural selection is not a cause of variation, 346
—— a piece of intellectual sleight of hand, 346
—— compared to the advice of a lawyer who wanted to leave plenty of loopholes, or to a cobbled Act of Parliament, 358
—— is "Hamlet" with the part of Hamlet cut out, 363
—— most readers would say that it advocated natural selection as the most important cause of variation, 363
—— and the "Zoonomia," or the "Philosophie Zoologique"; the one upholds natural selection, the other, sense of need, 363
Orthodoxy, scientific, and mystification, Buffon on, 138
—— scientific, clamouring for endowment, 360
—— dangers of, 368
Overseeing tends to oversight, 197
PAINS, genius a supreme capacity for taking, 76
Painting, a man should do something, no matter what, 51, 52
Paley, quotations from, 12, &c.
—— his argument a juggle, unless some one designed man, much as man designed the watch, 14, 16
—— on ordinary mechanism, as showing design, 15
—— on the human neck, 16, 17
—— on the patella, 18
—— on the joints, 19, 20
—— as a writer against evolution, 21
—— on the ligament that binds the tendons of the instep, 21, 22
—— opposes the view that structures have been formed through appetency, endeavour or effort, 22, 45
—— we turn on him and say, Show us your designer, 29
—— asks, How will our philosopher get an eye? 46
—— his "Natural Theology" written throughout at the "Zoonomia," 195
—— never gives a reference when quoting an opponent, 195, 306
Pantheism and Rome will in the end be the two sole combatants, 401
—— common ground held by Rome and Pantheism, 403-405
—— of Paul, 404
Parents and offspring, oneness of personality between (see "Personality")
Passions, of like passions, men of science are, with other pastors and prophets, 253
Patella, or knee-pan, Paley on the, 18
Paul, St., his pantheistic tendencies, 404
—— we want to accept him literally, 405
Peace, the, that passeth understanding, 35
Perception and sensation, Buffon on the difference between, 129, 130
Personality, oneness of, between parents and offspring, 37, 38, 39
—— Buffon on the, 151
—— Erasmus Darwin and Professor Hering on the, 198-200
—— Erasmus Darwin's failure to grasp the whole conception, 198, 201, 203
—— Erasmus Darwin on the, 214, 215
—— Patrick Matthew on the, 322, 323
—— mentioned, 332, 380, 381
[Pg 426]Personification, the, of Nature, comparatively venial, 367
Pessimism: "Which is the pessimist I or Mr. Darwin?" 59
Peuple des Naturalistes, le, 80, 171
"Philosophie Zoologique," summary of, 261-314
—— the, leaves "sense of need" on the reader's mind; the "Origin of Species," natural selection, 363
Pig, Buffon on the, 118, &c.
Pigeons and fowls, Buffon on, 169
Plaisanterie, Button's disclaimer of, 93
Planted upside down, the vertebrata regarded as vegetables, 137
Plants under domestication, Buffon on, 167, &c.
—— Dr. Erasmus Darwin, on the life of, 206, &c.
—— Lamarck's assertion that they have no action nor habits, 294, 295
Plato upheld teleology, 4
Plus il a su, &c., 44
Poem, a, by Dr. Erasmus Darwin, 189
Poetry, Dr. Erasmus Darwin's, 83, 189, 193
Pope's shoes, scientists would step into the, if we would let them, 360, 394
Portrait of Mr. Day, author of "Sandford and Merton," 180
Potto, the missing forefinger of the, 303
Power and desire, interaction of, 44, 45, 47, 127, 217, 221, 300, 323
Praising, with faint damnation, 111
Prescience, need not extend over more than the next step, and yet the whole road may have been travelled presciently, 52, 384
Present, development due to a wise use of the, 50-52
Probable, whatever in the teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas is not probable is to be rejected, 402, 403
Proficiency is due to design if each step was taken designedly, though the end was not far foreseen, 52, 384
Protestantism tends towards disintegration, 396
Proteus principle of life, one, 320
Pump, Erasmus Darwin's poetry about the, 84, 193
Purpose, instinctive actions were once done with a, 54
—— spent or extinct, and rudimentary organs, 38, 383
Purposive, if each step is purposive, the whole is purposive, 52, 384
Purposiveness: I maintain the lungs to be as purposive us the corkscrew, 5, 6, 7, 58
RACE, the runners in a, and natural selection, 366, 367
—— significance of the words being used for a breed and a competition, 366, 367
Racehorse or greyhound, "the well-adapted forms of the," 359
Ranunculus aquatilis, Lamarck's passage on, 260, 297
Raleigh, Sir Walter, and evolution, 21, 70
Ray Lankester, Professor, on Hering's theory connecting memory and heredity, 198-200
Reason, there is less reason than feeling in animals, Buffon, 51
—— perfected becomes instinct, but reasserts itself when the circumstances alter, 54, 55, 56, 203
—— and instinct, Buffon on, 110, 116
—— Erasmus Darwin on, 115, 116, 201-205
—— a less remarkable faculty than generation, Hume on, 233
—— and instinct, Lamarck on, 256, 274
—— declared to be incipient instinct, 256
Réel, au, Buffon's use of these words, 126
Relativity of the sciences, Buffon on the, 140
Religion, Buffon's appeals to, 91, 115
[Pg 427]Reopen settled questions, animals cannot, serpents must have no more than four legs, 303
Resume earlier habits, the tendency to, on the approach of a difficulty, 312, 313
Retrogressive, Mr. Darwin's views of evolution retrogressive, 66
Revelation, Buffon's appeals to, against evolution, 91, 115
Reviews of "Evolution, Old and New," 385, &c.
Riches, the normal growth of, and evolution, 222
Roman Empire, the, prophetic, 397
Romanes, G. R., on "Evolution, Old and New," 391-393
Rome, Church of, means the same by "gentleman" as we do, 395
—— I would join, if I could, 395, 396
—— a unifier, 398
—— the only source from which a church can come, 398-401
—— and Pantheism, the ultimate fight will be between, 401
—— points of agreement between Rome and Pantheists, 403-405
—— may, and should get rid of Protestantism by outbidding it, 407
Rousseau, Buffon would not play part of, 81
Rudimentary organs, the crux of the early evolutionist in respect of design, 34
—— are now mere cant formulæ, force of habit, 38, 383
—— like the protuberance at the bottom of a tobacco-pipe, 38
—— Buffon would not accept them as designed, 83
—— Buffon on, 120
—— Professor Haeckel on, 383
Run, how did the winner come to be able to run ever such a little faster than his fellows, 367
Runners in a race and natural selection, 366, 367
"SANDFORD and Merton," Miss Seward on the author of, 179, 180
Saints will commonly strain a point or two in their own favour, 253
Saturday Review on "Evolution, Old and New," 389-391
Savery, Captain, 54
Science, men of, of like passions with other priests and prophets, 253
—— not a kingdom into which a poor man can enter easily, 253
—— the leaders of will generally burke new-born wit unless, &c., 315
—— not of that kind which desires to know, 392
Scientific orthodoxy and mystification, Buffon on, 138
—— danger of, 360, 368
Scramble, birds learned to swim through scrambling, 48, 51
Self-indulgence, virtue has ever erred rather on the side of, than on that of asceticism, 35
Sensation, Buffon on, 126, 129
Sense, "in one sense," 355
Sensitive plants, Dr. E. Darwin on, 206, 210
Seriously, Buffon speaking, 126
Serpents, how it is that they have lost their legs, 302
Seward, Miss, her life of Erasmus Darwin, 174, &c.
Shakspeare and Handel address the many as well as the few, 81
Shortest day, and shortest day but one, no difference perceptible between, 48
Skeletons, the, of man and of the horse, 88, &c.
Skill, the unerring, of natural selection, 9
Siamese twins, desire and power compared to, 218, 300
Simplicity, happy, an example of, 276
Sisters, "his, and his cousins and his aunts," 253
Slit, a slit in one tendon to let another pass through, 20
[Pg 428]Something a man should do, no matter what, 51
Sometimes, "equally convenient" ("the survival of the fittest" with natural selection), 9, 354, 365
Son, the people who can get good sons and retain their affection are the only ones worth studying from, 76
Sorbonne, the, and Buffon, 82, 84
Sorbonnes, never do like people who write in this way, 143
Specialists, embryos are, 28
Species, Buffon on the causes or means of transformation, 159, &c.
—— Lamarck on, 267, &c.
—— clusters of, Lamarck on, 288
—— C. Darwin on, 289
Specific characteristics vary more than generic, Lamarck on, 287, 288
—— C. Darwin on, 288
Speech, Lamarck on, 313, 314
Spencer, Herbert, on Lamarck's hypothesis, 330, 331
—— a follower of Buffon, Dr. Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck, 332
Spent, or extinct purpose, and rudimentary organs, 383
Spontaneous: C. Darwin uses this word in connection with variability, 358
—— variability (or unknown causes), C. Darwin, on what it will account for, or make known, 358
Steam engine, latest development of, not foreseen, though each immediate step in advance was so, 54, 384
—— design lost sight of in the most common patterns, as with a bird's-nest, or the wheel, 55
Step, if each step is purposive, the whole road has been travelled purposively, 52, 384
—— only the few nearest are taken definitely, 44, 384
Sterility of hybrids, Lamarck on, 272
—— C. Darwin on, 273
Stock, Buffon on the, and the diaphragm, 130
Stronger, the, succeed, and the weaker fail, 320, 321
Strongest, the, eat the weaker, 282
Struggle for existence, Buffon on the, 123
—— and hence modification, according to Dr. Erasmus Darwin, mainly conversant about three wants, 226-229, 232
—— comparison between Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck's views on the foregoing, 257
—— Lamarck on the foregoing, 279
—— and survival of the fittest, Lamarck on the, 281, 282
—— Patrick Matthew on, 321
Style, Buffon on, 76, 77
Sudden, the question what is too, to be settled by higgling and haggling, 50
—— modifications, missionaries should avoid trying to effect, 183
Superficial, philosophy of the, 34, 35, 36, 198, 204
Supply and demand, and desire and power, 223, 300
Survival of the fittest, a synonym for natural selection, 9
—— Dr. Erasmus Darwin on the, 227
—— in the struggle for existence, Lamarck on the, 281, 282
—— understood and admitted by Buffon, Erasmus Darwin, and Lamarck, 301
—— subsequent to modification, and therefore not the cause of it, 302, 346
—— Patrick Matthew on, 321
—— this is not a theory, but a fact, 356, 357
Swimming, no shore bird ever set itself to learn, of malice prepense, 48, 51
TAIL, the beaver's, has become an incarnate trowel, 8
Teething, the pain an infant feels is the death-cry of many a good cell, 75
Teleological, failure of the early evolutionists to see their position as, 34
[Pg 429]Teleology, statement of the question, 1
—— Aristotle denied, Plato upheld, 4
—— the, of Paley and the theologians, 12, &c.
—— internal as much teleology as external, 36
—— See also "Design."
Telescope, Lord Rosse's, and dew-drop, 44, 47
Tempering, the felicitous, of two great contradictory principles, 35
Tendon, a slit in one, to let another pass through, 20
Terminology of botany harder than botany, 108
—— Buffon on, 140, 141
Test, Buffon's, as to the name an object is to bear, 115
—— of perception and sensation, Buffon's, 127
Theological writer, few passages in any, displease me more, &c., 368
Theory, the survival of the fittest is a fact, not a theory, 356, 357
Theories, true, Fontenelle on, 22, 23
—— to be ordered out of court if troublesome, 35
This: "I can no more believe in this," &c., 359
—— "it is impossible to attribute to this cause," 358
Thomas, St., Aquinas, Papal encyclical on, 402, 403
Thomson, Sir W., natural selection and design, 10
Thought is expressed in organ, 339, 341
Time, Buffon on, 103
—— Lamarck on, 241
Tobacco-pipe, a rudimentary organ on a, 38
Toes, a man who plays the violin with his, 50
Tools, organs are living tools, 2
—— the manufacture of, and that of organs, two species of the same genus, 39
Touch, all senses modifications of the sense of touch, 47
Transformation of species, Buffon on the causes or means of, 159
Translation of the "Loves of the Plants" into French, 63, 258, 259
Translation of the "Zoonomia" into German, 71
—— of Dr. E. Darwin's other works, 195
Trapa Natans, Erasmus Darwin's note on, 260
Treviranus alluded to, 72
Tree, life seen as a tree, by Lamarck, 269
—— by C. Darwin, 270
—— nature compared to a, by Buffon, 171
Trees, the blind man who saw men as trees walking, 137
Trowel, the beaver has an incarnate trowel, 8
True, vitally, 227
—— all very, as far as it goes (that Nature is the most important means of modification), 369
Truism, the survival of the fittest, a, 351
Tutbury bull running, 187
Tyndall, Professor, a rhapsody about C. Darwin, 41
—— calls evolution C. Darwin's theory, 360, 361
UNCLES and aunts do not beget their nephews and nieces, 367, 376
Unconscious, our acquired habits come to be done as unconsciously as though instinctive, on repetition, 56
—— difference between my view of the, and Von Hartmann's, 58
Unconsciousness, the, with which habitual actions come to be performed, 37, 38, 39, 56-58, 67, 203, 332, 381
Understanding, the peace of mind that passeth, 35
Unity of the individual, Buffon on the, 127, 128. (See "Oneness")
"Unknown causes," according to Mr. Darwin, can do so much, but not so much more, 359
—— their identity with spontaneous variability, 359
[Pg 430]—— heredity only another name for, unless the "Life and Habit" theory be adopted, 384
Upright position in man and certain apes, and children, Lamarck on, 312
Upside down, the vertebrata are perambulating vegetables planted, 137
Use and organ, 44, 45, 47, 217, 218, 221, 292, 294, 296, 299, 301, 302, 304, 305, 307-309, 311, 323
VACUUM, an omniscient and omnipotent, 28
Vague, efforts and desires are vague in the outset, 47, 52, 384
Variation, C. Darwin declares the fact of variation to be the cause of variation, 8, 9, 347, 369
Variations, one factor of modification provides, the other accumulates, 227
—— Lamarck strove to discover the law underlying, 337
—— C. Darwin sees no cause underlying them, 339, 340
—— according to Lamarck, they will tend to appear in definite directions in large numbers of individuals, for long periods together; according to C. Darwin they will not do thus, 341
—— must appear before they can be preserved, 346
—— the cause of variations is the cause of species (Professor Mivart on this), 370
Vary, man cannot vary his practices much more than animals can, 55
"Vestiges of Creation," the, 65
—— C. Darwin on the, 65
—— the author of, on Lamarck, 247
—— Darwin's treatment of, 247, 248
Virtue has ever erred on the side of excess than on that of asceticism, 35
Violin, a man who plays the, with his toes, 50
Vitally true, 227
Volition. (See "Will")
Voltaire, Buffon would not play the part of, 81
WALLACE, A. R., his review of Professor Haeckel's "Evolution of Man," 382-384
Want and power, interaction of, 44, 45, 47, 48, 217, 218, 221, 300, 323
Wasp, cutting a fly in half, Dr. Erasmus Darwin on, 205
Watch, Paley's argument from the, 13
Weaker, the strongest eat the, 282
Wealth, the normal growth of, and evolution, 222
Web-footed, how birds, became, 48, 49, 51
—— development of, birds, Lamarck on, 305
—— Paley on, 305
Wedge, Buffon let in the thin end of the wedge, by saying that changed habits modify form, 105, 106
Whisky, God keep you from—if he can, 176
Will, Patrick Matthew on, as influencing organism, 320-322. (See also "Desire," "Design," "Want," "Wish")
Will-o'-the-wisp, C. Darwin like a, 372
Wish and power, their interaction, 44, 45, 47, 48, 217, 218, 221, 300, 323
Wit, brevity may be its soul, but the leaders of science, &c., 315
Worcester, the Marquis of, 54
Words are apt to turn out compendious false analogies, 365
Worms, reasonable creatures, 255
Worth, nothing worth looking at or doing, except at a fair price, 35
Wright, of Derby, his portrait of Mr. Day, 180
ZEBRA and horse, Buffon on the, 80, 155, 164
"Zoonomia," German translation of the, 71
—— Paley's "Natural Theology" written at the, 195
—— fuller quotations from the, 214, &c.
—— the, and the "Origin of Species," the different ideas that an average reader would carry away with him from these two works ("Sense of Need" and "Natural Selection"), 363
ABORTION, neutralization of working bees as an act of, 250
Accessory touches, varying Buffon on, 92
Accident, many of our best thoughts come thoughtlessly, 48, 384
—— profiting by, 51, 53
—— and discovering a theory connecting meteors with comets, 53
—— shaking the bag to see what will come out, 53
—— effects of, transmitted to offspring, Dr. Erasmus Darwin, 224
—— and design, the line between these is hard to draw, 384
Accidental variations thrown as if with dice, 3
Accumulation of variations that C. Darwin deals with, not with the origin of, 340, 341
—— of small divergencies, Buffon on the, 103
Accurate, survival of the fittest is more accurate than Nat. Sel. and sometimes equally convenient, 9, 354, 365
Act of Parliament, Natural Selection compared to a certain kind of, 358
Age, old, the phenomena of, 67, 204, 381
Aggregation, the spirit of the age tends towards, 397, 398
Ahead, no organism sees very far, 44, 48, 54, 384
Aldrovandus, Buffon on the learned, 93
Alive, when we must not say that an animal is alive (to be retracted), 279
Allen, Grant, on 'Evolution, Old and New,' 386-388
—— on the decay of criticism, 388
—— calls Evolutionism "an almost exclusively English impulse," 393
Alternations of fat and lean years, Buffon on, 125
Amœba, the, did not conceive the idea of an eye and work towards it, 43, 44, 384
Analogies, false, all words are likely to turn out to be, 365
Animals, contracts among, Dr. E. Darwin on, 205
Ape, the, and man, 90
Apes and monkeys, Buffon on, 153
—— and children crawl on all fours at the approach of danger, 312
Apparentibus, de non, et non existentibus, &c., 36
Appearances, rather superficial, our only guide to classification, 34, 35, 36, 198, 204
Appetency, Paley's argument against the view that structures have developed through, 22, 45
Aristides, C. Darwin is just as, 363
Aristotle denied teleology, 4
Artificial and real foot, differences between, 25
Asceticism, virtue errs on the side of excess rather than on that of, 35
Ass, the, and horse, Buffon's insightful passage on their relationship, 80, 90, 91, 100, 101, 142, 143, 155, 164, 311
[Pg 410]Authority, a difficult thing to measure, 253
BACON, F., on evolution, 69
Balzac, quote from, on memory and instinct, 67
Bark, Erasmus Darwin's theory of, 208
Beaver, trowel incorporated into the beaver's body, 8
Bees, neutralization of working, an act of abortion, 250
Beetles, Madeira, comparing Lamarck and C. Darwin's views on their winglessness, 373, 380
Begin, How could the eye begin? 46, 47
Beginnings, of complex structures, a challenge for natural selection, 21, 22
—— difficulty of accounting for, 46, 47
—— a matter of speculation and inference, 48
Behind, it's more moral to be behind the times than ahead of them, 401
Best, making the most of whatever ability one has, 50
Bird, how birds became web-footed, 48, 49, 51
—— a, will slightly modify its nest under changing circumstances, 55
—— Buffon on, 170, &c.
—— nests, Dr. Erasmus Darwin's failure to connect the ability to create them with memory, 201, 203
—— aquatic and wading, Lamarck on, 305
Bishop, and Evêque, common origin of, 355
Blindfolded, we can see a few steps ahead, but no more, 44
—— us, C. Darwin has almost ostentatiously, 346
Blindly, forces interacting without design, 59
Body and mind, Lamarck on, 338, 339, 341
Brain, Lamarck had brain upon the brain, 36
—— Buffon on the, 131, 133, &c.
Brevity may be the soul of wit, but, &c., 315
Breeding, and feeding, 222
Brown-Séquard, his experiments on guinea-pigs' legs, 303
Buds, individuality of, Dr. Erasmus Darwin on the, 207, 208
Buffalo, Buffon on the, 148, &c.
Buffon, profoundly superficial, 34
—— plus il a su, plus il a pu, &c., 44
—— dans l'animal il y a moins de jugement que de sentiment, 51
—— ignorance concerning, 61
—— memoir of, 74, &c.
—— on glory, genius, and style, 76, 77
—— ironical character of his work and method (see Irony), 78, &c., 171
—— on the ass, horse, and zebra, 80, 90, 91, 100, 101, 142, 143, 155, 164, 311
—— would not play the part of Rousseau or Voltaire, 81
—— Sir W. Jardine on, and the Sorbonne, 82
—— views all animal and plant life as coming from one common source, 90
—— if a single species has ever emerged under domestication, &c., 91
—— on plaisanterie, and the learned Aldrovandus, 93, &c.
—— his compromise, 92
—— accessory touches, 92
—— "especially" the same, 96
—— fluctuation of opinion is an unfounded charge, 97, &c., 164
—— on the accumulation of small divergencies, 103
—— began preaching evolution almost on his first page, 104
—— chapter on the dégénération des animaux, equivalent to "on descent with modification," 104, &c.
—— difference of opinion between him and Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck, 105
—— probably did not differ from Lamarck, 105
[Pg 411]—— on direct action of changed conditions, 105, 145, 147
—— on man and the lower animals, 108
—— on classification, 108, 109, 141
—— on animals and plants, 109, 110
—— on reason and instinct, 110, 115
—— on final causes (the pig), 118, &c.
—— on hybridism, 117, 118
—— rudimentary organs, 120
—— on animals under domestication, 121, &c., 148
—— addresses these early, providing the best opportunities to illustrate the theory of evolution, 276
—— approaches natural selection in his "by some chance common enough in Nature," 122
—— preaches on the hare instead of the rabbit purely out of love for mischief, 123
—— returns of wild characteristics, 123
—— on the geometrical ratio of increase, 123, &c.
—— alternation of fat and lean years, 125
—— equilibrium of Nature, 125
—— "au réel," 126
—— on violent death, 126
—— on sensation, 126, &c.
—— on the interaction of organ and sense, 127
—— the carnivora, 126
—— his criterion for what name a thing should have, 127
—— his standard of perception and sensation, 127
—— on the unity of the individual, 127, 128
—— critiques our habit of judging everything by our own standards, 129
—— the diaphragm, 129
—— on the stock and the diaphragm, 130
—— distinction between perception and sensation, 129, 130
—— on the meninges, 132
—— on the brain, 131, 133, &c.
—— on scientific orthodoxy and mystification, 138
—— on the relativity of science, 140
—— on nomenclature and knowledge, 141
—— on the genus felis, 143
—— on the lion and the tiger, 143, 145
—— on the animals of the old and new world, 145, &c.
—— on the changed geographical distribution of land and water, 145, 164
—— on extinct species, 146
—— dislikes the new world, 146
—— on heredity and habit, 148, 159, 160, 161, 162
—— approaches Erasmus Darwin and Lamarck, re the Buffalo, Camel, and Llama, 148, 160, 161
—— on the unity of personality between parents and offspring, 151
—— on the organic and inorganic, 153, &c.
—— on apes and monkeys, 153, &c.
—— on the causes or means of species transformation, 159, &c.
—— on both generic and specific differences, 164
—— on plants under domestication, 167
—— on pigeons and fowls, 169
—— on birds, 170, &c.
—— the help he provided to Lamarck, 237, 258
—— Isidore Geoffroy's misunderstanding, 328
—— Colonel, 75
Bulk, a sine quâ non for success in literature or science, 315
Bull-running, Tutbury, and Erasmus Darwin, 187
CAMEL, Buffon on the hereditary issues of the, 161
Cant, and rudimentary organs, 38
[Pg 412]Captandum, all good things are done with an aim to, 85
Carnivora, Buffon on the, 126
Carriage, Dr. Erasmus Darwin's, 181
Cat, family, Buffon on the, 142, &c.
—— with a mane and long tail, 143
Cataclysms, the good cells that get exterminated during the cataclysms of our own development, 75
Catastrophes, Lamarck on, 277
Causes, or "means," of modification, 301
—— C. Darwin claims that Buffon has not addressed the, 104, &c.
—— C. Darwin confuses us about, 345, &c.
Change, under altered circumstances, Mr. Patrick Matthew on, 318
Charity, the greatest of these is, 77
Church, a, like a second chamber, 400
—— makes the world better with than without, 400
—— should function like the flywheel of a steam engine, 104
Circonstances (see Conditions of Existence), Lamarck on, 268, 281
Circumstance, suiting power, a, Mr. Patrick Matthew on, 318-321
Classification, rather superficial appearances are our best guide to, 34, 35, 36, 198, 204
—— Buffon on, 108, 109, 141
Clear, an ineradicable tendency to make things, 92
Clifford, Professor, on "Design," 6, 7
Climbing plants, the movements of, Dr. Erasmus Darwin on, 209
Coherency, the persistency of ideas is the best argument supporting their legitimate connection, 23
Coleridge, on "Darwinising," 21
Common terms, our, involve the link between memory and heredity, 201, 205
—— descent, the “hidden bond” of Lamarck, as well as C. Darwin, 271
Comparative anatomy, Lamarck on, 266, &c.
Complex structures, the beginnings of, presents a difficulty for the natural selection view of evolution, 21, 22
Compromise, Buffon's, 92
Conditions of existence, the essence of condition implies that there will be penalties for non-fulfillment, 352, 376, 377
—— and the winglessness of Madeira beetles, 373, &c.
—— according to C. Darwin, "include" yet "are fully embraced by" natural selection, 355
—— identical to "natural selection," 351-354
—— Étienne Geoffroy, and Lamarck on, 326, 327, 328
—— Buffon on the, 103;
the difference between Buffon's and Lamarck's perspectives on their actions, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
—— direct action of changed, Buffon on the, 145, 147, 160
—— Lamarck on, 105, 268, 270, 271, 275, 277, 278, 281, 291, 292, 294, 295, 298, 299, 300, &c.
Continuity in discontinuity, and vice versa, 47
Contracts of animals, Dr. E. Darwin on the, 205
Contrivance, does an organism show signs of this? 2
Convenient, not only sometimes, but always more, 365
Corkscrew for corks, and lungs for respiration, Prof. Clifford on, 7. See also p. 58
—— we would have developed a, if drawing corks had been significant to us, 7
Creator, a, who is not an organism, is unintelligible, 6, 11, 24
Criticising, the difficulty of, without knowing more than just the facts to be criticized, 172
Criticism, Miss Seward's, on Dr. Darwin's "Elegy," 189
[Pg 413]—— Grant Allen on the decay of, 388
Crux, the, of the early evolutionist, 35
Cuttle-fish, natural selection is like the secretion of a, 332
DAMNATION, praising with faint, 111
Darwin, Charles, on the eye, denies design, 8
—— states that variation is the cause of variation, 8, 347, 369
—— and blind chance working where; the accumulation of countless lucky accidents, 41, 42
—— our indebtedness to, 62, 66, 335
—— has adopted half of Isidore Geoffroy's conclusion without verifying either, 83
—— on Buffon's fluctuation of opinion, 97
—— on Isidore Geoffroy, 97
—— his claim that Buffon has not discussed the "causes or means" of transformation, 104
—— his brief mention of his grandfather, 196
—— his treatment of the author of the "Vestiges of Creation," __A_TAG PLACEHOLDER_312__, 247, 248
—— attributes the traits of neuter insects to natural selection, 249
—— his treatment of Lamarck, 249, 250, 251, 298, 314, 376
—— "great is the power of steady misrepresentation," 251
—— his "happy simplicity" regarding animals and plants under domestication, 276
—— his notice of Mr. Patrick Matthew in the imperfect historical sketch prefacing the "Origin of Species," 315, 316
—— points of agreement between him and Lamarck, 335-337
—— sees no broad principle underlying variation, 339
—— emphasizes the accumulation of variations, the origins of which he leaves unaddressed, 340, 341
—— his variations being due to no overarching principle will not systematically appear in certain directions, nor to many individuals simultaneously, nor will they be stable for long, 342
—— refers to natural selection as a cause of modification while declaring it to be merely a means, 345, &c.
—— his explanation of this, 384, &c.
—— his dilemma regarding the "Origin of Species," 346
—— states that the fact of variation is the cause of variation, 8, 347, 369
—— if he had shared more about what Buffon, &c., stated, and where they were mistaken, he would have taken a different course, &c., 357
—— reflects on the ease of concealing our ignorance with a flood of words, 358
—— apologizes for underestimating the frequency and significance of spontaneous variability, 358
—— his "Origin of Species" resembles the opinion of a lawyer intending to leave loopholes, or an Act of Parliament filled with repealed and added clauses, 358
—— accused of confusion and inaccuracy in thought, 359
—— as just as Aristides himself, 364
—— the most candid literary opponent in the world, 364
—— states that Nature is the most crucial means of modification, and variation is the cause of variations, 369
—— like a will-o'-the-wisp, 372
[Pg 414]—— disuse, the main factor in reducing the wings of Madeira beetles, 377
—— how he and Lamarck address the winglessness of Madeira beetles differently, 373-380
—— an example of his "style," 378
—— the way he responded to "Evolution, Old and New," 393
Darwin, Erasmus, never fully recognized design, 39
—— ignorance concerning, 61
—— on reason and instinct, 115, &c.
—— life of, 173, &c.
—— in Nottingham market, 182, 184, 197
—— and Dr. Johnson, 184, 185
—— and Tutbury bull running, 187
—— his poems about the pump, and illustrations, 84, 193
—— should have dedicated a book solely to his evolution theory, 197
—— had no desire to look far beyond the obvious, 197
—— must be acknowledged to have failed to recognize Buffon's humor, 83, 84, 197
—— did not attribute instincts and structures to memory straightforwardly, 198
—— on the reasoning abilities of animals, and on instinct, 201, 205
—— his failure to connect memory and instinct, as seen in birds' nests, 201-203
—— missed recognizing the four main propositions I defended in "Life and Habit," 37, 203, 204
—— on the similarities between animal and plant life, 206, &c.
—— on sensitive plants, 206, 210
—— on the individuality of buds, and his theory of bark, 207, 208
—— on the behaviors of climbing plants, 209
—— on the unity of personality between parents and offspring, 214;
the embryo is not a new animal, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
—— on animals under domestication, 223
—— on the effects of accidents passed down to offspring, 224
—— observes that struggle, and thus modification, primarily revolves around three significant needs, 226, 229, 257, 279
—— on desire as a means of modification, 226, 228, 259
—— by a slip approaches the error of his grandson, 227, 228
—— on embryonic transformations, 230, 231
—— believed that animals and plants descended from a common source, 233
—— compared with Lamarck, 257
—— on the struggle for existence, and the survival of the fittest, 227, 232, 259
Darwin, Mrs. Erasmus, death-bed of, 178
Darwin, Francis, mentioned, 109
—— his interesting lecture, 206
—— does not use the term "natural selection," 368
Darwinising, Coleridge on, 21
Darwinism, the old Darwinism includes desire, invention, and design, 58
—— modern Darwinism is falling out of favor, 60
—— and evolution should not be confused, 360, 361
Day, the portrait of, by Wright of Derby, 180
Death, violent, Buffon on, 126
—— of Dr. Erasmus Darwin, 193, 194
Death-bed of Mrs. Erasmus Darwin, 178
Deed, illustration drawn from a very intricate, 28
Definite, with Lamarck, the variations are 341, 344
Dégénérations, 87
Demand and supply, like power and desire, 222, 300
[Pg 415]Demonstrative case, "this demonstrative case of neuter insects, &c.," 249, 298, 314
Descent, with modification, referred to as synonymous with natural selection, 248, 356
Design, and organism, shall we connect these ideas or not? 2
—— Aristotle denied it, Plato upheld it, Haeckel on, 4
—— Prof. Clifford's rejection of, 6, 7
—— does certainly imply a designer who has an organism, who can think, and make mistakes, 6, 24
—— a belief in design and evolution is widely seen as incompatible, 9
—— Sir W. Thomson and Sir J. Herschel on, 11
—— Paley on, 12, &c.
—— light thrown by embryology on the method of, 25
—— G. H. Lewes opposes, 26
—— the three positions regarding it taken by Charles Darwin, Paley, and the earlier evolutionists, 31
—— the first evolutionists did not realize that their evolutionary view involved design, 34
—— involves teleology both from within as much as from without, 36
—— would be seen as theological design with the early evolutionists, 36
—— if each step is intentionally taken, the whole is done with intention, 52, 384
—— and accident, the line between them is difficult to draw; shaking the bag, &c., 53, 384
—— instinct originated in, 54
—— is as easily overlooked with established forms of the steam-engine as with birds' nests or the wheel, 55
—— Dr. E. Darwin's failure to see that evolution involves design, 195
—— we feel the need for, as much as we do for evolution, 407
—— evolution not only accepts but cannot function without, 408
Designer, "I believe in an organic and tangible designer of every complex structure," 6
—— "where is he? show him to us," &c., 29, 30
—— the, of any organism, is itself the organism, 30, 31, 40
Desire and power, interaction of, 44, 45, 47, 127, 217, 221, 300, 322
—— and power, like wealth, 222
—— as a means of modification, Dr. Erasmus Darwin on, 226, 228, 259
Development, the history of organic life is the history of a moral struggle, 45
—— always resulting from making the best of the present, 50
Devils, 20,000, dancing on the tip of a needle, 216
Dew drop, or lens, the, and Lord Rosse's telescope, 44, 47
Diaphragm, Buffon on the, 129
Dice, accidental variations thrown for as with, 3
Difference between animal and ordinary machinery, 24
—— the key, between tool-making and organ-making, 39
Dilemma, C. Darwin's, 346
Direct action of changed conditions, Buffon on the, 105, 145, 147, 160
Discontinuity within continuity, 47
Disease, accidents followed by, 303
Disintegration, Protestantism tends towards, 397
Distribution, geographical, altered, Buffon on, 145, 164
Disuse, and the winglessness of Madeira beetles, it is surprising to find they are related at all, 375
—— the main factor in reducing the wings of Madeira beetles, 377
[Pg 416]—— examples of the effects of, as noted by Lamarck, 378
Dog, Buffon on the, 120
—— Lamarck on the different breeds of, 297
Domestication, a single case of a species formed under domestication is enough to eliminate the à priori difficulty from a comprehensive theory of evolution, 90, 91, 311
—— plants under, Buffon on, 167, &c.
—— Buffon on animals under, 103, 120, &c., 148, &c., 159, &c., 276
—— animals under, Dr. Erasmus Darwin on, 223
—— animals under, Buffon on, 121, &c., 148, 276
—— C. Darwin on, 276
—— animals and plants under, Lamarck on, 275, 293, 296, 297, 300
—— animals and plants under, Mr. Patrick Matthew on, 324
Door, doing anything well will open the door to doing more, 51
Ducks, our domesticated ones, why they can't fly like the wild ones, 296, 309
EARN, "you are just doing your best to earn an honest living," 29
Ears are never found in a rudimentary state, 379
Eat, or be eaten, 177
Effort, Paley's argument that structures have not developed through, 22, 45
—— excessive effort, as harmful as laziness, 35
—— "neither too much nor too little," 50
—— Herculean, condemned, 197
Egyptian mummies, Lamarck on, 274, 275
Embryology, the insights it offers into how organisms have been designed, 25
Embryonic metamorphoses, Erasmus Darwin on, 230, 231
Embryonic development, Lamarck on, 289
Encyclical, the Pope's, on St. Thomas Aquinas, 402, &c.
Endeavour, Paley's argument against the view that structures have developed through, 22, 45
Endowment, the new orthodoxy clamoring for, 360
English wines, Dr. Erasmus Darwin's preference for, 175
Environment. See Conditions of Existence
Equilibrium, the, of Nature, Buffon on the, 125
Err, the ability to, is valued highly, 29
—— "it is on this margin that we may err or wander," 50
—— virtue always errs on the side of excess, 35
Error, significance of, depends on the distance rather than the direction, 50
"Especially" the same, 92, 96
Ethiopian, the, can change his skin if he tries hard enough and for long enough, 40
Evêque and bishop, common origin of, 355
Everlasting, God, how far, 32
Evolution, generally seen as incompatible with design, 9
—— Paley, its first serious opponent in England, 21
—— Sir Walter Raleigh on, 21, 70
—— must either succeed or fail based on whether it stands on a purposive foundation or not, 60
—— summary of its six principal stages, 62, &c.
—— Bacon on, 69
—— the theory of, separate from the evidence supporting it, 332
—— C. Darwin and Lamarck aim to establish the same theory of evolution, 335-337
—— and Darwinism should not be confused, 360, 361
[Pg 417]—— Rome and Pantheism converge in, 403
Evolutionists, the early, did not realize that they accepted teleology, 34
—— the early, perceived design only as the design of the God of theologians, 36
Experience and instinct, Mr. Patrick Matthew on, 322
Extinct species, Lamarck on, 277
—— Buffon on, 146, 277
Eye, no creature that lacks something similar to an eye has ever attempted to conceive one and grow one, 44, 387
—— Paley asks "how will our philosopher get an eye?" 46
—— of flat fish, Lamarck on the, 307
—— Lamarck on the, of underground and cave-dwelling animals, 378
—— disappear and reappear in the hierarchy of organisms based on the necessity of using them, 379
FAITH, forms of, or faiths of form, &c., 339
Familiarity, with a little of this, such superficial objections will be forgotten, 367
Far ahead, no organism has ever foreseen an improvement far ahead and made its way towards it, 43, 44, 48, 49, 54, 384
Father, a man capable of being the father of such a son and retaining his affection, &c., 76
Factors, there have been two, of modification, one producing, and the other accumulating variations, 227
Fecundity, alternate years of, Buffon on, 125
Feeding and breeding, 222
Feel, if plants and animals appear to feel, let's say they feel, 198
Feeling, there is more feeling than reason in animals, 51
Feral characteristics, resumption of, Buffon on, 123
Final causes, the doctrine of, as generally accepted during the time of early evolutionists, 34, 36
—— Buffon on, 118, &c.
Fitness, the cause of, is more significant than the fact that fitness is typically fit, and therefore successful, 351
Flat fish, Lamarck on the eyes of, 307
Fluctuation of opinion, C. Darwin on Buffon's, the claim refuted, 97, &c., 164, 166
Fontenelle, on theories, 22
Foot, and model of foot, differences between, 24
Forms of faith, or faiths of form, &c., 339
Four main points that early evolutionists failed to connect and understand in relation to each other, 37, 203
Four main principles, the, that I argued for in "Life and Habit," 37, 203, 380, 381
Fowls and pigeons, Buffon on, 169
GARNETT, Mr. R., and "Darwinising," 21
Genius, Mr. Allen says I am a, 388
Gentleman, the Church of Rome uses the term the same way we do, 395
Geoffroy, Étienne, how little he covers, 196
—— and Isidore, trimmers, 328
—— on Buffon, 328
—— on conditions of existence, 326, 327
—— opposes Lamarck's hypothesis, 328
—— his position, 325-328
Geoffroy, Isidore, on evolution and final causes, 9
—— on Buffon's shifting views, 98, &c., 164, 166
—— points out the difference between Buffon's and Lamarck's perspectives, 105
[Pg 418]—— asserts that Buffon's opinions fluctuated, which has been refuted, 166
—— and Lamarck's hypothesis, 244-246, 329
—— on Buffon, 328
—— his stance, 329
Genealogical order, Lamarck on, 264
—— C. Darwin on, 265
Generation is more remarkable than reason, Hume on, 233
Generic differences (as well as specific), Buffon on, 164
Genius, a supreme ability to take pains, 76
Geographical distribution, altered, Buffon on, 145, &c., 164
Geometrical ratio of increase, Buffon on the, 123
—— Lamarck, on, 280
—— Patrick Matthew on, 320, 321
Germ of oak indistinguishable from that of a man, 334
Germans, Buffon on the, 93
Glory "comes after labor if she can," &c., 76
Go away, because their uncles, aunts, 376
God, embodied in living forms, and present in them, 31
—— how far everlasting, invisible, imperishable, omnipotent, &c., 32
—— the unseen aspects of, are like a deep-buried history, 33
Goethe, as an evolutionist, 71
Gradations infinitely small, 87
Grant Allen, on "Evolution, Old and New," 386-388
—— on the decline of criticism, 388
—— remarks that "Evolutionism is an almost exclusively English impulse," 393
Greyhound or racehorse, the well-adapted form of the, 359
Growth is accompanied at each step by a fortunate balancing of two opposing principles, 35
Gueneau de Montbeillard, 172, 173
HABIT," "Life and. See "Life and Habit."
—— rudimentary organs repeated through pure force of habit, 38, 39
—— Buffon on, 148, 159, 160, 161, 162
—— a second nature, Lamarck on, 300
Habits, or use, and organ, Lamarck on their interaction, 292, 311
Haeckel, on design, 4, 5
—— does not seem to recognize Buffon as an evolutionist, 71
—— his surprising assertion about Lamarck, 71
—— his ignorance about Erasmus Darwin, 393, 73
—— on Lamarck, 246, 247
—— A. R. Wallace's review of his "Evolution of Man," 382, 384
Hamlet, the "Origin of Species" is like "Hamlet" without Hamlet, 363
Handiest, a man should do whatever comes most naturally, 51, 52
Hare, Buffon on the, 123, &c.
Hartmann's philosophy of the unconscious, and "Life and Habit," 56, 57
Hearing, once we reach animals so low as to lack an organ of, we lose this organ permanently, 379
Heredity and habit, Buffon on, 148, 159, 160, 161, 162
—— merely another term for unknown causes, unless the "Life and Habit" theory is adopted, 384
Hering, Professor, referred to, 66, 67
—— his theory as detailed in "Nature" by Ray Lankester, 198-200
Herschel, Sir John, compares natural selection to the Laputan method of creating books, 10
Higgling and haggling of the market, 50
[Pg 419]History of the universe, each organism is a, from its own perspective, 31
Horse and ass, Buffon's most insightful passage on the, 80, 90, 91, 100, 101, 142, 143, 155, 164, 311
—— and man, skeleton of the, 88, 89
—— and zebra, Buffon on the, an example of irony, 80, 155, 164
Hume, his statement that generation is more noteworthy than reason, 233
Huxley, Professor, referred to, 93
—— pointed out to Professor Mivart the challenges faced by natural selection, 344
—— his ignorance regarding the earlier history of evolution, 392, 393
Hybridism, Buffon on, 117, 118
Hybrids, sterility of, Lamarck on, and C. Darwin on, 272, 273
IDEAS, the bond or connection of our, 23, 29, 30
Ignorance, the common, regarding the earlier evolutionists, 61
—— it’s easy to disguise our, under phrases like "plan of creation," or natural selection, 358
Imitation, instinct cannot be reduced to that, as claimed by Erasmus Darwin, 202
Immutability of species and design generally accepted together, 9, 10
Improvements, small successive, in human inventions, 44, 46, 47, 54, 55, 384
Inaccuracy of thought, C. Darwin accused of, 359
Incipiency, of complex structures, a challenge for the Natural selection view of evolution, 21, 22
Incorporate, the designer is, with the organism, 30
Increase, geometrical ratio of Buffon on the, 123
—— Lamarck on, 280
—— Patrick Matthew on, 320, 321
Indefinite variations with C. Darwin, 342, 344
Indifference, I feel I am more indifferent than I think I am, whether mind is or is not the least misleading indication for the cause that sustains the universe, 371
Indirect action of conditions of existence according to Lamarck, 294, 299, 306. (See "Conditions of Existence")
Individuality, Buffon on, 128
—— of buds, Erasmus Darwin on the, 207, 208
—— our, a consensus, or full-flowing river, 318
Infallibility, potential effects of the Papal doctrine of, 406
Insectivorous plants, Erasmus Darwin on, 206
Instep, ligament that binds the tendons of the, Paley on the, 22
Instinct, present, does not exclude the possibility of it arising from reason and reflection, 53, 54
—— returns to its earlier form, i.e. to reason concerning the presence of the unfamiliar, 54, 55, 56
—— and reason, Buffon on, 110-116
—— Darwin, Erasmus, on, 115, 116, 204
—— cannot be explained by imitation as maintained by Erasmus Darwin, 202
—— is reason that has become habitual, 203
—— perfected and learned by heart, 256
—— and reason, Lamarck on, 256, 257, 274
—— referred to experience and memory, by Patrick Matthew, 322
Insult, "Evolution, Old and New," was not meant as an insult to scientists, 392
Interaction between want and power, 44, 45, 47, 217, 218, 221, 300, 323
—— of body and mind, Lamarck on the, 338, 339, 341
[Pg 420]Interesting, the more captivating the animal, the more evolution Buffon incorporates into his description of it, 84
Intermediate forms, Lamarck on, 283, 286
—— C. Darwin, 284, 285
Inventions, small successive improvements in human inventions, and development, are akin to those of organisms, 44, 46, 47, 54, 55, 384
Irony, good-natured and otherwise, 91
—— an apology for, and explanation of how far it is legitimate, 111, 112
—— Buffon's, 78, &c., 91, 92, 93, 155, 157, 163, 164
JARDINE, Sir W., on Buffon's character, 82
Johnson, Dr., and Erasmus Darwin, 184, 185
Joints, Paley on the human, 19, 20
Juggle, Paley's argument is a juggle unless man has a bona fide personal, and therefore organic designer, 14, 16
KNEE-PAN, Paley on the human, 18
Knowledge, nomenclature mistaken for, 141
LABOUR, glory comes after, if she can, 76
Lamarck, had brain upon the brain, 36
—— never fully recognized design, 39
—— Haeckel's surprising statement concerning, 73
—— where he mainly differs from Buffon, __A
The Mayflower Press, Plymouth, England. William Brendon & Son, Ltd.
The Mayflower Press, Plymouth, England. William Brendon & Son, Ltd.
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!