This is a modern-English version of Plutarch's Morals, originally written by Plutarch. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.


BOHN'S CLASSICAL LIBRARY

PLUTARCH'S MORALS

GEORGE BELL & SONS,
LONDON: YORK STREET, COVENT GARDEN
NEW YORK: 66, FIFTH AVENUE, AND
BOMBAY: 53, ESILANADE ROAD
CAMBRIDGE: DEIGHTON, BELL & CO.

PLUTARCH'S MORALS

ETHICAL ESSAYS

TRANSLATED

WITH NOTES AND INDEX

BY ARTHUR RICHARD SHILLETO, M.A.

Sometime Scholar of Trinity College, Cambridge,
Translator of Pausanias.
Printers mark
LONDON
GEORGE BELL AND SONS
1898
CHISWICK PRESS:—CHARLES WHITTINGHAM AND CO., TOOKS COURT,
CHANCERY LANE.

Transcriber's note: The original book uses often colons instead of semicolons. Spelling of proper names is different in different pages and some words occur in hyphenated and unhyphenated forms. These have not been changed. A couple of commas and periods have been added or removed to improve the reading and only obvious spelling errors have been corrected.

Transcriber's note: The original book often uses colons instead of semicolons. The spelling of proper names varies across different pages, and some words appear in both hyphenated and unhyphenated forms. These have not been altered. A few commas and periods have been added or removed for better readability, and only obvious spelling mistakes have been fixed.


PREFACE.

Plutarch, who was born at Chæronea in Bœotia, probably about A.D. 50, and was a contemporary of Tacitus and Pliny, has written two works still extant, the well-known Lives, and the less-known Moralia. The Lives have often been translated, and have always been a popular work. Great indeed was their power at the period of the French Revolution. The Moralia, on the other hand, consisting of various Essays on various subjects (only twenty-six of which are directly ethical, though they have given their name to the Moralia), are declared by Mr. Paley "to be practically almost unknown to most persons in Britain, even to those who call themselves scholars."1 Habent etiam sua fata libelli.

Plutarch, who was born in Chæronea in Bœotia around A.D. 50 and was a contemporary of Tacitus and Pliny, wrote two works that still exist today: the well-known Lives and the less-known Moralia. The Lives have been translated many times and have always been popular. Their influence was particularly strong during the time of the French Revolution. The Moralia, on the other hand, is made up of various essays on different subjects (only twenty-six of which are directly ethical, even though they lent their name to the Moralia), which Mr. Paley has stated are "practically almost unknown to most people in Britain, even to those who consider themselves scholars." 1 Habent etiam sua fata libelli.

In older days the Moralia were more valued. Montaigne, who was a great lover of Plutarch, and who observes in one passage of his Essays that "Plutarch and Seneca were the only two books of solid learning he seriously settled himself to read," quotes as much from the Moralia as from the Lives. And in the seventeenth century I cannot but think the Moralia were largely read at our Universities, at least at the University of Cambridge. For, not to mention the wonderful way in which the famous Jeremy Taylor has taken the cream of "Conjugal Precepts" in his Sermon called "The Marriage Ring," or the large and copious use viiihe has made in his "Holy Living" of three other Essays in this volume, namely, those "On Curiosity," "On Restraining Anger," and "On Contentedness of Mind," proving conclusively what a storehouse he found the Moralia, we have evidence that that most delightful poet, Robert Herrick, read the Moralia, too, when at Cambridge, so that one cannot but think it was a work read in the University course generally in those days. For in a letter to his uncle written from Cambridge, asking for books or money for books, he makes the following remark: "How kind Arcisilaus the philosopher was unto Apelles the painter, Plutark in his Morals will tell you."2

In the past, the Moralia were highly regarded. Montaigne, a huge fan of Plutarch, notes in one part of his Essays that "Plutarch and Seneca were the only two books of solid learning he really committed to reading," and he quotes just as much from the Moralia as from the Lives. I believe the Moralia were widely read at our universities in the seventeenth century, especially at the University of Cambridge. For instance, the renowned Jeremy Taylor took the essence of "Conjugal Precepts" in his sermon called "The Marriage Ring," and he extensively referenced three other essays from this volume, namely, "On Curiosity," "On Restraining Anger," and "On Contentedness of Mind," showing how much he valued the Moralia. We also know that the delightful poet Robert Herrick read the Moralia while at Cambridge, suggesting it was commonly included in the university curriculum back then. In a letter to his uncle from Cambridge, where he asked for books or money for books, he mentions: "How kind Arcisilaus the philosopher was unto Apelles the painter, Plutarch in his Morals will tell you."2

In 1882 the Reverend C. W. King, Senior Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge, translated the six "Theosophical Essays" of the Moralia, forming a volume in Bohn's Classical Library. The present volume consists of the twenty-six "Ethical Essays," which are, in my opinion, the cream of the Moralia, and constitute a highly interesting series of treatises on what might be called "The Ethics of the Hearth and Home." I have grouped these Essays in such a manner as to enable the reader to read together such as touch on the same or on kindred subjects.

In 1882, Reverend C. W. King, Senior Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge, translated six "Theosophical Essays" from the Moralia, creating a volume for Bohn's Classical Library. This volume contains the twenty-six "Ethical Essays," which I believe are the best part of the Moralia and form a fascinating series of discussions on what we might call "The Ethics of the Hearth and Home." I have organized these essays in a way that allows readers to explore those that address similar or related topics together.

As is well known, the text of the Moralia is very corrupt, and the reading very doubtful, in many places. In eight of the twenty-six Essays in this volume I have had the invaluable help of the text of Rudolf Hercher; help so invaluable that one cannot but sadly regret that only one volume of the Moralia has yet appeared in the Bibliotheca Teubneriana. Wyttenbach's text and notes I have always used when available, and when not so have fallen back upon Reiske. Reiske is always ingenious, but too fond of correcting a text, and the criticism of him by Wyttenbach ixis perhaps substantially correct. "In nullo auctore habitabat; vagabatur per omnes: nec apud quemquam tamdiu divertebat, ut in paulo interiorem ejus consuetudinem se insinuaret." I have also had constantly before me the Didot Edition of the Moralia, edited by Frederic Dübner.

As is well known, the text of the Moralia is quite corrupted, and the readings are very uncertain in many places. In eight of the twenty-six essays in this volume, I have had the invaluable assistance of Rudolf Hercher's text; this help is so invaluable that it’s a shame that only one volume of the Moralia has been published in the Bibliotheca Teubneriana so far. I have always used Wyttenbach's text and notes when they were available, and when they weren't, I relied on Reiske. Reiske is always clever, but he tends to correct the text too much, and Wyttenbach's criticism of him ix is likely quite accurate. "In nullo auctore habitabat; vagabatur per omnes: nec apud quemquam tamdiu divertebat, ut in paulo interiorem ejus consuetudinem se insinuaret." I've also kept the Didot Edition of the Moralia, edited by Frederic Dübner, constantly in mind.

Let any reader who wishes to know more about Plutarch, consult the article on Plutarch, in the Ninth Edition of the Encyclopaedia Britannica, by the well-known scholar F. A. Paley. He will also do well to read an Essay on Plutarch by R. W. Emerson, reprinted in Volume III. of the Bohn's Standard Library Edition of Emerson's Works, and Five Lectures on Plutarch by the late Archbishop Trench, published by Messrs. Macmillan and Co. in 1874. All these contain much of interest, and will repay perusal.

Let any reader who wants to learn more about Plutarch check out the article on Plutarch in the Ninth Edition of the Encyclopaedia Britannica, written by the well-known scholar F. A. Paley. It's also a good idea to read an essay on Plutarch by R. W. Emerson, which is included in Volume III of the Bohn's Standard Library Edition of Emerson's Works, and Five Lectures on Plutarch by the late Archbishop Trench, published by Messrs. Macmillan and Co. in 1874. All of these contain a lot of interesting information and are worth reading.

In conclusion, I hope this little volume will be the means of making popular some of the best thoughts of one of the most interesting and thoughtful of the ancients, who often seems indeed almost a modern.

In conclusion, I hope this small book will help spread some of the best ideas from one of the most fascinating and reflective figures of the ancient world, who often feels quite modern.

Cambridge,
March, 1888.

Cambridge,
March 1888.

1 See article Plutarch, in Encyclopaedia Britannica, Ninth Edition.

1 See article Plutarch, in Encyclopaedia Britannica, Ninth Edition.

2 Grosart's Herrick, vol. i. p. liii. See in this volume, p. 180, and also note to p. 288. Richard Baxter again is always quoting the Moralia.

2 Grosart's Herrick, vol. i. p. liii. Check this volume, p. 180, and also refer to note on p. 288. Richard Baxter frequently cites the Moralia.


CONTENTS

    Page
I.

ON EDUCATION.

ON EDUCATION.

1
II.

ON LOVE TO ONE'S OFFSPRING.

ON LOVE FOR ONE'S KIDS.

21
III.

ON LOVE.

ON LOVE.

29
IV.

CONJUGAL PRECEPTS.

Marriage Principles.

70
V.

CONSOLATORY LETTER TO HIS WIFE.

Sympathy letter to his wife.

85
VI.

THAT VIRTUE MAY BE TAUGHT.

Virtue can be taught.

92
VII.

ON VIRTUE AND VICE.

ON GOOD AND BAD.

95
VIII.

ON MORAL VIRTUE.

ON MORAL VIRTUE.

98
IX.

HOW ONE MAY BE AWARE OF ONE'S PROGRESS IN VIRTUE.

HOW ONE MAY BE AWARE OF ONE'S PROGRESS IN VIRTUE.

118
X.

WHETHER VICE IS SUFFICIENT TO CAUSE UNHAPPINESS.

WHETHER VICE IS ENOUGH TO CAUSE UNHAPPINESS.

138
XI.

WHETHER THE DISORDERS OF MIND OR BODY ARE WORSE.

WHICH IS WORSE, MENTAL OR PHYSICAL DISORDERS?

142
XII.

ON ABUNDANCE OF FRIENDS.

ON HAVING LOTS OF FRIENDS.

145
XIII.

HOW ONE MAY DISCERN A FLATTERER FROM A FRIEND.

HOW TO TELL A FLATTERER FROM A FRIEND.

153
XIV.

HOW A MAN MAY BE BENEFITED BY HIS ENEMIES.

HOW A MAN CAN BENEFIT FROM HIS ENEMIES.

201
XV.

ON TALKATIVENESS.

ON CHATTINESS.

214
XVI.

ON CURIOSITY.

ON CURIOSITY.

238
XVII.

ON SHYNESS.

ON SOCIAL ANXIETY.

252
XVIII.

ON RESTRAINING ANGER.

ON MANAGING ANGER.

267
XIX.

ON CONTENTEDNESS OF MIND.

On Being Content.

289
XX.

ON ENVY AND HATRED.

ON ENVY AND HATRED.

312
XXI.

HOW ONE CAN PRAISE ONESELF WITHOUT EXCITING ENVY.

HOW ONE CAN PRAISE ONESELF WITHOUT CREATING ENVY.

315
XXII.

ON THOSE WHO ARE PUNISHED BY THE DEITY LATE.

ON THOSE WHO ARE PUNISHED BY THE DEITY LATE.

331
XXIII.

AGAINST BORROWING MONEY.

NO TO BORROWING MONEY.

365
XXIV.

WHETHER "LIVE UNKNOWN" BE A WISE PRECEPT.

WHETHER "LIVE UNKNOWN" IS A SMART ADVICE.

373
XXV.

ON EXILE.

In Exile.

378
XXVI.

ON FORTUNE.

ON FATE.

394
     
INDEX   401

PLUTARCH'S MORALS.

ON EDUCATION.

§ i. Come let us consider what one might say on the education of free children, and by what training they would become good citizens.

§ i. Come, let's think about what we can say regarding the education of free children, and how they can be trained to become good citizens.

§ ii. It is perhaps best to begin with birth: I would therefore warn those who desire to be fathers of notable sons, not to form connections with any kind of women, such as courtesans or mistresses: for those who either on the father or mother's side are ill-born have the disgrace of their origin all their life long irretrievably present with them, and offer a ready handle to abuse and vituperation. So that the poet was wise, who said, "Unless the foundation of a house be well laid, the descendants must of necessity be unfortunate."3 Good birth indeed brings with it a store of assurance, which ought to be greatly valued by all who desire legitimate offspring. For the spirit of those who are a spurious and bastard breed is apt to be mean and abject: for as the poet truly says, "It makes a man even of noble spirit servile, when he is conscious of the ill fame of either his father or mother."4 On the other hand the sons of illustrious parents are full of pride and arrogance. As an instance of this it is recorded of Diophantus,5 the son of Themistocles, that he often used to say to various people "that he could do what he pleased with the Athenian people, for what he wished his mother wished, and what she wished Themistocles wished, and what Themistocles 2wished all the Athenians wished." All praise also ought we to bestow on the Lacedæmonians for their loftiness of soul in fining their king Archidamus for venturing to marry a small woman, for they charged him with intending to furnish them not with kings but kinglets.

§ ii. It’s probably best to start with birth: so I would advise those who want to be fathers of notable sons not to get involved with any kind of women, like courtesans or mistresses. Those who are poorly born on either the father’s or mother’s side carry the disgrace of their origins for their entire lives, making them easy targets for insults and criticism. Therefore, the poet was wise when he said, "Unless the foundation of a house is well laid, the descendants must inevitably be unfortunate."3 Good birth truly provides a strong sense of assurance, which should be highly valued by anyone wishing for legitimate offspring. The spirit of those from illegitimate or lowly backgrounds tends to be weak and lowly: as the poet accurately says, "It makes a man, even of noble spirit, servile, when he is aware of the bad reputation of either his father or mother."4 On the flip side, the sons of renowned parents are often filled with pride and arrogance. For example, it’s recorded that Diophantus,5 the son of Themistocles, frequently told various people that he could do whatever he wanted with the Athenian people because what he wanted, his mother wanted, and what she wanted, Themistocles wanted, and whatever Themistocles wanted, all the Athenians wanted. We should also commend the Lacedæmonians for their noble spirit in fining their king Archidamus for marrying a short woman, as they accused him of wanting to produce not kings but minor rulers.

§ iii. Next must we mention, what was not overlooked even by those who handled this subject before us, that those who approach their wives for procreation must do so either without having drunk any wine or at least very little. For those children, that their parents begot in drink, are wont to be fond of wine and apt to turn out drunkards. And so Diogenes, seeing a youth out of his mind and crazy, said, "Young man, your father was drunk when he begot you." Let this hint serve as to procreation: now let us discuss education.

§ iii. Next, we should mention, something that hasn’t gone unnoticed by those who discussed this topic before us: those who approach their wives for having children should either do so without drinking any wine or only have a little. Children whose parents conceived them while drunk tend to love wine and often end up being alcoholics. Diogenes, seeing a young man acting crazy, said, "Young man, your father was drunk when he conceived you." With that in mind about procreation, let's move on to education.

§ iv. To speak generally, what we are wont to say about the arts and sciences is also true of moral excellence, for to its perfect development three things must meet together, natural ability, theory, and practice. By theory I mean training, and by practice working at one's craft. Now the foundation must be laid in training, and practice gives facility, but perfection is attained only by the junction of all three. For if any one of these elements be wanting, excellence must be so far deficient. For natural ability without training is blind: and training without natural ability is defective, and practice without both natural ability and training is imperfect. For just as in farming the first requisite is good soil, next a good farmer, next good seed, so also here: the soil corresponds to natural ability, the training to the farmer, the seed to precepts and instruction. I should therefore maintain stoutly that these three elements were found combined in the souls of such universally famous men as Pythagoras, and Socrates, and Plato, and of all who have won undying fame. Happy at any rate and dear to the gods is he to whom any deity has vouchsafed all these elements! But if anyone thinks that those who have not good natural ability cannot to some extent make up for the deficiencies of nature by right training and practice, let such a one know that he is very wide of the mark, if not out of it altogether. For good natural parts are impaired by sloth; while inferior ability is3 mended by training: and while simple things escape the eyes of the careless, difficult things are reached by painstaking. The wonderful efficacy and power of long and continuous labour you may see indeed every day in the world around you.6 Thus water continually dropping wears away rocks: and iron and steel are moulded by the hands of the artificer: and chariot wheels bent by some strain can never recover their original symmetry: and the crooked staves of actors can never be made straight. But by toil what is contrary to nature becomes stronger than even nature itself. And are these the only things that teach the power of diligence? Not so: ten thousand things teach the same truth. A soil naturally good becomes by neglect barren, and the better its original condition, the worse its ultimate state if uncared for. On the other hand a soil exceedingly rough and sterile by being farmed well produces excellent crops. And what trees do not by neglect become gnarled and unfruitful, whereas by pruning they become fruitful and productive? And what constitution so good but it is marred and impaired by sloth, luxury, and too full habit? And what weak constitution has not derived benefit from exercise and athletics? And what horses broken in young are not docile to their riders? while if they are not broken in till late they become hard-mouthed and unmanageable. And why should we be surprised at similar cases, seeing that we find many of the savagest animals docile and tame by training? Rightly answered the Thessalian, who was asked who the mildest Thessalians were, "Those who have done with fighting."7 But why pursue the line of argument further? For the Greek name for moral virtue is only habit: and if anyone defines moral virtues as habitual virtues, he will not be beside the mark. But I will employ only one more illustration, and dwell no longer on this topic. Lycurgus, the Lacedæmonian legislator, took two puppies of the same parents, and brought them up in an entirely different way: the one he pampered and cosseted up, while he taught the other to hunt and be a retriever. Then on one occasion, when the 4Lacedæmonians were convened in assembly, he said, "Mighty, O Lacedæmonians, is the influence on moral excellence of habit, and education, and training, and modes of life, as I will prove to you at once." So saying he produced the two puppies, and set before them a platter and a hare: the one darted on the hare, while the other made for the platter. And when the Lacedæmonians could not guess what his meaning was, or with what intent he had produced the puppies, he said, "These puppies are of the same parents, but by virtue of a different bringing up the one is pampered, and the other a good hound." Let so much suffice for habit and modes of life.

§ iv. Generally speaking, what we often say about the arts and sciences also applies to moral excellence. To achieve its perfect development, we need three things: natural ability, theory, and practice. By theory, I mean training, and by practice, I mean working on one’s skills. The foundation must be built through training, and practice develops skill, but perfection is only reached through the combination of all three. If any one of these elements is missing, excellence will be lacking. Natural ability without training is directionless; training without natural ability is limited, and practice without both natural ability and training is incomplete. Just like in farming, where quality soil is essential, followed by a good farmer and good seed, here too: soil represents natural ability, training represents the farmer, and seed represents principles and instruction. Thus, I firmly assert that these three components were present in the lives of renowned individuals like Pythagoras, Socrates, and Plato, among others who achieved lasting fame. Blessed indeed is the person whom any divine force has granted all these elements! However, if anyone believes that lacking natural ability means one cannot somewhat compensate for nature's deficiencies through proper training and practice, they are greatly mistaken, if not entirely wrong. Natural talent can be wasted by laziness, while lesser talent can improve through training; simple tasks may go unnoticed by the indifferent, while complex ones require careful effort. The incredible effectiveness and power of sustained labor can be observed daily in the world around us.6 Just as water that persistently drips gradually erodes rocks, and iron and steel are shaped by a craftsman's hands, chariot wheels that have been bent cannot return to their original shape, and twisted staffs of actors cannot be straightened. Yet, through hard work, that which seems contrary to nature can grow stronger than nature itself. Are these the only examples that highlight the power of diligence? Not at all; countless examples demonstrate the same lesson. Untended, fertile soil can become barren, and the better its initial condition, the worse its final state if neglected. Conversely, rough and barren soil, when well-farmed, can produce excellent crops. Trees left unattended become twisted and unfruitful, while pruning helps them thrive. What healthy body hasn’t suffered from laziness, indulgence, and overindulgence? And what weak physique hasn’t benefited from exercise and athletics? What young horses that have been trained properly are not responsive to their riders? Yet, those that aren’t trained until later can become difficult and unmanageable. Why should we be surprised by similar outcomes, given that many fierce animals can be tamed through training? The Thessalian who was asked who the kindest Thessalians were rightly replied, "Those who have stopped fighting." 7 But why delve deeper into this argument? The Greek term for moral virtue essentially means habit, and if one defines moral virtues as habitual virtues, they are on the right track. However, I will only use one more example and won’t elaborate further. Lycurgus, the lawgiver from Lacedæmon, raised two puppies from the same parents in entirely different ways: one was spoiled and pampered, while the other was trained to hunt and retrieve. Then, one time, when the Lacedæmonians were gathered, he declared, "O Lacedæmonians, the influence of habit, education, training, and lifestyle on moral excellence is profound, as I will now demonstrate." With that, he brought forth the two puppies and placed a platter and a hare before them. One puppy dashed for the hare, while the other went for the platter. When the Lacedæmonians couldn't understand the purpose of the demonstration, he explained, "These puppies have the same parents, but their different upbringing has resulted in one being spoiled and the other being a skilled hound." Let this suffice regarding habit and lifestyle.

§ v. The next point to discuss will be nutrition. In my opinion mothers ought to nurse and suckle their own children. For they will bring them up with more sympathy and care, if they love them so intimately and, as the proverb puts it, "from their first growing their nails."8 Whereas the affection of wet or dry nurses is spurious and counterfeit, being merely for pay. And nature itself teaches that mothers ought themselves to suckle and rear those they have given birth to. And for that purpose she has supplied every female parent with milk. And providence has wisely provided women with two breasts, so that if they should bear twins, they would have a breast for each. And besides this, as is natural enough, they would feel more affection and love for their children by suckling them. For this supplying them with food is as it were a tightener of love, for even the brute creation, if taken away from their young, pine away, as we constantly see. Mothers must therefore, as I said, certainly try to suckle their own children: but if they are unable to do so either through physical weakness (for this contingency sometimes occurs), or in haste to have other children, they must select wet and dry nurses with the greatest care, and not introduce into their houses any kind of women. First and foremost they must be Greeks in their habits. For just as it is necessary immediately after birth to shapen the limbs of children, so that they may grow straight and not crooked, so from the beginning must their habits be carefully 5attended to. For infancy is supple and easily moulded, and what children learn sinks deeply into their souls while they are young and tender, whereas everything hard is softened only with great difficulty. For just as seals are impressed on soft wax, so instruction leaves its permanent mark on the minds of those still young. And divine Plato seems to me to give excellent advice to nurses not to tell their children any kind of fables, that their souls may not in the very dawn of existence be full of folly or corruption.9 Phocylides the poet also seems to give admirable advice when he says, "We must teach good habits while the pupil is still a boy."

§ v. The next topic to talk about is nutrition. In my opinion, mothers should breastfeed their own children. They will raise them with more empathy and care, having that close bond, as the saying goes, "from the time they start growing their nails."8 The affection shown by wet or dry nurses is fake and just for payment. Nature itself shows that mothers should breastfeed and raise the children they have brought into the world. To support this, every female parent is given milk. Moreover, nature wisely equipped women with two breasts, so if they have twins, each child has a breast. Also, it’s natural for them to feel stronger affection and love for their children while breastfeeding. Providing food like this strengthens love; even animals, if separated from their young, often suffer, as we frequently observe. Therefore, mothers must certainly try to breastfeed their own children: if they can’t due to physical weakness (which sometimes happens) or because they want to have more children quickly, they need to choose their wet or dry nurses very carefully and not allow just any women into their homes. First and foremost, these nurses should be Greek in their customs. It’s essential, just like shaping the limbs of children right after birth to ensure they grow straight and not crooked, to pay close attention to their habits from the start. Infancy is flexible and easily shaped, and what children learn deeply influences their minds when they are young and soft; in contrast, harder lessons are learned much more slowly. Just as seals make impressions on soft wax, teaching leaves a lasting impact on young minds. Divine Plato seems to give great advice to nurses not to share any fables with their children so that their minds aren't filled with foolishness or corruption right from the beginning.9 Phocylides, the poet, also offers wise counsel when he says, "We must teach good habits while the pupil is still a boy."

§ vi. Attention also must he given to this point, that the lads that are to wait upon and be with young people must be first and foremost of good morals, and able to speak Greek distinctly and idiomatically, that they may not by contact with foreigners of loose morals contract any of their viciousness. For as those who are fond of quoting proverbs say not amiss, "If you live with a lame man, you will learn to halt."10

§ vi. It's also important to note that the young men who are to be around and interact with young people must be of good character and able to speak Greek clearly and accurately, so they don’t pick up any bad habits from immoral foreigners. As the saying goes, "If you hang out with a lame person, you'll learn to limp."10

§ vii. Next, when our boys are old enough to be put into the hands of tutors,11 great care must be taken that we do not hand them over to slaves, or foreigners, or flighty persons. For what happens nowadays in many cases is highly ridiculous: good slaves are made farmers, or sailors, or merchants, or stewards, or money-lenders; but if they find a winebibbing, greedy, and utterly useless slave, to him parents commit the charge of their sons, whereas the good tutor ought to be such a one as was Phœnix, the tutor of Achilles. The point also which I am now going to speak about is of the utmost importance. The schoolmasters we ought to select for our boys should be of blameless life, of pure character, and of great experience. For a good training is the source and root of gentlemanly behaviour. And just as farmers prop up their trees, so good schoolmasters prop up the young by good advice and suggestions, 6that they may become upright. How one must despise, therefore, some fathers, who, whether from ignorance or inexperience, before putting the intended teachers to the test, commit their sons to the charge of untried and untested men. If they act so through inexperience it is not so ridiculous; but it is to the remotest degree absurd when, though perfectly aware of both the inexperience and worthlessness of some schoolmasters, they yet entrust their sons to them; some overcome by flattery, others to gratify friends who solicit their favours; acting just as if anybody ill in body, passing over the experienced physician, should, to gratify his friend, call him in, and so throw away his life; or as if to gratify one's friend one should reject the best pilot and choose him instead. Zeus and all the gods! can anyone bearing the sacred name of father put obliging a petitioner before obtaining the best education for his sons? Were they not then wise words that the time-honoured Socrates used to utter, and say that he would proclaim, if he could, climbing up to the highest part of the city, "Men, what can you be thinking of, who move heaven and earth to make money, while you bestow next to no attention on the sons you are going to leave that money to?"12 I would add to this that such fathers act very similarly to a person who should be very careful about his shoe but care nothing about his foot. Many persons also are so niggardly about their children, and indifferent to their interests, that for the sake of a paltry saving, they prefer worthless teachers for their children, practising a vile economy at the expense of their children's ignorance. Apropos of this, Aristippus on one occasion rebuked an empty-headed parent neatly and wittily. For being asked how much money a parent ought to pay for his son's education, he answered, "A thousand drachmæ." And he replying, "Hercules, what a price! I could buy a slave for as much;" Aristippus answered, "You shall have two slaves then, your son and the slave you buy."13 And is it not altogether strange that you accustom your son to take his food in his right hand, and chide him if he 7offers his left, whereas you care very little about his hearing good and sound discourses? I will tell you what happens to such admirable fathers, when they have educated and brought up their sons so badly: when the sons grow to man's estate, they disregard a sober and well-ordered life, and rush headlong into disorderly and low vices; then at the last the parents are sorry they have neglected their education, bemoaning bitterly when it is too late their sons' debasement. For some of them keep flatterers and parasites in their retinue—an accursed set of wretches, the defilers and pest of youth; others keep mistresses and common prostitutes, wanton and costly; others waste their money in eating; others come to grief through dice and revelling; some even go in for bolder profligacy, being whoremongers and defilers of the marriage bed,14 who would madly pursue their darling vice if it cost them their lives. Had they associated with some philosopher, they would not have lowered themselves by such practices, but would have remembered the precept of Diogenes, whose advice sounds rather low, but is really of excellent moral intent,15 "Go into a brothel, my lad, that you may see the little difference between vice and virtue."

§ vii. Next, when our boys are old enough to be placed in the care of tutors,11 we must be very careful not to hand them over to slaves, foreigners, or irresponsible individuals. What happens often today is quite ridiculous: good slaves become farmers, sailors, merchants, stewards, or money-lenders; but if parents find a drunken, greedy, and completely useless slave, they entrust their sons to him. The right tutor should be someone like Phœnix, the tutor of Achilles. The point I want to discuss now is extremely important. The schoolmasters we choose for our boys should have clean lives, pure characters, and extensive experience. Good training is the foundation of proper behavior. Just as farmers support their trees, good schoolmasters support the young with good advice and guidance, 6 so they can grow up straight. It’s really shameful for some fathers, who either out of ignorance or inexperience, put their sons in the care of untested and unreliable men without checking them first. If they act out of inexperience, it’s not so ridiculous; but it’s absurd to entrust their sons to inept schoolmasters when they know how unqualified they are—some are swayed by flattery, while others want to please friends who ask for favors. It’s like someone who is sick neglecting a skilled doctor just to satisfy a friend, risking their life; or choosing an inferior pilot just to please someone. Zeus and all the gods! Can a man who calls himself a father prioritize pleasing a friend over obtaining the best education for his sons? Wasn’t it wise what the well-respected Socrates used to say, that if he could, he would shout from the rooftops, “Men, what are you thinking? You move heaven and earth to make money while hardly paying attention to the sons who will inherit that money?”12 Additionally, such fathers act much like someone who is overly concerned about their shoe but indifferent to the wellbeing of their foot. Many people are so greedy regarding their children, yet neglect their interests, that for a small saving, they choose worthless teachers for their kids, practicing a terrible economy that sacrifices their children’s education. Apropos of this, Aristippus once cleverly rebuked a foolish parent. When asked how much a father should spend on his son's education, he replied, "A thousand drachmæ." The parent responded, "Hercules, what a price! I could buy a slave for that." Aristippus replied, "Then you shall have two slaves: your son and the slave you buy."13 Isn’t it strange that you make sure your son eats with his right hand and scold him for using his left, while you hardly care about him hearing good and meaningful conversations? I can tell you what happens with such misguided fathers: when their sons reach adulthood, they disregard a disciplined and proper life, diving headfirst into unruly and base vices; then, sadly, the parents regret their neglect of education, lamenting their sons' downfall when it’s too late. Some keep flatterers and parasites around them—an accursed bunch, ruining and corrupting youth; others have mistresses and prostitutes, wanton and expensive; others squander their money on lavish meals; others get into trouble with gambling and partying; some even engage in bolder debauchery, pursuing promiscuity and desecration of marriage,14 recklessly chasing their favorite vices even at the cost of their lives. Had they associated with some philosopher, they wouldn’t have degraded themselves this way but would have followed the advice of Diogenes, whose words may sound humble but are filled with excellent moral intent,15 "Go into a brothel, my lad, so you can see the little difference between vice and virtue."

§ viii. I say, then, to speak comprehensively (and I might be justly considered in so saying to speak as an oracle, not to be delivering a mere precept), that a good education and sound bringing-up is of the first and middle and last importance; and I declare it to be most instrumental and conducive to virtue and happiness. For all other human blessings compared to this are petty and insignificant. For noble birth is a great honour, but it is an advantage from our forefathers. And wealth is valuable, but it is the acquisition of fortune, who has often taken it away from those who had it, and brought it to those who little expected it; and much wealth is a sort of mark for villanous slaves and informers to shoot at to fill their own 8purses; and, what is a most important point, even the greatest villains have money sometimes. And glory is noble, but insecure. And beauty is highly desirable, but shortlived. And health is highly valuable, but soon impaired. And strength is desirable, but illness or age soon made sad inroads into it. And generally speaking, if anyone prides himself on his bodily strength, let him know that he is deficient in judgment. For how much inferior is the strength of a man to that of animals, as elephants, bulls, and lions! But education is of all our advantages the only one immortal and divine. And two of the most powerful agencies in man's nature are mind and reason. And mind governs reason, and reason obeys mind; and mind is irremovable by fortune, cannot be taken away by informers, cannot be destroyed by disease, cannot have inroads made into it by old age. For the mind alone flourishes in age; and while time takes away everything else, it adds wisdom to old age. Even war, that sweeps away everything else like a winter torrent, cannot take away education. And Stilpo, the Megarian, seems to me to have made a memorable answer when Demetrius enslaved Megara and rased it to the ground. On his asking whether Stilpo had lost anything, he replied, "Certainly not, for war can make no havoc of virtue." Corresponding and consonant to this is the answer of Socrates, who when asked, I think by Gorgias,16 if he had any conception as to the happiness of the King of Persia, replied, "I do not know his position in regard to virtue and education: for happiness lies in these, and not in adventitious advantages."

§ viii. So, I’d like to say, to put it simply (and you might think I’m wise for saying this, rather than just offering advice), that a good education and solid upbringing are incredibly important at every stage of life; I truly believe they are key to virtue and happiness. Compared to this, all other human blessings seem minor and insignificant. Noble birth is a great honor, but it comes from our ancestors. Wealth is valuable, but it’s often just a stroke of luck, which can be taken away from some and given to others unexpectedly. And having a lot of wealth can make one a target for greedy people looking to line their pockets; plus, even the worst villains sometimes have money. Glory is admirable, but it’s not stable. Beauty is highly desired, but it fades quickly. Health is very important, but it can be easily damaged. Strength is great, but illness or aging can quickly diminish it. Generally, if someone takes pride in their physical strength, they should realize they lack good judgment. After all, how much weaker is a human compared to strong animals like elephants, bulls, and lions? But education is the only advantage we have that is eternal and divine. Among the strongest aspects of humanity are the mind and reason. The mind controls reason, and reason follows the mind; the mind cannot be swayed by fortune, cannot be taken by informers, cannot be destroyed by illness, and cannot be diminished by old age. The mind is the only thing that thrives as we age; while time takes away everything else, it adds wisdom to old age. Even war, which destroys everything like a winter flood, cannot take away education. And Stilpo, the Megarian, gave a memorable reply when Demetrius conquered Megara and destroyed it. When asked if he had lost anything, he said, "Not at all, because war cannot destroy virtue." This ties in with what Socrates said when, I believe, Gorgias asked him about the happiness of the King of Persia; he replied, "I don’t know his standing in terms of virtue and education, because happiness lies in these, not in external advantages."

§ ix. And as I advise parents to think nothing more important than the education of their children, so I maintain that it must be a sound and healthy education, and that our sons must be kept as far as possible from vulgar twaddle. For what pleases the vulgar displeases the wise. I am borne out by the lines of Euripides, "Unskilled am I in the oratory that pleases the mob; but amongst the few that are my equals I am reckoned rather wise. For those who are little thought of by the wise, seem to hit the taste 9of the vulgar."17 And I have myself noticed that those who practise to speak acceptably and to the gratification of the masses promiscuously, for the most part become also profligate and lovers of pleasure in their lives. Naturally enough. For if in giving pleasure to others they neglect the noble, they would be hardly likely to put the lofty and sound above a life of luxury and pleasure, and to prefer moderation to delights. Yet what better advice could we give our sons than to follow this? or to what could we better exhort them to accustom themselves? For perfection is only attained by neither speaking nor acting at random—as the proverb says, Perfection is only attained by practice.18 Whereas extempore oratory is easy and facile, mere windbag, having neither beginning nor end. And besides their other shortcomings extempore speakers fall into great disproportion and repetition, whereas a well considered speech preserves its due proportions. It is recorded by tradition that Pericles, when called on by the people for a speech, frequently refused on the plea that he was unprepared. Similarly Demosthenes, his state-rival, when the Athenians called upon him for his advice, refused to give it, saying, "I am not prepared." But this you will say, perhaps, is mere tradition without authority. But in his speech against Midias he plainly sets forth the utility of preparation, for he says, "I do not deny, men of Athens, that I have prepared this speech to the best of my ability: for I should have been a poor creature if, after suffering so much at his hands, and even still suffering, I had neglected how to plead my case."19 Not that I would altogether reject extempore oratory, or its use in critical cases, but it should be used only as one would take medicine.20 Up, indeed, to man's estate I would have no extempore speaking, but when anyone's powers of speech are rooted and grounded, then, as emergencies call for it, I would allow his words to flow freely. For as those who have been for a long time in fetters stumble if unloosed, not being able 10to walk from being long used to their fetters, so those who for a long time have used compression in their words, if they are suddenly called upon to speak off-hand, retain the same character of expression. But to let mere lads speak extempore is to give rise to the acme of foolish talk. A wretched painter once showed Apelles, they say, a picture, and said, "I have just done it." Apelles replied, "Without your telling me, I should know it was painted quickly; I only wonder you haven't painted more such in the time." As then (for I now return from my digression), I advise to avoid stilted and bombastic language, so again do I urge to avoid a finical and petty style of speech; for tall talk is unpopular, and petty language makes no impression. And as the body ought to be not only sound but in good condition, so speech ought to be not only not feeble but vigorous. For a safe mediocrity is indeed praised, but a bold venturesomeness is also admired. I am also of the same opinion with regard to the disposition of the soul, which ought to be neither audacious nor timid and easily dejected: for the one ends in impudence and the other in servility; but to keep in all things the mean between extremes is artistic and proper. And, while I am still on this topic, I wish to give my opinion, that I regard a monotonous speech first as no small proof of want of taste, next as likely to generate disdain, and certain not to please long. For to harp on one string is always tiresome and brings satiety; whereas variety is pleasant always whether to the ear or eye.

§ ix. Just as I encourage parents to prioritize their children's education above all else, I argue that this education should be solid and healthy, keeping our sons as far away from meaningless chatter as possible. What entertains the masses often frustrates the wise. Euripides puts it well when he says, "I’m not skilled in the kind of speech that pleases the crowd; but among those who are my equals, I’m considered quite wise. Those who lack the approval of the wise often appeal to the taste of the masses."9 17 I’ve also noticed that those who focus on pleasing the crowd generally become careless and indulgent in their personal lives. This makes sense. If they sacrifice nobility to entertain others, they’re unlikely to prioritize higher values over a life filled with luxury and pleasure or choose moderation over excitement. So, what better advice could we give our sons than this? What better habit could we encourage them to adopt? True excellence is achieved by avoiding random speech and action—as the saying goes, Perfection is only attained by practice.18 While impromptu speaking may seem easy and casual, it's often just empty chatter, lacking structure. Impromptu speakers tend to get repetitive and lose balance, while a well-thought-out speech maintains its proportions. There’s a story that Pericles often turned down requests for speeches, claiming he wasn’t ready. Similarly, Demosthenes, his political rival, would refuse to offer his advice to the Athenians, saying, "I'm not prepared." You might argue that this is just tradition without proof, but in his speech against Midias, he clearly emphasizes the importance of preparation, stating, "I admit, men of Athens, that I’ve prepared this speech as well as I could: I would have shown poor judgment if, after enduring so much from him, and still suffering, I hadn’t figured out how to argue my case."19 I don’t completely dismiss extempore speaking or its use in critical situations, but it should be approached like medicine—only when necessary.20 Until someone is fully mature, I wouldn’t endorse extemporaneous speaking; however, when a person’s speech capabilities are solid, I’d let them respond freely as the situation demands. Just as someone who has been in chains for a long time stumbles when freed, having gotten used to their restraints, so too do those who have for a long time constrained their speech struggle to express themselves spontaneously. Allowing young people to speak impromptu leads to the height of foolish chatter. A struggling painter once showed Apelles a painting and said, "I just finished it." Apelles replied, "Without you saying so, I would have guessed it was painted quickly; I only wonder why you didn’t create more in that time." So, to return from my tangent, I advise avoiding both pretentious and overly minor language; grandiloquent speech is off-putting, while trivial language leaves no lasting impact. Just as the body should be healthy and fit, speech should be strong and vigorous, not weak. A safe middle ground is commendable, but boldness is also appreciated. I share this view regarding the soul's disposition, which should be neither overly bold nor cowardly and easily discouraged—because the former leads to arrogance and the latter to servility; finding a balance in everything is an art. Furthermore, I believe that a monotonous speech is not only a sign of poor taste but also likely to breed disdain and fail to hold interest. Repeating the same point becomes tiresome and boring; variety, on the other hand, remains pleasing to both the ear and the eye.

§ x. Next our freeborn lad ought to go in for a course of what is called general knowledge, but a smattering of this will be sufficient, a taste as it were (for perfect knowledge of all subjects would be impossible); but he must seriously cultivate philosophy. I borrow an illustration to show my meaning: it is well to sail round many cities, but advantageous to live in the best. It was a witty remark of the philosopher Bion,21 that, as those suitors who could not seduce Penelope took up with her maids as a pis aller, so those who cannot attain philosophy wear themselves out in useless pursuits. Philosophy, therefore, ought 11to be regarded as the most important branch of study. For as regards the cure of the body, men have found two branches, medicine and exercise: the former of which gives health, and the latter good condition of body; but philosophy is the only cure for the maladies and disorders of the soul. For with her as ruler and guide we can know what is honourable, what is disgraceful; what is just, what unjust; generally speaking, what is to be sought after, what to be avoided; how we ought to behave to the gods, to parents, to elders, to the laws, to foreigners, to rulers, to friends, to women, to children, to slaves: viz., that we ought to worship the gods, honour parents, reverence elders, obey the laws, submit ourselves to rulers, love our friends, be chaste in our relations with women, kind to our children, and not to treat our slaves badly; and, what is of the greatest importance, to be neither over elated in prosperity nor over depressed in adversity,22 nor to be dissolute in pleasures, nor fierce and brutish in anger. These I regard as the principal blessings that philosophy teaches. For to enjoy prosperity nobly shows a man; and to enjoy it without exciting envy shows a moderate man; and to conquer the passions by reason argues a wise man; and it is not everybody who can keep his temper in control. And those who can unite political ability with philosophy I regard as perfect men, for I take them to attain two of the greatest blessings, serving the state in a public capacity, and living the calm and tranquil life of philosophy. For, as there are three kinds of life, the practical, the contemplative, and the life of enjoyment, and of these three the one devoted to enjoyment is a paltry and animal life, and the practical without philosophy an unlovely and harsh life, and the contemplative without the practical a useless life, so we must endeavour with all our power to combine public life with philosophy as far as circumstances will permit. Such was the life led by Pericles, by Archytas of Tarentum, by Dion of Syracuse, by Epaminondas the Theban, one of whom was a disciple of Plato (viz., Dion). And as to education, I do not know that I need dwell any more on it. 12But in addition to what I have said, it is useful, if not necessary, not to neglect to procure old books, and to make a collection of them, as is usual in agriculture. For the use of books is an instrument in education, and it is profitable in learning to go to the fountain head.

§ x. Next, our freeborn young person should take a course in general knowledge, but just a bit of it will do, a taste if you will (because complete mastery of every subject is impossible); however, they must really focus on philosophy. To illustrate my point: it's good to explore many cities, but it's more beneficial to live in the best one. The philosopher Bion once cleverly remarked that just as the suitors who couldn’t win Penelope settled for her maids as a backup, those who can't grasp philosophy exhaust themselves on meaningless activities. Philosophy, therefore, should be seen as the most crucial field of study. When it comes to caring for the body, people have identified two areas: medicine and exercise; the former helps us stay healthy, while the latter keeps us fit; but philosophy is the only remedy for the ailments and troubles of the soul. With philosophy as our guide, we can understand what is honorable and what is disgraceful; what is just and what is unjust; in general, what we should pursue and what we should avoid; how we ought to act toward the gods, our parents, elders, the law, foreigners, rulers, friends, women, children, and slaves: namely, that we should worship the gods, honor our parents, respect our elders, obey the law, submit to rulers, love our friends, be virtuous in our relationships with women, be kind to our children, and not mistreat our slaves; and, most importantly, to avoid being overly elated in good times or excessively down in bad times, nor to indulge excessively in pleasures, nor to be savage and brutal in anger. I see these as the main lessons philosophy teaches. To enjoy prosperity nobly reflects well on a person; to do so without provoking envy shows moderation; to control one's passions with reason demonstrates wisdom; and not everyone can manage to stay calm. Those who can blend political skills with philosophy I regard as ideal individuals, as they achieve two of the greatest blessings: serving the state in a public role while living the peaceful and reflective life of philosophy. There are three types of life: the practical, the contemplative, and the life of pleasure. Of these, the pleasure-focused life is trivial and animalistic, the practical one without philosophy is harsh and unattractive, and the contemplative life without practical application is wasteful. Therefore, we must strive to combine public life with philosophy as much as circumstances allow. This was the kind of life lived by Pericles, Archytas of Tarentum, Dion of Syracuse, and Epaminondas the Theban, one of whom was a student of Plato (namely, Dion). And regarding education, I don't think I need to elaborate further. 12 But in addition to what I've mentioned, it is helpful, if not essential, to make sure to gather old books and build a collection, much like in farming. The use of books is a tool in education, and it’s beneficial to learn from the original sources.

§ xi. Exercise also ought not to be neglected, but we ought to send our boys to the master of the gymnasium to train them duly, partly with a view to carrying the body well, partly with a view to strength. For good habit of body in boys is the foundation of a good old age. For as in fine weather we ought to lay up for winter, so in youth one ought to form good habits and live soberly so as to have a reserve stock of strength for old age. Yet ought we to husband the exertions of the body, so as not to be wearied out by them and rendered unfit for study. For, as Plato says,23 excessive sleep and fatigue are enemies to learning. But why dwell on this? For I am in a hurry to pass to the most important point. Our lads must be trained for warlike encounters, making themselves efficient in hurling the javelin and darts, and in the chase. For the possessions of those who are defeated in battle belong to the conquerors as booty of war; and war is not the place for delicately brought up bodies: it is the spare warrior that makes the best combatant, who as an athlete cuts his way through the ranks of the enemies. Supposing anyone objects: "How so? As you undertook to give advice on the education of freeborn children, do you now neglect the poor and plebeian ones, and give instructions only suitable to the rich?" It is easy enough to meet such critics. I should prefer to make my teaching general and suitable to all; but if any, through their poverty, shall be unable to follow up my precepts, let them blame fortune, and not the author of these hints. We must try with all our might to procure the best education for the poor as well as the rich, but if that is impossible, then we must put up with the practicable. I inserted those matters into my discourse here, that I might hereafter confine myself to all that appertains to the right education of the young.

§ xi. Exercise shouldn't be overlooked; we should send our boys to a gym coach to train them properly, partly for good posture and partly for strength. Good physical habits in boys lay the groundwork for a healthy old age. Just like we prepare for winter during good weather, young people should develop good habits and live soberly to have a reserve of strength for old age. However, we should manage our physical efforts so we’re not worn out and unable to study. As Plato says, excessive sleep and fatigue are barriers to learning. But let's move on; I want to get to the main point. Our boys need to be trained for combat, becoming skilled in throwing javelins and darts, and in hunting. The belongings of those who lose in battle become the spoils of the victors; and war isn’t a place for those who are overly delicate. The lean fighter makes the best soldier, cutting through the enemy ranks like an athlete. If someone argues, "Why focus on freeborn children while ignoring the poor and common ones, giving advice only suitable for the rich?" it's easy to respond. I wish to make my teachings applicable to everyone; but if some can't follow my advice due to their financial situation, they should blame their luck, not me. We must strive to obtain the best education for both the poor and the rich, but if that’s not possible, we must settle for what we can achieve. I included these thoughts in my discussion so that I could later focus on what truly matters in educating the young.

§ xii. And this I say that we ought to try to draw our boys to good pursuits by entreaties and exhortation, but 13certainly not by blows or abusive language. For that seems to be more fitting for slaves than the freeborn. For slaves try to shirk and avoid their work, partly because of the pain of blows, partly on account of being reviled. But praise or censure are far more useful than abuse to the freeborn, praise pricking them on to virtue, censure deterring them from vice. But one must censure and praise alternately: when they are too saucy we must censure them and make them ashamed of themselves, and again encourage them by praise, and imitate those nurses who, when their children sob, give them the breast to comfort them. But we must not puff them up and make them conceited with excessive praise, for that will make them vain and give themselves airs.

§ xii. I believe we should encourage our boys to pursue good activities through gentle persuasion and encouragement, but 13 definitely not through punishment or harsh words. That approach seems more suited for slaves than for free individuals. Slaves often try to escape their responsibilities, partly because they fear punishment and partly because they’re insulted. But praise and constructive criticism are much more effective for the freeborn: praise motivates them to be virtuous, while criticism steers them away from wrongdoing. We should use a mix of both: when they get too arrogant, we should call them out and make them feel ashamed, and at other times, we should lift them up with praise, just like nurses who comfort their crying babies by breastfeeding them. However, we must avoid overly flattering them, as too much praise can lead to vanity and arrogance.

§ xiii. And I have ere now seen some fathers, whose excessive love for their children has turned into hatred. My meaning I will endeavour to make clearer by illustration. While they are in too great a hurry to make their sons take the lead in everything, they lay too much work upon them, so that they faint under their tasks, and, being overburdened, are disinclined for learning. For just as plants grow with moderate rain, but are done for by too much rain, so the mind enlarges by a proper amount of work, but by too much is unhinged. We must therefore give our boys remission from continuous labour, bearing in mind that all our life is divided into labour and rest; thus we find not only wakefulness but sleep, not only war but peace, not only foul weather but fine also, not only working days but also festivals. And, to speak concisely, rest is the sauce of labour. And we can see this not only in the case of animate, but even inanimate things, for we make bows and lyres slack that we may be able to stretch them. And generally the body is preserved by repletion and evacuation, and the soul by rest and work. We ought also to censure some fathers who, after entrusting their sons to tutors and preceptors, neither see nor hear how the teaching is done. This is a great mistake. For they ought after a few days to test the progress of their sons, and not to base their hopes on the behaviour of a hireling; and the preceptors will take all the more pains with the boys, if they have from time to time to give an account of their progress. 14 Hence the propriety of that remark of the groom, that nothing fats the horse so much as the king's eye.24 And especial attention, in my opinion, must be paid to cultivating and exercising the memory of boys, for memory is, as it were, the storehouse of learning; and that was why they fabled Mnemosyne to be the mother of the Muses, hinting and insinuating that nothing so generates and contributes to the growth of learning as memory. And therefore the memory must be cultivated, whether boys have a good one by nature, or a bad one. For we shall so add to natural good parts, and make up somewhat for natural deficiencies, so that the deficient will be better than others, and the clever will outstrip themselves. For good is that remark of Hesiod, "If to a little you keep adding a little, and do so frequently, it will soon be a lot."25 And let not fathers forget, that thus cultivating the memory is not only good for education, but is also a great aid in the business of life. For the remembrance of past actions gives a good model how to deal wisely in future ones.

§ xiii. I've seen some parents whose overwhelming love for their children has turned into resentment. Let me explain this with an example. In their eagerness to push their sons to excel in everything, they overload them with responsibilities, causing them to struggle under the pressure and lose their desire to learn. Just like plants thrive with moderate rain but get ruined by too much, the mind expands with the right amount of work but becomes unbalanced under excess. Therefore, we need to give our boys breaks from constant hard work, remembering that life is made up of both effort and rest; we experience not just wakefulness but sleep, not only war but peace, not just bad weather but nice, and not only workdays but also holidays. To put it simply, rest enhances labor. This can be seen not only in living things but even in inanimate objects, as we loosen bows and lyres to make them easier to stretch. Overall, the body thrives on both fullness and emptiness, while the soul is nourished by a mix of rest and work. We should also critique some parents who, after handing their sons over to tutors, fail to check in on their teaching methods. This is a serious mistake. Parents should evaluate their sons' progress after a few days instead of relying on how hired help is performing; tutors will be more invested in the students if they know they'll need to report on their advancements. 14 Hence the wisdom behind the saying that nothing fattens a horse like the king's eye.24 Additionally, I believe it's vital to focus on developing and exercising boys' memories, because memory is essentially the storage place of knowledge. This is why they mythologized Mnemosyne as the mother of the Muses, implying that nothing fosters learning like memory. Therefore, memory should be nurtured, whether boys have strong or weak ones by nature. By doing this, we enhance their natural talents and somewhat compensate for any shortcomings, making those who struggle outshine others, and the gifted surpass themselves. It aligns with Hesiod's saying, "If you keep adding a little to a little frequently, it will soon become a lot."25 And let parents not forget that by cultivating memory, they not only benefit education but also significantly aid their children's life skills. Remembering past experiences provides a good template for handling future situations wisely.

§ xiv. We must also keep our sons from filthy language. For, as Democritus says, Language is the shadow of action. They must also be taught to be affable and courteous. For as want of affability is justly hateful, so boys will not be disagreeable to those they associate with, if they yield occasionally in disputes. For it is not only excellent to know how to conquer, but also to know how to be defeated, when victory would be injurious, for there is such a thing as a Cadmean victory.26 I can cite wise Euripides as a witness of the truth of what I say, who says, "When two are talking, and one of them is in a passion, he is the wiser who first gives way."27

§ xiv. We also need to keep our sons from using crude language. As Democritus says, language reflects our actions. They should be taught to be friendly and polite. Just as a lack of friendliness is rightly despised, boys won’t annoy their peers if they are willing to back down sometimes during arguments. It's not just great to know how to win, but also how to accept defeat when winning would cause harm, since there is such a thing as a hollow victory.26 I can refer to the wise Euripides, who said, "When two people are talking and one is angry, the smarter one is the first to back down."27

I will next state something quite as important, indeed, if anything, even more important. That is, that life must be spent without luxury, the tongue must be 15under control, so must the temper and the hands. All this is of extreme importance, as I will show by examples. To begin with the last case, some who have put their hands to unjust gains, have lost all the fruits of their former life, as the Lacedæmonian Gylippus,28 who was exiled from Sparta for embezzling the public money. To be able to govern the temper also argues a wise man. For Socrates, when a very impudent and disgusting young fellow kicked him on one occasion, seeing all the rest of his class vexed and impatient, even to the point of wanting to prosecute the young man, said, "What! If a young ass kicked me would you have me kick it back?" Not that the young fellow committed this outrage on Socrates with impunity, for as all reviled him and nicknamed him the kicker, he hung himself. And when Aristophanes brought his "Clouds" on the stage, and bespattered Socrates with his gibes and flouts, and one of the spectators said, "Aren't you vexed, Socrates, at his exhibiting you on the stage in this comic light?" he answered, "Not I, by Zeus, for I look upon the theatre as only a large supper party."29 Very similar to this was the behaviour of Archytas of Tarentum and Plato. The former, on his return from war, where he had been general, finding his land neglected, called his bailiff, and said to him, "You would have caught it, had I not been very angry." And Plato, very angry with a gluttonous and shameless slave, called his sister's son Speusippus, and said, "Go and beat him, for I am too angry." But someone will say, these examples are difficult and hard to follow. I know it. But we must try, as far as possible, following these examples, to avoid ungovernable and mad rage. For we cannot in other respects equal those distinguished men in their ability and virtue, nevertheless we must, like initiating priests of the gods and torchbearers of wisdom, attempt as far as possible to imitate and nibble at their practice. Then, again, if anyone thinks it a small and unimportant matter to govern the tongue, another point I promised to touch on, he is very far from the reality. For silence at the proper season is wisdom, and better than any speech. And that is, I 16think, the reason why the ancients instituted the mysteries that we, learning therein to be silent, might transfer our secrecy to the gods to human affairs. And no one ever yet repented of his silence, while multitudes have repented of their speaking. And what has not been said is easy to say, while what has been once said can never be recalled. I have heard of myriads who have fallen into the greatest misfortunes through inability to govern their tongues. Passing over the rest, I will mention one or two cases in point. When Ptolemy Philadelphus married his sister Arsinoe, Sotades said, "You are contracting an unholy marriage."30 For this speech he long lingered in prison, and paid the righteous penalty for his unseasonable babbling, and had to weep a long time for making others laugh. Theocritus the Sophist similarly cracked his jokes, and had to pay even a greater penalty. For when Alexander ordered the Greeks to furnish him with purple robes to wear at the sacrifices on his triumphal return from war against the barbarians, and his subjects contributed so much per head, Theocritus said, "Before I doubted, but now I am sure, that this is the purple death Homer speaks of."31 By this speech he made Alexander his enemy. The same Theocritus put Antigonus, the King of the Macedonians, a one-eyed man, into a thundering rage by alluding to his misfortune. For the King sent his chief cook, Eutropio, an important person at his court, to go and fetch Theocritus before him to confer with him, and when he had frequently requested him to come without avail, Theocritus at last said, "I know well you wish to serve me up raw to the Cyclops;" flouting the King as one-eyed and the cook with his profession. Eutropio replied, "You shall lose your head, and pay the penalty for this babbling and mad insolence;" and reported his words to the King, who sent and had his head taken off. Our boys must also be taught to speak the truth as a most sacred duty; for to lie is servile, and most hateful in all men, hardly to be pardoned even in poor slaves.

I will now state something just as important, and maybe even more so. Life should be lived without luxury; we must keep our words, our tempers, and our hands in check. This is extremely important, as I will demonstrate with examples. To start with, some who resorted to unjust gains have lost everything they once had, like the Spartan Gylippus, who was exiled from Sparta for stealing public funds. Being able to control your temper shows wisdom. For instance, when a rude young man kicked Socrates, causing everyone in his class to get upset and want to take action, Socrates remarked, "What? If a young donkey kicked me, would you want me to kick it back?" But the young man didn’t escape consequences; everyone insulted him and called him "the kicker," and he ended up taking his own life. When Aristophanes performed his play "Clouds" and mocked Socrates, one audience member asked, "Aren't you upset, Socrates, about being portrayed this way?" Socrates replied, "Not at all, because I see the theater as just a big dinner party." Similarly, Archytas of Tarentum and Plato displayed comparable behavior. After returning from a military campaign where he served as a general, Archytas found his land neglected and told his bailiff, "You would have been in big trouble if I hadn't been so angry." Plato, infuriated by a gluttonous and shameless slave, called his sister's son Speusippus and instructed him, "Go beat him, as I’m too angry to do it myself." Some might argue that these examples are too difficult to emulate. I understand that. But we must do our best to avoid uncontrolled and frenzied anger. While we might never match the abilities and virtues of such remarkable individuals, we should strive, like initiates of the gods and torchbearers of wisdom, to imitate their practices as much as we can. Furthermore, if anyone thinks controlling the tongue is trivial, that’s far from the truth. Wise silence is often better than any speech. I believe this is why the ancients established mysteries, teaching us to be silent, which we could apply to both the divine and human matters. No one has ever regretted being silent, but many have regretted speaking. What hasn’t been said is easy to say, while what has been spoken can never be taken back. I’ve heard of countless people who have faced major misfortunes due to their inability to control their words. To illustrate this, let me mention a couple of examples. When Ptolemy Philadelphus married his sister Arsinoe, Sotades remarked, "You are entering an unholy marriage." For this, he spent a long time in prison, suffering the consequences of his ill-timed comments and ended up crying for making others laugh. Theocritus the Sophist also made jokes and paid an even greater price. When Alexander ordered the Greeks to provide him with purple robes for sacrifices on his victorious return from battle against the barbarians and his subjects contributed accordingly, Theocritus quipped, "Before, I had doubts; now I am sure this is the 'purple death' Homer mentioned." With this remark, he made an enemy of Alexander. Theocritus also angered Antigonus, the one-eyed King of the Macedonians, by referencing his misfortune. When the King sent his chief cook, Eutropio, a significant figure at court, to fetch Theocritus, and after repeated requests failed, Theocritus finally said, "I know you want to serve me up raw to the Cyclops," mocking the king's appearance and Eutropio's profession. Eutropio warned him, "You'll lose your head for this mad insolence," and reported his words to the King, who ordered his execution. Our children must also be taught to tell the truth as the highest duty; lying is servile and detestable to all, often unforgivable even in lowly slaves.

§ xv. Thus much have I said about the good conduct 17and self-control of boys without any doubt or hesitation: but as to what I am now going to say I am doubtful and undecided, and like a person weighed in the scales against exactly his weight, and feel great hesitation as to whether I should recommend or dissuade the practice. But I must speak out. The question is this—whether we ought to let the lovers of our boys associate and be with them, or on the contrary, debar them from their company and scare them off. For when I look at fathers self-opinionated sour and austere, who think their sons having lovers a disgrace not to be borne, I am rather afraid of recommending the practice. But when, on the other hand, I think of Socrates, Xenophon, Æschines, Cebes, and all the company of those men who have approved of male loves, and who have introduced their minions to learning, to high positions in the State, and to good morals, I change my opinion, and am moved to emulate those men. And Euripides seems to favour these views in the passage, "But there is among mortals another love, that of the righteous temperate and pure soul."32 Nor must we omit the remark of Plato, which seems to mix seriousness with mirth, that "those who have distinguished themselves ought to be permitted to kiss any handsome boy they like."33 Those then that seek only carnal enjoyment must be kept off, but those that love the soul must be encouraged. And while the loves common at Thebes and Elis, and the so-called rape at Crete, must be avoided, the loves of Athens and Lacedæmon should be emulated.

§ xv. I've said a lot about the good behavior 17 and self-discipline of boys without any doubt or uncertainty: but now I'm unsure and conflicted about what I’m about to say, feeling like I'm being weighed against my own weight, and I'm hesitant about recommending or discouraging this practice. Still, I need to speak up. The question is whether we should allow those who are attracted to our boys to spend time with them or, on the other hand, keep them away and alarm them. When I see fathers who are self-righteous, bitter, and strict, believing that their sons having lovers is a disgrace, I worry about recommending the practice. But then I think of Socrates, Xenophon, Æschines, Cebes, and all those who supported male love, who helped their mentees pursue education, achieve high positions in the government, and lead good lives, and I find myself swayed to their side. Euripides also seems to support this perspective in the line, "But there is another love among mortals, that of the righteous, temperate, and pure soul."32 We shouldn't forget Plato’s remark, which mixes seriousness with humor, that "those who have distinguished themselves should be allowed to kiss any handsome boy they like."33 Therefore, we need to keep those looking for only physical pleasure away, but we should encourage those who love the soul. While we should avoid the types of affection common in Thebes and Elis, and the so-called abduction in Crete, we should aspire to the loves found in Athens and Lacedæmon.

§ xvi. As to this matter, therefore, let every parent follow his inclination. And now, as I have spoken about the good and decent behaviour of boys, I shall change my subject and speak a little about youths. For I have often censured the introducers of bad habits, who have set over boys tutors and preceptors, but have given to youths full liberty, when they ought, on the contrary, to have watched and guarded them more than boys. For who does not know that the offences of boys are petty and easily cured, and proceed from the carelessness of tutors or want of 18obedience to preceptors; but the faults of young men are often grave and serious, as gluttony, and robbing their fathers, and dice, and revellings, and drinking-bouts, and deflowering of maidens, and seducing of married women. Such outbreaks ought to be carefully checked and curbed. For that prime of life is prodigal in pleasure, and frisky, and needs a bridle, so that those parents who do not strongly check that period, are foolishly, if unawares, giving their youths license for vice.34 Sensible parents, therefore, ought during all that period to guard and watch and restrain their youths, by precepts, by threats, by entreaties, by advice, by promises, by citing examples,35 on the one hand, of those who have come to ruin by being too fond of pleasure, on the other hand, of those who by their self-control have attained to praise and good report. For these are, as it were, the two elements of virtue, hope of honour, and fear of punishment; the former inciting to good practices, the latter deterring from bad.

§ xvi. Regarding this issue, every parent should follow their instincts. Now that I've discussed the proper conduct of boys, I will shift my focus to young men. I have often criticized those who introduce bad habits by providing boys with tutors and teachers, while giving young men complete freedom. In reality, they should be monitored and guided even more than boys. After all, everyone knows that the misdeeds of boys are minor and easily fixed, arising from neglect by tutors or lack of obedience to teachers. However, the mistakes of young men can be serious, such as gluttony, stealing from their fathers, gambling, partying, binge drinking, and seducing young women as well as married women. Such behaviors must be carefully controlled and restricted. This stage of life is often reckless and pleasure-seeking, needing restraint. Therefore, parents who do not firmly supervise this period are foolishly, though perhaps unknowingly, allowing their young men freedom to indulge in vice. 34 Sensible parents should, throughout this time, protect, monitor, and discipline their young men through guidance, warnings, appeals, advice, promises, and examples, 35 highlighting both those who have fallen into ruin from indulgence and those who have earned praise and respect through self-discipline. These represent the two key aspects of virtue: the hope of honor encouraging good behavior, and the fear of punishment deterring bad behavior.

§ xvii. We ought, at all hazards, to keep our boys also from association with bad men, for they will catch some of their villany. This was the meaning of Pythagoras' enigmatical precepts, which I shall quote and explain, as they give no slight momentum towards the acquisition of virtue: as, Do not touch black tails: that is, do not associate with bad men.36 Do not go beyond the balance: that is, we must pay the greatest attention to justice and not go beyond it. Do not sit on a measure: that is, do not be lazy, but earn tomorrow's bread as well as to-day's. Do not give everyone your right hand: that is, do not be too ready to strike up a friendship. Do not wear a tight ring: that is, let your life be free, do not bind yourself by a chain. Do not poke the fire with a sword: that is, do not provoke an angry person, but yield to such. Do not eat the heart: do not wear away the heart by anxiety. Abstain from beans: that is, do not meddle in state affairs, for the voting for offices was formerly taken by beans. Do not put your food in the chamber-pot: that is, do not throw your pearls before swine, for words are the food of the mind, and the villany of men 19twist them to a corrupt meaning. When you have come to the end of a journey do not look back: that is, when people are going to die and see that their end is near, they ought to take it easily and not be dejected. But I will return from my digression. We must keep our boys, as I said, from association with all bad men, but especially from flatterers. For, as I have often said to parents, and still say, and will constantly affirm, there is no race more pestilential, nor more sure to ruin youths swiftly, than the race of flatterers, who destroy both parents and sons root and branch, making the old age of the one and the youth of the others miserable, holding out pleasure as a sure bait. The sons of the rich are by their fathers urged to be sober, but by them to be drunk; by their fathers to be chaste, by them to wax wanton; by their fathers to save, by them to spend; by their fathers to be industrious, by them to be lazy. For they say, "'Our life's but a span;'37 we can only live once; why should you heed your father's threats? he's an old twaddler, he has one foot in the grave; we shall soon hoist him up and carry him off to burial." Some even pimp for them and supply them with prostitutes or even married women, and cut huge slices off the father's savings for old age, if they don't run off with them altogether. An accursed tribe, feigning friendship, knowing nothing of real freedom, flatterers of the rich, despisers of the poor, drawn to young men by a sort of natural logic,38 showing their teeth and grinning all over when their patrons laugh,39 misbegotten brats of fortune and bastard elements in life, living according to the nod of the rich, free in their circumstances, but slaves by inclination, when they are not insulted thinking themselves insulted, because they are parasites to no purpose. So, if any father cares for the good bringing-up of his sons, he must banish from his house this abominable race. He must also be on his guard against the viciousness of his sons' schoolfellows, for they are quite sufficient to corrupt the best morals.

§ xvii. At all costs, we need to keep our boys away from bad people because they will pick up some of their wrongdoing. This was the meaning behind Pythagoras' cryptic teachings, which I'll quote and explain, as they provide valuable guidance for gaining virtue: Don't touch black tails: meaning, stay away from bad people.36 Don't go beyond the balance: we should pay close attention to justice and not go overboard. Don't sit on a measure: meaning, don't be lazy, instead earn tomorrow's bread as well as today's. Don't give everyone your right hand: don't be too quick to make friends. Don't wear a tight ring: let your life be free, don’t chain yourself. Don't poke the fire with a sword: don't provoke someone who's angry, but rather yield to them. Don't eat the heart: don’t let worry wear out your heart. Abstain from beans: stay out of political matters, as voting was historically done with beans. Don't put your food in the chamber-pot: don’t waste your wisdom on those who won’t appreciate it, as words feed the mind, and the wicked twist them to corrupt meanings. When you’ve reached the end of a journey, don't look back: when people see death approaching, they should take it calmly and not be disheartened. But I’ll return to my main point. We must keep our boys, as I mentioned, from associating with all bad people, especially flatterers. For I have often told parents, and still do, and will always affirm, there is no group more toxic or more likely to lead youths to ruin than flatterers, who destroy both parents and children completely, making the old age of the former and the youth of the latter miserable, all while tempting them with pleasure. The children of the rich are encouraged by their fathers to be disciplined, yet pressured by these flatterers to indulge; their fathers advise them to be moral, while the flatterers lead them to be reckless; they are urged to save by their fathers but encouraged to spend by these flatterers; their fathers want them to work hard, while the flatterers tell them to be lazy. They say, "'Our life's just a short time;'37 we only live once; why should you care about your dad's warnings? He’s just an old fool, nearing the end; we’ll soon bury him and be done with it." Some even exploit them, providing prostitutes or even married women, and bleed their fathers' savings dry for old age, or even run off with them entirely. A cursed bunch, pretending to be friends, unaware of true freedom, flattering the rich while looking down on the poor, drawn to young men as if by instinct,38 grinning broadly when their patrons laugh,39 misbegotten children of fortune and illegitimate elements of life, living at the pleasure of the wealthy, free by their situation but slaves at heart, feeling insulted when not actually insulted, simply because they are aimless parasites. So, if any father truly cares about raising his sons well, he must eliminate this detestable group from his home. He should also be wary of the negative influences from his sons' schoolmates, as they can easily corrupt even the best values.

§ xviii. What I have said hitherto is apropos to my 20subject: I will now speak a word to the men. Parents must not be over harsh and rough in their natures, but must often forgive their sons' offences, remembering that they themselves were once young. And just as doctors by infusing a sweet flavour into their bitter potions find delight a passage to benefit, so fathers must temper the severity of their censure by mildness; and sometimes relax and slacken the reins of their sons' desires, and again tighten them; and must be especially easy in respect to their faults, or if they are angry must soon cool down. For it is better for a father to be hot-tempered than sullen, for to continue hostile and irreconcilable looks like hating one's son. And it is good to seem not to notice some faults, but to extend to them the weak sight and deafness of old age, so as seeing not to see, and hearing not to hear, their doings. We tolerate the faults of our friends; why should we not that of our sons? often even our slaves' drunken debauches we do not expose. Have you been rather near? spend more freely. Have you been vexed? let the matter pass. Has your son deceived you by the help of a slave? do not be angry. Did he take a yoke of oxen from the field, did he come home smelling of yesterday's debauch? wink at it. Is he scented like a perfume shop? say nothing. Thus frisky youth gets broken in.40

§ xviii. What I've said so far is related to my 20topic: I’ll now say a few words to the fathers. Parents shouldn’t be overly harsh and rough; they need to forgive their sons' mistakes often, remembering that they were young once, too. Just like doctors add a sweet flavor to bitter medicines to make them easier to take, fathers should soften their criticism with kindness. Sometimes they need to loosen the reins on their sons' desires and other times tighten them. They should be especially lenient regarding their faults, or if they can't help being angry, they should cool down quickly. It’s better for a father to lose his temper than to stay sour, because being unapproachable can come off as hating his son. It’s also wise to overlook certain faults, pretending to be oblivious as if showing the dulled sight and hearing of old age, so that they don’t fully acknowledge their wrongdoings. We tolerate our friends' mistakes, so why shouldn’t we do the same for our sons? We often overlook our slaves' drunken misbehavior too. If your son has been misbehaving, let it slide. If you’ve been annoyed, just move past it. If your son deceives you with a servant's help, don’t get angry. Did he take a yoke of oxen from the fields? Did he come home smelling like last night’s party? Just ignore it. If he smells like a perfume shop, don’t say a word. This is how lively youth learns and grows. 40

§ xix. Those of our sons who are given to pleasure and pay little heed to rebuke, we must endeavour to marry, for marriage is the surest restraint upon youth. And we must marry our sons to wives not much richer or better born, for the proverb is a sound one, "Marry in your own walk of life."41 For those who marry wives superior to themselves in rank are not so much the husbands of their wives as unawares slaves to their dowries.42

§ xix. We should try to marry off our sons who are focused on pleasure and don’t pay much attention to criticism, because marriage is the best way to keep young people in check. We need to find wives for our sons who aren’t too much richer or of higher status, because there’s wisdom in the saying, "Marry within your own social circle." 41 Those who marry women of a higher rank often end up becoming not so much their husbands but unwittingly enslaved to their fortunes. 42

§ xx. I shall add a few remarks, and then bring my subject to a close. Before all things fathers must, by a good behaviour, set a good example to their sons, that, looking at their lives as a mirror, they may turn away from 21bad deeds and words. For those fathers who censure their sons' faults while they themselves commit the same, are really their own accusers, if they know it not, under their sons' name; and those who live a depraved life have no right to censure their slaves, far less their sons. And besides this they will become counsellors and teachers of their sons in wrongdoing; for where old men are shameless youths will of a certainty have no modesty. We must therefore take all pains to teach our sons self-control, emulating the conduct of Eurydice, who, though an Illyrian and more than a barbarian, to teach her sons educated herself though late in life, and her love to them is well depicted in the inscription which she offered to the Muses: "Eurydice of Hierapolis made this offering to the Muses, having conceived a vast love for knowledge. For when a mother with sons full-grown she learnt letters, the preservers of knowledge."

§ xx. I want to add a few comments, and then I'll wrap up. Above all, fathers need to set a good example for their sons through their actions, so that by reflecting on their lives, their sons will turn away from 21 wrongful actions and words. Fathers who criticize their sons for faults they themselves have are, whether they realize it or not, just putting their own issues on display through their sons. Those leading a corrupt life shouldn't judge their servants, let alone their sons. Furthermore, they risk becoming misguided advisors and teachers for their sons; after all, if older men lack shame, young men will certainly lack modesty. Therefore, we must strive to instill self-control in our sons, taking inspiration from Eurydice, who, despite being Illyrian and more uncivilized, educated herself late in life to teach her sons, demonstrating her love for them in the inscription she dedicated to the Muses: "Eurydice of Hierapolis made this offering to the Muses, having conceived a vast love for knowledge. For when a mother had grown sons, she learned letters, the preservers of knowledge."

To carry out all these precepts would be perhaps a visionary scheme; but to attain to many, though it would need a happy disposition and much care, is a thing possible to human nature.43

Carrying out all these guidelines might seem like a lofty idea; however, achieving many of them, while requiring a positive attitude and a lot of effort, is something that human nature can accomplish.43

3 Euripides, "Here. Fur." 1261, 1262.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Here. Fur." 1261, 1262.

4 Euripides, "Hippol." 424, 425.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Hippol." 424, 425.

5 Cleophantus is the name given to this lad by other writers.

5 Cleophantus is the name that other writers have given to this young man.

6 Compare Sophocles, "Œdipus Tyrannus," 112, 113.

6 Check out Sophocles, "Oedipus Rex," 112, 113.

7 The Thessalians were very pugnacious. Cf. Isocrates, "Oratio de Pace," p. 316. οἱ μὲν (θετταλοὶ) σφίσιν αύσῖς ἀτοῖς ἀεὶ πολεμοῦσιν.

7 The Thessalians were very aggressive. See Isocrates, "Oratio de Pace," p. 316. They are always at war with themselves.

8 A proverbial expression among the ancients for earliest childhood. See Erasmus, "Adagia."

8 A saying from ancient times referring to early childhood. See Erasmus, "Adagia."

9 Plato, "Republic," ii. p. 429, E.

9 Plato, "Republic," ii. p. 429, E.

10 See Erasmus, "Adagia."

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Erasmus, "Adagia."

11 It is difficult to know how to render the word παιδαγωγὸς in English. He was the slave who took the boy to school, and generally looked after him from his seventh year upward. Tutor or governor seems the best rendering. He had great power over the boy entrusted to him.

11 It's hard to find the right English word for παιδαγωγὸς. He was the slave who took the boy to school and generally looked after him from the age of seven onward. "Tutor" or "governor" seems like the best options. He had significant authority over the boy he was responsible for.

12 Plato, "Clitophon," p. 255, D.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Plato, "Clitophon," p. 255, D.

13 Compare Diogenes Laertius, ii. 72.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare Diogenes Laertius, II. 72.

14 Reading κοιτοφθοροῦντες, the excellent emendation of Wyttenbach.

14 Reading sleeping by night, the excellent correction by Wyttenbach.

15 From the heathen standpoint of course, not from the Christian. Compare the advice of Cato in Horace's "Satires," Book i. Sat. ii. 31-35. It is a little difficult to know what Diogenes' precept really means. Is it that vice is universal? Like Shakespeare's "Measure for Measure," Act ii. Sc. ii. 5. "All sects, all ages smack of this vice."

15 From the perspective of nonbelievers, obviously, not from the Christian viewpoint. See Cato's advice in Horace's "Satires," Book i. Sat. ii. 31-35. It's somewhat challenging to understand what Diogenes' teaching truly implies. Is it that vice exists everywhere? Similar to Shakespeare's "Measure for Measure," Act ii. Sc. ii. 5. "All groups, all ages are marked by this vice."

16 He was asked by Polus, see Plato, "Gorgias," p. 290, F.

16 Polus asked him, see Plato, "Gorgias," p. 290, F.

17 "Hippolytus," 986-989.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Hippolytus," 986-989.

18 Cf. Plato, "Cratylus," p. 257, E. ὦ παῖ Ὶππονίκου Ὲρμόγενες, παλαιὰ παροιμἰα, ὃτι χαλεπὰ τὰ καλἀ ἐσιν ὃπη ἔχει μαθεῖν. So Horace, "Sat." i. ix. 59, 60, "Nil sine magno Vita labore dedit mortalibus."

18 See Plato, "Cratylus," p. 257, E. O child of Hipponikos, the old saying goes, “It's tough to learn what's good.” Similarly, Horace says in "Satires" i. ix. 59, 60, "Life gives nothing to mortals without great effort."

19 "Midias," p. 411, C.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Midias," p. 411, C.

20 i.e., occasionally and sparingly.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ i.e., sometimes and rarely.

21 Diogenes Laertius assigns the remark to Aristippus, while Stobæus fathers it on Aristo.

21 Diogenes Laertius attributes the remark to Aristippus, while Stobæus credits it to Aristo.

22 A favourite thought with the ancients. Compare Isocrates, "Admonitio ad Demonicum," p. 18; and Aristotle, "Nic. Eth.," iv. 3.

22 A popular idea among ancient thinkers. See Isocrates, "Admonitio ad Demonicum," p. 18; and Aristotle, "Nic. Eth.," iv. 3.

23 "Republic," vii. p. 489, E.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Republic," vii. p. 489, E.

24 A famous Proverb. It is "the master's eye" generally, as in Xenophon, "Œconom." xii. 20; and Aristotle, "Œconom." i. 6.

24 A well-known saying. It refers to "the master's eye" in general, as mentioned by Xenophon in "Œconom." xii. 20; and Aristotle in "Œconom." i. 6.

25 "Works and Days," 361, 362. The lines were favourite ones with our author. He quotes them again, § 3, of "How one may be aware of one's Progress in Virtue."

25 "Works and Days," 361, 362. These lines were a favorite of our author. He cites them again in § 3, "How to Recognize Your Progress in Virtue."

26 See Pausanias, ix. 9. Also Erasmus, "Adagia."

26 See Pausanias, ix. 9. Also Erasmus, "Adagia."

27 A fragment from the "Protesilaus" of Euripides. Our "It takes two to make a quarrel."

27 A quote from the "Protesilaus" by Euripides. Our saying is "It takes two to start a fight."

28 See Plutarch's Lysander.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Plutarch's Lysander.

29 Or symposium, where all sorts of liberties were taken.

29 Or symposium, where all kinds of freedoms were embraced.

30 I have softened his phrase. His actual words were very coarse, and would naturally be resented by Ptolemy. See Athenæus, 621, A.

30 I’ve toned down his words. What he actually said was pretty harsh, and Ptolemy would understandably take offense. See Athenæus, 621, A.

31 See "Iliad," v. 83; xvi. 334; xx, 477.

31 See "Iliad," v. 83; xvi. 334; xx, 477.

32 A fragment from the "Dictys" of Euripides.

32 A snippet from the “Dictys” by Euripides.

33 "Republ." v. 463, F. sq.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Republ." v. 463, F. sq.

34 Cf. Shakespeare's "Winter Tale," Act iii. sc. iii. 59-63.

34 See Shakespeare's "Winter's Tale," Act 3, Scene 3, lines 59-63.

35 As Horace's father did. See "Satires," Book i. Sat. iv. 105-129.

35 Just like Horace's father did. See "Satires," Book i. Sat. iv. 105-129.

36 What we call black sheep.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ What we call black sheep.

37 From Simonides. Cf. Seneca, "Epist." xlix. "Punctum est quod vivimus, et adhuc puncto minus."

37 From Simonides. See Seneca, "Epist." 49. "Life is just a moment, and even less than a moment."

38 Reading with Wyttenbach, ὡς ἐκ λογικῆς τέχνης.

38 Reading with Wyttenbach, as from the art of logic.

39 Like Carker in Dombey.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Like Carker in Dombey.

40 Compare the character of Micio in the "Adelphi" of Terence.

40 Compare the character of Micio in Terence's "Adelphi."

41 This saying is assigned by Diogenes Laertius to Pittacus.

41 This saying is attributed to Pittacus by Diogenes Laertius.

42 Compare Plautus, "Asinaria," i. l. 74. "Argentum accepi: dote imperum vendidi." Compare also our author, "Whether Vice is sufficient to cause Unhappiness," § i.

42 Compare Plautus, "Asinaria," i. l. 74. "I took the money: I sold my power for a dowry." Also check out our author, "Whether Vice is enough to cause Unhappiness," § i.

43 Wyttenbach thinks this treatise is not Plutarch's. He bases his conclusion partly on external, partly on internal, grounds. It is not quoted by Stobæus, or any of the ancients, before the fourteenth century. And its style is not Plutarch's; it has many words foreign to Plutarch: it has "nescio quid novum ac peregrinum, ab illa Plutarchea copia et gravitate diversum leve et inane." Certainly its matter is superior to its manner.

43 Wyttenbach believes this treatise isn't written by Plutarch. He supports his conclusion with both external and internal evidence. It isn't cited by Stobæus or any ancient source before the fourteenth century. Additionally, its style differs from Plutarch's; it includes many words that are not typical of him: it has "nescio quid novum ac peregrinum, ab illa Plutarchea copia et gravitate diversum leve et inane." Clearly, the content is much more impressive than the way it's presented.


ON LOVE TO ONE'S OFFSPRING.

§ i. Appeals to foreign law-courts were first devised among the Greeks through mistrust of one another's justice, for they looked on justice as a necessity not indigenous among them. Is it not on much the same principle that the philosophers, in regard to some of their questions, owing to their variety of opinion, have appealed to the brute creation as to a strange state, and submitted the decision to their instincts and habits as not to be talked over 22and impartial? Or is it a general charge against human infirmity that, having different opinions on the most necessary and important things, we seek in horses and dogs and birds how to marry and beget and rear children, as though we had no means of making our own nature known, and appeal to the habits and instincts of the brute creation, and call them in to bear witness against the many deviations from nature in our lives, which from the first are confused and disorderly. For among the brutes nature remains ever the same, pure and simple, but in men, owing to reason and habit, like oil in the hands of the perfumers, being mixed up with many added opinions, it becomes various and loses its original simplicity. And let us not wonder that the brutes follow nature more closely than human beings, for in that respect even they are outstripped by inanimate things, which, being dowered neither with imagination nor any appetite or inclination contrary to nature, ever continue in the one path which nature has prescribed for them, as if they were tied and bound. But in brutes the gentleness of mood inspired by reason, the subtlety, the love of freedom, are not qualities found in excess, but they have unreasonable appetites and desires, and act in a roundabout way within certain limits, riding, as it were, at the anchor of nature, and only going straight under bit and bridle. But in man reason, which is absolute master, inventing different modes and fashions of life, has left no plain or evident trace of nature.44

§ i. Appeals to foreign courts were first created among the Greeks due to distrust in each other's justice, as they viewed justice as something that wasn't naturally found among them. Isn't it similar that philosophers, when facing differing opinions on various matters, have turned to the animal kingdom for guidance, relying on their instincts and behaviors as impartial witnesses? Isn’t it a common critique of human weakness that, despite having different views on essential issues, we look to horses, dogs, and birds for advice on marriage, parenting, and raising children, as if we can't understand our own nature? We invoke the habits and instincts of animals as witnesses against the many ways we stray from our natural inclinations, which have always been chaotic and disordered. In the animal world, nature stays consistent, pure, and simple, while in humans, due to reasoning and habits, it becomes mixed and complicated like oil in a perfumer's hands, losing its original clarity. It's no surprise that animals follow nature more closely than humans do; in this respect, even inanimate objects surpass them, as they have no imagination or impulses that go against nature, always adhering to the singular path nature laid out for them, as if they are constrained. Animals may possess some qualities like reason, subtlety, and a love for freedom, but they also have irrational desires and tendencies, often acting in indirect ways within certain limits, only following nature directly when they are restrained. On the other hand, for humans, reason, which holds the ultimate authority, creates various lifestyles and has left no clear or obvious mark of nature. 44

§ ii. Consider in their marriages how much the animals follow nature. For they do not wait for any legislation about bachelor or late-married, like the citizens of Lycurgus and Solon, nor do they fear penalties for childlessness, nor are they anxious for the jus trium liberorum,45 like many of the Romans, who only marry and have children for the privileges it bestows, not to have heirs, but to be qualified for succeeding themselves to inheritances. Then, again, 23the male animal does not go with the female at all times; for its aim is not pleasure but procreation: so in the season of spring, the most appropriate time for such pairings,46 the female being submissive and tender attracts the male by her beautiful condition of body, coming as she does from the dew and fresh pastures, and when pregnant modestly retires and takes thought for the birth and safety of her offspring. We cannot adequately describe all this, but every animal exhibits for its young affection and forethought and endurance and unselfishness. We call the bee wise, and celebrate its "making the yellow honey,"47 flattering it for its tickling sweetness; but we neglect the wisdom and ingenuity of other creatures, both as regards the birth and bringing up of their young. For example, the kingfisher after conception weaves its nest with the thorns of the marine needle, making it round and oblong in shape like a fisherman's basket, and after deftly and closely weaving it together, subjects it to the action of the sea waves, that its surface may be rendered waterproof by this plash and cement, and it is hard for even iron or stone to break it. And what is more wonderful still, so symmetrically is the entrance of the nest adjusted to the kingfisher's shape and size, that no beast either greater or smaller can enter it, they even say that it does not admit the sea, or even the very smallest things. And cats, when they breed, very often let their kittens go out and feed, and take them back into their entrails again.48 And the bear, a most savage and ugly beast, gives birth to its young without shape or joints, and with its tongue as with an instrument moulds its features, so that it seems to give form as well as life to its progeny. And the lion in Homer, "whom the hunters meet in the wood with its whelps, exulting in its strength, which so frowns that it hides its eyes,"49 does it not intend to bargain with the hunters for its whelps? For universally the love of animals for their offspring makes timid ones bold, and lazy ones energetic, and greedy ones 24unselfish. And so the bird in Homer, feeding its young "with its beak, with whatever it has captured, even though it goes ill with itself,"50 nourishes its young at the cost of its own hunger, and when the food is near its maw abstains from it, and holds it tightly in its mouth, that it may not gulp it down unawares. "And so a bitch bestriding her tender pups, barks at a strange man, and yearns for the fray,"51 making her fear for them a sort of second anger. And partridges when they are pursued with their young let them fly on, and, contriving their safety, themselves fly so near the sportsmen as to be almost caught, and then wheel round, and again fly back and make the sportsmen hope to catch them, till at last, having thus provided for the safety of their young, they lead the sportsmen on a long way. As to hens, we see every day how they watch over their chicks, dropping their wings over some, and letting others climb on their backs, or anywhere about them, and clucking for joy all the time: and though they fly from dogs and dragons when only afraid for themselves, if they are afraid for their chicks they stand their ground and fight valiantly. Are we to suppose then that nature has only implanted these instincts in fowls and dogs and bears, anxious only about their offspring, to put us mortals out of countenance and to give us a bad name? considering these examples for us to follow, while disgrace justly attaches to our inhumanity, for mankind only is accused of having no disinterested affection, and of not knowing how to love except in regard to advantage. For that line is greatly admired in the theatres, "Man loves man only for reward," and is the view of Epicurus, who thinks that the father so loves his son, the mother her child, children their parents. Whereas, if the brutes could understand conversation, and if anyone were to introduce horses and cows and dogs and birds into a common theatre,52 and were to change the sentiment into "neither do dogs love their pups, nor horses their foals, nor birds their young, out 25of interest, but gratuitously and by nature," it would be recognized by the affections of all of them to be a true sentiment. Why it would be disgraceful, great God, that birth and travail and procreation should be gratis and mere nature among the beasts, while among mankind they should be merely mercenary transactions!

§ ii. Think about how animals behave in their relationships. They don’t wait for rules about being a bachelor or getting married late, like the citizens of Lycurgus and Solon do. They aren't afraid of penalties for not having kids, nor do they worry about the jus trium liberorum,45 like many Romans, who get married and have children just for the benefits it brings, not to have heirs, but to qualify for inheritances. Moreover, 23 male animals don’t mate with females all the time; their goal is not pleasure but reproduction. During spring, the best time for mating,46 the female attracts the male with her beautiful body, just coming from fresh dew and grass. When she’s pregnant, she retreats modestly, thinking about giving birth and caring for her young. It’s hard to describe all of this, but every animal shows affection, foresight, endurance, and selflessness for their young. We praise bees for being clever and for making sweet yellow honey,47 but we overlook the cunning and resourcefulness of other creatures in raising their young. For instance, the kingfisher, after conceiving, weaves its nest from the spines of marine needles, shaping it like a fisherman’s basket. After weaving it tightly, it subjects it to sea waves, making it waterproof through this natural process. It's so well-constructed that even iron or stone can hardly break it. Even more impressive, the entrance of the nest is sized just right for the kingfisher, so no animal, big or small, can enter it. They even say it keeps out the sea and the tiniest creatures. Cats, when they give birth, often let their kittens out to play and then take them back in.48 And the bear, a fierce and ugly animal, gives birth to shapeless young and molds their features with its tongue, seeming to provide them with form as well as life. In Homer’s tales, the lion "whom the hunters encounter in the woods with its cubs, proud of its strength, frowning fiercely to hide its eyes,"49 does it not intend to negotiate for its cubs with the hunters? Love for their offspring makes timid animals brave, lazy ones industrious, and greedy ones selfless. Thus, the bird in Homer feeds its young "with its beak, whatever it has caught, even when it doesn’t benefit itself,"50 sacrificing its own hunger to nourish its young, keeping food in its beak so it doesn’t eat it by mistake. "A dog guarding her tender puppies barks at a stranger, eager for a fight,"51 letting her fear for them become a second form of anger. When partridges are chased with their young, they let them fly ahead and risk themselves by flying close to the hunters, almost getting caught, then turn back to make the hunters think they can catch them, all the while ensuring their young are safe. With hens, we see how they constantly monitor their chicks, allowing some to nest under their wings and others to climb on them, all while joyfully clucking. While they flee from dogs and predators when scared for themselves, when their chicks are threatened, they stand their ground and fight fiercely. Should we assume that nature only gave these instincts to birds, dogs, and bears to make us humans look bad? These examples are here for us to emulate while we bear the shame of our inhumanity; only humanity is blamed for lacking genuine love and only knowing how to love when there's something to gain. That famous line admired in theaters, "Man loves man only for reward," reflects Epicurus's view that a father loves his son, a mother her child, and children their parents. However, if animals could understand conversation, and we brought horses, cows, dogs, and birds into a theater,52 and changed the sentiment to "neither do dogs love their pups, nor do horses love their foals, nor do birds care for their young except out of interest, but rather out of nature," it would be seen by all their affections as a true sentiment. It would be disgraceful, dear God, for reproduction and childbirth to be free and natural among animals, while among humans, they are mere business transactions!

§ iii. But such a statement is not true or worthy of credit. For as nature, in wild growths, such as wild vines, wild figs, or wild olives, makes the fruit imperfect and inferior to the fruit of cultivated trees, so has she given to the brutes an imperfect affection for their kind, one neither marked by justice nor going beyond commodity: whereas to man, a logical and social animal, she has taught justice and law, and honour to the gods, and building of cities, and philanthropy, and has contributed the noble and goodly and fruitful seeds of all these in love to one's offspring, thereby following the very first elements that are found in the construction of the body. For nature is everywhere perfect and artistic and complete, and, to borrow the expression of Erasistratus, has nothing tawdry about her: but one cannot adequately describe all the processes appertaining to birth, nor would it be perhaps decent to pry too closely into such hidden matters, and to particularize too minutely all their wondrous ingenuity. But her contrivance and dispensation of milk alone is sufficient to prove nature's wonderful care and forethought. For all the superfluous blood in women, that owing to their languor and thinness of spirit floats about on the surface and oppresses them, has a safety-valve provided by nature in the menses, which relieve and cleanse the rest of the body, and fit the womb for conception in due season. But after conception nature stops the menses, and arrests the flow of the blood, using it as aliment for the babe in the womb, until the time arrives for its birth, and it requires a different kind of food. At this stage the blood is most ingeniously changed into a supply of milk, not diffused all over the body, but externally in the breasts, so that the babe can with its mouth imbibe the gentle and soothing nutriment.53 But all these various 26processes of nature, all this economy, all this forethought, would be useless, had not nature also implanted in mothers love to their offspring and anxiety for their welfare.

§ iii. But that statement isn’t true or credible. Just as nature produces imperfect and inferior fruits in wild plants, like wild vines, wild figs, or wild olives, she has also given animals an incomplete affection for their kind, lacking in justice and focused only on basic needs. In contrast, for humans—who are logical and social beings—she has instilled a sense of justice, law, reverence for the gods, city-building, and philanthropy, offering the noble, good, and fruitful seeds of love for one’s offspring, reflecting the fundamental elements found in the creation of the body. Nature is always perfect, artistic, and complete, and to echo Erasistratus, there is nothing cheap about it. However, we can’t fully describe all the processes related to birth, nor might it be appropriate to pry too deeply into such private matters, or to detail all their amazing complexity. Yet, the way nature provides milk alone is enough to demonstrate her incredible care and foresight. The excess blood in women, which due to their weakness and lack of vitality rests near the surface and weighs them down, has a natural safety valve in menstruation that cleanses and prepares the body for conception. Once conception occurs, nature halts menstruation and stops the blood flow, converting it into nourishment for the baby in the womb until it’s ready for birth and needs different food. At this point, blood is remarkably transformed into milk, not spread throughout the body but stored in the breasts, allowing the baby to suckle on this gentle and soothing nourishment.53 But all these various 26functions of nature, all this organization, all this foresight, would be pointless if nature hadn’t also instilled mothers with love for their children and concern for their well-being.

"For of all things that breathe on the earth" "Or creep, man is by far the most miserable." 54

And the poet's words are especially applicable to a newborn babe. For there is nothing so imperfect, so helpless, so naked, so shapeless, so foul as a newborn babe: to whom almost alone nature has given an impure outlet to the light of day: being kneaded with blood, and full of defilement, and like one killed rather than born: which no one would touch, or lift up, or kiss, or embrace, but from natural affection. And that is why all the animals have their udders under the belly, women alone have their breasts high on their bodies, that they can lift up their babes to kiss, to dandle, and to fondle: seeing that their bearing and rearing children comes not from necessity but love.

And the poet's words really apply to a newborn baby. There’s nothing as imperfect, helpless, exposed, misshapen, or unclean as a newborn: nature has given it a raw entry into the world, born from blood and filled with impurities, like something that was killed instead of born. No one would want to touch, pick up, kiss, or hold it, except out of natural affection. That’s why all animals have their udders under their bodies, while women have their breasts higher up, so they can lift their babies to kiss, rock, and cuddle them: because raising children comes from love, not necessity.

§ iv. Refer the question to the ancient inhabitants of the earth, to the first mothers and fathers. There was no law ordering them to have families, no expectation of advantage or return to be got out of them. I should rather say that mothers would be likely to be hostile and bear malice to their babes, owing to the great danger and pains of travail. And women say the lines, "When the sharp pangs of travail seize on the pregnant woman, then come to her aid the Ilithyiæ, who help women in hard childbirth, those daughters of Hera, goddesses of travail,"55 were not written by Homer, but by some Homerid who had been a mother, or was even then in the throes of travail, and who vividly felt the sharp pain in her womb. But the love to one's offspring implanted by nature, moves and influences the mother even then: in the very height of her throes, she neglects not nor flees from her babe, but turns to it and smiles at it, and takes it up and caresses it, though she derives no pleasure or utility from it, but with pain and sorrow receives it, "warming it and fostering it 27in swaddling clothes, with unintermittent assiduity both night and day."56 What hope of gain or advantage had they in those days? nay, or even now? for the hopes of parents are uncertain, and have to be long waited for. He who plants a vine in the spring equinox, gleans its vintage in the autumnal equinox; he who sows corn when the Pleiads set, reaps it when they rise; cattle and horses and birds have produce at once fit for use; whereas man's bringing up is toilsome, his growth slow; and as excellence flowers late, most fathers die before their sons attain to fame. Neocles lived not to see Themistocles' victory at Salamis, nor Miltiades Cimon's at the Eurymedon, nor did Xanthippus hear Pericles haranguing, nor did Aristo hear Plato philosophizing, nor did their fathers know of the triumphs of Euripides and Sophocles. They heard them faltering in speech and lisping in syllables, the poor parents saw their errors in revelling and drinking and love-affairs, so that of all Evenus'57 lines, that one alone is most remembered and quoted, "to a father a son is always a cause of fear or pain." Nevertheless, parents do not cease to bring up sons, even when they can least need them. For it is ridiculous to suppose that the rich, when they have sons, sacrifice and rejoice that they will have people to take care of them and to bury them; unless indeed they bring up sons from want of heirs; as if one could not find or fall in with anyone who would be willing to have another's property! Why, the sand on the sea shore, and the dust, and the wings of birds of varied note, are less numerous than the number of would-be heirs. For had Danaus, the father of fifty daughters, been childless, he would have had more heirs, and of a different spirit. For sons have no gratitude, nor regard, nor veneration for inheritance; but take it as a debt; whereas the voices of strangers which you hear round the childless man, are like those lines in the play, "O People, first bathe, after one decision in the courts, then eat, drink, gobble, take the three-obol-piece."58 And what Euripides has said, "Money finds friends for men, and has the greatest 28power among mankind," is not merely a general truth, but is especially true in the case of the childless. For those the rich entertain to dinner, those great men pay court to, to those alone orators give their services gratis. "A mighty personage is a rich man, whose heir is unknown." It has at any rate made many much loved and honoured, whom the possession of one child would have made unloved and insignificant. Whence we see that there is no power or advantage to be got from children, but that the love of them, alike in mankind as among the animals, proceeds entirely from nature.

§ iv. Ask the ancient inhabitants of the earth, the first mothers and fathers. There was no law requiring them to have families, no expectation of some benefit or return from them. In fact, I would say that mothers might be more likely to resent and feel bitterness toward their babies, given the significant risks and pains of childbirth. Women express this when they say, "When the sharp pains of labor hit a pregnant woman, then the Ilithyiæ come to her aid, helping women during difficult births, those daughters of Hera, goddesses of labor,"55 which were not written by Homer, but by some Homerid who had been a mother or was currently in labor, vividly feeling the intense pain in her womb. Yet the love for one’s child that’s instilled by nature drives and influences the mother even then: at the peak of her pain, she doesn’t neglect or shy away from her baby but turns to it, smiles at it, picks it up, and holds it, even though she gets no joy or benefit from it, receiving it with pain and sorrow, "warming it and nurturing it 27in swaddling clothes, with constant attention both night and day."56 What hope of gain did they have back then? And even now? The hopes of parents are uncertain and take a long time to materialize. He who plants a vine at the spring equinox harvests its fruit at the autumn equinox; he who sows corn when the Pleiads set reaps it when they rise; livestock and poultry produce immediately; but raising a child is laborious, their growth slow; and since excellence comes late, most fathers die before their sons achieve any recognition. Neocles didn’t live to witness Themistocles’ victory at Salamis, nor did Miltiades see Cimon’s at the Eurymedon. Xanthippus didn’t hear Pericles speaking, nor did Aristo hear Plato philosophizing, nor did their fathers see the triumphs of Euripides and Sophocles. They could only hear them struggling to speak and stumbling over their words; the poor parents saw their children making mistakes, indulging in partying, drinking, and romantic pursuits. Hence, of all Evenus'57 lines, this one is most remembered and cited, "to a father a son is always a source of fear or pain." Nonetheless, parents continue to raise sons even when they seem to need them the least. It's absurd to think that the wealthy, when they have sons, celebrate and rejoice because they’ll have someone to care for them and bury them; unless they are raising sons out of a desire for heirs, as if one couldn’t find anyone willing to take care of another's property! The sand on the seashore, the dust, and the many types of birds are less numerous than the potential heirs. If Danaus, the father of fifty daughters, had been childless, he would have had more heirs, and of a different temperament. Sons show no gratitude, respect, or reverence for inheritance; they treat it as a right, while the voices of strangers heard around the childless man echo the lines in the play, "O People, first wash yourselves, after coming from the courts, then eat, drink, and gobble, take the three-obol-piece."58 Euripides said, "Money attracts friends to men and holds the greatest 28power among humanity," which is not just a general truth but especially applies to those without children. The rich entertain those they invite to dinner, the powerful seek their attention, and to those alone, orators offer their services for free. "A powerful figure is a wealthy man whose heir is unknown." In any case, this has made many loved and honored, while the possession of just one child could have made them unloved and insignificant. Thus, we see that there’s no true power or benefit from children, but rather that love for them, both in humans and animals, is entirely a product of nature.

§ v. What if this natural affection, like many other virtues, is obscured by badness, as a wilderness chokes a garden? Are we to say that man does not love himself by nature, because many cut their throats or throw themselves down precipices? Did not Œdipus put out his eyes? And did not Hegesias by his speeches make, many of his hearers to commit suicide?59 "Fatality has many different aspects."60 But all these are diseases and maladies of the soul driving a man contrary to nature out of his wits: as men themselves testify even against themselves. For if a sow destroys one of its litter, or a bitch one of its pups, men are dejected and troubled, and think it an evil omen, and sacrifice to the gods to avert any bad results, on the score that it is natural to all to love and cherish their offspring, unnatural to destroy it. For just as in mines the gold is conspicuous even though mixed up with earth, so nature manifests plainly love to offspring even in instances of faulty habits and affections. For when the poor do not rear their children, it is from fear that if reared to man's estate they would be more than ought to be the case servile, and have little culture, and be debarred of all advantages: so, thinking poverty the worst of all evils, they cannot bear to give it their children, any more than they would some bad disease.61

§ v. What if this natural affection, like many other virtues, is hidden by negativity, like a wilderness choking a garden? Should we say that people don’t love themselves by nature just because some cut their throats or throw themselves off cliffs? Didn’t Oedipus blind himself? And didn’t Hegesias persuade many of his listeners to commit suicide?59 "Fatality has many different aspects."60 But all these are illnesses and afflictions of the soul driving a person against their nature, which even people acknowledge about themselves. Because if a sow kills one of its piglets, or a dog one of its puppies, people feel sad and troubled, thinking it a bad sign, and they make sacrifices to the gods to avert any negative outcomes, since it is natural for all to love and nurture their young, and unnatural to destroy them. Just as gold is visible in mines even when mixed with dirt, nature clearly shows love for offspring even in cases of flawed behaviors and feelings. When the poor do not raise their children, it’s out of fear that if raised to adulthood, they would be more servile than they should be, have little education, and miss out on all opportunities: thus, thinking of poverty as the worst evil, they can’t bear to pass it on to their children, just like they wouldn’t want to pass on a terrible disease.61

44 Much of this is very corrupt in the Greek. I have tried to get the best sense I could; but it is very obscure. Certainly Plutarch's style is often very harsh and crabbed.

44 A lot of this is quite corrupt in the Greek. I’ve tried to understand it as best as I can, but it’s really unclear. Plutarch's writing style is definitely often very rough and difficult to follow.

45 The jus trium liberorum assigned certain privileges to the father of three children, under the Roman Emperors. Frequent allusions are made to this law by the ancient writers.

45 The jus trium liberorum granted specific benefits to the father of three children during the Roman Empire. Ancient writers often referenced this law.

46 Compare Lucretius, i. 10-20.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare Lucretius, i. 10-20.

47 A quotation from Simonides.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ A quote from Simonides.

48 We are not bound to swallow all the ancients tell us. Credat Judæus Apella!

48 We don’t have to accept everything the ancients say. Believe it if you want!

49 "Iliad," xvii. 134-136.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xvii. 134-136.

50 "Iliad," ix. 324. Quoted again in "How one may be aware of one's Progress in Virtue," § 8.

50 "Iliad," ix. 324. Quoted again in "How to Recognize Your Growth in Virtue," § 8.

51 "Odyssey," xx. 14, 15.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," xx. 14, 15.

52 A theatre, that is, in which animals and birds and human beings should meet in common.

52 A theater, where animals, birds, and humans should come together.

53 All that is said here about the milk, the menses, and the blood, I have been obliged somewhat to condense and paraphrase. The ancients sometimes speak more plainly than we can. Ever and anon one must pare down a phrase or word in translating an ancient author. It is inevitable. Verbum sat sapienti.

53 Everything mentioned here about the milk, the menstrual cycle, and the blood has needed some condensing and rephrasing. The ancients can sometimes express things more directly than we do. Every now and then, you have to simplify a phrase or word when translating an ancient writer. It’s unavoidable. Verbum sat sapienti.

54 Homer, "Iliad," xvii. 446, 447.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 17.446, 447.

55 Ibid. xi. 269-271.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source. xi. 269-271.

56 A fragment from Euripides, according to Xylander.

56 A quote from Euripides, as noted by Xylander.

57 Evenus of Paros was an Elegiac Poet.

57 Evenus of Paros was an elegiac poet.

58 Aristophanes, "Equites," 50, 51.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Aristophanes, "Knights," 50, 51.

59 See Cicero "Tuscul." i. 34.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Cicero "Tuscul." 1.34.

60 Euripides, "Alcestis," 1159; "Helena," 1688; "Andromache," 1284; "Bacchæ," 1388.

60 Euripides, "Alcestis," 1159; "Helena," 1688; "Andromache," 1284; "Bacchae," 1388.

61 The discourse breaks off abruptly. It is directed against the Epicureans. It throws ridicule on appealing to the affection of brutes for their offspring instead of appealing to human nature.

61 The conversation suddenly stops. It targets the Epicureans. It mocks the idea of relying on animals' love for their young instead of appealing to human nature.


ON LOVE.

FLAVIANUS AND AUTOBULUS, THE OPENERS OF THE DIALOGUE, ARE BROTHERS. THE OTHER SPEAKERS ARE THEIR FATHER, DAPHNÆUS, PROTOGENES, PISIAS, AND OTHERS.

FLAVIANUS AND AUTOBULUS, THE BEGINNERS OF THE DIALOGUE, ARE BROTHERS. THE OTHER SPEAKERS INCLUDE THEIR FATHER, DAPHNÆUS, PROTOGENES, PISIAS, AND OTHERS.

§ i. Flavianus.—You say that it was on Mount Helicon, Autobulus, that those conversations took place about Love, which you are now about to narrate to us at our request, as you either wrote them down, or at least remember them from frequently asking our father about them.

§ i. Flavianus.—You mentioned that those discussions about Love happened on Mount Helicon, Autobulus, which you are now going to share with us because we asked, as you either wrote them down or at least recall them from often asking our father about them.

Autobulus.—It was on Mount Helicon among the Muses, Flavianus, when the people of Thespiæ were celebrating their Festival to the God of Love, which they celebrate very magnificently and splendidly every five years to that God, as also to the Muses.

Autobulus.—It was on Mount Helicon, among the Muses, that Flavianus found himself when the people of Thespiæ were celebrating their Festival for the God of Love. They celebrate this event in a grand and spectacular manner every five years, honoring both him and the Muses.

Flavianus.—Do you know what all of us who have come to this audience intend to ask of you?

Flavianus.—Do you know what all of us here want to ask you?

Autobulus.—No, but I shall know if you tell me.

Autobulus.—No, but I will figure it out if you tell me.

Flavianus.—Remove from your discourse for this once the poet's meadows and shades, and talk about ivy and yews, and all other commonplaces of that kind that writers love to introduce, with more zeal than discretion, in imitation of Plato's Ilissus and the famous willow and the gentle slope of grass.62

Flavianus.—For once, set aside the poet’s meadows and shaded spots, and discuss ivy and yews, along with all those other clichés that writers tend to bring up with more enthusiasm than sense, trying to mimic Plato’s Ilissus and the well-known willow and the soft grassy slope.62

Autobulus.—My dear Flavianus, my narrative needs not any such exordium. The occasion that caused the conversation simply demands a chorus for the action and a stage, nothing else is wanting to the drama, let us only pray to the Mother of the Muses to be propitious, and give me memory for my narrative.

Autobulus.—My dear Flavianus, my story doesn’t need any introduction. The situation that sparked our conversation just needs a backdrop and a stage; nothing else is needed for the drama. Let us simply pray to the Mother of the Muses for her favor and ask for a good memory for my tale.

§ ii. Long ago our father, before we were born, having lately married our mother, had gone to sacrifice to the God of Love, in consequence of a dispute and variance that broke out among their parents, and took our mother to the Festival, for she also had her part in the vow and sacrifice. Some of their intimate friends journeyed with them from the town where they lived, and when they got to Thespiæ 30they found there Daphnæus the son of Archidamus, a lover of Lysandra the daughter of Simo, and of all her suitors the one who stood highest in her favour, and Soclarus the son of Aristio, who had come from Tithorea. And there were there also Protogenes of Tarsus, and Zeuxippus from Sparta, strangers, and my father said most of the most notable Bœotians were there also. For two or three days they went about the town in one another's company, as it was likely they would do, quietly carrying on philosophical discussions in the wrestling-schools and theatres: after that, to avoid a wearisome contest of harpers, decided beforehand by canvassing and cabal, most broke up their camp as if they had been in a hostile country, and removed to Mount Helicon, and bivouacked there with the Muses. In the morning they were visited by Anthemion and Pisias, both men of good repute, and very great friends of Baccho, who was surnamed the Handsome, and also rivals of one another somewhat through their affection for him. Now you must know that there was at Thespiæ a lady called Ismenodora, famous for her wealth and good family, and of uncommon good repute for her virtuous life: for she had been a widow some time without a breath of slander lighting upon her, though she was young and good-looking. As Baccho was the son of a friend and crony of hers, she had tried to bring about a marriage between him and a maiden who was her own relation, but by frequently being in his company and talking to him she had got rather smitten with him herself. And hearing much in his favour, and often talking about him, and seeing that many noble young men were in love with him, she fell violently in love with him, and, being resolved to do nothing unbecoming to her fair fame, determined to marry and live openly with him. And the matter seeming in itself rather odd, Baccho's mother looked rather askance at the proposed matrimonial alliance as being too high and splendid for her son, while some of his companions who used to go out hunting with him, frightening him and flouting him with Ismenodora's being rather too old for him, really did more to break off the match than those who seriously opposed it. And Baccho, being only a youth, somehow felt a little ashamed at the idea of31 marrying a widow, but, neglecting the opinions of everybody else, he submitted the decision as to the expediency of the marriage to Pisias and Anthemion, the latter being his cousin, though older than him, and the former the gravest63 of his lovers. Pisias objected to the marriage, and upbraided Anthemion with throwing the youth away on Ismenodora. Anthemion replied that it was not well in Pisias, being a good fellow in other respects, to imitate depraved lovers by shutting out his friend from house and marriage and wealth, merely that he might enjoy the sight of him as long as possible naked and in all his virgin bloom at the wrestling-schools.

§ ii. A long time ago, our father, before we were born and shortly after marrying our mother, went to offer a sacrifice to the God of Love due to a conflict that arose between their parents, and took our mother to the Festival, as she was also part of the vow and offering. Some of their close friends traveled with them from the town where they lived, and when they arrived at Thespiæ 30, they found Daphnæus, the son of Archidamus, who loved Lysandra, the daughter of Simo, and among all her suitors, he was the one she favored the most, along with Soclarus, the son of Aristio, who had come from Tithorea. Also present were Protogenes from Tarsus and Zeuxippus from Sparta, who were strangers, and my father noted that many notable Bœotians were there too. For two or three days, they wandered around the town together, as was expected, engaging in quiet philosophical discussions in the wrestling schools and theaters. After that, to avoid a tedious competition among harpers, which had already been decided through campaigning and scheming, most of the group broke camp as if they were in hostile territory and moved to Mount Helicon, camping there with the Muses. In the morning, they were visited by Anthemion and Pisias, both well-respected men and close friends of Baccho, who was nicknamed the Handsome, and who were also somewhat rivals for his affection. You should know that at Thespiæ there was a woman named Ismenodora, known for her wealth and good lineage, and held in high regard for her virtuous life. She had been a widow for some time with no hint of scandal against her, despite being young and attractive. Since Baccho was the son of a friend of hers, she attempted to arrange a marriage between him and a young woman who was her relative, but by spending time with him and talking to him, she became quite infatuated. Hearing so much praise about him and seeing that many noble young men were in love with him, she fell deeply in love, and determined to remain true to her reputation, decided she wanted to marry him and live openly together. The idea seemed a bit unusual, so Baccho's mother looked skeptically at the proposed marriage, considering it too grand for her son, while some of his friends who hunted with him mockingly pointed out that Ismenodora was a bit too old for him, doing more harm to the match than those who outright opposed it. Baccho, still a young man, felt a bit embarrassed at the thought of marrying a widow, but disregarding everyone else's opinions, he asked Pisias and Anthemion for advice on whether the marriage was a good idea—Anthemion being his cousin, though older, and Pisias being the most serious of his admirers. Pisias opposed the marriage and criticized Anthemion for wanting to waste the youth on Ismenodora. Anthemion responded that it wasn’t right for Pisias, who was generally a good guy, to act like twisted lovers by excluding his friend from family and wealth just so he could enjoy looking at him naked and in all his youthful glory at the wrestling schools.

§ iii. To avoid getting estranged by provoking one another on the question, they came and chose our father and his companions as umpires on the matter. And of the other friends, as if by concerted arrangement, Daphnæus espoused the view of Anthemion, and Protogenes the view of Pisias. And Protogenes inveighing somewhat too freely against Ismenodora, Daphnæus took him up and said, "Hercules, what are we not to expect, if Protogenes is going to be hostile to love? he whose whole life, whether in work or at play, has been devoted to love, in forgetfulness of letters, in forgetfulness of his country, not like Laius, away from his country only five days, his was only a torpid and land love: whereas your love 'unfolding its swift wings,' flew over the sea from Cilicia to Athens, merely to gaze at and saunter about with handsome boys. For that was the original reason, doubtless, of Protogenes' journey abroad."

§ iii. To prevent any conflicts from making them distant, they decided to have our father and his friends mediate the situation. Among the others, almost as if it were planned, Daphnæus supported Anthemion's perspective, while Protogenes backed Pisias's view. As Protogenes criticized Ismenodora a bit too harshly, Daphnæus interjected, saying, "Hercules, what can we expect if Protogenes is going to be against love? He who has spent his entire life, both in work and play, dedicated to love, forgetting about academics and his homeland, unlike Laius, who was only away from his country for five days; his was just a dull, land-based love. Meanwhile, your love, 'spreading its swift wings,' traveled across the sea from Cilicia to Athens, just to look at and hang out with attractive young men. That was surely the real reason for Protogenes' trip abroad."

§ iv. And some laughter ensuing, Protogenes replied, "Do I really seem to you now to be hostile to love, and not to be fighting for love against ungovernable lust, which with most disgraceful acts and emotions assumes the most honourable of titles?" Whereupon Daphnæus, "Do you call the marriage and union of man and woman most disgraceful, than which no holier tie exists nor ever 32did?" Protogenes replied, "Why, as all this is necessary for the human race to continue, our legislators do not act amiss in crying up marriage and eulogizing it to the masses, but of genuine love there is not a particle in the woman's side of a house;64 and I also say that you who are sweet on women and girls only love them as flies love milk, and bees the honey-comb, and butchers and cooks calves and birds, fattening them up in darkness.65 But as nature leads one to eat and drink moderately and sufficiently, and excess in this is called gluttony and gormandizing, so the mutual desires between men and women are natural; but that headlong, violent, and uncontrollable passion for the sex is not rightly called love. For love, when it seizes a noble and young soul, ends in virtue through friendship; but these violent passions for women, at the best, aim only at carnal enjoyment and reaping the harvest of a beauteous prime, as Aristippus showed in his answer to one who told him Lais loved him not, 'No more,' he said, 'do meat and wine love me, but I gladly enjoy both.'66 For the end of passion is pleasure and fruition: but love, when it has once lost the promise of friendship, will not remain and continue to cherish merely for beauty that which gives it pain, where it gives no return of friendship and virtue. You remember the husband in the play saying to his wife, 'Do you hate me? I can bear that hatred very easily, since of my dishonour I make money.' Not a whit more really in love than this husband is the one, who, not for gain but merely for the sexual appetite, puts up with a peevish and unsympathetic wife, as Philippides, the comic poet, ridiculed the orator, Stratocles, 'You scarce can kiss her if she turns her back on you.' If, however, we ought to give the name of love to this passion, then is it an effeminate and bastard love, and like at Cynosarges,67 taking us to the woman's side of the house: or rather as 33they say there is a genuine mountain eagle, which Homer called 'black, and a bird of prey,' and there are other kinds of spurious eagles, which catch fish and lazy birds in marshes, and often in want of food emit an hungry wail: so the genuine love is the love of boys, a love not 'flashing with desire,' as Anacreon said the love of maidens was, nor 'redolent of ointment and sprightly,' but you will see it plain and without airs in the schools of the philosophers, or perhaps in the gymnasiums and wrestling-schools, keenly and nobly pursuing youths, and urging on to virtue those who are well worthy of attention: but that soft and stay-at-home love, spending all its time in women's bosoms and beds, always pursuing effeminate delights, and enervated by unmanly, unfriendly, and unimpassioned pleasures, we ought to condemn as Solon condemned it: for he forbade slaves to love boys or to anoint them with oil, while he allowed them to associate with women. For friendship is noble and refined, whereas pleasure is vulgar and illiberal. Therefore, for a slave to love boys is neither liberal or refined: for it is merely the love of copulation, as the love of women."

§ iv. And with some laughter following, Protogenes responded, "Do I really seem to you to be against love, and not fighting for love against overwhelming lust, which engages in the most shameful acts and feelings while claiming the noblest of titles?" Daphnæus replied, "Do you think that the marriage and union of a man and woman are disgraceful, when there is no holier bond than that?" Protogenes answered, "While it's necessary for humanity's survival, our lawmakers don’t err in promoting marriage and praising it to the masses, but there’s not a single trace of genuine love in a woman’s household;64 and I also say that you who are infatuated with women and girls only love them like flies love milk, and bees the honeycomb, and butchers and cooks appreciate calves and birds, fattening them up in the dark.65 Just as nature encourages us to eat and drink in moderation, and excess in this is called gluttony, so the mutual desires between men and women are natural; but that reckless, intense, and uncontrollable passion for the opposite sex isn't rightly called love. Rather, love, when it takes hold of a noble young soul, leads to virtue through friendship; whereas these intense passions for women, at best, seek only physical pleasure, as Aristippus demonstrated when he responded to someone saying Lais didn’t love him, 'Neither do meat and wine love me, but I enjoy both.'66 The goal of passion is pleasure and fulfillment: but love, once it loses the promise of friendship, can no longer cherish mere beauty that brings pain, especially where there is no return of friendship and virtue. You remember the husband in the play saying to his wife, 'Do you hate me? I can handle that hatred quite well since I profit from my dishonor.' Not at all more in love than this husband is the one who, not for gain but merely for sexual desire, puts up with a difficult and unkind wife, as Philippides, the comic poet, mocked the orator Stratocles, 'You can barely kiss her if she turns her back on you.' If we are to label this passion as love, then it's a weak and illegitimate love, dragging us to the woman's side of the household; or rather, like they say about the true mountain eagle, which Homer called 'black and a bird of prey,' there are other kinds of false eagles that catch fish and lazy birds in marshes, and often hungry, emit a desperate cry: genuine love is the love of boys, a love not 'flashing with desire,' as Anacreon described the love of maidens, nor 'scented with ointment and lively,' but you will see it clear and straightforward in the schools of philosophers, or perhaps in the gymnasiums and wrestling schools, eagerly and nobly pursuing young men, encouraging those worthy of attention towards virtue: but that soft, domesticated love, which spends all its time in women's arms and beds, constantly seeking delicate pleasures, and weakened by unmanly, unfriendly, and unimpassioned joys, should be condemned as Solon condemned it: for he prohibited slaves from loving boys or anointing them with oil, while permitting them to associate with women. Friendship is noble and refined, whereas pleasure is base and unrefined. Thus, for a slave to love boys is neither liberal nor refined: it's merely the desire for copulation, just like the love of women."

§ v. Protogenes was intending to go on at greater length, when Daphnæus stopped him and said, "You do well, by Zeus, to mention Solon, and we too may use him as the test of an amorous man. Does he not define such a one in the lines, 'As long as you love boys in the glorious flower of their youth for their kisses and embraces.' And add to Solon the lines of Æschylus, 'You did not disdain the honour of the thighs, O thankless one after all my frequent kisses.'68 For some laugh at them if they bid lovers, like sacrificing priests and seers, to inspect thighs and loins; but I think this a mighty argument in behalf of the love of women. For if the unnatural commerce with males does not take away or mar the amorous propensity, much more likely is it that the natural love of women will end in friendship after the favour. For, Protogenes, the yielding of the female to the male was called by the ancients the favour. Thus Pindar says Hephæstus was the son of Hera 34'without any favours':69 and Sappho, addressing a girl not yet ripe for marriage, says to her, 'You seemed to me a little girl, too young for the favour.' And someone asks Hercules, 'Did you obtain the girl's favour by force or by persuasion?' But the love of males for males, whether rape or voluntary—pathicks effeminately submitting, to use Plato's words, 'to be treated bestially'—is altogether a foul and unlovely favour. And so I think Solon wrote the lines quoted above 'in his hot youth,' as Plato puts it; but when he became older wrote these other lines, 'Now I delight in Cyprus-born Aphrodite, and in Dionysus, and in the Muses: all these give joys to men': as if, after the heat and tempest of his boyish loves, he had got into a quiet haven of marriage and philosophy. But indeed, Protogenes, if we look at the real facts of the case, the love for boys and women is really one and the same passion: but if you wish in a disputatious spirit to make any distinction, you will find that this boy-love goes beyond all bounds, and, like some late-born and ill-begotten bastard brat, seeks to expel its legitimate brother the older love, the love of women. For indeed, friend, it is only yesterday or the day before, since the strippings and exposures of the youths in the gymnasiums, that this boy-love crept in, and gently insinuated itself and got a footing, and at last in a little time got fully-fledged in the wrestling-schools, and has now got fairly unbearable, and insults and tramples on conjugal love, that love that gives immortality to our mortal race, when our nature has been extinguished by death, kindling it again by new births. And this boy-love denies that pleasure is its aim: for it is ashamed and afraid to confess the truth: but it needs some specious excuse for the liberties it takes with handsome boys in their prime: the pretext is friendship and virtue. So your boy-lover wallows in the dust, bathes in cold water, raises his eyebrows, gives himself out for a philosopher, and lives chaste abroad because of the law: but in the stillness of night

§ v. Protogenes was about to elaborate further when Daphnæus interrupted him, saying, "You're right, by Zeus, to bring up Solon, and we can use him as a standard for an affectionate man. Doesn't he describe such a person in the lines, 'As long as you love boys in the prime of their youth for their kisses and embraces'? And let’s add Æschylus’s lines, 'You did not reject the honor of the thighs, you ungrateful one, after all my kisses.'68 Some laugh at this when they suggest that lovers should, like priests and seers, examine thighs and loins; however, I think this is a strong argument in favor of loving women. If the unnatural relationship with males doesn’t diminish or ruin the capacity for love, then it’s even more likely that the natural love for women will lead to a friendship after the romance. For, Protogenes, the ancient Greeks referred to the submission of the female to the male as ‘the favor.’ Pindar mentions that Hephaestus was the son of Hera 34 'without any favors':69 and Sappho, speaking to a girl too young for marriage, says, 'You seemed to me a little girl, too young for the favor.' Someone once asked Hercules, 'Did you win the girl's favor by force or by persuasion?' But the love of males for males, whether through violence or consent—men passively submitting, as Plato noted, 'to be treated like animals'—is purely a vile and unattractive favor. I believe Solon wrote the lines I just quoted 'in his youthful passion,' as Plato puts it; but as he grew older, he composed these other lines, 'Now I take delight in the love born from Cyprus, in Dionysus, and in the Muses: all these bring joy to men': as if, after the tumult of his youthful passions, he found refuge in the calm of marriage and philosophy. However, Protogenes, if we reflect on the actual situation, love for boys and for women is essentially the same passion: yet, if you want to argue about it, you'll see that this boy-love surpasses all limits, and, like a late and ill-conceived child, tries to push aside its rightful sibling, the older love for women. In truth, my friend, it’s only been a short time since the boys began stripping and revealing themselves in the gymnasiums that this boy-love crept in, subtly infiltrated, and eventually became fully developed in the wrestling schools, and now it's completely out of hand, insulting and trampling on conjugal love, the love that grants immortality to our mortal race, rekindling our essence through new births when death has extinguished it. And this boy-love denies that its aim is pleasure: it’s embarrassed and afraid to admit the truth, thus it needs some false justification for its advances towards handsome young boys at their prime: pretending to be about friendship and virtue. So your boy-lover rolls in the dirt, bathes in cold water, arches his eyebrows, pretends to be a philosopher, and lives chaste in public due to the law; but in the quiet of the night...

"Sweet is the ripe fruit when the guard is gone." __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

35 But if, as Protogenes says, there is no carnal intercourse in these boy-familiarities, how is it Love, if Aphrodite is not present, whom it is the destiny of Love to cherish and pay court to, and to partake of just as much honour and power as she assigns to him? But if there is any Love without Aphrodite, as there is drunkenness without wine in drinks made from figs and barley, the disturbing it will be fruitless and without effect, and surfeiting and disgusting."

35 But if, as Protogenes claims, there’s no physical intimacy in these relationships between boys, how can it be Love if Aphrodite isn’t involved? Love’s purpose is to honor and seek out her, sharing in the same respect and influence she grants him. However, if there can be Love without Aphrodite, like experiencing drunkenness without actual wine from fig and barley drinks, then discussing it will be pointless and ineffective, leaving one feeling overwhelmed and repulsed.

§ vi. At the conclusion of this speech, it was clear that Pisias was vexed and indignant with Daphnæus; and after a moment's silence he began: "O Hercules! what levity and audacity for men to state that they are tied to women as dogs to bitches, and to banish the god of Love from the gymnasiums and public walks, and light of day and open intercourse, and to restrict him to brothels71 and philtres and incantations of wanton women: for to chaste women, I am sure, it belongs not either to love or be loved." At this point our father told me he interposed, and took Protogenes by the hand, and said to him:

§ vi. By the end of this speech, it was clear that Pisias was upset and angry with Daphnæus; and after a brief pause, he began: "Oh Hercules! What a lack of seriousness and boldness for men to claim they're tied to women like dogs to bitches, and to banish the god of Love from the gymnasiums and public places, from the light of day and open interactions, and to confine him to brothels71 and charms and spells of promiscuous women: because, I’m sure, it doesn’t belong to chaste women to either love or be loved." At this point, our father told me he stepped in, took Protogenes by the hand, and said to him:

"'Your words inspire the Argive army,'

and of a verity Pisias makes us to side with Daphnæus by his extravagant language, charging marriage with being a loveless intercourse, and one that has no participation in divine friendship, although we can see that it is an intercourse, if erotic persuasion and favour fail, that cannot be restrained by shame and fear as by bit and bridle." Thereupon Pisias said, "I care little about his arguments; but I see that Daphnæus is in the same condition as brass: for, just as it is not worked upon so much by the agency of fire as by the molten and liquid brass fused with it, so is he not so much captivated by the beauty of Lysandra as by his association with one who is the victim of the gentle passion; and it is plain that, if he doesn't take refuge with 36us, he will soon melt away in the flame altogether. But I see, what Anthemion would very much like, that I am offending the Court, so I stop." "You amuse us," said Anthemion: "but you ought from the first to have spoken to the point."

and truly, Pisias makes us align with Daphnæus through his over-the-top language, accusing marriage of being a loveless interaction that lacks divine friendship. However, we can see that it is an interaction that, if erotic attraction and favor disappear, cannot be controlled by shame and fear like a horse by a bit and bridle. Then Pisias said, "I don’t really care about his arguments; but I notice that Daphnæus is like brass: just as brass isn’t shaped by fire alone but through the molten and liquid metal mixed with it, he is not so much enchanted by Lysandra’s beauty as he is by his connection with someone who is caught up in tender affection. It’s clear that if he doesn’t take refuge with 36 us, he will soon completely dissolve in the heat. But I can see that Anthemion is quite displeased with me, so I’ll stop." "You entertain us," said Anthemion, "but you should have gotten to the point from the start."

§ vii. "I say then," continued Pisias, "and give it out boldly, as far as I am concerned, let every woman have a lover; but we ought to guard against giving the wealth of Ismenodora to Baccho, lest, if we involve him in so much grandeur and magnificence, we unwittingly lose him in it, as tin is lost in brass. For if the lad were to marry quite a plain and insignificant woman, it would be great odds whether he would keep the upper hand, as wine mixed with water; and Ismenodora seems already marked out for sway and command; for otherwise she would not have rejected such illustrious and wealthy suitors to woo a lad hardly yet arrived at man's estate, and almost requiring a tutor still. And therefore men of sense prune the excessive wealth of their wives, as if it had wings that required clipping; for this same wealth implants in them luxury, caprice, and vanity, by which they are often elated and fly away altogether: but if they remain, it would be better to be bound by golden fetters, as in Ethiopia, than to a woman's wealth."

§ vii. "So I say," continued Pisias, "and I’ll say it loudly, as far as I'm concerned, every woman should have a lover; but we need to be careful about giving Ismenodora’s wealth to Baccho, because if we put him into such grandeur and luxury, we might unintentionally lose him in it, like tin gets lost in brass. If the guy were to marry a completely ordinary and unremarkable woman, it would be quite uncertain whether he’d maintain control, like wine mixed with water; and Ismenodora seems destined for power and leadership; otherwise, she wouldn’t have turned down such renowned and wealthy suitors to pursue a boy who’s barely reached adulthood and still almost needs a tutor. That’s why wise men trim back their wives' excessive wealth, as if it has wings that need clipping; because that wealth breeds luxury, whims, and vanity, which often uplift them and cause them to fly away completely: but if they do stay, it would be better to be bound by golden chains, like in Ethiopia, than to a woman’s wealth."

§ viii. Here Protogenes put in, "You say nothing about the risk we run of unseasonably and ridiculously reversing the well-known advice of Hesiod:

§ viii. Here Protogenes interjected, "You're not mentioning the danger we face of foolishly and absurdly going against the well-known advice of Hesiod:

If you want to have a timely marriage, Let's say the bridegroom is around thirty years old. The bride is in the fifth year of her adulthood: 72

if we thus marry a lad hardly old enough for marriage to a woman so many years older, than himself, as dates and figs are forced. You will say she loves him passionately: who prevents her, then, from serenading at his doors, singing her amorous ditty, putting garlands on his statues, and wrestling and boxing with her rivals in his affections? For all these are what people in love do. And let her lower her eyebrows, and give up the airs of a coquette, and 37assume the appearance of those that are deeply smitten. But if she is modest and chaste, let her decorously stay at home and await there her lovers and sweethearts; for any sensible man would be disgusted and flee from a woman who took the initiative in love, far less would he be likely to marry her after such a barefaced wooing."

If we marry a guy who's barely old enough for marriage to a woman who’s many years older than him, it’s forced like dates and figs. You might say she loves him passionately: so what’s stopping her from serenading outside his place, singing her romantic song, putting flowers on his statues, and competing with other women for his affection? Because those are all things that people in love do. Let her lower her gaze, drop the flirty act, and look like someone who’s genuinely in love. But if she’s modest and pure, she should gracefully stay home and wait for her admirers; any sensible man would be put off and run away from a woman who takes the lead in pursuing love, and he’s even less likely to marry her after such an obvious approach.

§ ix. When Protogenes had done speaking, my father said, "Do you see, Anthemion, that they force us to intervene again, who have no objection to dance in the retinue of conjugal Love?" "I do," said Anthernion, "but pray defend Love at some length, as you are on his side, and moreover come to the rescue of wealth,73 with which Pisias seeks to scare us." Thereupon my father began, "What on earth will not be brought as a charge against a woman, if we are to reject Ismenodora because she is in love and has money? Granted she loves sway and is rich? What then, if she is young and handsome? And what if she plumes herself somewhat on the lustre of her race? Have not chaste women often something of the morose and peevish in their character almost past bearing? Do they not sometimes get called waspish and shrewish by virtue of their very chastity? Would it be best then to marry off the street some Thracian Abrotonus, or some Milesian Bacchis, and seal the bargain by the present of a handful of nuts? But we have known even such turn out intolerable tyrants, Syrian flute-girls and ballet-dancers, as Aristonica, and Œnanthe with her tambourine, and Agathoclea, who have lorded it over kings' diadems.74 Why Syrian Semiramis was only the servant and concubine of one of king Ninus's slaves, till Ninus the great king seeing and falling in love with her, she got such power over him that she thought so cheap of him, that she asked to be allowed one day to sit on the royal throne, with the royal diadem on her head, and to transact state affairs. And 38Ninus having granted her permission, and having ordered all his subjects to obey her as himself, she first gave several very moderate orders to make trial of the guards; but when she saw that they obeyed her without the slightest hesitation, she ordered them to seize Ninus and put him in fetters, and at last put him to death; and all her commands being obeyed, she ruled over Asia for a long time with great lustre. And was not Belestiche a foreign woman off the streets, although at Alexandria she has shrines and temples, with an inscription as Aphrodite Belestiche, which she owes to the king's love? And she who has in this very town75 a temple and rites in common with Eros, and at Delphi stands in gold among kings and queens, by what dowry got she her lovers? But just as the lovers of Semiramis, Belestiche, and Phryne, became their prey unconsciously through their weakness and effeminacy, so on the other hand poor and obscure men, having contracted alliances with rich women of rank, have not been thereby spoilt nor merged their personality, but have lived with their wives on a footing of kindness, yet still kept their position as heads of the house. But he that abases his wife and makes her small, like one who tightens the ring on a finger too small for it fearing it will come off,76 is like those who cut their mares' tails off and then take them to a river or pond to drink, when they say that sorrowfully discerning their loss of beauty these mares lose their self-respect and allow themselves to be covered by asses.77 To select a wife for wealth rather than for her excellence or family is dishonourable and illiberal; but it is silly to reject wealth when it is accompanied by excellence and family. Antigonus indeed wrote to his officer who had garrisoned Munychia78 to make not only the collar strong but the dog lean, that he might undermine the strength of the Athenians; but it becomes not the husband of a rich or handsome woman to make his wife poor or ugly, but by his self-control39 and good sense, and by not too extravagantly showing his admiration for her, to exhibit himself as her equal not her slave, and (to borrow an illustration from the scales) to add just so much weight to his character as shall over-balance her, yet only just. Moreover, both Ismenodora and Baccho are of a suitable age for marriage and procreation of children; Ismenodora, I hear, is still in her prime, and" (here my father smiled slily at Pisias) "she is certainly not a bit older than her rivals, and has no grey hairs, as some of those who consort with Baccho have. And if their union is seasonable, who knows but that she may be a better partner for him than any young woman? For young couples do not blend and mix well together, and it takes a long time and is not an easy process for them to divest themselves of their pride and spirit, and at first there's a good deal of dirty weather and they don't pull well together, and this is oftenest the case when there's love on both sides, and, just as a storm wrecks the ship if no pilot is on board, so their marriage is trouble and confusion, neither party knowing how either to rule or to give way properly. And if the baby is under the nurse, and the boy under the master, and the lad under the master of the gymnasium, and the youth under his lover, and the full-grown man under the law and magistrate, and no one is his own master and exempt from obedience to someone, what wonder would it be if a sensible woman rather older than her husband would direct well the life of a young man, being useful to him by reason of her superior wisdom, and acceptable to him for her sweetness and gentleness? And to sum up the whole matter," said he, "we Bœotians ought to revere Hercules, and so find no fault in any inequality of age in marriages, seeing that he gave his own wife Megara in marriage to Iolaus, though he was only sixteen and she three-and-thirty."79

§ ix. When Protogenes finished speaking, my father said, "Do you see, Anthemion, that they're making us step in again, even though we have no problem dancing in the company of married Love?" "I do," replied Anthemion, "but please defend Love thoroughly, since you're on his side, and also stand up for wealth,73 which Pisias is trying to use to intimidate us." My father started, "What on earth won't be used against a woman if we turn down Ismenodora just because she's in love and has money? So she loves power and is wealthy? What if she's young and beautiful? And what if she takes some pride in her noble lineage? Haven't chaste women often been seen as a bit moody and hard to bear? Don't they sometimes get labeled as sharp-tongued and shrewish simply because of their chastity? Would it be better to marry off any random Thracian Abrotonus or some Milesian Bacchis, sealing the deal with just a handful of nuts? But even such women can turn out to be unbearable tyrants, like Syrian flute-girls and dancers such as Aristonica, and Œnanthe with her tambourine, and Agathoclea, who have reigned over kings' crowns.74 Look at how Syrian Semiramis was just a servant and concubine of one of King Ninus's slaves, until the great king noticed her, fell in love, and she gained such power over him that she thought so little of him that she asked to simply sit on the royal throne for a day, wear the royal crown, and handle state affairs. When Ninus granted her request and commanded all his subjects to obey her like they would him, she first made some very reasonable orders to test the guards; but when she saw they followed her without hesitation, she commanded them to capture Ninus and lock him up, ultimately leading to his death; and with her commands being obeyed, she ruled over Asia for many years with great brilliance. And wasn’t Belestiche just a woman off the street, even though she has temples and shrines in Alexandria, with an inscription saying Aphrodite Belestiche, which she owes to the king’s affection? And she who has in this town75 a temple and rituals alongside Eros, and stands in gold at Delphi among kings and queens, what dowry did she receive to attract her lovers? Just as the lovers of Semiramis, Belestiche, and Phryne fell victim to their own weaknesses and softness, poor and obscure men who formed connections with wealthy women of high status haven’t been ruined or lost their identities; instead, they’ve lived with their wives amicably while still maintaining their position as heads of the household. But one who belittles his wife and makes her feel small, like someone tightening a ring that’s too small for their finger, fearing it might come off,76 resembles those who cut off their mares' tails and then take them to drink at a river or pond, where these mares sorrowfully, realizing their loss of beauty, lose their self-respect and allow themselves to be mated by donkeys.77 Choosing a wife for her wealth instead of her virtues or family reputation is dishonorable and unrefined; however, it’s foolish to dismiss wealth when it comes with virtue and a noble family. Antigonus indeed wrote to his officer who was stationed in Munychia78 to ensure not only the collar was strong but the dog lean, which would undermine the power of the Athenians; but it's unfitting for the husband of a rich or beautiful woman to make his wife poor or unattractive. Instead, through his self-control39 and good judgment, and by not overly showing his admiration for her, he should present himself as her equal, not her servant, and (to borrow an analogy from scales) add just enough weight to his character to slightly outweigh hers. Moreover, both Ismenodora and Baccho are of an appropriate age for marriage and having children; Ismenodora, I hear, is still in her prime, and" (here my father slyly smiled at Pisias) "she is certainly not older than her competitors, and has no gray hairs, unlike some of those who associate with Baccho. If their union is timely, who knows? She might actually be a better match for him than any young woman. Young couples often don’t mix well together, and it takes time and effort for them to shed their pride and spirit. In the beginning, it’s often a rough ride and they don’t mesh well, which is often the case even when both are in love. Just like a storm damages a ship if there’s no pilot, their marriage can become troubled and chaotic, with neither knowing how to lead or concede properly. And if the child is under the nurse's care, the boy under the tutor's guidance, the young man under the gym instructor, and the adult man under the law and magistrates, and no one is truly in command of their own life, why would it be surprising if a smart woman who’s older than her husband could effectively guide a young man's life, being helpful to him due to her greater wisdom and endearing to him with her kindness and gentleness? To wrap up the whole discussion," he said, "we Bœotians should honor Hercules, and thus find no fault in any age difference in marriages, especially since he married his own wife Megara to Iolaus, even though he was just sixteen and she was thirty-three."79

§ x. As the conversation was going on, our father said that a friend of Pisias came galloping up from the town to report an act of marvellous audacity. Ismenodora, it appears, thinking Baccho had no personal dislike to the 40match, but only stood in awe of his friends who tried to dissuade him from it, determined that she would not let the young fellow slip through her fingers. Accordingly, she sent for the most active and intimate80 of her male friends, and for some of her female cronies, and instructed them as to what part they should play, and waited for the hour when Baccho was accustomed regularly to pass by her house on his way to the wrestling-school. And as he passed by on this occasion with two or three of his companions, anointed for the exercise, Ismenodora met him at the door and just touched his cloak, and her friends rushed out all together and prettily seized the pretty fellow as he was in his cloak and jersey,81 and hurried him into the house and at once locked the doors. And the women inside at once divested him of his cloak and put on him a bridal robe; and the servants ran about the town and put olive wreaths and laurel garlands at the doors of Baccho's house as well as Ismenodora's, and a flute-girl went up and down the street playing and singing the wedding-song. And some of the inhabitants of Thespiæ and the strangers laughed, others were indignant and tried to make the superintendents of the gymnasium move in the matter, for they have great power in Thespiæ over the youths, and pay great attention to their actions. And now there was no more talk about the sports, but everyone left the theatre for the neighbourhood of Ismenodora's house, and there stood in groups talking and disputing about what had happened.

§ x. As the conversation continued, our father mentioned that a friend of Pisias came riding up from the town to share news of a bold stunt. It turns out that Ismenodora believed Baccho didn’t personally dislike her, but rather was intimidated by his friends who were trying to talk him out of it. So, she decided not to let him get away. She called for her most energetic and close male friends, along with a few of her female buddies, and explained what roles they should play. Then she waited for the time when Baccho usually passed her house on his way to the wrestling school. When he passed this time, accompanied by two or three friends, all oiled up for the event, Ismenodora met him at the door and lightly touched his cloak. Her friends then jumped out all at once, playfully grabbing the handsome guy in his cloak and jersey, and quickly pulled him inside, locking the doors behind them. The women inside immediately stripped him of his cloak and dressed him in a bridal gown. Meanwhile, the servants ran around the town putting olive wreaths and laurel garlands on the doors of both Baccho's and Ismenodora's homes, while a flute girl strolled down the street, playing and singing the wedding song. Some of the locals from Thespiæ and visitors laughed, while others were angry and tried to get the gymnasium officials involved, as they hold significant influence over the young men and closely monitor their behavior. With that, there was no more talk of sports, and everyone left the theater to gather near Ismenodora’s house, where they formed groups to discuss and argue about what had just happened.

§ xi. Now when Pisias' friend had come up like an aide-de-camp in war, "bloody with spurring, fiery red with haste," to report this news that Ismenodora had seized Baccho, my father said that Zeuxippus smiled, and being a great lover of Euripides repeated the line,

§ xi. Now when Pisias' friend arrived like a aide-de-camp in battle, "bloody from spurring, fiery red with urgency," to deliver the news that Ismenodora had captured Baccho, my father remarked that Zeuxippus smiled, and since he was a huge fan of Euripides, he quoted the line,

"Lady, even though you’re wealthy, you still have the feelings of your gender."

But Pisias jumped up and cried out, "Ye gods, what will be the end of license like this which will overthrow our town? Already we are fast tending to lawlessness through our independence. And yet it is perhaps ridicu41lous to be indignant about law and justice, when nature itself is trampled upon by being thus subjected to women? Saw even Lemnos ever the like of this?82 Let us go," he continued, "let us go and hand over to the women the gymnasium and council-hall, if the townsmen have lost all their nerve." Pisias then left the company, and Protogenes went with him, partly sympathizing with his indignation, but still endeavouring to cool him. And Anthemion said, "'Twas a bold deed and certainly does savour somewhat of Lemnos—I own it now we are alone—this Ismenodora must be most violently in love." Hereupon Soclarus said, with a sly smile, "You don't think then that this rape and detention was an excuse and stratagem on the part of a wily young man to escape from the clutches of his lovers, and fly of his own volition to the arms of a rich and handsome widow?" "Pray don't say so, Soclarus," said Anthemion, "pray don't entertain any such suspicions of Baccho, for even if he were not by nature most simple and naïve, he would not have concealed the matter from me to whom he divulges all his secrets, especially as he knows that I have always been very anxious he should marry Ismenodora. But as Heraclitus says truly, It is more difficult to control love than anger; for whatever love has a fancy to, it will buy even at the cost of life, money, and reputation. Who lives a more quiet life in our town than Ismenodora? When did ever any ugly rumour attach itself to her? When did ever any breath of suspicion sully her house? Some divine inspiration, beyond human calculation, seems now to have possessed her."

But Pisias jumped up and yelled, "Oh gods, what’s going to happen with this kind of freedom that will ruin our town? We're already heading towards chaos with all this independence. And yet, it might be silly to be outraged about law and justice when nature itself is being violated by allowing this to happen with women. Has Lemnos ever seen anything like this? Let’s go," he continued, "let’s hand over the gym and council hall to the women if the men of the town have lost all their courage." Pisias then left the group, and Protogenes followed him, partly agreeing with his outrage but still trying to calm him down. And Anthemion said, "That was a bold move and definitely feels a bit like Lemnos—I admit it now that we’re alone—this Ismenodora must be head over heels in love." Then Soclarus said with a sly smile, "So you don’t think that this kidnapping and holding her hostage was just a clever trick by a crafty young man to escape from his lovers and run off to the arms of a wealthy and attractive widow?" "Please don’t say that, Soclarus," Anthemion replied, "don’t suspect Baccho of such things, because even if he weren’t incredibly simple and naive, he wouldn’t hide something like this from me, who he tells all his secrets to, especially since he knows I’ve always been pushing him to marry Ismenodora. But as Heraclitus wisely says, it’s harder to control love than anger; for whatever love desires, it will pursue even at the cost of life, money, and reputation. Who leads a quieter life in our town than Ismenodora? When has any ugly rumor ever been associated with her? When has any suspicion ever tarnished her home? It seems some divine inspiration, beyond human calculation, has taken hold of her now."

§ xii. Then Pemptides laughed and said, "Of course you know that there is a certain disease of the body called the sacred disease.83 It is no wonder, therefore, if some call the greatest and most insane passion of the soul sacred and divine. However, as in Egypt I once saw two neighbours 42disputing when a serpent passed by them on the road, both calling it a good omen, but each claiming the blessing as his alone; so seeing lately that some of you drag Love to the men's apartments, while others confine it to the women's side of the house, while all of you regard it as a divine and superlative blessing, I do not wonder, since it is a passion that has such power and honour, that those who ought to banish it from every quarter and clip its wings do themselves add to its influence and power. And hitherto I held my peace, for I saw that the discussion turned rather on private than public interests, but now that we have got rid of Pisias, I would gladly hear from you to what they had an eye who first called Love a god."

§ xii. Then Pemptides laughed and said, "Of course you know that there's a certain illness called the sacred disease.83 It's not surprising, then, that some people refer to the greatest and most overwhelming passion of the soul as sacred and divine. However, just like when I once saw two neighbors in Egypt arguing as a serpent passed by, both calling it a good sign but each claiming the blessing was theirs alone; I notice that some of you bring Love into the men's quarters while others restrict it to the women's side of the house, though all of you see it as a divine and extraordinary blessing. I’m not surprised that those who should be pushing it away and trying to tame it instead contribute to its strength and influence. Until now, I kept quiet because I saw that the discussion was more about personal stakes than public matters, but now that we've gotten rid of Pisias, I’d love to hear your thoughts on who first referred to Love as a god."

§ xiii. Just as Pemptides had left off, and our father was about to answer his question, another messenger came from the town, sent by Ismenodora to summon Anthemion, for the tumult had increased, and there was a difference of opinion between the superintendents of the gymnasium, one thinking they ought to demand the liberation of Baccho, the other thinking they ought not to interfere. Anthemion got up at once and went off. And our father, addressing Pemptides especially, said, "You seem to me, my dear Pemptides, to be handling a great and bold matter, or rather to be discussing things that ought not to be discussed, in asking for a reason in each case for our opinion about the gods. Our ancient and hereditary faith is sufficient, a better argument than which we cannot either utter or find,

§ xiii. Just as Pemptides was finishing up, and our dad was about to respond to his question, another messenger arrived from the town, sent by Ismenodora to call for Anthemion, because the uproar had grown, and there was a disagreement among the gymnasium supervisors. One believed they should demand the release of Baccho, while the other thought they shouldn't get involved. Anthemion immediately stood up and left. Our dad then turned specifically to Pemptides and said, "You seem to me, my dear Pemptides, to be tackling a significant and daring topic, or rather discussing matters that shouldn’t be discussed, in seeking a reason for our views on the gods. Our long-standing and inherited faith is enough, a better argument than we can either express or discover."

'Not even if wisdom resides in our brains;' __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

but if this common foundation and basis of all piety be disturbed, and its stability and time-honoured ideas be unsettled, it becomes undermined and is suspected by everybody. You have heard, of course, what hot water Euripides got into, when he wrote at the beginning of his 'Melanippe,'

but if this common foundation and basis of all faith is disturbed, and its stability and traditional ideas are challenged, it becomes undermined and is doubted by everyone. You’ve heard, of course, about the trouble Euripides got into when he wrote at the beginning of his 'Melanippe,'

"Zeus, whoever he is, I don't know." Except by hearsay, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

but if he changed the opening line, he had confidence, 43it seems, that his play would go down with the public uncommonly well,86 so he altered it into

but if he changed the opening line, he felt confident, 43that his play would be exceptionally well-received by the public,86 so he changed it to

"Zeus the divine, as he is truly known." __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

And what difference is there between calling in question the received opinion about Zeus or Athene, and that about Love? For it is not now for the first time that Love asks for an altar and sacrifices, nor is he a strange god introduced by foreign superstition, as some Attis or Adonis, furtively smuggled in by hermaphrodites and women, and secretly receiving honours not his own, to avoid an indictment among the gods for coming among them under false pretences. And when, my friend, you hear the words of Empedocles,

And what's the difference between questioning the common beliefs about Zeus or Athena and those about Love? It's not the first time Love has asked for an altar and sacrifices, nor is he some foreign god brought in by strange beliefs, like Attis or Adonis, sneaked in by hermaphrodites and women, secretly getting honors that aren’t really his, just to dodge scrutiny among the gods for showing up under false pretenses. And when, my friend, you hear the words of Empedocles,

Friendship is also present, with the same length and width, But you can only see it with the mind's eye, Until with the sight your very soul is captivated.

you must suppose that they refer to Love. For this god is invisible, but to be extolled by us as one of the very oldest gods. And if you demand proofs about every one of the gods, laying a profane hand on every temple, and bringing a learned doubt to every altar, you will scrutinize and pry into everything. But we need not go far to find Love's pedigree.

you have to assume that they are talking about Love. This god is invisible but should be celebrated as one of the oldest gods. And if you want evidence for every one of the gods, touching every temple and questioning every altar with skepticism, you'll end up examining everything. But we don’t need to look very far to find Love's lineage.

Do you see how great a goddess Aphrodite is? She is the one who gave us and created Love, "From this, all living things on earth come." 88

And so Empedocles calls Aphrodite Life-giving,89 and Sophocles calls her Fruitful, both very appropriate epithets. And though the wonderful act of generation belongs to Aphrodite only, and Love is only present in it as a subordinate, yet if he be absent the whole affair becomes undesirable, and low, and tame. For a loveless coition brings only satiety, as the satisfaction of hunger and thirst, and has nothing noble resulting from it, whereas by Love Aphrodite removes the cloying element in pleasure, and 44produces harmonious friendship. And so Parmenides declares Love to be the oldest of the creations of Aphrodite, writing in his Cosmogony,

And so Empedocles refers to Aphrodite as Life-giving,89 and Sophocles calls her Fruitful, both of which are very fitting titles. Even though the amazing act of creation belongs solely to Aphrodite, and Love plays a supportive role, if Love is missing, the whole experience becomes undesirable, unrefined, and dull. A loveless sexual encounter only leads to boredom, similar to merely satisfying hunger or thirst, and results in nothing meaningful. In contrast, Love allows Aphrodite to eliminate the excessive part of pleasure and creates a sense of harmonious friendship. Therefore, Parmenides claims that Love is the oldest of Aphrodite’s creations, as he writes in his Cosmogony,

"Of all the gods, she created first Love."

But Hesiod, more naturally in my opinion, makes Love the most ancient of all, so that all things derive their existence from him.90 If we then deprive Love of his ancient honours, those of Aphrodite will be lost also. For we cannot argue that, while some revile Love, all spare Aphrodite, for on the same stage we hear of Love,

But Hesiod, I think more convincingly, makes Love the oldest of all, so that everything comes into being through him.90 If we strip Love of his ancient honors, Aphrodite’s will be lost too. We can't say that while some criticize Love, everyone treats Aphrodite with respect, because they are both part of the same story.

"Love is a trivial thing and for the lazy:"91

and again of Aphrodite,

and again of Aphrodite,

'Cypris, my boys, is just one of her names, She has many names. She is a nightmare, A ruthless power, even a wild madness. 92

Just as in the case of the other gods there is hardly one that has not been reviled, or escaped the scurrility of ignorance. Look, for example, at Ares, who may be considered as it were the counterpart of Love, what honours he has received from men, and again what abuse, as

Just like the other gods, there's hardly one that hasn't been criticized or escaped the mockery of ignorance. Take Ares, for example, who can be seen as the opposite of Love. Look at the honors he's received from people and, on the other hand, the insults he endures.

'Ares is blind, ladies, has no eyes, And with his pig's snout, he digs up all the good things.93

And Homer calls him 'blood-stained' and 'fickle.'94 And Chrysippus brings a grievous charge against him, in defining his name to mean destroyer,95 thereby giving a handle to those who think that Ares is only the fighting, wrangling, and quarrelsome instinct among mankind. Others again will tell us that Aphrodite is simply desire, and Hermes eloquence, and the Muses the arts and sciences, and Athene wisdom. You see what an abyss of impiety opens up before us, if we describe each of the gods, as only a passion, a power, or a virtue!"

And Homer calls him 'blood-stained' and 'fickle.'94 And Chrysippus makes a serious accusation against him, saying his name means destroyer,95 which gives a reason for those who believe that Ares represents only the instinct for fighting, arguing, and quarreling among people. Others will argue that Aphrodite is just desire, Hermes is just eloquence, the Muses represent the arts and sciences, and Athene embodies wisdom. You can see how a huge gap of disrespect opens up in front of us if we define each of the gods as merely a passion, a power, or a virtue!

§ xiv. "I see it," said Pemptides, "and it is impious either to make the gods passions, or to do just the con45trary, and make the passions gods." "What then?" said my father, "do you consider Ares a god, or only a human passion?" And Pemptides, answering that he looked on Ares as god of the passionate and manly element in mankind, "What," cried my father, "shall the passionate and warlike and antagonistic instincts in man have a god, but the affectionate and social and clubable have none? Shall Ares, under his names of Enyalius and Stratius, preside over arms and war and sieges and sacks of cities, and shall there be no god to witness and preside over, to direct and guide, conjugal affection, that friendship of closest union and communion? Why even those who hunt gazelles and hares and deer have a silvan deity who harks and halloos them on, for to Aristæus96 they pay their vows when in pitfalls and snares they trap wolves and bears,

§ xiv. "I get it," said Pemptides, "and it's disrespectful to either turn the gods into passions or to do the opposite and turn passions into gods." "So what do you think?" my father asked. "Do you see Ares as a god or just a human emotion?" Pemptides replied that he viewed Ares as the god representing the passionate and manly aspects of humanity. "What?" my father exclaimed. "Are we saying that the passionate, warlike, and combative instincts in humans deserve a god, while the loving, social, and friendly ones don't? Ares, known as Enyalius and Stratius, oversees arms, war, sieges, and the plundering of cities, but there's no god to witness and guide the deep bond of marriage and close friendship? Even those who hunt gazelles, hares, and deer have a woodland deity cheering them on; they offer their vows to Aristæus96 when they catch wolves and bears in traps and snares,

'For Aristæus was the first to set traps for animals.'

And Hercules invoked another god, when he was about to shoot at the bird, as the line of Æschylus shows,

And Hercules called on another god right before he was about to shoot at the bird, as the line from Æschylus shows,

"Hunter Apollo, ensure my bolt flies straight!"97

And shall no god or good genius assist and prosper the man who hunts in the best chase of all, the chase of friendship? For I cannot for my part, my dear Daphnæus, consider man a less beautiful or important plant than the oak, or sacred olive, or the vine which Homer glorifies,98 seeing that man too has his growth and glorious prime alike of soul and body."

And should not any god or good spirit help and support the person who seeks the best pursuit of all, the pursuit of friendship? Because I can’t see, my dear Daphnæus, how a person is any less beautiful or significant than the oak, the sacred olive, or the vine that Homer praises,98 since a person also has their own growth and magnificent prime in both soul and body.

§ xv. Then said Daphnæus, "In the name of the gods, who thinks differently?" "All those certainly must," answered my father, "who think that the gods care only about ploughing and planting and sowing. Have they not Nymphs attending upon them, called Dryads, 'whose age is coeval with the trees they live in: and Dionysus the mirth-giving does he not increase the yield of the trees, the sacred splendour of Autumn,' as Pindar says?99 And if they care about all this, is there no god or genius who is interested in the nurture and growth of boys and youths in all their glorious flower? is there no one that cares that 46the growing man may be upright and virtuous, and that the nobility of his nature may not be warped and corrupted, either through want of a guardian or by the depravity of those he associates with? Is it not monstrous and thankless to say so, seeing that we enjoy the divine bounty, which is dealt out to us richly, and never abandons us in our straits? And yet some of these same straits have more necessity than beauty. For example, our birth, in spite of the unpleasant circumstances attending it, is witnessed by the divine Ilithyia and Artemis: and it would be better not to be born at all than to become bad through want of a good guardian and guide. Moreover in sickness the god who is over that province does not desert us, nor even in death: for even then there is a conductor and guide for the departed, to lay them to sleep, and convey their souls to Hades,100 as the poet says,

§ xv. Then Daphnæus said, "In the name of the gods, who thinks differently?" "Certainly all those must," my father replied, "who believe that the gods only care about farming and planting. Don’t the Nymphs, called Dryads, attend to them, 'whose age is as old as the trees they live in: and does Dionysus, the bringer of joy, not enhance the yield of the trees, the sacred beauty of Autumn,' as Pindar says?99 And if they care about all this, is there no god or spirit who is invested in the nurturing and growth of boys and young men in all their splendid potential? Is there no one who cares that 46the developing man remains upright and virtuous, and that the goodness of his nature isn’t twisted and corrupted, either from lack of a mentor or by the corruption of those he associates with? Is it not absurd and ungrateful to say so, considering we benefit from the divine generosity that abundantly provides for us and never abandons us in our troubles? Yet some of these troubles are more necessary than beautiful. For instance, our birth, despite the unpleasant circumstances surrounding it, is attended by the divine Ilithyia and Artemis: and it would be better not to be born at all than to turn bad due to insufficient guardianship and guidance. Furthermore, in sickness, the god responsible does not abandon us, nor even in death: for even then there is a guide who helps the departed find rest and lead their souls to Hades,100 as the poet says,

'Night didn't allow me to be the master of the lyre, Neither to be a seer nor a healer of diseases, But to guide the souls of the departed.

And yet these duties involve much unpleasantness, whereas we cannot mention a holier work, nor any struggle or contest more fitting for a god to attend and play the umpire in, than the guidance of the young and beautiful in the prosecution of their love-affairs. For there is here nothing of an unpleasant nature, no compulsion of any kind, but persuasion and grace, truly making toil sweet and labour delightful, lead the way to virtue and friendship, and do not arrive at that desired goal without the deity, for they have as their leader and lord no other god than Love, the companion of the Muses and Graces and Aphrodite. For Love 'sowing in the heart of man the sweet harvest of desire,' to borrow the language of Melanippides, mixes the sweetest and most beautiful things together. But perhaps you are of a different opinion, Zeuxippus."

And yet these responsibilities come with a lot of unpleasantness, while we can hardly think of a nobler task, or any struggle or competition more suitable for a god to oversee, than helping the young and lovely in their love lives. Here, there’s nothing unpleasant, no force of any kind, just persuasion and charm, truly making hard work sweet and labor enjoyable, leading the way to virtue and friendship. They don’t reach that desired goal without the divine influence since they have as their leader and lord none other than Love, the companion of the Muses, Graces, and Aphrodite. Love, "sowing in the heart of man the sweet harvest of desire," to use Melanippides’ words, mixes the sweetest and most beautiful things together. But perhaps you see it differently, Zeuxippus.

§ xvi. "Not I, by Zeus," replied Zeuxippus. "To have a different opinion would be ridiculous." "Then," continued my father, "is it not also ridiculous, if there are four kinds of friendship, for so the ancients distinguished, the natural first, the second that to one's kindred, the third 47that to one's companions, the fourth the friendship of love, and each of the first three have a god as patron, either a god of friendship, or a god of hospitality, or a god of the family, or a god of the race,101 whereas the friendship of love only, as something altogether unholy, is left without any patron god, and that, too, when it needs most of all attentive direction?" "It is," said Zeuxippus, "highly ridiculous." My father continued, "The language of Plato is very suggestive here, to make a slight digression. One kind of madness (he says) is conveyed to the soul from the body through certain bad temperaments or mixtures, or through the prevalence of some noxious spirit, and is harsh, difficult to cure, and baneful. Another kind of madness is not uninspired or from within, but an afflatus from without, a deviation from sober reason, originated and set in motion by some higher power, the ordinary characteristic of which is called enthusiasm. For, as one full of breath is called ἔμτνοος, and as one full of sense is called ἔμφρων, so the name enthusiasm is given to the commotion of the soul caused by some Divine agency.102 Thus there is the prophetic enthusiasm which proceeds from Apollo, and the Bacchic enthusiasm which comes from Dionysus, to which Sophocles alludes where he says, 'Dance with the Corybantes;' for the rites of Cybele and Pan have great affinities to the orgies of Bacchus. And the third madness proceeds from the Muses, and possesses an impressionable and pure soul, and stirs up the poetry and music in a man. As to the martial and warlike madness, it is well known from what god it proceeds, namely, Ares, 'kindling tearful war, that puts an end to the dance and the song, and exciting civic strife.'103 There remains, Daphnæus, one more kind of madness in man, neither obscure nor tranquil, as to which I should like to ask Pemptides here,

§ xvi. "Not me, by Zeus," replied Zeuxippus. "Having a different opinion would be absurd." "Then," my father continued, "isn't it also absurd that, if there are four types of friendship, as the ancients defined—first, natural friendship; second, that towards one's relatives; third, the friendship of companions; and fourth, romantic love—each of the first three has a god as its patron, whether a god of friendship, hospitality, family, or heritage, whereas romantic love, considered completely unholy, lacks any patron god, especially when it requires the most careful guidance?" "It is," Zeuxippus agreed, "highly absurd." My father went on, "Plato's language is very insightful here, so let me diverge slightly. One type of madness, he says, comes from the body to the soul through certain toxic humors or mixtures, or due to the influence of some harmful spirit, and it is harsh, hard to cure, and destructive. Another type of madness isn’t born from within but is inspired from the outside, a departure from rational thought, initiated by a higher power, and this is typically characterized as enthusiasm. Just as someone full of breath is called ἔμτνοος, and someone full of reason is ἔμφρων, the term enthusiasm describes the stirring of the soul caused by some Divine influence.102 Thus, there is prophetic enthusiasm that comes from Apollo, and Bacchic enthusiasm that comes from Dionysus, which Sophocles references when he says, 'Dance with the Corybantes;' since the rites of Cybele and Pan strongly resemble the Bacchic festivities. The third kind of madness arises from the Muses and touches a sensitive and pure soul, awakening poetry and music within a person. As for martial madness, everyone knows it comes from Ares, 'igniting tearful war, interrupting dance and song, and stirring civil discord.'103 There remains, Daphnæus, one more kind of madness in man, neither obscure nor calm, about which I'd like to ask Pemptides here,

"Which god is it that shakes the fruitful thyrsus?"

I refer to that love-fury for modest boys and chaste women, 48which is far the keenest and fiercest passion of all. For have you not observed how the soldier, when he lays aside his arms, ceases from his warlike fury, as the poet says,

I’m talking about that intense passion for modest boys and pure women, 48which is the sharpest and most intense emotion of all. Haven't you noticed how a soldier, when he puts down his weapons, stops his battle rage, as the poet mentions,

Then from him His squires happily took off the armor, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

and sits down a peaceful spectator of others?105 The Bacchic and Corybantic dances one can also modulate and quell, by changing the metre from the trochaic and the measure from the Phrygian. Similarly, too, the Pythian priestess, when she descends from her tripod, possesses her soul in peace. Whereas the love-fury, when once it has really seized on a man and inflamed him, can be laid by no Muse, no charm or incantation, no change of place; but present they burn, absent they desire, by day they follow their loves about, by night they serenade them, sober call for them, and drunken sing about them. And he who said that poetic fancies, owing to their vividness, were dreams of people awake, would have more truly spoken so of the fancies of lovers, who, as if their loves were present, converse with them, greet them, chide them. For sight seems to paint all other fancies on a wet ground, so soon do they fade and recede from the memory, but the images of lovers, painted by the fancy as it were on encaustic tiles, leave impressions on the memory, that move, and live, and speak, and are permanent for all time. The Roman Cato, indeed, said that the soul of the lover resided in the soul of the loved one, and I should extend the remark to the appearance, the character, the life, and the actions, conducted by which he travels a long journey in a short time, as the Cynics say they have found a short cut and, as it were, forced march to virtue, for there is also a short cut to friendship and love when the god is propitious. To sum up, the enthusiasm of lovers is not a thing uninspired, and the god that guides and governs it is none other than the god whose festival we are now keeping, and to whom we are now sacrificing. Nevertheless, as we judge of a god mainly from his power and usefulness (as among human advantages we reckon and call these two the most divine, 49dominion and virtue), it is high time to consider, before we proceed any further, whether Love yields to any of the gods in power. Certainly, as Sophocles says, 'Wonderful is the power which the Cyprian Queen exerts so as always to win the victory:'106 great also is the might of Ares; and in some sort we see the power of all the other gods divided among these two; for Aphrodite has most intimate connection with the beautiful, and Ares is in our souls from the first to combat against the sordid, to borrow the idea of Plato. Let us consider, then, to begin with, that the venereal delight can be purchased for six obols, and that no one ever yet put himself into any trouble or danger about it, unless he was in love. And not to mention here such famous courtesans as Phryne or Lais, Gnathænium, 'kindling her lamp at evening time,' on the look-out for lovers and inviting them, is often passed by; 'yet, if some sudden whiff arise' of mighty love and desire, it makes this very delight seem equal to the fabled wealth of Tantalus and his domains. So feeble and cloying is the venereal indulgence, if Love inspires it not. And you will see this more plainly still from the following consideration. Many have allowed others to share in their venereal enjoyments, prostituting not only their mistresses but their wives, like that Roman Galba, who used to ask Mæcenas to dinner, and when he saw from his nods and winks that he had a mind to do with his wife, turned his head gently aside as if asleep; but when one of his slaves came up to the table and stole some wine, his eyes were wide open enough, and he said, 'Villain, don't you know that I am asleep only for Mæcenas?'107 But this is not perhaps so strange, considering Galba was a buffoon. But at Argos Nicostratus and Phayllus were great political rivals: so when King Philip visited that city, Phayllus thought if he prostituted his wife, who was very handsome, to the King, he would get from him some important office or place. And Nicostratus getting wind of this, and walking about the doors of Phayllus' house with some of his servants on the qui vive, 50Phayllus made his wife put on men's boots, and a military cloak, and a Macedonian broad-brimmed hat, and so smuggled her into the King, without being detected, as one of the King's young men. But, of all the multitude of lovers, did you ever hear of one that prostituted his boy-love even for the honours of Zeus? I think not. Why, though no one will generally either speak or act against tyrants, many will who find them their rivals and are jealous about their handsome minions. You must have heard how Aristogiton of Athens, and Antileon of Metapontum, and Melanippus of Agrigentum, rose not against tyrants, although they saw how badly they managed affairs, and what drunken tricks they played, yet, when they attempted the chastity of their boy-loves, they retaliated on them, jeoparding their lives, as if they were defending the inviolability of temples and sanctuaries. It is also recorded that Alexander wrote to Theodoras, the brother of Proteas, 'Send me your singing-girl, unless you love her yourself, and I will give you ten talents;' and when Antipatridas, one of his companions, came to revel with him, bringing with him a female harper, he fancied the girl not a little, and asked Antipatridas if he cared very much about her. And when he replied that he did immensely, Alexander said, 'Plague take you,' but nevertheless abstained from touching the girl.

and sits down as a peaceful observer of others?105 The Bacchic and Corybantic dances can also be adjusted and calmed by changing the meter from trochaic to Phrygian. Likewise, the Pythian priestess, when she gets up from her tripod, holds her soul in peace. However, the love-fury, once it has genuinely taken hold of someone and ignited them, cannot be calmed by any Muse, charm, or incantation, nor by changing locations; but when present, they burn, when absent, they long, by day they pursue their loves, by night they serenade them, soberly call for them, and drunkenly sing about them. He who claimed that poetic inspirations, due to their vividness, were like dreams of people awake, would have been more accurate speaking about the thoughts of lovers, who, as if their loves were right there, talk to them, greet them, scold them. For sight seems to draw all other fantasies on a wet surface, as they quickly fade away from memory, but the images of lovers, painted by the imagination as if on wax tiles, leave lasting impressions that move, live, speak, and endure forever. The Roman Cato indeed said that the soul of a lover resides in the soul of the beloved, and I would expand this observation to include their appearance, character, life, and actions, which allow them to undertake a long journey in a short time, as the Cynics say they have discovered a shortcut and, in a sense, a forced march to virtue, for there is also a shortcut to friendship and love when the god is favorable. In summary, the passion of lovers is not uninspired, and the god that guides and controls it is none other than the god whose festival we are currently observing, and to whom we are now making sacrifices. Nevertheless, as we evaluate a god mainly by his power and usefulness (and among human advantages, we often consider and label these two as the most divine, 49dominion and virtue), it is time to reflect, before we go any further, whether Love ranks with any of the gods in power. Certainly, as Sophocles states, 'Wonderful is the power which the Cyprian Queen exerts to always achieve victory:'106 great also is the power of Ares; and in some ways we observe the power of all the other gods divided between these two; for Aphrodite has the closest connection with beauty, and Ares is within us from the beginning to fight against the shameful, borrowing Plato's idea. Let’s first note that sexual pleasure can be bought for six obols, and no one has ever truly put themselves into trouble or danger for it unless they were in love. And not to mention famous courtesans like Phryne or Lais, Gnathænium, 'lighting her lamp at evening time,' just waiting for lovers and inviting them, often gets overlooked; 'yet, if a sudden wave of intense love and desire arises,' this very pleasure seems equal to the legendary riches of Tantalus and his realm. So weak and cloying is sexual indulgence if Love does not inspire it. You will see this even more clearly from the following thought. Many have let others share in their sexual pleasures, selling not only their mistresses but also their wives, like that Roman Galba, who would invite Mæcenas to dinner, and when he noticed from his nods and winks that Mæcenas wanted to be with his wife, he gently turned his head aside as if asleep; but when one of his slaves approached the table and stole some wine, his eyes were wide open, and he said, 'Villain, don't you know that I am only pretending to be asleep for Mæcenas?'107 But this may not be so surprising, considering Galba was a fool. In Argos, Nicostratus and Phayllus were major political opponents: when King Philip visited that city, Phayllus thought if he offered his beautiful wife to the King, he would gain some important position. Nicostratus caught wind of this and walked around Phayllus' house with some of his servants on alert, while Phayllus made his wife put on men's boots, a military cloak, and a Macedonian wide-brimmed hat, managing to sneak her into the King undetected as one of the King's young men. But out of the countless lovers, have you ever heard of one who sold his boy-love even for the honors of Zeus? I think not. While no one generally speaks or acts against tyrants, many will when they see them as rivals and are jealous of their handsome favorites. You must have heard how Aristogiton of Athens, Antileon of Metapontum, and Melanippus of Agrigentum did not rise against tyrants, even though they recognized how poorly they were governing and the drunken antics they engaged in; yet, when those tyrants attempted to violate the chastity of their boy-loves, they retaliated with their lives on the line, as if defending sacred places. It is also recorded that Alexander wrote to Theodoras, the brother of Proteas, 'Send me your singing girl, unless you love her yourself, and I will give you ten talents;' and when Antipatridas, one of his companions, came to celebrate with him, bringing a female musician, he took a liking to her and asked Antipatridas how much he cared for her. When Antipatridas replied that he cared deeply, Alexander said, 'Curse you,' yet still refrained from touching the girl.

§ xvii. "Consider also how Love excels in warlike feats, and is by no means idle, as Euripides called him,108 nor a carpet-knight, nor 'sleeping on a maiden's soft cheeks.'109 For a man inspired by Love needs not Ares to help him when he goes out as a warrior against the enemy, but at the bidding of his own god is 'ready' for his friend 'to go through fire and water and whirlwinds.' And in Sophocles' play,110 when the sons of Niobe are being shot at and dying, one of them calls out for no helper or assister but his lover. And you know of course how it was that Cleomachus the Pharsalian fell in battle?" "We cer51tainly don't," said Pemptides and those near him, "but we should very much like to." "Well," said my father, "the tale's worth hearing. When the war between the Eretrians and Chalcidians was at its height, Cleomachus had come to aid the latter with a Thessalian force; and the Chalcidian infantry seemed strong enough, but they had great difficulty in repelling the enemy's cavalry. So they begged that high-souled hero Cleomachus to charge the Eretrian cavalry first. And he asked his boy-love, who was by, if he would be a spectator of the fight, and he saying he would, and affectionately kissing him and putting his helmet on his head, Cleomachus with a proud joy put himself at the head of the bravest of the Thessalians, and charged the enemy's cavalry with such impetuosity that he threw them into disorder and routed them; and the Eretrian infantry also fleeing in consequence, the Chalcidians won a splendid victory. However, Cleomachus got killed, and they show his tomb in the market-place at Chalcis, over which a huge pillar stands to this day, and whereas before that the people of Chalcis had censured boy-loves, from that time forward they preferred that kind of love to the normal love. Aristotle gives a slightly different account, namely, that this Cleomachus came not from Thessaly, but from Chalcis in Thrace, to the help of the Chalcidians in Eubœa; and that that was the origin of the song in vogue among the Chalcidians,

§ xvii. "Consider how Love stands out in acts of bravery and is by no means inactive, as Euripides described him,108 nor a dandy, nor 'sleeping on a maiden's soft cheeks.'109 A man filled with Love doesn’t need Ares to support him when he goes into battle against the enemy; he is 'ready' for his friend 'to go through fire and water and whirlwinds' at the behest of his own god. In Sophocles' play,110 when the children of Niobe are being shot at and dying, one of them calls out not for any helper but for his lover. And of course, you know how Cleomachus the Pharsalian met his end in battle?" "We certainly don't," said Pemptides and those around him, "but we would really like to hear it." "Well," said my father, "the story is worth telling. When the war between the Eretrians and the Chalcidians was at its peak, Cleomachus came to support the latter with a force from Thessaly; the Chalcidian infantry looked strong enough but struggled to fend off the enemy's cavalry. So they asked the noble hero Cleomachus to charge the Eretrian cavalry first. He asked his young lover, who was there, if he would watch the fight, and upon receiving a positive response, he affectionately kissed him and placed his helmet on his head. With a heart full of pride, Cleomachus led the bravest of the Thessalians and charged the enemy’s cavalry with such force that he threw them into confusion and routed them; as a result, the Eretrian infantry fled, and the Chalcidians achieved a remarkable victory. However, Cleomachus was killed, and they have his tomb in the market-place at Chalcis, beneath a large pillar that stands to this day. Although the people of Chalcis had previously disapproved of boy-loves, from that time on they favored that type of love over conventional love. Aristotle tells a slightly different story, stating that this Cleomachus was not from Thessaly but from Chalcis in Thrace, who came to assist the Chalcidians in Eubœa; and that was the reason behind the popular song among the Chalcidians,

You boys, who come from noble fathers and are beautiful in appearance, Do not hesitate to give brave men the joy of your embrace: For love that relaxes the body is intertwined with bravery. In the Chalcidian cities, there is a reputation that will never fade.

But according to the account of the poet Dionysius, in his 'Causes,'111 the name of the lover was Anton, and that of the boy-love was Philistus. And among you Thebans, Pemptides, is it not usual for the lover to give his boy-love a complete suit of armour when he is enrolled among the men? And did not the erotic Pammenes change the disposition of the heavy-armed infantry, censuring Homer as knowing nothing about love, because he drew up the Achæans in 52order of battle in tribes and clans, and did not put lover and love together, that so

But according to the poet Dionysius in his 'Causes,' the lover's name was Anton, and the boy's name was Philistus. And among you, Thebans, Pemptides, isn't it common for the lover to give his boy-love a full set of armor when he becomes part of the military? And didn’t the passionate Pammenes change the formation of the heavy infantry, criticizing Homer for not knowing anything about love, because he arranged the Achaeans in battle order by tribes and clans, instead of pairing lovers together?

'Spear should be next to spear, helmet to helmet,'112

seeing that Love is the only invincible general.113 For men in battle will leave in the lurch clansmen and friends, aye, and parents and sons, but what warrior ever broke through or charged through lover and love, seeing that even when there is no necessity lovers frequently display their bravery and contempt of life. As Thero the Thessalian, who put his left hand on a wall, and drew his sword, and chopped off his thumb, and challenged his rival to do the same. And another in battle falling on his face, as his enemy was about to give him the coup-de-grace, begged him to wait a little till he could turn round, that his love should not see him with a wound in his back. And not only are the most warlike nations most amorous, as the Bœotians the Lacedæmonians and the Cretans, but also of the old heroes, who were more amorous than Meleager, Achilles, Aristomenes, Cimon, and Epaminondas. Why, Epaminondas had as his boy-loves Asopichus and Cephisodorus, the latter of whom fell with him at Mantinea, and is buried near him. As to ..., who was most formidable and a source of terror to the enemy, Eucnamus of Amphissa, who first stood up against him and smote him, received hero honours from the Phocians for his exploit. And as to all the loves of Hercules, it would take up too much time to enumerate them, but those who think that Iolaus was one of them do up to this day worship and honour him, and make their loves swear fidelity at his tomb. Hercules is also said, having understood the art of healing, to have preserved the life of Alcestis, when she was given up by the doctors, to gratify Admetus, who passionately loved his wife, and was Hercules' minion. They say also in legend that Apollo was enamoured of Admetus,

seeing that Love is the only unbeatable general.113 Men in battle will abandon their clansmen and friends, even parents and sons, but what warrior has ever broken through or charged past their lover and love? Even when there's no need, lovers often show bravery and contempt for life. Like Thero the Thessalian, who placed his left hand on a wall, drew his sword, and chopped off his thumb, challenging his rival to do the same. Another warrior, while lying face down in battle as his enemy was about to finish him off, asked his opponent to wait a moment until he could roll over, so his love wouldn't see him with a wound on his back. The most warlike nations, like the Bœotians, Lacedæmonians, and Cretans, are also the most passionate. The old heroes were more in love than Meleager, Achilles, Aristomenes, Cimon, and Epaminondas. For example, Epaminondas had his boy-loves Asopichus and Cephisodorus, the latter of whom died with him at Mantinea and is buried nearby. As for Eucnamus of Amphissa, who was feared by the enemy and first stood up against him and struck him, he received hero honors from the Phocians for his deed. Listing all of Hercules' loves would take too long, but those who believe Iolaus was one of them still worship and honor him, making their lovers swear fidelity at his tomb. Hercules is also said to have learned the art of healing and saved Alcestis when the doctors had given up on her, to please Admetus, who deeply loved his wife and was Hercules' close companion. Legend also says that Apollo was infatuated with Admetus.

"And he was his hired slave for one whole year."

It was a happy thought our remembering Alcestis, for 53though women have not much of Ares in them, yet when possessed by Love they are bold even to the death, beyond what one would expect from their nature. For if we may credit legendary lore, the stories about Alcestis, and Protesilaus, and Eurydice the wife of Orpheus, show that the only one of the gods that Hades pays attention to is Love; although to everybody else, as Sophocles says, "he knows of no forbearance or favour, or anything but strict justice; "yet before lovers his genius stands rebuked, and they alone find him neither implacable nor relentless. Wherefore although, my friend, it is an excellent thing to be initiated in the Eleusinian mysteries, yet I see that the votaries and initiated of Love have a better time of it in Hades than they have, * *114 though in regard to legendary lore I stand in the position of one who neither altogether believes nor altogether disbelieves. For legendary lore speaks well, and by a certain wonderful good fortune lights upon the truth, in saying that lovers have a return from Hades to the light of day, but it knows not by what way or how, having as it were got benighted on the road which Plato first discovered by philosophy. There are, indeed, some slender and obscure particles of truth scattered about in the mythology of the Egyptians, but they require a clever man to hunt them out, a man capable of getting great results from small data. Wherefore let that matter pass. And now next to the mighty power of Love let us consider its good will and favour to mankind, I do not mean as to whether it bestows many gifts on its votaries—that is palpable to all—but whether they derive any further advantage from it. For Euripides, though very amorous, admired a very small matter, when he wrote the line—

It was a joyful thought for us to remember Alcestis, because although women may not show much of Ares, when they are driven by Love, they become incredibly brave, even to the point of death, more than one might expect from their nature. If we can trust the legends, the stories about Alcestis, Protesilaus, and Eurydice, Orpheus’s wife, show that the only god that Hades pays attention to is Love. For everyone else, as Sophocles says, "he knows nothing of mercy or kindness, only strict justice;" yet, in the presence of lovers, his nature is softened, and they are the only ones who find him neither unforgiving nor relentless. Therefore, my friend, while being part of the Eleusinian mysteries is certainly a wonderful thing, I see that those devoted to and initiated by Love have a better experience in Hades than they do, * *114 even though when it comes to legendary stories, I find myself in a place where I neither completely believe nor completely disbelieve. For legendary tales often speak the truth and, by some fortunate chance, occasionally stumble upon reality, stating that lovers can return from Hades to the light, but it doesn’t explain how or by what means, as if it has lost its way on the path that Plato first sought through philosophy. There are indeed some thin and obscure truths scattered throughout Egyptian mythology, but it takes a clever person to uncover them, someone capable of drawing significant insights from minimal information. So let’s leave that aside. Now, next to Love's immense power, let’s consider its goodwill and favor towards humanity; I’m not referring to whether it grants many gifts to its followers—that's obvious—but whether they gain any further benefits from it. For Euripides, despite being very passionate, admired something quite trivial when he wrote the line—

"Love shows a man who hasn't learned the letters." 115

For it makes one previously sluggish quick and intelligent, and, as has been said before, it makes the coward brave, as people harden wood in the fire and make it strong from being weak. And every lover becomes liberal and genuine 54and generous, even if he was mean before, his littleness and miserliness melting away like iron in the fire, so that they rejoice to give to their loves more than they do to receive themselves from others. You know of course that Anytus, the son of Anthemion, was in love with Alcibiades, and was on one occasion sumptuously entertaining several of his friends, when Alcibiades broke in and took from the table half the cups and went away again; and when some of the guests were indignant and said, 'The stripling has used you most insolently and contemptuously,' Anytus replied, 'Nay, rather, he has dealt kindly with me, for when he might have taken all he has left me half.'"

For it makes someone who was previously slow become quick and smart, and, as has been said before, it turns a coward into a brave person, just like how people strengthen wood by putting it in the fire. Every lover becomes generous and sincere 54 and giving, even if they were stingy before, with their meanness and miserly nature melting away like iron in the fire, so that they take joy in giving to their loves more than they enjoy receiving from others. You know, of course, that Anytus, the son of Anthemion, was in love with Alcibiades, and once he was hosting a lavish feast for several friends when Alcibiades burst in, took half of the cups from the table, and left. When some guests were upset and said, "That young man has treated you very rudely and disrespectfully," Anytus responded, "No, rather, he has been kind to me, for when he could have taken everything, he left me half."

§ xviii. Zeuxippus was pleased with this story, and said, "O Hercules, you have been within an ace of making me forget my hereditary hatred to Anytus for his behaviour to Socrates and philosophy,116 since he was so mild and noble to his love." "Be it so," said my father, "Love also makes peevish and gloomy persons kind and agreeable to those they live with; for as 'when the fire blazes the house looks brighter,'117 so man, it seems, becomes more cheerful through the heat of love. But most people are affected rather curiously; if they see by night a light in a house, they look on it with admiration and wonder; but if they see a little, mean, and ignoble soul suddenly filled with noble-mindedness, freedom, dignity, grace, and liberality, they do not feel constrained to say with Telemachus, 'Surely, some god is there within.'118 And is it not wonderful, Daphnæus," continued my father,119 "in the name of the Graces, that the lover who cares about hardly anything, either his companions and friends, or even the laws and magistrates and kings, who fears nothing, admires nothing, courts nothing, but can even endure to gaze on 'the forked lightning,'120 yet directly he looks on his love 'he crouches like a cock with drooping feathers,' and his boldness is 55broken and his pride is cowed. And among the Muses it would not be amiss to mention Sappho; for as the Romans say Cacus the son of Hephæstus vomited out of his mouth fire and flames, so she really speaks words that burn like fire, and in her songs shows the warmth of her heart, as Philoxenus puts it, 'by euphonious songs assuaging the pains of love.' And if you have not in your love for Lysandra forgot all your old love-songs, do repeat to us, Daphnæus, the lines in which beautiful Sappho says that 'when her love appeared her voice failed and her body burned, and she was seized with paleness and trembling and vertigo.'" And when Daphnæus had repeated the lines, my father resumed, "In the name of Zeus, is not this plainly a divine seizure? Is not this a wonderful commotion of soul? Why, the Pythian priestess on the tripod is not moved so much as this! Who of those inspired by Cybele are made beside themselves to this extent by the flute and the kettledrum? Moreover, while many see the same body and the same beauty, only the lover is taken by it. Why is this the case? We get no light on it from Menander's words, 'Love is opportunity; and he that is smitten is the only one wounded.' But the god is the cause of it, striking one and letting another go scot-free. But I will not pass over now, 'since it has come into my mouth,' as Æschylus says, what perhaps would have been better spoken before, for it is a very important point. Perhaps, my friend, of all other things which we do not perceive through the senses, some got believed through legend, some through the law, some through reason; whereas we owe our conception of the gods altogether to the poets and legislators and philosophers: all alike teaching the existence of gods, but greatly differing as to their number and order, nature and power. For the gods of the philosophers 'know nothing of disease or old age or pain, and have not to cross the resounding Acheron;' nor do the philosophers accept as gods Strifes, or Prayers, which are found in poetry;121 nor will they admit Terror and Fear as gods or as the sons of Ares. And on many points also they are at variance with the legislators, as Xenophanes bade the 56Egyptians, if they regarded Osiris as mortal, not to honour him as a god; but if they thought him a god not to mourn for him. And, again, the poets and legislators will not listen to, nor can they understand, the philosophers who make gods of ideas and numbers and units and spirits. And their views generally are very different. As there were formerly three parties at Athens, the Parali, the Epacrii, and the Pediei, all at variance with one another, yet all agreed to vote for Solon, and chose him with one accord as their mediator and ruler and lawgiver, as he seemed indisputably to hold the first place in merit; so the three parties that entertain different views about the gods are all unanimous on one point, for poets legislators and philosophers all alike register Love as one of the gods, 'loudly singing his praises with one voice,' as Alcæus says the people of Mitylene chose Pittacus as their monarch. But our king and ruler and governor, Love, is brought down crowned from Helicon to the Academy by Hesiod and Plato and Solon, and in royal apparel rides in a chariot drawn by friendship and intimacy (not such as Euripides speaks of in the line, 'he has been bound in fetters not of brass,'122 shamefully throwing round him cold and heavy necessity), and soars aloft to the most beautiful and divine things, about which others have spoken better than I can."

§ xviii. Zeuxippus enjoyed this story and said, "Oh Hercules, you almost made me forget my inherited dislike for Anytus because of how he treated Socrates and philosophy,116 since he was so gentle and noble with his love." "True enough," my father replied, "Love can turn grumpy and moody people into kind and pleasant companions; for just as 'when the fire blazes, the house looks brighter,'117 it appears that a person becomes more cheerful in the warmth of love. Yet, most people respond strangely; if they see a light in a house at night, they gaze at it in admiration and awe; but if they witness a small, petty, and unworthy soul suddenly filled with noble qualities, freedom, dignity, grace, and generosity, they don’t hesitate to exclaim with Telemachus, 'Surely, some god must be present.'118 And isn’t it remarkable, Daphnæus," my father continued,119 "on behalf of the Graces, that the lover, who cares about little—whether it’s companions, friends, laws, magistrates, or kings—who fears nothing, admires nothing, and pursues nothing, can even endure to look at 'the forked lightning,'120 yet the moment he sees his love, he cowers 'like a cock with drooping feathers,' and his confidence shatters and his pride diminishes. Among the Muses, Sappho deserves mention; just as the Romans say Cacus, the son of Hephæstus, spewed forth fire and flames, she truly speaks words that burn like fire, expressing the warmth of her heart in her songs, as Philoxenus puts it, 'by melodious songs easing the pains of love.' If you haven’t forgotten your old love songs for Lysandra, then please recite for us, Daphnæus, the lines where beautiful Sappho describes how 'when her love appeared, her voice faltered and her body burned, and she was struck with paleness, trembling, and dizziness.'" After Daphnæus recited the lines, my father continued, "By Zeus, is this not clearly a divine experience? Is this not an extraordinary emotional upheaval? The Pythian priestess on the tripod doesn’t even show that much agitation! Who among those inspired by Cybele gets so beside themselves from the flute and the drums? Moreover, while many see the same body and beauty, only the lover is genuinely affected. Why is that? Menander’s line, 'Love is opportunity; and he who is struck is the only one wounded,' doesn’t shed any light on this. The god is the reason behind it, affecting one person while sparing another. But I must not overlook now, 'since it has come to my attention,' as Æschylus says, what might have been better said earlier, since it’s very relevant. Perhaps, my friend, concerning many things we can’t perceive through our senses, some things are believed through legends, others through laws, and some through reason; whereas our understanding of the gods is entirely due to poets, lawmakers, and philosophers—all teaching of the gods' existence, but differing greatly in their number, order, nature, and power. The gods of the philosophers 'know nothing of disease, old age, or pain, and do not have to cross the resounding Acheron,' nor do the philosophers accept Strifes or Prayers as gods, which are found in poetry;121 and they will not recognize Terror and Fear as gods or as children of Ares. Moreover, they differ from lawmakers on several points, as Xenophanes advised the 56Egyptians—if they saw Osiris as mortal, they should not honor him as a god; but if they viewed him as divine, they should not mourn for him. Again, the poets and lawmakers will not heed the philosophers who make gods out of ideas, numbers, units, and spirits. Their views are generally very distinct. Just as there were once three factions in Athens—the Parali, the Epacrii, and the Pediei—all in disagreement yet agreeing to elect Solon as their mediator, ruler, and lawgiver, as he seemed to clearly hold the top position in merit; so the three factions with differing perspectives on the gods are unanimous on one point: poets, lawmakers, and philosophers all acknowledge Love as one of the gods, 'loudly singing his praises in unison,' as Alcæus describes how the people of Mitylene chose Pittacus as their monarch. But our king, ruler, and governor, Love, is brought down crowned from Helicon to the Academy by Hesiod, Plato, and Solon, and in royal attire rides in a chariot pulled by friendship and closeness (not like what Euripides refers to in the line, 'he's been bound in fetters not of brass,'122 cruelly wrapped in cold and heavy necessity), soaring towards the most beautiful and divine things, about which others have articulated better than I can."

§ xix. When my father had spoken thus much, Soclarus began, "Do you see that a second time you have committed the same fault, not cancelling your debts as you ought to do—for I must speak my mind—but evading them on purpose, and not delivering to us your promised ideas on a sacred subject? For as some little time back you only just touched on Plato and the Egyptians as if unwilling to enter on the subject more fully, so now you are doing again. However, as to what has been 'eloquently told'123 by Plato, or rather by the Muses through Plato's mouth, do not tell us that, my good friend, even if we ask for it; but as to your hint that the Egyptian legend about Love corresponded with Plato's views, you need not discuss it fully and minutely, we shall be satisfied if we hear a little of 57such mighty matters." And as the rest of the company made the same request, my father said, "The Egyptians, (like the Greeks) recognize two Loves, the Pandemian and the Celestial, to which they add the Sun, they also highly venerate Aphrodite. We also see much similarity between Love and the Sun, for neither is a fire, as some think, but a sweet and productive radiance and warmth, the Sun bringing to the body nourishment and light and growth, and Love doing the same to the soul. And as the heat of the Sun is more powerful when it emerges from clouds and after mist, so Love is sweeter and hotter after a jealous tiff with the loved one,124 and moreover, as some think the Sun is kindled and extinguished, so also do people conceive of Love as mortal and uncertain. Moreover, just as without training the body cannot easily bear the heat of the Sun, so neither can the untrained soul easily bear the yoke of Love, but both are equally out of tune and suffer, for which they blame the deity and not their own weakness. But in this respect they seem to differ, in that the Sun exhibits to the eye things beautiful and ugly alike, whereas Love throws its light only on beautiful things, and persuades lovers to concentrate their attention on these, and to neglect all other things. As to those that call Aphrodite the Moon, they, too, find some points in common between them; for the Moon is divine and heavenly and a sort of halfway-house between mortal and immortal, but inactive in itself and dark without the presence of the Sun, as is the case with Aphrodite in the absence of Love. So we may say that Aphrodite resembles the Moon, and Love the Sun, more than any other deities, yet are not Love and the Sun altogether the same, for just as body and soul are not the same, but something different, so is it with the Sun and Love, the former can be seen, the latter only felt. And if it should not seem too harsh a saying, one might argue that the Sun acts entirely opposite to Love, for it turns the mind away from the world of fancy to the world of reality, beguiling us by its grace and splendid appearance, and persuading us to seek for truth and everything else in and round it and nowhere else. For as Euripides says,

§ xix. After my father finished speaking, Soclarus began, "Do you realize that you've made the same mistake again by not taking care of your debts as you should? I have to say this—you're dodging your responsibilities and not sharing your promised thoughts on an important topic. Just like the last time, when you barely mentioned Plato and the Egyptians, you seem reluctant to dive deeper into the discussion now. But, as for what has been 'eloquently told'123 by Plato, or rather by the Muses through him, don't feel the need to share that, my friend, even if we ask. However, regarding your suggestion that the Egyptian legend about Love aligns with Plato's ideas, you don’t have to go into detail; we’ll be happy to hear just a bit about 57 such significant matters." With the rest of the group echoing the same request, my father said, "The Egyptians, like the Greeks, recognize two types of Love: Pandemian and Celestial, and they also honor the Sun greatly. There are many similarities between Love and the Sun, as neither is a fire, as some believe, but rather a sweet and nurturing radiance and warmth—the Sun provides nourishment, light, and growth to the body, while Love does the same for the soul. Just like the Sun's heat becomes more intense when it breaks through clouds and mist, Love feels sweeter and hotter after a jealous spat with someone you care about,124 and, in some views, just as the Sun is believed to be both ignited and extinguished, people also see Love as fleeting and uncertain. Additionally, just as the body requires training to withstand the Sun's heat, the untrained soul struggles with the burden of Love; both are out of tune and in pain, blaming the divine rather than their own weaknesses. However, they differ in that the Sun reveals both beautiful and ugly things, whereas Love shines its light only on the beautiful, encouraging lovers to focus solely on these and to overlook everything else. Those who call Aphrodite the Moon also see some similarities; the Moon is divine and heavenly, serving as a bridge between the mortal and immortal but is inactive and dark without the Sun, just like Aphrodite without Love. So we can say that Aphrodite resembles the Moon, and Love resembles the Sun, more than any other deities; yet, Love and the Sun are not entirely the same, just as body and soul are distinct. The Sun is visible, while Love is only felt. And if I may be blunt, one might argue that the Sun operates in direct contrast to Love, drawing our attention away from imagination to reality, captivating us with its beauty and grandeur, and leading us to seek truth and other things exclusively in its presence and nowhere else. As Euripides says,

We love the Sun too passionately, Because it always shines on the earth, From the inexperience of another life, '125

or rather from forgetfulness of those things which Love brings to our remembrance. For as when we are woke by a great and bright light, everything that the soul has seen in dreams is vanished and fled, so the Sun is wont to banish the remembrance of past changes and chances, and to bewitch the intelligence, pleasure and admiration causing this forgetfulness. And though reality is really there, yet the soul cleaves to dreams and is dazzled by what is most beautiful and divine. 'For round the soul are poured sweet yet deceiving dreams,' so that the soul thinks everything here good and valuable, unless it obtain divine and chaste Love as its physician and preserver. For Love brings the soul through the body to truth and the region of truth, where pure and guileless beauty is to be found, kindly befriending its votaries like an initiator at the mysteries. And it associates with the soul only through the body. And as geometricians, in the case of boys who cannot yet be initiated into the perception of incorporeal and impassive substance, convey their ideas through the medium of spheres, cubes, and dodecahedrons, so celestial Love has contrived beautiful mirrors of beautiful things, and exhibits them to us glittering in the shapes colours and appearances of youths in all their flower, and calmly stirs the memory which is inflamed first by these. Consequently some, through the stupidity of their friends and intimates, who have endeavoured by force and against reason to extinguish the flame, have got no advantage from it, but filled themselves with smoke and confusion, or have rushed into secret and lawless pleasures and ingloriously wasted their prime. But as many as by sober reason and modesty have abated the extravagance of the passion, and left in the soul only a bright glow—not exciting a tornado of passion, but a wonderful and productive diffusion, as in a growing plant, opening the pores of complaisance and friendliness—these in no long time cease to regard the personal charms of those they love, and study their inward 59characters, and gaze at one another with unveiled eyes, and associate with one another in words and actions, if they find in their minds any fragment or image of the beautiful; and if not they bid them farewell and turn to others, like bees that only go to those flowers from which they can get honey. But wherever they find any trace or emanation or pleasing resemblance of the divine, in an ecstasy of pleasure and delight they indulge their memory, and revive to whatever is truly lovely and felicitous and admired by everybody."

or rather from forgetting those things that Love brings to our minds. Just like when we wake up to a bright and intense light, everything the soul has seen in dreams disappears, the Sun has a way of fading the memory of past events and enchanting us, leading to this forgetfulness. Even though reality is present, the soul clings to dreams and is captivated by what is most beautiful and divine. 'For surrounding the soul are sweet yet misleading dreams,' causing the soul to perceive everything here as good and valuable, unless it achieves divine and pure Love as its healer and protector. Love guides the soul through the body to truth and the realm of truth, where pure and genuine beauty exists, kindly supporting its followers like a mentor in a sacred rite. It connects with the soul only through the body. Just as mathematicians, with boys who aren't yet ready to perceive non-physical and unmoving substances, use spheres, cubes, and dodecahedrons to express their ideas, celestial Love has created beautiful reflections of beautiful things, dazzling us with the forms, colors, and appearances of young people in their prime, gently stirring memories ignited by these first. Unfortunately, some people, due to the ignorance of their friends who have tried to extinguish the flame against reason, gain nothing from it, instead filling themselves with confusion, or diving into secret and unlawful pleasures, squandering their best years. But those who, with sober reason and modesty, have moderated the intensity of their passions, and left in their souls just a bright glow—not a whirlwind of desire, but a wonderful and productive spreading, like a growing plant that opens its pores to friendliness—these soon stop fixating on the external charms of their loved ones and begin to explore their inner characters. They look at each other with open eyes, relating through words and actions, if they find any aspects or images of beauty within their minds; if not, they say goodbye and move on to others, like bees that only visit the flowers that provide them with honey. Wherever they perceive any sign, trace, or pleasing resemblance of the divine, in a state of joy and delight they indulge their memories and return to whatever is truly lovely, fortunate, and admired by all.

§ xx. "The poets indeed seem for the most part to have written and sung about Love in a playful and merry manner, but have sometimes spoken seriously about him, whether out of their own mind, or the god helping them to truth. Among these are the lines about his birth, 'Well-sandalled Iris bare the most powerful of the gods to golden-haired Zephyr.'126 But perhaps the learned have persuaded you that these lines are only a fanciful illustration of the variety and beauty of love." "Certainly," said Daphnæus, "what else could they mean?" "Hear me," said my father, "for the heavenly phenomenon compels us so to speak. The rainbow127 is, I suppose, a reflection caused by the sun's rays falling on a moist cloud, making us think the appearance is in the cloud. Similarly erotic fancy in the case of noble souls causes a reflection of the memory, from things which here appear and are called beautiful, to what is really divine and lovely and felicitous and wonderful. But most lovers pursuing and groping after the semblance of beauty in boys and women, as in mirrors,128 can derive nothing more certain than pleasure mixed with pain. And this seems the love-delirium of Ixion, who instead of the joy he desired embraced only a cloud, as children who desire to take the rainbow into their hands, clutching at whatever they see. But different is the be60haviour of the noble and chaste lover: for he reflects on the divine beauty that can only be felt, while he uses the beauty of the visible body only as an organ of the memory, though he embraces it and loves it, and associating with it is still more inflamed in mind. And so neither in the body do they sit ever gazing at and desiring this light, nor after death do they return to this world again, and skulk and loiter about the doors and bedchambers of newly-married people, disagreeable ghosts of pleasure-loving and sensual men and women, who do not rightly deserve the name of lovers. For the true lover, when he has got into the other world and associated with beauties as much as is lawful, has wings and is initiated and passes his time above in the presence of his Deity, dancing and waiting upon him, until he goes back to the meadows of the Moon and Aphrodite, and sleeping there commences a new existence. But this is a subject too high for the present occasion. However, it is with Love as with the other gods, to borrow the words of Euripides, 'he rejoices in being honoured by mankind,'129 and vice versa, for he is most propitious to those that receive him properly, but visits his displeasure on those that affront him. For neither does Zeus as god of Hospitality punish and avenge any outrages on strangers or suppliants, nor as god of the family fulfil the curses of parents, as quickly as Love hearkens to lovers unfairly treated, being the chastiser of boorish and haughty persons. Why need I mention the story of Euxynthetus and Leucomantis, the latter of whom is called The Peeping Girl to this day in Cyprus? But perhaps you have not heard of the punishment of the Cretan Gorgo, a somewhat similar case to that of Leucomantis, except that she was turned into stone as she peeped out of window to see her lover carried out to burial. For this Gorgo had a lover called Asander, a proper young man and of a good family, but reduced in fortune, though he thought himself worthy to mate with anybody. So he wooed Gorgo, being a relation of hers, and though he had many rivals, as she was much run after for her wealth belike, yet he had won the esteem of all the guardians and relations of the young girl.130 * * * *

§ xx. "Most poets tend to write and sing about Love in a light-hearted and joyful way, but sometimes they speak about him earnestly, either from their own insights or with the inspiration of the divine guiding them toward the truth. Take, for example, the lines about his origin, 'Well-sandalled Iris brought the mightiest of the gods to golden-haired Zephyr.'126 But maybe the scholars have convinced you that these lines are just a whimsical depiction of the diversity and beauty of love." "Of course," Daphnæus replied, "what else could they imply?" "Listen to me," my father said, "for the heavenly spectacle requires us to discuss it. The rainbow127 is, I believe, a reflection created by the sun's rays hitting a wet cloud, making it seem like the appearance is within the cloud itself. Similarly, erotic imagination in noble souls reflects memories of what seems beautiful here onto what is genuinely divine, lovely, blissful, and remarkable. But most lovers, chasing after the illusion of beauty in boys and girls, like looking into mirrors,128 can only find in it a mix of pleasure and pain. This is reminiscent of Ixion's love madness, who, instead of enjoying what he desired, only embraced a cloud, much like children who try to grasp the rainbow, reaching for whatever they see. However, the true noble and chaste lover reflects on the divine beauty that can only be felt, using the beauty of the physical body solely as a trigger for memory, while he cherishes and loves it, becoming even more inspired in heart and mind through that association. Thus, they don't stay focused on the body, always fixated on this light, nor do they return to the earthly realm after death, lingering around the homes and beds of newlyweds like bothersome ghosts of pleasure-seeking and sensual individuals who don't truly merit the title of lovers. Because a true lover, once they’ve transitioned to the next world and have mingled with beauties as is permissible, gains wings and is initiated into higher realms, spending time close to their Deity, dancing and serving him until they return to the meadows of the Moon and Aphrodite, where they rest and begin a new existence. But this topic is too profound for now. Nevertheless, Love, like the other gods, as Euripides said, 'delights in being honored by humanity,'129 and vice versa, for he is most generous to those who properly receive him but brings his wrath upon those who disrespect him. Neither does Zeus, as the god of Hospitality, quickly punish and avenge attacks on guests or supplicants, nor does he, as the god of family, swiftly carry out the curses of parents as Love readily responds to wronged lovers, acting as a punisher of rude and arrogant individuals. Why should I even bring up the tale of Euxynthetus and Leucomantis, the latter of whom is still referred to as The Peeping Girl in Cyprus? But maybe you haven't heard about the punishment of the Cretan Gorgo, a story similar to that of Leucomantis, except she was turned to stone while peering out of a window to see her lover being taken for burial. This Gorgo had a lover named Asander, a decent young man from a respected family, but he had fallen on hard times, although he believed himself worthy of anyone. So he pursued Gorgo, a relative of his, and despite having many competitors, as she was highly sought after for her wealth, he had gained the favor of all her guardians and relatives.130 * * * *

§ xxi. * * * Now the origins and causes of Love are not peculiar to either sex, but common to both. For those attractions that make men amorous may as well proceed from women as from boys.131 And as to those beautiful and holy reminiscences and invitations to the divine and genuine and Olympian beauty, by which the soul soars aloft, what hinders but that they may come either from boys or lads, maidens or grown women, whenever a chaste and orderly nature and beauteous prime are associated together (just as a neat shoe exhibits the shapeliness of the foot, to borrow the illustration of Aristo), whenever connoisseurs of beauty descry in beautiful forms and pure bodies clear traces of an upright and unenervated soul.132 For if133 the man of pleasure, who was asked whether "he was most given to the love of women or boys," and answered, "I care not which so beauty be but there," is considered to have given an appropriate answer as to his erotic desires, shall the noble lover of beauty neglect beauty and nobility of nature, and make love only with an eye to the sexual parts? Why, the lover of horses will take just as much pleasure in the good points of Podargus, as in those of Æthe, Agamemnon's mare,134 and the sportsman rejoices not only in dogs, but also rears Cretan and Spartan bitches,135 and shall the lover of the beautiful and of humanity be unfair and deal unequally with either sex, and think that the difference between the loves of boys and women is only their different dress? And yet they say that beauty is a flower of virtue; and it is ridiculous to assert that the female sex never blossoms nor make a goodly show of virtue, for as Æschylus truly says,

§ xxi. * * * The origins and causes of Love aren't unique to one gender; they're shared by both. The attractions that make men fall in love can come from women just as much as from boys.131 And when it comes to those beautiful and sacred memories and calls to the divine and authentic and Olympian beauty, which lift the soul, what prevents them from arising from either boys or young men, girls or adult women, whenever purity and an orderly nature are found together (just like a well-fitted shoe showcases the shape of the foot, to borrow from Aristo)? Whenever experts in beauty recognize in beautiful forms and pure bodies clear signs of a strong and wholesome soul.132 Because if133 the hedonist, asked whether he preferred to love women or boys, replied, "I don't mind as long as there's beauty," is seen as giving a fitting response about his desires, should the true lover of beauty ignore beauty and nobility of character and only focus on physical aspects? Just as the horse lover enjoys the good characteristics of Podargus as much as those of Æthe, Agamemnon's mare,134 and the sportsman takes pleasure not just in dogs, but also breeds Cretan and Spartan bitches,135 should the lover of beauty and humanity be unfair and treat one gender differently, thinking that the difference between loving boys and loving women is just a matter of clothing? And yet, they say beauty is a sign of virtue; it's absurd to claim that women never bloom or show good virtue, for as Æschylus rightly states,

"I can never mistake the burning eye." Of the young woman who has once known a man. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

Shall the indications then of a forward wanton and corrupt 62character be found in the faces of women, and shall there be no gleam of chastity and modesty in their appearance? Nay, there are many such, and shall they not move and provoke love? To doubt it would be neither sensible nor in accordance with the facts, for generally speaking, as has been pointed out, all these attractions are the same in both sexes.... But, Daphnæus, let us combat those views which Zeuxippus lately advanced, making Love to be only irregular desire carrying the soul away to licentiousness, not that this was so much his own view as what he had often heard from morose men who knew nothing of love: some of whom marry unfortunate women for their dowries, and force on them economy and illiberal saving, and quarrel with them every day of their lives: while others, more desirous of children than wives, when they have made those women they come across mothers, bid farewell to marriage, or regard it not at all, and neither care to love nor be loved. Now the fact that the word for conjugal love differs only by one letter from the word for endurance, the one being στέργειν the other στέγειν, seems to emphasize the conjugal kindness mixed by time and intimacy with necessity. But that marriage which Love has inspired will in the first place, as in Plato's Republic, know nothing of Meum and Tuum, for the proverb, 'whatever belongs to a friend is common property,'137 is especially true of married persons who, though disunited in body, are perforce one in soul, neither wishing to be two, nor thinking themselves so. In the second place there will be mutual respect, which is a vital necessity in marriage. For as to that external respect which has in it more of compulsion than choice, being forced by the law and shame and fear,

Shall we then find signs of a forward, reckless, and corrupt 62 character in women's faces, and will there be no hint of purity and modesty in their appearance? No, there are many such women, and shouldn’t they inspire and stir love? To doubt that would be neither sensible nor true, for generally speaking, as has been pointed out, all these attractions are the same in both genders.... But, Daphnæus, let’s challenge the ideas that Zeuxippus recently put forward, suggesting that Love is merely a wild craving leading the soul to indulgence. This wasn't really his own view but rather something he heard from gloomy men who know nothing of love: some of whom marry unfortunate women for their dowries and subject them to frugality and constant bickering; while others, more interested in having children than having wives, after they’ve made women into mothers, abandon marriage or disregard it altogether, caring neither to love nor to be loved. The fact that the term for marital love is only one letter different from the term for endurance—στέργειν versus στέγειν—highlights how conjugal kindness is intertwined over time and intimacy with necessity. Yet marriage inspired by Love will, firstly, as in Plato's Republic, know nothing of Meum and Tuum, since the saying “whatever belongs to a friend is common property”137 holds particularly true for married people who, although separated in body, are essentially one in spirit, neither wanting to be two nor believing they are. Secondly, there will be mutual respect, which is crucial for a successful marriage. As for that external respect—which is often more about compulsion than choice, driven by laws, shame, and fear—

"Those necessary bits and limits to stubborn weeds,"138

that will always exist in wedlock. But in Love there is such self-control and decorum and constancy, that if the god but once enter the soul of a licentious man, he makes him give up all his amours, abates his pride, and breaks down his haughtiness and dissoluteness, putting in their place modesty and silence and tranquillity and decorum, 63and makes him constant to one. You have heard of course of the famous courtesan Lais,139 how she set all Greece on fire with her charms, or rather was contended for by two seas,140 and how, when she fell in love with Hippolochus the Thessalian, 'she left Acro-Corinthus washed by the green sea,'141 and deserted all her other lovers, that great army, and went off to Thessaly and lived faithful to Hippolochus. But the women there, envious and jealous of her for her surpassing beauty, dragged her into the temple of Aphrodite, and there stoned her to death, for which reason probably it is called to this day the temple of Aphrodite the Murderess.142 We have also heard of servant girls who have refused the embraces of their masters, and of private individuals who have scorned an amour with queens, when Love has had dominion in their hearts. For as in Rome, when a dictator is proclaimed, all other magistrates lay down their offices, so those over whom Love is lord are free henceforward from all other lords and masters, and pass the rest of their lives dedicate to the god and slaves in his temple. For a noble woman united by Love to her lawful husband would prefer the embraces of bears and dragons to those of any other man."

that will always exist in marriage. But in Love, there is such self-control, propriety, and loyalty that if the god ever enters the heart of a libertine, he makes him abandon all his affairs, lowers his ego, and breaks down his arrogance and recklessness, replacing them with modesty, silence, calm, and decorum, 63 and makes him devoted to one person. You've heard of the famous courtesan Lais,139 how she captivated all of Greece with her beauty, or rather was sought after by two seas,140 and how, when she fell for Hippolochus the Thessalian, 'she left Acro-Corinthus washed by the green sea,'141 and abandoned all her other lovers, that large crowd, to go to Thessaly and stayed faithful to Hippolochus. But the women there, envious and jealous of her extraordinary beauty, dragged her into the temple of Aphrodite and stoned her to death, which is probably why it is still called the temple of Aphrodite the Murderess.142 We've also heard of maidservants who rejected their masters' advances and everyday people who turned down relationships with queens when Love held sway in their hearts. For just like in Rome, when a dictator is appointed, all other officials resign, so those governed by Love are freed from all other lords and masters and spend the rest of their lives devoted to the god, becoming his servants in his temple. For a noble woman united by Love with her rightful husband would prefer the embraces of bears and dragons to anyone else.

§ xxii. "Although there are plenty of examples of this virtue of constancy, yet to you, that are the festive votaries of the god,143 it will not be amiss to relate the story of the Galatian Camma. She was a woman of most remarkable beauty, and the wife of the tetrarch Sinatus, whom Sinorix, one of the most influential men in Galatia, and desperately in love with Camma, murdered, as he could neither get her by force or persuasion in the lifetime of her husband. And Camma found a refuge and comfort in her grief in discharging the functions of hereditary priestess to Artemis, and most of her time she spent in her temple, 64and, though many kings and potentates wooed her, she refused them all. But when Sinorix boldly proposed marriage to her, she declined not his offer, nor blamed him for what he had done, as though she thought he had only murdered Sinatus out of excessive love for her, and not in sheer villany. He came, therefore, with confidence, and asked her hand, and she met him and greeted him and led him to the altar of the goddess, and pledged him in a cup of poisoned mead, drinking half of it herself and giving him the rest. And when she saw that he had drunk it up, she shouted aloud for joy, and calling upon the name of her dead husband, said, 'Till this day, dearest husband, I have lived, deprived of you, a life of sorrow: but now take me to yourself with joy, for I have avenged you on the worst of men, as glad to share death with him as life with you.' Then Sinorix was removed out of the temple on a litter, and soon after gave up the ghost, and Camma lived the rest of that day and following night, and is said to have died with a good courage and even with gaiety."144

§ xxii. "Although there are many examples of this virtue of constancy, it would be fitting for you, the joyful followers of the god,143 to hear the story of the Galatian Camma. She was an incredibly beautiful woman and the wife of the tetrarch Sinatus. Sinorix, one of the most powerful men in Galatia who was madly in love with Camma, murdered him because he could not win her over by force or persuasion while her husband was alive. Camma found solace in her sorrow by fulfilling her role as the hereditary priestess of Artemis, spending most of her time in her temple. 64 Many kings and rulers pursued her, but she rejected them all. When Sinorix boldly proposed marriage to her, she didn't refuse his offer and didn’t blame him for his actions, as if she believed he only killed Sinatus out of a deep love for her, rather than out of pure malice. He confidently came to ask for her hand, and she welcomed him, greeting him and leading him to the altar of the goddess. She poured poisoned mead into a cup, drank half of it herself, and then handed the rest to him. As soon as she saw that he had finished drinking it, she shouted with joy. Calling on the name of her deceased husband, she said, 'Until now, dearest husband, I have lived a sorrowful life without you: but now, let me join you with joy, for I have avenged you on the worst of men, and I am just as happy to share death with him as I would be to share life with you.' Sinorix was then carried out of the temple on a litter, and shortly after, he passed away. Camma is said to have lived the rest of that day and the following night, dying with courage and even with a sense of joy."144

§ xxiii. "As many similar examples might be adduced, both among ourselves and foreigners, who can feel any patience with those that reproach Aphrodite with hindering friendship when she associates herself with Love as a partner? Whereas any reflecting person would call the love of boys wanton and gross lasciviousness, and say with the poet:

§ xxiii. "There are many similar examples to point to, both among our own people and others, who can tolerate the criticism of Aphrodite for disrupting friendship when she teams up with Love? On the other hand, anyone who thinks critically would label the affection for boys as inappropriate and shameless, echoing the words of the poet:

"This is outrageous, not an act of love."

All willing pathics, therefore, we consider the vilest of mankind, and credit them with neither fidelity, nor modesty, nor friendship, for as Sophocles says:

All willing pathics, therefore, we consider the lowest of mankind, and we trust them with neither loyalty, nor decency, nor friendship, for as Sophocles says:

"Those who lose such friends might actually feel relieved," And those who have these wish they could get rid of them,'145

But as for those who, not being by nature vicious, have been seduced or forced, they are apt all their life to despise and hate their seducers, and when an opportunity has presented itself to take fierce vengeance. As Crateus, who murdered Archelaus, and Pytholaus, who murdered 65Alexander of Pheræ. And Periander, the tyrant of the Ambraciotes, having asked a most insulting question of his minion, was murdered by him, so exasperated was he. But with women and wives all this is the beginning of friendship, and as it were an initiation into the sacred mysteries. And pleasure plays a very small part in this, but the esteem and favour and mutual love and constancy that result from it, proves that the Delphians did not talk nonsense in giving the name of Arma146 to Aphrodite, nor Homer in giving the name of friendship147 to sexual love, and testifies to the fact that Solon was a most experienced legislator in conjugal matters, seeing that he ordered husbands not less than thrice a month to associate with their wives, not for pleasure, but as states at certain intervals renew their treaties with one another, so he wished that by such friendliness marriage should, as it were, be renewed after any intervening tiffs and differences. But you will tell me there is much folly and even madness in the love of women. Is there not more extravagance in the love of boys?

But for those who aren’t naturally cruel and have been seduced or forced, they tend to despise and hate their seducers for the rest of their lives, and when they get the chance, they often seek brutal revenge. Like Crateus, who killed Archelaus, and Pytholaus, who murdered Alexander of Pheræ. And Periander, the tyrant of the Ambraciotes, who was killed by his own assistant after asking a highly insulting question that angered him deeply. But for women and wives, this is just the beginning of friendship, like an initiation into sacred mysteries. Pleasure plays a small role in this, but the respect, favor, love, and loyalty that come from it show that the Delphians weren’t being ridiculous when they named Aphrodite as Arma and that Homer wasn’t wrong in calling sexual love friendship. This reflects that Solon was a wise lawmaker regarding marriage, as he mandated that husbands should connect with their wives at least three times a month, not for pleasure, but to renew their bonds, much like how states periodically reaffirm their treaties. He hoped this would help keep marriages strong after any arguments or disagreements. You might argue that there’s much foolishness and even madness in love for women. But isn’t there even more excess in love for boys?

Seeing my many rivals, I feel weak. The guy is clean-shaven, smooth, soft, and good-looking. Oh, that I could die in his arms, "Make sure to have this fact inscribed on my tomb."

Such extravagant language as this is madness not love. And it is absurd to detract from woman's various excellence. Look at their self-restraint and intelligence, their fidelity and uprightness, and that bravery courage and magnanimity so conspicuous in many! And to say that they have a natural aptitude for all other virtues, but are deficient as regards friendship alone, is monstrous. For they are fond of their children and husbands, and generally speaking the natural affection in them is not only, like a fruitful soil, capable of friendship, but is also accompanied by persuasion and other graces. And as poetry gives to words a kind of relish by melody and metre and rhythm, making instruction thereby more interesting, but what is injurious more insidious, so nature, 66investing woman with beautiful appearance and attractive voice and bewitching figure, does much for a licentious woman in making her wiles more formidable, but makes a modest one more apt thereby to win the goodwill and friendship of her husband. And as Plato advised Xenocrates, a great and noble man in all other respects, but too austere in his temperament, to sacrifice to the Graces, so one might recommend a good and modest woman to sacrifice to Love, that her husband might be a mild and agreeable partner, and not run after any other woman, so as to be compelled to say like the fellow in the comedy, 'What a wretch I am to ill-treat such a woman!' For to love in marriage is far better than to be loved, for it prevents many, nay all, of those offences which spoil and mar marriage.

Such extravagant language as this is madness, not love. It’s absurd to downplay a woman's many strengths. Look at their self-control and intelligence, their loyalty and integrity, and the bravery and generosity evident in so many! To suggest that they have a natural talent for every virtue except friendship is outrageous. They care deeply for their children and husbands, and generally speaking, their natural affection isn’t just like fertile soil, capable of friendship; it also comes with charm and other qualities. Just as poetry enhances words with melody, rhythm, and structure, making lessons more engaging but also disguising harmful ideas, nature, 66gives women beauty, a lovely voice, and a captivating figure, making a seductive woman’s tricks more dangerous, but also making a modest one more likely to gain her husband’s goodwill and friendship. Just as Plato advised Xenocrates—a great and noble man in many respects but too stern in nature—to honor the Graces, one might suggest that a good and modest woman should honor Love so that her husband remains kind and pleasant, and doesn’t chase after other women, ending up lamenting like the character in the play, 'What a fool I am to mistreat such a woman!' For loving in marriage is far better than being loved, as it prevents many—if not all—of the issues that ruin and damage the marriage.

§ xxiv. As to the passionate affection in the early days of marriage,148 my dear Zeuxippus, do not fear that it will leave any sore or irritation, though it is not wonderful that there should be some friction at the commencement of union with a virtuous woman, just as at the grafting of trees, as there is also pain at the beginning of conception, for there can be no complete union without some suffering. Learning puts boys out somewhat when they first go to school, as philosophy does young men at a later day, but the ill effects are not lasting, either in their cases or in the case of lovers. As in the fusion of two liquors, love does indeed at first cause a simmering and commotion, but eventually cools down and settles and becomes tranquil. For the union of lovers is indeed a complete union, whereas the union of those that live together without love resembles only the friction and concussion of Epicurus' atoms in collision and recoil, forming no such union as Love makes, when he presides over the conjugal state. For nothing else produces so much pleasure, or such lasting advantages, or such beautiful remarkable and desirable friendship,

§ xxiv. Regarding the intense affection in the early days of marriage,148 my dear Zeuxippus, don’t worry that it will leave any wounds or irritation. It's not surprising that there might be some friction at the start of a union with a virtuous woman, just as there’s some discomfort at the beginning of conception; complete union inevitably involves some suffering. Learning can be a bit challenging for boys when they first go to school, just as philosophy can unsettle young men later on. However, these negative effects are not lasting, whether for students or lovers. Just like when two liquids are mixed, love might initially create a bit of bubbling and turmoil, but in time it calms down and stabilizes. The union of lovers is truly a complete union, while the connection between those living together without love is more like the collision and rebound of Epicurus’ atoms, lacking the genuine bond that love brings when it governs the marital relationship. Nothing else brings as much pleasure, lasting benefits, or such beautiful, remarkable friendships.

'Just like when a husband and wife live together in one house, Two hearts beating as one. '149

And the law gives its countenance, and nature shows that 67even the gods themselves require love for the production of everything. Thus the poets tell us that 'the earth loves a shower, and heaven loves the earth,' and the natural philosophers tell us that the sun is in love with the moon, and that they are husband and wife, and that the earth is the mother of man and beast and the producer of all plants. Would not the world itself then of necessity come to an end, if the great god Love and the desires implanted by the god should leave matter, and matter should cease to yearn for and pursue its lead? But not to seem to wander too far away and altogether to trifle, you know that many censure boy-loves for their instability, and jeeringly say that that intimacy like an egg is destroyed by a hair,150 for that boy-lovers like Nomads, spending the summer in a blooming and flowery country, at once decamp then as from an enemy's territory. And still more vulgarly Bion the Sophist called the sprouting beards of beautiful boys Harmodiuses and Aristogitons,151 inasmuch as lovers were delivered by them from a pleasant tyranny. But this charge cannot justly be brought against genuine lovers, and it was prettily said by Euripides, as he embraced and kissed handsome Agatho whose beard was just sprouting, that the Autumn of beautiful youths was lovely as well as the Spring. And I maintain that the love of beautiful and chaste wives flourishes not only in old age amid grey hairs and wrinkles, but even in the grave and monument. And while there are few such long unions in the case of boy-loves, one might enumerate ten thousand such instances of the love of women, who have kept their fidelity to the end of their lives. One such case I will relate, which happened in my time in the reign of the Emperor Vespasian.

And the law supports it, and nature shows that 67even the gods themselves need love to create everything. That's why poets say that 'the earth loves a shower, and heaven loves the earth,' and natural philosophers say that the sun is in love with the moon, calling them husband and wife, while the earth is the mother of humans and animals and the source of all plants. Wouldn't the world itself inevitably come to an end if the great god Love and the desires instilled by the god vanished, causing matter to stop yearning for and chasing after its influence? But not to stray too far and trivialize things, you're aware that many criticize boy-loves for their fickleness, mockingly claiming that this intimacy is easily disrupted like an egg by a hair,150 suggesting that boy-lovers are like nomads, spending the summer in a blooming and beautiful land, only to pack up and leave as if escaping from an enemy's territory. Even more crudely, Bion the Sophist referred to the emerging beards of handsome boys as Harmodiuses and Aristogitons,151 since lovers were freed by them from a pleasant tyranny. But this accusation can't justly be made against true lovers, and it was beautifully expressed by Euripides when he embraced and kissed the handsome Agatho, whose beard was just starting to grow, saying that the autumn of beautiful youths is lovely just like the spring. I argue that the love for beautiful and virtuous wives thrives not just in old age with grey hairs and wrinkles, but even in death and memorials. While there may be few enduring connections among boy-loves, one could list countless examples of women's love, who have remained faithful until the end of their lives. I'll share one such example, which took place during my time in the reign of Emperor Vespasian.

§ xxv. Julius, who stirred up a revolt in Galatia, among several other confederates had one Sabinus, a young man of good family, and for wealth and renown the most conspicuous of all the men in those parts. But having attempted 68what was too much for them they were foiled, and expecting to pay the penalty, some committed suicide, others fled and were captured. Now Sabinus himself could easily have got out of the way and made his escape to the barbarians, but he had married a most excellent wife, whose name in that part of the world was Empone, but in Greek would be Herois, and he could neither leave her behind nor take her with him. As he had in the country some underground caves, known only to two of his freedmen, where he used to stow away things, he dismissed all the rest of his slaves, as if he intended to poison himself, and taking with him these two trusty freedmen he descended with them into those underground caves, and sent one of them, Martialis, to tell his wife that he had poisoned himself, and that his body was burnt in the flames of his country-house, for he wanted his wife's genuine sorrow to lend credit to the report of his death. And so it happened. For she, throwing herself on to the ground, groaned and wailed for three days and nights, and took no food. And Sabinus, being informed of this, and fearing that she would die of grief, told Martialis to inform her secretly that he was alive and well and in hiding, and to beg her not to relax her show of grief, but to keep up the farce. And she did so with the genius of a professional actress, but yearning to see her husband she visited him by night, and returned without being noticed, and for six or seven months she lived with him this underground life. And she disguised him by changing his dress, and cutting off his beard, and re-arranging his hair, so that he should not be known, and took him to Rome, having some hopes of obtaining his pardon. But being unsuccessful in this she returned to her own country, and spent most of her time with her husband underground, but from time to time visited the town, and showed herself to some ladies who were her friends and relations. But what is most astonishing of all is that, though she bathed with them, she concealed her pregnancy from them. For the dye which women use to make their hair a golden auburn, has a tendency to produce corpulence and flesh and a full habit, and she rubbed this abundantly over all parts of her body, and so concealed her pregnancy. And she bare the pangs of travail by herself, as a lioness bears her whelps, having hid herself in the cave with her69 husband, and there she gave birth to two boys, one of whom died in Egypt, the other, whose name was Sabinus, was among us only the other day at Delphi. Vespasian eventually put her to death, but paid the penalty for it, his whole progeny in a short time being wiped off the face of the earth.152 For during the whole of his reign he did no more savage act, nor could gods or demons have turned away their eyes from a crueller sight. And yet her courage and bold language abated the pity of the spectators, though it exasperated Vespasian, for, despairing of her safety, she bade them go and tell the Emperor, 'that it was sweeter to live in darkness and underground than to wear his crown.'"153

§ xxv. Julius, who incited a revolt in Galatia, had among his various allies one Sabinus, a young man from a respected family who was well-known for his wealth and fame in that region. However, after trying to push their limits, they were thwarted, and facing the consequences, some chose to take their own lives while others fled and were captured. Now, Sabinus himself could have easily escaped and fled to the barbarians, but he was married to an exceptional wife named Empone in that area, or Herois in Greek, and he couldn’t bear to leave her behind or take her with him. Since he had some hidden caves in the countryside, known only to two of his freedmen, where he used to stash things away, he sent off all of his other slaves as if he planned to poison himself. He took with him these two trusted freedmen and went down into the caves with them, instructing one of them, Martialis, to inform his wife that he had poisoned himself and that his body was burned in the flames of his villa, wanting his wife's genuine sorrow to validate the news of his death. And so it happened. She fell to the ground, grieving and lamenting for three days and nights without eating. Upon hearing this, Sabinus, worried that she might die from grief, told Martialis to secretly let her know that he was alive and well and hiding, and to ask her not to stop showing her sorrow but to keep up the act. She did this with the skill of a seasoned actress, but longing to see her husband, she visited him at night and returned unnoticed, living this underground life with him for six or seven months. She disguised him by changing his clothes, shaving off his beard, and styling his hair differently so that he wouldn’t be recognized, and took him to Rome hoping to secure his pardon. But after failing in this, she returned to her hometown, spending most of her time with her husband underground while occasionally visiting the town to meet with some of her friends and relatives. What’s most remarkable is that, even while bathing with them, she hid her pregnancy. The dye used by women to achieve golden auburn hair tends to add weight and fullness, and she generously applied it all over her body, successfully concealing her pregnancy. She endured the pains of childbirth on her own like a lioness in a den, giving birth to two boys in the cave with her husband; one of whom died in Egypt, while the other, named Sabinus, was just recently seen with us at Delphi. Vespasian eventually had her executed, but he faced the consequences for it, as his entire lineage was quickly eradicated from existence.152 During his entire reign, he committed no other savage act, nor could gods or demons have looked away from a more brutal sight. And yet, her courage and fierce words diminished the audience's sympathy, though they angered Vespasian, as in despair for her safety, she urged them to go and inform the Emperor, "that it was sweeter to live in darkness and underground than to wear his crown."153

§ xxvi. Here my father said that the conversation about Love which took place at Thespiæ ended. And at this moment Diogenes, one of Pisias' companions, was noticed coming up at a faster pace than walking. And while he was yet a little way off, Soclarus hailed him with, "You don't announce war, Diogenes," and he replied, "Hush! it is a marriage; come with me quickly, for the sacrifice only waits for you." All were delighted, and Zeuxippus asked if Pisias was still against the marriage. "As he was first to oppose it," said Diogenes, "so he was first to yield the victory to Ismenodora, and he has now put on a crown and robed himself in white, so as to take his place at the head of the procession to the god through the market-place." "Come," said my father, "in Heaven's name, let us go and laugh at him, and worship the god; for it is clear that the god has taken delight in what has happened, and been propitious."

§ xxvi. At this point, my father mentioned that the conversation about Love that happened at Thespiæ had come to an end. Just then, Diogenes, a friend of Pisias, was seen approaching quickly. While he was still a bit far away, Soclarus called out to him, "You're not here to declare war, Diogenes," to which he replied, "Shh! It's a wedding; come with me quickly, because the sacrifice is only waiting for you." Everyone was excited, and Zeuxippus asked if Pisias was still against the marriage. "As he was the first to oppose it," Diogenes said, "he's now the first to give in to Ismenodora. He's put on a crown and dressed in white to lead the procession to the god through the market." "Come on," my father said, "for heaven's sake, let’s go laugh at him and worship the god; it’s clear the god is pleased with what’s happened and is favorable."

62 The allusion is to Plato's "Phædrus," p. 230, B. Much, indeed, of the subject-matter here is, we shall find, somewhat similar to that of the Phædrus.

62 The reference is to Plato's "Phaedrus," p. 230, B. A lot of the content here is, as we will see, quite similar to that of the Phaedrus.

63 It is difficult to know what the best English word here is. From the sly thrust in § ix. Pisias was evidently grey. I have therefore selected the word gravest. But the most austere, the most sensible, the most solid, the most sedate, all might express the Greek word also. Let the reader take which he likes best.

63 It's hard to figure out the best English word here. From the subtle hint in § ix, Pisias was clearly grey. So, I've chosen the word gravest. However, the most austere, the most sensible, the most solid, and the most sedate could also capture the Greek word. Readers can pick whichever one they prefer.

64 In a Greek house the women and men had each their own separate apartments. This must be borne in mind here to explain the allusion.

64 In a Greek house, women and men each had their own separate living spaces. This is important to remember here to clarify the reference.

65 That is, from interested and selfish motives.

65 In other words, for self-serving and selfish reasons.

66 On Lais and Aristippus see Cicero, "Ad. Fam.," ix. 26.

66 For information on Lais and Aristippus, see Cicero, "Ad. Fam.," ix. 26.

67 Pausanias, i. 19, shows us that there was at Athens a Temple of Hercules called Cynosarges. But the matter is obscure. What the exact allusion is I cannot say.

67 Pausanias, i. 19, tells us that there was a Temple of Hercules in Athens called Cynosarges. However, the details are unclear. I can't say what the exact reference is.

68 Fragment of Æschylus. See Athenæus, xiii. p. 602, E, which explains the otherwise obscure allusion.

68 Fragment of Æschylus. See Athenæus, xiii. p. 602, E, which clarifies the otherwise unclear reference.

69 That is the son of Hera alone, who was unwilling to be outdone by Zeus, who had given birth to Pallas Athene alone. Hesiod has the same view, "Theog." 927.

69 He is the son of Hera alone, who didn’t want to be overshadowed by Zeus, who had given birth to Pallas Athene by himself. Hesiod shares the same perspective, "Theog." 927.

70 ὀπώρα is so used also in Æsch. "Suppl.," 998, 1015. See also "Athenæus," 608, F. Daphnæus implies these very nice gentlemen, like the same class described by Juvenal, "Curios simulant et Bacchanalia vivunt."

70 ὀπώρα is used in Æsch. "Suppl.," 998, 1015. See also "Athenæus," 608, F. Daphnæus refers to these very polite gentlemen, similar to the kind described by Juvenal, "They pretend to be curious and live for the Bacchanalia."

71 I omit καὶ κοπίδας as a gloss or explanation of the old reading μακελεῖα instead of ματρυλεῖα. Nothing can be made of καὶ κοπίδας in the context.

71 I leave out and κοπίδας as a note or clarification of the old version μακελεῖα instead of ματρυλεῖα. There’s no way to interpret καὶ κοπίδας in this context.

72 "Works and Days," 606-608.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Works and Days," 606-608.

73 I follow here the reading of Wyttenbach. Through the whole of this essay the reading is very uncertain frequently. My text in it has been formed from a careful collation of Wyttenbach, Reiske, and Dübner. I mention this here once for all, for it is unnecessary in a translation to minutely specify the various readings on every occasion. I am not editing the "Moralia."

73 I follow Wyttenbach’s version here. Throughout this essay, the text is often quite uncertain. My text has been created from a careful comparison of Wyttenbach, Reiske, and Dübner. I mention this once for clarity, as it's not necessary in a translation to detail every variation each time. I am not editing the "Moralia."

74 "De Œnantha et Agathoclea, v. Polyb. excerpt, l. xv."—Reiske.

74 "On Œnantha and Agathoclea, see Polybius excerpts, book xv."—Reiske.

75 Thespiæ. The allusion is to Phryne. See Pausanias, ix. 27; x. 15.

75 Thespiæ. This refers to Phryne. See Pausanias, ix. 27; x. 15.

76 Reading with Wyttenbach, ὥσπερ δακτύλιον ἰσχνοῦ ὡ μὴ περιῤῥυῇ δεδιώς.

76 Reading with Wyttenbach, just as a thin ring does not flow away in fear.

77 Perhaps cur = coward, was originally cur-tail.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Maybe cur = coward, originally cur-tail.

78 One of the three ports at Athens. See Pausanias, i. 1.

78 One of the three harbors in Athens. See Pausanias, i. 1.

79 Iolaus was the nephew of Hercules, and was associated with him in many of his Labours. See Pausanias, i. 19; vii. 2; viii. 14, 45.

79 Iolaus was Hercules' nephew and accompanied him in many of his tasks. See Pausanias, i. 19; vii. 2; viii. 14, 45.

80 I read συνοαρίζοντας. The general reading συνερῶντας will hardly do here. Wyttenbach suggests συνεαρίζοντας.

80 I read συνοαρίζοντας. The general reading συνερῶντας will hardly work here. Wyttenbach suggests συνεαρίζοντας.

81 What the διβολἰα was is not quite clear. I have supposed a jersey.

81 What the diabolia was is not entirely clear. I have assumed it was a jersey.

82 The women of Lemnos were very masterful. On one memorable occasion they killed all their husbands in one night. Thus the line of Ovid has almost a proverbial force, "Lemniadesque viros nimium quoque vincere norunt."—Heroides, vi. 53. Siebelis in his Preface to Pausanias, p. xxi, gives from an old Scholia a sort of excuse for the action of the women of Lemnos.

82 The women of Lemnos were quite powerful. On one unforgettable night, they killed all their husbands. Therefore, Ovid's line has become almost proverbial: "Lemniadesque viros nimium quoque vincere norunt."—Heroides, vi. 53. Siebelis, in his Preface to Pausanias, p. xxi, provides an old Scholium as a sort of justification for the actions of the women of Lemnos.

83 Probably the epilepsy. See Herodotus, iii. 33.

83 Probably the epilepsy. See Herodotus, iii. 33.

84 Euripides, "Bacchae," 203.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Bacchae," 203.

85 Euripides, Fragment of the "Melanippe."

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, Fragment of "Melanippe."

86 I take Wyttenbach's suggestion as to the reading here.

86 I accept Wyttenbach's recommendation for the reading here.

87 This line is taken bodily by Aristophanes in his "Frogs," 1244.

87 This line is quoted directly by Aristophanes in his "Frogs," 1244.

88 The first line is the first line of a passage from Euripides, consisting of thirteen lines, containing similar sentiments to this. See Athenæus, xiii. p. 599, F. The last two lines are from Euripides, "Hippolytus," 449, 450.

88 The first line is the opening line of a passage from Euripides, made up of thirteen lines that express similar thoughts. Refer to Athenæus, xiii. p. 599, F. The last two lines are from Euripides, "Hippolytus," 449, 450.

89 Compare Lucretius, i. 1-5.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare Lucretius, i. 1-5.

90 Hesiod, "Theogony," 116-120.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hesiod, "Theogony," 116-120.

91 Euripides, "Danae," Frag. Compare Ovid, "Cedit amor rebus: res age, tutus eris."

91 Euripides, "Danae," Frag. Compare Ovid, "Love gives way to circumstances: take action, and you'll be safe."

92 Sophocles, Fragm. 678, Dindorf. Compare a remark of Sophocles, recorded by Cicero, "De Senectute," ch. xiv.

92 Sophocles, Fragm. 678, Dindorf. Compare a comment by Sophocles noted by Cicero in "On Old Age," chapter 14.

93 Sophocles, Fragm. 720. Reading καλὰ with Reiske.

93 Sophocles, Fragm. 720. Reading καλὰ with Reiske.

94 "Iliad," v. 831.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," v. 831.

95 Connecting Ἄρῃς with ἀναιρεῖν.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Connecting Ἄρῃς with ἀναιρεῖν.

96 The Saint Hubert of the Middle Ages.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ The medieval Saint Hubert.

97 Æschylus, Frag. 1911. Dindorf.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Aeschylus, Frag. 1911. Dindorf.

98 Odyssey, v. 69.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Odyssey, v. 69.

99 Fragm. 146, 125.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Frag. 146, 125.

100 Hermes is alluded to.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hermes is mentioned.

101 All these four were titles of Zeus. They are very difficult to put into English so as to convey any distinctive and definite idea to an English reader.

101 All four of these were titles of Zeus. They are quite challenging to translate into English in a way that conveys any clear and specific meaning to an English reader.

102 Enthusiasm is the being ἔνθεος, or inspired by some god.

102 Enthusiasm is being ἔνθεος, or inspired by a god.

103 From Æschylus, "Supplices," 681, 682.

103 From Aeschylus, "The Suppliants," 681, 682.

104 "Iliad," vii. 121, 122.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," vii. 121, 122.

105 Like the character described in Lucretius, ii. 1-6.

105 Similar to the character mentioned in Lucretius, ii. 1-6.

106 Sophocles, "Trachiniae," 497. The Cyprian Queen is, of course, Aphrodite.

106 Sophocles, "Trachiniae," 497. The Queen of Cyprus is, of course, Aphrodite.

107 Hence the famous Proverb, "Non omnibus dormio." See Cic. "Ad. Fam." vii. 24.

107 Hence the famous saying, "Not everyone sleeps." See Cic. "Ad. Fam." vii. 24.

108 Above, in § xiii.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Above, in § xiii.

109 See Sophocles, "Antigone," 783, 784. And compare Horace, "Odes," Book iv. Ode xiii. 6-8, "Ille virentis et Doctæ psallere Chiæ Pulchris excubat in genis."

109 See Sophocles, "Antigone," 783, 784. And check out Horace, "Odes," Book iv. Ode xiii. 6-8, "Ille virentis et Doctæ psallere Chiæ Pulchris excubat in genis."

110 The "Niobe," which exists only in a few fragments.

110 The "Niobe," which only survives in a few fragments.

111 This was the name of Dionysius' Poem. He was a Corinthian poet.

111 This was the name of Dionysius' poem. He was a poet from Corinth.

112 "Iliad," xiii. 131.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 13.131.

113 Reading according to the conjecture of Wyttenbach, ὡς τὸν Ἔρωτα υὁνον ἀήττητον ὄντα τῶν στρατηγῶν.

113 Reading according to Wyttenbach's theory, as the undefeated love of the leaders.

114 Something has probably dropped out here, as Dübner suspects.

114 Something likely got missed here, as Dübner thinks.

115 Fragment from the "Sthenebœa" of Euripides.

115 Fragment from the "Sthenebœa" of Euripides.

116 Anytus was one of the accusers of Socrates, and so one of the causers of his death. So Horace calls Socrates "Anyti reum," "Sat." ii. 4, 3.

116 Anytus was one of the people who accused Socrates, and thus one of the reasons for his death. Horace refers to Socrates as "Anyti reum," "Sat." ii. 4, 3.

117 Homeric Epigrammata, xiii. 5. Quoted also in "On Virtue and Vice," § I.

117 Homeric Epigrams, xiii. 5. Also quoted in "On Virtue and Vice," § I.

118 Odyssey, xix. 40.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Odyssey, 19.40.

119 I adopt the suggestion of Wyttenbach, εἶπεν ῶ Δαφναῖε.

119 I take on Wyttenbach's suggestion, he said, O Daphnaeus.

120 Pinder, "Pyth." i. 8.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Pinder, "Pyth." 1.8.

121 See for example Homer, "Iliad," xi. 3, 73; ix. 502.

121 See for example Homer, "Iliad," xi. 3, 73; ix. 502.

122 Euripides, "Pirithous," Fragm. 591. Dindorf.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Pirithous," Fragm. 591. Dindorf.

123 An allusion to Homer, "Odyssey," xii. 453.

123 A reference to Homer, "Odyssey," xii. 453.

124 So Terence, "Andria," 555. "Amantium iræ amoris integratiost."

124 So Terence, "Andria," 555. "The anger of lovers is the result of their love."

125 Euripides, "Hippolytus," 194-196.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Hippolytus," 194-196.

126 The lines are from Alcæus. Thus Love was the child of the Rainbow and the West Wind. A pretty conceit.

126 The lines are from Alcæus. So, Love was the child of the Rainbow and the West Wind. A nice idea.

127 Greek iris.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Greek iris.

128 The mirrors of the ancients were of course not like our mirrors. They were only burnished bronze. Hence the view in them would be at best somewhat obscure. This explains 1 Cor. xiii. 12; 2 Cor. iii. 18; James i. 23.

128 The mirrors of ancient times were definitely not like our mirrors today. They were just polished bronze. So, the reflection seen in them was at best somewhat unclear. This is explained in 1 Cor. xiii. 12; 2 Cor. iii. 18; James i. 23.

129 See Euripides, "Hippolytus," 7, 8.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Euripides, "Hippolytus," 7, 8.

130 Here the story unfortunately ends, and for all time we shall know no more of it. Reiske somewhat forcibly says, "Vel lippus videat Gorgus historiam non esse finitam, et multa, ut et alias, periisse."

130 Here the story unfortunately ends, and we will never know more about it. Reiske bluntly states, "Well, let anyone see that the history of Gorgus is not finished, and that much, as before, has been lost."

131 Like Reiske we condense here a little.

131 Like Reiske, we're summarizing a bit here.

132 Reading with Reiske ὀρθῆς και ἀθρύπτου.

132 Reading with Reiske correct and undivided.

133 I read εἰ γἁρ.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ I read if indeed.

134 See "Iliad," xxiii. 295. Podargus was an entire horse.

134 See "Iliad," xxiii. 295. Podargus was a complete horse.

135 See Ovid, "Metamorph." iii. 206-208.

135 Check out Ovid, "Metamorph." iii. 206-208.

136 Æschylus, "Toxotides," Fragm. 224.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Aeschylus, "Toxotides," Fragm. 224.

137 A very favourite proverb among the ancients. See Plat. "Phaedr." fin. Martial, ii. 43.

137 A very popular saying among the ancients. See Plat. "Phaedr." fin. Martial, ii. 43.

138 Soph. Fragm. 712.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Soph. Fragm. 712.

139 On Lais, see Pausanias, ii. 2. Her Thessalian lover is there called Hippostratus. Her favours were so costly that the famous proverb is said to owe its origin to her, "Non cuivis homini contingit adire Corinthum."

139 For more about Lais, check out Pausanias, ii. 2. In that account, her Thessalian lover is referred to as Hippostratus. Her favors were so expensive that the well-known saying, "Not everyone has the chance to go to Corinth," is believed to have originated from her.

140 The Ægean and Ionian. Cf. Horace, "Odes," i. 7, 2.

140 The Aegean and Ionian. See Horace, "Odes," i. 7, 2.

141 On Acro-Corinthus, see Pausanias, ii. 4. The words in inverted commas are from Euripides, Fragm. 921.

141 On Acro-Corinthus, refer to Pausanias, ii. 4. The phrases in quotation marks are from Euripides, Fragm. 921.

142 On Lais generally, and her end, see Athenæus, xiii. 54, 55.

142 For details about Lais in general and her fate, refer to Athenæus, xiii. 54, 55.

143 See § I. The Festival of Love was being kept at this very time.

143 See § I. The Festival of Love was happening right now.

144 This story is also told by Plutarch, "De Mulierum Virtutibus," § xx.

144 This story is also recounted by Plutarch in "On the Virtues of Women," § xx.

145 Sophocles, Fragm. 741. Quoted again in "On Abundance of Friends," § iii.

145 Sophocles, Fragm. 741. Quoted again in "On Abundance of Friends," § iii.

146 A Delphic word for love. Can it be connected with ἅρμα?

146 A Delphic word for love. Can it be linked to ἅρμα?

147 Very frequent in Homer, e.g., "Iliad," ii. 232; vi, 165; xiii. 636: xiv. 353, etc.

147 Very common in Homer, e.g., "Iliad," ii. 232; vi, 165; xiii. 636: xiv. 353, etc.

148 See Lucretius, iv. 1105-1114. I tone down the original here a little.

148 See Lucretius, iv. 1105-1114. I’ve softened the original a bit here.

149 Homer, "Odyssey," vi. 183, 184. Cf. Eurip. "Medea," 14, 15.

149 Homer, "Odyssey," vi. 183, 184. See also Euripides, "Medea," 14, 15.

150 This means when the moustache and beard and whiskers begin to grow.

150 This means when the mustache, beard, and whiskers start to grow.

151 The whole story about Harmodius and Aristogiton and how they killed Hipparchus is told by Thucydides, vi. 54-59. Bion therefore practically called these sprouting beards tyrant-killers, tyrannicides.

151 The entire story about Harmodius and Aristogiton and how they killed Hipparchus is recounted by Thucydides, vi. 54-59. Bion therefore essentially referred to these budding beards as tyrant-killers, tyrannicides.

152 "Scriptus igitur hic libellus est post caedem Domitiani."—Reiske.

152 "So, this little book was written after the assassination of Domitian."—Reiske.

153 Vespasian certainly was not cruel generally. "Non temere quis punitus insons reperietur, nisi absente eo et ignaro aut certe invito atque decepto..... Sola est, in qua merito culpetur, pecuniæ cupiditas."—Suetonius, "Divus Vespasianus," 15, 16.

153 Vespasian wasn’t generally cruel. "You will rarely find an innocent person punished unless it’s done without their knowledge or approval, or if they’ve been tricked... The only thing for which he justifiably deserves blame is the greed for money."—Suetonius, "Divus Vespasianus," 15, 16.


CONJUGAL PRECEPTS.

PLUTARCH SENDS GREETING TO POLLIANUS AND EURYDICE.

After the customary marriage rites, by which, the Priestess of Demeter has united you together, I think that to make an appropriate discourse, and one that will chime in with the occasion, will be useful to you and agreeable to the law. For in music one of the tunes played on the flute is called Hippothorus,154 which is a tune that excites fierce desire in stallions to cover mares; and though in philosophy there are many goodly subjects, yet is there none more worthy of attention than that of marriage, on which subject philosophy spreads a charm over those who are to pass life together, and makes them gentle and mild to one another. I send therefore as a gift to both of you a summary of what you have often heard, as you are both well versed in philosophy, arranging my matter in a series of short observations that it may be the more easily remembered, and I pray that the Muses will assist and co-operate with Aphrodite, so that no lyre or lute could be more harmonious or in tune than your married life, as the result of philosophy and concord. And thus the ancients set up near Aphrodite statues of Hermes, to show that conversation was one of the great charms of marriage, and also statues of Peitho155 and the Graces, to teach married people to gain their way with one another by persuasion, and not by wrangling or contention.

After the traditional wedding rituals that united you by the Priestess of Demeter, I believe it would be beneficial for you and in line with the occasion to make an appropriate speech. In music, there's a flute tune called Hippothorus, which stirs fiery passion in stallions towards mares; similarly, in philosophy, while there are many valuable topics, none is more deserving of our focus than marriage. This subject enchants those who are about to share their lives, encouraging them to be kind and gentle with each other. So, I present to both of you a summary of what you have often heard, as you are well-versed in philosophy, laid out in a series of brief points for easier recall. I hope that the Muses will lend their support alongside Aphrodite, so that no lyre or lute could create a more harmonious tune than your life together, shaped by philosophy and unity. In this way, the ancients created statues of Hermes near Aphrodite to signify that conversation is one of the essential joys of marriage, alongside statues of Peitho and the Graces, teaching married couples to win each other over with persuasion rather than arguments or disputes.

§ i. Solon bade the bride eat a quince the first night of marriage, intimating thereby, it seems, that the bridegroom, was to expect his first pleasure from the bride's mouth and conversation.

§ i. Solon advised the bride to eat a quince on her wedding night, suggesting that the groom was to look forward to his first enjoyment from the bride's words and conversation.

§ ii. In Bœotia they dress up the bride with a chaplet 71of asparagus, for as the asparagus gives most excellent fruit from a thorny stalk, so the bride, by not being too reluctant and coy in the first approaches, will make the married state more agreeable and pleasant. But those husbands who cannot put up with the early peevishness of their brides, are not a whit wiser than those persons who pluck unripe grapes and leave the ripe grapes for others.156 On the other hand, many brides, being at first disgusted with their husbands, are like those that stand the bee's sting but neglect the honey.

§ ii. In Bœotia, they adorn the bride with a crown 71 of asparagus, because just like asparagus produces great fruit from a thorny stalk, the bride, by not being too hesitant and shy at first, will make married life more enjoyable and pleasant. However, husbands who can't handle their brides' early irritability are no wiser than those who pick unripe grapes and leave the ripe ones for others.156 On the flip side, many brides, initially put off by their husbands, are like those who endure a bee's sting but overlook the honey.

§ iii. Married people should especially at the outset beware of the first quarrel and collision, observing that vessels when first fabricated are easily broken up into their component parts, but in process of time, getting compact and firmly welded together, are proof against either fire or steel.

§ iii. Married people should, especially at the beginning, be cautious of the first argument or conflict, noting that when vessels are first made, they can be easily broken apart, but over time, as they become more solid and tightly bonded, they can withstand fire or steel.

§ iv. As fire gets kindled easily in chaff or in a wick or in the fur of hares, but is easily extinguished again, if it find no material to keep it in and feed it, so we must not consider that the love of newly-married people, that blazes out so fiercely in consequence of the attractions of youth and beauty, will be durable and lasting, unless it be fixed in the character, and occupy the mind, and make a living impression.157

§ iv. Just like fire easily ignites in dry grass, a candlewick, or even in a hare’s fur, but can quickly die out without something to keep it going, we shouldn't assume that the intense love of newlyweds, sparked by the allure of youth and beauty, will last. It needs to be rooted in their character, occupy their thoughts, and create a lasting impression.157

§ v. As catching fish by drugged bait is easy, but makes the fish poor to eat and insipid, so those wives that lay traps for their husbands by philtres and charms, and become their masters by pleasure, have stupid senseless and spoiled husbands to live with. For those that were bewitched by Circe did her no good, nor could she make any use of them when they were turned into swine and asses, but she was greatly in love with the prudent Odysseus who dwelt with her sensibly.

§ v. Just like catching fish with drugged bait is easy but results in tasteless and unappetizing fish, wives who trap their husbands with love potions and charms, and dominate them through pleasure, end up with foolish, dull, and spoiled husbands. Those who were enchanted by Circe brought her no benefit, nor could she do anything useful with them once they were turned into pigs and donkeys; instead, she was deeply in love with the wise Odysseus, who stayed with her in a sensible way.

§ vi. Those women who would rather lord it over fools than obey sensible men, resemble those people who would rather lead the blind on a road, and not people who have eyesight and know how to follow.

§ vi. Those women who would rather boss around fools than listen to sensible men are like those people who prefer to guide the blind along a path instead of following those who can see and know how to lead.

§ vii. Women disbelieve that Pasiphäe, a king's wife, 72was enamoured of a bull, although they see some of their sex despising grave and sober men, and preferring to associate with men who are the slaves of intemperance and pleasure, and like dogs and he-goats.

§ vii. Women can't believe that Pasiphäe, a king's wife, 72was in love with a bull, even though they notice some women look down on serious and respectable men, choosing instead to hang out with men who are caught up in indulgence and pleasure, like dogs and he-goats.

§ viii. Men who through weakness or effeminacy cannot vault upon their horses' backs, teach them to kneel and so receive their riders. Similarly, some men that marry noble or rich wives, instead of making themselves better humble their wives, thinking to rule them easier by lowering them. But one ought to govern with an eye to the merit of a woman, as much as to the size of a horse.

§ viii. Men who are too weak or effeminate to mount their horses teach them to kneel so riders can get on. In the same way, some men who marry wealthy or noble wives end up making their wives feel inferior, believing it's easier to control them by putting them down. However, one should lead with respect for a woman's worth, just like one would consider the strength of a horse.

§ ix. We see that the moon when it is far from the sun is bright and glorious, but pales and hides its light when it is near. A modest wife on the contrary ought to be seen chiefly with her husband, and to stay at home and in retirement in his absence.

§ ix. We notice that the moon, when it's far from the sun, shines bright and beautifully, but loses its light and dims when it's close. A modest wife, on the other hand, should primarily be seen with her husband and stay at home in seclusion when he is not around.

§ x. It is not a true observation of Herodotus, that a woman puts off her modesty with her shift.158 On the contrary, the modest woman puts on her modesty instead, and great modesty is a sign of great conjugal love.

§ x. It's not accurate to say, as Herodotus did, that a woman sheds her modesty along with her nightgown.158 In fact, a modest woman embraces her modesty more, and a high level of modesty signifies a deep love for her partner.

§ xi. As where two voices are in unison the loudest prevails; so in a well-managed household everything is done by mutual consent, but the husband's supremacy is exhibited, and his wishes are consulted.

§ xi. Just like when two voices sing together, the louder one wins; in a well-run household, everything is decided by agreement, but the husband’s authority is clear, and his preferences are taken into account.

§ xii. The Sun beat the North Wind.159 For when it blew a strong and terrible blast, and tried to make the man remove his cloak, he only drew it round him more closely, but when the Sun came out with its warm rays, at first warmed and afterwards scorched, he stripped himself of coat as well as cloak. Most woman act similarly: if their husbands try to curtail by force their luxury and extravagance, they are vexed and fight for their rights, but if they are convinced by reason, they quietly drop their expensive habits, and keep within bounds.

§ xii. The Sun defeated the North Wind.159 When the wind howled fiercely and attempted to force the man to take off his cloak, he just pulled it tighter around himself. But when the Sun emerged with its warm rays, initially warming him and then becoming scorching, he removed both his coat and cloak. Most women behave similarly: when their husbands try to restrict their luxury and extravagance by force, they get frustrated and stand their ground, but when they are persuaded with reason, they easily let go of their expensive habits and stay within limits.

§ xiii. Cato turned out of the Senate a man who kissed his own wife in the presence of his daughter. This was perhaps too strong a step, but if it is unseemly, as indeed it is, for husband and wife in the presence of others to fondle 73and kiss and embrace one another, is it not far more unseemly in the presence of others to quarrel and jangle? Just as conjugal caresses and endearments ought to be private, so ought admonition and scolding and plain speaking.

§ xiii. Cato expelled a man from the Senate for kissing his own wife in front of their daughter. This might have been too harsh, but if it's inappropriate, which it is, for a husband and wife to be affectionate in front of others, isn't it even more inappropriate to argue and bicker in public? Just as love and affection between spouses should be kept private, so should criticism and scolding and straightforward talk.

§ xiv. Just as there is little use in a mirror adorned with gold or precious stones, unless it conveys a true likeness, so there is no advantage in a rich wife, unless she conforms her life and habits to her husband's position. For if when a man is joyful the mirror makes him look sad, and when he is put out and sad it makes him look gay and smiling from ear to ear, the mirror is plainly faulty. So the wife is faulty and devoid of tact, who frowns when her husband is in the vein for mirth and jollity, and who jokes and laughs when he is serious: the former conduct is disagreeable, the latter contemptuous.160 And, just as geometricians say lines and surfaces do not move of themselves, but only in connection with bodies, so the wife ought to have no private emotions of her own, but share in her husband's gravity or mirth, anxiety or gaiety.

§ xiv. Just like there's not much value in a mirror that's decorated with gold or gemstones unless it reflects a true image, a wealthy wife is of no real benefit unless she adjusts her life and habits to match her husband's status. If a man is happy but the mirror makes him appear sad, or if he is upset and the mirror shows him smiling brightly, then the mirror is clearly flawed. Similarly, a wife who frowns when her husband is happy and playful, or who jokes and laughs when he is serious, is lacking in consideration; the former behavior is unpleasant, while the latter is disrespectful.160 Moreover, just as mathematicians say that lines and surfaces don't move on their own but rather in relation to objects, a wife should not have her own private feelings but instead partake in her husband’s somberness or joy, worries or happiness.

§ xv. As those husbands who do not like to see their wives eating and drinking in their company only teach them to take their food on the sly, so those husbands who are not gay and jolly with their wives, and never joke or smile with them, only teach them to seek their pleasures out of their company.

§ xv. Just like husbands who don't want to see their wives eating and drinking with them only encourage them to sneak their meals, husbands who aren't cheerful and playful with their wives, and never joke or smile with them, only push them to find their happiness outside the marriage.

§ xvi. The kings of Persia have their wedded wives at their side at banquets and entertainments; but when they have a mind for a drunken debauch they send them away,161 and call for singing-girls and concubines, rightly so doing, for so they do not mix up their wives with licentiousness and drunkenness. Similarly, if a private individual, lustful and dissolute, goes astray with a courtesan or maid-servant, the wife should not be vexed or impatient, but consider that it is out of respect to her that he bestows upon another all his wanton depravity.

§ xvi. The kings of Persia have their wives with them at parties and events; but when they want to indulge in a wild night of drinking, they send their wives away,161 and call for entertainers and mistresses, which makes sense, as it keeps their wives away from debauchery and drunkenness. Similarly, if a man, driven by lust and excess, goes off with a prostitute or maid, his wife shouldn't feel angry or annoyed, but should understand that he is showing her respect by directing all his inappropriate desires towards someone else.

74§ xvii. As kings make162 if fond of music many musicians, if lovers of learning many men of letters, and many athletes if fond of gymnastics, so the man who has an eye for female charms teaches his wife to dress well, the man of pleasure teaches his meretricious tricks and wantonness, while the true gentleman makes his virtuous and decorous.

74§ xvii. Just as kings surround themselves with many musicians if they love music, and scholars gather many writers if they cherish learning, while athletes enjoy the company of many gymnasts, the man who appreciates female beauty advises his wife on fashion, the hedonist shares his tricks and indulgences, but a true gentleman cultivates her virtue and grace.

§ xviii. A Lacedæmonian maiden, when someone asked her if she had yet had dealings with a man, replied, "No, but he has with me." This methinks is the line of conduct a matron should pursue, neither to decline the embraces of a husband when he takes the initiative, nor to provoke them herself, for the one is forward and savours of the courtesan, the other is haughty and unnatural.

§ xviii. A Spartan girl, when someone asked her if she had ever been with a man, replied, "No, but he has been with me." I think this is how a woman should act: not to refuse her husband's advances when he makes the first move, nor to seek them out herself, because the former is too bold and has the feel of a prostitute, while the latter is arrogant and not natural.

§ xix. The wife ought not to have her own private friends, but cultivate only those of the husband. Now the gods are our first and greatest friends, so the wife ought only to worship and recognize her husband's gods, and the door ought to be shut on all superfluous worship and strange superstitions, for none of the gods are pleased with stealthy and secret sacrifices on the part of a wife.

§ xix. A wife shouldn’t have her own separate friends but should instead focus on those of her husband. The gods are our first and most important friends, so a wife should only honor and acknowledge her husband’s gods. The door should be closed to any unnecessary worship and unfamiliar superstitions, as no gods are happy with secret and hidden sacrifices made by a wife.

§ xx. Plato says that is a happy and fortunate state, where the words Meum and Tuum are least heard,163 because the citizens regard the common interest in all matters of importance. Far more essential is it in marriage that the words should have no place. For, as the doctors say, that blows on the left shoulders are also felt on the right,164 so is it good165 for husband and wife to mutually sympathize with one another, that, just as the strength of ropes comes from the twining and interlacing of fibres together, so the marriage knot may be confirmed and strengthened by the interchange of mutual affection and kindness. Nature itself teaches this by the birth of children, which are so much a joint result, that neither husband nor wife can dis75criminate or discern which part of the child is theirs. So, too, it is well for married persons to have one purse, and to throw all their property into one common stock, that here also there may be no Meum and Tuum. And just as we call the mixture of water and wine by the name of wine, even though the water should preponderate,166 so we say that the house and property belongs to the man, even though the wife contribute most of the money.

§ xx. Plato states that a happy and fortunate condition exists where the words Mine and Yours are rarely spoken,163 because the citizens prioritize the common good in all important matters. It's even more crucial in marriage for these words to be absent. As doctors suggest, blows to the left shoulder are also felt on the right,164 similarly, it's beneficial for husband and wife to empathize with one another. Just like the strength of ropes comes from the twisting and intertwining of fibers, the marriage bond is strengthened through mutual affection and kindness. Nature itself proves this through the creation of children, which are such a joint result that neither husband nor wife can discern which part of the child belongs to whom. Likewise, it is advisable for married couples to have a shared purse and combine all their assets into a common pool, ensuring there are no Mine and Yours here as well. Just as we refer to the mixture of water and wine as wine, even if water makes up the majority,166 we say that the house and property belong to the man, even if the wife contributes most of the money.

§ xxi. Helen was fond of wealth, Paris of pleasure, whereas Odysseus was prudent, Penelope chaste. So the marriage of the last two was happy and enviable, while that of the former two brought an Iliad of woe on Greeks and barbarians alike.

§ xxi. Helen loved luxury, Paris loved fun, while Odysseus was wise and Penelope was faithful. So, the marriage of the last two was happy and admired, while the union of the first two led to a tragic war for both Greeks and non-Greeks alike.

§ xxii. The Roman who was taken to task by his friends for repudiating a chaste wealthy and handsome wife, showed them his shoe and said, "Although this is new and handsome, none of you know where it pinches me."167 A wife ought not therefore to put her trust in her dowry, or family, or beauty, but in matters that more vitally concern her husband, namely, in her disposition and companionableness and complaisance with him, not to make every-day life vexatious or annoying, but harmonious and cheerful and agreeable. For as doctors are more afraid of fevers that are generated from uncertain causes, and from a complication of ailments, than of those that have a clear and adequate cause, so the small and continual and daily matters of offence between husband and wife, that the world knows nothing about, set the household most at variance, and do it the greatest injury.

§ xxii. The Roman who got called out by his friends for rejecting a pure, wealthy, and attractive wife showed them his shoe and said, "Even though this is new and nice-looking, none of you know where it pinches me."167 A wife shouldn't rely solely on her dowry, family, or looks, but on qualities that truly matter to her husband—like her attitude, being a good companion, and being accommodating, so daily life isn't frustrating or annoying, but instead harmonious, cheerful, and pleasant. Just as doctors worry more about fevers that come from uncertain causes and a mix of problems than those with clear, straightforward reasons, the small, constant annoyances between husband and wife that nobody else sees cause the most conflict in a household and do the greatest harm.

§ xxiii. King Philip was desperately enamoured of a Thessalian woman,168 who was accused of bewitching him; his wife Olympias therefore wished to get this woman into her power. But when she came before her, and was 76evidently very handsome, and talked to her in a noble and sensible manner, Olympias said, "Farewell to calumny! Your charms lie in yourself."169 So invincible are the charms of a lawful wife to win her husband's affection by her virtuous character, bringing to him in herself dowry, and family, and philtres, and even Aphrodite's cestus.170

§ xxiii. King Philip was deeply in love with a woman from Thessaly,168 who was rumored to have enchanted him; his wife Olympias wanted to gain control over this woman. However, when she met her, she found her to be very attractive and engaging in a refined and intelligent way. Olympias remarked, "Forget the gossip! Your beauty comes from within."169 The allure of a virtuous wife is so strong that it can secure her husband's love through her character, bringing him not just her dowry and family, but also enchantments and even the magic of Aphrodite’s girdle.170

§ xxiv. Olympias, on another occasion, when a young courtier had married a wife who was very handsome, but whose reputation was not very good, remarked, "This fellow has no sense, or he would not have married with his eyes." We ought neither to marry with our eyes, nor with our fingers, as some do, who reckon up on their fingers what dowry the wife will bring, not what sort of partner she will make.

§ xxiv. Olympias, at another time, commented that when a young courtier married a very attractive woman with a questionable reputation, she said, "This guy has no sense, or he wouldn’t have married without thinking." We shouldn’t marry based purely on looks or money, like some do, who count on their fingers the dowry the wife will bring instead of considering what kind of partner she will be.

§ xxv. It was advice of Socrates, that when young men looked at themselves in the mirror, those who were not handsome should become so through virtue, and those who were so should not by vice deform their beauty. Good also is it for the matron, when she has the mirror in her hands, if not handsome to say to herself, "What should I be, if I were not virtuous?" and if handsome to say to herself, "How good it were to add virtue to beauty!" for it is a feather in the cap of a woman not handsome to be loved for herself and not for good looks.

§ xxv. Socrates advised that when young men look at themselves in the mirror, those who aren't good-looking should strive to be so through their character, while those who are good-looking shouldn't spoil their beauty with bad behavior. It's also wise for a woman, when she has a mirror in her hands, to consider, if she doesn’t find herself attractive, "What would I be if I weren’t virtuous?" and if she does see beauty in herself, to think, "How wonderful it would be to add virtue to my looks!" It’s a point of pride for a woman who isn't traditionally attractive to be loved for who she is, not just for her appearance.

§ xxvi. Dionysius, the tyrant of Sicily, sent some costly dresses and necklaces to the daughters of Lysander, but he would not receive them, and said, "These presents will bring my daughters more shame than adornment." And Sophocles said still earlier than Lysander, "Your madness of mind will not appear handsome, wretch, but most unhandsome." For, as Crates says, "that is adornment which adorns," and that adorns a woman that makes her more comely; and it is not gold or diamonds or scarlet robes that make her so, but her dignity, her correct conduct, and her modesty.

§ xxvi. Dionysius, the tyrant of Sicily, sent expensive dresses and necklaces to Lysander's daughters, but he refused to accept them and said, "These gifts will bring my daughters more shame than beauty." And Sophocles said even before Lysander, "Your insanity will not make you look good, you miserable one, but rather very unappealing." As Crates puts it, "True adornment enhances," and what truly enhances a woman is what makes her more beautiful; it's not gold, diamonds, or fancy robes that do that, but her dignity, proper behavior, and modesty.

§ xxvii. Those who sacrifice to Hera as goddess of 77marriage,171 do not burn the gall with the other parts of the victim, but when they have drawn it throw it away beside the altar: the lawgiver thus hinting that gall and rage have no place in marriage. For the austerity of a matron should be, like that of wine, wholesome and pleasant, not bitter as aloes, or like a drug.

§ xxvii. Those who make offerings to Hera, the goddess of 77marriage,171 do not burn the gall along with the other parts of the sacrificial animal. Instead, they set it aside next to the altar. This practice suggests that bitterness and anger have no place in marriage. The seriousness of a married woman should be like good wine—wholesome and enjoyable, not bitter like aloe or harsh like a medicine.

§ xxviii. Plato advised Xenocrates, a man rather austere but in all other respects a fine fellow, to sacrifice to the Graces. I think also that a chaste wife needs the graces with her husband that, as Metrodorus said, "she may live agreeably with him, and not be bad-tempered because she is chaste." For neither should the frugal wife neglect neatness, nor the virtuous one neglect to make herself attractive, for peevishness makes a wife's good conduct disagreeable, as untidiness makes one disgusted with simplicity.

§ xxviii. Plato advised Xenocrates, a rather serious man but a good person in every other way, to make offerings to the Graces. I believe that a chaste wife also needs to be gracious with her husband so that, as Metrodorus said, "she can live harmoniously with him and not become irritable just because she is chaste." A practical wife shouldn't overlook cleanliness, nor should a virtuous one ignore her appearance, as irritability can make a wife's good behavior unpleasant, just as messiness can turn one off from simplicity.

§ xxix. The wife who is afraid to laugh and jest with her husband, lest she should appear bold and wanton, resembles one that will not anoint herself with oil lest she should be thought to use cosmetics, and will not wash her face lest she should be thought to paint. We see also in the case of those poets and orators, that avoid a popular illiberal and affected style, that they artificially endeavour to move and sway their audience by the facts, and by a skilful arrangement of them, and by their gestures. Consequently a matron will do well to avoid and repudiate over-preciseness meretriciousness and pomposity, and to use tact in her dealings with her husband in every-day life, accustoming him to a combination of pleasure and decorum. But if a wife be by nature austere and apathetic, and no lover of pleasure, the husband must make the best of it, for, as Phocion said, when Antipater enjoined on him an action neither honourable nor becoming, "You cannot have me as a friend and flatterer both," so he must say to himself about his strict and austere wife, "I cannot have in the same woman wife and mistress."

§ xxix. A wife who is afraid to laugh and joke with her husband, worried she might seem bold or inappropriate, is like someone who won't apply oil to their skin because they're afraid of being seen as someone who wears makeup, and won't wash their face because they might look like they’re putting on paint. We also see poets and speakers who avoid a common, shallow, and affected style; they try hard to connect with their audience through facts, how they present them, and their body language. So, a wife should avoid being overly precise, flashy, or pompous, and instead handle her relationship with her husband with care, mixing enjoyment with respect in everyday life. However, if a wife is naturally stern and disinterested in pleasure, the husband has to make the best of it, because, as Phocion said when Antipater asked him to do something dishonorable, "You can't have me both as a friend and a flatterer." He must remind himself that he can't have both a wife and a mistress in the same person.

§ xxx. It was a custom among the Egyptian ladies not to wear shoes, that they might stay at home all day and not go abroad. But most of our women will only stay at 78home if you strip them of their golden shoes, and bracelets, and shoe-buckles, and purple robes, and pearls.

§ xxx. Egyptian women traditionally didn't wear shoes so they could stay home all day and not go out. However, most of our women will only stay at 78home if you take away their golden shoes, bracelets, shoe buckles, purple robes, and pearls.

§ xxxi. Theano, as she was putting on her shawl, displayed her arm, and somebody observing, "What a handsome arm!" she replied, "But not common." So ought not even the speech, any more than the arm, of a chaste woman, to be common, for speech must be considered as it were the exposing of the mind, especially in the presence of strangers. For in words are seen the state of mind and character and disposition of the speaker.

§ xxxi. Theano, while putting on her shawl, showed her arm, and someone remarked, "What a beautiful arm!" She replied, "But it’s not ordinary." Likewise, the words of a modest woman should not be ordinary either, as speech reveals the mind, especially around strangers. Words reflect the speaker's thoughts, character, and temperament.

§ xxxii. Phidias made a statue of Aphrodite at Elis, with one foot on a tortoise,172 as a symbol that women should stay at home and be silent. For the wife ought only to speak either to her husband, or by her husband, not being vexed if, like a flute-player, she speaks more decorously by another mouth-piece.

§ xxxii. Phidias created a statue of Aphrodite in Elis, with one foot on a tortoise,172 symbolizing that women should remain at home and keep quiet. A wife should only speak to her husband or through him, not getting upset if, like a flute player, she communicates more appropriately through someone else's voice.

§ xxxiii. When rich men and kings honour philosophers, they really pay homage to themselves as well; but when philosophers pay court to the rich, they lower themselves without advancing their patrons. The same is the case with women. If they submit themselves to their husbands they receive praise, but if they desire to rule, they get less credit even than the husbands who submit to their rule. But the husband ought to rule his wife, not as a master does a chattel, but as the soul governs the body, by sympathy and goodwill. As he ought to govern the body by not being a slave to its pleasures and desires, so he ought to rule his wife by cheerfulness and complaisance.

§ xxxiii. When wealthy people and kings honor philosophers, they are really honoring themselves too; but when philosophers seek favor from the wealthy, they diminish themselves without helping their benefactors. The same applies to women. If they submit to their husbands, they receive praise, but if they try to take control, they get even less respect than the husbands who submit to them. However, a husband should lead his wife not like a master with a possession, but like the soul leads the body, with empathy and goodwill. Just as he should manage the body by not being a slave to its pleasures and desires, he should lead his wife with cheerfulness and kindness.

§ xxxiv. The philosophers tell us that some bodies are composed of distinct parts, as a fleet or army; others of connected parts, as a house or ship; others united and growing together, as every animal is. The marriage of lovers is like this last class, that of those who marry for dowry or children is like the second class, and that of those who only sleep together is like the first class, who may be said to live in the same house, but in no other sense to live together. But, just as doctors tell us that liquids are the only things that thoroughly mix, so in married people there must be a complete union of bodies, wealth, friends, 79and relations. And thus the Roman legislator forbade married people to exchange presents with one another, not that they should not go shares with one another, but that they should consider everything as common property.

§ xxxiv. Philosophers explain that some groups are made up of separate parts, like a fleet or an army; others are made of connected parts, like a house or a ship; and some are united and grow together, like all animals do. The marriage of lovers falls into the last category, while those who marry for wealth or children are more like the second category. People who merely sleep together fit into the first category—they might live in the same house but don’t truly live together in any other sense. Just as doctors say that liquids are the only substances that mix completely, there must also be a full union of bodies, wealth, friends, 79, and family among married couples. This is why Roman lawmakers prohibited married couples from giving gifts to each other—not to stop them from sharing with one another, but to encourage them to view everything as shared property.

§ xxxv. At Leptis, a town in Libya, it is the custom for the bride the day after marriage to send to her mother-in-law's house for a pipkin, who does not lend her one, but says she has not got one, that from the first the daughter-in-law may know her mother-in-law's stepmotherly mind,173 that if afterwards she should be harsher still, she should be prepared for it and not take it ill. Knowing this the wife ought to guard against any cause of offence, for the bridegroom's mother is jealous of his affection to his wife. But there is one cure for this condition of mind, to conciliate privately the husband's affection, and not to divert or diminish his love for his mother.

§ xxxv. In Leptis, a town in Libya, it's customary for the bride, the day after her wedding, to send someone to her mother-in-law's house asking for a small cooking pot. The mother-in-law refuses to lend her one, claiming she doesn't have any. This signals to the daughter-in-law the mother-in-law's unkind intentions, so that if the mother-in-law behaves even more harshly later, the bride is prepared and won't take it to heart. Understanding this, the wife should avoid any actions that might offend her because the groom's mother is envious of his affection for his wife. However, there is a way to address this situation: she should privately nurture her husband's love while ensuring that it doesn't decrease or interfere with his love for his mother.

§ xxxvi. Mothers seem to love their sons best as able to help them, and fathers their daughters as needing their help; perhaps also it is in compliment to one another, that each prefers the other sex in their children, and openly favours it. This, however, is a matter perhaps of little importance. But it looks very nice in the wife to show greater respect to her husband's parents than to her own, and if anything unpleasant has happened to confide it to them rather than to her own people. For trust begets trust,174 and love love.

§ xxxvi. Mothers seem to love their sons more when they can help them, and fathers love their daughters more when they need their help; maybe it's also a way to compliment each other, with parents favoring the opposite sex in their children. This might not be that significant. However, it looks good for a wife to show more respect for her husband’s parents than her own, and if something unpleasant happens, she tends to confide in them rather than her own family. After all, trust breeds trust,174 and love breeds love.

§ xxxvii. The generals of the Greeks in Cyrus's army ordered their men to receive the enemy silently if they came up shouting, but if they came up silently to rush out to meet them with a shout. So sensible wives, in their husband's tantrums, are quiet when they storm, but if they are silent and sullen talk them round and appease them.

§ xxxvii. The Greek generals in Cyrus's army instructed their soldiers to stay silent if the enemy approached shouting, but to rush out and shout back if the enemy came quietly. Similarly, wise wives remain calm during their husbands' outbursts but know how to talk to them and calm them down when they're silent and downcast.

§ xxxviii. Rightly does Euripides175 censure those who introduce the lyre at wine-parties, for music ought to be 80called in to assuage anger and grief, rather than to enervate the voluptuous still more than before. Think, therefore, those in error who sleep together for pleasure, but when they have any little difference with one another sleep apart, and do not then more than at any other time invoke Aphrodite, who is the best physician in such cases, as the poet, I ween, teaches us, where he introduces Hera, saying:

§ xxxviii. Euripides rightly criticizes those who bring the lyre to wine parties because music should be called upon to soothe anger and sadness, not to further weaken the already indulgent atmosphere. So, consider those who are mistaken—couples who share a bed for pleasure but choose to sleep apart during small disagreements, and at those times fail to call upon Aphrodite, who is the best healer in such situations, as the poet suggests when he features Hera saying:

"I will now put an end to their prolonged conflict," "I will send them to the bed of love." __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

§ xxxix. Everywhere and at all times should husband and wife avoid giving one another cause of offence, but most especially when they are in bed together. The woman who was in labour and had a bad time said to those that urged her to go to bed, "How shall the bed cure me, which was the very cause of this trouble?"177 And those differences and quarrels which the bed generates will not easily be put an end to at any other time or place.

§ xxxix. Couples should always avoid upsetting each other, especially when they're in bed together. The woman in labor who was struggling replied to those who encouraged her to lie down, "How can the bed help me when it was the reason for my pain?"177 The disagreements and arguments that happen in bed are hard to resolve at any other time or place.

§ xl. Hermione seems to speak the truth where she says:

§ xl. Hermione seems to be honest when she says:

"The visits from troublesome women messed me up."178

But this case does not happen naturally, but only when dissension and jealousy has made wives open not only their doors but their ears to such women. But that is the very time when a sensible wife will shut her ears more than at any other time, and be especially on her guard against whisperers, that fire may not be added to fire,179 and remember the remark of Philip, who, when his friends tried to excite him against the Greeks, on the ground that they were treated well and yet reviled him, answered, "What will they do then, if I treat them ill?" Whenever, then, calumniating women come and say to a wife, "How badly your husband treats you, though a chaste and loving wife!" let her answer, "How would he act then, if I were to begin to hate him and injure him?"

But this situation doesn’t happen on its own; it only arises when conflict and jealousy cause wives to open their doors and ears to such women. However, that's precisely when a wise wife should shut her ears more than ever and stay on guard against gossipers, so that the flames of discord don’t get any higher,179 and remember Philip's saying. When his friends tried to stir him up against the Greeks for treating him well yet speaking ill of him, he replied, "What will they do then, if I treat them badly?" So when slandering women come to a wife and say, "Your husband treats you so badly, even though you’re a faithful and loving wife!" she should respond, "How would he behave if I were to start hating him and causing him harm?"

§ xli. The master who saw his runaway slave a long 81time after he had run away, and chased him, and came up with him just as he had got to the mill, said to him, "In what more appropriate place could I have wished to find you?"180 So let the wife, who is jealous of her husband, and on the point of writing a bill of divorce in her anger, say to herself, "In what state would my rival be better pleased to see me in than this, vexed and at variance with my husband, and on the point of abandoning his house and bed?"

§ the. The master who spotted his runaway slave a long 81 time after he had escaped, chased him down, and caught up with him right as he reached the mill, said to him, "Is there a more fitting place I could have found you?"180 Similarly, let the wife who is jealous of her husband and on the verge of writing a divorce notice in her anger think to herself, "What state would my rival find more satisfying than this, upset and in conflict with my husband and about to leave his home and bed?"

§ xlii. The Athenians have three sacred seedtimes: the first at Scirus, as a remembrance of the original sowing of corn, the second at Rharia, the third under Pelis, which is called Buzygium.181 But a more sacred seedtime than all these is the procreation of children, and therefore Sophocles did well to call Aphrodite "fruitful Cytherea." Wherefore it behoves both husband and wife to be most careful over this business, and to abstain from lawless and unholy breaches of the marriage vow, and from sowing in quarters where they desire no produce, or where, if any produce should come, they would be ashamed of it and desire to conceal it.182

§ xlii. The Athenians have three sacred planting times: the first at Scirus, as a reminder of the original sowing of grain, the second at Rharia, and the third under Pelis, which is called Buzygium.181 However, a more significant planting time than all these is the creation of children, which is why Sophocles aptly referred to Aphrodite as "fruitful Cytherea." Therefore, both husband and wife should be very attentive to this matter and should avoid unlawful and immoral violations of their marriage vows, as well as refraining from planting in places where they do not intend to see any results, or where, if any results do arise, they would feel ashamed and want to hide them.182

§ xliii. When Gorgias the Rhetorician recited his speech at Olympia recommending harmony to the Greeks, Melanthius cried out, "He recommend harmony to us! Why, he can't persuade his wife and maid to live in harmony, though there are only three of them in the house!" Gorgias belike had an intrigue with the maid, and his wife was jealous. He then must have his own house in good order who undertakes to order the affairs of his friends and the public, for any ill-doings on the part of husbands to their wives is far more likely to come out and be known to the public than the ill-doings of wives to their husbands.

§ xliii. When Gorgias the Rhetorician gave his speech at Olympia urging the Greeks to embrace harmony, Melanthius shouted, "He wants us to be harmonious! Why, he can't even get his wife and maid to get along, and there are only three of them in the house!" It seems Gorgias might have been involved with the maid, and his wife was jealous. Anyone who wants to manage the affairs of friends and the public must keep their own house in order, because any wrongdoing by husbands towards their wives is more likely to become public knowledge than the wrongdoings of wives towards their husbands.

§ xliv. They say the cat is driven mad by the smell of perfumes. If it happens that wives are equally affected 82by perfumes, it is monstrous that their husbands should not abstain from using perfumes, rather than for so small a pleasure to incommode so grievously their wives. And since they suffer quite as much when their husbands go with other women, it is unjust for a small pleasure to pain and grieve wives, and not to abstain from connection with other women, when even bee-keepers will do as much, because bees are supposed to dislike and sting those that have had dealings with women.

§ xliv. They say cats go crazy from the smell of perfumes. If wives are similarly affected 82 by perfumes, it’s ridiculous that their husbands don’t stop using them, choosing such a minor pleasure over the discomfort it causes their wives. And since they suffer just as much when their husbands are with other women, it’s unfair for a small pleasure to cause pain and distress for wives, while not avoiding relationships with other women, especially when even beekeepers take precautions, since bees are thought to dislike and sting those who’ve been involved with women.

§ xlv. Those that approach elephants do not dress in white, nor those that approach bulls in red, for these colours render those animals savage; and tigers they say at the beating of drums go quite wild, and tear themselves in their rage. Similarly, as some men cannot bear to see scarlet and purple dresses, and others are put out by cymbals and drums,183 what harm would it do wives to abstain from these things, and not to vex or provoke husbands, but to live with them quietly and meekly?

§ xlv. Those who get close to elephants don't wear white, and those who approach bulls don't wear red, because these colors can make the animals aggressive. It's said that tigers go completely wild when they hear drums and hurt themselves in their fury. Likewise, since some men can't stand seeing red or purple clothing, and others get irritated by cymbals and drums,183 what damage would it cause for wives to avoid these things, not to annoy or provoke their husbands, but to live with them calmly and gently?

§ xlvi. A woman said to Philip, who against her will was pulling her about, "Let me go, all women are alike when the lamp is put out."184 A good remark to adulterers and debauchees. But the married woman ought to show when the light is put out that she is not like all other women, for then, when her body is not visible, she ought to exhibit her chastity and modesty as well as her personal affection to her husband.

§ xlvi. A woman said to Philip, who was pulling her around against her will, "Let me go; all women are the same when the lights are off."184 It's a good point for those who cheat and indulge. But a married woman should prove that she’s different when it’s dark because, when her body isn’t visible, she should still show her purity and modesty, as well as her love for her husband.

§ xlvii. Plato185 recommended old men to act with decorum especially before young men, that they too might show respect to them; for where the old behave shamelessly, no modesty or reverence will be exhibited by the young. The husband ought to remember this, and show no one more respect than his wife, knowing that the bridal chamber will be to her either a school of virtue or of vice. And he who enjoys pleasures that he forbids his wife, is like a man that orders his wife to go on fighting against an enemy to whom he has himself surrendered.

§ xlvii. Plato185 advised older men to behave with dignity, especially in front of younger men, so that the young would also show them respect. When older people act without shame, the young will lack modesty and respect in return. A husband should keep this in mind and show his wife the utmost respect, understanding that their shared space can either be a place for virtue or for vice. A man who enjoys pleasures that he prohibits his wife from experiencing is like someone who tells his wife to keep fighting an enemy he has already surrendered to.

§ xlviii. As to love of show, Eurydice, read and try to 83remember what was written by Timoxena to Aristylla: and do you, Pollianus, not suppose that your wife will abstain from extravagance and expense, if she sees that you do not despise such vanities in others, but delight in gilt cups, and pictures in houses, and trappings for mules, and ornaments for horses. For it is not possible to banish extravagance from the women's side of the house if it is always to be seen in the men's apartments. Moreover, Pollianus, as you are already old enough for the study of philosophy, adorn your character by its teaching, whether it consists of demonstration or constructive reasoning, by associating and conversing with those that can profit you. And for your wife gather honey from every quarter, as the bees do, and whatever knowledge you have yourself acquired impart to her, and converse with her, making the best arguments well known and familiar to her. For now

§ xlviii. Regarding the love of show, Eurydice, read and try to 83 remember what Timoxena wrote to Aristylla: and Pollianus, don’t think that your wife will avoid extravagance and spending if she sees you not shunning such vanities in others, but enjoying fancy cups, art in your home, fancy gear for mules, and decorations for horses. It's impossible to eliminate extravagance from the women's side of the house if it’s always visible in the men’s quarters. Furthermore, Pollianus, since you’re old enough to study philosophy, better your character through its teachings, whether through logic or constructive reasoning, by surrounding yourself with and talking to those who can help you grow. And for your wife, gather knowledge from everywhere, like bees do, and share whatever you’ve learned with her, engaging in conversations that make solid arguments familiar to her. For now

"Father, you are to her, and mother dear, And brother too. 186

And no less decorous is it to hear the wife say, "Husband, you are my teacher and philosopher and guide in the most beautiful and divine subjects." For such teaching in the first place detaches women from absurdities: for the woman who has learnt geometry will be ashamed to dance, nor will she believe in incantations and spells, if she has been charmed by the discourses of Plato and Xenophon; and if anyone should undertake to draw the moon down from the sky, she will laugh at the ignorance and stupidity of women that credit such nonsense, well understanding geometry, and having heard how Aglaonice, the daughter of the Thessalian Hegetor, having a thorough knowledge of the eclipses of the moon, and being aware beforehand of the exact time when the moon would be in eclipse, cheated the women, and persuaded them that she herself had drawn it down from the sky. For no woman was ever yet credited with having had a child without intercourse with a man, for those shapeless embryos and gobbets of flesh that take form from corruption are called moles. We must guard against such false conceptions as these arising in the minds 84of women, for if they are not well informed by good precepts, and share in the teaching that men get, they generate among themselves many foolish and absurd ideas and states of mind. But do you, Eurydice, study to make yourself acquainted with the sayings of wise and good women, and ever have on your tongue those sentiments which as a girl you learnt with us, that so you may make your husband's heart glad, and be admired by all other women, being in yourself so wonderfully and splendidly adorned. For one cannot take or put on, except at great expense, the jewels of this or that rich woman, or the silk dresses of this or that foreign woman, but the virtues that adorned Theano,187 and Cleobuline, and Gorgo the wife of Leonidas, and Timoclea the sister of Theagenes, and the ancient Claudia,188 and Cornelia the sister of Scipio,189 and all other such noble and famous women, these one may array oneself in without money and without price, and so adorned lead a happy and famous life. For if Sappho plumed herself so much on the beauty of her lyrical poetry as to write to a certain rich woman, "You shall lie down in your tomb, nor shall there be any remembrance of you, for you have no part in the roses of Pieria," how shall you not have a greater right to plume yourself on having a part not in the roses but in the fruits which the Muses bring, and which they freely bestow on those that admire learning and philosophy?190

And it's equally fitting to hear a wife say, "Husband, you're my teacher, my philosopher, and my guide in the most beautiful and divine matters." This kind of education first helps women move away from foolishness; a woman who learns geometry won't feel embarrassed to dance, nor will she believe in magic and spells if she's been captivated by the teachings of Plato and Xenophon. If someone tries to pull the moon down from the sky, she'll laugh at the ignorance of women who buy into such nonsense, clearly understanding geometry and knowing how Aglaonice, the daughter of the Thessalian Hegetor, with her deep knowledge of lunar eclipses, tricked other women into thinking she had drawn it down herself. No woman has ever been believed to have a child without having been with a man; those distorted embryos and bits of flesh that come from decay are called moles. We must be cautious of such false beliefs forming in the minds of women, for if they aren’t well educated and lack the guidance that men receive, they will generate foolish and absurd ideas. But you, Eurydice, should strive to learn from the wise and good women, and always keep in mind the principles you learned as a girl with us, so you can bring joy to your husband's heart and be admired by all other women, as you are wonderfully and splendidly adorned. For one cannot easily acquire the jewels of a rich woman or the silk dresses of a foreign lady without great expense, but the virtues that adorned Theano, Cleobuline, Gorgo the wife of Leonidas, Timoclea the sister of Theagenes, ancient Claudia, Cornelia the sister of Scipio, and all such noble and famous women, can be embraced without cost, allowing one to lead a joyful and renowned life. If Sappho took such pride in the beauty of her lyrical poetry that she wrote to a wealthy woman, "You will lie down in your tomb, and there will be no memory of you, for you have no share in the roses of Pieria," how much more right do you have to take pride in having a share, not just in roses but in the fruits the Muses provide, which they generously bestow on those who appreciate learning and philosophy?

154 This tune is again alluded to by Plutarch in "Quæstion. Convival"., p. 704, F. See also Clemens Alexandrinus, "Pædagog." ii. p. 164, Α ταῐς δὲ ἵπποις μιγνυμέναις οἷον ὑμέναιος ἐπαυλεῖται νόμος αὐλωδιας ἱππόθορον τοῦτον κεκληκασιν οἱ Μουσικοί.

154 This tune is mentioned again by Plutarch in "Questions at the Dinner Table", p. 704, F. See also Clement of Alexandria, "The Instructor," ii. p. 164, “And among the horses mixed as if it were a hymn, the law of the aulodia that modern musicians have called this.”

155 Peitho means Persuasion, and is represented as one of the Graces by Hermes anax. See Pausanias, ix. 35.

155 Peitho means Persuasion and is depicted as one of the Graces by Hermes, the lord. See Pausanias, ix. 35.

156 Compare the Proverb Εικελὸς ὀμφακίζεται, and Tibullus, iii. 5, 19: "Quid fraudare juvat vitem crescentibus uvis?"

156 Compare the Proverb Εικελὸς ὀμφακίζεται, and Tibullus, iii. 5, 19: "What good is it to trick the vine when the grapes are growing?"

157 Cf. Shakspere, "Romeo and Juliet," A. ii. Sc. vi. 9-15.

157 See Shakespeare, "Romeo and Juliet," Act II, Scene vi, lines 9-15.

158 Herodotus, i. 8.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Herodotus, i. 8.

159 An allusion to the well-known Fable of Æsop, No. 82 in Halm's edition.

159 A reference to the famous Fable of Aesop, No. 82 in Halm's edition.

160 This comparison of the mirror is beautifully used by Keble in his "Christian Year:"

160 Keble makes a beautiful comparison of the mirror in his "Christian Year:"

"With no hope left on earth to find" "A reflection in a responsive mind." Wednesday before Easter.

161 Does this throw light on Esther, i. 10-12?

161 Does this clarify Esther, i. 10-12?

162 By their patronage.

By their support.

163 "Republic," v. p. 462, C.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Republic," vol. p. 462, C.

164 By the power of sympathy. This is especially true of eyes. Wyttenbach compares the Epigram in the Anthology, i. 46. 9. Καὶ γὰρ δέξιον ὄμμα κακούμενον ὄμματι λαίῳ Πολλάκι τοῦς ἰδίους ἀντιδίδωσι πόνους.

164 Through the power of empathy. This is particularly true of the eyes. Wyttenbach refers to the Epigram in the Anthology, i. 46. 9. For a right eye, when it suffers from a wicked gaze, often shares its pains with its own.

165 Reading καλον with Hercher.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading with Hercher.

166 The ancients hardly ever drank wine neat. Hence the allusion. The symposiarch, or arbiter bibendi, settled the proportions to be used.

166 The ancients rarely consumed wine straight. That's why it's mentioned. The symposiarch, or the person in charge of the drinking, determined the ratios to be used.

167 Compare the French proverb, "Le beau soulier blesse souvent le pied."

167 Compare the French proverb, "A pretty shoe often hurts the foot."

168 Thessaly was considered by the ancients famous for enchantments and spells. So Juvenal, vi. 610, speaks of "Thessala philtia," and see Horace, "Odes," i. 27. 21, 22; "Epodes," v. 45.

168 Thessaly was known in ancient times for its magic and spells. In Juvenal, vi. 610, he refers to "Thessala philtia," and check out Horace, "Odes," i. 27. 21, 22; "Epodes," v. 45.

169 Wyttenbach well compares the lines of Menander:—

169 Wyttenbach accurately compares the lines of Menander:—

true potion grateful way, τούτῳ κατακρατεῖν ἀνδρὸς εἴωθεν γυνή.

170 An allusion to Homer, "Iliad," xiv. 214-217.

170 A reference to Homer, "Iliad," xiv. 214-217.

171 Called by the Romans "pronuba Juno." See Verg. "Æneid," iv. 166; Ovid, "Heroides," vi. 43.

171 Known to the Romans as "pronuba Juno." See Verg. "Æneid," iv. 166; Ovid, "Heroides," vi. 43.

172 See Pausanias, vi. 25. The statue was made of ivory and gold.

172 See Pausanias, vi. 25. The statue was crafted from ivory and gold.

173 Compare Terence, "Hecyra," 201. "Uno animo omnes socrus oderunt nurus." As to stepmotherly feelings, the "injusta noverca" has passed into a proverb with all nations. See for example Hesiod, "Works and Days," 823, ἄλλοτε μητρυιὴ πἐλει ἡμἐρη, ἄλλοτε μήτηρ.

173 Compare Terence, "Hecyra," 201. "All mothers-in-law universally dislike their daughters-in-law." Regarding stepmotherly feelings, the phrase "unjust stepmother" has become a proverb in many cultures. For instance, see Hesiod, "Works and Days," 823, sometimes a stepmother is like a mother, at other times just a mother.

174 Wyttenbach compares Seneca's "Fidelem si putaveris facies." "Ep." iii. p. 6.

174 Wyttenbach compares Seneca's "If you think, you'll create a loyal friend." "Ep." iii. p. 6.

175 Euripides, "Medea," 190-198.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Medea," 190-198.

176 Homer, "Iliad," xiv. 205, 209.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 14.205, 14.209.

177 See Mulier Parturiens, Phaedrus' "Fables," i. 18.

177 See Mulier Parturiens, Phaedrus' "Fables," i. 18.

178 Euripides, "Andromache," 930.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Andromache," 930.

179 Proverb. Cf. Horace, "Oleum adde camino," ii. "Sat." iii. 321.

179 Proverb. See Horace, "Add oil to the fire," ii. "Sat." iii. 321.

180 See Æsop's Fables, No. 121. Halme. Δραπέτης is the title. All readers of Plautus and Terence know what a bugbear to slaves the threat of being sent to the mill was. They would have to turn it instead of horses, or other cattle.

180 See Æsop's Fables, No. 121. Halme. The title is Escapee. All readers of Plautus and Terence know how terrifying the threat of being sent to the mill was for slaves. They would have to turn it instead of horses or other livestock.

181 That is, Yoking oxen for the plough.

181 That is, Pairing oxen for the plow.

182 Procreation of children was among the ancients frequently called Ploughing and Sowing. Hence the allusions in this paragraph. So, too, Shakspere, "Measure for Measure," Act i. Sc. iv. 41-44.

182 In ancient times, having children was often referred to as Ploughing and Sowing. This is why there are references in this paragraph. Similarly, Shakespeare uses this in "Measure for Measure," Act i. Sc. iv. 41-44.

183 The reference is to the rites of Cybele. See Lucretius, ii. 618.

183 The reference is to the rituals of Cybele. See Lucretius, ii. 618.

184 See Erasmus, "Adagia." The French proverb is "La nuit tous les chats sont gris."

184 See Erasmus, "Adagia." The French saying is "At night, all cats are gray."

185 "Laws," p. 729, C.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Laws," p. 729, C.

186 From the words of Andromache to Hector, "Iliad," vi. 429, 430.

186 From Andromache's words to Hector, "Iliad," vi. 429, 430.

187 Theano was the wife of Pythagoras.

187 Theano was the wife of Pythagoras.

188 See Livy, xxix. 14. Propertius, v. 11. 51, 52. Ovid, "Fasti," iv. 305 sq.

188 See Livy, xxix. 14. Propertius, v. 11. 51, 52. Ovid, "Fasti," iv. 305 sq.

189 And mother of the Gracchi.

189 And the mother of the Gracchi.

190 Jeremy Taylor, in his beautiful sermon on "The Marriage Ring," has borrowed not a few hints from this treatise of Plutarch, as usual investing with a new beauty whatever he borrows, from whatever source. He had the classics at his fingers' end, and much of his unique charm he owes to them. But he read them as a philosopher, and not as a grammarian.

190 Jeremy Taylor, in his inspiring sermon on "The Marriage Ring," has taken several ideas from this essay by Plutarch, always giving a fresh beauty to whatever he borrows, no matter the source. He was well-versed in the classics, and he owes much of his distinctive charm to them. However, he approached them as a philosopher, not just as a grammarian.


CONSOLATORY LETTER TO HIS WIFE.

§ i. Plutarch to his wife sends greeting. The messenger that you sent to me to announce the death of our little girl seems to have missed his way en route for Athens; but when I got to Tanagra I heard the news from my niece. I suppose the funeral has already taken place, and I hope everything went off so as to give you least sorrow both now and hereafter. But if you left undone anything you wished to do, waiting for my opinion, and thinking your grief would then be lighter, be it without ceremoniousness or superstition, both which things are indeed foreign to your character.

§ i. Plutarch sends greetings to his wife. The messenger you sent to tell me about our little girl's death seems to have gotten lost on the way to Athens; however, when I arrived in Tanagra, I heard the news from my niece. I assume the funeral has already happened, and I hope everything went well to minimize your sadness both now and in the future. But if there was anything you wanted to do and held off waiting for my opinion, thinking it would make your grief easier, do it without any formality or superstition, as those things are really not like you.

§ ii. Only, my dear wife, let us both be patient at this calamity. I know and can see very clearly how great it is, but should I find your grief too excessive, it would trouble me even more than the event itself. And yet I have not a heart hard as heart of oak or flintstone, as you yourself know very well, who have shared with me in the bringing up of so many children, as they have all been educated at home by ourselves. And this one I know was more especially beloved by you, as she was the first daughter after four sons, when you longed for a daughter, and so I gave her your name.191 And as you are very fond of children your grief must have a peculiar bitterness when you call to mind her pure and simple gaiety, which was without a tincture of passion or querulousness. For she had from nature a wonderful contentedness of mind and meekness, and her affectionateness and winning ways not only pleased one but also afforded a means of observing her kindliness of heart, for she used to bid her nurse192 give the teat not only to other children but even to her favourite playthings, and so invited them as it were to her table in kindliness of heart, and gave them a share of her good things, and provided the best entertainment for those that pleased her.

§ ii. My dear wife, let’s both try to stay calm during this tough time. I see how serious it is, but if your sadness overwhelms you, it will trouble me even more than what’s happened. And although you know I’m not heartless, having raised so many children with you who were all educated at home, I understand how much this one meant to you, especially since she was the first daughter after four sons, when you wished for a girl. That’s why I gave her your name.191 Since you love children so much, your sorrow must be especially deep when you think of her innocent joy, which was free from any anger or complaints. She naturally had a wonderful contentment and gentleness, and her affection and charm not only pleased us but also showed her kindness. She would ask her nurse192 to let her play with not just other kids but her favorite toys too, inviting them to her little gatherings and sharing her treats, making sure to entertain those she liked best.

§ iii. But I see no reason, my dear wife, why these and similar traits in her character, that gave us delight in her lifetime,86 should now, when recalled to the memory, grieve and trouble us. Though, on the other hand, I fear that if we cease to grieve we may also cease to remember her, like Clymene, who says in the Play193

§ iii. But I don’t see why, my dear wife, the traits in her character that brought us joy when she was alive,86 should now cause us sadness when we think of them. However, I worry that if we stop grieving, we might also stop remembering her, like Clymene, who says in the Play193

"I dislike the flexible curve of cornel-wood," And would quit athletics,"

because she ever avoided and trembled at anything that reminded her of her son, for it brought grief with it, and it is natural to avoid everything that gives us pain. But as she gave us the greatest pleasure in embracing her and even in seeing and hearing her, so ought her memory living and dwelling with us to give us more, aye, many times more, joy than grief, since those arguments that we have often used to others ought to be profitable to us in the present conjuncture, nor should we sit down and rail against fortune, opposing to those joys many more griefs.

because she always avoided and felt uneasy around anything that reminded her of her son, since it brought her sorrow, and it's natural to steer clear of things that cause us pain. But just as we found immense joy in hugging her and even in simply seeing and hearing her, her memory should bring us even more, yes, many times more, happiness than sadness, since the reasons we've often shared with others should benefit us now. We shouldn't just sit back and complain about our fate, letting our sorrows overshadow the joys we have.

§ iv. Those who were present at the funeral tell me with evident surprise that you put on no mourning, and that you bedizened up neither yourself nor your maids with the trappings of woe, and that there was no ostentatious expenditure of money at the funeral, but that everything was done orderly and silently in the presence of our relations. I am not myself surprised that you, who never made a display either at the theatre or on any other public occasion, and thought extravagance useless even in the case of pleasure, should have been frugal in your grief. For not only ought the chaste woman to remain uncorrupt in Bacchanalian revels,194 but she ought to consider her self-control not a whit less necessary in the surges of sorrow and emotion of grief, contending not (as most people think) against natural affection, but against the extravagant wishes of the soul. For we are indulgent to natural affection in the regret, and honour, and memory that it pays to the dead: but the insatiable desire for a passionate display of funeral grief, coming to the climax in coronachs and beatings of the breast, is not less unseemly than intemperance in 87pleasure and is unreasonably195 forgiven only because pain and grief instead of delight are elements in the unseemly exhibition. For what is more unreasonable than to curtail excessive laughter or any other demonstration of joy, and to allow a free vent to copious lamentation and wailing that come from the same source? And how unreasonable is it, as some husbands do, to quarrel with their wives about perfume and purple robes, while they allow them to shear their heads in mourning, and to dress in black, and to sit in idle grief, and to lie down in weariness! And what is worst of all, how unreasonable is it for husbands to interfere if their wives chastise the domestics and maids immoderately or without sufficient cause, yet allow them to ill-treat themselves cruelly in cases and conjunctures that require repose and kindness!

§ iv. Those who attended the funeral tell me with clear surprise that you didn’t wear any mourning clothes, and that you didn’t deck yourself or your maids in signs of sorrow. They say there was no extravagant spending at the funeral; everything was done quietly and orderly in front of our relatives. I’m not surprised, considering you’ve never been one to make a show at the theater or in public, and you think waste is pointless even during happy times, so it makes sense you would be reserved in your grief. A modest woman should remain unaffected by wild celebrations, but she should also see her self-discipline as just as necessary in moments of sorrow and emotional turmoil, not battling against natural feelings as most people think, but against the excessive desires of the heart. We tend to be lenient with natural feelings in the regret, honor, and memories we offer to the deceased; however, the endless craving for a dramatic display of mourning, reaching its peak in wailing and beating of the breast, is just as inappropriate as excessiveness in enjoyment, and it is unreasonably excused only because the emotions involved are pain and grief rather than joy. What is more unreasonable than to suppress excessive laughter or any joyful expression while allowing an outpouring of excessive lamentation and wailing from the same emotional source? And how absurd is it, as some husbands do, to argue with their wives about perfume and fancy clothing while permitting them to shave their heads in mourning, wear black, sit in idle sadness, and lie down in exhaustion? And worst of all, how unreasonable is it for husbands to step in when their wives punish the servants and maids excessively or without good reason, yet let them mistreat themselves harshly in situations that call for rest and compassion!

§ v. But between us, my dear wife, there never was any occasion for such a contest, nor do I think there ever will be. For as to your economy in dress and simple way of living, there is no philosopher with whom you are acquainted whom you did not amaze, nor is there any citizen who has not observed196 how plainly you dressed at sacred rites, and sacrifices, and theatres. You have also already on similar painful occasions exhibited great fortitude, as when you lost your eldest son, and again when our handsome Chæron died. For when I was informed of his death, I well remember some guests from the sea were coming home with me to my house as well as some others, but when they saw the great quiet and tranquillity of the household, they thought, as they afterwards told some other people, that no such disaster had really happened, but that the news was untrue. So well had you ordered everything in the house, at a time when there would have been great excuse for disorder. And yet you had suckled that son, though your breast had had to be lanced owing to a contusion. This was noble conduct and showed your great natural affection.

§ v. But honestly, my dear wife, there was never a reason for such a competition, nor do I think there ever will be. Your frugality in dress and simple lifestyle have amazed every philosopher you know, and every citizen has noticed how plainly you dressed at sacred rites, sacrifices, and theater events. You have shown remarkable strength in difficult times, like when you lost our eldest son, and again when our handsome Chæron passed away. I remember when I was told about his death; some guests returning from the sea were coming to my house, and when they saw the calm and peaceful atmosphere there, they thought— as they later shared with others— that the disaster couldn’t be true. You managed everything in the house so well, even when it would have been completely understandable to be in chaos. And yet, you nursed that son even after your breast had to be lanced because of an injury. That was a noble thing to do and showed your deep natural love.

§ vi. But most mothers we see, when their children are 88brought to them clean and tidy, take them into their hands as playthings, and when they die burst out into idle and unthankful grief, not so much out of affection—for affection is thoughtful and noble—but a great yearning for vain glory197 mixed with a little natural affection makes their grief fierce and vehement and hard to appease. And this does not seem to have escaped Æsop's notice, for he says that when Zeus assigned their honours to various gods, Grief also claimed his. And Zeus granted his wish, with this limitation that only those who chose and wished need pay him honour.198 It is thus with grief at the outset, everyone welcomes it at first, but after it has got by process of time settled, and become an inmate of the house, it is with difficulty dislodged again, however much people may wish to dislodge it. Wherefore we ought to keep it out of doors, and not let it approach the garrison by wearing mourning or shearing the hair, or by any similar outward sign of sorrow. For these things occurring daily and being importunate make the mind little, and narrow, and unsocial, and harsh, and timid, so that, being besieged and taken in hand by grief, it can no longer laugh, and shuns daylight, and avoids society. This evil will be followed by neglect of the body, and dislike to anointing and the bath and the other usual modes of life: whereas the very opposite ought to be the case, for the mind ill at ease especially requires that the body should be in a sound and healthy condition. For much of grief is blunted and relaxed when the body is permeated by calm, like the sea in fine weather. But if the body get into a dry and parched condition from a low diet, and gives no proper nutriment to the soul, but only feeds it with sorrow and grief, as it were with bitter and injurious exhalations, it cannot easily recover its tone however people may wish it should. Such is the state of the soul that has been so ill-treated.

§ vi. Most mothers we see, when their children are 88 brought to them clean and tidy, tend to treat them like toys. When the children die, the mothers often express uninhibited and ungrateful sorrow, not necessarily out of love—since true affection is thoughtful and profound—but rather from a strong desire for superficial recognition197, mixed with a bit of genuine affection, making their grief intense and overwhelming and hard to soothe. This didn't escape Æsop's attention; he noted that when Zeus was distributing honors among the gods, Grief also demanded his share. Zeus granted this wish but added that only those who chose to acknowledge him should honor him.198 Grief is initially welcomed by everyone, but as time passes and it becomes a permanent resident in the home, it becomes incredibly hard to remove, despite anyone's desire to get rid of it. Therefore, we should keep it at bay, avoiding outward signs of mourning, like dressing in black or cutting our hair, because these daily reminders can constrict our minds, making them small, narrow, unsociable, harsh, and timid. When overwhelmed by grief, the mind can no longer find joy, shuns daylight, and looks to avoid society. This negativity leads to neglecting the body and losing interest in grooming and bathing, which should be the opposite response because when the mind is troubled, it especially needs a healthy body. Much of grief can be softened and soothed when the body is calm, like a sea on a clear day. However, if the body becomes dry and weak from poor nutrition, offering only grief and sorrow, akin to toxic fumes, it becomes hard for the mind to regain its strength, no matter how much we wish for it to recover. Such is the condition of a soul that has been so poorly treated.

§ vii. Moreover, I should not hesitate to assert199 that the 89most formidable peril in connection with this is "the visits of bad women,"200 and their chatter, and joint lamentation, all which things fan the fire of sorrow and aggravate it, and suffer it not to be extinguished either by others or by itself. I am not ignorant what a time of it you had lately, when you went to the aid of Theon's sister, and fought against the women who came on a visit of condolence and rushed up with lamentation and wailing, adding fuel as it were to her fire of grief in their simplicity. For when people see their friends' houses on fire they put it out as quickly and energetically as they can, but when their souls are on fire they themselves bring fuel. And if anybody has anything the matter with his eyes they will not let him put his hands to them, however much he wish, nor do they themselves touch the inflamed part; but a person in grief sits down and gives himself up to every chance comer, like a river [that all make use of], to stir up and aggravate the sore, so that from a little tickling and discomfort it grows into a great and terrible disease. However, as to all this I know you will be on your guard.

§ vii. Furthermore, I wouldn’t hesitate to say199 that the 89 biggest danger here is "the visits of toxic people,"200 and their gossip, along with their shared mourning, all of which just stoke the flames of sorrow and make it worse, preventing it from being put out by anyone or even by the person in pain. I'm aware of how difficult it was for you recently when you intervened for Theon’s sister and faced the women who arrived to express their condolences, rushing in with their wailing and crying, unintentionally adding more fuel to her grief. Because when people see their friends’ homes burning, they rush to extinguish the flames, but when someone’s heart is on fire, they often add to the blaze. And if someone has an issue with their eyes, they won’t let him touch them, no matter how much he wants to, nor will they touch the affected area themselves; but someone who’s grieving just sits back and allows anyone to come along and stir up the pain, like a river [that everyone uses], turning a small discomfort into a significant and overwhelming problem. However, I know you’ll be careful about all this.

§ viii. Try also often to carry yourself back in memory to that time when, this little girl not having been then born, we had nothing to charge Fortune with, and to compare that time and this together, as if our circumstances had gone back to what they were then. Otherwise, my dear wife, we shall seem discontented at the birth of our little daughter, if we consider our position before her birth as more perfect. But we ought not to erase from our memory the two years of her life, but to consider them as a time of pleasure giving us gratification and enjoyment, and not to deem the shortness of the blessing as a great evil, nor to be unthankful for what was given us, because Fortune did not give us a longer tenure as we wished. For ever to be careful what we say about the gods, and to be cheerful and not rail against Fortune, brings a sweet and goodly profit; and he who in such conjunctures as ours mostly tries to remember his blessings, and turns and diverts his mind from the dark and disturbing things in life to the 90bright and radiant, either altogether extinguishes his grief or makes it small and dim from a comparison with his comforts. For as perfume gives pleasure to the nose, and is a remedy against disagreeable smells, so the remembrance of past happiness in present trouble gives all the relief they require to those who do not shut out of their memory the blessings of the past, or always and everywhere rail against Fortune. And this certainly ought not to be our case, that we should slander all our past life because, like a book, it has one erasure in it, when all the other pages have been bright and clean.

§ viii. Try to often remember the time before our little girl was born, when we had nothing to blame on Fate, and compare that time with now as if our circumstances had returned to what they were. Otherwise, my dear wife, we might seem unhappy about the birth of our daughter if we view our life before her arrival as more perfect. But we shouldn't forget the two years of her life; we should see them as a time of joy that brought us gratification and happiness, not view the short duration of that blessing as a significant misfortune, nor be ungrateful for what we received just because Fate didn’t give us a longer period as we wished. Being careful with what we say about the gods and remaining positive instead of complaining about Fate brings us sweet and valuable rewards. Whoever, in difficult times like ours, mostly focuses on their blessings and shifts their mind from dark and troubling thoughts to the 90bright and positive can either completely diminish their grief or make it less overwhelming by comparing it to their joys. Just as perfume delights the senses and masks unpleasant odors, so does recalling past happiness in present troubles offer relief to those who don't block out memories of their past blessings or constantly criticize Fate. We certainly shouldn’t slam our entire past just because, like a book, it has one scribbled-over part while all the other pages remain bright and clean.

§ ix. You have often heard that happiness consists in right calculations resulting in a healthy state of mind, and that the changes which Fortune brings about need not upset it, and introduce confusion into our life. But if we too must, like most people, be governed by external events, and make an inventory of the dealings of Fortune, and constitute other people the judges of our felicity, do not now regard the tears and lamentations of those who visit you, which by a faulty custom are lavished on everybody, but consider rather how happy you are still esteemed by them for your family, your house, and life. For it would be monstrous, if others would gladly prefer your destiny to theirs, even taking into account our present sorrow, that you should rail against and be impatient at our present lot, and in consequence of our bitter grief not reflect how much comfort is still left to us. But like those who quote imperfect verses of Homer201 and neglect the finest passages of his writings, to enumerate and complain of the trials of life, while you pay no attention to its blessings, is to resemble those stingy misers, who heap up riches and make no use of them when they have them, but lament and are impatient if they are lost. And if you grieve over her dying unmarried and childless, you can comfort yourself with the thought that you have had both those advantages. For they should not be reckoned as great blessings in the case of those who do not enjoy them, and small blessings in the case of those who do. And that she has gone to a 91place where she is out of pain ought not to pain us, for what evil can we mourn for on her account if her pains are over? For even the loss of important things does not grieve us when we have no need of them. But it was only little things that your Timoxena was deprived of, little things only she knew, and in little things only did she rejoice; and how can one be said to be deprived of things of which one had no conception, nor experience, nor even desire for?

§ ix. You've probably heard that happiness comes from making the right choices that lead to a healthy mindset, and that the changes brought by fate shouldn't throw us off balance or create chaos in our lives. But if we, like most people, let outside events dictate our feelings and let others judge our happiness based on fate's whims, don’t focus too much on the tears and sadness of those who come to see you—though society may expect it. Instead, think about how much they still value you for your family, your home, and your life. It would be outrageous if others would prefer your situation to theirs, even considering our current grief, and for you to complain and be impatient with where we are now, ignoring how much comfort we still have. Just like those who quote imperfect lines of Homer201 while ignoring his best work, complaining about life’s hardships and overlooking its blessings is like those greedy hoarders who accumulate wealth but never use it, lamenting and getting upset when they lose it. And if you're upset about her dying without a partner or kids, remember that you have experienced both of those blessings. They shouldn’t be seen as great gifts for people who don’t have them, and small blessings for those who do. The fact that she has moved to a 91place without pain shouldn't bother us, because what can we truly mourn for her if her suffering is over? Even losing significant things doesn’t make us sad when we no longer need them. Yet, your Timoxena only lost small things, things only she understood, and her joy was found in those little things; but how can you say she was deprived of things she didn’t know, hadn’t experienced, or even desired?

§ x. As to what you hear from some people, who get many to credit their notion, that the dead suffer no evil or pain, I know that you are prevented from believing that by the tradition of our fathers and by the mystic symbols of the mysteries of Dionysus, for we are both initiated. Consider then that the soul, being incorruptible, is in the same condition after death as birds that have been caught. For if it has been a long time in the body, and during this mortal life has become tame by many affairs and long habit, it swoops down again and a second time enters the body, and does not cease to be involved in the changes and chances of this life that result from birth. For do not suppose that old age is abused and ill-spoken of only for its wrinkles and white hair and weakness of body, but this is the worst feature about it, that it makes the soul feeble in its remembrance of things in the other world, and strong in its attachment to things in this world, and bends and presses it, if it retain the form which it had in the body from its experience. But that soul, which does indeed enter the body, but remains only a short time in it, being liberated from it by the higher powers, rears as it were at a damp and soft turning post in the race of life, and hastens on to its destined goal. For just as if anyone put out a fire, and light it again at once, it is soon rekindled, and burns up again quickly, but if it has been out a long time, to light it again will be a far more difficult and irksome task, so the soul that has sojourned only a short time in this dark and mortal life, quickly recovers the light and blaze of its former bright life, whereas for those who have not had the good fortune very early, to use the language of the poet, "to pass the gates of Hades,"202 nothing remains but a great 92passion for the things of this life, and a softening of the soul through contact with the body, and a melting away of it as if by the agency of drugs.203

§ x. Regarding what you hear from some people who convince many that the dead feel no pain or suffering, I know you can’t believe that due to the traditions of our ancestors and the mystical symbols from the mysteries of Dionysus, because we are both initiated. Consider that the soul, being immortal, is in the same state after death as birds that have been caught. If it has spent a long time in the body and during this life has become accustomed to many experiences and habits, it swoops down again and re-enters the body, continuing to be caught up in the changes and chances of this life that come from birth. Don’t think that old age is criticized only for its wrinkles, gray hair, and physical weakness; the worst part is that it weakens the soul’s memory of things in the other world and strengthens its attachment to this world, bending and pressing it, especially if it retains the form it had in the body from its experiences. But the soul that enters the body only briefly, being freed from it by higher powers, as if at a damp and soft turning point in the race of life, quickly moves toward its destined goal. For just as when a fire is put out and then immediately reignited, it blazes up again quickly, but if it has been out for a long time, rekindling it becomes a much harder and more tedious task, the soul that has spent only a short time in this dark and mortal life quickly regains the light and brilliance of its previous bright life. In contrast, for those who haven’t been fortunate enough to use the poet's words and “pass the gates of Hades”202, nothing remains but a strong desire for the things of this life, a softening of the soul through contact with the body, and a gradual dissolution of it as if influenced by drugs.203

§ xi. And the truth of this is rendered more apparent in our hereditary and time-honoured customs and laws. For when infants die no libations are poured out for them, nor are any other rites performed for them, such as are always performed for adults. For they have no share in the earth or in things of the earth, nor do parents haunt their tombs or monuments, or sit by their bodies when they are laid out. For the laws do not allow us to mourn for such, seeing that it is an impious thing to do so in the case of persons who have departed into a better and more divine place and sphere. I know that doubts are entertained about this, but since to doubt is harder for them than to believe, let us do externally as the laws enjoin, and internally let us be more holy and pure and chaste.204

§ xi. The truth of this is made clearer in our long-standing customs and laws. When infants die, no offerings are made for them, nor are any other ceremonies performed, unlike those for adults. They have no part in the earth or its matters, and their parents do not visit their graves or memorials, nor do they stay by their bodies when they are prepared. The laws prevent us from mourning for them, since it's considered disrespectful to grieve for those who have moved on to a better and more divine existence. I understand that there are doubts about this, but since it’s harder for some to doubt than to believe, let us follow the laws outwardly, and strive to be more holy, pure, and chaste on the inside.204

191 Timoxena, as we see later on, § ix.

191 Timoxena, as we will see later, § ix.

192 Adopting Reiske's reading, μαστὸν κελεύουσα, προεκαλεῖτο καθάπερ.

192 Following Reiske's interpretation, μαστὸν κελεύουσα, was called upon just like that.

193 Euripides' "Phaethon," which exists only in fragments. Clymene was the daughter of Oceanus, and mother of Phaethon.

193 Euripides' "Phaethon," which only survives in pieces. Clymene was the daughter of Oceanus and the mother of Phaethon.

194 An allusion to Euripides, "Bacchæ," 317, 318.

194 A reference to Euripides, "Bacchæ," 317, 318.

195 Reading with Reiske οὐδένι λόγῳ δὲ, or ἀλόγως δὲ. Some such reading seems necessary to comport with the τί γὰρ ἀλογώτερον two lines later.

195 Reading with Reiske in no way, or irrationally. Some kind of reading seems necessary to fit with the what is more irrational two lines later.

196 Reading παρεῖχες with Xylander.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading with Xylander.

197 A great craving for sympathy would be the modern way of putting it.

197 A strong desire for empathy would be the modern way of saying it.

198 See the Fable of Æsop, entitled Πένθους γερας, No. 355. Halme. See also Plutarch's "Consolation to Apollonius," § xix., where the Fable is told at some length.

198 Check out the Fable of Aesop called Πένθους γερας, No. 355. Halme. Also, take a look at Plutarch's "Consolation to Apollonius," § xix., where the Fable is discussed in more detail.

199 Reading with Reiske οὐκ ἂν εἰπεῖν φοβηθείην.

199 Reading with Reiske, I would not say I was afraid.

200 An allusion to Euripides, "Andromache," 930. See Plutarch's "Conjugal Precepts," § xl.

200 A reference to Euripides, "Andromache," 930. See Plutarch's "Conjugal Guidelines," § xl.

201 The whole subject is discussed in full by Athenæus, p. 632, F. F. A false quantity we see was a bugbear even before the days of Universities.

201 The entire topic is fully covered by Athenæus, p. 632, F. F. A false quantity was a concern even before the establishment of universities.

202 Homer, "Iliad," v. 646; xxiii. 71.

202 Homer, "Iliad," v. 646; xxiii. 71.

203 This section is dreadfully corrupt. I have adopted, it will be seen, the suggestions of Wyttenbach.

203 This section is really corrupt. As you’ll notice, I have taken on the suggestions of Wyttenbach.

204 This Consolatory Letter ends rather abruptly. It is probable that there was more of it.

204 This Consolatory Letter ends quite suddenly. It's likely that there was more to it.


THAT VIRTUE MAY BE TAUGHT.

§ i. As to virtue we deliberate and dispute whether good sense, and justice, and rectitude can be taught: and then we are not surprised that, while the works of orators, and pilots, and musicians, and house-builders, and farmers, are innumerable, good men are only a name and expression, like Centaurs and Giants and Cyclopes, and that it is impossible to find any virtuous action without alloy of base motives, or any character free from vice: but if nature produces spontaneously anything good, it is marred by much that is alien to it, as fruit choked by weeds. Men learn to play on the harp, and to dance, and to read, and to farm, and to ride on horseback: they learn how to put on their shoes and clothes generally: people teach how 93to pour out wine, how to cook; and all these things cannot be properly performed, without being learned. The art of good living alone, though all those things I have mentioned only exist on its account, is untaught, unmethodical, inartistic, and supposed to come by the light of nature!

§ i. When it comes to virtue, we ponder and debate whether good judgment, fairness, and integrity can be taught. So, it’s no wonder that while there are countless works by orators, pilots, musicians, builders, and farmers, the idea of good people seems merely a name or concept, like Centaurs, Giants, and Cyclopes. It’s nearly impossible to find a virtuous action that isn’t mixed with selfish motives, or a character that is completely free of flaws. If nature does manage to produce anything good, it often gets ruined by a lot of extraneous factors, much like fruit overrun by weeds. People can learn to play the harp, dance, read, farm, and ride horses. They learn how to put on shoes and their clothes in general. Instruction is provided on how 93 to pour wine and how to cook. All of these tasks require learning to do them properly. However, the art of living well, even though all those other skills are based on it, remains untaught, unstructured, and unrefined, supposedly coming naturally!

§ ii. O sirs, by asserting that virtue is not a thing to be taught, why are we making it unreal? For if teaching produces it, the deprivation of teaching prevents it. And yet, as Plato says, a discord and false note on the lyre makes not brother go to war with brother, nor sets friends at variance, nor makes states hostile to one another, so as to do and suffer at one another's hands the most dreadful things:205 nor can anyone say that there was ever a dissension in any city as to the pronunciation of Telchines: nor in a private house any difference between man and wife as to woof and warp. And yet no one without learning would undertake to ply the loom, or write a book, or play on the lyre, though he would thereby do no great harm, but he fears making himself ridiculous, for as Heraclitus says, "It is better to hide one's ignorance," yet everyone thinks himself competent to manage a house and wife and the state and hold any magisterial office. On one occasion, when a boy was eating rather greedily, Diogenes gave the lad's tutor a blow with his fist, ascribing the fault not to the boy, who had not learnt how to eat properly, but to the tutor who had not taught him. And can one not properly handle a dish or a cup, unless one has learnt from a boy, as Aristophanes bids us, "not to giggle, nor eat too fast, nor cross our legs,"206 and yet be perfectly fit to manage a family and city, and wife, and live well, and hold office, when one has not learnt how one should behave in the conduct of life? When Aristippus was asked by someone, "Are you everywhere then?" he smiled and said, "If I am everywhere, I lose my passage money."207 Why should not you also say, "If men are not better for learning, the money paid to tutors is also lost?" For just as nurses mould with their hands 94the child's body, so tutors, receiving it immediately it is weaned, mould its soul, teaching it by habit the first vestiges of virtue. And the Lacedæmonian, who was asked, what good he did as a tutor, replied, "I make what is good pleasant to boys." Moreover tutors teach boys to walk in the streets with their heads down,208 to touch salt fish with one finger only, other fish bread and meat with two, to scratch themselves in such a way, and in such a way to put on their cloak.209

§ ii. Oh gentlemen, by claiming that virtue can’t be taught, why are we making it seem unreal? If teaching creates virtue, then the lack of teaching removes it. Yet, as Plato says, a disharmony and false note on the lyre doesn’t cause brothers to go to war with each other, nor does it create conflict among friends, nor does it make states enemies, leading them to inflict horrible actions upon one another:205 nor can anyone claim there was ever a disagreement in any city about how to pronounce Telchines; and in a household, there’s no conflict between a husband and wife over woof and warp. Still, no one would attempt to weave, write a book, or play the lyre without some learning, even though they wouldn’t cause great harm. They fear looking foolish, as Heraclitus said, "It’s better to hide one’s ignorance," yet everyone believes they can manage a home, a spouse, their community, and hold any official position. Once, when a boy was eating rather greedily, Diogenes hit the boy’s tutor, blaming not the boy—who hadn’t learned proper eating habits—but the tutor, who had failed to teach him. And can anyone really handle a plate or a cup properly without having learned as a child, as Aristophanes advises us, "not to giggle, nor eat too fast, nor cross our legs,"206 yet be completely capable of running a household and a community, managing a wife, living well, and hold a public office without learning how to act in life? When Aristippus was asked, "Are you everywhere then?" he smiled and replied, "If I am everywhere, I lose my travel money."207 Why shouldn’t you say, "If men aren’t better for learning, the money spent on tutors is wasted?" Just as nurses shape the child's body with their hands, so tutors, once a child is weaned, shape their soul, teaching them the beginnings of virtue through habits. And the Lacedæmonian, when asked what good he did as a tutor, replied, "I make what is good enjoyable for boys." Furthermore, tutors teach boys to walk in the streets with their heads down,208 to touch salted fish with one finger only, while using two fingers for other fish, bread, and meat, to scratch themselves in a certain way, and to wear their cloak in a specific manner.209

§ iii. What then? He that says that the doctor's skill is wanted in the case of a slight skin-eruption or whitlow, but is not needed in the case of pleurisy, fever, or lunacy, in what respect does he differ from the man that says that schools and teaching and precepts are only for small and boyish duties, while great and important matters are to be left to mere routine and accident? For, as the man is ridiculous who says we ought to learn to row but not to steer, so he who allows all other arts to be learnt, but not virtue, seems to act altogether contrary to the Scythians. For they, as Herodotus tells us,210 blind their slaves that they may remain with them, but such an one puts the eye of reason into slavish and servile arts, and takes it away from virtue. And the general Iphicrates well answered Callias, the son of Chabrias, who asked him, "What are you? an archer? a targeteer? cavalry, or infantry?" "None of these," said he, "but the commander of them all." Ridiculous therefore is he who says that the use of the bow and other arms and the sling and riding are to be taught, but that strategy and how to command an army comes by the light of nature. Still more ridiculous is he who asserts that good sense alone need not be taught, without which all other arts are useless and profitless, seeing that she is the mistress and orderer and arranger of all of them, and puts each of them to their proper use. For example, what grace would there be in a banquet, though the servants had been well-trained, and had learnt how to dress and cook 95the meat and pour out the wine,211 unless there was good order and method among the waiters?212

§ iii. So what’s the point? Someone who thinks that a doctor is needed for a minor skin rash or a small infection, but not for serious issues like pleurisy, fever, or mental illness, is no different from someone who believes that education and teaching are only for small, childish tasks, while important matters should just be left to chance and routine. Just like it’s foolish to say we should learn to row but not to steer, it’s just as foolish to allow learning in all other areas except virtue, which goes completely against the Scythians. As Herodotus tells us,210 they blind their slaves to keep them with them, but someone like this puts the ability to reason into trivial, servile tasks and takes it away from virtue. General Iphicrates gave a great response to Callias, the son of Chabrias, when Callias asked him, "What are you? An archer? A spear thrower? Calvary or infantry?" Iphicrates replied, "None of those, but the leader of them all." It’s absurd to think that learning to use a bow and other weapons, as well as riding, is necessary, but that strategy and commanding an army come naturally. Even more absurd is the idea that good judgment doesn’t need to be taught, when without it, all other skills are pointless and ineffective, since it is the one that organizes and manages everything, using each skill appropriately. For example, what would a banquet look like if the servants were well-trained in cooking and serving the food and pouring the wine,95 but there was no order or coordination among the waiters?211

205 Plato, "Clitophon," p. 407, C.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Plato, "Clitophon," p. 407, C.

206 Aristophanes, "Clouds," 983.

Aristophanes, "Clouds," 983.

207 Does Juvenal allude to this, viii. 97?

207 Is Juvenal referring to this, viii. 97?

208 So as to look modest and be "Ingenui vultus pueri, ingenuique pudoris."

208 To appear modest and embody "The innocent face of a boy, and the innocence of his shame."

209 Reading with Salmasius, ἀναβαλεῐν.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading with Salmasius, ἀναβαλεῖν.

210 Herodotus, iv. 2. The historian, however, assigns other reasons for blinding them.

210 Herodotus, iv. 2. The historian, however, gives different reasons for blinding them.

211 A line from "Odyssey," xv. 323.

211 A line from "Odyssey," xv. 323.

212 "Malim δαιτυμόνας." Wyttenbach, who remarks generally on this short treatise, "Non integra videtur esse nec continua disputatio, sed disputationis, Plutarcheæ tamen, excerptum compendium."

212 "Malim δαιτυμόνας." Wyttenbach, commenting on this brief text, says, "It doesn't seem to be a complete or continuous discussion, but rather a summarized excerpt from Plutarch's discussion."


ON VIRTUE AND VICE.

§ i. Clothes seem to warm a man, not by throwing out heat themselves (for in itself every garment is cold, whence in great heat or in fevers people frequently change and shift them), but the heat which a man throws out from his own body is retained and wrapped in by a dress fitting close to the body, which does not admit of the heat being dissipated when once it has got firm hold. A somewhat similar case is the idea that deceives the mass of mankind, that if they could live in big houses, and get together a quantity of slaves and money, they would have a happy life. But a happy and cheerful life is not from without, on the contrary, a man adds the pleasure and gratification to the things that surround him, his temperament being as it were the source of his feelings.213

§ i. Clothes seem to make a person feel warm, not because they generate heat themselves (since every piece of clothing is inherently cold, which is why people often change their outfits in extreme heat or during fevers), but because the heat a person emits from their body is trapped and held in by clothing that fits closely. This prevents the heat from escaping once it has settled in. A similar misconception affects many people: they believe that if they could live in large houses and gather wealth and servants, they would lead a happy life. However, true happiness and joy do not come from external sources; instead, a person brings pleasure and satisfaction to their surroundings, with their mindset being the true source of their emotions.213

"But when the fire burns, the house looks brighter." 214

So, too, wealth is pleasanter, and fame and power more splendid, when a man has joy in his heart, seeing that men can bear easily and quietly poverty and exile and old age if their character is a contented and mild one.

Wealth is more enjoyable, and fame and power feel more impressive when a person has happiness in their heart, as people can handle poverty, exile, and old age with ease and grace if they have a calm and contented character.

§ ii. For as perfumes make threadbare coats and rags to smell sweet, while the body of Anchises sent forth a fetid 96 discharge, "distilling from his back on to his linen robe," so every kind of life with virtue is painless and pleasurable, whereas vice if infused into it makes splendour and wealth and magnificence painful, and sickening, and unwelcome to its possessors.

§ ii. Just as perfumes can make worn-out coats and rags smell nice, even though the body of Anchises was giving off a terrible 96 odor, "dripping from his back onto his linen robe," every kind of life filled with virtue is easy and enjoyable. However, when vice is mixed in, it turns beauty, wealth, and grandeur into burdensome, unpleasant, and unwelcome experiences for those who have them.

"He is considered happy in the marketplace, But when he gets him home, three times miserable, His wife controls everything, fights, and bossy. 215

And yet there would be no great difficulty in getting rid of a bad wife, if one was a man and not a slave. But a man cannot by writing a bill of divorce to his vice get rid of all trouble at once, and enjoy tranquillity by living apart: for it is ever present in his vitals, and sticks to him night and day, "and burns without a torch, and consigns him to gloomy old age,"216 being a disagreeable fellow-traveller owing to its arrogance, and a costly companion at table owing to its daintiness, and an unpleasant bed-fellow, disturbing and marring sleep by anxiety and care and envy. For during such a one's sleep the body indeed gets rest, but the mind has terrors, and dreams, and perturbations, owing to superstition,

And yet, it wouldn’t be too hard to get rid of a bad wife if a man were free and not a slave. But a man can't just write a divorce paper to escape all his problems at once and find peace by living separately. The issues are always there, haunting him day and night, "burning without a torch, and sending him into a gloomy old age,"216 being an annoying companion because of its arrogance, and an expensive guest at the dinner table because of its finickiness, and an unwelcome bedmate, disturbing his sleep with anxiety, care, and envy. Because even if the body gets rest during sleep, the mind is still plagued by fears, dreams, and worries, thanks to superstition.

"When my troubles find me while I'm asleep, I am overwhelmed by the most terrifying dreams.

as one says. For thus envy, and fear, and anger, and lust affect one. During the daytime, indeed, vice looks abroad and imitates the behaviour of others, is shy and conceals its evil desires, and does not altogether give way to its propensities, but often even resists and fights stoutly against them; but in sleep it escapes the observation of people and the law, and, being as far as possible removed from fear or modesty, gives every passion play, and excites its depravity and licentiousness, for, to borrow Plato's expression,217 "it attempts incest with its mother, and procures for itself unlawful meats, and abstains from no action what97ever," and enjoys lawlessness as far as is practicable in visions and phantasies, that end in no complete pleasure or satisfaction, but can only stir up and inflame the passions and morbid emotions.

as one says. For this is how envy, fear, anger, and lust affect a person. During the day, vice puts on a show, mimicking others’ behavior, being shy, and hiding its evil desires; it doesn’t fully give in to its impulses but often pushes back and fights against them. However, in sleep, it evades the scrutiny of others and the law, and, being as free as possible from fear or shame, lets every passion take the stage, fueling its depravity and promiscuity. To borrow from Plato's words,217 "it tries to commit incest with its mother, seeks out forbidden pleasures, and holds back from no action whatsoever," reveling in lawlessness as much as it can within dreams and fantasies, which lead to no real pleasure or satisfaction, but instead only stir up and intensify the passions and unhealthy emotions.

§ iii. Where then is the pleasure of vice, if there is nowhere in it freedom from anxiety and pain, or independence, or tranquillity, or rest?218 A healthy and sound constitution does indeed augment the pleasures of the body, but for the soul there can be no lasting joy or gratification, unless cheerfulness and fearlessness and courage supply a calm serenity free from storms; for otherwise, even if hope or delight smile on the soul, it is soon confused and disturbed by care lifting up its head again, so that it is but the calm of a sunken rock.

§ iii. Where is the pleasure in vice if it doesn't bring any freedom from anxiety and pain, independence, peace, or rest? A healthy and strong body can indeed enhance physical pleasures, but for the soul, true happiness or fulfillment cannot last unless cheerfulness, fearlessness, and courage provide a calm serenity free from turmoil. Otherwise, even if hope or joy briefly shines on the soul, it will quickly become troubled and disturbed by worries resurfacing, making it just a calm moment like that of a submerged rock.

§ iv. Pile up gold, heap up silver, build covered walks, fill your house with slaves and the town with debtors, unless you lay to rest the passions of the soul, and put a curb on your insatiable desires, and rid yourself of fear and anxiety, you are but pouring out wine for a man in a fever, and giving honey to a man who is bilious, and laying out a sumptuous banquet for people who are suffering from dysentery, and can neither retain their food nor get any benefit from it, but are made even worse by it. Have you never observed how sick persons turn against and spit out and refuse the daintiest and most costly viands, though people offer them and almost force them down their throats, but on another occasion, when their condition is different, their respiration good, their blood in a healthy state, and their natural warmth restored, they get up, and enjoy and make a good meal of simple bread and cheese and cress? Such, also, is the effect of reason on the mind. You will be contented, if you have learned what is good and honourable. You will live daintily and be a king in poverty, and enjoy a quiet and private life as much as the public life of general or statesman. By the aid of philosophy you will live not unpleasantly, for you will learn to extract pleasure from all places 98and things: wealth will make you happy, because it will enable you to benefit many; and poverty, as you will not then have many anxieties; and glory, for it will make you honoured; and obscurity, for you will then be safe from envy.

§ iv. Hoard gold, stack up silver, build covered walkways, fill your house with servants and your town with people in debt. Unless you calm the passions of your soul, control your endless desires, and free yourself from fear and anxiety, you’re just pouring wine for a person in a fever, giving honey to someone with nausea, and throwing a lavish feast for people suffering from dysentery, who can't keep anything down and only feel worse from it. Have you ever noticed how sick people reject and spit out the most exquisite and expensive foods, even when others offer them forcefully? Yet, when they're feeling better, breathing well, with healthy blood and warmth restored, they get up and enjoy a simple meal of bread, cheese, and cress? That’s the effect of reason on the mind. You'll find satisfaction once you learn what is good and honorable. You can live well and be a king in poverty, enjoying a quiet life just as much as the public life of a general or statesman. With philosophy, you’ll find joy in everything: wealth will bring you happiness because it allows you to help many; poverty will ease your worries; glory will earn you respect; and obscurity will protect you from envy.

213 Happiness comes from within, not from without. The true seat of happiness is the mind. Compare Milton, "Paradise Lost," Book i. 254, 255:—

213 Happiness comes from within, not from external sources. The real source of happiness is the mind. Compare Milton, "Paradise Lost," Book i. 254, 255:—

"The mind is its own space, and within it "Can turn a Heaven into Hell, a Hell into Heaven."

214 Homeric Epigrammata, xiii. 5.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homeric Epigrams, xiii. 5.

215 Wyttenbach thinks these lines are by Menander. Plutarch quotes them again "On Contentedness of Mind," § xi.

215 Wyttenbach believes these lines were written by Menander. Plutarch references them again in "On Contentedness of Mind," § xi.

216 Hesiod, "Works and Days," 705.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hesiod, "Works and Days," 705.

217 Plato, "Republic," ix. p. 571, D. Quoted again, "How one may be aware of one's Progress in Virtue," § xii.

217 Plato, "Republic," ix. p. 571, D. Quoted again, "How to Recognize Your Progress in Virtue," § xii.

218 And so Dr. Young truly says,—

218 And so Dr. Young really says,—

"A man who seeks pleasure is a man who experiences pain." Late Night Thoughts.

ON MORAL VIRTUE.

§ i. I propose to discuss what is called and appears to be moral virtue (which differs mainly from contemplative virtue in that it has emotion for its matter, and reason for its form), what its nature is, and how it subsists, and whether that part of the soul which takes it in is furnished with reason of its own, or participates in something foreign, and if the latter, whether as things that are mixed with something better than themselves, or rather as that which is subject to superintendence and command, and may be said to share in the power of that which commands. For I think it is clear that virtue can exist and continue altogether free from matter and mixture. My best course will be to run briefly over the views of others, not so much to display my research as because, when their ideas have been set forth, mine will become more clear and be on a firmer basis.

§ i. I want to talk about what we call moral virtue (which mainly differs from contemplative virtue in that it involves emotions more than thoughts) — what it really is, how it exists, and whether the part of the soul that receives it has its own reasoning or depends on something external. If it depends on something else, I want to know whether it mixes with something better or is just something that is controlled and directed by that which commands it. I believe it's obvious that virtue can exist and thrive completely independent of any material or mix. I’ll briefly cover the opinions of others, not just to show my research, but because presenting their ideas will help clarify and strengthen my own.

§ ii. Menedemus of Eretria took away the number and differences of virtues, on the ground that virtue was one though it had many names; for that just as mortal is synonymous with man, so temperance and bravery and justice were the same thing. And Aristo of Chios also made virtue one in substance, and called it soundness of mind: its diversities and varieties only existing in certain relations, as if one called our sight when it took in white objects white-sight, and when it took in black objects black-sight, and so on. For virtue, when it considers what it ought to do and what it ought not to do, is called prudence; and when it curbs passion, and sets a fit and proper limit to pleasure, it is called self-control; and when it is associated with our dealings and covenants with one another, it is called justice; just as a knife is one article,99 though at different times it cuts different things in half: and so, too, fire acts on different matter though it has but one property. And Zeno of Cittium seems to incline somewhat to the same view, as he defines prudence in distribution as justice, in choice as self-control, in endurance as fortitude: and those who defend these views maintain that by the term prudence Zeno means knowledge. But Chrysippus, thinking each particular virtue should be arranged under its particular quality, unwittingly stirred up, to use Plato's language, "a whole swarm of virtues,"219 unusual and unknown. For as from brave we get bravery, and from mild mildness, and from just justice, so from acceptable he got acceptableness, and from good goodness, and from great greatness, and from the honourable honourableness, and he made virtues of many other such clevernesses, affabilities, and versatilities, and filled philosophy, which did not at all require it, with many strange names.

§ ii. Menedemus of Eretria argued that there are not many virtues but one virtue with different names; just as “mortal” means “human,” temperance, bravery, and justice are all the same. Aristo of Chios also believed that virtue is fundamentally one and defined it as soundness of mind. The different forms of virtue only exist in certain contexts, similar to how we might call our vision of white things “white-sight” and our vision of black things “black-sight.” When virtue considers what actions to take or avoid, it’s called prudence; when it controls our desires and places limits on pleasure, it’s called self-control; and when it relates to our interactions and agreements with others, it’s called justice. A knife serves one purpose, even if it cuts different things at different times, and fire affects different materials while having just one property. Zeno of Cittium also seemed to agree with this perspective, defining prudence in distribution as justice, in choice as self-control, and in endurance as fortitude. Supporters of these ideas claim that when Zeno spoke of prudence, he meant knowledge. However, Chrysippus believed that each specific virtue should be categorized under its unique quality, which, as Plato might say, unintentionally gave rise to “a whole swarm of virtues,”219 unusual and unfamiliar. Just as we derive bravery from brave, mildness from mild, and justice from just, he derived acceptableness from acceptable, goodness from good, greatness from great, and honourableness from honourable, creating names for many other traits like cleverness, affability, and versatility, unnecessarily complicating philosophy with many strange terms.

§ iii. Now all these agree in supposing virtue to be a disposition and faculty of the governing part of the soul set in motion by reason, or rather to be reason itself conformable and firm and immutable. They think further that the emotional and unreasoning part of the soul is not by any natural difference distinct from the reasoning part, but that that same part of the soul, which they call intellect and the leading principle of action, being altogether diverted and changed by the passions, and by the alterations which habit or disposition have brought about, becomes either vice or virtue, without having in itself any unreasoning element, but that it is called unreasoning when, by the strong and overpowering force of appetite, it launches out into excesses contrary to the direction of reason. For passion, according to them, is only vicious and intemperate reason, getting its strength and power from bad and faulty judgement. But all of those philosophers seem to have been ignorant that we are all in reality two-fold and composite, though they did not recognize it, and only saw the more evident mixture of soul and body. And yet that there is in the soul itself something composite and two-fold and 100dissimilar (the unreasoning part of it, as if another body, being by necessity and nature mixed up with and united to reason), seems not to have escaped the notice even of Pythagoras, as we infer from his zeal for music, which he introduced to calm and soothe the soul, as knowing that it was not altogether amenable to precept and instruction, or redeemable from vice only by reason, but that it needed some other persuasion and moulding and softening influence to co-operate with reason, unless it were to be altogether intractable and refractory to philosophy. And Plato saw very plainly and confidently and decidedly that the soul of this universe is not simple or uncomposite or uniform, but is made up of forces that work uniformly and differently, in the one case it is ever marshalled in the same order and moves about in one fixed orbit, in the other case it is divided into motions and orbits contrary to each other and changing about, and thus generates differences in things. So, too, the soul of man, being a part or portion of the soul of the universe, and compounded upon similar principles and proportions, is not simple or entirely uniform, but has one part intelligent and reasoning, which is intended by nature to rule and dominate in man, and another part unreasoning, and subject to passion and caprice, and disorderly, and in need of direction. And this last again is divided into two parts, one of which, being most closely connected with the body, is called desire, and the other, sometimes taking part with the body, sometimes with reason, lending its influence against the body, is called anger. And the difference between reason and sense on the one hand, and anger and desire on the other, is shown by their antipathy to one another, so that they are often at variance with one another as to what is best.220 These were at first221 the views of Aristotle, as is clear from his writings, though afterwards he joined anger to desire, as if anger were nothing but a desire and passion for revenge. However, he always considered the emotional and unreasoning part of the soul as distinct from the reasoning, not that it is altogether unreasoning as the perceptive, or nutritive, or 101vegetative portions of the soul, for these are always deaf and disobedient to reason, and in a certain sense are off-shoots from the flesh, and altogether attached to the body; but the emotional, though it is destitute of any reason of its own, yet is naturally inclined to listen to reason and sense, and turn and submit and mould itself accordingly, unless it be entirely corrupted by brute pleasure and a life of indulgence.

§ iii. All these thinkers agree that virtue is the disposition and ability of the mind's governing part, driven by reason, or, more accurately, that it is reason itself—steady and unchanging. They also believe that the emotional and irrational parts of the mind aren't naturally separate from the rational part, but rather that this same part, which they call intellect and the guiding principle of action, gets misdirected and altered by emotions and the changes brought on by habits or tendencies, becoming either vice or virtue. It doesn't inherently contain any irrational aspects, but is deemed irrational when driven by strong desires that lead it to go against reason. According to them, passion is simply misguided and excessive reason, drawing strength from poor judgment. However, these philosophers seem to overlook that we are essentially complex beings, not realizing this and just observing the more visible mixture of mind and body. Still, the idea that the mind itself has a composite and dual aspect—though not easily recognized—has been noted even by Pythagoras, as we understand from his passion for music, which he introduced to comfort and calm the mind, recognizing that it isn’t fully responsive to rules and teachings or redeemable from vice solely through reason. Instead, it requires some additional influence and nurturing cooperation with reason, or it risks being completely unmanageable and resistant to philosophical thought. Moreover, Plato clearly understood and confidently asserted that the soul of the universe is not simple, uniform, or indivisible; it consists of forces that operate consistently yet differently. In one scenario, it is always organized in the same way and moves along a fixed path; in another, it is divided into opposing and fluctuating movements, resulting in variations among things. Similarly, the human soul, being part of the universe's soul and composed of the same principles and proportions, is also not simple or entirely uniform. It contains one part that is intelligent and rational, intended to govern in us, and another part that is irrational, driven by emotions and whims, disordered, and requiring guidance. This latter part can be further divided: one portion is closely tied to the body, known as desire, while the other sometimes aligns with the body and at other times with reason, countering the body’s urges, which is referred to as anger. The distinction between reason and perception on one side and anger and desire on the other is illustrated by their opposition to each other, often being at odds about what is best.220 These views reflect Aristotle's initial thinking, as evident in his writings, although later he equated anger with desire, suggesting that anger is merely a longing for revenge. Nonetheless, he always regarded the emotional and irrational part of the mind as separate from the rational one, not in the same way as the sensory, nutritive, or vegetative aspects which consistently ignore reason and are somewhat extensions of the flesh, wholly tied to the body. The emotional part, while lacking its own reason, is naturally inclined to heed reason and perception, adapting and conforming accordingly, unless it becomes thoroughly corrupted by base pleasures and a life of indulgence.

§ iv. As for those who wonder that what is unreasoning should obey reason, they do not seem to me to recognize the power of reason, how great it is, and how far-reaching its dominion is—a power not gained by harsh and repelling methods, but by attractive ones, as mild persuasion which always accomplishes more than compulsion or violence. For even the spirit and nerves and bones, and other parts of the body, though devoid of reason, yet at any instigation of reason, when she shakes as it were the reins, are all on the alert and compliant and obedient, the feet to run, and the hands to throw or lift, at her bidding. Right excellently has the poet set forth in the following lines the sympathy and accordance between the unreasoning and reason:—

§ iv. For those who wonder how something without reason could follow reason, it seems to me they don’t grasp the power of reason, how immense it is, and how widespread its influence can be—a power not achieved through harshness and force, but through gentle persuasion that consistently works better than coercion or aggression. Even the spirit, nerves, bones, and other parts of the body, while lacking reason, respond to the prompts of reason; when she gives the command, they all become alert, compliant, and obedient—the feet ready to run, and the hands to throw or lift at her request. The poet beautifully illustrates the connection and harmony between the irrational and reason in the following lines:—

"Her beautiful cheeks were stained with tears," She was crying; her husband was truly there with her. But even though Odysseus felt compassion for her, His eyes, like horn or steel, remained expressionless. "Within their eyelids, and shape his held-back tears."222

So completely under the control of judgement did he keep his spirit and blood and tears. The same is shown by the subsidence of our passions, which are laid to rest in the presence of handsome women or boys, whom reason and the law forbid us to touch; a case which most frequently happens to lovers, when they hear that they have unwittingly fallen in love with a sister or daughter. For at once passion is laid at the voice of reason, and the body exhibits its members as subservient to decorum. And frequently in the case of dainty food, people very much attracted by it, if they find out at the time or learn afterwards that they have eaten what is unclean or unlawful, 102not only suffer distress and grief in their imagination, but even their very body is upset by the notion, and violent retchings and vomitings follow.223 I fear I should seem to be introducing merely novel and enticing arguments, if I were to enumerate stringed instruments and lyres, and harps and flutes, and other harmonious musical instruments, which, although inanimate, yet speak to man's passions, rejoicing with him, and mourning with him, and chiming in with him, and rioting with him,—in a word, falling in with the vein and emotions and characters of those that play on them. And they say that Zeno on one occasion, going into the theatre when Amœbeus224 was playing on the harp, said to the pupils, "Let us go and learn what music can be produced by guts and nerves and wood and bones, when they preserve proportion and time and order." But passing these things over, I would gladly learn from them, if, when they see dogs and horses and birds domesticated, and by habit and training uttering sounds that can be understood, and making obedient movements and gestures, and acting quietly and usefully to us, and when they notice that Achilles in Homer cheers on horses as well as men to the fight,225 they still wonder and doubt, whether the passionate and emotional and painful and pleasurable elements in us are by nature obedient to the voice of reason, and influenced and affected by it, seeing that those elements are not apart from us or detached from us, or formed from outside, or hammered into us by force, but are innate in us, and ever associate with us, and are nourished within us, and abound in us through habit. Accordingly moral character is well called by the Greeks ἧθος, for it is, to speak generally, a quality of the unreasoning element in man, and is called ἧθος because the unreasoning element moulded by reason receives this quality and difference by habit, which is called ἔθος.226 Not that reason wishes to expel passion altogether (that is neither 103possible, nor advisable), but only to keep it within bounds and order, and to engender the moral virtues, which are not apathetic, but hold the due proportion and mean in regard to passion. And this she does by reducing the power of passion to a good habit. For there are said to be three things existing in the soul, power, passion, and habit. Power is the principle or matter of passion, as power to be angry, ashamed, or confident: and passion is the actual setting in motion of that power, being itself anger, confidence, or shame; and habit is the strong formation of power in the unreasoning element engendered by use, being vice if the passions are badly tutored by reason, virtue if they are well tutored.

So completely under the control of judgment did he keep his spirit, blood, and tears. The same is shown by how our passions settle down when we're in the presence of attractive women or boys, whom reason and the law don’t allow us to touch; this often happens to lovers who realize they've unknowingly fallen in love with a sister or daughter. Immediately, passion quiets at the voice of reason, and the body shows its parts as complying with decency. Similarly, for people who are very drawn to delicacies, if they discover at that moment or learn later that what they've eaten is unclean or forbidden, 102 they not only feel distress and grief mentally, but their bodies can also be unsettled by the idea, resulting in nausea and vomiting.223 I worry I might seem to be bringing in only new and attractive arguments if I were to list stringed instruments and lyres, harps and flutes, and other harmonious musical tools that, though lifeless, still resonate with human emotions, celebrating with us, grieving with us, chiming in with us, and indulging with us—in short, connecting with the feelings and character of those who play them. They say Zeno, on one occasion, went into the theater when Amœbeus224 was playing the harp and told his students, "Let’s go learn what music can be created by guts and nerves, wood, and bones when they maintain proportion, time, and order." But setting these aside, I’d like to learn from them whether, when they see dogs and horses and birds domesticated, expressing understandable sounds and obedient actions through training, and acting calmly and helpfully to us, and when they notice that Achilles in Homer encourages horses just like men to fight,225 they still wonder and doubt whether our emotional elements are naturally obedient to reason, influenced and affected by it. These elements aren’t separate from us or formed externally or beaten into us, but are ingrained in us, always accompanying us, nurtured within us, and flourishing in us through habit. Thus, moral character is aptly called by the Greeks ἧθος, as it is generally a quality of the non-rational part of human beings and is named ἧθος because the non-rational part molded by reason gains this quality and difference through habit, which is called ἔθος.226 Reason doesn’t aim to completely eliminate passion (that’s neither 103 possible nor advisable), but rather to keep it in check and order and foster moral virtues, which are not devoid of feeling but maintain the right balance regarding passion. It achieves this by refining the intensity of passion into a good habit. It is said that three things exist in the soul: power, passion, and habit. Power is the principle or essence of passion, such as the ability to feel anger, shame, or confidence; passion is the actual expression of that power, thus embodying anger, confidence, or shame; and habit is the strong formation of power within the non-rational part that develops through usage, becoming vice if passions are poorly guided by reason, and virtue if they are well directed.

§ v. But since they do not regard every virtue as a mean, nor call it moral, we must discuss this difference by approaching the matter more from first principles. Some things in the world exist absolutely, as the earth, the sky, the stars, and the sea; others have relation to us, as good and evil, as what is desirable or to be avoided, as pleasant and painful: and since reason has an eye to both of these classes, when it considers the former it is scientific and contemplative, when it considers the latter it is deliberative and practical. And prudence is the virtue in the latter case, as knowledge in the former. And there is this difference between prudence and knowledge, prudence consists in applying the contemplative to the practical and emotional so as to make reason paramount. On which account it often needs the help of fortune; whereas knowledge needs neither the help of fortune nor deliberation to gain its ends: for it considers only things which are always the same. And as the geometrician does not deliberate about the triangle, as to whether its interior angles are together equal to two right angles, for he knows it as a fact—and deliberation only takes place in the case of things which differ at different times, not in the case of things which are certain and unchangeable—so the contemplative mind having its scope in first principles, and things that are fixed, and that ever have one nature which does not admit of change, has no need for deliberation. But prudence, which has to enter into matters full of obscurity and confusion, frequently has to take its chance, and104 to deliberate about things which are uncertain, and, in carrying the deliberation into practice, has to co-operate with the unreasoning element, which comes to its help, and is involved in its decisions, for they need an impetus. Now this impetus is given to passion by the moral character, an impetus requiring reason to regulate it, that it may render moderate and not excessive help, and at the seasonable time. For the emotional and unreasoning elements are subject to motions sometimes too quick and vehement, at other times too remiss and slow. And so everything we do may be a success from one point of view, but a failure from many points of view; as to hit the mark one thing only is requisite, but one may miss it in various ways, as one may shoot beyond or too short. This then is the function of practical reason following nature, to prevent our passions going either too far or too short. For where from weakness and want of strength, or from fear and hesitation, the impetus gives in and abandons what is good, there reason is by to stir it up and rekindle it; and where on the other hand it goes ahead too fast and in disorder, there it represses and checks its zeal. And thus setting bounds to the emotional motions, it engenders in the unreasoning part of the soul moral virtues, which are the mean between excess and deficiency. Not that we can say that all virtue exists in the mean, but knowledge and prudence being in no need of the unreasoning element, and being situated in the pure and unemotional part of the soul, is a complete perfection and power of reason, whereby we get the most divine and happy fruit of understanding. But that virtue which is necessary because of the body, and needs the help of the passions as an instrument towards the practical, not destroying or doing away with but ordering and regulating the unreasoning part of the soul, is perfection as regards its power and quality, but in quantity it is a mean correcting both excess and deficiency.

§ v. But since they don't view every virtue as a mean, nor label it moral, we need to discuss this difference by starting from the basic principles. Some things in the world exist absolutely, like the earth, the sky, the stars, and the sea; others relate to us, like good and evil, what we desire or want to avoid, and what is pleasant versus painful. Reason considers both types of things; when addressing the former, it is scientific and contemplative, and when addressing the latter, it is deliberative and practical. Prudence is the virtue related to the latter, while knowledge pertains to the former. The difference between prudence and knowledge is that prudence applies contemplation to practicality and emotions to ensure reason is primary. For this reason, it often requires the help of luck; in contrast, knowledge doesn’t need the help of luck or deliberation to achieve its goals, as it focuses solely on things that are always the same. A geometer doesn’t deliberate about whether the angles of a triangle always add up to two right angles, because they know that to be a fact—and deliberation only occurs regarding things that vary over time, not with things that are certain and unchanging. Therefore, the contemplative mind operates on first principles and fixed matters that have an unchanging nature and requires no deliberation. Prudence, however, must navigate unclear and chaotic situations and often has to rely on chance, deliberating about uncertain matters, and in putting deliberation into action, it has to work with the unreasoning element that assists it and is part of its decisions since they need motivation. This motivation is provided by passion through moral character, requiring reason to regulate it so that it offers guidance that is moderate and timely. Emotional and unreasoning elements can sometimes act too quickly and forcefully, and at other times, they can be too hesitant and slow. Thus, everything we do can be seen as successful from one perspective, but a failure from many others; hitting a target requires only one specific action, yet one can miss in various ways, such as shooting too far or too short. This is the role of practical reason in following nature, preventing our passions from going too far or falling short. When weakness, fear, or hesitation causes motivation to give up on what is good, reason intervenes to inspire and reignite it; conversely, if it rushes ahead too quickly and chaotically, reason holds back and checks its enthusiasm. By setting limits on emotional movements, it cultivates moral virtues in the unreasoning part of the soul, which lie between excess and deficiency. Not that we can claim that all virtue exists in the mean, but knowledge and prudence do not rely on the unreasoning element and reside in the pure, unemotional part of the soul, representing complete perfection and the power of reason, yielding the most divine and fulfilling results of understanding. However, the virtue necessary because of the body, which requires help from passions as tools for practicality—not destroying or eliminating but rather organizing and regulating the unreasoning side of the soul—is perfect in its power and quality but is a mean in quantity, correcting both excess and deficiency.

§ vi. But since the word mean has a variety of meanings—for there is one kind of mean compounded of two simple extremes, as grey is the mean between white and black; and there is another kind of mean, where that which contains and is contained is the mean between the containing and contained, as eight is the mean between twelve and105 four; and there is a third kind of mean which has part in neither extreme, as the indifferent is the mean between good and bad,—virtue cannot be a mean in any of these ways. For neither is it a mixture of vices, nor containing that which is defective is it contained by that which is excessive, nor is it again altogether free from, emotional storms of passion, wherein are excess and deficiency. But it is, and is commonly so called, a mean like that in music and harmony. For as in music there is a middle note between the highest and lowest in the scale, which being perfectly in tune avoids the sharpness of the one and the flatness of the other; so virtue, being a motion and power in the unreasoning part of the soul, takes away the remissness and strain, and generally speaking the excess and defect of the appetite, by reducing each of the passions to a state of mean and rectitude. For example, they tell us that bravery is the mean between cowardice and foolhardiness, whereof the former is a defect, the latter an excess of anger: and that liberality is the mean between stinginess and prodigality: and that meekness is the mean between insensibility and savageness: and so of temperance and justice, that the latter, being concerned with contracts, is to assign neither too much nor too little to litigants, and that the former ever reduces the passions to the proper mean between apathy (or insensibility) and gross intemperance. This last illustration serves excellently to show us the radical difference between the unreasoning and reasoning parts of the soul, and to prove to us that passion and reason are wide as the poles asunder. For the difference would not be discernible between temperance and continence, nor between intemperance and incontinence, in pleasure and desires, if the appetite and judgement were in the same portion of the soul. Now temperance is a state, wherein reason holds the reins, and manages the passions as a quiet and well-broken-in animal, finding them obedient and submissive to the reins and masters over their desires.227 Continence on the other hand is not driven by reason without some trouble, not being docile but jibbing and 106kicking, like an animal compelled by bit and bridle and whip and backing, being in itself full of struggles and commotion. Plato explains this by his simile of the chariot-horses of the soul, the worse one of which ever kicking against the other and disturbing the charioteer, he is obliged ever to hold them in with all his might, and to tighten the reins, lest, to borrow the language of Simonides, "he should drop from his hands the purple reins." And so they do not consider continence to be an absolute virtue, but something less than a virtue; for no mean arises from the concord of the worse with the better, nor is the excess of the passion curtailed, nor does the appetite obey or act in unison with reason, but it both gives and suffers trouble, and is constrained by force, and is as it were an enemy in a town given up to faction.

§ vi. The word "mean" has multiple meanings. One type of mean is created by combining two simple extremes, like grey being the mean between white and black. Another type involves what contains and what is contained, such as eight being the mean between twelve and105 four. There’s also a third kind of mean that doesn’t partake in either extreme, like the indifferent mean between good and bad. Therefore, virtue cannot be considered a mean in any of these ways. It isn’t a mix of vices, nor is it something defective that is shaped by something excessive, nor is it completely free from emotional turmoil caused by excess and deficiency. Instead, it is, and is often referred to as, a mean similar to those found in music and harmony. Just as there is a middle note in music that balances the highest and lowest notes, perfectly in tune and avoiding sharpness and flatness, virtue functions as a movement and power in the irrational part of the soul, eliminating slackness and strain, along with the excesses and deficiencies of appetites, bringing the passions into a state of balance and righteousness. For instance, bravery is seen as the mean between cowardice and foolhardiness, with cowardice being a deficiency and foolhardiness an excess of anger; liberality is the mean between stinginess and extravagance; meekness is the mean between insensitivity and savagery; similarly, temperance and justice—where justice involves finding the right balance in contracts, giving neither too much nor too little to those involved, and temperance moderates the passions between apathy and excessive indulgence. This last example clearly illustrates the fundamental difference between the irrational and rational parts of the soul, proving that passion and reason are fundamentally opposed. The distinction between temperance and continence, or between intemperance and incontinence concerning pleasure and desires, would be unclear if appetite and judgment were part of the same area of the soul. Temperance is a state where reason takes control, managing passions like a well-trained animal that obeys and submits to its reins, acting over its desires.227 On the other hand, continence struggles with reason; it is not easily guided, akin to an animal that resists control, kicking and fighting against its bit, bridle, and whip, full of turmoil and agitation. Plato illustrates this with his analogy of the soul's chariot-horses, where the more unruly horse constantly kicks against the other and disrupts the charioteer, who must continually exert all his strength to keep them in check, tightening the reins to avoid the scenario where, as Simonides puts it, "he should drop from his hands the purple reins." Therefore, continence is not viewed as a true virtue but something less; no true mean comes from the agreement of the inferior with the superior, nor does it lessen the intensity of the passion, nor does appetite follow or align with reason. Instead, it brings about conflict and is forced into compliance, acting like an enemy in a troubled city.

"The town is filled with incense, and all at once" "Echoes with songs of victory and painful cries." 228

Such is the state of soul of the continent person owing to his conflicting condition. On the same grounds they consider incontinence to be something less than vice, but intemperance to be a complete vice. For it, having both its appetite and reason depraved, is by the one carried away to desire disgraceful things,229 by the other, through bad judgement consenting to desire, loses even the perception of wrongdoing. But incontinence keeps its judgement sound through reason, but is carried away against its judgement by passion which is too strong for reason, whence it differs from intemperance. For in the one case reason is mastered by passion, in the other it does not even make a fight against it, in the one case it opposes its desires even when it follows them, in the other it is their advocate and even leader, in the one case it gladly participates in what is wrong, in the other sorrowfully, in the one case it willingly rushes into what is disgraceful, in the other it abandons the honourable unwillingly. And as there is a difference in their deeds, so no less manifest is the difference 107in their language. For these are the expressions of the intemperate. "What grace or pleasure in life is there without golden Aphrodite? May I die, when I care no longer for these things!" And another says, "To eat, to drink, to enjoy the gifts of Aphrodite is everything, for all other things I look upon as supplementary," as if from the bottom of his soul he gave himself up to pleasures, and was completely subverted by them. And not less so he who said, "Let me be ruined, it is best for me," had his judgement diseased through his passion. But the sayings of incontinence are quite different, as

Such is the state of the soul of the continent person due to their conflicting condition. For this reason, they see incontinence as something less than a vice, but intemperance as a complete vice. Intemperance, having both its desires and reasoning corrupted, is led by one to seek disgraceful things,229 while the other, through poor judgment, agrees to desire, losing even the awareness of wrongdoing. In contrast, incontinence keeps its judgment intact through reason but is overwhelmed against its better judgment by an overpowering passion, which is how it differs from intemperance. In one case, reason is dominated by passion; in the other, it doesn't even resist. In the former, it opposes its desires even while pursuing them; in the latter, it actively supports and leads them. In one situation, it willingly participates in wrongdoing; in the other, it does so reluctantly. One rushes willingly into disgraceful acts, while the other abandons honorable behavior against its will. And just as there is a difference in their actions, so too is the distinction clear in their words. The intemperate offer expressions like, "What enjoyment or pleasure in life is there without golden Aphrodite? I’d rather die than stop caring about these things!" Another might say, "Eating, drinking, and enjoying Aphrodite's gifts are everything; all other things are just extras," as if they completely surrender to pleasure, having been utterly corrupted by it. Even the one who said, "Let me be ruined; it’s best for me," displayed judgment that was impaired by passion. However, the statements of those lacking self-control are quite different, as

"My nature drives me to act against my better judgment,"230

and

and

"Unfortunately, it is a curse and a burden for us mere mortals," "To know what is good, but not to seek it out." 231

And again—

And again—

"My anger drives me forward, is out of control, "It's just a sandy hook in the face of a storm."

Here he compares not badly to a sandy hook, a sorry kind of anchor, the soul that is unsettled and has no steady reason, but surrenders judgment through flabbiness and feebleness. And not unlike this image are the lines,

Here he compares well to a sandy hook, a pretty weak anchor, the soul that is restless and lacks a solid reason, but gives up judgment due to laziness and weakness. And similarly to this image are the lines,

"As some ship docked and secured to the shore, "If the wind blows, the cables can't handle it."

By cables he means the judgement which resists what is disgraceful, though sometimes it gives way under a tremendous storm of passion. For indeed it is with full sail that the intemperate man is borne on to pleasure by his desires, and surrenders himself to them, and even plays the part of pilot to the vessel; whereas the incontinent man is dragged sidelong into the disgraceful, and is its victim, as it were, while he desires eagerly to resist and overcome his passion, as Timon bantered Anaxarchus: "The recklessness and frantic energy of Anaxarchus to rush anywhere seemed like a dog's courage, but he being aware of it was miserable, so people said, but his voluptuous nature ever plunged him into excesses again, nature which even 108most sophists are afraid of." For neither is the wise man continent but temperate, nor the fool incontinent but intemperate; for the one delights in what is good, and the other is not vexed at what is bad. Incontinence, therefore, is a mark of a sophistical soul, endued with reason which cannot abide by what it knows to be right.

By "cables," he means the judgment that resists what is shameful, although it sometimes gives way during an overwhelming surge of emotion. Indeed, it's full sail that the intemperate person is carried toward pleasure by their desires and lets go of themselves, even taking on the role of captain of the ship; while the incontinent person gets dragged sideways into disgrace and becomes its victim, even though they desperately want to resist and overcome their urges—just like Timon teased Anaxarchus: "The wildness and frantic energy of Anaxarchus to rush anywhere seemed like a dog's bravery, but since he was aware of it, he was miserable, as people said. Still, his indulgent nature always plunged him back into excesses again, a nature that even 108 most philosophers fear." For a wise person is not incontinent but temperate, and a fool is not incontinent but intemperate; the wise finds joy in what is good, while the fool is not bothered by what is bad. Therefore, incontinence is a sign of a sophistical soul, equipped with reason but unable to stick to what it knows is right.

§ vii. Such, then, are the differences between incontinence and intemperance, and continence and temperance have their counterpart and analogous differences; for remorse and trouble and annoyance are companions of continence, whereas in the soul of the temperate person there is everywhere such equability and calm and soundness, by which the unreasoning is adjusted and harmonized to reason, being adorned with obedience and wonderful mildness, that looking at it you would say with the poet, "At once the wind was laid, and a wondrous calm ensued, for the god allayed the fury of the waves,"232 reason having extinguished the vehement and furious and frantic motions of the desires, and making those which nature necessarily requires sympathetic and obedient and friendly and co-operative in carrying purposes out in action, so that they do not outrun or come short of reason, or behave disorderly and disobediently, but that every appetite is tractable, "as sucking foal runs by the side of its dam."233 And this confirms the saying of Xenocrates about true philosophers, that they alone do willingly what all others do unwillingly at the compulsion of the law, as dogs are turned away from their pleasures by a blow, or cats by a noise, looking at nothing but their danger. It is clear then that there is in the soul a perception of such a generic and specific difference in relation to the desires, as of something fighting against and opposing them. But some say that there is no radical distinction difference or variance between reason and passion, but that there is a shifting of one and the same reason from one to the other, which escapes our notice owing to the sharpness and quickness of the change, so that we do not see at a glance that desire and repentance, anger and fear, giving way to what is disgraceful 109through passion, and recovery from the same, are the same natural property of the soul. For desire and fear and anger and the like they consider only depraved opinions and judgements, not in one portion of the soul only but in all its leading principles, inclinations and yieldings, and assents and impulses, and generally speaking in its energies soon changed, like the sallies of children, whose fury and excessive violence is unstable by reason of their weakness. But these views are, in the first place, contrary to evidence and observation; for no one observes in himself a change from passion to judgement, and from judgement back to passion; nor does anyone cease from loving when he reflects that it would be well to break the affair off and strive with all his might against it; nor again, does he put on one side reflection and judgement, when he gives way and is overcome by desire. Moreover, when he resists passion by reason, he does not escape passion altogether; nor again, when he is mastered by passion does he fail to discern his fault through reason: so that neither by passion does he abolish reason, nor does he by reason get rid of passion, but is tossed about to and fro alternately between passion and reason. And those who suppose that the leading principle in the soul is at one time desire, and at another time reason in opposition to desire, are not unlike people who would make the hunter and the animal he hunts one and the same person, but alternately changing from hunter to animal, from animal to hunter. As their eyesight is plainly deficient, so these are faulty in regard to their perceptions, seeing that they must perceive in themselves not a change of one and the same thing, but a difference and struggle between two opposing elements. "What then," say they, "does not the deliberative element in a man often hold different views, and is it not swayed to different opinions as to expediency, and yet it is one and the same thing?" Certainly, I reply; but the case is not similar. For the rational part of the soul does not fight against itself, but though it has only one faculty, it makes use of different reasonings; or rather the reasoning is one, but employs itself in different subjects as on different matter. And so there is neither pain in reasonings without passion, nor are men compelled, as it were, to choose something contrary to110 their judgement, unless indeed some passion, as in a balance, secretly predominates in the scale. For this often happens, reason not opposing reason, but ambition, or contention, or favour, or jealousy, or fear opposing reason, that we do but think there is a difference between two reasons, as in the line, "They were ashamed to refuse, and feared to accept,"234 or, "To die in battle is dreadful but glorious; but not to die, though cowardly, is more pleasant." Moreover, in judgements about contracts passions come in and cause the greatest delay; and in the councils of kings those who speak to ingratiate themselves do not favour either of the two cases, but give themselves up to passion without regard to what is expedient; and so those that rule in aristocracies do not allow orators to be pathetic in their pleadings. For reasoning without passion has a direct tendency to justice, while if passion is infused, a contest and difference is excited between pleasure and pain on the one hand, and judgement and justice on the other. For otherwise how is it that in philosophical speculations people are with little pain frequently induced by others to change their opinions, and even Aristotle himself and Democritus and Chrysippus have rejected without trouble or pain, and even with pleasure, some of the opinions which they formerly advocated? For no passion stands in the way in the theoretic and scientific part of the soul, and the unreasoning element is quiet and gives no trouble therein. And so reason gladly inclines to the truth, when it is evident, and abandons error; for in it, and not in passion, lies a willingness to listen to conviction and to change one's opinions on conviction. But the deliberations and judgements and arbitrations of most people as to matters of fact being mixed up with passion, give reason no easy or pleasant access, as she is held fast and incommoded by the unreasonable, which assails her through pleasure, or fear, or pain, or desire. And the decision in these cases lies with sense which has dealings with both passion and reason, for if one gets the better of the other the other is not destroyed, but only dragged along by force in spite of its resistance. For he who is dissatisfied with himself for 111falling in love calls in reason to his aid to overcome his passion, for both reason and passion are in his soul, and he perceives they are contrary one to the other, and violently represses the inflammatory one of the two. On the other hand, in deliberations and speculations without passion (such as the contemplative part of the soul is most conversant with), if they are evenly balanced no decision takes place, but the matter is left in doubt, which is a sort of stationary position of the mind in conflicting arguments. But should there be any inclination to one of the two sides, the most powerful opinion carries the day, yet without giving pain or creating hostility. And, generally speaking, when reason seems opposed to reason, there is no perception of two distinct things, but only of one under different phases, whereas when the unreasoning has a controversy with reason, since there can be no victory or defeat without pain, forthwith they tear the soul in two,235 and make the difference between them apparent.

§ vii. So, these are the differences between lack of self-control and overindulgence, and self-restraint and moderation have their own similar distinctions. Remorse, anxiety, and annoyance accompany self-restraint, while in the mind of a moderate person, there is a consistent calmness and stability. This balance allows irrational impulses to be aligned and harmonized with reason, exhibiting obedience and remarkable mildness, leading one to agree with the poet, "As soon as the wind calmed down, a wonderful stillness followed, for the god soothed the wildness of the waves,"232 as reason extinguishes intense and chaotic desires, making natural needs sympathetic, obedient, friendly, and cooperative in carrying out actions, so they neither exceed nor fall short of reason, nor act disorderly or disobediently, but each desire is manageable, "like a foal running alongside its mother."233 This supports Xenocrates' saying about true philosophers, that they alone willingly do what others do reluctantly under the pressure of the law, like dogs being driven away from their pleasures with a strike, or cats startled by a noise, focused solely on their threats. It is clear that within the soul there is an awareness of both a general and specific difference in relation to desires, indicating something that fights against and opposes them. Some argue that there is no fundamental distinction or variation between reason and emotion, but that one and the same reason shifts back and forth, which goes unnoticed due to the speed and sharpness of the transition, such that we don't see at once that desire and regret, anger and fear, yielding to what is disgraceful, are simply related aspects of the same natural property of the soul. Desire, fear, and anger are seen as merely distorted opinions and judgments that affect all leading principles, inclinations, agreements, and impulses throughout the soul, generally behaving erratically, similar to children whose fury and excessive energy are unstable because of their weakness. However, such views contradict clear evidence; for no one recognizes within themselves a transition between passion and judgment, or vice versa; nor does anyone stop loving when they reflect on the benefits of ending the relationship and strive against it; nor does one set aside reflection and judgment when overwhelmed by desire. Additionally, when resisting passion with reason, one does not completely escape passion; nor when succumbing to passion does one become blind to their faults through reason. Thus, neither does passion eliminate reason, nor does reason erase passion; instead, one is continuously tossed between the two. Those who believe that the primary force in the soul alternates between desire and reason in opposition are like people who would think the hunter and the hunted are the same person, switching back and forth between the two. Their vision is clearly flawed, as they fail to recognize a struggle between two opposing forces rather than a change in one single thing. "But then," they argue, "doesn't the deliberative part of a person frequently hold different opinions and is swayed by different views on what is best, and isn't it still the same thing?" Certainly, I reply; however, the situation is different. The rational part of the soul does not conflict with itself; although it has a single faculty, it employs various forms of reasoning; or rather, the reasoning is consistent but applies to different subjects. Therefore, there’s no discomfort in reasoning without emotion, nor are individuals forcefully compelled to choose against their judgment, unless some emotion, like in a balance, subtly tips the scale. This often occurs when not reason opposing reason, but ambition, competition, favoritism, jealousy, or fear oppose reason, leading us to mistakenly believe there's a difference between two rational arguments, as expressed in the line, "They felt ashamed to refuse, and afraid to accept,"234 or, "To die in battle is dreadful but glorious; yet not to die, though cowardly, is more pleasant." Furthermore, emotions can complicate contract negotiations, causing significant delays; among kings, those who try to persuade others to gain favor do not support either side but are swept away by their emotions, disregarding what is sensible; hence, rulers in aristocracies do not permit speakers to employ emotional pleas. This is because reasoning without emotion is naturally directed toward justice, whereas the infusion of emotion stirs up a conflict between pleasure and pain on one side, and judgment and justice on the other. Otherwise, how is it that during philosophical discussions people can easily be swayed to change their opinions, and even Aristotle, Democritus, and Chrysippus have comfortably abandoned some views they once championed? Because there’s no emotion hindering the theoretical and scientific aspect of the soul, and the irrational part remains calm without interference. Thus, reason naturally leans towards the truth when it’s clear and abandons falsehood; for it is within reason, not passion, that one finds the willingness to accept new ideas and change beliefs upon reflection. However, the deliberations, judgments, and decisions of most people regarding factual matters are mixed with emotion, preventing reason from easily and pleasantly gaining access as it is constrained and troubled by the irrational, which assaults it through pleasure, fear, pain, or desire. The resolution in these cases relies on sensation, which interacts with both emotion and reason; if one prevails over the other, neither is destroyed but merely dragged along against its will. For someone unhappy with themselves for falling in love will call upon reason to help overcome their passion, as both reason and emotion coexist in their soul, and they recognize they are in opposition, forcefully suppressing the more inflamed of the two. On the other hand, in deliberations and speculations free from passion (like the contemplative part of the soul is most engaged with), if they are evenly matched, no decision is made, leaving the matter uncertain, which is a kind of mental standstill in conflicting arguments. Yet if there’s a leaning towards one side, the more powerful opinion will prevail without causing pain or animosity. Generally, when reason seems to oppose reason, there isn't an awareness of two distinct entities, but merely of one under different circumstances; whereas when the irrational clashes with reason, since victory or defeat comes with pain, they immediately split the soul apart,235 making the difference between them clear.

§ viii. And not only from their contest, but quite as much from their agreement, can we see that the source of the passions is something quite distinct from that of reason. For since236 one may love either a good and excellent child or a bad and vicious one, and be unreasonably angry with one's children or parents, yet in behalf of them show a just anger against enemies or tyrants; as in the one case there is the perception of a difference and struggle between passion and reason, so in the other there is a perception of persuasion and agreement inclining, as it were, the scale, and giving their help. Moreover a good man marrying a wife according to the laws is minded to associate and live with her justly and soberly, but as time goes on, his intercourse with her having engendered a strong passion for her, he perceives that his love and affection are increased by reason. Just so, again, young fellows falling in with kindly teachers at first submit themselves to them out of necessity and emulation for learning, but end by loving them, and instead of being their pupils and scholars become and get the title of their lovers. The same is the case in cities in respect to good 112magistrates, and neighbours, and connections by marriage; for beginning at first to associate with one another from necessity and propriety, they afterwards go on to love almost insensibly, reason drawing over and persuading the emotional element. And he who said—

§ viii. We can see that the source of our passions is different from that of our reasoning, not just from their conflicts, but also from their agreements. For example, one can love a good and wonderful child or a bad and troublesome one, and feel unreasonable anger towards one's own children or parents, yet also display justified anger towards enemies or tyrants. In one case, there’s a clear struggle between passion and reason, while in the other, there’s a sense of agreement that tips the balance and provides support. Additionally, a good man who marries according to the law intends to live fairly and responsibly with his wife, but over time, as their relationship deepens and he grows passionate, he realizes that his love and affection are enhanced by reason. Similarly, young men who encounter supportive teachers initially follow them out of necessity and a desire to learn, but eventually develop love for them, transitioning from being students to being called their admirers. The same holds true in communities regarding good 112leaders, neighbors, and family connections; they start interacting out of necessity and propriety but gradually begin to love one another almost without realizing it, as reason subtly influences and persuades their feelings. And he who said—

"There are two types of shame, one that's not harmful, "The other is a sad burden to a family,"237

is it not clear that he felt this emotion in himself often contrary to reason and detrimental by hesitation and delay to opportunities and actions?

Isn't it obvious that he often felt this emotion within himself, even though it was unreasonable and harmful due to hesitation and delaying opportunities and actions?

§ ix. In a certain sense yielding to the force of these arguments, they call shame modesty, pleasure joy, and timidity caution; nor would anyone blame them for this euphemism, if they only gave those specious names to the emotions that are consistent with reason, while they gave other kinds of names to those emotions that resist and do violence to reason. But whenever, though convicted by their tears and tremblings and changes of colour, they avoid the terms pain and fear, and speak of bitings and states of excitement, and gloss over the passions by calling them inclinations, they seem to contrive evasions and flights from facts by names sophistical, and not philosophical. And yet again they seem to use words rightly when they call those joys and wishes and cautions not apathies but good conditions of the mind. For it is a happy disposition of the soul when reason does not annihilate passion, but orders and arranges it in the case of temperate persons. But what is the condition of worthless and incontinent persons, who, when they judge they ought to love their father and mother better than some boy or girl they are enamoured of, yet cannot, and yet at once love their mistress or flatterer, when they judge they ought to hate them? For if passion and judgement were the same thing, love and hate would immediately follow the judging it right to love and hate, whereas the contrary happens, passion following some judgements, but declining to follow others. Wherefore they acknowledge, the facts compelling them to do so, that every judgement is not passion, but only that judgement that is provocative of violent and excessive impulse: ad113mitting that judgement and passion in us are something different, as what moves is different from what is moved. Even Chrysippus himself, by his defining in many places endurance and continence to be habits that follow the lead of reason, proves that he is compelled by the facts to admit, that that element in us which follows absolutely is something different from that which follows when persuaded, but resists when not persuaded.

§ ix. In a way, by giving in to these arguments, they refer to shame as modesty, pleasure as joy, and timidity as caution; no one would really blame them for this softer language if they only applied such misleading terms to emotions that align with reason and used different terms for those emotions that fight against reasoning. However, when they avoid saying pain and fear, using phrases like “bitings” and “states of excitement,” and try to soften the passions by calling them inclinations, they seem to create excuses and escape from reality with terms that are more deceptive than philosophical. Yet they also appear to use language correctly when they describe those joys, wishes, and cautions not as apathies but as positive states of mind. It’s a good state of the soul when reason doesn’t obliterate passion but instead organizes and channels it in people who are moderate. But what about the state of those who are worthless and uncontrolled? They may realize that they should love their parents more than a crush, yet they can't help it and still feel drawn to their lover or flatterer, even when they think they should hate them. If passion and judgment were the same, love and hate would immediately follow the decision to love or hate, but the opposite occurs; passion follows some judgments but not others. Thus, they recognize, due to the circumstances pushing them to do so, that not every judgment is a passion, but only those judgments that provoke intense and excessive impulses. This acknowledges that judgment and passion within us are different, just as what moves is distinct from what is moved. Even Chrysippus, by defining endurance and self-control as habits that follow reason in various contexts, shows he is compelled by the evidence to accept that what follows purely is different from what follows when convinced, but resists when not persuaded.

§ x. Now as to those who make all sins and offences equal, it is not now the occasion to discuss if in other respects they deviate from truth: but as regards the passions238 they seem to go clean contrary to reason and evidence. For according to them every passion is a sin, and everyone who grieves, or fears, or desires, commits sin. But in good truth it is evident that there are great differences between passions, according as one is more or less affected by them. For who would say that the craven fear of Dolon239 was not something very different from the fear of Ajax, "who retreated with his face to the enemy and at a foot's pace, drawing back slowly knee after knee"?240 Or who would say that the grief of Plato at the death of Socrates was identical with the grief of Alexander at the death of Clitus, when he attempted to lay violent hands on himself? For grief is beyond measure intensified by falling out against expectation: and the calamity that comes unlooked for is more painful than that we may reasonably fear: as if when expecting to see one's friend basking in prosperity and admiration, one should hear that he had been put to the torture, as Parmenio heard about Philotas. And who would say that the anger of Magas against Philemon was equal to that of Nicocreon against Anaxarchus? Both Magas and Nicocreon had been insulted, but whereas Nicocreon brayed Anaxarchus to death with iron pestles and made mincemeat of him, Magas contented himself with bidding the executioner lay his naked sword on Philemon's neck, and then let him go.241 And so Plato called anger the 114nerves of the mind, since it can be both intensified by bitterness, and slackened by mildness. To evade these and similar arguments, they deny that intensity and excess of passion are according to judgement, wherein is the propensity to fault, but maintain that they are bites and contractions and diffusings capable of increase or diminution through the unreasoning element. And yet it is evident that there are differences as regards judgements; for some judge poverty to be no evil, while others judge it to be a great evil, and others again the very greatest evil, insomuch that they even throw themselves headlong down rocks and into the sea on account of it. Again as to death, some think it an evil only in depriving us of good things, whereas others think it so in regard to eternal punishments and awful torments in the world below. Health again is valued by some as natural and advantageous, while to others it seems the greatest blessing of life, in comparison with which they reckon little either of wealth or children or "royal power that makes one equal to the gods," and at last come to think even virtue useless and unprofitable, if health be absent. Thus it is clear that even with regard to judgements themselves some err more, some less. But I shall bring no further proof of this now, but this one may assume therefrom, that they themselves concede that the unreasoning element is something different from judgement, in that they allow that by it passion becomes greater and more violent, and while they quarrel about the name and word they give up the thing itself to those who maintain that the emotional and unreasoning part of the soul is distinct from the reasoning and judging element. And in his treatise on Anomaly,242 Chrysippus, after telling us that anger is blind, and frequently does not let one see what is obvious, frequently also obscures what we do get a sight of, goes on to say, "The encroachment of the passions blots out reason, and makes things look different to what they should look, violently forcing people on unreasonable acts." And he quotes as witness Menander, who says, "Alas! 115poor me, wherever were my brains in my body at the time when I chose that line of conduct, and not this?" And Chrysippus proceeds, "Though every living creature endowed with reason is naturally inclined to use reason and to be governed by it on every occasion, yet often do we reject it, being borne away by a more violent impulse;" thus admitting what results from the difference between passion and reason. For otherwise it is ridiculous, as Plato says, to argue that a man is sometimes better than himself, sometimes worse, sometimes master of himself, sometimes not master of himself.

§ x. Now, as for those who consider all sins and wrongdoings to be the same, this isn’t the time to discuss if they deviate from truth in other ways: however, when it comes to passions238, they seem to completely contradict reason and evidence. According to them, every passion is a sin, and anyone who feels grief, fear, or desire is committing a sin. But the truth is that there are significant differences between passions, depending on how strongly one is affected by them. Who would claim that the cowardly fear of Dolon239 is the same as the fear of Ajax, "who retreated with his face to the enemy, moving back slowly one knee at a time"?240 Or who would argue that Plato’s grief over Socrates' death is the same as Alexander's grief for Clitus, who almost took his own life in despair? Grief is intensely magnified when it comes unexpectedly: the disaster that arrives out of the blue is more painful than what we might reasonably fear, like when one expects to see a friend thriving in success and admiration, only to hear they’ve been tortured, as Parmenio learned about Philotas. And who would say that Magas's anger towards Philemon is equal to Nicocreon's anger towards Anaxarchus? Both Magas and Nicocreon faced insults, but while Nicocreon brutally killed Anaxarchus with iron pestles, Magas only instructed the executioner to put his naked sword on Philemon's neck and then let him go.241 So, Plato referred to anger as the 114nerves of the mind, since it can be intensified by bitterness and softened by gentleness. To sidestep these and similar arguments, they deny that the intensity and excess of passion relate to judgement, where the inclination to err lies, and assert instead that they are mere impulses and automatic reactions that can increase or decrease through irrational elements. Yet it’s clear that there are differences in judgement; some consider poverty no evil, others see it as a great evil, while some see it as the worst of all evils, to the point of throwing themselves off cliffs or into the sea over it. Regarding death, some believe it’s only an evil because it takes away good things, while others think it’s a moral evil due to eternal punishments and horrific torments in the afterlife. For health, some value it as a natural and beneficial state, while others regard it as the greatest blessing of life, leaving little importance to wealth, children, or "royal power that makes one equal to the gods," to the extent that they even view virtue as useless and unprofitable without health. Thus, it’s clear that even regarding judgements themselves, some err more and some less. However, I won’t present further evidence on this now, but one can conclude that they themselves admit that the irrational part is different from judgement, as they recognize that it can amplify passion and make it more aggressive. While they debate the terminology, they concede the reality to those who argue that the emotional and irrational part of the soul is distinct from the rational and judgemental aspect. In his work on Anomaly,242 Chrysippus notes that anger is blind and often obscures obvious truths, making things appear different than they actually are and forcefully pushing individuals toward unreasonable actions. He cites Menander, who laments, "Oh! 115poor me, where was my head when I chose that path instead of this one?" Chrysippus adds, "While every rational being is naturally inclined to use reason and be guided by it in all situations, we often reject it, swayed by stronger impulses," thereby acknowledging the difference between passion and reason. Otherwise, as Plato points out, it’s absurd to say that a person is sometimes better than themselves, sometimes worse, sometimes in control of themselves, and sometimes not.

§ xi. For how is it possible that the same person can be both better and worse than himself, both master of himself and not master, unless everyone is in some way twofold, having in himself both a better and worse self? For so he that makes the baser element subject to the better has self-control and is a superior man, whereas he who allows the nobler element of the soul to follow and be subservient to the incorrigible and unreasoning element, is inferior to what he might be, and is called incontinent, and is in an unnatural condition. For by nature it appertains to reason, which is divine, to rule and govern the unreasoning element, which has its origin from the body, which it also naturally resembles and participates in its passions, being placed in it and mixed up with it, as is proved by the impulses to bodily delights, which are always fierce or languid according to the changes of the body. And so it is that young men are keen and vehement in their desires, being red hot and raging from their fulness of blood and animal heat, whereas with old men the liver, which is the seat of desire, is dried up and weak and feeble, and reason has more power with them than passion which decays with the body. This principle also no doubt characterizes the nature of animals as regards the sexual appetite. For it is not of course from any fitness or unfitness of opinions, that some animals are so bold and resolute in the presence of danger, while others are helpless and full of fear and trembling; but this difference of emotion is produced by the workings of the blood and spirit and body, the emotional part growing out of the flesh, as from a root, and carrying along with it its quality and temperament. And that the body of man116 sympathizes with and is affected by the emotional impulses is proved by pallors, and blushings, and tremblings, and palpitations of the heart, as on the other hand by an all-pervading joy in the hope and expectation of pleasures. But whenever the mind is by itself and unmoved by passion, the body is in repose and at rest, having no participation or share in the working of the intellect, unless it involve the emotional, or the unreasoning element call it in. So that it is clear that there are two distinct parts of the soul differing from one another in their faculties.

§ xi. How can it be that the same person can be both better and worse than themselves, both in control and not in control, unless everyone has a dual nature, containing both a better self and a worse self? The person who brings their lower self under the control of their higher self exhibits self-control and is considered a better person, while someone who lets their higher self be led by the reckless and irrational part is falling short of their potential, often seen as lacking self-control, and is in an unnatural state. Naturally, it is the divine aspect of reason that should rule over the irrational part, which originates from the body, resembling it and sharing in its passions, being intertwined with it. This is evident in the strong urges for physical pleasures, which fluctuate in intensity according to the body's state. For instance, young people often have intense and passionate desires, driven by their high levels of blood and vitality, while older individuals experience a decline in desire as their liver, the source of need, weakens, allowing reason to take over more than passion, which diminishes with age. This idea also reflects the behavior of animals regarding their sexual instincts. The boldness of some animals in the face of danger and the timidity of others isn’t due to their thoughts or beliefs but arises from the influence of blood, spirit, and body, with emotional tendencies stemming from the flesh, like roots, carrying their unique qualities and temperaments. Moreover, the human body shows that it responds to emotional impulses, as indicated by signs like paleness, blushing, trembling, and heart palpitations, contrasting with an overarching joy that comes from hopes and expectations of pleasure. However, when the mind is solely engaged and unaffected by passion, the body remains calm and at rest, not participating in the workings of the intellect, unless it draws in emotional or irrational elements. Therefore, it's clear that there are two distinct parts of the soul that differ in their functions.

§ xii. And generally speaking of all existing things, as they themselves admit and is clear, some are governed by nature, some by habit, some by an unreasoning soul, some by a soul that has reason and intelligence. Man too participates in all this, and is subject to all those differences here mentioned, for he is affected by habit, and nourished by nature, and uses reason and intelligence. He has also a share of the unreasoning element, and has the principle of passion innate in him, not as a mere episode in his life but as a necessity, which ought not therefore to be entirely rooted out, but requires care and attention. For the function of reason is no Thracian or Lycurgean one to root up and destroy all the good elements in passion indiscriminately with the bad, but, as some genial and mild god, to prune what is wild, and to correct disproportion, and after that to train and cultivate the useful part. For as those who are afraid to get drunk do not pour on the ground their wine, but mix it with water, so those who are afraid of the disturbing element in passion do not eradicate passion altogether but temper it. Similarly with oxen and horses people try to restrain their mad bounds and restiveness, not their movements and powers of work, and so reason makes use of the passions when they have become tame and docile, not by cutting out the sinews or altogether mutilating the serviceable part of the soul. For as Pindar says, "The horse to the chariot, and the ox to the plough, while he that meditates destruction for the boar must find a staunch hound."243 But much more useful than these are the whole tribe of passions when they wait on reason and 117run parallel to virtue. Thus moderate anger is useful to courage, and hatred of evil to uprightness, and righteous indignation against those who are fortunate beyond their deserts, when they are inflamed in their souls with folly and insolence and need a check. And no one if they wished could pluck away or sever244 natural affection from friendship, or pity from philanthropy, or sympathy both in joy and grief from genuine goodwill. And if those err who wish to banish love because of erotic madness, neither are they right who blame all desire because of love of money, but they act like people who refuse to run because they might stumble, or to throw because they might throw wide of the mark, or object to sing altogether because they might make a false note. For as in sounds music does not create melody by the banishment of sharps and flats, and as in bodies the art of the physician procures health not by the doing away of cold and heat but by their being blended in due proportions and quantities, so is victory won in the soul by the powers and motions of the passions being reduced by reason to moderation and due proportion. For excessive grief or fear or joy in the soul (I speak not of mere joy grief or fear), resembles a body swollen or inflamed. And Homer when he says excellently,

§ xii. Generally speaking about everything that exists, as they themselves acknowledge and as is obvious, some things are driven by nature, some by habit, some by an unreasoning spirit, and some by a reasoning and intelligent soul. Humans are part of this too, influenced by habit, nurtured by nature, and capable of reason and intelligence. They also share an element of unreasoning, possessing the innate principle of passion, which isn't just a random part of life but a necessity that shouldn’t be completely eliminated but should be managed and cared for. The role of reason isn’t to indiscriminately eradicate all the beneficial aspects of passion along with the harmful ones, but rather, like a gentle and kind deity, to refine what is untamed, correct imbalances, and then nurture and develop the useful aspects. Just as those who fear getting drunk don’t pour their wine on the ground but mix it with water, those who are cautious of the disruptive nature of passion don’t completely eliminate it but temper it. Similarly, people try to restrain the wildness and restlessness of oxen and horses, not their abilities to move and work. Reason utilizes passions when they are controlled and manageable, without severing the connections or entirely maiming the functional aspects of the soul. As Pindar says, "The horse to the chariot, and the ox to the plough, while he that meditates destruction for the boar must find a staunch hound." But much more valuable are all the various passions when they align with reason and 117 complement virtue. For instance, moderate anger supports courage, a hatred of injustice promotes integrity, and righteous indignation against those who seem to thrive despite their faults, when their souls are filled with folly and arrogance, serves as necessary restraint. No one, if they truly wished, could separate natural affection from friendship, or compassion from philanthropy, or shared joy and grief from true goodwill. Those who wish to eliminate love because of its obsessive nature are just as mistaken as those who blame all desire because of greed; they behave like someone who refuses to run for fear of stumbling, or to throw something because they might miss the target, or refrain from singing altogether because they might hit a wrong note. Just as music doesn’t create harmony by eliminating sharps and flats, and a physician promotes health not by removing cold and heat but by achieving the right balance, victory in the soul is attained when the powers and movements of passion are moderated and balanced by reason. Extreme grief, fear, or joy in the soul (not just simple joy, grief, or fear) resembles an inflamed or swollen body. And Homer articulates this excellently,

"The brave man's color never changes, nor" Is he very scared? __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

does not take away all fear but only excessive fear, that bravery may not become recklessness, nor confidence foolhardiness. So also in regard to pleasure we must do away with excessive desire, and in regard to vengeance with excessive hatred of evil. For so in the former case one will not be apathetic but temperate, and in the latter one will not be savage or cruel but just. But if the passions were entirely removed, supposing that to be possible, reason would become in many duller and blunter, like the pilot in the absence of a storm. And no doubt it is from having noticed this that legislators try to excite in states ambition and emulation among their townsmen, and stir up and increase their courage and pugnacity against enemies 118by the sound of trumpets and flutes. For it is not only in poems, as Plato says, that he that is inspired by the Muses, and as it were possessed by them, will laugh to shame the plodding artist, but also in fighting battles passion and enthusiasm will be irresistible and invincible, such as Homer makes the gods inspire men with, as in the line,

does not eliminate all fear but only excessive fear, so that bravery doesn’t turn into recklessness, and confidence doesn’t become foolhardiness. Similarly, regarding pleasure, we need to eliminate excessive desire, and in relation to vengeance, excessive hatred of evil. This way, one will be temperate rather than apathetic, and one will be just instead of savage or cruel. However, if passions were completely removed—if that were even possible—reason would likely become duller and less sharp, much like a pilot during calm weather. It’s probably because of this understanding that lawmakers aim to instill ambition and competition among their citizens, and to stir up courage and aggression against enemies 118 with the sounds of trumpets and flutes. For it’s not just in poetry, as Plato mentions, that someone inspired by the Muses will outperform the hard-working artist; in battles, passion and enthusiasm become unstoppable and unbeatable, just as Homer illustrates how the gods inspire men, as noted in the line,

"By saying this, he instilled great strength in Hector, "The leader of the people."246

and,

and,

"He's not crazy like this without the divine,"247

as if the god had added passion to reason as an incitement and spur. And you may see those very persons, whose opinions I am combating, frequently urging on the young by praises, and frequently checking them by rebukes, though pleasure follows the one, pain the other. For rebukes and censure produce repentance and shame, the one bringing grief, the other fear, and these they mostly make use of for purposes of correction. And so Diogenes, when Plato was being praised, said, "What has he to vaunt of, who has been a philosopher so long, and yet never gave pain to anyone?" For one could not say, to use the words of Xenocrates, that the mathematics are such handles to philosophy as are the emotions of young men, such as shame, desire, repentance, pleasure, pain, ambition, whereon reason and the law laying a suitable grip succeed in putting the young man on the right road. So that it was no bad remark of the Lacedæmonian tutor, that he would make the boy entrusted to his charge pleased with what was good and displeased with what was bad,248 for a higher or nobler aim cannot be proposed in the education fit for a freeborn lad.

as if the god had infused passion into reason as motivation and encouragement. You can see those same people, whose ideas I’m challenging, often pushing young people with compliments and frequently holding them back with criticism, even though pleasure comes from the first and pain from the second. Rebukes and criticism lead to regret and embarrassment, one causing sorrow, the other fear, and these are mainly used for corrective purposes. So, Diogenes, when Plato was being praised, remarked, "What does he have to boast about, having been a philosopher for so long and still never causing pain to anyone?" Because one cannot claim, to echo Xenocrates, that math is as crucial to philosophy as young men's emotions like shame, desire, regret, pleasure, pain, and ambition, where reason and law can effectively guide the young man on the right path. So it was a wise comment from the Spartan teacher that he aimed to make the boy in his care appreciate what is good and dislike what is bad,248 since a higher or nobler goal is not appropriate for the education of a freeborn lad.

219 See "Meno," p. 72, A.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See "Meno," p. 72, A.

220 Omitting ἕτερα, which Reiske justly suspects.

220 Leaving out ἕτερα, which Reiske rightly questions.

221 Reading πρῶτον with Wyttenbach.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading first with Wyttenbach.

222 Homer, "Odyssey," xix. 208-212.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Odyssey," 19.208-212.

223 As in the story in "Gil Blas" of the person who, after eating a ragout of rabbit, was told it was a ragout of cat.—Book X. chapter xii.

223 As in the story in "Gil Blas" about the person who, after eating a rabbit stew, found out it was actually cat stew. —Book X. chapter xii.

224 As to Amœbeus, see Athenæus, p. 623. D.

224 Regarding Amœbeus, refer to Athenæus, p. 623. D.

225 "Iliad," xvi. 167.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xvi. 167.

226 Generally speaking ἔθος is the habit, ἦθος the moral character generated by habit. The former is Aristotle's ἐνέργεια, the latter his ἕξις.

226 Generally speaking, ἔθος refers to habit, while ἦθος represents the moral character developed through habit. The former aligns with Aristotle's ἐνέργεια, and the latter corresponds to his ἕξις.

227 I have adopted, it will be seen, the suggestion of Wyttenbach, "τῷ λογισμῷ mutandum videtur in τὸν χαλινόν."

227 I've taken on the suggestion from Wyttenbach, "It seems necessary to change the reason to the restraint."

228 Sophocles, "Œdipus Tyrannus," 4, 5. Quoted by our author again "On Abundance of Friends," § vi.

228 Sophocles, "Oedipus Rex," 4, 5. Quoted by our author again in "On Abundance of Friends," § vi.

229 Reading with "Reiske," ἐξάγεται πρὸς τὸ ἐπιθυμεῖν τὰ αἰσχρά.

229 Reading with "Reiske," it means to be led towards desiring shameful things.

230 In the "Chrysippus" of Euripides, Fragm.

230 In the "Chrysippus" by Euripides, Fragm.

231 Compare Romans viii. 19.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare Romans 8:19.

232 "Odyssey," xii. 168, 169.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," 12. 168, 169.

233 This line is from Simonides, and is quoted again in "How one may be aware of one's Progress in Virtue," § xiv.

233 This quote is from Simonides and is referenced again in "How to Recognize Your Progress in Virtue," § xiv.

234 "Iliad," vii. 93.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," vii. 93.

235 Reading with Reiske, εἰς δύο.

Reading with Reiske, into two.

236 Reading ἐτεὶ with Reiske and Wyttenbach.

236 Reading etei with Reiske and Wyttenbach.

237 Euripides, "Hippolytus" 385, 386.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Hippolytus" 385, 386.

238 Reading with Reiske πάθεσι for πλείοσι.

238 Reading with Reiske suffering for more.

239 See "Iliad," x. 374, sq.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See "Iliad," x. 374, sq.

240 "Iliad," xi. 547.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 11.547.

241 "De Anaxarchi supplicio nota res. v. Menage ad Diog. Läert. 9, 59. De Magae, reguli Cyrenarum, adversus Philemonem lenitate v. De Cohibenda Ira, § ix."—Reiske.

241 "The situation around Anaxarchus's punishment is well-documented. See Menage in Diogenes Laertius 9, 59. Regarding Magas, the ruler of Cyrene, in relation to Philemon's leniency. See On Controlling Anger, § ix."—Reiske.

242 "Celebres fuere quondam Chrysippi sex libri περὶ τῆς κατὰ τὰς λήξεις ἀνωμαλίας, in quibus auctore Varrone, propositum habuit ostendere, similes res dissimilibus verbis et similibus dissimiles esse notatas vocabulis. v. Menage ad Diog. Läert. 7, 192."—Reiske.

242 "Chrysippus once had six famous books on the irregularities in the endings, in which, with Varro as the author, he aimed to show that similar things are marked by different words while dissimilar things are marked by similar words. See Menage on Diogenes Laertius 7, 192."—Reiske.

243 Compare "On Contentedness of Mind," § xiii.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare "On Mindfulness," __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__

244 Reading with Reiske, ἀποῤῥήξειεν.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading with Reiske, aput lexicis.

245 "Iliad," xiii. 284, 285.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 13.284, 285.

246 "Iliad," xv. 262.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xv. 262.

247 "Iliad," v. 185.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," Book 5.

248 Compare "That Virtue may be Taught," § ii.

248 Compare "That Virtue can be Taught," § ii.


HOW ONE MAY BE AWARE OF ONE'S PROGRESS IN VIRTUE.

§ i. What amount of argument, Sossius Senecio, will make a man know that he is improving in respect to virtue, 119if his advances in it do not bring about some diminution in folly, but vice, weighing equally with all his good intentions, "acts like the lead that makes the net go down?"249 For neither in music nor grammatical knowledge could anyone recognize any improvement, if he remained as unskilful in them as before, and had not lost some of his old ignorance. Nor in the case of anyone ill would medical treatment, if it brought no relief or ease, by the disease somewhat yielding and abating, give any perception of improvement of health, till the opposite condition was completely brought about by the body recovering its full strength. But just as in these cases there is no improvement unless, by the abatement of what weighs them down till they rise in the opposite scale, they recognize a change, so in the case of those who profess philosophy no improvement or sign of improvement can be supposed, unless the soul lay aside and purge itself of some of its imperfection, and if it continue altogether bad until it become absolutely good and perfect. For indeed a wise man cannot in a moment of time change from absolute badness to perfect goodness, and suddenly abandon for ever all that vice, of which he could not during a long period of time divest himself of any portion. And yet you know, of course, that those who maintain these views frequently give themselves much trouble and bewilderment about the difficulty, that a wise man does not perceive that he has become wise, but is ignorant and doubtful that in a long period of time by little and little, by removing some things and adding others, there will be a secret and quiet improvement, and as it were passage to virtue. But if the change were so great and sudden that the worst man in the morning could become the best man at night, or should the change so happen that he went to bed vicious and woke up in the morning wise, and, having dismissed from his mind all yesterday's follies and errors, should say,

§ i. What kind of reasoning, Sossius Senecio, would help someone realize they are improving in virtue, 119 if their progress doesn’t reduce their foolishness and if vice, balancing out all their good intentions, "acts like the lead that makes the net go down?"249 Just as with music or grammar, no one can recognize any improvement if they remain as unskilled as before and haven’t lost some of their old ignorance. Similarly, in the case of someone who is sick, medical treatment wouldn’t indicate improvement if it doesn’t provide some relief or if the illness doesn’t ease up; real improvement in health only becomes clear when the body regains its strength. Just like in these situations, there’s no real improvement for those who study philosophy unless the soul lets go of and cleanses itself of some imperfections; if it remains entirely flawed until it becomes completely good and perfect, no progress can be seen. After all, a wise person can't instantaneously transform from completely bad to perfectly good, or suddenly rid themselves forever of vices they’ve struggled with for a long time. Yet, you know that people who believe this often get confused and worried about the idea that a wise person doesn’t realize they’ve become wise. They doubt that over a long period, through gradual changes—removing some things and adding others—there can be a quiet improvement towards virtue. But if the transformation were so dramatic and swift that the worst person in the morning could turn into the best person by night, or if someone went to bed with vices, woke up wise in the morning, and dismissed all the follies and mistakes of the day before, they would say,

"Fake dreams, go away, you didn’t mean anything back then!"250

who on earth could be ignorant of so great a change happening to himself, of virtue blazing forth so completely 120all at once? I myself am of opinion that anyone, like Caeneus,251 who, according, to his prayer, got changed from a woman into a man, would sooner be ignorant of the transformation, than that a man should become at once, from a cowardly and senseless person with no powers of self-control, brave and sensible and perfect master of himself, and should in a moment change from a brutish life to a divine without being aware of it.

Who on earth could be unaware of such a huge change happening to him, of virtue shining so brightly all at once? In my opinion, anyone, like Caeneus, who, according to his wish, was transformed from a woman into a man, would be less likely to miss that transformation than a man who suddenly shifts from being cowardly and foolish, lacking self-control, to becoming brave, sensible, and a perfect master of himself, changing in a moment from a brutish existence to a divine one without even realizing it. 120

§ ii. That was an excellent observation, Measure the stone by the mason's rule, not the rule by the stone.252 But the Stoics, not applying dogmas to facts but facts to their own preconceived opinions, and forcing things to agree that do not by nature, have filled philosophy with many difficulties, the greatest of which is that all men but the perfect man are equally vicious, which has produced the enigma called progress, one little short of extreme folly, since it makes those who have not at once under its guidance given up all passions and disorders equally unfortunate as those who have not got rid of a single vile propensity. However they are their own confuters, for while they lay down in the schools that Aristides was as unjust as Phalaris, and Brasidas as great a craven as Dolon, and Plato actually as senseless as Meletus, in life and its affairs they turn away from and avoid one class as implacable, while they make use of the others and trust them in most important matters as most worthy people.

§ ii. That was a great observation: measure the stone by the mason's rule, not the rule by the stone.252 But the Stoics, instead of applying facts to reality, impose their own preconceived opinions on facts, forcing things to fit together that naturally do not. This has made philosophy riddled with challenges, the biggest being the idea that all men, except the perfect one, are equally flawed, leading to the confusing notion of progress, which is almost absurd. It suggests that those who haven't completely abandoned all passions and flaws are just as unfortunate as those who haven't overcome any of their bad habits. However, their own arguments contradict them—while they claim in theory that Aristides was as unjust as Phalaris, and Brasidas as cowardly as Dolon, and that Plato was actually just as foolish as Meletus, in real life they avoid one group as unforgivable while relying on the others, trusting them with the most important matters as if they were the most reliable people.

§ iii. But we who see that in every kind of evil, but especially in a disordered and unsettled state of mind, there are degrees of more and less (so that the progress made differs in different cases, badness abating, as a shadow flees away, under the influence of reason, which calmly illuminates and cleanses the soul), cannot consider it unreasonable to think that the change will be perceived, as people who come up out of some ravine can take note of the progress they make upwards. Look at the case from the following point of view first. Just as mariners sailing with full sail over the gaping253 ocean measure the course 121they have made by the time they have taken and the force of the wind, and compute their progress accordingly, so anyone can compute his progress in philosophy by his continuous and unceasing course, by his not making many halts on the road, and then again advancing by leaps and bounds, but by his quiet and even and steady march forward guided by reason. For the words of the poet, "If to a little you keep adding a little, and do so frequently, it will soon be a lot,"254 are not only true of the increase of money, but are universally applicable, and especially to increase in virtue, since reason invokes to her aid the enormous force of habit. On the other hand the inconsistencies and dulnesses of some philosophers not only check advance, as it were, on the road, but even break up the journey altogether, since vice always attacks at its leisure and forces back whatever yields to it.255 The mathematicians tell us that planets, after completing their course, become stationary; but in philosophy there is no such intermission or stationary position from the cessation of progress, for its nature is ever to be moving and, as it were, to be weighed in the scales, sometimes being overweighted by the good preponderating, sometimes by the bad. If, therefore, imitating the oracle given to the Amphictyones by the god, "to fight against the people of Cirrha every day and every night,"256 you are conscious that night and day you ever maintain a fierce fight against vice, not often relaxing your vigilance, or long off your guard, or receiving as heralds to treat of peace257 the pleasures, or idleness, or stress of business, you may reasonably go forward to the future courageously and confidently.

§ iii. We understand that in every type of evil, especially in a chaotic and unsettled state of mind, there are varying degrees (meaning progress can differ greatly in different situations, with negativity fading, like a shadow disappearing, under the calming guidance of reason that illuminates and purifies the soul). Therefore, it’s reasonable to expect that changes can be recognized, similar to how people emerging from a ravine can notice their ascent. Let’s consider the issue from this perspective: just as sailors navigating with full sails across an open ocean assess their journey based on the time spent and the wind’s strength, and calculate their progress accordingly, anyone can evaluate their advancement in philosophy through a consistent and unbroken path—by not frequently stopping to rest or making large leaps, but by steadily moving forward, guided by reason. The poet’s words, "If you keep adding a little to a little, and do this often, it will soon become a lot," are true not only for increasing wealth but universally applicable, especially for growing in virtue, since reason calls upon the powerful force of habit. Conversely, the inconsistencies and dullness of some philosophers not only halt progress but can even derail the journey entirely, as vice easily takes advantage and pushes back whatever it can. Mathematicians say that planets, after completing their orbits, become stationary. However, in philosophy, there’s no pause or standstill in advancing; its essence is to keep moving, often weighed on a scale that sometimes tips toward good and sometimes toward bad. Thus, if you emulate the oracle's advice to the Amphictyones to "fight against the people of Cirrha day and night," and you are aware that you constantly engage in a fierce battle against vice day and night, rarely letting your guard down or accepting peace talks from pleasure, idleness, or busyness, then you can confidently and bravely move forward into the future.

§ iv. Moreover, if there be any intermissions in philosophy, and yet your later studies are firmer and more continuous than your former ones, it is no bad indication that your sloth has been expelled by labour and exercise; for the contrary is a bad sign, when after a short time your lapses 122from zeal become many and continuous, as if your zeal were dying away. For as in the growth of a reed, which shoots up from the ground finely and beautifully to an even and continuous height, though at first from its great intervals it is hindered and baffled in its growth, and afterwards through its weakness is discouraged by any breath of air, and though strengthened by many and frequent joints, yet a violent wind gives it commotion and trembling, so those who at first make great launches out into philosophy, and afterwards find that they are continually hindered and baffled, and cannot perceive that they make any progress, finally get tired of it and cry off. "But he who is as it were winged,"258 is by his simplicity borne along to his end, and by his zeal and energy cuts through impediments to his progress, as merely obstacles on the road. As it is a sign of the growth of violent love, not so much to rejoice in the presence of the loved one, for everyone does that, as to be distressed and grieved at his absence,259 so many feel a liking for philosophy and seem to take a wonderful interest in the study, but if they are diverted by other matters and business their passion evaporates and they take it very easily. "But whoever is strongly smitten with love for his darling"260 will show his mildness and agreeableness in the presence of and joint pursuit of wisdom with the loved one, but if he is drawn away from him and is not in his company you will see him in a stew and ill at ease and peevish whether at work or leisure, and unreasonably forgetful of his friends, and wholly impelled by his passion for philosophy. For we ought not to rejoice at discourses only when we hear them, as people like perfumes only when they smell them, and not to seek or care about them in their absence, but in the same condition as people who are hungry and thirsty are in if torn away from food and drink, we ought to follow after true proficiency in philosophy, whether marriage, or wealth, or friendship, or military service, strike in and produce a separation. For just as more 123is to be got from philosophy, so much the more does what we fail to obtain trouble us.

§ iv. Furthermore, if there are breaks in your philosophy studies, and your more recent efforts are steadier and more consistent than your earlier ones, it's a good sign that your laziness has been replaced with hard work and effort. Conversely, if you find that your enthusiasm quickly fades and your lapses become frequent, it's a troubling sign that your passion is dwindling. Just like a reed that grows tall and straight from the ground but is hindered in its early stages and easily swayed by the slightest breeze, those who initially make bold strides in philosophy but then face constant obstacles and feel stuck often end up losing interest and quitting. But someone who is genuinely passionate is driven toward their goals and, fueled by their enthusiasm and determination, pushes through any challenges that come their way. Just as it's a sign of intense love not just to enjoy being with the one you love but to feel distressed by their absence, many show an interest in philosophy and briefly engage in its study, but if they're distracted by other pursuits their passion quickly fades and they become indifferent. However, someone deeply in love with wisdom will be kind and engaged when pursuing knowledge together with their beloved. When separated from that connection, you'll notice them restless, uneasy, and even irritable, regardless of whether they're working or relaxing. They'll forget their friends and be completely driven by their love for philosophy. We shouldn't just find joy in philosophical discussions when we're hearing them, like how people enjoy fragrances while they're present, but we should feel a yearning for them even when they're absent, much like a hungry or thirsty person is driven to chase after food and drink. We should actively seek true mastery in philosophy, regardless of whether marriage, wealth, friendship, or military duties interfere and cause separation. Just as the potential rewards from philosophy are greater, so too does the absence of what we could gain trouble us more.

§ v. Either precisely the same as this or very similar is Hesiod's261 very ancient definition of progress in virtue, namely, that the road is no longer very steep or arduous, but easy and smooth and level, its roughness being toned down by exercise, and casting the bright light of philosophy on doubt and error and regrets, such as trouble those who give themselves to philosophy at the outset, like people who leave a land they know, and do not yet descry the land they are sailing to. For by abandoning the common and familiar, before they know and apprehend what is better, they frequently flounder about in the middle and are fain to return. As they say the Roman Sextius, giving up for philosophy all his honours and offices in Rome, being afterwards discontented with philosophy from the difficulties he met with in it at first, very nearly threw himself out of window. Similarly they relate of Diogenes of Sinope,262 when he began to be a philosopher, that the Athenians were celebrating a festival, and there were public banquets and shows and mutual festivities, and drinking and revelling all night, and he, coiled up in a corner of the market-place intending to sleep, fell into a train of thought likely seriously to turn him from his purpose and shake his resolution, for he reflected that he had adopted without any necessity a toilsome and unusual kind of life, and by his own fault sat there debarred of all the good things. At that moment, however, they say a mouse stole up and began to munch some of the crumbs of his barley-cake, and he plucked up his courage and said to himself, in a railing and chiding fashion, "What say you, Diogenes? Do your leavings give this mouse a sumptuous meal, while you, the gentleman, wail and lament because you are not getting drunk yonder and reclining on soft and luxurious couches?" Whenever such depressions of mind are not frequent, and the mind when they take place quickly recovers from them, after having put them to flight as it were, and when such annoyance and distraction is easily 124got rid of, then one may consider one's progress in virtue as a certainty.

§ v. Hesiod's very old definition of progress in virtue is either exactly the same or very similar to this. He describes the journey as no longer steep or difficult but easy, smooth, and level, with the rough edges softened by practice. Philosophy shines a light on doubts, errors, and regrets that trouble beginners in philosophy, much like people who leave a familiar place without seeing the new land they’re heading towards. By letting go of what’s known before realizing what’s better, they often find themselves lost in between and want to go back. For example, it’s said that the Roman Sextius, after giving up all his honors and positions in Rome to pursue philosophy, became so frustrated with the difficulties he encountered that he nearly threw himself out of a window. The same is said of Diogenes of Sinope, who, when he first started as a philosopher, found himself during a festival in Athens, surrounded by public celebrations, banquets, and revelry. As he curled up in a corner of the marketplace to sleep, he fell into thoughts that might have shaken his commitment, questioning why he had chosen such a hard and unusual lifestyle, depriving himself of all the good things. Just then, a mouse came up and started nibbling on the crumbs from his barley-cake, prompting him to regain his courage and scold himself, saying, “What do you say, Diogenes? Are your leftovers a feast for this mouse while you, the gentleman, are whining because you’re not partying over there and lounging on soft, luxurious couches?” If such feelings of despair are rare and quickly fade away, then one can confidently consider their progress in virtue assured.

§ vi. And since not only the things that in themselves shake and turn them in the opposite direction are more powerful in the case of weak philosophers, but also the serious advice of friends, and the playful and jeering objections of adversaries bend and soften people, and have ere now shaken some out of philosophy altogether, it will be no slight indication of one's progress in virtue if one takes all this very calmly, and is neither disturbed nor aggravated by people who tell us and mention to us that some of our former comrades are flourishing in kings' courts, or have married wives with dowries, or are attended by a crowd of friends when they come down to the forum to solicit some office or advocateship. He that is not moved or affected by all this is already plainly one upon whom philosophy has got a right hold; for it is impossible that we should cease to be envious of what most people admire, unless the admiration of virtue was strongly implanted in us. For over-confidence may be generated in some by anger and folly, but to despise what men admire is not possible without a true and steady elevation of mind. And so people in such a condition of mind, comparing it with that of others, pride themselves on it, and say with Solon, "We would not change virtue for wealth, for while virtue abides, wealth changes hands, and now one man, now another, has it."263 And Diogenes compared his shifting about from Corinth to Athens, and again from Thebes to Corinth, to the different residences of the King of Persia, as his spring residence at Susa, his winter residence at Babylon, and his summer residence in Media. And Agesilaus said of the great king, "How is he better than me, if he is not more upright?" And Aristotle, writing to Antipater about Alexander, said, "that he ought not to think highly of himself because he had many subjects, for anyone who had right notions about the gods was entitled to think quite as highly of himself." And Zeno, observing that Theophrastus was admired for the number of his pupils,264 said, 125"His choir is, I admit, larger than mine, but mine is more harmonious."

§ vi. Not only are the things that shake us and push us in the opposite direction more influential for less secure philosophers, but also the serious advice from friends and the teasing objections from opponents can sway and weaken us. Some have even been completely driven away from philosophy by these influences. It would be a notable sign of one's growth in virtue if one could remain calm in the face of this, unaffected and unbothered by those who remind us that some of our former peers are thriving in royal courts, have married wealthy spouses, or are surrounded by friends when they go to the forum to seek a position or legal representation. A person who remains unmoved by all of this is clearly someone who has truly embraced philosophy; for it is impossible to stop feeling envy for what most people admire unless we have a strong appreciation for virtue instilled within us. Overconfidence may come from anger and stupidity, but to belittle what people admire is not possible without a genuine and stable elevation of spirit. Those in this mindset, comparing themselves to others, take pride in it and echo Solon's words, "We would not trade virtue for wealth, for while virtue remains, wealth changes hands, with one man having it now and another having it later."263 Diogenes compared his travels from Corinth to Athens, then back to Thebes and again to Corinth, to the shifting residences of the Persian King, with his spring home in Susa, winter home in Babylon, and summer home in Media. Agesilaus remarked about the great king, "How is he better than me if he is not more virtuous?" Aristotle, in a letter to Antipater about Alexander, stated that one should not think too highly of himself just because he has many subjects—anyone with a proper understanding of the gods has every right to hold himself in high regard. Observing that Theophrastus was admired for the size of his student body, Zeno remarked, 125"His group is indeed larger than mine, but mine is more harmonious."

§ vii. Whenever then, by thus comparing the advantages of virtue with external things, you get rid of envies and jealousies and those things which fret and depress the minds of many who are novices in philosophy, this also is a great indication of your progress in virtue. Another and no slight indication is a change in the style of your discourses. For generally speaking all novices in philosophy adopt most such as tend to their own glorification; some, like birds, in their levity and ambition soaring to the height and brightness of physical things; others like young puppies, as Plato265 says, rejoicing in tearing and biting, betake themselves to strifes and questions and sophisms; but most plunging themselves into dialectics immediately store themselves for sophistry; and some collect sentences266 and histories and go about (as Anacharsis said he saw the Greeks used money for no other purpose but to count it up), merely piling up and comparing them, but making no practical use of them. Applicable here is that saying of Antiphanes, which someone applied to Plato's pupils. Antiphanes said playfully that in a certain city words were frozen directly they were spoken, owing to the great cold, and were thawed again in the summer, so that one could then hear what had been said in the winter. So he said of the words which were spoken by Plato to young men, that most of them only understood them late in life when they were become old men. And this is the condition people are in in respect to all philosophy, until the judgement gets into a sound and healthy state, and begins to adapt itself to those things which can produce character and greatness of mind, and to seek discourses whose footsteps turn inwards rather than outwards, to borrow the language of Æsop.267 For as Sophocles said he had first toned down the pompous style of Æschylus, then his harsh and over-artificial method, and had in the third 126place changed his manner of diction, a most important point and one that is most intimately connected with the character, so those who go in for philosophy, when they have passed from flattering and artificial discourses to such as deal with character and emotion, are beginning to make genuine and modest progress in virtue.

§ vii. Whenever you compare the benefits of virtue with external things, and you free yourself from envy and jealousy—things that trouble and distress many beginners in philosophy—this is a significant sign of your growth in virtue. Another important sign is a shift in how you express yourself. Generally, beginners in philosophy tend to adopt styles that seek their own praise; some, like birds, in their lightness and ambition, aspire to the heights and shine of physical things; others, like young puppies, as Plato265 describes, take joy in arguing and questioning, engaging in debates and sophistry; but most dive into dialectics, just preparing themselves for sophistry right away; some gather phrases266 and histories and travel around (as Anacharsis said he observed the Greeks used money for nothing more than counting it), simply stacking and comparing them without using them practically. This is where the saying from Antiphanes comes into play, which someone associated with Plato's students. Antiphanes joked that in a certain city, words froze as soon as they were spoken due to the extreme cold, and were thawed in the summer, allowing one to hear what was said in the winter. He remarked that most of the words spoken by Plato to young people were only understood much later in life, when they had become old men. And this reflects the state of people concerning all philosophy until their judgment matures and aligns with what builds character and greatness of mind, seeking discussions that turn inward rather than outward, to borrow from Æsop.267 Just as Sophocles mentioned he first softened the grand style of Æschylus, then his harsh and overly complicated approach, and in the third 126 place changed his way of speaking—an essential point closely related to character—those who pursue philosophy, after moving from flattering and artificial expressions to those that engage with character and emotion, are beginning to make real and humble progress in virtue.

§ viii. Furthermore, take care, in reading the writings of philosophers or hearing their speeches, that you do not attend to words more than things, nor get attracted more by what is difficult and curious than by what is serviceable and solid and useful. And also, in studying poems or history, let nothing escape you of what is said to the point, which is likely either to correct the character or to calm the passions. For as Simonides says the bee hovers among the flowers "making the yellow honey,"268 while others value and pluck flowers only for their beauty and fragrance, so of all that read poems for pleasure and amusement he alone that finds and gathers what is valuable seems capable of knowledge from his acquaintance with and friendship for what is noble and good.269 For those who study Plato and Xenophon only for their style, and cull out only what is pure and Attic, and as it were the dew and the bloom, do they not resemble people who love drugs for their smell and colour, but care not for them as anodynes or purges, and are not aware of those properties? Whereas those who have more proficiency can derive benefit not from discourses only, but from sights and actions, and cull what is good and useful, as is recorded of Æschylus and other similar kind of men. As to Æschylus, when he was watching a contest in boxing at the Isthmus, and the whole theatre cried out upon one of the boxers being beaten, he nudged with his elbow Ion of Chios, and said, "Do you observe the power of training? The beaten man holds his peace, while the spectators cry out." And Brasidas having caught hold of a mouse among some figs, being bitten by it let it go, and said to himself, "Hercules, there is no creature so small or weak that it will not fight for its life!" 127And Diogenes, seeing a lad drinking water out of the palm of his hand, threw away the cup which he kept in his wallet. So much does attention and assiduous practice make people perceptive and receptive of what contributes to virtue from any source. And this is the case still more with those who mix discourses with actions, who not only, to use the language of Thucydides,270 "exercise themselves in the presence of danger," but also in regard to pleasures and strifes, and judgements, and advocateships, and magistrateships make a display of their opinions, or rather form their opinions by their practice. For we can no more think those philosophers who are ever learning and busy and investigating what they have got from philosophy, and then straightway publish it in the market-place or in the haunt of young men, or at a royal supper-party, any more than we give the name of physicians to those who sell drugs and mixtures. Nay rather such a sophist differs very little at all from the bird described in Homer,271 offering his scholars like it whatever he has got, and as it feeds its callow young from its own mouth, "though it goes ill with itself," so he gets no advantage or food from what he has got for himself.

§ viii. Furthermore, when reading the writings of philosophers or listening to their speeches, be careful not to focus more on the words than on the ideas, nor get drawn in by what is complex and intriguing at the expense of what is practical, solid, and useful. Also, when studying poems or history, pay attention to anything said that is relevant and likely to either improve your character or soothe your emotions. As Simonides puts it, the bee hovers among the flowers "making the yellow honey,"268 while others only value and pick flowers for their beauty and scent. Similarly, among those who read poems for enjoyment, it is only the one who identifies and collects what is valuable who seems truly knowledgeable due to their connection with what is noble and good.269 Those who study Plato and Xenophon just for their style, picking only what is 'pure and Attic' like dew or bloom, are like those who appreciate drugs only for their aroma and color, without knowing their properties as effective remedies. In contrast, those with greater understanding can gain benefits not only from discussions but from experiences and actions as well, pulling out what is good and useful, as shown in the stories of Æschylus and others like him. For instance, when Æschylus was watching a boxing match at the Isthmus and the audience reacted when one boxer lost, he nudged Ion of Chios and said, "Do you see the power of training? The beaten man stays quiet while the spectators shout." And when Brasidas caught a mouse among some figs, it bit him, so he let it go and thought, "Hercules, there's no creature so small or weak that it won't fight for its life!" 127 Diogenes, on seeing a boy drinking water from his hand, tossed aside the cup he carried. This shows how much attention and consistent practice can make people aware and receptive to what fosters virtue from any source. This is even more true for those who combine discussions with actions, who not only, as Thucydides puts it,270 "prepare themselves in the face of danger," but also regarding pleasures, conflicts, judgments, and roles in leadership, express their opinions or rather develop their views through practice. We can't consider those philosophers who are always learning, busy investigating what they've gained from philosophy, and then immediately sharing it in public spaces or among young people, or at royal banquets, to be real philosophers, just as we wouldn't call those who sell drugs and mixtures real physicians. Rather, such a sophist is not much different from the bird mentioned in Homer,271 offering whatever it has to its students like a mother bird feeding its chicks from its beak, "though it goes poorly for itself," gaining no benefit from what it has gathered for itself.

§ ix. We must therefore see to it that our discourse be serviceable to ourselves, and that it may not appear to others to be vain-glorious or ambitious, and we must show that we are as willing to listen as to teach, and especially must we lay aside all disputatiousness and love of strife in controversy, and cease bandying fierce words with one another as if we were contending with one another at boxing, and leave off rejoicing more in smiting and knocking down one another than in learning and teaching. For in such cases moderation and mildness, and to commence arguing without quarrelsomeness and to finish without getting into a rage, and neither to be insolent if you come off best in the argument, nor dejected if you come off worst, is a sufficient sign of progress in virtue. Aristippus was an excellent example of this, when overcome in argument by the 128sophistry of a man, who had plenty of assurance, but was generally speaking mad or half-witted. Observing that he was in great joy and very puffed up at his victory, he said, "I who have been vanquished in the argument shall have a better night's rest than my victor." We can also test ourselves in regard to public speaking, if we are not timid and do not shrink from speaking when a large audience has unexpectedly been got together, nor dejected when we have only a small one to harangue to, and if we do not, when we have to speak to the people or before some magistrate, miss the opportunity through want of proper preparation; for these things are recorded both of Demosthenes and Alcibiades. As for Alcibiades, though he possessed a most excellent understanding, yet from want of confidence in speaking he often broke down, and in trying to recall a word or thought that slipped his memory had to stop short.272 And Homer did not deny that his first line was unmetrical,273 though he had sufficient confidence to follow it up by so many other lines, so great was his genius. Much more then ought those who aim at virtue and what is noble to lose no opportunity of public speaking, paying very little attention to either uproar or applause at their speeches.

§ ix. We must ensure our discussions are helpful to us and that we don’t come across as boastful or overly ambitious. We need to show that we are just as eager to listen as we are to teach. Especially, we should avoid being argumentative and combative in debates, stopping the tendency to hurl harsh words at each other as if we’re boxing. We should take more joy in learning and teaching rather than in putting each other down. In such instances, maintaining moderation and kindness, starting conversations without hostility, and ending them without anger, and not being arrogant if we win or downcast if we lose an argument is a clear sign of growth in virtue. Aristippus was a great example of this. When he was outmatched in a debate by a man who was self-assured but generally misguided, he noticed the man was reveling in his victory and remarked, "I who have been defeated in the argument will sleep better than my victor." We can also evaluate ourselves in terms of public speaking—if we’re not shy and don’t shrink back when faced with a large, unexpected audience, and if we don’t feel disheartened by only having a small crowd to speak to. Furthermore, we shouldn’t miss chances to speak in front of people or magistrates due to poor preparation; this has been noted about both Demosthenes and Alcibiades. As for Alcibiades, despite having an exceptional mind, his lack of confidence often led him to falter while speaking, causing him to lose his train of thought. 272 And Homer didn’t deny that his first line was off-meter,273 but he had enough confidence to follow it with many more lines, showcasing his brilliance. Those who strive for virtue and nobility should seize every opportunity for public speaking, paying little attention to either chaos or applause during their speeches.

§ x. And not only ought each to see to his discourses but also to his actions whether he regards utility more than show, and truth more than display. For if a genuine love for youth or maiden seeks no witnesses, but is content to enjoy its delights privately, far more does it become the philosopher and lover of the beautiful, who is conversant with virtue through his actions, to pride himself on his silence, and not to need people to praise or listen to him. As that man who called his maid in the house, and cried out to her, "See, Dionysia, I am angry no longer,"274 so he that does anything agreeable and polite, and then goes and spreads it about the town, plainly shows that he looks for public applause and has a strong propensity to vain-glory, and as yet has no acquaintance with virtue as a reality but only as a dream, restlessly roving about amid 129phantoms and shadows, and making a display of whatever he does as painters display a picture. It is therefore a sign of progress in virtue not merely to have given to a friend or done a good turn to an acquaintance without mentioning it to other people, but also to have given an honest vote among many unjust ones, and to have withstood the dishonourable request of some rich man or of some man in office, and to have been above taking bribes, and, by Zeus, to have been thirsty all night and not to have drunk, or, like Agesilaus,275 to have resisted, though strongly tempted, the kiss of a handsome youth or maiden, and to have kept the fact to oneself and been silent about it. For one's being satisfied with one's own good opinion276 and not despising it, but rejoicing in it and acquiescing in it as competent to see and decide on what is honourable, proves that reason is rooted and grounded within one, and that, to borrow the language of Democritus, one is accustomed to draw one's delights from oneself. And just as farmers behold with greater pleasure those ears of corn which bend and bow down to the ground, while they look upon those that from their lightness stand straight upright as empty pretenders, so also among those young men who wish to be philosophers those that are most empty and without any solidity show the greatest amount of assurance in their appearance and walk, and a face full of haughtiness and contempt that looks down on everybody, but when they begin to grow full and get some fruit from study they lay aside their proud and vain277 bearing. And just as in vessels that contain water the air is excluded, so with men that are full of solid merit their pride abates, and their estimate of themselves becomes a lower one, and they cease to plume themselves on a long beard and threadbare cloak,278 and transfer their training to the mind, and are most severe and austere to themselves, while they are milder in their intercourse with everybody else; and they do not as before 130eagerly snatch at the name and reputation of philosopher, nor do they write themselves down as such, but even if he were addressed by that title by anyone else, an ingenuous young man would say, smiling and blushing, "I am not a god: why do you liken me to the immortals?"279 For as Æschylus says,

§ x. Everyone should pay attention not just to what they say but also to what they do, making sure they value substance over appearance and truth over show. If a real love for a young man or woman doesn't seek an audience but prefers to enjoy its pleasures in private, then it is even more fitting for a philosopher and a lover of beauty—who understands virtue through their actions—to take pride in their silence and not feel the need for others to praise or notice them. Like the man who called his maid and exclaimed, "Look, Dionysia, I'm not angry anymore,"274 someone who does something nice or polite and then tells everyone about it is clearly seeking public approval and has a tendency toward vanity, showing they only know virtue in theory, not in practice, wandering restlessly among 129illusions and shadows, displaying their actions like artists showcase a painting. Therefore, it's a mark of true virtue not just to have done a good deed for a friend without broadcasting it but also to have cast an honest vote among many unfair ones, to have resisted an unethical request from a wealthy person or public official, to reject bribes, and, by Zeus, to have been thirsty all night and not given in to drinking, or, like Agesilaus,275 to have resisted, despite strong temptation, the kiss of a beautiful youth or maiden, keeping that to oneself and remaining silent. Being satisfied with your own good opinion276 and not belittling it, but rather celebrating it as capable of recognizing and making honorable decisions shows that reason is firmly established within you and that, to borrow the words of Democritus, you find joy within yourself. Just as farmers take greater pleasure in ears of corn that bend low, while viewing upright and light ones as empty pretenders, among aspiring young philosophers, those who are the most empty and insubstantial display the most confidence in their demeanor, sporting faces full of arrogance and disdain. However, when they begin to fill out and gain substance from their studies, they shed their proud and vain277 demeanor. Just as air is expelled from vessels holding water, those filled with true merit find their pride diminishing, their self-view becoming more humble, and they stop taking pride in a long beard and worn-out cloak,278 focusing instead on cultivating their minds, being strict and serious with themselves while being gentler with others; they no longer eagerly claim the title of philosopher or write it for themselves. Even if someone else calls them that, a sincere young person would smile and blush, saying, "I'm not a god: why do you compare me to the immortal?"279 As Æschylus states,

I can never confuse the burning eye. Of the young woman who once knew a man, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

so to the young man who has tasted of true progress in philosophy the following lines of Sappho are applicable, "My tongue cleaves to the roof of my month, and a fire courses all over my lean body," and his eye will be gentle and mild, and you would desire to hear him speak. For as those who are initiated come together at first with confusion and noise and jostle one another, but when the mysteries are being performed and exhibited, they give their attention with awe and silence, so also at the commencement of philosophy you will see round its doors much confusion and assurance and prating, some rudely and violently jostling their way to reputation, but he who once enters in, and sees the great light, as when shrines are open to view, assumes another air and is silent and awe-struck, and in humility and decorum follows reason as if she were a god. And the playful remark of Menedemus seems to suit these very well. He said that the majority of those who went to school at Athens became first wise, and then philosophers, after that orators, and as time went on became ordinary kind of people, the more they had to do with learning, so much the more laying aside their pride and high estimate of themselves.

So, for the young man who has truly progressed in philosophy, the following lines from Sappho apply: "My tongue sticks to the roof of my mouth, and a fire runs all over my lean body." His gaze will be gentle and mild, and you would want to hear him speak. Just as those who are initiated initially come together with chaos and noise, bumping into each other, when the mysteries are performed and revealed, they focus with awe and silence. Similarly, at the beginning of philosophy, you'll see a lot of commotion and confidence at its entrance, with some rudely and aggressively pushing their way to fame. But once a person enters and sees the great light, like when shrines are revealed, they adopt a different demeanor and become silent and amazed. In humility and respect, they follow reason as if she were a goddess. Menedemus's playful comment fits this well: he said that most people who went to school in Athens first became wise, then philosophers, then orators, and as time went on, they became just ordinary people, laying aside their pride and high self-worth the more they engaged with learning.

§ xi. Of people that need the help of the physician some, if their tooth ache or even finger smart, run at once to the doctor, others if they are feverish send for one and implore his assistance at their own home, others who are melancholy or crazy or delirious will not sometimes even see the doctor if he comes to their house, but drive him away, or avoid him, ignorant through their grievous disease that they are diseased at all. Similarly of those who have done 131 what is wrong some are incorrigible, being hostile and indignant and furious at those who reprove and admonish them, while others are meeker and bear and allow reproof. Now, when one has done what is wrong, to offer oneself for reproof, to expose the case and reveal one's wrongdoing, and not to rejoice if it lies hid, or be satisfied if it is not known, but to make confession of it and ask for interference and admonishment, is no small indication of progress in virtue. And so Diogenes said that one who wished to do what was right ought to seek either a good friend or red-hot enemy, that either by rebuke or mild entreaty he might flee from vice. But as long as anyone, making a display of dirt or stains on his clothes, or a torn shoe, prides himself to outsiders on his freedom from arrogance, and, by Zeus, thinks himself doing something very smart if he jeers at himself as a dwarf or hunchback, but wraps up and conceals as if they were ulcers the inner vileness of his soul and the deformities of his life, as his envy, his malignity, his littleness, his love of pleasure, and will not let anyone touch or look at them from fear of disgrace, such a one has made little progress in virtue, yea rather none. But he that joins issue with his vices, and shows that he himself is even more pained and grieved about them than anyone else, or, what is next best, is able and willing to listen patiently to the reproof of another and to correct his life accordingly, he seems truly to be disgusted at his depravity and resolute to divest himself of it. We ought certainly to be ashamed of and shun every appearance of vice, but he who is more put about by his vice itself than by the bad reputation that ensues upon it, will not mind either hearing it spoken against or even speaking against it himself if it make him a better man. That was a witty remark of Diogenes to a young man, who when seen in a tavern retired into the kitchen: "The more," said he, "you retire, the more are you in the tavern."281 Even so the more a vicious man denies his vice, the more does it 132insinuate itself and master him: as those people really poor who pretend to be rich get still more poor from their false display. But he who is really making progress in virtue imitates Hippocrates, who confessed publicly and put into black and white that he had made a mistake about the sutures of the skull,282 for he will think it monstrous, if that great man declared his mistake, that others might not fall into the same error, and yet he himself for his own deliverance from vice cannot bear to be shown he is in the wrong, and to confess his stupidity and ignorance. Moreover the sayings of Bion and Pyrrho will test not so much one's progress as a greater and more perfect habit of virtue. Bion maintained that his friends might think they had made progress, when they could listen as patiently to abuse as to such language as the following, "Stranger, you look not like a bad or foolish person,"283 "Health and joy go with you, may the gods give you happiness!"284 While as to Pyrrho they say, when he was at sea and in peril from a storm, that he pointed out a little pig that was quietly enjoying some grain that had been scattered about, and said to his companions that the man who did not wish to be disturbed by the changes and chances of life should attain a similar composedness of mind through reason and philosophy.

§ xi. Some people who need a doctor's help, if they have a toothache or a sore finger, rush straight to the doctor. Others who feel feverish call for one and plead for assistance at home. Some, who are depressed, insane, or delirious, might even refuse to see the doctor when he comes to their house, pushing him away or avoiding him, unaware due to their serious illness that they are unwell at all. Similarly, among those who have done wrong, some are unchangeable, becoming hostile and furious at those who criticize and warn them, while others are gentler and accept criticism. Now, when someone has done wrong, the willingness to accept correction, to bring their case to light, and to admit their wrongdoing—rather than feeling pleased if it remains hidden or being satisfied if it's unknown—is a significant sign of progress in virtue. Diogenes once said that someone who wants to do what is right should look for either a good friend or a fierce enemy since either harsh criticism or kind encouragement can help them escape vice. However, those who display dirt or stains on their clothes or wear torn shoes while boasting to others of their modesty, believing they are clever for mocking themselves as a dwarf or hunchback but hiding the deep flaws of their soul—like their envy, spite, smallness, and love of pleasure—and refuse to let anyone examine these issues out of fear of embarrassment, such people have made little to no progress in virtue. On the other hand, someone who confronts their vices and shows that they are more hurt and troubled by them than anyone else, or, at the very least, who is willing and able to patiently listen to the criticism of others and adjust their life accordingly, seems genuinely disgusted by their depravity and determined to rid themselves of it. We should certainly feel ashamed of and avoid any hint of vice; however, someone who is more troubled by their vice itself than by the bad reputation it brings will not mind hearing criticism or even speaking against it themselves if it makes them a better person. Diogenes made a clever remark to a young man who, when spotted in a tavern, retreated to the kitchen: "The more you retreat, the more you're still in the tavern." 281 Similarly, the more a vicious person denies their vice, the more it sneaks in and takes control: just as those who are genuinely poor but pretend to be wealthy only become poorer from their false display. Conversely, someone who is truly progressing in virtue mimics Hippocrates, who publicly admitted and documented his mistake regarding skull sutures,282 because it would seem outrageous that such a great man would acknowledge his mistake to prevent others from making the same one, yet that person can't bear to be shown they are wrong or to confess their ignorance. Moreover, the teachings of Bion and Pyrrho assess not just one's development but also a greater, more refined habit of virtue. Bion believed that his friends could truly feel they had made progress when they could tolerate insults just as calmly as they could welcome remarks like, "Stranger, you don’t seem like a bad or foolish person,"283 and "Health and happiness be with you; may the gods grant you joy!"284 As for Pyrrho, it is said that when he was at sea and in danger from a storm, he pointed out a little pig happily eating some scattered grain and told his companions that anyone wishing to avoid being disturbed by life's uncertainties should attain a similar peace of mind through reason and philosophy.

§ xii. Look also at the opinion of Zeno, who thought that everybody might gauge his progress in virtue by his dreams, if he saw himself in his dreams pleasing himself with nothing disgraceful, and neither doing nor wishing to do anything dreadful or unjust, but that, as in the clear depths of a calm and tranquil sea, his fancy and passions were plainly shown to be under the control of reason. And this had not escaped the notice of Plato,285 it seems, who had earlier expressed in form and outline the part that fancy and unreason played in sleep in the soul that was by nature tyrannical, "for it attempts incest," he says, "with its mother, and procures for itself unlawful meats, and gives 133itself up to the most abandoned desires, such as in daytime the law through shame and fear debars people from." As then beasts of burden that have been well-trained do not, even if their driver let go the reins, attempt to turn aside and leave the proper road, but go forward orderly as usual, pursuing their way without stumbling, so those whose unreason has become obedient and mild and tempered by reason, will not easily wish, either in dreams or in illnesses, to deal insolently or lawlessly through their desires, but will keep to their usual habits, which acquire their power and force by attention. For if the body can by training make itself and its members so subject to control, that the eyes in sorrow can refrain from tears, and the heart from palpitating in fear, and the passions can be calm in the presence of beautiful youths and maidens, is it not far more likely that the training of the passions and emotions of the soul will allay, tame down, and mould their propensities even in dreams? A story is told about the philosopher Stilpo,286 that he thought he saw in a dream Poseidon angry with him because he had not sacrificed an ox to him, as was usual among the Megarians:287 and that he, not a bit frightened, said, "What are you talking about, Poseidon? Do you come here as a peevish boy, because I have not with borrowed money filled the town with the smell of sacrifice, and have only sacrificed to you out of what I had at home on a modest scale?" Then he thought that Poseidon smiled at him, and held out his right hand, and said that for his sake he would give the Megarians a large shoal of anchovies. Those, then, that have such pleasant, clear, and painless dreams, and no frightful, or harsh, or malignant, or untoward apparition, may be said to have reflections of their progress in virtue; whereas agitation and panics and ignoble flights, and boyish delights, and lamentations in the case of sad and strange dreams, are like the waves that break on the coast, the soul not having yet got its proper composure, but being still in course of being moulded by opinions and laws, from which it escapes in dreams as far 134as possible, so that it is once again set free and open to the passions. Do you investigate all these points too, as to whether they are signs of progress in virtue, or of some habit which has already a settled constancy and strength through reason.

§ xii. Also consider Zeno's opinion, who believed that everyone could measure their growth in virtue by their dreams. If in his dreams he saw himself enjoying nothing shameful and not doing or wishing to do anything terrible or unjust, it would show that, like the clear depths of a calm sea, his desires and passions were under the control of reason. Plato also seemed to have noticed this, as he had previously outlined the role that imagination and unreason play in the dreams of a naturally tyrannical soul, saying, "for it attempts incest with its mother, and seeks out illegal pleasures, surrendering itself to the most abandoned desires that, during the day, shame and fear prevent people from pursuing." Just as well-trained pack animals, even if their driver releases the reins, won't stray from the right path but continue steadily on without stumbling, those whose irrational impulses have become obedient, gentle, and tempered by reason will not easily wish to act recklessly or unlawfully in dreams or during illness. Instead, they will stick to their usual behaviors, which gain their strength through focus. If the body can be trained to control itself to the extent that sorrowful eyes hold back tears, a fearful heart can remain calm, and passionate feelings can be subdued in the presence of attractive youths and maidens, isn't it much more probable that training the passions and emotions of the soul will calm and shape their tendencies even in dreams? There's a story about the philosopher Stilpo, who believed he dreamt that Poseidon was angry with him for not sacrificing an ox, as was customary among the Megarians. He, however, was not intimidated and said, "What are you talking about, Poseidon? Do you come here like a petulant child just because I haven't used borrowed money to fill the town with the scent of sacrifice, and have only made a modest offering from what I had at home?" Then he thought Poseidon smiled at him, extended his right hand, and said that for his sake, he would give the Megarians a huge catch of anchovies. Thus, those who have such pleasant, clear, and painless dreams, without frightening, harsh, or malevolent visions, can be said to reflect their progress in virtue. In contrast, feelings of agitation, panic, base escapes, childish pleasures, and lamentation in strange and sad dreams are like waves crashing on the shore—the soul hasn't yet found its proper balance and is still being shaped by beliefs and laws, from which it breaks free in dreams as much as possible, allowing itself to be exposed once again to passions. Be sure to explore all these points regarding whether they indicate progress in virtue or a habit that has already settled with constancy and strength through reason.

§ xiii. Now since entire freedom from the passions is a great and divine thing, and progress in virtue seems, as we say, to consist in a certain remissness and mildness of the passions, we must observe the passions both in themselves and in reference to one another to gauge the difference: in themselves as to whether desire, and fear, and rage are less strong in us now than formerly, through our quickly extinguishing their violence and heat by reason; and in reference to one another as to whether we are animated now by modesty more than by fear, and by emulation more than by envy, and by love of glory rather than by love of riches, and generally speaking whether—to use the language of musicians—it is in the Dorian more than in the Lydian measures that we err either by excess or deficiency,288 whether we are plainer in our manner of living or more luxurious, whether we are slower in action or quicker, whether we admire men and their discourses more than we should or despise them. For as it is a good sign in diseases if they turn aside from vital parts of the body, so in the case of people who are making progress in virtue, when vice seems to shift to milder passions, it is a sign it will soon die out. When Phrynis added to the seven chords two chords more, the Ephors asked him which he preferred to let them cut off, the upper or lower ones;289 so we must cut off both above and below, if we mean to attain, to the mean and to due proportion: for progress in virtue first diminishes the excess and sharpness of the passions,

§ xiii. Since complete freedom from our passions is a significant and divine goal, and our growth in virtue seems to rely on a certain relaxation and gentleness of those passions, we need to observe the passions both on their own and in relation to one another to understand the differences: looking at them individually to see if our desires, fears, and anger are less intense now than they were before, as we quickly cool their intensity and heat with reason; and considering them in relation to one another to determine if we are now motivated more by modesty than by fear, by healthy competition rather than by envy, and by a love for glory instead of a love for wealth; generally speaking, whether—using musical terminology—we tend to be more aligned with the Dorian scale than the Lydian in terms of our excesses or deficits. We also need to reflect on whether we live more simply or lavishly, whether we act more slowly or quickly, and whether we admire or despise people and their ideas more than we should. Just as it's a good sign in sickness if it moves away from crucial parts of the body, when individuals are progressing in virtue, if their vices seem to shift towards milder passions, it's a sign that those vices will soon fade away. When Phrynis added two more strings to the seven, the Ephors asked him which he preferred to remove, the upper or the lower ones; so, we must be willing to remove both the upper and lower extremes if we want to reach balance and proper proportion: because progress in virtue first reduces the excess and sharpness of our passions.

"That intensity that madmen are so passionate about,"

as Sophocles says.

as Sophocles said.

§ xiv. I have already said that it is a very great indication of progress in virtue to transfer our judgement to action, 135and not to let our words remain merely words, but to make deeds of them. A manifestation of this is in the first place emulation as regards what we praise, and a zeal to do what we admire, and an unwillingness either to do or allow what we censure. To illustrate my meaning by an example, it is probable that all Athenians praised the daring and bravery of Miltiades; but Themistocles alone said that the trophy of Miltiades would not let him sleep, but woke him up of a night, and not only praised and admired him, but manifestly emulated and imitated his glorious actions. Small, therefore, can we think the progress we have made, as long as our admiration for those who have done noble things is barren, and does not of itself incite us to imitate them. For as there is no strong love without jealousy, so there is no ardent and energetic praise of virtue, which does not prick and goad one on, and make one not envious but emulous of what is noble, and desirous to do something similar. For not only at the discourses of a philosopher ought we, as Alcibiades said,290 to be moved in heart and shed tears, but the true proficient in virtue, comparing his own deeds and actions with those of the good and perfect man, and grieved at the same time at the knowledge of his own deficiency, yet rejoicing in hope and desire, and full of impulses that will not let him rest, is, as Simonides says,

§ xiv. I’ve already mentioned that a significant sign of progress in virtue is when we turn our judgments into actions, 135 instead of letting our words stay just words; we need to turn them into deeds. A clear example of this is striving to emulate what we admire and feeling a strong desire to act on our praises, while refusing to engage in or accept what we criticize. For instance, it’s likely that all Athenians admired Miltiades’ courage and bravery, but only Themistocles confessed that Miltiades’ trophy kept him awake at night; rather than just praising him, he actively emulated and imitated his remarkable achievements. Thus, we cannot regard our progress as significant if our admiration for those who have accomplished great things remains unproductive and doesn’t inspire us to follow in their footsteps. Just as there’s no deep love without a hint of jealousy, there’s no genuine and passionate praise for virtue that doesn’t spur us on and inspire us—not out of envy, but with the desire to pursue noble actions ourselves. At the philosophical discussions, we shouldn’t just be moved to tears, as Alcibiades suggested,290 but the true person of virtue should reflect on their own actions compared to those of exemplary individuals. They should feel pained by their shortcomings while also filled with hope and drive, unable to find peace, as Simonides puts it.

"Like a foal sucking while running beside its mother,"291

being desirous all but to coalesce with the good man. For it is a special sign of true progress in virtue to love and admire the disposition of those whose deeds we emulate, and to resemble them with a goodwill that ever assigns due honour and praise to them. But whoever is steeped in contentiousness and envy against his betters, let him know that he may be pricked on by a jealous desire for glory or power, but that he neither honours nor admires virtue.

wanting nothing more than to unite with the good person. It's a clear indication of real growth in virtue to love and admire the character of those whose actions we strive to imitate and to reflect their qualities through a genuine appreciation that always gives them the respect and praise they deserve. However, anyone who is consumed by bitterness and envy towards those who are better than them should realize that while they might be driven by a jealous desire for fame or control, they are not honoring or admiring virtue.

§ xv. Whenever, then, we begin so much to love good men that we deem happy, "not only," as Plato292 says, "the temperate man himself, but also the man who hears 136the words that flow from his wise lips," and even admire and are pleased with his figure and walk and look and smile, and desire to adapt ourselves to his model and to stick closely to him, then may we think that we are making genuine progress. Still more will this be the case, if we admire the good not only in prosperity, but like lovers who admire even the lispings and paleness of those in their flower,293 as the tears and dejection of Panthea in her grief and affliction won the affections of Araspes,294 so we fear neither the exile of Aristides, nor the prison of Anaxagoras, nor the poverty of Socrates, nor the condemnation of Phocion, but think virtue worthy our love even under such trials, and join her, ever chanting that line of Euripides,

§ xv. So, when we start to love good people so much that we consider them happy, "not only," as Plato292 puts it, "the self-controlled person himself, but also the person who listens to the wise things that come from his mouth," and we even admire and take pleasure in his appearance, his walk, his look, and his smile, and wish to shape ourselves to be like him and stay close to him, then we can believe we are truly progressing. This will be even more true if we admire the good not just when they are thriving, but like lovers who appreciate even the quirks and frailty of those in their prime,293 just as the tears and sorrow of Panthea in her grief and distress captured the heart of Araspes,294 so we don't fear the exile of Aristides, the imprisonment of Anaxagoras, the poverty of Socrates, or the condemnation of Phocion, but consider virtue deserving of our love even in such hardships, and we join her, always singing that line from Euripides,

"To the noble, everything is good."295

For the enthusiasm that can go so far as not to be discouraged at the sure prospect of trouble, but admires and emulates what is good even so, could never be turned away from what is noble by anybody. Such men ever, whether they have some business to transact, or have taken upon them some office, or are in some critical conjuncture, put before their eyes the example of noble men, and consider what Plato would have done on the occasion, what Epaminondas would have said, how Lycurgus or Agesilaus would have dealt; that so, adjusting and re-modelling themselves, as it were, at their mirrors, they may correct any ignoble expression, and repress any ignoble passion. For as those that have learnt the names of the Idæan Dactyli296 make use of them to banish their fear by quietly repeating them over, so the bearing in mind and remembering good men, which soon suggests itself forcibly to those who have made some progress in virtue in all their emotions and difficulties, keeps them upright and not liable to fall. Let this also then be a sign to you of progress in virtue.

For the kind of enthusiasm that remains undeterred by the certainty of trouble and still admires and strives for what is good can never be swayed from doing what is noble by anyone. These individuals, whether they have tasks to accomplish, hold some position, or face a challenging situation, keep the examples of great individuals in mind. They think about what Plato would have done, what Epaminondas might have said, or how Lycurgus or Agesilaus would have acted; this way, by reflecting on these role models, they can correct any unworthy behavior and suppress any negative feelings. Just as those who have learned the names of the Idæan Dactyli296 use them to calm their fears by quietly repeating them, remembering great people can strongly guide those who have made progress in virtue through their emotions and challenges, helping them stay upright and avoid falling. Let this also be a sign of your growth in virtue.

§ xvi. In addition to this, not to be too much disturbed, 137nor to blush, nor to try and conceal oneself, or make any change in one's dress, on the sudden appearance of a man of distinction and virtue, but to feel confident and go and meet such a one, is the confirmation of a good conscience. It is reported that Alexander, seeing a messenger running up to him full of joy and holding out his right hand, said, "My good friend, what are you going to tell me? Has Homer come to life again?" For he thought that his own exploits required nothing but posthumous fame.297 And a young man improving in character instinctively loves nothing better than to take pride and pleasure in the company of good and noble men, and to display his house, his table, his wife, his amusements, his serious pursuits, his spoken or written discourses; insomuch that he is grieved when he remembers that his father or guardian died without seeing him in that condition in life, and would pray for nothing from the gods so much, as that they could come to life again, and be spectators of his life and actions; as, on the contrary, those that have neglected their affairs, and come to ruin, cannot look upon their relatives even in dreams without fear and trembling.

§ xvi. Furthermore, one shouldn’t be overly disturbed, 137 blush, try to hide, or change their appearance suddenly when encountering an accomplished and virtuous person, but instead feel confident and approach them. This demonstrates a clear conscience. It’s said that when Alexander saw a messenger running towards him, excited and with his hand outstretched, he asked, “My good friend, what news do you bring? Has Homer come back to life?” He believed that his own achievements deserved nothing less than lasting fame.297 A young man striving to improve his character naturally takes pride in being with good and noble people, wanting to showcase his home, his meals, his partner, his hobbies, and his serious interests, to the extent that he feels a deep sadness when he remembers that his father or guardian passed away before seeing him in such a good place in life. He would wish nothing more from the gods than for them to return to life and witness his deeds and accomplishments; in contrast, those who have neglected their responsibilities and fallen into ruin cannot bear to think about their relatives, even in dreams, without feeling fear and dread.

§ xvii. Add, if you please, to what I have already said, as no small indication of progress in virtue, the thinking no wrong-doing small, but being on your guard and heed against all. For as people who despair of ever being rich make no account of small expenses, thinking they will never make much by adding little to little,298 but when hope is nearer fruition, then with wealth increases the love of it,299 so in things that have respect to virtue, not he that generally assents to such sayings as "Why trouble about hereafter?" "If things are bad now, they will some day be better,"300 but the man who pays heed to everything, and is vexed and concerned if vice gets pardon, when it lapses into even the most trifling wrongdoing, plainly shows that he has 138already attained to some degree of purity, and deigns not to contract defilement from anything whatever. For the idea that we have nothing of any importance to bring disgrace upon, makes people inclined to what is little and careless.301 To those who are building a stone wall or coping it matters not if they lay on any chance wood or common stone, or some tombstone that has fallen down, as bad workmen do, heaping and piling up pell-mell every kind of material; but those who have made some progress in virtue, whose life "has been wrought on a golden base,"302 like the foundation of some holy or royal building, undertake nothing carelessly, but lay and adjust everything by the line and level of reason, thinking the remark of Polycletus superlatively good, that that work is most excellent, where the model stands the test of the nail.303

§ xvii. Moreover, if you wish to add to what I have already mentioned, let it be a significant indication of progress in virtue that one considers no wrongdoing to be trivial but remains vigilant against all. Just as people who have given up on becoming wealthy tend to disregard small expenditures, believing that accumulating little by little won’t lead to much,298 when hope for wealth draws nearer, the desire for it increases,299 so in matters related to virtue, it’s not the person who casually agrees with sayings like "Why worry about the future?" or "If things are bad now, they’ll get better someday,"300 but rather the individual who pays attention to everything and feels disturbed and anxious if vice receives forgiveness, even for the slightest misdeeds, who clearly demonstrates that he has 138already reached a level of purity and doesn’t stoop to be tainted by anything. The notion that we have nothing significant to disgrace us can lead people to engage in minor and careless actions.301 For those constructing a stone wall or coping, it doesn't matter if they throw on any random wood or ordinary stone, or even a fallen tombstone, as careless workers do, piling up all sorts of materials haphazardly; but those who have made some strides in virtue, whose lives "have been built on a golden foundation,"302 like the base of a sacred or royal structure, do nothing thoughtlessly but lay and align everything according to the principles of reason, believing the saying of Polycletus holds true: that the best work is that which stands up to the test of a nail.303

249 See Erasmus, Adagia, "Eadem pensari trutina."

249 See Erasmus, Adagia, "The same weighed in the balance."

250 Euripides, "Iphigenia in Tauris," 569.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Iphigenia in Tauris," 569.

251 See Ovid, "Metamorphoses," xii. 189, sq.

251 See Ovid, "Metamorphoses," book 12, line 189, and following.

252 See Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 1103.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 1103.

253 Compare Shakspere, "Tempest," A. i. Sc. i. 63, "And gape at widest to glut him."

253 Compare Shakespeare, "Tempest," Act 1, Scene 1, 63, "And stare wide open to satisfy him."

254 Hesiod, "Works and Days," 361, 362. Quoted again by our author, "On Education," § 13.

254 Hesiod, "Works and Days," 361, 362. Cited again by our author, "On Education," § 13.

255 "In via ad virtutem qui non progreditur, is non stat et manet, sed regreditur."—Wyttenbach.

255 "On the path to virtue, if one does not move forward, they do not stand still but instead fall back."—Wyttenbach.

256 Adopting the reading of Hercher. See Pausanias, x. 37, where the oracle is somewhat different.

256 Taking the interpretation from Hercher. Check Pausanias, x. 37, where the oracle varies slightly.

257 For the town which parleys surrenders.

257 For the town that negotiates its surrender.

258 From Homer, "Iliad," xix. 386.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ From Homer, "Iliad," Book 19, Line 386.

259 Compare Aristotle, Rhetoric, i. 11. και ἀρχή δὲ τοῦ ἔρωτος γίγνεται αὕτη πᾶσιν, ὅταν μὴ μόνον παρόντος χαίρωσιν, ἀλλὰ και ἀπόντος μεμνημένοι ἔρῶσιν.

259 Compare Aristotle, Rhetoric, i. 11. The beginning of love happens when people are not only happy in each other's presence but also remember and long for each other when they're apart.

260 The line is a Fragment of Sophocles.

260 The line is a quote from Sophocles.

261 See Hesiod, "Works and Days," 289-292.

261 See Hesiod, "Works and Days," 289-292.

262 The well-known Cynic philosopher.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ The famous Cynic philosopher.

263 Bergk. fr. 15. Compare Homer, "Iliad," vi. 339. νίκη δ᾽ ἐπαμείβεται ἄνδρας.

263 Bergk. fr. 15. Compare Homer, "Iliad," vi. 339. Victory moves among men.

264 We are told by Diogenes Läertius, v. 37, that Theophrastus had 2000 hearers sometimes at once.

264 Diogenes Laertius tells us in section 37 that Theophrastus sometimes had 2000 listeners at the same time.

265 "Republic," vii. p. 539, B.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Republic," vii. p. 539, B.

266 Sentences borrowed from some author or other, such, as we still possess from the hands of Hermogenes and Aphthonius; compare the collection of bon-mots of Greek courtesans in Athenæus.

266 Sentences taken from various authors, like those we have from Hermogenes and Aphthonius; see the collection of clever sayings from Greek courtesans in Athenæus.

267 A reference to Æsop's Fable, Λέων και Ἀλώπηξ. Cf. Horace, "Epistles," i. i. 73-75.

267 A reference to Aesop's Fable, "The Lion and the Fox." See Horace, "Epistles," i. i. 73-75.

268 This passage is alluded to also in "On Love to one's Offspring." § ii.

268 This passage is also referenced in "On Love to One's Children." § ii.

269 Madvig's text.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Madvig's text.

270 Thucydides, i. 18.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Thucydides, i. 18.

271 Homer, "Iliad," ix. 323, 324. Quoted also in "On Love to One's Offspring," § ii.

271 Homer, "Iliad," ix. 323, 324. Quoted also in "On Love to One's Offspring," § ii.

272 The remark about Demosthenes has somehow slipped out, as Wyttenbach has suggested.

272 The comment about Demosthenes has somehow gotten overlooked, as Wyttenbach has pointed out.

273 Does this refer to Πηληίαδεω before Ἀχιλῆος in "Iliad," i. 1?

273 Does this refer to Πηληίαδεω before Ἀχιλῆος in "Iliad," i. 1?

274 An allusion to some passage in a Play that has not come down to us.

274 A reference to some part of a play that has not survived.

275 Compare our Author, De Audiendis Poetis, § xi. ὥσπερ ὁ Ἀγησίλαοσ οὐκ ὑπέμεινεν ὑπὸ τοῦ καλοῦ φιληθῆναι προσιόντος.

275 Compare our Author, De Audiendis Poetis, § xi. Just like Agesilaus could not endure to be kissed by the beautiful while it was approaching.

276 Reading with Madvig and Hercher, τὸ γὰρ αὺτὸν, sq.

276 Reading with Madvig and Hercher, the same thing, sq.

277 Literally cork-like, so vain, empty. So Horace, "levior cortice," "Odes," iii. 9, 22.

277 Literally cork-like, so superficial, empty. So Horace, "lighter than bark," "Odes," iii. 9, 22.

278 Marks of a philosopher among the ancients. Compare our Author, "How one may discern a flatterer from a friend," § vii.

278 Signs of a philosopher from ancient times. See our Author, "How to tell a flatterer from a friend," § vii.

279 "Odyssey," xvi. 187.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," xvi. 187.

280 Æschylus, "Toxotides," Fragm. 224. Quoted again by our author, "On Love," § xxi.

280 Aeschylus, "Toxotides," Fragm. 224. Cited again by our author, "On Love," § xxi.

281 "Turpe habitum fuisse in caupona conspici, et hoc exemplo apparet, et alia sunt indicia. Isocrates Orat. Areopagitica laudans antiquorum Atheniensium mores, p. 257: ἐν καπηλείῳ δὲ φαγεῖν ἢ πιεῖν οὐδεὶς ἃν οἰκέτης ἐπιεικὴς ἐτὸλμησε: quem locum citans Athenæus alia etiam adfert xiii. p. 566, F."—Wyttenbach.

281 "It was considered shameful to be seen in a tavern, and this example shows it, along with other signs. Isocrates, in his work *Areopagitica*, praises the customs of the ancient Athenians, p. 257: ἐν καπηλείῳ δὲ φαγεῖν ἢ πιεῖν οὐδεὶς ἃν οἰκέτης ἐπιεικὴς ἐτὸλμησε: Athenæus, citing this passage, also refers to others in xiii. p. 566, F."—Wyttenbach.

282 Wyttenbach compares Quintilian, "Institut. Orat." iii. 6, p. 255: "Nam et Hippocrates clarus arte medicinæ videtur honestissime fecisse, qui quosdam errores suos, ne posteri errarent, confessus est."

282 Wyttenbach compares Quintilian, "Institut. Orat." iii. 6, p. 255: "For even Hippocrates, renowned for his medical skill, seems to have done wisely by admitting some of his mistakes so that future generations would not repeat them."

283 Homer, "Odyssey," vi. 187.

Homer, "Odyssey," vi. 187.

284 Homer, "Odyssey," xxiv. 402.

Homer, "Odyssey," xxiv. 402.

285 Plato, "Republic," ix. p. 571, D.

285 Plato, "Republic," ix. p. 571, D.

286 A somewhat similar story about Stilpo is told in Athenæus, x. p. 423, D.

286 A somewhat similar story about Stilpo is told in Athenæus, x. p. 423, D.

287 So Haupt and Herscher very ingeniously for ἱερεῦσιν.

287 So Haupt and Herscher cleverly for ἱερεῦσιν.

288 Adopting the suggestion of Wyttenbach as to the reading. The Dorian measure was grave and severe, the Lydian soft and effeminate.

288 Following Wyttenbach's suggestion for the reading. The Dorian mode was serious and disciplined, while the Lydian was gentle and more delicate.

289 See our author, "Apophthegmata Laconica," p. 220 C.

289 Check out our author, "Apophthegmata Laconica," p. 220 C.

290 Plato, "Symposium," p. 25, E.

Plato, "Symposium," p. 25, E.

291 This line is quoted again by our author, "On Moral Virtue," § vii.

291 This line is quoted again by our author, "On Moral Virtue," § vii.

292 Plato, "Laws," iv. p. 711, E.

292 Plato, "Laws," iv. p. 711, E.

293 See those splendid lines of Lucretius, iv. 1155-1169.

293 Check out those beautiful lines of Lucretius, iv. 1155-1169.

294 "Res valde celebrata ex Institutione Cyri Xenophontea, v. 1, 2; vi. 1, 17."—Wyttenbach.

294 "A highly regarded thing from Xenophon's Cyropedia, book 1, 2; book 6, 1, 17."—Wyttenbach.

295 This line is very like a Fragment in the "Danae" of Euripides. Dind. (328).

295 This line is very similar to a fragment in Euripides' "Danae." Dind. (328).

296 On these see Pausanias, v. 7.

296 For more on this, check out Pausanias, v. 7.

297 Such as Homer could have brought. Compare Horace, "Odes," iv. ix. 25-28; and Cicero, "pro Archia," x. "Magnus ille Alexander—cum in Sigeo ad Achillis tumulum adstitisset, O fortunate, inquit, adolescens, qui tuæ virtutis Homerum præconem inveneris."

297 Such as Homer could have provided. See Horace, "Odes," iv. ix. 25-28; and Cicero, "pro Archia," x. "That great Alexander—when he stood by Achilles' tomb at Sigeo, said, 'O fortunate young man, who have found Homer as the herald of your virtue.'"

298 Contrary to Hesiod's saw, "Works and Days," 361, 362.

298 Unlike Hesiod's saying, "Works and Days," 361, 362.

299 So Juvenal, xiv. 138-140.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ So Juvenal, xiv. 138-140.

300 Like Horace's "Non si male nunc, et olim Sic erit." "Odes," ii. x. 16, 17.

300 Like Horace's "It may not be bad now, and it won't be in the future." "Odes," ii. x. 16, 17.

301 Noblesse oblige in fact.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Noblesse oblige for real.

302 Pindar, Frag. 206.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Pindar, Frag. 206.

303 Like Horace's factus ad unguem, because the sculptor tries its polish and the niceness of the joints by drawing his nail over the surface. Casaub. Pers. i. 64; Horace, "Sat." i. v. 32, 33; A. P. 294; Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 507.

303 Just like Horace's factus ad unguem, since the sculptor checks the polish and the precision of the joints by running his nail along the surface. Casaub. Pers. i. 64; Horace, "Sat." i. v. 32, 33; A. P. 294; Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 507.


WHETHER VICE IS SUFFICIENT TO CAUSE UNHAPPINESS.304

§ i. ... He who gets a dowry with his wife sells himself for it, as Euripides says,305 but his gains are few and uncertain; but he who does not go all on fire through many a funeral pile, but through a regal pyre, full of panting and fear and sweat got from travelling over the sea as a merchant, has the wealth of Tantalus, but cannot enjoy it owing to his want of leisure. For that Sicyonian horse-breeder was wise, who gave Agamemnon as a present a swift mare, "that he should not follow him to wind-swept Ilium, but delight himself at home,"306 in the quiet enjoyment of his abundant riches 139and painless leisure. But nowadays courtiers, and people who think they have a turn for affairs, thrust themselves forward of their own accord uninvited into courts and toilsome escorts and bivouacs, that they may get a horse, or brooch, or some such piece of good luck. "But his wife is left behind in Phylace, and tears her cheeks in her sorrow, and his house is only half complete without him,"307 while he is dragged about, and wanders about, and wastes his time in idle hopes, and has to put up with much insult. And even if he gets any of those things he desires, giddy and dizzy at Fortune's rope-dance, he seeks retirement, and deems those happy who live obscure and in security, while they again look up admiringly at him who soars so high above their heads.308

§ i. ... A man who marries for a dowry essentially sells himself for it, as Euripides says,305 but his rewards are minimal and uncertain. On the other hand, a man who doesn't rush blindly into danger, but takes a noble path filled with effort, fear, and sweat from traveling as a merchant across the sea, has wealth that he cannot fully enjoy due to a lack of time. The wise horse-breeder from Sicyon knew this when he gifted Agamemnon a fast mare, "so he wouldn’t have to follow him to wind-swept Ilium, but could enjoy himself at home,"306 relishing his abundant riches and comfortable leisure. Nowadays, however, courtiers and those who think they're adept at politics push their way into courts, arduous soldiering, and camps, hoping to acquire a horse, a piece of jewelry, or some stroke of luck. "But his wife is left behind in Phylace, tearing at her cheeks in grief, and his home feels incomplete without him,"307 while he is dragged around, wandering aimlessly, wasting time on futile dreams, and enduring much indignity. Even if he attains some of his desires, dizzy from the ups and downs of Fortune's game, he longs for solitude and considers those who live quietly and securely to be truly fortunate, while they look up in admiration at him soaring high above them.308

§ ii. Vice has universally an ill effect on everybody, being in itself a sufficient producer of infelicity, needing no instruments nor ministers. For tyrants, anxious to make those whom they punish wretched, keep executioners and torturers, and contrive branding-irons and other instruments of torture to inspire fear309 in the brute soul, whereas vice attacks the soul without any such apparatus, and crushes and dejects it, and fills a man with sorrow, and lamentation, and melancholy, and remorse. Here is a proof of what I say. Many are silent under mutilation, and endure scourging or torture at the hand of despots or tyrants without uttering a word, whenever their soul, abating the pain by reason, forcibly as it were checks and represses them: but you can never quiet anger or smother grief, or persuade a timid person not to run away, or one suffering from remorse not to cry out, nor tear his hair, nor smite his thigh. Thus vice is stronger than fire and sword.

§ ii. Vice has a negative impact on everyone, causing misery on its own without needing any tools or accomplices. Tyrants, eager to make their victims suffer, employ executioners and torturers and create branding irons and other devices of torture to instill fear in the heart of their targets. In contrast, vice attacks the soul without any such devices, crushing and depressing it, filling a person with sorrow, grief, melancholy, and guilt. This proves my point: many remain silent under torture, enduring beatings or torment from tyrants without saying a word, as their minds help them endure the pain. However, you can never suppress anger or hide grief, nor convince a scared person not to flee, or someone filled with guilt not to cry out, tear their hair, or strike their thigh. Thus, vice is more powerful than fire and sword.

§ iii. You know of course that cities, when they desire to publicly contract for the building of temples or colossuses, listen to the estimates of the contractors who compete for the job, and bring their plans and charges, and finally select the contractor who will do the work at least 140expense, and best, and quickest. Let us suppose then that we publicly contract to make the life of man miserable, and take the estimates of Fortune and Vice for this object. Fortune shall come forward, provided with all sorts of instruments and costly apparatus to make life miserable and wretched. She shall come with robberies and wars, and the blood-guiltiness of tyrants, and storms at sea, and lightning drawn down from the sky, she shall compound hemlock, she shall bring swords, she shall levy an army of informers, she shall cause fevers to break out, she shall rattle fetters and build prisons. It is true that most of these things are owing to Vice rather than Fortune, but let us suppose them all to come from Fortune. And let Vice stand by naked, without any external things against man, and let her ask Fortune how she will make man unhappy and dejected. Fortune, dost thou threaten poverty? Metrocles laughs at thee, who sleeps during winter among the sheep, in summer in the vestibules of temples, and challenges the king of the Persians,310 who winters at Babylon, and summers in Media, to vie with him in happiness. Dost thou bring slavery, and bondage, and sale? Diogenes despises thee, who cried out, as he was being sold by some robbers, "Who will buy a master?" Dost thou mix a cup of poison? Didst not thou offer such a one to Socrates? And cheerfully, and mildly, without fear, without changing colour or countenance, he calmly drank it up: and when he was dead, all who survived deemed him happy, as sure to have a divine lot in Hades. And as to thy fire, did not Decius, the general of the Romans, anticipate it for himself, having piled up a funeral pyre between the two armies, and sacrificed himself to Cronos, dedicating himself for the supremacy of his country? And the chaste and loving wives of the Indians strive and contend with one another for the fire, and she that wins the day and gets burnt with the body of her husband, is pronounced happy by the rest, and her praises sung. And of the wise men in that part of the world no one is esteemed or pronounced happy, who does not in his 141lifetime, in good health and in full possession of all his faculties, separate soul from body by fire, and emerge pure from flesh, having purged away his mortal part. Or wilt thou reduce a man from a splendid property, and house, and table, and sumptuous living, to a threadbare coat and wallet, and begging of daily bread? Such was the beginning of happiness to Diogenes, of freedom and glory to Crates. Or wilt thou nail a man on a cross, or impale him on a stake? What cares Theodorus whether he rots above ground or below? Such was the happy mode of burial amongst the Scythians,311 and among the Hyrcanians dogs, among the Bactrians birds, devour according to the laws the dead bodies of those who have made a happy end.

§ iii. You know that when cities want to publicly hire someone to build temples or statues, they listen to the bids from contractors who compete for the job, presenting their plans and costs, and ultimately choose the contractor who will do the work for the least 140 expense, and do it best and fastest. Let’s say we publicly contract to make human life miserable, and we take bids from Fortune and Vice for this purpose. Fortune shows up, equipped with all kinds of tools and expensive resources to create misery and suffering. She arrives with robberies, wars, the guilt of tyrants, storms at sea, lightning strikes, poisons like hemlock, swords, an army of informers, outbreaks of fevers, rattling chains, and the construction of prisons. It’s true that most of this misery comes from Vice rather than Fortune, but let's assume it all comes from Fortune. And let Vice stand there naked, without any resources to harm humanity, asking Fortune how she plans to make people unhappy and depressed. Fortune, do you threaten poverty? Metrocles laughs at you, who sleeps among sheep in winter and in temple doorways in summer, challenging the king of Persia,310 who resides in Babylon through winter and in Media during summer, to compete with him in happiness. Do you bring slavery, bondage, and sale? Diogenes scoffs at you, who shouted out while being sold by robbers, “Who will buy a master?” Do you mix a cup of poison? Didn’t you offer that to Socrates? He drank it calmly and cheerfully, without fear or changing his expression: after his death, everyone who survived considered him fortunate, destined for a divine fate in the afterlife. And regarding your fire, didn’t Decius, the Roman general, welcome it for himself, building a funeral pyre between two armies and sacrificing himself for his country’s supremacy? And among the faithful and loving wives of the Indians, they compete to gain the fire; the one who wins and gets burned together with her husband’s body is called fortunate by the others, and her praises are sung. In that part of the world, no wise man is considered fortunate unless he separates his soul from his body by fire while still alive, in good health, and in full control of his faculties, emerging pure from his flesh after cleansing his mortal side. Or will you reduce someone from a lavish lifestyle, a beautiful home, and luxurious living to a tattered coat and a bag, begging for daily bread? That’s how Diogenes found happiness, and how Crates found freedom and glory. Or will you crucify someone or impale them? What does Theodorus care if he rots above ground or below? This was the happy way of burial among the Scythians,311 and among the Hyrcanians, dogs feast on the dead, while among the Bactrians, birds devour the bodies of those who have met a happy end, following the customs.

§ iv. Who then are made unhappy by these things? Those who have no manliness or reason, the enervated and untrained, who retain the opinions they had as children. Fortune therefore does not produce perfect infelicity, unless Vice co-operate. For as a thread saws through a bone that has been soaked in ashes and vinegar, and as people bend and fashion ivory only when it has been made soft and supple by beer, and cannot under any other circumstances, so Fortune, lighting upon what is in itself faulty and soft through Vice, hollows it out and wounds it. And as the Parthian juice, though hurtful to no one else nor injurious to those who touch it or carry it about, yet if it be communicated to a wounded man straightway kills him through his previous susceptibility to receive its essence, so he who will be upset in soul by Fortune must have some secret internal ulcer or sore to make external things so piteous and lamentable.

§ iv. So who ends up unhappy because of these things? It's those who lack courage or reason, the weak and untrained, who cling to the same beliefs they had as kids. Luck alone doesn't create complete misery unless Vice plays a part. Just like a thread can saw through a bone that's been soaked in ashes and vinegar, and like people can only shape ivory when it's been softened by beer, Fortune exposes and wounds what is already flawed and weak due to Vice. Similarly, the Parthian juice, which doesn't harm anyone else nor injure those who handle it, can kill a wounded person as soon as it's given to them because their vulnerability allows it to take effect. Likewise, someone who gets deeply troubled by Fortune must have some hidden internal wound or sore that makes them perceive external circumstances as pitiful and tragic.

§ v. Does then Vice need Fortune to bring about infelicity? By no means. She lashes not up the rough and stormy sea, she girds not lonely mountain passes with robbers lying in wait by the way, she makes not clouds of hail to burst on the fruitful plains, she suborns not Meletus or Anytus or Callixenus as accusers, she takes not away wealth, excludes not people from the prætorship to make them wretched; but she scares the rich, the well-to-do, and great heirs; by land and sea she insinuates herself and 142sticks to people, infusing lust, inflaming with anger, afflicting them with superstitious fears, tearing them in pieces with envy.

§ v. So, does Vice need Fortune to create misfortune? Not at all. It doesn’t stir up the rough and stormy seas, it doesn't surround lonely mountain paths with robbers lying in wait, it doesn't make clouds of hail burst over the fertile plains, it doesn't hire Meletus or Anytus or Callixenus as accusers, it doesn't take away wealth, nor does it prevent people from holding office to make them miserable; instead, it frightens the rich, the comfortable, and the wealthy heirs; it works its way in by land and sea and 142clings to people, stirring up lust, igniting anger, burdening them with superstitious fears, and tearing them apart with envy.

304 The beginning of this short Treatise is lost. Nor is the first paragraph at all clear. We have to guess somewhat at the meaning.

304 The start of this brief essay is missing. The first paragraph isn’t very clear either. We have to make some educated guesses about its meaning.

305 In a fragment of the "Phaethon." Compare also "On Education," § 19.

305 In a piece of the "Phaethon." Also see "On Education," § 19.

306 "Iliad," xxiii. 297, 298.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 23. 297, 298.

307 "Iliad," ii. 700, 701.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 2. 700, 701.

308 'Tis ever so. Compare Horace, "Sat." i. i. 1-14.

308 It's always like that. Check out Horace, "Sat." i. i. 1-14.

309 Adopting Reiske's reading.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Adopting Reiske's interpretation.

310 Proverbial for extreme good fortune. Cf. Horace, "Odes," iii. ix. 4, "Persarum vigui rege beatior."

310 Known for incredible luck. Cf. Horace, "Odes," iii. ix. 4, "Persarum vigui rege beatior."

311 See Herodotus, iv. 72.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Herodotus, vol. 4, 72.


WHETHER THE DISORDERS OF MIND OR BODY ARE WORSE.

§ i. Homer, looking at the mortality of all living creatures, and comparing them with one another in their lives and habits, gave vent to his thoughts in the words,

§ i. Homer, reflecting on the mortality of all living beings and comparing their lives and habits, expressed his thoughts with the words,

"Among all the living things on earth," Or creep, man is by far the most miserable; __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

assigning to man an unhappy pre-eminence in extreme misfortune. But let us, assuming that man is, as thus publicly declared, supreme in infelicity and the most wretched of all living creatures, compare him with himself, in the estimate of his misery dividing body and soul, not idly but in a very necessary way, that we may learn whether our life is more wretched owing to Fortune or through our own fault. For disease is engendered in the body by nature, but vice and depravity in the soul is first its own doing, then its settled condition. And it is no slight aid to tranquillity of mind if what is bad be capable of cure, and lighter and less violent.

assigning to humans an unfortunate superiority in extreme misfortune. But let’s, assuming that humans are, as publicly claimed, the most miserable and wretched of all living beings, compare them with themselves, separating body and soul, not idly but in a necessary way, so we can understand whether our lives are more miserable because of fate or our own actions. Disease is caused in the body by nature, but vice and corruption in the soul is primarily our own doing, then it becomes its permanent state. And it is a significant help to peace of mind if what is bad can be cured and is lighter and less severe.

§ ii. The fox in Æsop313 disputing with the leopard as to their respective claims to variety, the latter showed its body and appearance all bright and spotted, while the tawny skin of the former was dirty and not pleasant to look at. Then the fox said, "Look inside me, sir judge, and you will see that I am more full of variety than my opponent," referring to his trickiness and versatility in shifts. Let us similarly say to ourselves, Many diseases and disorders, good sir, thy body naturally produces of itself, many also it receives from without; but if thou lookest at thyself within thou wilt find, to borrow the language of Democritus, a 143varied and susceptible storehouse and treasury of what is bad, not flowing in from without, but having as it were innate and native springs, which vice, being exceedingly rich and abundant in passion, produces. And if diseases are detected in the body by the pulse and by pallors and flushes,314 and are indicated by heats and sudden pains, while the diseases of the mind, bad as they are, escape the notice of most people, the latter are worse because they deprive the sufferer of the perception of them. For reason if it be sound perceives the diseases of the body, but he that is diseased in his mind cannot judge of his sufferings, for he suffers in the very seat of judgement. We ought to account therefore the first and greatest of the diseases of the mind that ignorance,315 whereby vice is incurable for most people, dwelling with them and living and dying with them. For the beginning of getting rid of disease is the perception of it, which leads the sufferer to the necessary relief, but he who through not believing he is ill knows not what he requires refuses the remedy even when it is close at hand. For amongst the diseases of the body those are the worst which are accompanied by stupor, as lethargies, headaches, epilepsies, apoplexies, and those fevers which raise inflammation to the pitch of madness, and disturb the brain as in the case of a musical instrument,

§ ii. The fox in Aesop313 argued with the leopard about who had more variety. The leopard showed off its bright, spotted body, while the fox’s tawny fur looked dirty and unappealing. The fox then said, "Look inside me, sir judge, and you’ll see I have more variety than my opponent," meaning his cleverness and adaptability. Similarly, we might say to ourselves, many illnesses and issues, dear sir, your body naturally creates—some come from outside. But if you look within yourself, you’ll find, to quote Democritus, a 143 diverse and vulnerable storehouse of negativity that doesn’t just come from the outside but has its own innate sources, as vice, flourishing in passion, generates. While physical diseases are detectable via pulses, paleness, and flushes,314 and indicated by fevers and sudden pains, mental diseases, unpleasant as they may be, often go unnoticed by many, yet they are worse because they rob the sufferer of awareness. A healthy mind can recognize bodily ailments, but someone mentally unwell can't judge their own pain since they suffer at the very core of judgement. We should thus consider ignorance as the foremost and most significant mental illness,315 allowing vice to be incurable for most, living and dying alongside them. The first step to overcoming an illness is recognizing it, which guides the sufferer to necessary help; however, someone who doesn't believe they're ill won't know what they need and will refuse remedies even when they’re readily available. Among physical ailments, the worst are those that come with a sense of numbness, like lethargy, headaches, epilepsy, strokes, and those fevers that drive inflammation to madness, affecting the brain just like a musical instrument.

"And pull the mind's strings that have remained untouched." 316

§ iii. And so doctors wish a man not to be ill, or if he is ill to be ignorant of it, as is the case with all diseases of the soul. For neither those who are out of their minds, nor the licentious, nor the unjust think themselves faulty—some even think themselves perfect. For no one ever yet called a fever health, or consumption a good condition of body, or gout swift-footedness, or paleness a good colour; but many call anger manliness, and love friendship, and envy competition, 144and cowardice prudence. Then again those that are ill in body send for doctors, for they are conscious of what they need to counteract their ailments; but those who are ill in mind avoid philosophers, for they think themselves excellent in the very matters in which they come short. And it is on this account that we maintain that ophthalmia is a lesser evil than madness, and gout than frenzy. For the person ill in body is aware of it and calls loudly for the doctor, and when he comes allows him to anoint his eye, to open a vein, or to plaster up his head; but you hear mad Agave in her frenzy not knowing her dearest ones, but crying out, "We bring from the mountain to the halls a young stag recently torn limb from limb, a fortunate capture."317 Again he who is ill in body straightway gives up and goes to bed and remains there quietly till he is well, and if he toss and tumble about a little when the fit is on him, any of the people who are by saying to him,

§ iii. Doctors hope that a person isn’t sick or, if they are, that they don’t realize it, especially when it comes to mental illnesses. People who are out of touch with reality, those who act recklessly, or those who are unjust often don’t see themselves as having any flaws—some even believe they’re perfect. No one would consider a fever to be health, or view tuberculosis as a healthy condition, or think that gout is quickness, or that being pale is a good complexion; yet many call anger strength, love companionship, envy rivalry, and cowardice caution. On the other hand, those who are physically ill seek out doctors because they know they need help to overcome their issues; but those who are mentally unwell shy away from philosophers, believing they excel in the very areas where they fall short. This is why we argue that an eye infection is less troubling than insanity, and gout is less serious than frenzy. The physically ill person recognizes their condition and calls loudly for help from the doctor, allowing them to treat their eye, draw blood, or bandage their head; meanwhile, you can hear mad Agave in her delirium, not recognizing her loved ones, but shouting, "We bring from the mountain to the halls a young stag recently torn limb from limb, a fortunate capture."317 Conversely, a physically ill person immediately lies down and rests quietly until they recover, and if they fidget a bit during a fit, anyone nearby says to them,

Gently, "Stay in bed, you poor soul, and relax,"318

restrain him and check him. But those who suffer from a diseased brain are then most active and least at rest, for impulses bring about action, and the passions are vehement impulses. And so they do not let the mind rest, but when the man most requires quiet and silence and retirement, then is he dragged into the open air, and becomes the victim of anger, contentiousness, lust, and grief, and is compelled to do and say many lawless things unsuitable to the occasion.

restrain him and check him. But those who suffer from a diseased brain are the most active and least at peace, as impulses drive them to act, and their passions are intense impulses. Thus, they do not allow the mind to rest. When a person needs quiet, solitude, and peace the most, they are instead pulled into the open air, becoming a victim of anger, conflict, lust, and sorrow, and are forced to do and say many inappropriate things that don't fit the situation.

§ iv. As therefore the storm which prevents one's putting into harbour is more dangerous than the storm which will not let one sail, so those storms of the soul are more formidable which do not allow a man to take in sail, or to calm his reason when it is disturbed, but without a pilot and without ballast, in perplexity and uncertainty through contrary and confusing courses, he rushes headlong and falls into woeful shipwreck, and shatters his life. So that 145from these points of view it is worse to be diseased in mind than body, for the latter only suffer, but the former do ill as well as suffer ill. But why need I speak of our various passions? The very times bring them to our mind. Do you see yon great and promiscuous crowd jostling against one another and surging round the rostrum and forum? They have not assembled here to sacrifice to their country's gods, nor to share in one another's rites; they are not bringing to Ascræan Zeus the firstfruits of Lydian produce,319 nor are they celebrating in honour of Dionysus the Bacchic orgies on festival nights with common revellings; but a mighty plague stirring up Asia in annual cycles drives them here for litigation and suits at law at stated times: and the mass of business, like the confluence of mighty rivers, has inundated one forum, and festers and teems with ruiners and ruined. What fevers, what agues, do not these things cause? What obstructions, what irruptions of blood into the air-vessels, what distemperature of heat, what overflow of humours, do not result? If you examine every suit at law, as if it were a person, as to where it originated, where it came from, you will find that one was produced by obstinate temper, another by frantic love of strife, a third by some sordid desire.320

§ iv. Just like a storm that keeps a ship from reaching the harbor is more dangerous than one that prevents it from setting sail, the storms within a person are even more threatening, as they stop a person from calming their mind when it's troubled. Without guidance and stability, they navigate through confusion and uncertainty, rushing headfirst into disaster and wrecking their lives. From this perspective, it’s worse to have a troubled mind than a sick body because the body only suffers while the mind does wrong and suffers. But why should I dwell on our different emotions? The current times make them obvious. Do you see that large, chaotic crowd pushing against each other around the speaker’s platform and the forum? They haven’t gathered here to honor their country’s gods or to participate in each other's rituals; they’re not bringing offerings to Ascræan Zeus with the first crops from Lydia, nor are they celebrating Dionysus with wild party nights. Instead, a terrible plague that sweeps through Asia each year drives them here for lawsuits and legal battles. The overwhelming amount of business, like the convergence of powerful rivers, has flooded one forum, overflowing with ruiners and the ruined. What fevers, what chills, don’t these issues cause? What blockages, what surges of blood, what imbalance of heat, what overflow of fluids, arise from this? If you look into each lawsuit as if it were a person, trying to trace back where it came from, you’ll find that one came from stubbornness, another from a desperate love of conflict, and a third from some greedy desire.320

312 Homer, "Iliad," xvii. 446, 447.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 17.446, 447.

313 See the Fable Ἀλώπηξ και Πὰρδαλις. No. 42, Ed. Halme.

313 See the Fable The Fox and the Leopard. No. 42, Ed. Halme.

314 Reading with Wyttenbach, ὠχριάσεσι και ἐρυθήμασι.

314 Reading with Wyttenbach, pale with shades and hues of red.

315 Forte ἄγνοιαν."—Wyttenbach. The ordinary reading is ἂνοιαν. "E cœlo descendit γνῶθι σεαυτόν," says Juvenal truly, xi. 27.

315 Forte ignorance."—Wyttenbach. The usual reading is unintelligence. "From heaven came the advice to know yourself," Juvenal says correctly, xi. 27.

316 Compare the image in Shakspere, "Hamlet," A. iii. Sc. I. 165, 166.

316 Compare the image in Shakespeare, "Hamlet," Act III, Scene I, lines 165-166.

"Now look at that noble and most supreme reason, "Like sweet bells ringing, out of tune and jarring."

317 Euripides, "Bacchæ," 1170-1172. Agave's treatment of her son Pentheus was a stock philosophical comparison. See for example Horace, ii. "Sat." iii. 303, 304, and context.

317 Euripides, "Bacchæ," 1170-1172. Agave's behavior towards her son Pentheus was a common philosophical analogy. For example, see Horace, ii. "Sat." iii. 303, 304, and the surrounding context.

318 Euripides, "Orestes," 258.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Orestes," 258.

319 "Aurum puta. Pactolus enim aurum fert. Videtur dictio e Pindaro desumta esse."—Reiske.

319 "Gold I say. For Pactolus brings gold. This phrase seems to be taken from Pindar."—Reiske.

320 "Libellus hic fine carere videtur. Quare autem opusculum hoc Plutarcho indignum atque suppositum visum Xylandro fuerit, non intelligo."—Reiske.

320 "This little book seems to lack any conclusion. I don’t understand why Xylander considered this work unworthy of Plutarch and a forgery."—Reiske.


ON ABUNDANCE OF FRIENDS.

§ i. Menon the Thessalian, who thought he was a perfect adept in discourse, and, to borrow the language of Empedocles, "had attained the heights of wisdom," was asked by Socrates, what virtue was, and upon his answering quickly and glibly, that virtue was a different thing in boy and old man, and in man and woman, and in magistrate and private person, and in master and servant, "Capital," said Socrates, "you were asked about one virtue, but you 146have raised up a whole swarm of them,"321 conjecturing not amiss that the man named many because he knew not one. Might not someone jeer at us in the same way, as being afraid, when we have not yet one firm friendship, that we shall without knowing it fall upon an abundance of friends? It is very much the same as if a man maimed and blind should be afraid of becoming hundred-handed like Briareus or all eyes like Argus. And yet we wonderfully praise the young man in Menander, who said that he thought anyone wonderfully good, if he had even the shadow of a friend.322

§ i. Menon from Thessaly, who believed he was an expert in discussion and, to use Empedocles' words, "had reached the pinnacle of wisdom," was asked by Socrates what virtue is. After responding quickly and confidently that virtue differs for boys and old men, for men and women, for public officials and private individuals, and for masters and servants, Socrates replied, "Great, you were asked about one virtue, but you've brought up a whole bunch of them." 146321 suggesting correctly that Menon mentioned many because he didn't know a single one. Could someone not tease us similarly, that lacking even one true friendship, we're scared we'll unwittingly end up with too many? It's much like a man who's maimed and blind fearing he might become a hundred-handed like Briareus or all-seeing like Argus. Yet, we praise the young man in Menander who thought anyone was truly good if they had even a hint of a friend.322

§ ii. But among many other things what stands chiefly in the way of getting a friend is the desire for many friends, like a licentious woman who, through giving her favours indiscriminately, cannot retain her old lovers, who are neglected and drop off;323 or rather like the foster-child of Hypsipyle, "sitting in the meadow and plucking flower after flower, snatching at each prize with gladsome heart, insatiable in its childish delight,"324 so in the case of each of us, owing to our love of novelty and fickleness, the recent flower ever attracts, and makes us inconstant, frequently laying the foundations of many friendships and intimacies that come to nothing, neglecting in love of what we eagerly pursue what we have already possession of. To begin therefore with the domestic hearth,325 as the saying is, with the traditions of life that time has handed down to us about constant friends, let us take the witness and counsel of antiquity, according to which friendships go in pairs, as in the cases of Theseus and Pirithous, Achilles and Patroclus, Orestes and Pylades, Phintias and Damon, Epaminondas and Pelopidas. For friendship is a creature that goes in pairs, and is not gregarious, or crow-like,326 and to think a 147friend a second self, and to call him companion as it were second one,327 shows that friendship is a dual relation. For we can get neither many slaves nor many friends at small expense. What then is the purchase-money of friendship? Benevolence and complaisance conjoined with virtue, and yet nature has nothing more rare than these. And so to love or be loved very much cannot find place with many persons; for as rivers that have many channels and cuttings have a weak and thin stream, so excessive love in the soul if divided out among many is weakened. Thus love for their young is most strongly implanted in those that bear only one, as Homer calls a beloved son "the only one, the child of old age,"328 that is, when the parents neither have nor are likely to have another child.

§ ii. But among many other things, what primarily hinders us from making a friend is the desire for many friends, like a promiscuous woman who, by sharing her favors indiscriminately, cannot keep her old lovers, who feel neglected and drift away; 323 or rather like the foster-child of Hypsipyle, "sitting in the meadow and picking one flower after another, eagerly grasping each one with joy, insatiable in its youthful delight," 324 so in our case, because of our love for novelty and inconsistency, the latest attraction always entices us, making us unreliable, often laying the groundwork for numerous friendships and connections that end up meaningless, neglecting in our pursuit what we already possess. To start, therefore, with home life, 325 as the saying goes, with the traditions of life that time has passed down about lasting friendships, let’s take the wisdom and advice of the past, which shows that friendships come in pairs, like Thoseus and Pirithous, Achilles and Patroclus, Orestes and Pylades, Phintias and Damon, Epaminondas and Pelopidas. For friendship is something that pairs up and is not sociable or flock-like, 326 and to consider a friend as a second self and to refer to him as a companion implies that friendship is a dual relationship. We cannot acquire many friends or many slaves without significant investment. So what is the cost of friendship? It combines kindness, willingness to please, and virtue, yet nature has nothing rarer than these. Thus, loving or being loved extensively cannot occur with many people; for just as rivers that have many channels and branches have weak and thin flows, so too does excessive love in the soul, if spread among many, become diluted. Hence, a strong love for their young is most deeply rooted in those who have only one, as Homer refers to a beloved son as "the only one, the child of old age," 328 that is, when the parents either have no other child or are not likely to have another.

§ iii. Not that we insist on only one friend, but among the rest there should be one eminently so, like a child of old age, who according to that well-known proverb has eaten a bushel of salt with one,329 not as nowadays many so-called friends contract friendship from drinking together once, or playing at ball together, or playing together with dice, or passing the night together at some inn, or meeting at the wrestling-school or in the market. And in the houses of rich and leading men people congratulate them on their many friends, when they see the large and bustling crowd of visitors and handshakers and retainers: and yet they see more flies in their kitchens, and as the flies only come for the dainties, so they only dance attendance for what they can get. And since true friendship has three main requirements, virtue, as a thing good; and familiarity, as a thing pleasant; and use, as a thing serviceable; for we ought to choose a friend with judgement, and rejoice in his company, and make use of him in need; and all these things are prejudicial to abundance of friends, especially judgement, which is the most important point; we must first consider, if it is impossible in a short time to test dancers who are to form a chorus, or rowers who are to pull together, or slaves who are to act as stewards of estates, 148or as tutors of one's sons, far more difficult is it to meet with many friends who will take off their coats to aid you in every fortune, each of whom "offers his services to you in prosperity, and does not object to share your adversity." For neither does a ship encounter so many storms at sea, nor do they fortify places with walls, or harbours with defences and earthworks, in the expectation of so many and great dangers, as friendship tested well and soundly promises defence and refuge from. But if friends slip in without being tested, like money proved to be bad,

§ iii. We're not saying you can only have one friend, but among your friends, there should be one who stands out, like a beloved child in old age, who, as the well-known saying goes, has shared a bushel of salt with someone,329 unlike the way many so-called friends today form bonds through a single night of drinking, playing ball, gambling, staying at an inn, or meeting at the gym or in the marketplace. In the homes of wealthy and influential people, others often admire their many friends when they see the large and lively crowds of visitors and handshakers; yet they only notice more flies in their kitchens, as flies come only for the treats, just as those friends are drawn by what they can gain. True friendship requires three key elements: virtue, which is beneficial; familiarity, which is enjoyable; and usefulness, which is practical. We need to choose our friends wisely, take joy in their company, and rely on them when needed. However, each of these elements makes it hard to have a lot of friends, especially the element of judgment, which is the most crucial. It’s much easier to test dancers who are going to form a chorus, rowers who will work together, or servants acting as estate managers or tutors for your children than it is to find many friends who will genuinely support you in every situation, each of whom "offers their help during good times and doesn’t shy away from sharing in your struggles." A ship doesn’t face so many storms at sea, nor do people build walls around their homes or fortify harbors with defenses and earthen works, expecting so many and such grave dangers, as true friendship, tested and proven, offers protection and refuge from. But if friends enter your life without being tested, they’re as unreliable as bad money.

"Those who lose friends like that may actually feel relieved, "And those who have them wish they could lose them."330

Yet is it difficult and by no means easy to avoid and bring to a close an unpleasant friendship: as in the case of food which is injurious and harmful, we cannot retain it on the stomach without damage and hurt, nor can we expel it as it was taken into the mouth, but only in a putrid mixed up and changed form, so a bad friend is troublesome both to others and himself if retained, and if he be got rid of forcibly it is with hostility and hatred, and like the voiding of bile.

Yet it's difficult and not at all easy to end an unpleasant friendship. Just like with harmful food, we can't keep it in our system without suffering damage, nor can we get rid of it as easily as we consumed it; we can only expel it in a mixed and unpleasant form. Similarly, a bad friend is a burden to both themselves and others if kept around, and if they are removed forcefully, it often leads to hostility and resentment, much like getting rid of bile.

§ iv. We ought not, therefore, lightly to welcome or strike up an intimate friendship with any chance comers, or love those who attach themselves to us, but attach ourselves to those who are worthy of our friendship. For what is easily got is not always desirable: and we pass over and trample upon heather and brambles that stick to us331 on our road to the olive and vine: so also is it good not always to make a friend of the person who is expert in twining himself around us, but after testing them to attach ourselves to those who are worthy of our affection and likely to be serviceable to us.

§ iv. We shouldn't, therefore, casually welcome or form close friendships with just anyone who comes our way, or love those who cling to us, but instead connect with those who truly deserve our friendship. Because what comes easily isn't always the best: we often overlook and push aside heather and brambles that cling to us on our way to the olive and vine. Similarly, it’s wise not to befriend someone simply because they are skilled at wrapping themselves around us, but rather to test them first and then attach ourselves to those who are genuinely deserving of our affection and likely to be helpful to us.

§ v. As therefore Zeuxis, when some people accused him of painting slowly, replied, "I admit that I do, but then I paint to last," so ought we to test for a long time the friendship and intimacy that we take up and mean to 149keep. Is it not easy then to put to the test many friends, and to associate with many friends at the same time, or is this impossible? For intimacy is the full enjoyment of friendship, and most pleasant is companying with and spending the day with a friend. "Never again shall we alive, apart from dear friends, sit and take counsel alone together."332 And Menelaus said about Odysseus, "Nor did anything ever divide or separate us, who loved and delighted in one another, till death's black cloud overshadowed us."333 The contrary effect seems to be produced by abundance of friends. For the friendship of a pair of friends draws them together and puts them together and holds them together, and is heightened by intercourse and kindliness, "as when the juice of the fig curdles and binds the white milk,"334 as Empedocles says, such unity and complete union will such a friendship produce. Whereas having many friends puts people apart and severs and disunites them, by transferring and shifting the tie of friendship too frequently, and does not admit of a mixture and welding of goodwill by the diffusing and compacting of intimacy. And this causes at once an inequality and difficulty in respect of acts of kindness, for the uses of friendship become inoperative by being dispersed over too wide an area. "One man is acted upon by his character, another by his reflection."335 For neither do our natures and impulses always incline in the same directions, nor are our fortunes in life identical, for opportunities of action are, like the winds, favourable to some, unfavourable to others.

§ v. So, just like Zeuxis, when some people criticized him for painting slowly, replied, "I admit I do, but I paint to last," we should really take our time to evaluate the friendships and closeness we choose to nurture and maintain. Is it really that easy to test many friendships and to connect with numerous people at the same time, or is it impossible? Because true intimacy is the full experience of friendship, and there’s nothing better than hanging out and spending time with a friend. "We will never again sit and deliberate together, apart from our dear friends." 332 Menelaus said about Odysseus, "Nothing ever divided or separated us, who cherished and delighted in one another, until death's dark shadow loomed over us." 333 On the other hand, having too many friends seems to create distance. The friendship between two close friends pulls them together and keeps them united, growing stronger through interaction and kindness, "just as the juice of the fig thickens and binds the white milk," 334 as Empedocles puts it; such unity and complete connection is what that kind of friendship brings. In contrast, being friends with many people pulls individuals apart and breaks their bonds by frequently shifting the dynamics of friendship, making it harder to blend and unify their affections. This leads to an imbalance and difficulty regarding acts of kindness, as the benefits of friendship get diluted over too wide a range. "One person is influenced by their character, another by their reflections." 335 Our natures and instincts don't always point in the same direction, and our life circumstances aren’t the same either; chances for action, like the winds, can be favorable for some and unfavorable for others.

§ vi. Moreover, if all our friends want to do the same things at the same time, it will be difficult to satisfy them all, whether they desire to deliberate, or to act in state affairs, or wish for office, or are going to entertain guests. If again at the same time they chance to be engaged in different occupations and interests and ask you all together, one who is going on a voyage that you will sail with him, another who is going to law that you will be his advocate, another who is going to try a case that you will try it with him, another who is selling or buying that you will go into 150partnership with him, another who is going to marry that you will join him in the sacrifice, another who is going to bury a relation that you will be one of the mourners,

§ vi. Plus, if all our friends want to do the same things at the same time, it can be tough to meet everyone's needs, whether they want to discuss something, participate in important matters, run for office, or have guests over. If they happen to be involved in different activities and all ask you at once—one wanting you to join him on a trip, another needing you as his lawyer, someone else asking you to help with a case, another wanting you to partner up with him in a business deal, another inviting you to share in his wedding, and yet another asking you to mourn a relative with him—

"The town is filled with incense, and at once" Echoes with songs of victory and painful cries,"336

that is the fruit of many friends; to oblige all is impossible, to oblige none is absurd, and to help one and offend many is grievous.

that is the result of many friends; it's impossible to please everyone, it's ridiculous to please no one, and helping one person while offending many others is painful.

"No lover has ever imagined neglect." __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

And yet people bear patiently and without anger the carelessness and neglect of friends, if they get from them such excuses as "I forgot," "I did it unwittingly." But he who says, "I did not assist you in your lawsuit, for I was assisting another friend," or "I did not visit you when you had your fever, for I was helping so-and-so who was entertaining his friends," excusing himself for his inattention to one by his attention to another, so far from making the offence less, even adds jealousy to his neglect. But most people in friendship regard only, it seems, what can be got out of it, overlooking what will be asked in return, and not remembering that he, who has had many of his own requests granted, must oblige others in turn by granting their requests. And as Briareus with his hundred hands had to feed fifty stomachs, and was therefore no better provided than we are, who with two hands have to supply the necessities of only one belly, so in having many friends338 one has to do many services for them, one has to share in their anxiety, and to toil and moil with them. For we must not listen to Euripides when he says, "mortals ought to join in moderate friendships for one another, and not love with all their heart, that the spell may be soon broken, and the friendship may either be ended or become closer at will,"339 that so it may be adjusted to our requirements, like the sail of a ship that we can either slacken or haul 151tight. But let us transfer, Euripides, these lines of yours to enmities, and bid people make their animosities moderate, and not hate with all their heart, that their hatred, and wrath, and querulousness, and suspicions, may be easily broken. Recommend rather for our consideration that saying of Pythagoras, "Do not give many your right hand,"340 that is, do not make many friends, do not go in for a common and vulgar friendship, which is sure to cause anyone much trouble; for its sharing in others' anxieties and griefs and labours and dangers is quite intolerable to free and noble natures. And that was a true saying of the wise Chilo341 to one who told him he had no enemy, "Neither," said he, "do you seem to me to have a friend." For enmities inevitably accompany and are involved in friendships.

And yet people patiently put up with the carelessness and neglect of friends without getting angry, especially if they receive excuses like "I forgot" or "I didn’t mean to." However, someone who says, "I didn’t help you with your lawsuit because I was helping another friend," or "I couldn’t visit you when you were sick because I was busy with someone else who was hosting friends," only makes things worse. Instead of lessening the offense, these excuses often create jealousy around their neglect. Most people in friendships, it seems, only care about what they can gain, ignoring what will be expected in return, not realizing that someone who has had many of their own requests fulfilled owes it to others to grant their requests too. Just as Briareus with his hundred hands had to feed fifty stomachs and was no better off than we are, who with two hands only need to provide for one stomach, having many friends means you have to do many services for them, share their worries, and work hard alongside them. We shouldn't listen to Euripides when he says, "mortals ought to engage in moderate friendships for one another, and not love wholeheartedly, so that the ties can easily be broken, and the friendship can end or become closer as needed," treating it like a sail that we can either loosen or tighten. Instead, Euripides, let’s suggest your lines apply to enmities, urging people to keep their hatred moderate and not hate too passionately, so their anger, bitterness, and suspicions can be easily resolved. Let's rather consider Pythagoras's saying, "Do not give your right hand to many," meaning don’t make too many friends, avoiding common and superficial friendships, which are bound to bring a lot of trouble; sharing in others' worries and burdens is quite unbearable for noble individuals. Chilo's wise remark to someone who claimed to have no enemy—"Then, you don’t seem to have a friend either"—rings true, as enmities inevitably accompany and intertwine with friendships.

§ vii. It is impossible I say not to share with a friend in his injuries and disgraces and enmities, for enemies at once suspect and hate the friend of their enemies, and even friends are often envious and jealous and carp at him. As then the oracle given to Timesias about his colony foretold him, "that his swarm of bees would soon be followed by a swarm of wasps," so those that seek a swarm of friends have sometimes lighted unawares on a wasp's-nest of enemies. And the remembrance of wrongs done by an enemy and the kindness of a friend do not weigh in the same balance. See how Alexander treated the friends and intimates of Philotas and Parmenio, how Dionysius treated those of Dion, Nero those of Plautus, Tiberius those of Sejanus, torturing and putting them to death. For as neither the gold nor rich robes of Creon's daughter342 availed her or her sire, but the flame that burst out suddenly involved him in the same fate as herself, as he ran up to embrace her and rescue her, so some friends, though they have had no enjoyment out of their friends' prosperity, are involved in their misfortunes. And this is especially the case with philosophers and kind people, as Theseus, when his friend Pirithous was punished and im152prisoned, "was also bound in fetters not of brass."343 And Thucydides tells us that during the plague at Athens those that most displayed their virtue perished with their friends that were ill, for they neglected their own lives in going to visit them.344

§ vii. I believe it's impossible not to share in a friend’s suffering, shame, and conflicts, because enemies immediately suspect and despise the friend of their foes, and even friends can often be envious, jealous, and critical. Just like the oracle warned Timesias about his colony, saying, "that his swarm of bees would soon be followed by a swarm of wasps," those who look for many friends sometimes stumble upon a nest of enemies. The memories of wrongs inflicted by an enemy and the kindness from a friend don’t weigh the same. Just look at how Alexander treated the friends and associates of Philotas and Parmenio, how Dionysius dealt with the followers of Dion, how Nero treated those close to Plautus, and how Tiberius handled the friends of Sejanus, torturing and executing them. For just as neither the gold nor the fine clothes of Creon's daughter342 saved her or her father, but the sudden flames consumed them both when he rushed to embrace and save her, some friends, even when they haven’t benefited from their friends’ success, find themselves caught up in their misfortunes. This is especially true for philosophers and kind-hearted people, as when Theseus was also "bound in fetters not of brass" while his friend Pirithous was punished and imprisoned.343 Thucydides mentions that during the plague in Athens, those who showed the most virtue perished alongside their ill friends because they disregarded their own lives to care for them.344

§ viii. We ought not therefore to be too lavish with our virtue, binding it together and implicating it in various people's fortunes, but we ought to preserve our friendship for those who are worthy of it, and are capable of reciprocating it. For this is indeed the greatest argument against many friends that friendship is originated by similarity. For seeing that even the brutes can hardly be forced to mix with those that are unlike themselves, but crouch down, and show their dislike, and run away, while they mix freely with those that are akin to them and have a similar nature, and gently and gladly make friends with one another then, how is it possible that there should be friendship between people differing in characters and temperaments and ideas of life? For harmony on the harp or lyre is attained by notes in unison and not in unison, sharp and flat somehow or other producing concord, but in the harmony of friendship there must be no unlike, or uneven, or unequal element, but from all alike must come agreement in opinions and wishes and feeling, as if one soul were put into several bodies.

§ viii. We shouldn't be too generous with our virtue, tying it to the fortunes of various people. Instead, we should maintain our friendships with those who truly deserve it and can reciprocate. This highlights a key reason against having too many friends: true friendship comes from similarity. Even animals are reluctant to mix with those who are different; they tend to back away or display dislike, while they easily associate with those similar to them and happily form friendships. So, how can we expect friendship to exist between people with different characters, temperaments, and life views? Just like harmony in music comes from notes that are both in tune and at times out of tune, creating a pleasant sound, true friendship cannot have dissimilar, uneven, or unequal elements. Instead, there must be a shared agreement in opinions, wishes, and feelings, as though a single soul exists within multiple bodies.

§ ix. What man then is so industrious, so changeable, and so versatile, as to be able to make himself like and adapt himself to many different persons, and not to laugh at the advice of Theognis, "Imitate the ingenuity of the polypus, that takes the colour of whatever stone it sticks to."345 And yet the changes in the polypus do not go deep but are only on the surface, which, from its thickness or thinness takes the impression of everything that approaches it, whereas friends endeavour to be like one another in character, and feeling, and language, and pursuits, and disposition. It requires a not very fortunate or very good Proteus,346 able by jugglery to assume various forms, to be 153frequently at the same time a student with the learned, and ready to try a fall with wrestlers, or to go a hunting with people fond of the chase, or to get drunk with tipplers, or to go a canvassing with politicians, having no fixed character of his own.347 And as the natural philosophers say of unformed and colourless matter when subjected to external change, that it is now fire, now water, now air, now solid earth, so the soul suitable for many friendships must be impressionable, and versatile, and pliant, and changeable. But friendship requires a steady constant and unchangeable character, a person that is uniform in his intimacy. And so a constant friend is a thing rare and hard to find.

§ ix. What man is so hardworking, so adaptable, and so flexible that he can make himself like and adjust to many different people, without laughing at the advice of Theognis, "Mimic the cleverness of the octopus, which changes color based on the stone it clings to."345 Yet the changes in the octopus are only skin-deep, taking on the appearance of whatever comes near it due to its thickness or thinness, while friends strive to become alike in character, feelings, speech, interests, and temperament. It takes a rather unfortunate or exceptionally skilled Proteus,346 who can through trickery take on different forms, to often be both a scholar with the educated and ready to wrestle with athletes, or go hunting with outdoorsy folks, or drink with heavy drinkers, or campaign with politicians, without having a firm identity of his own.347 And just as natural philosophers say about formless and colorless matter when it experiences external changes, that it can be fire, water, air, or solid earth, so the soul fit for many friendships must be impressionable, adaptable, flexible, and changeable. However, true friendship demands a steady, constant, and unchanging character, someone who is consistent in their closeness. Thus, a loyal friend is something rare and difficult to find.

321 Plato, "Men." p. 71 E.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Plato, "Men." p. 71 E.

322 Quoted more fully by our author, "De Fraterno Amore," § iii.

322 Quoted in full by our author, "De Fraterno Amore," § iii.

323 "Eadem comparatione utitur Lucianus in Toxari T. ii. p. 351: ὅστις ἂν πολύφιλος ᾗ ὅμοιος ἡμῖν δοκεῖ ταῖς κοιναῖς ταύταις καὶ μοιχευομέναις γυναιξί· και οἰόμεθ᾽ οὐκεθ᾽ ὁμοίως ἰσχυρὰν τὴν φιλίαν αὐτοῦ εἷναι πρὸς πολλὰς εὐνοίας διαιρεθεῖσαν."— Wyttenbach.

323 "Lucian uses the same comparison in Toxari T. ii. p. 351: Whoever is very affectionate seems to us to be similar to those common and adulterous women; and we think that his strong friendship is divided among many favors."—Wyttenbach.

324 From the "Hypsipyle" of Euripides.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ From "Hypsipyle" by Euripides.

325 A well-known proverb for beginning at the beginning. Aristophanes, "Vespæ." 846; Plato, "Euthryphro," 3 A; Strabo, 9.

325 A well-known saying about starting from the start. Aristophanes, "Vespæ." 846; Plato, "Euthryphro," 3 A; Strabo, 9.

326 An allusion to the well-known proverb, κολοιὸς ποτι κολοιόν. See Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 1644.

326 A reference to the well-known saying, κολοιὸς ποτι κολοιόν. See Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 1644.

327 The paronomasia is on ἑταῖρος, ἕτερος.

327 The pun is on ἑταῖρος, ἕτερος.

328 "Iliad," ix. 482; "Odyssey," xvi. 19.

328 "Iliad," ix. 482; "Odyssey," xvi. 19.

329 Cf. Cicero, "De Amicitia," xix.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Cicero, "On Friendship," 19.

330 Sophocles, Fragm. 741. Quoted again by our author, "On Love," § xxiii.

330 Sophocles, Fragm. 741. Quoted again by our author, "On Love," § xxiii.

331 For the image compare Lucio's speech, Shakspere, "Measure for Measure," A. iv. Sc. iii. 189, 190: "Nay, friar, I am a kind of burr; I shall stick."

331 For the image, compare Lucio's speech in Shakespeare's "Measure for Measure," Act IV, Scene III, lines 189-190: "No, friar, I'm like a burr; I'll stick."

332 "Iliad," xxiii. 77, 78.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xxiii. 77, 78.

333 "Odyssey," iv. 178-180.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," iv. 178-180.

334 "Iliad," v. 902, altered somewhat.

334 "Iliad," v. 902, changed a bit.

335 Bergk. p. 13443.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Bergk. p. 13443.

336 Sophocles, "Œdipus Tyrannus," 4, 5. Quoted again "On Moral Virtue," § vi.

336 Sophocles, "Oedipus the King," 4, 5. Quoted again "On Moral Virtue," § vi.

337 A line from Menander. Quoted again "De Fraterno Amore," § xx.

337 A line from Menander. Quoted again in "De Fraterno Amore," § xx.

338 Reading with Halm and Hercher ἐν τῷ πολλοῖς φιλοῖς χρῆσθαι.

338 Reading with Halm and Hercher in many friendly contexts.

339 Euripides, "Hippolytus," 253-257, where Dindorf and Hercher agree in the reading.

339 Euripides, "Hippolytus," 253-257, where Dindorf and Hercher both agree on the interpretation.

340 Compare "On Education," § xvii.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare "On Education," § 17.

341 Chilo was one of the Seven Wise Men. See Pausanias, iii. 16; X. 24.

341 Chilo was one of the Seven Wise Men. See Pausanias, iii. 16; X. 24.

342 For the circumstances see Euripides, "Medea," 1136 sq.

342 For the situation, see Euripides, "Medea," 1136 sq.

343 For the friendship of Theseus and Pirithous, see Pausanias, i. 17; x. 29. The line is from Euripides, "Pirithous," Fragm. 591. Cf. "On Shyness," § x.

343 For the friendship between Theseus and Pirithous, check Pausanias, i. 17; x. 29. The quote is from Euripides, "Pirithous," Fragm. 591. See also "On Shyness," § x.

344 Thucydides, ii. 51.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Thucydides, 2.51.

345 Bergk. p. 5003.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Bergk. p. 5003.

346 On Proteus, see Verg. "Georg." iv. 387 sq.; Ovid, "Art." i. 761; "Met." ii. 9; "Fasti," i. 367 sq., and especially Horace, "Epistles," i. i. 90: "Quo teneam vultus mutantem Protea nodo?"

346 For Proteus, see Verg. "Georg." iv. 387 sq.; Ovid, "Art." i. 761; "Met." ii. 9; "Fasti," i. 367 sq., and especially Horace, "Epistles," i. i. 90: "How should I hold the shape-changing Proteus by the knot?"

347 Literally, "having no hearth of character," the hearth being an emblem of stability. Compare "How One may Discern a Flatterer from a Friend," § vii., where the same image is employed.

347 Literally, "having no sense of stability," with the hearth symbolizing emotional security. See "How One may Discern a Flatterer from a Friend," § vii., where the same imagery is used.


HOW ONE MAY DISCERN A FLATTERER FROM A FRIEND.

§ i. Plato says,348 Antiochus Philopappus, that all men pardon the man who acknowledges that he is excessively fond of himself, but that there is among many other defects this very grave one in self-love, that by it a man becomes incapable of being a just and impartial judge about himself, for love is blind in regard to the loved object, unless a person has learnt and accustomed himself to honour and pursue what is noble rather than his own selfish interests. This gives a great field for the flatterer in friendship, who finds a wonderful base of operations in our self-love, which makes each person his own first and greatest flatterer, and easily admits a flatterer from without, who will be, so he thinks and hopes, both a witness and confirmer of his good opinion of himself. For he that lies open to the reproach of being fond of flatterers is very fond of himself, and owing to his 154goodwill to himself wishes to possess all good qualities, and thinks he actually does; the wish is not ridiculous, but the thought is misleading and requires a good deal of caution. And if truth is a divine thing, and, according to Plato,349 the beginning of all good things both to the gods and men, the flatterer is likely to be an enemy to the gods, and especially to Apollo, for he always sets himself against that famous saying, "Know thyself,"350 implanting in everybody's mind self-deceit and ignorance of his own good or bad qualities, thus making his good points defective and imperfect, and his bad points altogether incorrigible.

§ i. Plato says,348 Antiochus Philopappus, that everyone forgives someone who openly admits they are too self-loving. However, there’s a serious flaw in self-love: it prevents a person from being a fair and impartial judge of themselves, since love can blind you to the truth about what you cherish, unless you've learned to value and strive for what is noble over your own selfish desires. This creates a big opportunity for flatterers in friendship, who exploit our self-love, making each person their own biggest flatterer and easily allowing outside flattery in, believing it will reinforce their good opinion of themselves. A person who is open to criticism for liking flattery is usually very self-absorbed and, because of their self-interest, wants to possess all good traits, convincing themselves that they do. While wanting this is not foolish, believing it can be misleading and requires a lot of caution. If truth is a divine quality and, according to Plato,349 the foundation of all good things for both gods and humans, then flatterers could be seen as adversaries to the gods, particularly to Apollo because they go against the well-known saying, "Know thyself,"350 instilling self-deception and ignorance about one's own strengths and weaknesses, leading to flawed positive traits and irreparable negative ones.

§ ii. If however, as is the case with most other bad things, the flatterer attacked only or chiefly ignoble or worthless persons, the evil would not be so mischievous or so difficult to guard against. But since, as wood-worms breed most in soft and sweet wood, those whose characters are honourable and good and equitable encourage and support the flatterer most,—and moreover, as Simonides says, "rearing of horses does not go with the oil-flask,351 but with fruitful fields," so we see that flattery does not join itself to the poor, the obscure, or those without means, but is the snare and bane of great houses and estates, and often overturns kingdoms and principalities,—it is a matter of no small importance, needing much foresight, to examine the question, that so flattery may be easily detected, and neither injure nor discredit friendship. For just as lice leave dying persons, and abandon bodies when the blood on which they feed is drying up, so one never yet saw flatterers dancing attendance on dry and cold poverty, but they fasten on wealth and position and there get fat, but speedily decamp if reverses come. But we ought not to wait to experience that, which would be unprofitable, or rather injurious and dangerous. For not to find friends at a time when you want them is hard, as also not to be able to exchange an inconstant and bad friend for a constant and good one. For a friend should be like money tried before being re155quired, not found faulty in our need. For we ought not to have our wits about us only when the mischief is done, but we ought to try and prevent the flatterer doing any harm to us: for otherwise we shall be in the same plight as people who test deadly poisons by first tasting them, and kill or nearly kill themselves in the experiment. We do not praise such, nor again all those who, looking at their friend simply from the point of view of decorum and utility, think that they can detect all agreeable and pleasant companions as flatterers in the very act. For a friend ought not to be disagreeable or unpleasant, nor ought friendship to be a thing high and mighty with sourness and austerity, but even its decorous deportment ought to be attractive and winning,352 for by it

§ ii. However, if, like most bad things, the flatterer only targeted lowly or worthless people, the harm wouldn’t be as serious or hard to guard against. But because, similar to how wood-borers thrive in soft and sweet wood, those with honorable, good, and fair characters are the ones who mostly encourage and support flatterers—plus, as Simonides points out, "the raising of horses doesn’t come from the oil-flask,351 but from fertile fields," we see that flattery doesn’t attach itself to the poor, the unknown, or those who lack resources. Instead, it becomes a trap and curse for wealthy families and estates and frequently brings down kingdoms and principalities. It’s crucial to examine this carefully so that flattery can be spotted easily and not damage or discredit true friendships. Just like lice abandon dying people when their blood is gone, flatterers never stick around dry and cold poverty; they latch onto wealth and status, grow fat there, and quickly flee when things turn sour. We shouldn’t wait to see this firsthand, as that would be unhelpful, or worse, harmful and risky. It’s tough to be without friends when you need them, just as it’s hard to swap a fickle and bad friend for a loyal and good one. A friend should be like money that has been tested before it’s needed, not something faulty discovered in a moment of need. We shouldn’t be on guard only after the damage is done; we need to take steps to prevent the flatterer from harming us. Otherwise, we’d be like people who test deadly poisons by tasting them first and end up injuring or almost killing themselves in the process. We don’t commend such actions, nor do we help those who look at their friends solely in terms of appearances and usefulness, thinking they can immediately spot flattering companions. A friend shouldn't be unpleasant or unattractive, nor should friendship be overly serious or harsh; instead, it should exhibit a charm and warmth,352 because through it

"The Graces and Desire have set up their tents,"353

and not only to a person in misfortune "is it sweet to look into the eyes of a friendly person," as Euripides354 says, but no less does it bring pleasure and charm in good fortune, than when it relieves the sorrows and difficulties of adversity. And as Evenus said "fire was the best sauce,"355 so the deity, mixing up friendship with life, has made everything bright and sweet and acceptable by its presence and the enjoyment it brings. How else indeed could the flatterer insinuate himself by the pleasure he gives, unless he knew that friendship admitted the pleasurable element? It would be impossible to say. But just as spurious and mock gold only imitates the brightness and glitter of real gold, so the flatterer seems to imitate the pleasantness and agreeableness of the real friend, and to exhibit himself ever merry and bright, contradicting and opposing nothing. We must not however on that account suspect all who 156praise as simple flatterers. For friendship requires praise as much as censure on the proper occasion. Indeed peevishness and querulousness are altogether alien to friendship and social life: but when goodwill bestows praise ungrudgingly and readily upon good actions, people endure also easily and without pain admonition and plainspeaking, believing and continuing to love the person who took such pleasure in praising, as if now he only blamed out of necessity.

and not only to someone in trouble "is it sweet to look into the eyes of a friendly person," as Euripides354 says, but it also brings joy and delight in good times, just as it eases the sorrows and challenges of hard times. And as Evenus mentioned, "fire was the best sauce,"355 so the divine, mixing friendship with life, has made everything bright, sweet, and enjoyable through its presence and the joy it brings. How else could a flatterer insert themselves through the pleasure they provide unless they realized that friendship includes enjoyable aspects? It's hard to say. But just like fake gold only mimics the shine and sparkle of real gold, a flatterer seems to copy the warmth and charm of a true friend, always appearing cheerful and bright, not contradicting or opposing anything. However, we shouldn't suspect everyone who156praises as mere flatterers. Friendship needs praise just as much as it needs criticism at the right moments. In fact, irritability and complaining are completely foreign to friendship and social life: but when goodwill freely and willingly praises good deeds, people can also handle criticism and straightforwardness easily and without hurt, believing in and continuing to care for the person who so enjoys praising, as if they only criticized out of necessity.

§ iii. It is difficult then, someone may say, to distinguish between the flatterer and the friend, if they differ neither in the pleasure they give nor in the praise they bestow; for as to services and attentions you may often see friendship outstripped by flattery. Certainly it is so, I should reply, if we are trying to find the genuine flatterer who handles his craft with cleverness and art, but not if, like most people, we consider those persons flatterers who are called their own oil-flask-carriers and table-men, men who begin to talk, as one said, the moment their hands have been washed for dinner,356 whose servility, ribaldry, and want of all decency, is apparent at the first dish and glass. It did not of course require very much discrimination to detect Melanthius the parasite of Alexander of Pheræ of flattery, who, to those who asked how Alexander was murdered, answered, "Through his side into my belly": or those who formed a circle round a wealthy table, "whom neither fire, nor sword, nor steel, would keep from running to a feast":357 or those female flatterers in Cyprus, who after they crossed over into Syria were nicknamed "step-ladders,"358 because they lay down and let the kings' wives use their bodies as steps to mount their carriages.

§ iii. It's tough, someone might say, to tell the difference between a flatterer and a friend when they offer the same pleasure and praise. Often, you can see that flattery outshines genuine friendship in the services and attention given. That's true, I’d say, if we’re looking for a real flatterer who skillfully plays his role. But if, like most people, we view those who are just sycophants and hangers-on as flatterers—those who start talking the moment their hands are clean for dinner,356 whose servility, crude humor, and lack of decency are obvious from the first dish and drink—then it’s clear. It didn't take much insight to spot Melanthius, the parasite of Alexander of Pheræ, who, when asked how Alexander was killed, replied, "Through his side into my belly": or those who clustered around a wealthy table, "whom neither fire, nor sword, nor steel, would keep from running to a feast":357 or those female flatterers in Cyprus, who, after crossing into Syria, were nicknamed "step-ladders,"358 because they would lie down and let the kings' wives use them as steps to get into their carriages.

§ iv. What kind of flatterer then must we be on our guard against? The one who neither seems to be nor acknowledges himself to be one: whom you will not always find in the vicinity of your kitchen, who is not to be 157caught watching the dial to see how near it is to dinner-time,359 nor gets so drunk as to throw himself down anyhow, but one who is generally sober, and a busybody, and thinks he ought to have a hand in your affairs, and wishes to share in your secrets, and as to friendship plays rather a tragic than a satyric or comic part. For as Plato says, "it is the height of injustice to appear to be just when you are not really so,"360 so we must deem the most dangerous kind of flattery not the open but the secret, not the playful but the serious. For it throws suspicion even upon a genuine friendship, which we may often confound with it, if we are not careful. When Gobryas pursued one of the Magi into a dark room, and was on the ground wrestling with him, and Darius came up and was doubtful how he could kill one without killing both, Gobryas bade him thrust his sword boldly through both of them;361 but we, since we give no assent to that saying, "Let friend perish so the enemy perish with him,"362 in our endeavour to distinguish the flatterer from the friend, seeing that their resemblances are so many, ought to take great care that we do not reject the good with the bad, nor in sparing what is beneficial fall in with what is injurious. For as wild grains mixed up with wheat, if very similar in size and appearance, are not easily kept apart, for if the sieve have small holes they don't pass through, and if large holes they pass with the corn, so flattery is not easily distinguished from friendship, being mixed up with it in feeling and emotion, habit and custom.

§ iv. What kind of flatterer should we be cautious of? The one who doesn't seem like one and doesn't recognize himself as such: someone you won't always find hanging around your kitchen, who isn't watching the clock to see when dinner is, nor does he get so drunk that he falls over, but rather someone who generally stays sober, meddles in your business, feels entitled to be involved in your affairs, and wants to be included in your secrets. In terms of friendship, he plays a more serious than lighthearted role. As Plato says, "it is the height of injustice to appear just when you are not truly so," so we should consider the most dangerous form of flattery as not being overt but subtle, not playful but serious. It casts doubt even on real friendships, which we might often confuse with it if we're not careful. When Gobryas chased one of the Magi into a dark room and was wrestling with him on the ground, when Darius showed up and was unsure how to kill one without killing the other, Gobryas told him to boldly stab through both of them; but we, since we don’t agree with the idea, "Let the friend die so the enemy perishes too," in our effort to tell apart the flatterer from the friend, given their many similarities, should be cautious not to dismiss the good alongside the bad. We should ensure that in trying to protect what is beneficial, we don’t accidentally accept what is harmful. Just like wild grains mixed with wheat, if they look similar in size and appearance, they're hard to separate; if the sieve has small holes, they won’t fall through, and if it has large holes, they’ll mix with the wheat. Flattery is similarly hard to distinguish from friendship as they are intertwined in feelings, emotions, habits, and customs.

§ v. Because however friendship is the most pleasant of all things, and nothing more glads the heart of man, therefore the flatterer attracts by the pleasure he gives, pleasure being in fact his field. And because favours and good services accompany friendship, as the proverb says "a friend is more necessary than fire or water,"363 therefore 158the flatterer volunteers all sorts of services, and strives to show himself on all occasions zealous and obliging and ready. And since friendship is mainly produced by a similarity of tastes and habits, and to have the same likes and dislikes first brings people together and unites them through sympathy,364 the flatterer observing this moulds himself like material and demeans himself accordingly, seeking completely to imitate and resemble those whom he desires to ingratiate himself with, being supple in change, and plausible in his imitations, so that one would say,

§ v. Friendship is one of the most enjoyable things in life, and nothing brings more joy to a person's heart. That's why a flatterer draws people in with the pleasure they offer, as pleasure is essentially their specialty. Since favors and good deeds often accompany friendship—like the saying goes, "a friend is more necessary than fire or water,"363the flatterer willingly offers all kinds of help and tries to appear eager, helpful, and ready at every opportunity. Additionally, because friendship usually arises from shared tastes and habits, having the same likes and dislikes initially brings people together and connects them through empathy,364the flatterer, seeing this, shapes himself like clay and behaves accordingly, trying to fully imitate and resemble those he wants to win over, being adaptable and convincing in his mimicry, so that one might say,

"Achilles' son, oh no, it is him." 365

But his cleverest trick is that, observing that freedom of speech, is both spoken of and reckoned as the peculiar and natural voice of friendship, while not speaking freely is considered unfriendly and disingenuous, he has not failed to imitate this trait of friendship also. But just as clever cooks infuse bitter sauces and sharp seasoning to prevent sweet things from cloying, so these flatterers do not use a genuine or serviceable freedom of speech, but merely a winking and tickling innuendo. He is therefore difficult to detect, like those creatures which naturally change their colour and take that of the material or place near them.366 But since he deceives and conceals his true character by his imitations, it is our duty to unmask him and detect him by the differences between him and the true friend, and to show that he is, as Plato says, "tricked out in other people's colours and forms, from lack of any of his own."367

But his cleverest trick is that he notices that freedom of speech is often seen as a unique and natural expression of friendship, while not speaking freely is viewed as unfriendly and insincere. He has, therefore, adopted this aspect of friendship as well. Just like skilled cooks add bitter sauces and sharp spices to balance out sweetness, these flatterers don’t offer genuine or helpful freedom of speech; instead, they rely on sly remarks and veiled suggestions. As a result, he’s hard to spot, similar to those creatures that can naturally change their color to blend in with their surroundings. But since he deceives and hides his true nature through imitation, it’s our responsibility to reveal him and highlight the differences between him and a true friend, showing that he is, as Plato says, "dressed in other people's colors and shapes, due to lacking any of his own."

§ vi. Let us examine the matter then from the beginning. I said that friendship originated in most cases from a similar disposition and nature, generally inclined to the same habits and morals, and rejoicing in the same pursuits, studies, and amusements, as the following lines testify: "To old man the voice of old man is sweetest, to boy that of boy, to woman is most acceptable that of woman, to the sick person that of sick person, while he that is overtaken 159by misfortune is a comforter to one in trouble." The flatterer knowing then that it is innate in us to delight in, and enjoy the company of, and to love, those who are like ourselves, attempts first to approach and get near a person in this direction, (as one tries to catch an animal in the pastures,) by the same pursuits and amusements and studies and modes of life quietly throwing out his bait, and disguising himself in false colours, till his victim give him an opportunity to catch him, and become tame and tractable at his touch. Then too he censures the things and modes of life and persons that he knows his victim dislikes, while he praises those he fancies immoderately, overdoing it indeed368 with his show of surprise and excessive admiration, making him more and more convinced that his likes and dislikes are the fruits of judgement and not of caprice.

§ vi. Let's take a closer look at the issue from the start. I mentioned that friendships usually come from similar personalities and natures, often leaning toward the same habits and morals, and enjoying the same activities, studies, and fun, as shown in the following lines: "To an old person, the voice of another old person is sweetest; to a boy, it’s the voice of another boy; to a woman, it's most pleasing to hear another woman; and to someone who is sick, the voice of another sick person is comforting. Meanwhile, someone facing misfortune often finds comfort in someone else who is troubled." The flatterer, knowing that we naturally enjoy the company of and feel affection for those like ourselves, first tries to get close to a person in this way (like trying to catch an animal in the field) through similar interests and activities, quietly dropping hints and pretending to be something he's not, until his target gives him a chance to catch them and becomes meek and pliable at his touch. He also criticizes the things and lifestyles and people that he knows his target dislikes, while excessively praising those he thinks favorably of, going overboard with his fake surprise and admiration, making his target more convinced that their likes and dislikes are based on sound judgment rather than whim.

§ vii. How then is the flatterer convicted, and by what differences is he detected, of being only a counterfeit, and not really like his victim? We must first then look at the even tenor and consistency of his principles, if he always delights in the same things, and always praises the same things, and directs and governs his life after one pattern, as becomes the noble lover of consistent friendship and familiarity. Such a person is a friend. But the flatterer having no fixed character of his own,369 and not seeking to lead the life suitable for him, but shaping and modelling himself after another's pattern, is neither simple nor uniform, but complex and unstable, assuming different appearances, like water poured from vessel to vessel, ever in a state of flux and accommodating himself entirely to the fashion of those who entertain him. The ape indeed, as it seems, attempting to imitate man, is caught imitating his movements and dancing like him, but the flatterer himself attracts and decoys other men, imitating not all alike, for with one he sings and dances, with another he wrestles and gets covered with the dust of the palæstra, 160while he follows a third fond of hunting and the chase all but shouting out the words of Phædra,

§ vii. How can we identify the flatterer, and what clues show he is just a fake and not genuinely like his victim? First, we need to examine the steady nature and consistency of his values. If he continuously enjoys the same things, always praises the same things, and lives his life following one pattern, like a true friend valuing consistent companionship, then he is a friend. However, the flatterer has no stable identity of his own,369 and instead of striving for a life that suits him, he molds himself based on others’ patterns. He is neither straightforward nor steady, but rather intricate and unreliable, taking on different appearances like water flowing from one container to another, always shifting and completely adapting to the tastes of those around him. The ape, it seems, tries to mimic humans by copying their movements and dancing like them, but the flatterer himself ensnares and lures other people, imitating not everyone in the same way. With one person, he sings and dances; with another, he wrestles and gets dusty in the gym, 160 while with a third, who loves hunting, he nearly shouts Phaedra's words.

"How I wish to call out to the dogs, Chasing the spotted deer,370

and yet he has really no interest in the chase, it is the hunter himself he sets the toils and snares for. And if the object of his pursuit is some young scholar and lover of learning, he is all for books then, his beard flows down to his feet,371 he's quite a sight with his threadbare cloak, has all the indifference of the Stoic, and speaks of nothing but the rectangles and triangles of Plato. But if any rich and careless fellow fond of drink come in his way,

and yet he really has no interest in the chase; it's the hunter himself for whom he sets the traps. If the target of his pursuit is some young student and lover of knowledge, he’s all about books then, his beard flowing down to his feet, 371 he’s quite a sight in his worn cloak, exuding all the indifference of a Stoic, and he talks only about the rectangles and triangles of Plato. But if any wealthy, careless guy who enjoys drinking crosses his path,

"Then wise Odysseus took off his rags,"372

his threadbare cloak is thrown aside, his beard is shorn off like a fruitless crop, he goes in for wine-coolers and tankards, and laughs loudly in the streets, and jeers at philosophers. As they say happened at Syracuse, when Plato went there, and Dionysius was seized with a furious passion for philosophy, and so great was the concourse of geometricians that they raised up quite a cloud of dust in the palace, but when Plato fell out of favour, and Dionysius gave up philosophy, and went back again headlong to wine and women and trifles and debauchery, then all the court was metamorphosed, as if they all had drunk of Circe's cup, for ignorance and oblivion and silliness reigned rampant. I am borne out in what I say by the behaviour of great flatterers and demagogues,373 the greatest of whom Alcibiades, a jeerer and horse-rearer at Athens, and living a gay and merry life, wore his hair closely shaven at Lacedæmon, and washed in cold water, and attired himself in a threadbare cloak; while in Thrace he fought374 and drank; and at Tissaphernes' court lived delicately and luxuriously and in a pretentious style; and thus curried favour and was 161popular with everybody by imitating their habits and ways. Such was not the way however in which Epaminondas or Agesilaus acted, for though they associated with very many men and states and different modes of life, they maintained everywhere their usual demeanour, both in dress and diet and language and behaviour. So Plato375 at Syracuse was exactly the same man as in the Academy, the same with Dionysius as with Dion.

His worn-out cloak is tossed aside, his beard is trimmed off like a useless harvest. He indulges in wine coolers and tankards, laughs loudly in the streets, and mocks philosophers. This reminds me of what happened in Syracuse when Plato visited, and Dionysius was struck by a strong passion for philosophy. There was such a gathering of mathematicians that they kicked up a huge cloud of dust in the palace. But when Plato lost favor and Dionysius abandoned philosophy, diving back into wine, women, trivialities, and excess, the entire court transformed, as if they had all drunk from Circe's cup, with ignorance and foolishness running wild. My point is supported by the behavior of prominent flatterers and demagogues, the most famous of whom was Alcibiades, a mocker and horse breeder in Athens who lived a carefree life. He wore his hair closely shaved in Lacedæmon, bathed in cold water, and dressed in a shabby cloak. In Thrace, he fought and drank, and at Tissaphernes' court, he lived in luxury and pretense, currying favor and becoming popular by mimicking others' lifestyles. However, Epaminondas and Agesilaus acted differently; despite mingling with many people, cultures, and ways of life, they maintained their usual demeanor in dress, diet, language, and behavior. Plato in Syracuse was exactly the same man as he was in the Academy, the same with Dionysius as with Dion.

§ viii. As to the changes of the flatterer, which resemble those of the polypus,376 a man may most easily detect them by himself pretending to change about frequently, and by censuring the kind of life he used formerly to praise, and anon approving of the words actions and modes of life that he used to be displeased with. He will then see that the flatterer is never consistent or himself, never loving hating rejoicing grieving at his own initiative, but like a mirror, merely reflecting the image of other people's emotions and manners and feelings. Such a one will say, if you censure one of your friends to him, "You are slow in finding the fellow out, he never pleased me from the first." But if on the other hand you change your language and praise him, he will swear by Zeus that he rejoices at it, and is himself under obligations to the man, and believes in him. And if you talk of the necessity of changing your mode of life, of retiring from public life to a life of privacy and ease, he says, "We ought long ago to have got rid of uproar377 and envy." But if you think of returning again to public life, he chimes in, "Your sentiments do you honour: retirement from business is pleasant, but inglorious and mean." One ought to say at once to such a one, "'Stranger, quite different now you look to what you did before.'378 I do not need a friend to change his opinions with me and to assent to me in everything, my shadow will do that better, but I need one that will speak the truth and help me with his judgement." This is one way of detecting the flatterer.

§ viii. As for the changes in the flatterer, which are similar to those of a chameleon,376 a person can easily spot them by pretending to shift their own views frequently and by criticizing the lifestyle they once praised, while soon after endorsing the words, actions, and lifestyles they previously disliked. They will then realize that the flatterer is never consistent or true to themselves, never genuinely loving, hating, rejoicing, or grieving on their own, but rather like a mirror, simply reflecting the emotions, behaviors, and feelings of others. Such a person will say, if you criticize one of your friends to them, "You're slow to figure him out; he never impressed me from the start." But if you change your tone and speak positively about that friend, they will swear by Zeus that they’re thrilled about it, feel indebted to the person, and genuinely believe in them. And if you mention the need to change your lifestyle, retreat from public life, and embrace ease and privacy, they'll say, "We should have ditched the noise377 and jealousy a long time ago." However, if you consider going back to public life, they'll chime in, "Your views are commendable: stepping back from work is comfortable, but it's also inglorious and low." One should quickly point out to such a person, "'Stranger, you look different now than you did before.'378 I don’t need a friend who changes their opinions to match mine and agrees with me on everything; my shadow can do that better. I need someone who will speak the truth and challenge me with their judgment." This is one way to identify the flatterer.

§ ix. We must also observe another difference in the resemblance between the friend and flatterer. The true friend does not imitate you in everything, nor is he too keen to praise, but praises only what is excellent, for as Sophocles says,

§ ix. We should also note another distinction in the similarity between a friend and a flatterer. A true friend doesn't copy you in everything, nor are they overly eager to give compliments; they only praise what is genuinely outstanding, because as Sophocles says,

"He wasn't born to spread hate but love,"379

yes, by Zeus, and he is born to share in doing what is right and in loving what is noble, and not to share in wrong-doing or misbehaviour, unless it be that, as a running of the eyes is catching, so through companionship and intimacy he may against his will contract by infection some vice or ill habit, as they say Plato's intimates imitated his stoop, Aristotle's his lisp, and king Alexander's his holding his head a little on one side, and rapidity of utterance in conversation,380 for people mostly pick up unawares such traits of character. But the flatterer is exactly like the chameleon,381 which takes every colour but white, and so he, though unable to imitate what is worth his while, leaves nothing that is bad unimitated. And just as poor painters unable to make a fine portrait from inefficiency in their craft, bring out the likeness by painting all the wrinkles, moles and scars, so the flatterer imitates his friend's intemperance, superstition, hot temper, sourness to domestics, suspicion of his friends and relations. For he is by nature inclined to what is worst, and thinks that imitation of what is bad is as far as possible removed from censure. For those are suspected who have noble aims in life, and seem to be vexed and disgusted at their friends' faults, for that injured and even ruined Dion with Dionysius, Samius with Philip, and Cleomenes with Ptolemy. But he that wishes to be and appear at the same time both agreeable and trustworthy pretends 163to rejoice more in what is bad, as being through excessive love for his friend not even offended at his vices, but as one with him in feeling and nature in all matters. And so they claim to share in involuntary and chance ailments, and pretend to have the same complaints, in flattery to those who suffer from any, as that their eyesight and sense of hearing are deficient, if their friends are somewhat blind or deaf, as the flatterers of Dionysius, who was rather short-sighted, jostled one another at a dinner party, and knocked the dishes off the table, as if from defect of vision.382 And some to make their cases more similar wind themselves in closer, and dive even into family secrets for parallels. For seeing that their friends are unfortunate in marriage, or suspicious about the behaviour of their sons or relations, they do not spare themselves, but make quite a Jeremiad about their own sons, or wife, or kinsfolk, or relations, proclaiming loudly their own family secrets. For similarity in situation makes people more sympathetic, and their friends having received as it were hostages by their confessions, entrust them in return with their secrets, and having once made confidants of them, dare not take back their confidence.383 I actually know of a man who turned his wife out of doors because his friend had put away his; but as he secretly visited her and sent messages to her, he was detected by his friend's wife noticing his conduct. So little did he know the nature of a flatterer that thought the following lines more applicable to a crab than a flatterer, "His whole body is belly, his eye is on everything, he is a creature creeping on his teeth," for such is a true picture of the parasite, "friends of the frying-pan, hunting for a dinner," to borrow the language of Eupolis.

yes, by Zeus, and he is born to do what’s right and to love what’s noble, not to engage in wrongdoing or misbehavior, unless, like catching someone’s eye, through companionship and closeness he might unintentionally pick up some vice or bad habit, as they say Plato’s friends copied his stoop, Aristotle’s his lisp, and King Alexander’s his tilted head and fast speech in conversation,380 because people often unknowingly adopt such traits. But the flatterer is just like a chameleon,381 which absorbs every color except white, and though he can’t imitate what’s truly admirable, he will mimic everything bad. Similarly, poor painters, unable to create a fine portrait because of their lack of skill, bring out the likeness by highlighting all the wrinkles, moles, and scars, and thus the flatterer copies his friend’s excess, superstition, bad temper, harshness to servants, and distrust of his friends and family. He is naturally inclined toward the worst and believes that imitating bad behavior is as far from criticism as possible. Those with noble aspirations are often suspected and seen as annoyed and disgusted by their friends’ flaws, which led to the downfall of Dion by Dionysius, Samius by Philip, and Cleomenes by Ptolemy. But someone who wants to appear both likable and trustworthy pretends 163to take pleasure in what is bad, claiming that out of great love for his friend, he is not even bothered by his vices, but shares in feelings and nature. They pretend to share involuntary ailments and mimic the complaints of those who suffer, such as feeble eyesight or hearing, if their friends are somewhat blind or deaf, like the flatterers of Dionysius, who was somewhat short-sighted, bumping into each other at a dinner and knocking dishes off the table,as if from defect of vision.382 Some even tighten the bond further and delve into family matters for parallels. When they see their friends struggling in marriage or questioning the actions of their sons or relatives, they hold nothing back, lamenting their own sons, wives, relatives, or family secrets loudly. Shared situations create sympathy, and their friends, having received secrets like hostages through their confessions, entrust them with their own secrets and, once they’ve made confidants of them, hesitate to withdraw their trust.383 I actually know a man who threw his wife out because his friend had done the same, but when he secretly visited her and sent her messages, his friend’s wife caught on to his actions. He understood so little about the nature of a flatterer that he thought these lines were more fitting for a crab than a flatterer: "His whole body is belly, his eye is on everything, he is a creature crawling on his teeth," for such is a true depiction of the parasite, "friends of the frying-pan, hunting for a dinner," to borrow the words of Eupolis.

§ x. However let us put off all this to its proper place in the discourse. But let us not fail to notice the wiliness of the flatterer's imitation, in that, even if he imitates any good points in the person he flatters, he always takes care to give him the palm. Whereas among real friends there is no rivalry or jealousy of one another, but they are satisfied and contented alike whether they are equal or one of them 164is superior. But the flatterer, ever remembering that he is to play second fiddle,384 makes his copy always fall a little short of the original, for he admits that he is everywhere outstripped and left behind, except in vice. For in that alone he claims pre-eminence, for if his friend is peevish, he says he is atrabilious; if his friend is superstitious, he says he is a fanatic; if his friend is in love, he says he is madly in love; if his friend laughs, he will say, "You laughed a little unseasonably, but I almost died of laughter." But in regard to any good points his action is quite the opposite. He says he can run quickly, but his friend flies; he says he can ride pretty well, but his friend is a Centaur on horseback. He says "I am not a bad poet, and don't write very bad lines,"

§ x. Nevertheless, let’s save all of this for later in the discussion. But we shouldn't overlook the cunning nature of the flatterer's imitation; even when he copies some good traits from the person he flatters, he always makes sure to give them the top spot. In contrast, among true friends, there’s no rivalry or jealousy; they are equally happy and satisfied whether they are equals or if one is 164superior. However, the flatterer, always aware that he plays a supporting role,384 ensures his imitation falls short of the original because he knows he is always overshadowed and left behind, except in wrongdoing. In that area alone does he claim superiority; if his friend is irritable, he calls him moody; if his friend is superstitious, he labels him fanatical; if his friend is in love, he says he is hopelessly in love; and if his friend laughs, he might say, "You laughed at an awkward moment, but I nearly died of laughter." However, regarding any positive traits, his stance is completely the opposite. He boasts that he can run fast, but his friend is much quicker; he claims he can ride well, but his friend is like a centaur on horseback. He says, "I’m not a bad poet, and I don’t write terrible lines,"

"But your powerful verse is like Jove's thunder."

Thus he shows at once that his friend's aims in life are good, and that his friend has reached a height he cannot soar to. Such then are the differences in the resemblances between the flatterer and the friend.

Thus he shows at once that his friend's goals in life are good, and that his friend has achieved a level he cannot reach. These are the differences in the similarities between the flatterer and the friend.

§ xi. But since, as has been said before, to give pleasure is common to both, for the good man delights in his friends as much as the bad man in his flatterers, let us consider the difference between them here too. The difference lies in the different aim of each in giving pleasure. Look at it this way. There is no doubt a sweet smell in perfume. So there is also in medicine. But the difference is that while in perfume pleasure and nothing else is designed, in medicine either purging, or warming, or adding flesh to the system, is the primary object, and the sweet smell is only a secondary consideration. Again painters mix gay colours and dyes: there are also some drugs which are gay in appearance and not unpleasing in colour. What then is the difference between these? Manifestly we distinguish by the end each aims at. So too the social life of friends employs mirth to add a charm to some good and useful end,385 and sometimes makes joking and a good table and wine, aye, and even chaff and banter, the seasoning to 165noble and serious matters, as in the line,

§ xi. But since, as mentioned earlier, both good and bad people find joy in their relationships—good people delight in their friends just as much as bad people do in their flatterers—let’s take a look at how they differ. The distinction lies in their different goals when it comes to giving pleasure. Consider this: there’s undoubtedly a pleasant scent in perfume, just as there is in medicine. However, the key difference is that in perfume, the intention is purely to provide pleasure, while in medicine, the main goal is to cleanse, warm, or build up the body, with the pleasant scent being a secondary aspect. Similarly, artists use bright colors and dyes, just as some medicines are visually appealing and colorful. So what sets these apart? Clearly, we can tell them apart based on the purpose each serves. Likewise, the social interactions among friends use humor to enhance a good and useful purpose,385 and sometimes make fun, a good meal, and wine, even teasing and banter, the spice to 165important and serious topics, as illustrated in the line,

"They really enjoyed talking to each other,"386

and again,

and again,

"Never did anything else" "Interfere with our love or happiness for each other." 387

But the flatterer's whole aim and end is to cook up and season his joke or word or action, so as to produce pleasure. And to speak concisely, the flatterer's object is to please in everything he does, whereas the true friend always does what is right, and so often gives pleasure, often pain, not wishing the latter, but not shunning it either, if he deems it best. For as the physician, if it be expedient, infuses saffron or spikenard, aye, or uses some soothing fomentation or feeds his patient up liberally, and sometimes orders castor,

But the flatterer’s main goal is to craft and spice up his joke, words, or actions to create pleasure. To put it simply, the flatterer aims to please in everything he does, while a true friend always acts with what's right in mind, which often brings both pleasure and pain. The true friend doesn’t intend to cause pain but isn’t afraid of it either if he thinks it’s necessary. Just like a doctor who, when it’s best for the patient, might use saffron or spikenard, or provides soothing treatments, or makes sure the patient eats well, and sometimes prescribes castor,

"Or poley,__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ that smells so strong and awful,"

or pounds hellebore and compels him to drink it,—neither in the one case making unpleasantness, nor in the other pleasantness, his end and aim, but in both studying only the interest of his patient,—so the friend sometimes by praise and kindness, extolling him and gladdening his heart, leads him to what is noble, as Agamemnon,

or pounds hellebore and forces him to drink it—neither in the first case does he intend to create discomfort, nor in the second does he aim for pleasure; instead, he focuses solely on his patient's well-being—similarly, a friend sometimes, through praise and kindness, lifts him up and fills his heart with joy, guiding him toward what is good, like Agamemnon.

"Teucer, dear friend, you son of Telamon, "Keep shooting like this, captain of your crew;"389

or Diomede,

or Diomede,

"How could I ever forget divine Odysseus?"390

But where on the other hand there is need of correction, then he rebukes with biting words and with the freedom worthy of a friend,

But when correction is needed, he calls out the issue with sharp words and the honesty that comes from a true friend,

"Zeus-loved Menelaus, are you crazy?" "And in your foolishness, you pay no attention to safety?"391

Sometimes also he joins action to word, as Menedemus sobered the profligate and disorderly son of his friend Asclepiades, by shutting him out of his house, and not speaking to him. And Arcesilaus forbade Bato his school, 166when he wrote a line in one of his plays against Cleanthes, and only got reconciled with him after he repented and made his peace with Cleanthes. For we ought to give our friend pain if it will benefit him, but not to the extent of breaking off our friendship; but just as we make use of some biting medicine, that will save and preserve the life of the patient. And so the friend, like a musician, in bringing about an improvement to what is good and expedient, sometimes slackens the chords, sometimes tightens them, and is often pleasant, but always useful. But the flatterer, always harping on one note, and accustomed to play his accompaniment only with a view to please and to ingratiate himself, knows not how either to oppose in deed, or give pain in word, but complies only with every wish, ever chiming in with and echoing the sentiments of his patron. As then Xenophon says Agesilaus took pleasure in being praised by those who would also censure him,392 so ought we to think that to please and gratify us is friendly in the person who can also give us pain and oppose us, but to feel suspicion at an intercourse which is merely for pleasure and gratification, and never pungent, aye and by Zeus to have ready that saying of the Lacedæmonian, who, on hearing king Charillus praised, said, "How can he be a good man, who is not severe even to the bad?"

Sometimes he combines action with words, like Menedemus did when he sobered up the reckless and unruly son of his friend Asclepiades by shutting him out of his house and refusing to speak to him. Arcesilaus also banned Bato from his school 166 after he wrote a line in a play that criticized Cleanthes, only reconciling with him after he apologized and made peace with Cleanthes. We should give our friends tough love if it benefits them, but not to the point of ending our friendship; it’s like using a strong medicine that can save and protect a patient’s life. A true friend, like a musician, knows how to improve what is beneficial—sometimes loosening the strings and other times tightening them—always being pleasant but consistently useful. In contrast, a flatterer only plays the same pleasing tune, always trying to ingratiate themselves, never opposing or challenging, merely echoing the wishes of their patron. As Xenophon points out, Agesilaus enjoyed praise from those who would also criticize him; similarly, we should appreciate friends who can please and also challenge us, and be wary of relationships that are solely for pleasure and never make us think or hurt, remembering the saying of the Lacedæmonian who, after hearing king Charillus praised, remarked, "How can he be a good man if he isn’t even strict with the bad?"

§ xii. They say the gadfly attacks bulls, and the tick dogs, in the ear: so the flatterer besieges with praise the ears of those who are fond of praise, and sticks there and is hard to dislodge. We ought therefore here to make a wide-awake and careful discrimination, whether the praise is bestowed on the action or the man. It is bestowed on the action, if people praise the absent rather than the present, if also those that have the same aims and aspirations praise not only us but all that are similarly disposed, and do not evidently say and do one thing at one time, and the direct contrary at another; and the greatest test is if we are conscious, in the matters for which we get the praise, that we have not regretted them, and are not ashamed at them, and would not rather have said and done differently. For 167our own inward judgement, testifying the contrary and not admitting the praise, is above passion, and impregnable and proof against the flatterer. But I know not how it is that most people in misfortune cannot bear exhortation, but are captivated more by condolence and sympathy, and when they have done something wrong and acted amiss, he that by censure and blame implants in them the stings of repentance is looked upon by them as hostile and an accuser, while they welcome and regard as friendly and well-disposed to them the person who bestows praise and panegyric on what they have done. Those then that readily praise and join in applauding some word or action on the part of someone whether in jest or earnest, only do temporary harm for the moment, but those who injure the character by their praise, aye, and by their flattery undermine the morals, act like those slaves who do not steal from the bin, but from the seed corn.393 For they pervert the disposition, which is the seed of actions, and the character, which is the principle and fountain of life, by attaching to vice names that belong properly only to virtue. For as Thucydides says,394 in times of faction and war "people change the accustomed meaning of words as applied to acts at their will and pleasure, for reckless daring is then considered bravery to one's comrades, and prudent delay specious cowardice, and sober-mindedness the cloak of the coward, and taking everything into account before action a real desire to do nothing." So too in the case of flattery we must observe and be on our guard against wastefulness being called liberality, and cowardliness prudence, and madness quick-wittedness, and meanness frugality, and the amorous man called social and affectionate, and the term manly applied to the passionate and vain man, and the term civil applied to the paltry and mean man. As I remember Plato395 says the lover is a flatterer 168of the beloved one, and calls the snub nose graceful, and the aquiline nose royal, and swarthy people manly, and fair people the children of the gods, and the olive complexion is merely the lover's phrase to gloss over and palliate excessive pallor. And yet the ugly man persuaded he is handsome, or the short man persuaded he is tall, cannot long remain in the error, and receives only slight injury from it, and not irreparable mischief: but praise applied to vices as if they were virtues, so that one is not vexed but delighted with a vicious life, removes all shame from wrong-doing, and was the ruin of the Sicilians, by calling the savage cruelty of Dionysius and Phalaris detestation of wickedness and uprightness. It was the ruin of Egypt, by styling Ptolemy's effeminacy, and superstition, and howlings, and beating of drums, religion and service to the gods.396 It was nearly the overthrow and destruction of the ancient manners of the Romans, palliating the luxury and intemperance and display of Antony as exhibitions of jollity and kindliness, when his power and fortune were at their zenith. What else invested Ptolemy397 with his pipe and fiddle? What else brought Nero398 on the tragic stage, and invested him with the mask and buskins? Was it not the praise of flatterers? And are not many kings called Apollos if they can just sing a song,399 and Dionysuses if they get drunk, and Herculeses if they can wrestle, and do they not joy in such titles, and are they not dragged into every kind of disgrace by flattery?

§ xii. They say that the gadfly bothers bulls, just as a tick annoys dogs in their ears: similarly, the flatterer bombards the ears of those who love compliments with praise and sticks around, making it hard to get rid of them. We should therefore be wide awake and make careful distinctions about whether the praise is aimed at the action or the person. Praise is directed at the action if people commend those who aren’t there instead of those who are present, if those with similar goals and aspirations praise not just us but everyone else in the same boat, and if they don’t clearly say one thing at one time and the exact opposite at another; the biggest test is whether we are aware, regarding the things we are praised for, that we have no regrets and feel no shame about them, and wouldn’t wish we had acted differently. Our own inner judgment, which counters the praise, stands above passion and is immune to flatterers. However, I don’t understand why most people in tough times struggle to accept advice, gravitating instead towards consolation and sympathy. When they mess up and act poorly, the person who criticizes and holds them accountable making them feel regret is viewed as an enemy and an accuser, while they welcome and see as friendly the one who showers them with praise for their misdeeds. So those who easily applaud some action or statement from someone, whether jokingly or sincerely, only cause temporary harm in the moment, but those who damage a person's character with their praise, and who through their flattery sabotage morals, act like slaves who don’t steal from the storage, but from the seed corn.393 They corrupt the nature that is the root of actions, and the character that is the foundation of life, by attaching to vice names that should only belong to virtue. As Thucydides states,394 in times of conflict and war, "people alter the usual meanings of words regarding actions as they wish, for reckless daring is seen as bravery by peers, and cautious delay is falsely viewed as cowardice, sober-mindedness is seen as a cover for cowardice, and thoroughly considering before acting as a true desire to do nothing." Likewise, in the case of flattery, we must be careful not to confuse wastefulness with generosity, cowardice with prudence, madness with cleverness, stinginess with thriftiness, and the lustful man with being social and affectionate, and the terms manly being applied to the passionate and vain, and civil to the petty and small-minded. As I recall, Plato395 mentions that the lover is a flatterer of the beloved, calling a snub nose attractive, an aquiline nose noble, and dark-skinned people manly, while fair-skinned individuals are called the offspring of gods, and olive skin is merely the lover’s way of dressing up excessive paleness. Yet, an ugly person convinced they are handsome, or a short person believing they are tall, can only persist in that delusion for so long, suffering only minor harm, not irreparable damage: but praising vices as if they were virtues, making one not agitated but pleased with a vicious life, removes all shame from wrongdoing, leading to the downfall of the Sicilians, by referring to the savage cruelty of Dionysius and Phalaris as a rejection of wickedness and a commitment to righteousness. It was the downfall of Egypt, calling Ptolemy's decadence, superstition, and wild rituals religion and worship of the gods.396 It nearly caused the collapse and destruction of ancient Roman values, downplaying Antony’s excess and indulgence as displays of happiness and generosity when his power and fortune were at their peak. What else empowered Ptolemy397 with his pipe and fiddle? What else brought Nero398 onto the tragic stage, draping him in a disguise and costume? Was it not the flattery of admirers? And aren’t many kings referred to as Apollos if they can just sing a song,399 and Dionysuses if they indulge in drink, and Herculeses if they can wrestle? Do they not take pride in such titles, and are they not dragged into every sort of disgrace by flattery?

§ xiii. Wherefore we must be especially on our guard against the flatterer in regard to praise; as indeed he is very well aware himself, and clever to avoid suspicion. If he light upon some dandy, or rustic in a thick leather garment, he treats him with nothing but jeers and mocks,400 as Struthias insulted Bias, ironically praising him for his stupidity, saying, "You have drunk more than king Alex169ander,"401 and, "that he was ready to die of laughing at his tale about the Cyprian."402 But when he sees people more refined very much on their guard, and observing both time and place, he does not praise them directly, but draws off a little and wheels round and approaches them noiselessly, as one tries to catch a wild animal. For sometimes he reports to a man the panegyric of other persons upon him, (as orators do, introducing some third person,) saying that he had a very pleasant conversation in the market with some strangers and men of worth, who mentioned how they admired his many good points. On another occasion he concocts and fabricates some false and trifling charges against him, pretending he has heard them from other people, and runs up with a serious face and inquires, where he said or did such and such a thing. And upon his denying he ever did, he pounces on him at once403 and compliments his man with, "I thought it strange that you should have spoken ill of your friends, seeing that you don't even treat your enemies so: and that you should have tried to rob other people, seeing that you are so lavish with your own money."

§ xiii. Therefore, we need to be especially cautious of flatterers when it comes to praise; they know this very well and are skilled at avoiding suspicion. If they come across someone flashy or a country bumpkin dressed in heavy leather, they mock and ridicule him, as Struthias did to Bias, sarcastically complimenting him for his foolishness by saying, "You've drunk more than King Alexander," and, "He was ready to die laughing at your story about the Cyprian." But when he notices more refined people being cautious and aware of the right moment and setting, he doesn’t praise them outright. Instead, he steps back a bit and approaches quietly, like someone trying to catch a wild animal. Sometimes he lets a person know what others have said about him (like orators do when bringing up a third party), claiming he had a pleasant chat in the market with some strangers and respected individuals who expressed admiration for his many good qualities. At other times, he makes up some trivial and false accusations against him, pretending he heard them from others, and then approaches with a serious expression, asking where he said or did something specific. When that person denies it, he jumps on the chance and praises him, saying, "I found it strange that you would speak badly of your friends, considering you don't even treat your enemies that way: and that you would try to take advantage of others when you're so generous with your own money."

§ xiv. Other flatterers again, just as painters heighten the effect of their pictures by the combination of light and shade, so by censure abuse detraction and ridicule of the opposite virtues secretly praise and foment the actual vices of those they flatter. Thus they censure modesty as merely rustic behaviour in the company of profligates, and greedy people, and villains, and such as have got rich by evil and dishonourable courses; and contentment and uprightness they call having no spirit or energy in action; and when they associate with lazy and idle persons who avoid all public duties, they are not ashamed to call the life of a citizen wearisome meddling in other people's affairs, and the desire to hold office fruitless vain-glory. And some ere now to flatter an orator have depreciated a philosopher, and others won favour with wanton women by traducing those wives who are faithful to their husbands as constitutionally cold and countrybred. And by an acme of villainy flatterers 170do not always spare even themselves. For as wrestlers stoop that they may the easier give their adversaries a fall, so by censuring themselves they glide into praising others. "I am a cowardly slave," says such a one, "at sea, I shirk labour, I am madly in rage if a word is said against me; but this man fears nothing, has no vices, is a rare good fellow, patient and easy in all circumstances." But if a person has an excellent idea of his own good sense, and desires to be austere and self-opinionated, and in his moral rectitude is ever spouting that line of Homer,

§ xiv. Other flatterers, just like painters enhance their artwork with light and shadow, use criticism to undermine and mock the opposite virtues while secretly praising and encouraging the flaws of those they flatter. They criticize modesty as just simple behavior in the company of immoral people, greedy individuals, and those who have become wealthy through dishonest means; they label contentment and integrity as signs of weakness or lack of drive. When they hang out with lazy and idle people who avoid public responsibilities, they shamelessly call the life of a citizen a tiresome interference in others' business, and the desire for public office as pointless vanity. Some have even belittled philosophers to flatter an orator, while others have tried to win favor with promiscuous women by criticizing faithful wives as inherently cold and provincial. In an extreme act of treachery, these flatterers 170 don’t even spare themselves. Just as wrestlers bend down to more easily topple their opponents, they undermine themselves to slip into praising others. "I’m a cowardly slave," one might say, "at sea, I avoid hard work, I fly into a rage if anyone says something negative about me; but this guy fears nothing, has no faults, is an exceptionally good person, patient and easygoing in all situations." However, if someone has a high opinion of their own judgment, and aims to be strict and self-righteous, they often find themselves quoting that line from Homer,

"Tydides, don't praise or blame me too much,"404

the artistic flatterer does not attack him as he attacked others, but employs against such a one a new device. For he comes to him about his own private affairs, as if desirous to have the advice of one wiser than himself; he has, he says, more intimate friends, but he is obliged to trouble him; "for whither shall we that are deficient in judgement go? whom shall we trust?" And having listened to his utterance he departs, saying he has received an oracle not an opinion. And if he notices that somebody lays claim to experience in oratory, he gives him some of his writings, and begs him to read and correct them. So, when king Mithridates took a fancy to play the surgeon, several of his friends offered themselves for operating upon, as for cutting or cauterizing, flattering in deed and not in word, for his being credited by them would seem to prove his skill.405

The artistic flatterer doesn’t attack like he does with others; instead, he uses a different approach. He comes to the person with his own personal issues, pretending he seeks guidance from someone wiser. He claims to have closer friends but feels he must bother this person because, "Where else can we, who lack judgment, turn? Who can we trust?" After hearing what he has to say, he leaves, claiming he has received a revelation, not just an opinion. If he notices someone claiming to be experienced in speaking, he shares some of his writings and asks them to read and correct it. Similarly, when King Mithridates wanted to play the surgeon, several of his friends volunteered to be operated on, whether for cutting or cauterizing, flattering him through their actions, not just words, as their trust would likely demonstrate his skill.405

"For Providence has many different facets." __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

But we can test this kind of negative praise, that needs more wary caution, by purposely giving strange advice and suggestions, and by adopting absurd corrections. For if he raises no objection but nods assent to everything, and approves of everything, and is always crying out, "Good! How admirable!" he is evidently

But we can test this type of negative praise, which requires more careful attention, by intentionally giving odd advice and suggestions, and by making ridiculous corrections. Because if he doesn’t object but instead agrees with everything, and approves of everything, and is always exclaiming, "Good! How wonderful!" he is clearly

"Requesting advice, but looking for something different,"

wishing by praise to puff you up.

wishing to inflate you with compliments.

171§ xv. Moreover, as some have defined painting to be silent poetry,407 so is there praise in silent flattery. For as hunters are more likely to catch the objects of their chase unawares, if they do not openly appear to be so engaged, but seem to be walking, or tending their sheep, or looking after the farm, so flatterers obtain most success in their praise, when they do not seem to be praising but to be doing something else. For he who gives up his place or seat to the great man when he comes in, and while making a speech to the people or senate breaks off even in the middle, if he observes any rich man wants to speak, and gives up to him alike speech and platform, shows by his silence even more than he would by any amount of vociferation that he thinks the other the better man, and superior to him in judgement. And consequently you may always see them occupying the best places at theatres and public assembly rooms, not that they think themselves worthy of them, but that they may flatter the rich by giving up their places to them; and at public meetings they begin speaking first, and then make way as for better men, and most readily take back their own view, if any influential or rich or famous person espouse the contrary view. And so one can see plainly that all such servility and drawing back on their part is a lowering their sails, not to experience or virtue or age, but to wealth and fame. Not so Apelles the famous painter, who, when Megabyzus sat with him, and wished to talk about lines and shades, said to him, "Do you see my lads yonder grinding colours, they admired just now your purple and gold, but now they are laughing at you for beginning to talk about what you don't understand."408 And Solon, when Crœsus asked him about happiness, replied that Tellus, an obscure Athenian, and Bito and Cleobis were happier than he was.409 But flatterers proclaim kings and rich men and rulers not only happy and fortunate, but also pre-eminent for wisdom, and art, and every virtue.

171§ xv. Moreover, just as some have described painting as silent poetry,407 flattery operates in silence as well. Hunters are more likely to catch their prey off guard if they don’t act like hunters but instead seem to be just walking, tending to their sheep, or managing their farm. Similarly, flatterers achieve the most success in their compliments when they don’t appear to be praising but seem to be engaged in something else. When someone gives up their seat for a prominent person who comes in, or interrupts their speech to the people or senate to allow a wealthy person to speak instead, their silence communicates even more than loud words ever could—it shows they believe the other person is superior. You can often find these individuals occupying the best seats in theaters and public venues, not because they think they deserve them, but to flatter the wealthy by yielding their places. At public events, they often start speaking first, only to step aside as if for someone better, and will quickly shift their stance if any influential, wealthy, or famous person takes a different position. It’s clear that this servility and retreat are not based on experience, virtue, or age, but solely on wealth and fame. This wasn’t the case for Apelles, the famous painter, who, when Megabyzus sat with him and wanted to discuss lines and shades, said, “Do you see those young men over there grinding colors? They just admired your purple and gold, but now they’re laughing at you for trying to discuss something you don’t understand.”408 And when Crœsus asked Solon about happiness, he answered that Tellus, a humble Athenian, along with Bito and Cleobis, were actually happier than he was.409 Yet, flatterers portray kings, wealthy individuals, and rulers as not only happy and fortunate but also superior in wisdom, skill, and every virtue.

172§ xvi. Now some cannot bear to hear the assertion of the Stoics410 that the wise man is at once rich, and handsome, and noble, and a king; but flatterers declare that the rich man is at once orator and poet, and (if he likes) painter, and flute-player, and swift-footed, and strong, falling down if he wrestles with them, and if contending with him in running letting him win the race, as Crisso of Himera purposely allowed Alexander to outrun him, which vexed the king very much when he heard of it.411 And Carneades said that the sons of rich men and kings learnt nothing really well and properly except how to ride, for their master praised and flattered them in their studies, and the person who taught them wrestling always let them throw him, whereas the horse, not knowing or caring whether his rider were a private person or ruler, rich or poor, soon threw him over his head if he could not ride well. Simple therefore and fatuous was that remark of Bion, "If you could by encomiums make your field to yield well and be fruitful, you could not be thought wrong in tilling it so rather than digging it and labouring in it: nor would it be strange in you to praise human beings if by so doing you could be useful and serviceable to them." For a field does not become worse by being praised, but those who praise a man falsely and against his deserts puff him up and ruin him.

172§ xvi. Some people can’t stand the Stoics' claim410 that a wise person is inherently rich, attractive, noble, and a ruler; meanwhile, flattering people say that a wealthy person can be an orator, poet, painter, flute player, incredibly fast, and strong. They’ll even let him win in competitions, just like Crisso of Himera intentionally allowed Alexander to outrun him, which really upset the king when he found out.411 Carneades argued that the sons of wealthy individuals and kings don’t truly learn anything well except how to ride horses, because their teachers praise and flatter them in their studies, and the wrestling coach always lets them win. But a horse, not caring whether its rider is a commoner or a ruler, will throw them off if they can't ride properly. Thus, Bion’s comment seems simple and misguided: "If you could make your field produce well just by praising it, it wouldn’t be wrong to tend to it that way instead of actually working the land; and it wouldn’t be strange to praise people if it could actually help them." However, while a field doesn’t suffer from being praised, those who falsely praise a person despite their true worth inflate their ego and ultimately harm them.

§ xvii. Enough has been said on this matter: let us now examine outspokenness. For just as Patroclus put on the armour of Achilles, and drove his horses to the battle, only durst not touch his spear from Mount Pelion, but let that alone, so ought the flatterer, tricked out and modelled in the distinctive marks and tokens of the friend, to leave untouched and uncopied only his outspokenness, as the special burden of friendship, "heavy, huge, strong."412 But since flatterers, to avoid the blame they incur by their buffoonery, and drinking, and gibes, and jokes, sometimes work their ends by frowns and gravity, and intermix cen173sure and reproof, let us not pass this over either without examination. And I think, as in Menander's Play the sham Hercules comes on the stage not with a club stout and strong, but with a light and hollow cane, so the outspokenness of the flatterer is to those who experience it mild and soft, and the very reverse of vigorous, and like those cushions for women's heads, which seem able to stand their ground, but in reality yield and give way under their pressure; so this sham outspokenness is puffed up and inflated with an empty and spurious and hollow bombast, that when it contracts and collapses draws in the person who relies on it. For true and friendly outspokenness attacks wrong-doers, bringing pain that is salutary and likely to make them more careful, like honey biting but cleansing ulcerated parts of the body,413 but in other respects serviceable and sweet. But we will speak of this anon.414 But the flatterer first exhibits himself as disagreeable and passionate and unforgiving in his dealings with others. For he is harsh to his servants, and a terrible fellow to attack and ferret out the faults of his kinsmen and friends, and to look up to and respect nobody who is a stranger, but to look down upon them, and is relentless and mischief-making in making people provoked with others, hunting after the reputation of hating vice, as one not likely knowingly to mince matters with the vicious, or ingratiate himself with them either in word or deed. Next he pretends to know nothing of real and great crimes, but he is a terrible fellow to inveigh against trifling and external shortcomings, and to fasten on them with intensity and vehemence, as if he sees any pot or pipkin out of its place, or anyone badly housed, or neglecting his beard or attire, or not adequately attending to a horse or dog. But contempt of parents, and neglect of children, and bad treatment of wife, and haughtiness to friends, and throwing away money, all this he cares nothing about, but is silent and does not dare to make any allusion to it: just as if the trainer in a gymnasium were to allow the athlete to get drunk and live in debauchery,415 174and yet be vexed at the condition of his oil-flask or strigil if out of order; or as if the schoolmaster scolded a boy about his tablet and pen, but paid no attention to a solecism or barbarism. The flatterer is like a man who should make no comment on the speech of a silly and ridiculous orator, but should find fault with his voice, and chide him for injuring his throat by drinking cold water; or like a person bidden to read some wretched composition, who should merely find fault with the thickness of the paper, and call the copyist a dirty and careless fellow. So too when Ptolemy seemed to desire to become learned, his flatterers used to spin out the time till midnight, disputing about some word or line or history, but not one of them all objected to his cruelty and outrages, his torturing and beating people to death.416 Just as if, when a man has tumours and fistulas, one were to cut his hair and nails with a surgeon's knife, so flatterers use outspokenness only in cases where it gives no pain or distress.

§ xvii. Enough has been said on this topic: let’s now look at honesty. Just like Patroclus wore Achilles' armor and drove his horses into battle, but wouldn’t dare touch his spear from Mount Pelion, the flatterer—dressed up and shaped like a friend—should also leave untouched and unreplicated his honesty, as it is the special burden of friendship, "heavy, huge, strong."412 But since flatterers often try to escape the blame they earn through their silliness, drinking, teasing, and jokes, they sometimes achieve their goals through frowns and seriousness, mixing in criticism and reproach, we shouldn’t overlook this either. I think, like the fake Hercules in Menander’s Play, who steps onto the stage not with a strong, sturdy club, but with a light and hollow cane, the honesty of the flatterer feels mild and soft to those who experience it, entirely the opposite of strong, like those cushions for women’s heads that seem to hold their ground but actually give way under pressure; this fake honesty is puffed up and inflated with empty and fake bombast, and when it collapses, it pulls in those who rely on it. True and friendly honesty calls out wrongdoers, bringing pain that is helpful and likely to make them more careful, like honey that stings but cleanses infected parts of the body,413 but is otherwise useful and sweet. But we’ll talk about this later.414 The flatterer first shows himself as unpleasant, emotional, and unforgiving in dealing with others. He is tough on his servants, a real bully when it comes to calling out the faults of his relatives and friends, and he looks down on strangers, having no respect for them, relentless and causing trouble by provoking people against one another, while pretending to hate vice, as someone unlikely to engage with the wicked in any way. Next, he pretends not to notice serious and significant wrongdoings, but he’s quick to criticize minor and superficial flaws, going after them with intensity and passion, as if he notices any pot or pan out of place, or anyone poorly housed, or neglecting their beard or clothing, or not properly caring for their horse or dog. However, he doesn’t care about disrespecting parents, neglecting children, poor treatment of a wife, arrogance towards friends, or wasting money, staying silent and not daring to bring it up: just like a gym trainer who allows an athlete to get drunk and live recklessly,415 174but gets upset over the condition of his oil flask or strigil if they’re out of order; or like a teacher who scolds a boy about his tablet and pen but ignores poor grammar or bad language. The flatterer is like someone who comments on a silly and ridiculous speaker’s delivery but only criticizes their voice, chiding them for hurting their throat by drinking cold water; or like someone asked to read a terrible piece of writing, who only complains about the thickness of the paper and calls the copyist dirty and careless. Similarly, when Ptolemy pretended to want to be educated, his flatterers would drag out conversations until midnight, debating some word or line or historical detail, yet not one of them objected to his cruelty and abuse, his torture and beatings.416 Just like if a man has tumors and fistulas, one were to cut his hair and nails with a surgeon’s knife, so flatterers use honesty only in situations where it causes no pain or discomfort.

§ xviii. Moreover some of them are cleverer still and make their outspokenness and censure a means of imparting pleasure. As Agis the Argive,417 when Alexander bestowed great gifts on a buffoon, cried out in envy and displeasure, "What a piece of absurdity!" and on the king turning angrily to him and saying, "What are you talking about?" he replied, "I admit that I am vexed and put out, when I see that all you descendants of Zeus alike take delight in flatterers and jesters, for Hercules had his Cercopes, and Dionysus his Sileni, and with you too I see that such are held in good repute." And on one occasion, when the Emperor Tiberius entered the senate, one of his flatterers got up and said, that being free men they ought to be outspoken, and not suppress or conceal anything that might be important, and having by this exordium engaged everybody's attention, a dead silence prevailing, and even Tiberius being all attention, he said, "Listen, Cæsar, to what we all charge you with, although no one ventures to tell you openly of it; you neglect yourself, and are careless 175about your health, and wear yourself out with anxiety and labour on our behalf, taking no rest either by night or day." And on his stringing much more together in the same strain, they say the orator Cassius Severus said, "This outspokenness will ruin the man."

§ xviii. Some of them are even smarter and use their honesty and criticism to bring joy. Like Agis from Argos,417 when Alexander gave lavish gifts to a comedian, he exclaimed in envy and frustration, "What nonsense!" When the king turned to him angrily and asked, "What are you talking about?" he replied, "I admit I’m annoyed and bothered when I see all you descendants of Zeus enjoying flatterers and jokers. Hercules had his Cercopes, and Dionysus had his Sileni, and I see the same appreciation for such people among you." And once, when Emperor Tiberius entered the Senate, one of his sycophants stood up and said that as free men, they should speak their minds and not hide anything important. Having grabbed everyone's attention with this opening, a heavy silence fell, even Tiberius was all ears, and he continued, "Listen, Caesar, to what we all accuse you of, even though no one dares to say it out loud; you neglect your well-being and are careless about your health, wearing yourself out with worry and hard work for us, without rest day or night." After he strung together even more points in this tone, they say the speaker Cassius Severus remarked, "This bluntness will ruin the man."

§ xix. These are indeed trifling matters: but the following are more important and do mischief to foolish people, when flatterers accuse them of the very contrary vices and passions to those to which they are really addicted; as Himerius the flatterer twitted a very rich, very mean, and very covetous Athenian with being a careless spendthrift, and likely one day to want bread as well as his children; or on the other hand if they rail at extravagant spendthrifts for meanness and sordidness, as Titus Petronius railed at Nero; or exhort rulers who make savage and cruel attacks on their subjects to lay aside their excessive clemency, and unseasonable and inexpedient mercy. Similar to these is the person who pretends to be on his guard against and afraid of a silly stupid fellow as if he were clever and cunning; and the one who, if any person fond of detraction, rejoicing in defamation and censure, should be induced on any occasion to praise some man of note, fastens on him and alleges against him that he has an itch for praising people. "You are always extolling people of no merit: for who is this fellow, or what has he said or done out of the common?" But it is in regard to the objects of their love that they mostly attack those they flatter, and additionally inflame them. For if they see people at variance with their brothers, or despising their parents, or treating their wives contemptuously, they neither take them to task nor scold them, but fan the flame of their anger still more. "You don't sufficiently appreciate yourself," they say, "you are yourself the cause of your being put upon in this way, through your constant submissiveness and humility." And if there is any tiff or fit of jealousy in regard to some courtesan or adulteress, the flatterer is at hand with remarkable outspokenness, adding fuel to flame,418 and taking the lady's part, and accusing her lover of acting in a very unkind harsh and shameful manner to her,

§ xix. These are indeed trivial matters, but the following are more significant and can harm foolish people when flatterers accuse them of the exact opposite faults and desires from what they actually have; like how Himerius, the flatterer, mocked a very wealthy, very petty, and very greedy Athenian for being a careless spendthrift, suggesting he might one day run out of money like his children. Or, on the flip side, they criticize extravagant spenders for being stingy and cheap, much like Titus Petronius criticized Nero; or they advise leaders who viciously oppress their subjects to tone down their excessive mercy and misplaced compassion. Similarly, there’s the person who pretends to be cautious and wary of a foolish person as if they were clever and cunning; and the one who, if someone who enjoys talking behind others' backs—taking pleasure in slander and criticism—ever praises a notable individual, attacks them by saying they have an obsession with praising people. "You’re always glorifying people of no value: who is this guy, or what has he said or done that's extraordinary?" But it's mostly about the things they love that they attack those they flatter, further fueling their anger. If they notice someone at odds with their siblings, or disrespecting their parents, or treating their wives with contempt, they neither confront them nor scold them, but rather stoke the fire of their anger even more. "You don’t appreciate yourself enough," they say, "you’re the reason you’re treated this way, because of your continual submission and humility." And if there’s any quarrel or jealousy over a mistress or an affair, the flatterer is quick to step in, passionately defending the woman and accusing her partner of being extremely unkind, harsh, and shameful towards her.

"O ungrateful one, after all those frequent kisses!"419

Thus Antony's friends, when he was passionately in love with the Egyptian woman,420 persuaded him that he was loved by her, and twitted him with being cold and haughty to her. "She," they said, "has left her mighty kingdom and happy mode of life, and is wasting her beauty, taking the field with you like some camp-follower,

Thus Antony's friends, when he was deeply in love with the Egyptian woman,420 convinced him that she loved him back, and teased him for being distant and arrogant towards her. "She," they said, "has given up her powerful kingdom and her happy way of life, and is wasting her beauty by following you around like a camp follower.

"While your heart remains immune to all her charms,"421

as you neglect her love-lorn as she is." But he that is pleased at being reproached with his wrong-doing, and delights in those that censure him, as he never did in those that praised him, is unconscious that he is really perverted also by what seems to be rebuke. For such outspokenness is like the bites of wanton women,422 that while seeming to hurt really tickle and excite pleasure. And just as if people mix pure wine, which is by itself an antidote against hemlock, with it and so offer it, they make the poison quite deadly, being rapidly carried to the heart by the warmth,423 so ill-disposed men, knowing that outspokenness is a great antidote to flattery, make it a means of flattering. And so it was rather a bad answer Bias424 made, to the person who inquired what was the most formidable animal, "Of wild animals the tyrant, and of tame the flatterer." For it would have been truer to observe that tame flatterers are those that are found round the baths and table, but the one that intrudes into the interior of the house and into the women's apartments with his curiosity and calumny and malignity, like the legs and arms of the polypus, is wild and savage and unmanageable.

as you ignore her, love-lorn as she is." But someone who takes pleasure in being criticized for their wrongs and enjoys the company of those who point fingers at them, unlike those who praise them, doesn't realize that they are also twisted by what seems like criticism. This kind of bluntness is like the playful bites of flirtatious women,422 which, while appearing to hurt, actually provoke and excite pleasure. Similarly, when people mix pure wine, which on its own is an antidote to hemlock, with the poison and then serve it, they make the poison deadly as it rushes to the heart due to the warmth,423 so ill-natured people, knowing that frankness is a strong antidote to flattery, use it as a tool for flattery instead. It was rather a poor response by Bias424 when asked what the most dangerous animal is, saying, "The tyrant among wild animals and the flatterer among tame ones." It would have been more accurate to say that tame flatterers are the ones found around baths and dining tables, while the one who intrudes into the privacy of homes and women's spaces with their prying, slanderous, and malicious nature—like the limbs of a octopus—is wild, savage, and uncontrollable.

§ xx. Now one kind of caution against his snares is to 177know and ever remember that, whereas the soul contains true and noble and reasoning elements, as also unreasoning and false and emotional ones, the friend is always a counsellor and adviser to the better instincts of the soul, as the physician improves and maintains health, whereas the flatterer works upon the emotional and unreasoning ones, and tickles and titillates them and seduces them from reason, employing sensuality as his bait. As then there are some kinds of food which neither benefit the blood or spirit, nor brace up the nerves and marrow, but stir the passions, excite the lower nature, and make the flesh unsound and rotten, so the language of the flatterer adds nothing to soberness and reason, but encourages some love passion, or stirs up foolish rage, or incites to envy, or produces the empty and burdensome vanity of pride, or joins in bewailing woes, or ever by his calumnies and hints makes malignity and illiberality and suspicion sharp and timid and jealous, and cannot fail to be detected by those that closely observe him. For he is ever anchoring himself upon some passion, and fattening it, and, like a bubo, fastens himself on some unsound and inflamed parts of the soul. Are you angry? Have your revenge, says he. Do you desire anything? Get it. Are you afraid? Let us flee. Do you suspect? Entertain no doubts about it. But if he is difficult to detect in thus playing upon our passions, since they often overthrow reason by their intensity and strength, he will give a handle to find him out in smaller matters, being consistent in them too. For if anyone feels a little uneasy after a surfeit or excess in drink, and so is a little particular about his food and doubts the advisability of taking a bath, a friend will try and check him from excess, and bid him be careful and not indulge, whereas the flatterer will drag him to the bath, bid him serve up some fresh food, and not starve himself and so injure his constitution. And if he see him reluctant about a journey or voyage or some business or other, he will say that there is no hurry, that it's all one whether the business be put off, or somebody else despatched to look after it. And if you have promised to lend or give some money to a friend, but have repented of your offer, and yet feel ashamed not to keep your promise, the flatterer will throw178 his influence into the worse scale, he will confirm your desire to save your purse, he will destroy your reluctance, and will bid you be careful as having many expenses, and others to think about besides that person. And so, unless we are entirely ignorant of our desires, our shamelessness, and our timidity, the flatterer cannot easily escape our detection. For he is ever the advocate of those passions, and outspoken when we desire to repress them.425 But so much for this matter.

§ xx. One way to guard against his traps is to 177 recognize and remember that, while the soul has true, noble, and rational elements, it also contains irrational, false, and emotional ones. A true friend always acts as a counselor and advisor to the better instincts of the soul, just as a doctor helps maintain and improve health. In contrast, the flatterer preys on the emotional and irrational aspects, tickling and tempting them away from reason, using sensuality as bait. Just as there are foods that neither nourish the blood nor strengthen the nerves and instead stir up passions, excite the lower nature, and cause decay, the flatterer’s words add nothing to clarity or rationality. Instead, they provoke romantic feelings, foolish anger, envy, burdensome pride, join in lamenting sorrows, and through slanderous hints, sharpen malice, stinginess, and suspicion, making others timid and jealous— all of which can be spotted by those who pay attention. He continuously latches onto some passion, feeding it, much like a parasite clinging to inflamed parts of the soul. Are you angry? Get revenge, he says. Do you want something? Go for it. Are you scared? Let’s run away. Are you suspicious? Don’t doubt it. While he may be hard to identify in his manipulation of our passions since their intensity often overwhelms reason, he provides clues in smaller matters, being consistent there too. For example, if someone feels a bit uneasy after drinking too much and doubts whether to eat or take a bath, a true friend will urge moderation and caution, while the flatterer will push him to bathe, encourage him to eat fresh food, insisting he shouldn't starve himself and hurt his health. If he notices hesitation about traveling or handling a task, he might say there's no rush; it doesn't matter if it’s delayed or if someone else takes care of it. And if you’ve promised to lend or give money but regret it yet feel guilty breaking your promise, the flatterer will influence you to lean toward selfishness, supporting your desire to keep your money while dismissing your hesitation, urging caution because there are many expenses and others to consider. Therefore, unless we remain completely unaware of our desires, lack of shame, and our fears, the flatterer cannot easily evade our notice. He consistently champions those passions and speaks up when we want to suppress them.425 But that’s enough on this topic.

§ xxi. Now let us pass on to useful and kind services, for in them too the flatterer makes it very difficult and confusing to detect him from the friend, seeming to be zealous and ready on all occasions and never crying off. For, as Euripides says,426 a friend's behaviour is, "like the utterance of truth, simple," and plain and inartificial, while that of the flatterer "is in itself unsound, and needs wise remedies," aye, by Zeus, and many such, and not ordinary ones. As for example in chance meetings the friend often neither speaks nor is spoken to, but merely looks and smiles, and then passes on, showing his inner affection and goodwill only by his countenance, which his friend also reciprocates, but the flatterer runs up, follows, holds out his hand at a distance, and if he is seen and addressed first, frequently protests with oaths, and calls witnesses to prove, that he did not see you. So in business friends neglect many unimportant points, are not too punctilious and officious, and do not thrust themselves upon every service, but the flatterer is persevering and unceasing and indefatigable in it, giving nobody else either room or place to help, but putting himself wholly at your disposal, and if you will not find him something to do for you, he is troubled, nay rather altogether dejected and lamenting loudly.427

§ xxi. Now let’s move on to helpful and kind services, because in these situations, the flatterer makes it hard and confusing to tell him apart from a true friend. He seems eager and ready in every circumstance and never backs down. As Euripides says,426 a friend's behavior is "like the utterance of truth, simple,” straightforward and genuine, while the flatterer’s actions "are in themselves unsound and need wise remedies," yes, by Zeus, many of them, and not just ordinary ones. For instance, in casual encounters, a friend often neither speaks nor is spoken to, but simply looks and smiles, passing by while expressing his genuine affection and goodwill with a smile, which his friend returns. In contrast, the flatterer rushes in, follows you, reaches out his hand from a distance, and if he’s the first to see you and get your attention, he often swears that he didn’t see you and calls witnesses to confirm it. In business, friends overlook many little things; they aren’t too picky and intrusive, and they don’t impose themselves on every task, while the flatterer is persistent, never stops, and is tireless in this, leaving no space for anyone else to help. He makes himself entirely available to you, and if you don’t give him something to do, he becomes upset, even entirely dejected, and loudly complains.427

§ xxii. To all sensible people all this is an indication, not of true or sober friendship, but of a meretricious one, 179that embraces you more warmly than there is any occasion for. Nevertheless let us first look at the difference between the friend and flatterer in their promises. For it has been well said by those who have handled this subject before us, that the friend's promise is,

§ xxii. To all reasonable people, this is a sign not of genuine or sincere friendship, but of a shallow one, 179 that embraces you more warmly than is necessary. However, let’s first examine the difference between a friend and a flatterer in their promises. As has been wisely noted by those who have discussed this topic before us, a friend's promise is,

"If I can do it, and it needs to be done,"

but the flatterer's is,

but the flatterer's is,

"Speak your mind, whatever it is, to me." 428

And the comic dramatists put such fellows on the stage,

And the comedic playwrights put characters like that on stage,

"Nicomachus, put me up against that soldier, Let's see if I can beat him into jelly. "And make his face even softer than a sponge."429

In the next place no friend participates in any matter, unless he has first been asked his advice, and put the matter to the test, and set it on a suitable and expedient basis. But the flatterer, if anyone allows him to examine a matter and give his opinion on it, not only wishes to gratify him by compliance, but also fearing to be looked upon with suspicion as unwilling and reluctant to engage in the business, gives in to and even urges on his friend's desire. For there is hardly any king or rich man who would say,

In addition, no friend gets involved in anything unless they’ve first been asked for their advice, tested the situation, and established a solid and practical plan. However, the flatterer, if someone lets him weigh in on a matter and share his thoughts, not only wants to appease him by agreeing, but also, fearing to be seen as uncooperative or hesitant, goes along with and even pushes his friend's wishes. Because there are hardly any kings or wealthy people who would say,

"Oh, how I wish I could find a beggar, or something even worse." Than beggar, if you genuinely want to, to me, He would openly and honestly reveal his heart;"430

but, like the tragedians, they require a chorus of sympathizing friends, or the applause of a theatre. And so Merope gives the following advice in the tragedy,

but, like the actors in a tragedy, they need a group of supportive friends or the applause of an audience. And so Merope offers the following advice in the tragedy,

"Choose friends who will speak their mind," For those wicked men who only say what pleases Make sure you lock and secure your house. 431

But they act just the contrary, for they turn away with horror from those who speak their mind, and hold different 180views as to what is expedient, while they welcome those bad and illiberal impostors (that only speak to please them) not only within their houses, but also to their affections and secrets. Now the simpler of these do not think right or claim to advise you in important matters, but only to assist in the carrying out of them: but the more cunning one stands by during the discussion, and knits his brows, and nods assent with his head, but says nothing, but if his friend express an opinion, he then says, "Hercules, you only just anticipated me, I was about to make that very remark." For as the mathematicians tell us that surfaces and lines neither bend nor extend nor move of themselves, being without body and only perceived by the mind, but only bend and extend and change their position with the bodies whose extremities they are: so you will catch the flatterer ever assenting with, and agreeing with, aye, and feeling with, and being angry with, another, so easy of detection in all these points of view is the difference between the friend and the flatterer. Moreover as regards the kind of good service. For the favour done by a friend, as the principal strength of an animal is within, is not for display or ostentation, but frequently as a doctor cures his patient imperceptibly, so a friend benefits by his intervention, or by paying off creditors, or by managing his friend's affairs, even though the person who receives the benefit may not be aware of it. Such was the behaviour of Arcesilaus on various occasions, and when Apelles432 of Chios was ill, knowing his poverty, he took with him twenty drachmæ when he visited him, and sitting down beside him he said, "There is nothing here but those elements of Empedocles, 'fire and water and earth and balmy expanse of air,' but you don't lie very comfortably," and with that he moved his pillow, and privately put the money under it. And when his old housekeeper found it, and wonderingly told Apelles of it, he laughed and said, "This is some trick of Arcesilaus." And the saying is also true in philosophy that "children are like their parents."433 For 181when Cephisocrates had to stand his trial on a bill of indictment, Lacydes (who was an intimate friend of Arcesilaus) stood by him with several other friends, and when the prosecutor asked for his ring, which was the principal evidence against him, Cephisocrates quietly dropped it on the ground, and Lacydes noticing this put his foot on it and so hid it. And after sentence was pronounced in his favour, Cephisocrates going up to thank the jury, one of them who had seen the artifice told him to thank Lacydes, and related to him all the matter, though Lacydes had not said a word about it to anybody. So also I think the gods do often perform benefits secretly, taking a natural delight in bestowing their favours and bounties.434 But the good service of the flatterer has no justice, or genuineness, or simplicity, or liberality about it; but is accompanied with sweat, and running about, and noise, and knitting of the brow, creating an impression and appearance of toilsome and bustling service, like a painting over-curiously wrought in bold colours, and with bent folds wrinkles and angles, to make the closer resemblance to life. Moreover he tires one by relating what journeys and anxieties he has had over the matter, how many enemies he has made over it, the thousand bothers and annoyances he has gone through, so that you say, "The affair was not worth all this trouble." For being reminded of any favour done to one is always unpleasant and disagreeable and insufferable:435 but the flatterer not only reminds us of his services afterwards, but even during the very moment of doing them upbraids us with them and is importunate. But the friend, if he is obliged to mention the matter, relates it modestly, and says not a word about himself. And so, when the Lacedæmonians sent corn to the people of Smyrna that needed it, and the people of Smyrna wondered at their kindness, the Lacedæmonians said, "It was no great matter, we only voted that 182we and our beasts of burden should go without our dinner one day, and sent what was so saved to you."436 Not only is it handsome to do a favour in that way, but it is more pleasant to the receivers of it, because they think those who have done them the service have done it at no great loss to themselves.

But they do the opposite; they recoil in horror from those who speak their mind and have different views on what's appropriate, while they welcome those deceitful and insincere people (who only say what they want to hear) not just into their homes but also into their hearts and secrets. The simpler ones don’t claim to offer important advice but merely assist in executing plans. On the other hand, the more cunning ones stand by during discussions, frowning and nodding in agreement without saying a word. But if a friend shares an opinion, they chime in, saying, "Wow, you just read my mind; I was about to say that." Just as mathematicians explain that surfaces and lines don't bend, extend, or move on their own—they’re just perceived mentally and only change with the bodies they connect to—so too can you spot a flatterer easily. They always agree and sympathize with others, revealing the clear difference between a true friend and a flatterer. Additionally, when it comes to genuine service, a friend's help—like an animal’s strength that lies within—is not for show, but often works quietly and effectively. A friend provides support by intervening, paying off debts, or managing affairs, even if the one benefiting isn’t fully aware. Such was the case with Arcesilaus. When Apelles of Chios was ill and knowing he was struggling financially, Arcesilaus brought him twenty drachmæ. Sitting beside him, he said, “There’s nothing here but Empedocles’ elements, ‘fire, water, earth, and the gentle air,’ but you don’t seem comfortable,” and then he adjusted the man’s pillow and discreetly placed the money underneath it. When Apelles’ housekeeper discovered the money and told him, Apelles laughed, saying, “This must be one of Arcesilaus’ tricks.” It’s also true in philosophy that “children resemble their parents.” When Cephisocrates had to face trial, Lacydes—an intimate friend of Arcesilaus—stood with him alongside several others. When the prosecutor requested a ring that served as key evidence, Cephisocrates calmly dropped it on the ground. Lacydes noticed this and quickly stepped on it to hide it. After the verdict was in Cephisocrates’ favor, when he went to thank the jury, one member told him to thank Lacydes and explained the clever trick, although Lacydes hadn’t mentioned it to anyone. Similarly, I believe the gods often do good things in secret, enjoying the act of giving gifts quietly. In contrast, the flatterer’s service lacks justice, authenticity, simplicity, or generosity; it’s marked by sweat, commotion, and a furrowed brow, creating a false sense of hard work and effort, like an overly detailed painting that tries too hard to mirror life. Moreover, they exhaust others by recounting their stressful journeys and conflicts, claiming how many enemies they've made and the many annoyances they've faced, leading you to think, “Was all this trouble really worth it?” Being reminded of a favor received is always uncomfortable and annoying, while the flatterer not only brings it up during the act but also nags about it. In contrast, a friend, if they must mention it, does so humbly and doesn’t boast about themselves. For example, when the Lacedæmonians sent grain to the needy people of Smyrna, the Smyrnaeans were amazed at their generosity, to which the Lacedæmonians replied, “It’s nothing special; we just decided to skip one meal that day and sent you what we saved instead.” Not only is it admirable to give a favor in this manner, but it’s also more pleasant for those receiving it because they feel that the helpers didn’t suffer significant loss themselves.

§ xxiii. But it is not so much by the importunity of the flatterer in regard to services, nor by his facility in making promises, that one can recognize his nature, as by the honourable or dishonourable kind of service, and by the regard to please or to be of real use. For the friend is not as Gorgias defined him, one who will ask his friend to help him in what is right, while he will himself do many services for his friend that are not right.

§ xxiii. But you can't really understand someone’s true nature just by how persistent a flatterer is in asking for favors or how easily they make promises. It’s more about whether the help they offer is honorable or dishonorable, and whether they genuinely want to please you or to be helpful. A true friend isn't like Gorgias described, as someone who asks their friend for help with the right things while themselves doing many favors that are not right.

"A friend should be there for you in good times, not just in bad." 437

He will therefore rather try and turn him away from what is not becoming, and if he cannot persuade him, good is that answer of Phocion to Antipater, "You cannot have me both as friend and flatterer,"438 that is, as friend and no friend. For one must indeed assist one's friend but not do anything wrong for him, one must advise with him but not plot with him, one must bear witness for him but not join him in fraud, one must certainly share adversity with him but not crime. For since we should not wish even to know of our friends' dishonourable acts, much less should we desire to share their dishonour by acting with them. As then the Lacedæmonians, when conquered in battle by Antipater, on settling the terms of peace, begged that he would lay upon them what burdens he pleased, provided he enjoined nothing dishonourable, so the friend, if any necessity arise involving expense or danger or trouble, is the first to desire to be applied to and share in it with alacrity and without crying off, but if there be anything disgraceful in connection with it he begs to have nothing to do with it. The flatterer on the contrary cries off from 183toilsome and dangerous employments, and if you put him to the test by ringing him,439 he returns a hollow and spurious sound, and finds some excuse; whereas use him in disgraceful and low and disreputable service, and trample upon him, he will think no treatment too bad or ignominious. Have you observed the ape? He cannot guard the house like the dog, nor bear burdens like the horse, nor plough like the ox, so he has to bear insult and ribaldry, and put up with being made sport of, exhibiting himself as an instrument to produce laughter. So too the flatterer, who can neither advocate your cause, nor give you useful counsel, nor share in your contention with anybody, but shirks all labour and toil, never makes any excuses in underhand transactions, is sure to lend a helping hand in any love affair, is energetic in setting free some harlot, and not careless in clearing off the account of a drinking score, nor remiss in making preparations for banquets, and obsequious to concubines, but if ordered to be uncivil to your relations, or to help in turning your wife out of doors, he is relentless and not to be put out of countenance. So that he is not hard to detect here too. For if ordered to do anything you please disreputable or dishonourable, he is ready to take any pains to oblige you.

He will instead try to steer him away from what’s inappropriate, and if he can’t convince him, the response of Phocion to Antipater is fitting: "You can’t have me both as a friend and a flatterer," that is, as a true friend and a false one. One must help a friend, but not do anything wrong for them; one must advise them but not conspire with them; one must testify for them but not participate in deceit; one must definitely share hardships with them but not crimes. Since we wouldn’t even want to know about our friends’ dishonorable acts, we definitely shouldn’t want to share in their shame by acting with them. Just as the Spartans, after being defeated by Antipater, requested that he impose any burdens he wished as long as they were not dishonorable, a friend, if there’s a need that involves cost, danger, or trouble, is the first to step up and share in it willingly without backing out. But if it involves something disgraceful, they’ll want nothing to do with it. The flatterer, on the other hand, avoids hard and dangerous tasks, and if you test him, he gives a hollow and fake response and makes excuses; however, if you put him in a shameful, low, or disreputable position, he’ll think no treatment is too bad or humiliating. Have you noticed the monkey? It can’t guard the house like a dog, carry burdens like a horse, or plow like an ox, so it has to endure insults and mockery, becoming a source of laughter. Similarly, the flatterer can neither support your cause nor give you useful advice nor help you in any conflict, but he avoids all hard work and toil, is quick to make excuses for shady dealings, will gladly assist in love affairs, is eager to help some mistress, won’t skip settling drinking debts, and is attentive to concubines, yet if asked to be rude to your relatives or help kick your wife out, he becomes relentless and unashamed. So he’s not hard to spot either. If asked to do anything disreputable or dishonorable, he’s ready to go out of his way to please you.

§ xxiv. One might detect again how greatly the flatterer differs from the friend by his behaviour to other friends. For the friend is best pleased with loving and being beloved by many, and also always tries to contrive for his friend that he too may be much loved and honoured, for he believes in the proverb "the goods of friends are common property,"440 and thinks it ought to apply to nothing more than to friends; but the false and spurious and counterfeit friend, knowing how much he debases friendship, like debased and spurious coin, is not only by nature envious, but shows his envy even of those who are like himself, striving to outdo them in scurrility and gossip, while he quakes and trembles at any of his betters, not by Zeus "merely walking on foot by their Lydian chariot," but, to use the language of Simonides, "not even, having pure lead by 184 comparison with their refined gold."441 Whenever then, being light and counterfeit and false, he is put to the test at close quarters with a true and solid and cast-iron friendship, he cannot stand the test but is detected at once, and imitates the conduct of the painter that painted some wretched cocks, for he ordered his lad to scare away all live cocks as far from his picture as possible. So he too scares away real friends and will not let them come near if he can help it, but if he cannot prevent that, he openly fawns upon them, and courts them, and admires them as his betters, but privately runs them down and spreads calumnies about them. And when secret detraction has produced a sore feeling,442 if he has not effected his end completely, he remembers and observes the teaching of Medius, who was the chief of Alexander's flatterers, and a leading sophist in conspiracy against the best men. He bade people confidently sow their calumny broadcast and bite with it, teaching them that even if the person injured should heal his sore, the scar of the calumny would remain. Consumed by these scars, or rather gangrenes and cancers, Alexander put to death Callisthenes, and Parmenio, and Philotas; while he himself submitted to be completely outwitted by such as Agnon, and Bagoas, and Agesias, and Demetrius, who worshipped him and tricked him up and feigned him to be a barbaric god. So great is the power of flattery, and nowhere greater, as it seems, than among the greatest people. For their thinking and wishing the best about themselves makes them credit the flatterer, and gives him courage.443 For lofty heights are difficult of approach and hard to reach for those who 185endeavour to scale them, but the highmindedness and conceit of a person thrown off his balance by good fortune or good natural parts is easily reached by mean and petty people.

§ xxiv. You can clearly see how much a flatterer differs from a true friend based on how they act around other friends. A true friend is happiest when they love and are loved by many and always tries to help their friend be well-liked and respected too, believing in the saying "the goods of friends are common property,"440 and thinking it should apply primarily to friendships. However, the fake and dishonest friend, knowing how they cheapen friendship, like a worthless coin, is not only naturally envious but shows that envy even towards those similar to them, trying to outdo them in mean behavior and gossip. They cower in fear around anyone of higher status, not just by "simply walking by their Lydian chariot," but, as Simonides puts it, "not even being comparable to their refined gold with their pure lead."441 Therefore, whenever this counterfeit friend, being light and false, is tested against a genuine and solid friendship, they fail immediately. They behave like a painter who, after painting miserable roosters, tells his servant to drive all real roosters far away from his artwork. So, this flatterer tries to keep real friends at a distance and, if they can’t avoid it, they toady up to them, admire them, and act like they are superior, all while secretly criticizing and spreading rumors about them. When their sly scheming creates resentment,442 if they haven’t fully achieved their goal, they remember the advice of Medius, one of Alexander's top flatterers and a leading conspirator against the best men. He urged people to spread their lies widely and bite with them, teaching that even if the victim heals, the scar from the slander remains. Consumed by these scars, or rather by gangrene and cancerous wounds, Alexander executed Callisthenes, Parmenio, and Philotas; while he himself was constantly outsmarted by people like Agnon, Bagoas, Agesias, and Demetrius, who idolized him and tricked him into seeing himself as a god. Such is the power of flattery, especially among the most powerful individuals. Their inclination to think highly of themselves allows flatterers to manipulate them and gives the flatterers confidence.443 High elevations are difficult to reach for those trying to climb, but the arrogance and vanity of someone thrown off balance by good luck or natural talent are easily accessible to small-minded and petty individuals.

§ xxv. And so we advised at the beginning of this discourse, and now advise again, to cut off self-love and too high an opinion of ourselves; for that flatters us first, and makes us more impressionable and prepared for external flatterers. But if we hearken to the god, and recognize the immense importance to everyone of that saying, "Know thyself,"444 and at the same time carefully observe our nature and education and training, with its thousand shortcomings in respect to good, and the large proportion of vice and vanity mixed up with our words and deeds and feelings, we shall not make ourselves so easy a mark for flatterers. Alexander said that he disbelieved those who called him a god chiefly in regard to sleep and the sexual delight, for in both those things he was more ignoble and emotional than in other respects.445 So we, if we observe the blots, blemishes, shortcomings, and imperfections of our private selves, shall perceive clearly that we do not need a friend who shall bestow upon us praise and panegyric, but one that will reprove us, and speak plainly to us, aye, by Zeus, and censure us if we have done amiss. For it is only a few out of many that venture to speak plainly to their friends rather than gratify them, and even among those few you will not easily find any who know how to do so properly, for they think they are outspoken when they abuse and scold. And yet, just as in the case of any other medicine, to employ freedom of speech unseasonably is only to give needless pain and trouble, and in a manner to do so as to produce vexation the very thing the flatterer does so as to produce pleasure. For it does people harm not only to praise them unseasonably but also to blame them unseasonably, and especially exposes them to the successful attack of flatterers, for, like water, they abandon the rugged hills for the soft grassy valleys. And so outspokenness ought to be tempered with kindness, and reason ought to be called in 186to correct its excessive tartness, (as we tone down the too powerful glare of a lamp), that people may not, by being troubled and grieved at continual blame and rebuke, fly for refuge to the shade of the flatterer, and turn aside to him to free themselves from annoyance. For we ought, Philopappus, to banish all vice by virtue, not by the opposite vice, as some hold,446 by exchanging modesty for impudence, and countrified ways for town ribaldry, and by removing their character as far as possible from cowardice and effeminacy, even if that should make people get very near to audacity and foolhardiness. And some even make superstition a plea for atheism, and stupidity a plea for knavery, perverting their nature, like a stick bent double, from inability to set it straight. But the basest disowning of flattery is to be disagreeable without any purpose in view, and it shows an altogether inelegant and clumsy unfitness for social intercourse to shun by unpleasing moroseness the suspicion of being mean and servile in friendship; like the freedman in the comedy who thought railing only enjoying freedom of speech. Seeing then, that it is equally disgraceful to become a flatterer through trying only to please, as in avoiding flattery to destroy all friendship and intimacy by excessive freedom of speech, we must avoid both these extremes, and, as in any other case, make our freedom of speech agreeable by its moderation. So the subject itself seems next to demand that I should conclude it by discussing that point.

§ xxv. As we mentioned at the start of this discussion, and reiterate now, it's important to let go of self-love and an inflated sense of self. This often flatters us at first, making us more susceptible to external flattery. However, if we listen to the wisdom that tells us to "Know thyself,"444 and closely examine our nature, upbringing, and training—recognizing our many flaws, along with the vices and vanity that mix with our words, actions, and feelings—we'll be less vulnerable to flatterers. Alexander claimed he doubted those who called him a god, especially regarding sleep and sexual pleasure, admitting he was more base and emotional in those aspects than in others.445 Therefore, if we acknowledge our own shortcomings and imperfections, we'll understand that we don't need a friend who just praises us with flattery, but rather someone who will criticize us honestly, even harshly, if we've done wrong. Few people are willing to be straightforward with their friends instead of just trying to please them; even among those few, it's hard to find anyone who does it correctly, as they often mistake insults for honesty. But, like with any medicine, using blunt honesty at the wrong time can cause unnecessary pain and annoyance, leading to frustration—the same effect a flatterer aims to avoid while trying to please. Praising someone inappropriately is harmful, but so is unwarranted blame, exposing them to flatterers who, like water, flow away from hard paths to softer, easier trails. Therefore, straightforwardness should be balanced with kindness, and reason should soften its harshness, just like we dim a bright lamp, so that people won't become so troubled by constant criticism that they seek comfort from flatterers. We should, Philopappus, eliminate vice with virtue, not with another vice, as some mistakenly believe,446 by swapping modesty for shamelessness or simple ways for urban debauchery, even if it nudges them closer to reckless audacity. Some even use superstition as an excuse for atheism and ignorance as a cover for trickery, warping their nature like a bent stick that can't be straightened. Yet the lowest form of rejecting flattery is to be unpleasant without purpose, demonstrating a total lack of social grace by avoiding the appearance of being servile in friendship with a gloomy attitude, similar to the freedman in a comedy who believed that insulting others was the same as enjoying free speech. Recognizing that it’s equally disgraceful to become a flatterer just to please as it is to ruin all friendships with excessive frankness, we should aim to avoid both extremes and, like in any situation, keep our honesty pleasant through moderation. Thus, it seems fitting to conclude this topic by addressing that point.

§ xxvi. As then we see that much trouble arises from excessive freedom of speech, let us first of all detach from it any element of self-love, being carefully on our guard that we may not appear to upbraid on account of any private hurt or injury. For people do not regard a speech on the speaker's own behalf as arising from goodwill, but from anger, and reproach rather than admonition. For freedom in speech is friendly and has weight, but reproach is selfish and little. And so people respect and admire those that speak their mind freely, but accuse back and despise those that reproach them: as Agamemnon would not stand the moderate freedom of speech of Achilles, but 187submitted to and endured the bitter attack and speech of Odysseus,

§ xxvi. Since we see that a lot of trouble comes from too much freedom of speech, let’s start by separating it from any self-serving motives, making sure we don’t come across as criticizing out of personal hurt or injury. People tend to view a speech that defends the speaker as coming from anger rather than goodwill, seeing it more as blame than a helpful suggestion. Freedom of speech is constructive and carries weight, but blame is selfish and petty. Therefore, people respect and admire those who speak their minds openly, but resent and look down on those who criticize them. For example, Agamemnon couldn’t tolerate Achilles’ balanced freedom of speech, but 187 endured the harsh words and attacks from Odysseus.

"Destructive leader, I wish you would command" "Some unfortunate host, not men like these!"447

for he was restrained by the carefulness and sobriety of his speech, and also Odysseus had no private motive of anger but only spoke out on behalf of Greece,448 whereas Achilles seemed rather vexed on his own account. And Achilles himself, though not sweet-tempered or mild of mood, but "a terrible man, and one that would perchance blame an innocent person,"449 yet silently listened to Patroclus bringing against him many such charges as the following,

for he was held back by the carefulness and seriousness of his speech, and also Odysseus had no personal motive of anger but was only speaking up for Greece,448 while Achilles seemed more annoyed for his own reasons. And Achilles himself, though not sweet-tempered or gentle, but "a fearsome man, and one who might blame an innocent person,"449 still listened quietly to Patroclus leveling many such accusations against him,

"Heartless one, your father was never" Knight Peleus, nor your gentle mother Thetis, But the blue sea and steep, rocky cliffs Your parents were, so hard is your heart.450

For as Hyperides the orator bade the Athenians consider not only whether he spoke bitterly, but whether he spoke so from interested motives,451 so the rebuke of a friend void of all private feeling is solemn and grave and what one dare not lightly face. And if anyone shows plainly in his freedom of speech, that he altogether passes over and dismisses any offences his friend has done to himself, and only blames him for other shortcomings, and does not spare him but gives him pain for the interests of others, the tone of his outspokenness is invincible, and the sweetness of his manner even intensifies the bitterness and austerity of his rebuke. And so it has well been said, that in anger and differences with our friends we ought more especially to act with a view to their interest or honour. And no less friendly is it, when it appears that we have been passed over and neglected, to boldly put in a word for others that are neglected too, and to remind people of them, as Plato, when he was out of favour with Dionysius, begged for an 188audience, and Dionysius granted it, thinking that Plato had some personal grievance and was going to enter into it, but Plato opened the conversation as follows, "If, Dionysius, you knew that some enemy had sailed to Sicily with a view to do you some harm, but found no opportunity, would you allow him to sail back again, and go off scot-free?" "Certainly not, Plato," replied Dionysius, "for we must not only hate and punish the deeds of our enemies, but also their intentions." "If then," said Plato, "anyone has come here for your benefit, and wishes to do you good, and you do not find him an opportunity, is it right to let him go away with neglect and without thanks?" And on Dionysius asking, who he meant, he replied, "I mean Æschines, a man of as good a character as any of Socrates' pupils whatever, and able to improve by his conversation any with whom he might associate: and he is neglected, though he has made a long voyage here to discuss philosophy with you." This speech so affected Dionysius, that he at once threw his arms round Plato and embraced him, admiring his benevolence and loftiness of mind, and treated Æschines well and handsomely.

For just as Hyperides the orator urged the Athenians to think not only about whether he spoke harshly, but whether he did so out of self-interest,451 the criticism from a friend, free of any personal feelings, is serious and weighty, something that should not be taken lightly. If someone clearly shows in their honest remarks that they completely overlook any wrongs their friend has done to them personally, and only calls them out for other failings, while also not holding back and causing them pain for the benefit of others, their bluntness is unassailable, and the charm of their demeanor only heightens the severity of their rebuke. It's been rightly said that in moments of anger and disagreements with our friends, we should especially think about their interests or honor. Similarly, it's also a friendly act when we, feeling overlooked and ignored, advocate for others who are also neglected and remind people of them. For instance, when Plato had fallen out of favor with Dionysius, he requested an 188audience, and Dionysius granted it, thinking that Plato had some personal grievance to discuss. However, Plato opened the conversation by saying, “If, Dionysius, you knew that an enemy had come to Sicily intending to harm you, but found no chance to do so, would you let him leave without consequences?” “Of course not, Plato,” Dionysius replied, “because we must not only hate and punish our enemies' actions but also their intentions.” “Then,” Plato continued, “if someone has come here for your benefit and genuinely wishes to help you, but you don’t give them an opportunity, is it right to let them leave unacknowledged and unappreciated?” When Dionysius asked whom he meant, Plato replied, “I mean Æschines, a man of excellent character, among the best of Socrates' students, capable of enriching anyone's conversation: he is being overlooked even though he has traveled a long way to discuss philosophy with you.” This speech touched Dionysius so much that he immediately embraced Plato, admiring his kindness and high-mindedness, and treated Æschines with great respect and generosity.

§ xxvii. In the next place, let us clear away as it were and remove all insolence, and jeering, and mocking, and ribaldry, which are the evil seasonings of freedom of speech. For as, when the surgeon performs an operation, a certain neatness and delicacy of touch ought to accompany his use of the knife, but all pantomimic and venturesome and fashionable suppleness and over-finicalness ought to be far away from his hand, so freedom of speech admits of dexterity and politeness, provided that a pleasant way of putting it does not destroy the power of the rebuke, for impudence and coarseness and insolence, if added to freedom of speech, entirely mar and ruin the effect. And so the harper plausibly and elegantly silenced Philip, who ventured to dispute with him about proper playing on the harp, by answering him, "God forbid that you should be so unfortunate, O king, as to understand harping better than me." But that was not a right answer of Epicharmus, when Hiero a few days after putting to death some of his friends invited him to supper, "You did not invite me," he189 said, "the other day, when you sacrificed your friends." Bad also was that answer of Antiphon, who, when Dionysius asked him "which was the best kind of bronze," answered, "That of which the Athenians made statues of Harmodius and Aristogiton." For this unpleasant and bitter kind of language profits not those that use it, nor does scurrility and puerile jesting please, but such kind of speeches are indications of an incontinent tongue inspired by hate, and full of malignity and insolence, and those who use such language do but ruin themselves, recklessly dancing on the verge of a well.452 For Antiphon was put to death by Dionysius, and Timagenes lost the friendship of Augustus, not by using on any occasion too free a tongue, but at supper-parties and walks always declining to talk seriously, "only saying what he knew would make the Argives laugh,"453 and thus virtually charging friendship with being only a cloak for abuse. For even the comic poets have introduced on the stage many grave sentiments well adapted to public life, but joking and ribaldry being mixed with them, like insipid sauces with food, destroy their effect and make them lose their nourishing power, so that the comic poets only get a reputation for malignity and coarseness, and the audience get no benefit from what is said. We may on other occasions jest and laugh with our friends, but let our outspokenness be coupled with seriousness and gravity, and if it be on important matters, let our speech be trustworthy and moving from its pathos, and animation, and tone of voice. And on all occasions to let an opportunity slip by is very injurious, but especially does it destroy the usefulness of freedom of speech. It is plain therefore that we must abstain from freedom of speech when men are in their cups. For he disturbs the harmony of a social gathering454 who, in the midst of mirth and jollity, introduces a topic that shall knit the brows and contract the face, and shall act as a damper to the Lysian455 190god, who, as Pindar says, "looses the rope of all our cares and anxieties." There is also great danger in such ill-timed freedom of speech. For wine makes people easily slip into rage, and oftentimes freedom of speech in liquor makes enemies. And generally speaking it is not noble or brave but cowardly to conceal your ideas when people are sober and to give free vent to them at table, snarling like cowardly dogs. We need say no more therefore on this head.

§ xxvii. Next, let’s get rid of all the arrogance, mockery, and crude jokes that can spoil free speech. Just like a surgeon needs to handle his tools delicately during an operation, free speech should be thoughtful and courteous. However, being polite should not weaken the strength of a criticism. Rudeness and crassness ruin the impact of what we say. For instance, the harper cleverly silenced Philip, who questioned his harp playing, by saying, "God forbid that you understand harping better than I do, O king." But Epicharmus made a poor choice when, after Hiero executed some friends, he said at dinner, "You didn’t invite me the other day when you sacrificed your friends." Antiphon also made a bad choice when, in response to Dionysius asking which bronze was best, he said, "The kind the Athenians used for the statues of Harmodius and Aristogiton." This bitter and hurtful language helps no one, and childish jokes don’t please either. Such remarks reveal a reckless tongue fueled by hate and malice, and those who speak this way only bring trouble on themselves. Antiphon was executed by Dionysius, and Timagenes lost Augustus's friendship, not because they spoke too freely, but because at gatherings they refused to speak seriously, only saying things to make people laugh, which trivialized friendship into a cover for insults. Even comic poets have included serious thoughts suited for public life in their work, but when mixed with humor and crude jokes, like bland sauces ruining a dish, they lose their effectiveness and fail to nourish. This way, comic poets become known for their rudeness, and the audience gains nothing. While we can joke and laugh with friends at times, our honesty should be tied to seriousness. When discussing important topics, our words should be sincere and impactful, carrying emotional weight. Always letting opportunities pass us by is harmful, especially when it undermines the purpose of free speech. Thus, we should avoid freely speaking when people are drinking. It disrupts the joy of a gathering when someone brings up heavy topics that cause frowns and tension, acting as a dampener on the spirits of the party, as Pindar says, who "loosens the rope of all our cares and anxieties." There is also significant danger in poorly timed free speech. Alcohol can easily spark anger, and often, speaking freely while drunk creates enemies. In general, it’s not brave or noble to hide your thoughts while sober and let them out while drinking, like cowardly dogs growling. So, there’s no need to say more on this matter.

§ xxviii. But since many people do not think fit or even dare to find fault with their friends when in prosperity, but think that condition altogether out of the reach and range of rebuke, but inveigh against them if they have made a slip or stumble, and trample upon them if they are in dejection and in their power, and, like a stream swollen above its banks, pour upon them then the torrent of all their eloquence,456 and enjoy and are glad at their reverse of fortune, owing to their former contempt of them when they were poor themselves, it is not amiss to discuss this somewhat, and to answer those words of Euripides,

§ xxviii. Many people don't think it's right or even feel brave enough to criticize their friends when they’re doing well. They believe that situation is beyond any kind of criticism. However, they quickly condemn them if they make a mistake or trip up, and they take advantage of them when they’re feeling down, unleashing a flood of their opinions on them, and take pleasure in their misfortune because they used to look down on them when they were struggling. It's worth discussing this a bit and responding to those words of Euripides,

"What need of friends, when things go well with us?"457

for those in prosperity stand in especial need of friends who shall be outspoken to them, and abate their excessive pride. For there are few who are sensible in prosperity, most need to borrow wisdom from others, and such considerations as shall keep them lowly when puffed up and giving themselves airs owing to their good fortune. But when the deity has abased them and stripped them of their conceit, there is something in their very circumstances to reprove them and bring about a change of mind. And so there is no need then of a friendly outspokenness, nor of weighty or caustic words, but truly in such reverses "it is sweet to look into the eyes of a friendly person,"458 consoling 191and cheering one up: as Xenophon459 tells us that the sight of Clearchus in battle and dangers, and his calm benevolent face, inspired courage in his men when in peril. But he who uses to a man in adversity too great freedom and severity of speech, like a man applying too pungent a remedy to an inflamed and angry eye, neither cures him nor abates his pain, but adds anger to his grief, and exasperates his mental distress. For example anyone well is not at all angry or fierce with a friend, who blames him for his excesses with women and wine, his laziness and taking no exercise, his frequent baths, and his unseasonable surfeiting: but to a person ill all this is unsufferable, and even worse than his illness to hear, "All this has happened to you through your intemperance, and luxury, your dainty food, and love for women." The patient answers, "How unseasonable is all this, good sir! I am making my will, the doctors are preparing me a dose of castor and scammony, and you are scolding me and plying me with philosophy." And thus the affairs of the unfortunate do not admit of outspokenness and a string of Polonius-like saws, but they require kindness and help. For when children fall down their nurses do not run up to them and scold, but pick them up, and clean them, and tidy their dress, and afterwards find fault and correct them. The story is told of Demetrius of Phalerum, when an exile from his native country, and living a humble and obscure life at Thebes, that he was not pleased to see Crates approaching, for he expected to receive from him cynical outspokenness and harsh language. But as Crates talked kindly to him, and discussed his exile, and pointed out that there was no evil in it, or anything that ought to put him about, for he had only got rid of the uncertainties and dangers of public life, and at the same time bade him trust in himself and his condition of mind, Demetrius cheered up and became happier, and said to his friends, "Out upon all my former business and employments, that left me no leisure to know such a man as this!"

For those who are successful, it's especially important to have friends who can speak honestly to them and keep their excessive pride in check. Few people are sensible during their success; most need to borrow wisdom from others to stay humble when they feel inflated and arrogant from their good fortune. But when fate has humbled them and stripped them of their arrogance, there’s something about their situation that reproaches them and prompts a change of heart. In those moments, there’s no need for blunt honesty or harsh words; instead, “it is sweet to look into the eyes of a friendly person,"458 providing solace 191 and encouragement. As Xenophon459 tells us, the sight of Clearchus in battle with his calm and kind expression inspired courage in his men during perilous times. However, someone who speaks too freely and harshly to a person in trouble, much like applying a strong remedy to an irritated eye, neither helps nor alleviates their pain but instead adds frustration to their sorrow and worsens their mental distress. For instance, someone who is well isn't angry or upset with a friend for pointing out their excesses with women and wine, laziness, lack of exercise, frequent bathing, and indulgence. However, for someone who is sick, hearing, "All this has happened to you because of your excesses and luxury," is unbearable and even worse than their illness. The sick person might respond, "How untimely is all this, good sir! I’m making my will, the doctors are preparing me a dose of castor oil and scammony, and you’re scolding me with philosophy." Thus, the matters of the unfortunate call for kindness and support rather than blunt advice and a list of platitudes. For when children fall down, their caregivers don’t scold them; they pick them up, clean them off, and fix their clothes, and only afterward do they correct their behavior. There’s a story about Demetrius of Phalerum, who, when he was exiled from his homeland and living a humble life in Thebes, was uneasy at the sight of Crates approaching because he expected cynical remarks and harsh criticism. But when Crates spoke kindly to him and discussed his exile, pointing out that there was nothing wrong with it and nothing to be upset about since he had escaped the uncertainties and dangers of public life, and encouraged him to have faith in himself and his state of mind, Demetrius felt uplifted and happier, exclaiming to his friends, "Forget all my past jobs and responsibilities that left me no time to know someone like this!"

"Because kind words are comforting to someone who is hurting, "Harsh words are only fitting for a fool."460

192 This is the way with generous friends. But the ignoble and low flatterers of those in prosperity, as Demosthenes says fractures and sprains always give us pain again when the body is not well,461 adhere to them in reverses, as if they were pleased at and enjoyed them. But indeed if there be any need of reminding a man of the blunders he committed through unadvisedly following his own counsel, it is enough to say, "This was not to my mind, indeed I often tried to dissuade you from it."462

192 This is how it is with generous friends. But the unworthy and petty flatterers of those who are doing well, as Demosthenes says, cause us pain again when our body isn’t well, 461 stick around during hard times, as if they are happy about and enjoy them. But really, if there’s a need to remind someone of the mistakes he made by unthinkingly following his own advice, it’s enough to say, “I wasn’t on board with this; in fact, I often tried to talk you out of it.” 462

§ xxix. In what cases then ought a friend to be vehement, and when ought he to use emphatic freedom of language? When circumstances call upon him to check some headlong pleasure or rage or insolence, or to curtail avarice, or to correct some foolish negligence. Thus Solon spoke out to Crœsus, who was corrupted and enervated by insecure good fortune, bidding him look to the end.463 Thus Socrates restrained Alcibiades, and wrung from him genuine tears by his reproof, and changed his heart.464 Such also was the plain dealing of Cyrus with Cyaxares, and of Plato with Dion, for when Dion was most famous and attracted to himself the notice of all men, by the splendour and greatness of his exploits, Plato warned him to fear and be on his guard against "pleasing only himself, for so he would lose all his friends."465 Speusippus also wrote to him not to plume himself on being a great person only with lads and women, but to see to it that by adorning Sicily with piety and justice and good laws he might make the Academy glorious. On the other hand Euctus and Eulæus, companions of Perseus, in the days of his prosperity ingratiated themselves with him, and assented to him in all things, and danced attendance upon him, like all the other courtiers, but when he fled after his defeat by the Romans at Pydna, they attacked him and censured him bitterly, reminding him and upbraiding him in regard to everything he had done amiss or neglected to do, till he was so greatly 193exasperated both from grief and rage that he whipped out his sword and killed both of them.

§ xxix. In what situations should a friend be assertive, and when should he speak freely? When the circumstances require him to curb reckless pleasures, anger, arrogance, greed, or foolish negligence. This is how Solon admonished Crœsus, who was weakened and corrupted by unstable fortune, urging him to consider the outcome.463 Similarly, Socrates restrained Alcibiades, making him genuinely cry with his criticism and prompting a change in his heart.464 Cyrus also confronted Cyaxares directly, as did Plato with Dion. When Dion was celebrated and gained attention for his impressive deeds, Plato cautioned him to be wary of only seeking personal pleasure, as that would cost him all his friends.465 Speusippus also wrote to him, advising him not to take pride in being admired only by young people and women but to focus on making Sicily renowned through piety, justice, and good laws to enhance the glory of the Academy. In contrast, Euctus and Eulæus, companions of Perseus, ingratiated themselves with him during his successful days, supporting his every decision and flattering him like all the other courtiers. However, after his defeat by the Romans at Pydna, they turned against him and harshly criticized him, reminding him of all his mistakes and oversights until he was so furious and grief-stricken that he drew his sword and killed both of them.

§ xxx. Let so much suffice for general occasions of freedom of speech. There are also particular occasions, which our friends themselves furnish, that one who really cares for his friends will not neglect, but make use of. In some cases a question, or narrative, or the censure or praise of similar things in other people, gives as it were the cue for freedom of speech. Thus it is related that Demaratus came to Macedonia from Corinth at the time when Philip was at variance with his wife and son, and when the king asked if the Greeks were at harmony with one another, Demaratus, being his well-wisher and friend, answered, "It is certainly very rich of you, Philip, inquiring as to concord between the Athenians and Peloponnesians, when you don't observe that your own house is full of strife and variance."466 Good also was the answer of Diogenes, who, when Philip was marching to fight against the Greeks, stole into his camp, and was arrested and brought before him, and the king not recognizing him asked if he was a spy, "Certainly," replied he, "Philip, I have come to spy out your inconsiderate folly, which makes you, under no compulsion, come here and hazard your kingdom and life on a moment's467 cast of the die." This was perhaps rather too strong a remark.

§ xxx. That should cover general instances of freedom of speech. There are also specific moments that our friends provide, which someone who truly cares for their friends won’t ignore but will take advantage of. Sometimes, a question, story, or the criticism or praise of similar situations involving others prompts a chance for open conversation. For example, it’s said that Demaratus came to Macedonia from Corinth when Philip was having conflicts with his wife and son. When the king asked if the Greeks were united, Demaratus, as his friend and supporter, replied, "It’s pretty rich of you, Philip, to ask about peace between the Athenians and Peloponnesians when you can’t even see that your own household is filled with conflict and discord." 466 Diogenes also gave a clever response when Philip was preparing to fight the Greeks. He sneaked into the king’s camp and was captured, then brought before Philip, who didn’t recognize him and asked if he was a spy. Diogenes replied, "Absolutely, Philip, I’ve come to investigate your reckless foolishness, which leads you to risk your kingdom and life for a gamble." 467 That might have been a bit too harsh.

§ xxxi. Another suitable time for reproof is when people have been abused by others for their faults, and have consequently become humble, and abated their pride. The man of tact will ingeniously seize the occasion, checking and baffling those that used the abuse, but privately speaking seriously to his friend, and reminding him, that he ought to be more careful if for no other reason than to take off the edge of his enemies' satire. He will say, "How can they open their mouths against you, or what can they urge, if you give up and abandon what you get this bad name about?" Thus pain comes only from abuse, but profit from reproof. And some correct their friends more 194daintily by blaming others; censuring others for what they know are their friends' faults. Thus my master Ammonius in afternoon school, noticing that some of his pupils had not dined sufficiently simply, bade one of his freedmen scourge his own son, charging him with being unable to get through his dinner without vinegar,468 but in acting thus he had an eye to us, so that this indirect rebuke touched the guilty persons.

§ xxxi. Another good time for a reality check is when people have been mistreated by others because of their faults and have become more humble and less prideful. A tactful person will cleverly take advantage of the situation, confronting those who were abusive, while privately having a serious conversation with his friend, reminding him that he should be more careful, if for no other reason than to lessen the sting of his enemies' criticism. He might say, "How can they criticize you, or what can they say, if you let go of the things that give you this bad reputation?" So, suffering comes only from abuse, but we gain from honest feedback. Some people correct their friends more delicately by blaming others, pointing out the faults of others that they know are actually their friends' issues. For instance, my teacher Ammonius, during afternoon class, noticing some of his students hadn't eaten simply enough, had one of his freedmen punish his own son, accusing him of being unable to finish his meal without vinegar,468 but by doing this, he was also subtly addressing us, so that this indirect criticism reached the ones at fault.

§ xxxii. We must also beware of speaking too freely to a friend in the company of many people, remembering the well-known remark of Plato. For when Socrates reproved one of his friends too vehemently in a discussion at table, Plato said, "Would it not have been better to have said this privately?" Whereupon Socrates replied, "And you too, sir, would it not have become you to make this remark also privately?" And Pythagoras having rebuked one of his pupils somewhat harshly before many people, they say the young fellow went off and hung himself, and from that moment Pythagoras never again rebuked anyone in another's presence. For, as in the case of some foul disease, so also in the case of wrong-doing we ought to make the detection and exposure private, and not ostentatiously public by bringing witnesses and spectators. For it is not the part of a friend but a sophist to seek glory by the ill-fame of another, and to show off in company, like the doctors that perform wonderful cures in the theatres as an advertisement.469 And independently of the insult, which ought not to be an element in any cure, we must remember that vice is contentious and obstinate. For it is not merely "love," as Euripides says, that "if checked becomes more vehement," but an unsparing rebuke before many people makes every infirmity and vice more impudent. As then Plato470 urges old men who want to teach the young reverence to act reverently to them first themselves, so among friends a gentle rebuke is gently taken, and 195a cautious and careful approach and mild censure of the wrong-doer undermines and destroys vice, and makes its own modesty catching. So that line is most excellent, "holding his head near, that the others might not hear."471 And most especially indecorous is it to expose a husband in the hearing of his wife, or a father before his children, or a lover in the presence of the loved one, or a master before his scholars. For people are beside themselves with pain and rage if reproached before those with whom they desire to be held in good repute. And I think it was not so much wine that exasperated Alexander with Clitus, as his seeming to put him down in the presence of many people. And Aristomenes, the tutor of Ptolemy,472 because he went up to the king and woke him as he was asleep in an audience of some ambassadors, gave a handle to the king's flatterers who professed to be indignant on his behalf, and said, "If after your immense state-labours and many vigils you have been overpowered by sleep, he ought to have rebuked you privately, and not put his hands upon you before so many people." And Ptolemy sent for a cup of poison and ordered the poor man to drink it up. And Aristophanes said Cleon blamed him for "railing against the state when strangers were present,"473 and so irritating the Athenians. We ought therefore to be very much on our guard in relation to this point too as well as others, if we wish not to make a display and catch the public ear, but to use our freedom of speech for beneficial purposes and to cure vice. Moreover, what Thucydides has represented the Corinthians saying of themselves, that "they had a right to blame their neighbours,"474 is not a bad precept for those to remember who intend to use freedom of speech. Lysander, it seems, on one occasion said to a Megarian, who was speaking somewhat boldly on behalf of Greece among the allies, "Your words require a state to back 196them":475 similarly every man's freedom of speech requires character behind it, and especially true is this in regard to those who censure and correct others. Thus Plato said that his life was a tacit rebuke to Speusippus: and doubtless Xenocrates by his mere presence in the schools, and by his earnest look at Polemo, made a changed man of him. Whereas a man of levity and bad character, if he ventures to rebuke anybody, is likely to hear the line,

§ xxxii. We also need to be careful about speaking too openly to a friend in front of a lot of people, keeping in mind Plato's famous comment. When Socrates scolded one of his friends too harshly during a meal, Plato said, "Wouldn’t it have been better to say this privately?" Socrates replied, "And you too, would it not have been more appropriate to make that comment privately?" When Pythagoras reprimanded one of his students a bit too harshly in front of a crowd, the young man reportedly went off and hanged himself, after which Pythagoras never rebuked anyone in public again. Just like we would handle an unpleasant disease, we should address wrongdoing privately rather than making a public spectacle of it with witnesses and onlookers. It’s not what a friend does to gain attention through someone else's misfortune and to show off in front of others, like doctors who perform impressive cures for the sake of advertisement in theaters.469 Beyond the insult, which should not be part of any remedy, we must recognize that vice is stubborn and confrontational. It's not just "love," as Euripides mentioned, that "if restrained becomes even more fervent," but a harsh reprimand in front of many people makes every flaw and vice bolder. Just as Plato470 advised older men who wish to teach the young to first act respectfully towards them, a gentle reproach among friends is better received, and a cautious and thoughtful approach to correcting the wrongdoer can undermine and eliminate vice, making modesty contagious. That line, "holding his head close so that others wouldn't hear," is truly excellent.471 It's particularly inappropriate to call out a husband in front of his wife, a father in front of his children, a lover in front of the beloved, or a teacher in front of his students. People are consumed with pain and anger when criticized before those they want to impress. I believe it wasn't just wine that angered Alexander with Clitus, but rather Clitus's putting him down in front of others. Aristomenes, Ptolemy's tutor, went up to the king and woke him while he was asleep during an audience with some ambassadors, providing ammunition for the king's flatterers who pretended to be outraged for his sake, saying, "If after your immense state duties and many sleepless nights you've fallen asleep, he should have scolded you privately, instead of waking you in front of so many." Ptolemy then ordered the poor man to drink a cup of poison. Aristophanes mentioned that Cleon criticized him for "attacking the state when strangers were present,"472 which upset the Athenians. Therefore, we should be very cautious about this issue, as well as others, if we wish to avoid making a spectacle and attracting public attention, and instead use our freedom of speech for positive outcomes and to correct vice. Moreover, what Thucydides recorded the Corinthians saying about themselves, that "they had a right to blame their neighbors,"473 is not a bad guideline for anyone intending to use their freedom of speech. It seems that Lysander once told a Megarian, who was speaking boldly on behalf of Greece among the allies, "Your words need a state to support them":474 similarly, everyone's freedom of speech needs character behind it, especially for those who criticize and advise others. Plato claimed that his life was a subtle rebuke to Speusippus: indeed, Xenocrates, just by being present at the schools and his serious gaze at Polemo, transformed him into a different person. On the other hand, a frivolous and immoral person, if they dare to scold someone, is likely to be met with the line,

"He treats others, even though he is sick himself." 476

§ xxxiii. Yet since circumstances frequently call on people who are bad themselves in association with other such to reprove them, the most convenient mode of reproof will be that which contrives to include the reprover in the same indictment as the reproved, as in the case of the line,

§ xxxiii. Yet because situations often require people who are flawed themselves, alongside others who are also flawed, to criticize them, the easiest way to criticize will be to include the critic in the same accusation as the one being criticized, as in the case of the line,

"Tydides, how on earth have we forgotten" Our reckless bravery? __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

and,

and,

"Are we not all worth just one Hector?"478

In this mild way did Socrates rebuke young men, as not himself without ignorance, but one that needed in common with them to prosecute virtue, and seek truth. For they gain goodwill and influence, who seem to have the same faults as their friends, and desire to correct themselves as well as them. But he who is high and mighty in setting down another, as if he were himself perfect and without any imperfections, unless he be of a very advanced age, or has an acknowledged reputation for virtue and worth, does no good, but is only regarded as a tiresome bore. And so it was wisely done of Phœnix to relate his own mishaps, how he had meant killing his father, but quickly repented at the thought "that he would be called by the Achæans parricide,"479 that he might not seem to be rebuking Achilles, as one that had himself never suffered from excess of rage. For kindness of this sort has great influence, 197and people yield more to those who seem to be sympathetic and not supercilious. And since we ought not to expose an inflamed eye to a strong light, and a soul a prey to the passions cannot bear unmixed reproof and rebuke, one of the most useful remedies will be found to be a slight mixture of praise, as in the following lines,

In this gentle way, Socrates challenged young men, acknowledging that he too had his own ignorance and needed to pursue virtue and seek truth alongside them. People gain favor and influence when they show they share the same flaws as their friends and want to improve themselves as well. But someone who is arrogant and harsh in criticizing others, as if they are perfect and have no faults themselves—unless they are very old or have a recognized reputation for virtue—doesn’t do any good; they are just seen as irritating. It was wise of Phœnix to share his own mistakes, how he almost killed his father but quickly regretted it, fearing the label of "parricide" from the Achæans, so that he wouldn’t come off as chastising Achilles, someone who had also struggled with rage. This kind of kindness has a strong impact, and people are more likely to listen to those who appear understanding rather than condescending. Just as we shouldn't expose an inflamed eye to bright light, a soul tormented by emotions can’t handle straightforward criticism alone. One of the most effective remedies is to mix in a bit of praise, as in the following lines,

"You surely won’t give up your brave courage, The best men in the group! I wouldn't mind. If any coward backed out of the fight, it wouldn't be me; "But doing that really hurts me."480

And,

And,

"Where is your bow, where are your winged arrows, Pandarus? "Where is your great fame, which no one here can match?"481

Such language again plainly cheers very much those that are down as,

Such language clearly cheers up those who are feeling low, as,

"Where is Oedipus now, and his famous riddles?"482

and,

and,

"Does enduring Hercules say this?"483

For not only does it soften the harsh imperiousness of censure, but also, by reminding a man of former noble deeds, implants a desire to emulate his former self in the person who is ashamed of what is low, and makes himself his own exemplar for better things. But if we make a comparison between him and other men, as his contemporaries, his fellow-citizens, or his relations, then the contentious spirit inherent in vice is vexed and exasperated, and is often apt to chime in angrily, "Why don't you go off to my betters then, and leave off bothering me?" We must therefore be on our guard against praising others, when we are rebuking a man, unless indeed it be their parents, as Agamemnon says in Homer,

Not only does it soften the harshness of criticism, but it also reminds a person of their past noble actions, creating a desire to be like their better self in someone who feels ashamed of their lower behavior, encouraging them to be their own role model for improvement. However, if we compare him to others, such as his peers, fellow citizens, or relatives, the argumentative nature of vice becomes irritated and frequently responds angrily, "Why don't you go to my betters and leave me alone?" We should, therefore, be cautious about praising others while reprimanding someone unless it involves their parents, as Agamemnon mentions in Homer.

"He's just like his father, Tydeus!"484

or as Odysseus in the play called "The Scyrians,"485

or as Odysseus in the play called "The Scyrians,"485

"Do you card wool and thus smudge the shine" "Of your distinguished father, your noble lineage?"

198§ xxxiv. But it is by no means fitting when rebuked to rebuke back, and when spoken to plainly to answer back, for that soon kindles a flame and causes dissension; and generally speaking such altercation will not look so much like a retort as an inability to bear freedom of speech. It is better therefore to listen patiently to a friend's rebuke, for if he should afterwards do wrong himself and so need rebuke, he has set you the example of freedom of speech. For being reminded without any malice, that he himself has not been accustomed to spare his friends when they have done wrong, but to convince them and show them their fault, he will be the more inclined to yield and give himself up to correction, as it will seem a return of goodwill and kindness rather than scolding or rage.

198§ xxxiv. However, it’s not appropriate to respond with a rebuke when you’re being called out, nor to snap back when someone speaks to you directly. That just ignites conflict and creates division; usually, such exchanges come off less like a rebuttal and more like an inability to accept open dialogue. It’s better to patiently accept a friend’s criticism because if they eventually make a mistake and need correcting, they’ve already set the example for honest communication. When reminded without any ill intent that they rarely hold back from pointing out their friends' faults, they’ll be more willing to listen and accept correction, as it will feel more like a gesture of goodwill and kindness, rather than just scolding or anger.

§ xxxv. Moreover, as Thucydides says "he is well advised who [only] incurs envy in the most important matters,"486 so the friend ought only to take upon himself the unpleasant duty of reproof in grave and momentous cases. For if he is always in a fret and a fume, and rates his acquaintances more like a tutor than a friend, his rebuke will be blunt and ineffective in cases of the highest importance, and he will resemble a doctor who dispenses some sharp and bitter, but important and costly, drug in trifling cases of common occurrence, where it was not at all needed, and so will lose all the advantages that might come from a judicious use of freedom of speech. He will therefore be very much on his guard against continual fault-finding, and if his friend is always pettifogging about minute matters, and is needlessly querulous, it will give him a handle against him in more important shortcomings. Philotimus the doctor, when a patient who had abscesses on his liver showed him his sore finger, said to him, "My friend, it is not the whitlow that matters."487 So an opportunity sometimes offers itself to a friend to say to a man, who is always finding fault on small and trivial points, "Why are we always discussing mere child's play, tippling,488 199and trifles? Let such a one, my dear sir, send away his mistress, or give up playing at dice, he will then be in my opinion in all respects an excellent fellow." For he who receives pardon on small matters is content that his friend should rebuke him on matters of more moment: but the man who is ever on the scold, everywhere sour and glum, knowing and prying into everything, is scarcely tolerable to his children or brothers, and insufferable to his slaves.

§ xxxv. Moreover, as Thucydides says, "it's wise to only attract envy in the most significant matters,"486 so a friend should only take on the uncomfortable job of criticism in serious situations. If he’s always upset and nitpicking, treating his friends more like a strict teacher than a buddy, his criticisms will lose their effectiveness when they really matter. He’ll end up like a doctor who prescribes a harsh and unpleasant but necessary medication for trivial issues that don’t need it, losing the benefits that come from using honest feedback wisely. He needs to be cautious about constantly pointing out flaws, because if a friend fixates on tiny issues and is unnecessarily grumpy, it will undermine his credibility when bigger problems arise. Philotimus the doctor, when a patient with liver abscesses showed him a sore finger, told him, "My friend, it’s not the finger that’s important."487 Sometimes, a friend should tell someone who always nitpicks about insignificant things, "Why are we constantly focusing on trivial matters, games,488 199 and small stuff? If he were to send away his girlfriend or stop gambling, then I think he’d be a great person overall." Because someone who gets forgiveness for minor mistakes is more likely to accept criticism on bigger issues: but a person who complains constantly, is sour, and is always in everyone’s business is hard to be around, even for his own family and unbearable for his servants.

§ xxxvi. But since "neither," to use the words of Euripides, "do all troubles proceed only from old age,"489 nor from the stupidity of our friends, we ought to observe not only the shortcomings but also the good points of our friends, aye, by Zeus, and to be ready to praise them first, and only censure them afterwards. For as iron receives its consistency and temper by first being submitted to fire and so made soft and then dipped into cold water, so when friends have been first warmed and melted with praises we can afterwards use gentle remonstrance, which has a similar effect to that of dipping in the case of the metal. For an opportunity will offer itself to say, "Are those actions worthy to be compared with these? Do you see what fruits virtue yields? These are the things we your friends ask of you, these become you, for these you are designed by nature; but all that other kind of conduct we must reject with abhorrence, 'cast it away on a mountain, or throw it into the roaring sea.'"490 For as a clever doctor would prefer to cure the illness of his patient by sleep and diet rather than by castor or scammony, so a kind friend and good father or teacher delight to use praise rather than blame to correct the character. For nothing makes rebuke less painful or more beneficial than to refrain from anger, and to inveigh against wrong-doing mildly and kindly. And so we ought not sharply to drive home the guilt of those who deny it, or prevent their making their defence, but even contrive to furnish them with specious excuses, and if they seem reluctant to give a bad motive for their action we ought ourselves to find for them a better, as Hector did for his brother Paris,

§ xxxvi. But since "neither," as Euripides said, "do all troubles come just from old age,"489 nor from the foolishness of our friends, we should pay attention not only to their faults but also to their strengths. Indeed, by Zeus, we should be ready to praise them first and only criticize them afterward. Just as iron gains its strength and temper by first being heated and softened in fire and then plunged into cold water, so when friends are initially warmed and softened by praise, we can later use gentle reminders, which have a similar effect as cooling the metal. There will come a time to ask, "Are those actions worthy of comparison to these? Do you see what fruits virtue produces? These are the things we, your friends, desire from you; these suited you, for these are what you were made for; but we must reject all that other behavior with disgust, 'cast it away on a mountain, or throw it into the roaring sea.'"490 Just as a skilled doctor would prefer to heal his patient with rest and diet instead of harsh medicines like castor oil or scammony, a kind friend, good parent, or teacher enjoys using praise rather than blame to improve character. Nothing makes criticism less painful or more effective than avoiding anger and addressing wrongdoing gently and kindly. Therefore, we should not harshly emphasize the guilt of those who deny it or hinder their defense, but instead find ways to provide them with plausible reasons, and if they seem hesitant to admit a bad motive for their actions, we should help them find a better one, just as Hector did for his brother Paris.

"Unhappy man, your anger was not good,"491

200suggesting that his absconding from the battle was not running away or cowardice, but only anger. And Nestor says to Agamemnon,

200indicating that his escape from the battle wasn't about fleeing or being cowardly, but just fueled by anger. And Nestor says to Agamemnon,

"You only gave in to your high passion."492

For it has, I think, a better moral tendency to say "You forgot," or "You did it inadvertently," than to say "You acted unfairly," or "You behaved shamefully:" as also "Don't contend with your brother," than "Don't envy your brother;" and "Avoid the woman who is your ruin," than "Stop ruining the woman." Such is the language employed in rebuke that desires to reform and not to wound; that rebuke which looks merely at the effect to be produced acts on another principle. For when it is necessary to stop people on the verge of wrong-doing, or to check some violent and irregular impulse, or if we wish to rouse and infuse vigour in those who prosecute virtue only feebly and languidly, we may then assign strange and unbecoming motives for their behaviour. As Odysseus in Sophocles' play,493 striving to rouse Achilles, says he is not angry about his supper,494 but "that he is afraid now that he looks upon the walls of Troy," and when Achilles was vexed at this, and talked of sailing home again, he said,

For I believe it's more constructive to say "You forgot" or "You did it accidentally" rather than "You acted unfairly" or "You behaved shamefully." Similarly, it's better to advise, "Don't argue with your brother" instead of "Don't envy your brother," and to suggest "Stay away from the woman who's bringing you down" rather than "Stop bringing down the woman." This is the kind of language used in rebuke that aims to reform rather than hurt; that rebuke which focuses only on the outcome follows a different approach. When it's important to stop someone on the brink of wrongdoing, or to curb some extreme or chaotic impulse, or if we want to motivate those who are only pursuing virtue half-heartedly, we might assign unusual and inappropriate motives for their actions. As Odysseus in Sophocles' play,493 trying to motivate Achilles, states that he isn't upset about his meal,494 but rather "that he is now afraid when he looks at the walls of Troy," and when Achilles grew frustrated with this and mentioned going home, he said,

"I know what you're avoiding: it's not bad reputation:" But Hector is nearby; it’s not safe to confront him.

Thus by frightening the high-spirited and courageous man by the imputation of cowardice, and the sober and orderly man by that of licentiousness, and the liberal and munificent man by that of meanness and avarice, people urge them on to what is good, and deter them from what is bad, showing moderation in cases past remedy, and exhibiting in their freedom of speech more sorrow and sympathy than fault-finding; but in the prevention of wrong-doing and in earnest fighting against the passions they are vehement and inexorable and assiduous: for that is the time 201for downright plainness and truth. Besides we see that enemies censure one another for what they have done amiss, as Diogenes said,495 he who wished to lead a good life ought to have good friends or red-hot enemies, for the former told you what was right, and the latter blamed you if you did what was wrong. But it is better to be on our guard against wrong actions, through listening to the persuasion of those that advise us well, than to repent, after we have done wrong, in consequence of the reproaches of our enemies. And so we ought to employ tact in our freedom of speech, as it is the greatest and most powerful remedy in friendship, and always needs a well-chosen occasion, and moderation in applying it.

By intimidating the spirited and brave person with accusations of cowardice, the sensible and orderly individual with claims of recklessness, and the generous person with suggestions of stinginess and greed, people encourage them towards good actions and steer them away from bad ones. They show restraint in situations that can't be fixed and express more sadness and empathy in their criticism than blame; however, when it comes to preventing wrongdoing and sincerely combating passions, they are passionate, relentless, and diligent, as that's the moment for straightforward honesty and truth. Additionally, we see that adversaries criticize each other for their mistakes, as Diogenes said, those who want to live well should have good friends or fierce enemies, since the former will point out what's right, and the latter will challenge you when you're wrong. It's better to be cautious about potential wrong actions by heeding the advice of those who guide us well than to regret our mistakes after facing the accusations of our rivals. Therefore, we should use discretion in our speech, as it's the most significant and effective tool in friendship, and it always requires a well-timed approach and moderation in its delivery.

§ xxxvii. Since then, as I have said before, freedom of speech is often painful to the person who is to receive benefit from it, we must imitate the surgeons, who, when they have performed an operation, do not leave the suffering part to pain and smart, but bathe and foment it; so those who do their rebuking daintily run496 off after paining and smarting, and by different dealing and kind words soothe and mollify them, as statuaries smooth and polish images which have been broken or chipped. But he that is broken and wounded by rebuke, if he is left sullen and swelling with rage and off his equilibrium, is henceforth hard to win back or talk over. And so people who reprove ought to be especially careful on this point, and not to leave them too soon, nor break off their conversation and intercourse with their acquaintances at the exasperating and painful stage.

§ xxxvii. As I mentioned earlier, freedom of speech can often be tough for the person who stands to gain from it. We should take a cue from surgeons who, after performing an operation, don’t just leave the painful area unattended but instead treat it gently. Similarly, those who offer criticism delicately often run off after causing discomfort, while kind words and thoughtful actions can help ease the pain, much like artists smooth and polish broken sculptures. However, if someone is left feeling hurt and angry after a rebuke, they become much harder to reach and persuade later on. Thus, those who offer criticism should be especially mindful of this, ensuring they don’t walk away too quickly or cut off their conversations during the frustrating and painful moments.

348 Plato, "Laws," v. p. 731 D, E.

348 Plato, "Laws," v. p. 731 D, E.

349 "Laws," v. p. 730 C.

"Laws," p. 730 C.

350 Inscribed in the vestibule of the temple of Apollo at Delphi. See Pausanias, x. 24.

350 Written in the entrance of the temple of Apollo at Delphi. See Pausanias, x. 24.

351 Used here apparently proverbially for poverty or low position in life.

351 Used here apparently in a figurative sense for poverty or a low status in life.

352 Wyttenbach well compares Cicero, "De Amicitia," xviii.: "Accedat huc suavitas quædam oportet sermonum atque morum, haudquaquam mediocre condimentum amicitiæ. Tristitia autem et in omni re severitas, habet illa quidem gravitatem: sed amicitia remissior esse debet, et liberior, et dulcior, et ad omnem comitatem facilitatemque proclivior."

352 Wyttenbach compares Cicero, "De Amicitia," xviii.: "We must also add a certain sweetness to conversations and behavior, which is no small ingredient in friendship. However, sadness and strictness in everything may certainly imply seriousness; but friendship should be more relaxed, freer, sweeter, and more inclined towards kindness and ease."

353 Hesiod, "Theogony," 64.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hesiod, "Theogony," 64.

354 Euripides, "Ion," 732.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Ion," 732.

355 Our author assigns this saying to Prodicus, "De Sanitate Præcepta," § viii. But to Evenus, "Quæst. Conviv." Lib. vii. Proœmium, and "Platonicæ Quæstiones," x. § iii.

355 Our author attributes this saying to Prodicus in "De Sanitate Præcepta," § viii. However, it is also linked to Evenus in "Quæst. Conviv." Book vii. Proœmium, and "Platonicæ Quæstiones," x. § iii.

356 As was usual. See Homer, "Odyssey," i. 146. Cf. Plautus, "Persa," v. iii. 16: "Hoc age, accumbe: hunc diem suavem meum natalem agitemus amœnum: date aquam manibus: apponite mensam."

356 As was typical. See Homer, "Odyssey," i. 146. Compare with Plautus, "Persa," v. iii. 16: "Do this, recline: let’s celebrate this pleasant day of my birth: give me water for my hands: set the table."

357 From a play of Eupolis called "The Flatterers." Cf. Terence, "Eunuchus," 489-491.

357 From a play by Eupolis called "The Flatterers." See Terence, "Eunuchus," 489-491.

358 See Athenæus, 256 D. Compare also Valerius Maximus, ix. 1.

358 See Athenæus, 256 D. Also check Valerius Maximus, ix. 1.

359 "Videatur Casaubonus ad Athenæum, vi. p. 243 A."—Wyttenbach.

359 "See Casaubonus in Athenæum, vol. vi, p. 243 A."—Wyttenbach.

360 "Republic," p. 361 A.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Republic," p. 361 A.

361 See Herodotus, iii. 78.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Check Herodotus, iii. 78.

362 See Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 1883.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 1883.

363 "Proverbium etiam a Cicerone laudatum 'De Amicitia,' cap. vi.: Itaque non aqua, non igne, ut aiunt, pluribus locis utimur, quam amicitia. Notavit etiam Erasmus 'Adag.' p. 112."—Wyttenbach.

363 "As praised by Cicero in 'On Friendship,' chapter 6: Therefore, we use neither water nor fire in as many places as we do friendship. Erasmus also noted this in 'Adages,' p. 112."—Wyttenbach.

364 Compare Sallust, "De Catilinæ Conjuratione," cap. xx.: "Nam idem velle atque idem nolle, ea demum firma amicitia est."

364 Compare Sallust, "De Catilinæ Conjuratione," ch. xx.: "For wanting the same things and rejecting the same things is the true strength of friendship."

365 "Proverbiale, quo utitur Plutarchus in Alcibiade, p. 203 D. Iambus Tragici esse videtur, ad Neoptolemum dictus."—Wyttenbach.

365 "Proverbially, as Plutarch uses it in Alcibiades, p. 203 D. It seems to be a tragic verse, spoken to Neoptolemus."—Wyttenbach.

366 As the polypus, or chameleon.

366 Like the octopus or the chameleon.

367 Plato, "Phædrus," p. 239 D.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Plato, "Phaedrus," p. 239 D.

368 Wyttenbach compares Juvenal, iii. 100-108.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Wyttenbach compares Juvenal, III. 100-108.

369 See my note "On Abundance of Friends," § ix. Wyttenbach well points out the felicity of the expression here, "siquidem parasitus est άοικος καὶ ἀνέστιος."

369 Check out my note "On Abundance of Friends," § ix. Wyttenbach highlights how effective the expression is here, "siquidem parasitus est άοικος καὶ ἀνέστιος."

370 Euripides, "Hippolytus," 219, 218. Cf. Ovid, "Heroides," iv. 41, 42.

370 Euripides, "Hippolytus," 219, 218. See also Ovid, "Heroides," iv. 41, 42.

371 Compare "How one may be aware of one's progress in virtue," § x. Cf. also Horace, "Satires," ii. iii. 35; Quintilian, xi. 1.

371 Compare "How one can see their progress in virtue," § x. Cf. also Horace, "Satires," ii. iii. 35; Quintilian, xi. 1.

372 "Odyssey," xxii. 1.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," xxii. 1.

373 The demagogue is a kind of flatterer. See Aristotle, "Pol." iv. 4.

373 The demagogue is a type of sycophant. See Aristotle, "Pol." iv. 4.

374 Cf. Aristophanes, "Acharnians," 153, ὅπερ μαχιμώτατον θρᾳκῶν ἔθνος.

374 See Aristophanes, "Acharnians," 153, which refers to the most warlike Thracian nation.

375 Plato was somewhat of a traveller, he three times visited Syracuse, and also travelled in Egypt.

375 Plato was a bit of a traveler; he visited Syracuse three times and also traveled in Egypt.

376 As to the polypus, see "On Abundance of Friends," § ix.

376 Regarding the polyp, check out "On Abundance of Friends," § ix.

377 As "Fumum et opes strepitumque Romæ."—Horace, "Odes," iii. 29. 12.

377 As "Smoke and wealth and the noise of Rome."—Horace, "Odes," iii. 29. 12.

378 Homer, "Odyssey," xvi. 181.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Odyssey," 16.181.

379 Sophocles, "Antigone," 523.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Sophocles, "Antigone," 523.

380 As to these traits in Plato and Aristotle, compare "De Audiendis Poetis," § viii. And as to Alexander, Plutarch tells us in his Life that he used to hold his head a little to the left, "Life," p. 666 B. See also "De Alexandri Fortuna aut Virtute," § ii.

380 Regarding these characteristics in Plato and Aristotle, refer to "De Audiendis Poetis," § viii. And about Alexander, Plutarch mentions in his Life that he would tilt his head slightly to the left, "Life," p. 666 B. Also see "De Alexandri Fortuna aut Virtute," § ii.

381 "De Chamæleonte Aristoteles 'Hist. Animal.' i. 11; 'Part. Animal.' iv. 11; Theophrastus Eclog. ap. Photium edit. Aristot. Sylburg. T. viii. p. 329: μεταβάλλει δὲ ὁ χαμαιλέων εἰς πάντα τὰ χρώματα· πλὴν τὴν εἰς τὸ λευκὸν και τὸ ἐρυθρὸν οὐ δέχεται μεταβολήν. Similiter Plinius 'Hist. Nat.' viii. 51."—Wyttenbach.

381 "In 'Hist. Animal.' i. 11 and 'Part. Animal.' iv. 11, Aristotle discusses the chameleon. Theophrastus in the Eclogues, edited by Photios in the edition of Aristotle by Sylburg, T. viii. p. 329, writes: 'The chameleon changes into all colors except white and red.' Similarly, Pliny in 'Hist. Nat.' viii. 51."—Wyttenbach.

382 See Athenæus, 249 F; 435 E.

382 See Athenæus, 249 F; 435 E.

383 Cf. Juv. iii. 113; "Scire volunt secreta domus, atque inde timeri."

383 See Juv. iii. 113; "They want to know the secrets of the house, and from that, they are afraid."

384 Cf. Menander apud Stob. p. 437: Τὰ δεύτερ᾽ αἰεὶ τὴν γυναῖκα δεὶ λέγειν, Τὴν δ᾽ ἡγεμονιαν τῶν ὅλων τὸν ἄνδρ᾽ ἔχειν.

384 See Menander in Stob. p. 437: Always mention the woman second, but the man should have the overall leadership.

385 As Lord Stowell used to say that "dinners lubricated business."

385 As Lord Stowell used to say, "Dinners smooth the way for business."

386 Homer, "Iliad," xi. 643.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," xi. 643.

387 Homer, "Odyssey," iv. 178, 179.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Odyssey," Book 4, lines 178-179.

388 Perhaps the poley-germander. See Pliny, "Nat. Hist," xxi. 84. The line is from Nicander Theriac. 64.

388 Maybe the poley-germander. See Pliny, "Nat. Hist," xxi. 84. The line is from Nicander Theriac. 64.

389 "Iliad," viii. 281, 282.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," viii. 281, 282.

390 "Iliad," x. 243.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," x. 243.

391 "Iliad," vii. 109, 110.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," vii. 109, 110.

392 Xenophon, "Agesilaus," xi. 5. p. 673 C.

392 Xenophon, "Agesilaus," xi. 5. p. 673 C.

393 To filch the grain from the bin or granary would not of course be so important a theft as to steal the seed-stock preserved for sowing. So probably Cato, "De Re Rustica," v. § iv.: "Segetem ne defrudet," sc. villicus.

393 Taking grain from the storage bin or granary isn't as significant of a theft as stealing the seed stock saved for planting. This reflects what Cato mentions in "De Re Rustica," v. § iv.: "Don't cheat the crop," referring to the overseer.

394 Thucydides, iii. 82.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Thucydides, vol. iii, p. 82.

395 Plato, "Republic," v. p. 474 E. Compare also Lucretius, iv. 1160-1170; Horace, "Satires," i. 3. 38 sq.

395 Plato, "Republic," v. p. 474 E. Also compare Lucretius, iv. 1160-1170; Horace, "Satires," i. 3. 38 sq.

396 This Ptolemy was a votary of Cybele, and a spiritual ancestor of General Booth. The worship of Cybele is well described by Lucretius, ii. 598-643.

396 This Ptolemy was a follower of Cybele and a spiritual predecessor of General Booth. The worship of Cybele is well described by Lucretius, ii. 598-643.

397 This was Ptolemy Auletes, as the former was Ptolemy Philopator.

397 This was Ptolemy Auletes, while the former was Ptolemy Philopator.

398 See Suetonius, "Nero," ch. 21.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Suetonius, "Nero," chap. 21.

399 "Plerumque minuta voce cantillare."—Wyttenbach. What Milton would have called "a lean and flashy song."

399 "Usually to sing in a soft voice."—Wyttenbach. What Milton would have referred to as "a thin and showy song."

400 Naso suspendit adunco, as Horace, "Sat." i. 6. 5.

400 Naso hangs on a hook, as Horace says in "Sat." i. 6. 5.

401 See Athenæus, p. 434 C.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Athenæus, p. 434 C.

402 As Gnatho in Terence, "Eunuch." 496-498.

402 As Gnatho in Terence, "Eunuch." 496-498.

403 Reading ἑλών, as Courier, Hercher.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading selected, as Courier, Hercher.

404 "Iliad," x. 249. They are words of Odysseus.

404 "Iliad," x. 249. These are the words of Odysseus.

405 This was carrying flattery rather far. "Mithridatis medicinæ scientia multis memorata veterum."—Wyttenbach.

405 This was taking flattery a bit too far. "Mithridatic medicine is often mentioned by many of the ancients."—Wyttenbach.

406 Euripides, "Alcestis," 1159.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Alcestis," 1159.

407 Our author gives this definition to Simonides, "De Gloria Atheniensium," § iii.

407 Our author gives this definition to Simonides, "On the Glory of the Athenians," § iii.

408 So our author again, "On Contentedness of Mind," § xii.

408 So our author again, "On Contentedness of Mind," § xii.

409 See Herodotus, i. 30, 33; Juvenal, x. 274, 275; and Pausanias, ii. 20.

409 See Herodotus, i. 30, 33; Juvenal, x. 274, 275; and Pausanias, ii. 20.

410 "Nobile Stoæ Paradoxum. Cicero Fin. iii. 22, ex persona Catonis. Horatius ridet Epistol. i. 1. 106-108. Ad summam sapiens uno minor est Jove: dives, Liber, honoratus, pulcher, rex denique regum; Præcipue sanus, nisi quum pituita molesta est."—Wyttenbach.

410 "Noble Stoic Paradox. Cicero Fin. iii. 22, from the perspective of Cato. Horace laughs in Epistle i. 1. 106-108. In summary, the wise man is one degree below Jupiter: wealthy, free, esteemed, handsome, finally the king of kings; especially sane, unless when troubled by annoying phlegm."—Wyttenbach.

411 See also "On Contentedness of Mind," § xii.

411 Check out "On Contentedness of Mind," § xii.

412 Homer, "Iliad," xvi. 141. See the context also from 130 sq.

412 Homer, "Iliad," xvi. 141. See the context also from 130 onward.

413 Our author has used this illustration again in "Phocion," p. 742 B.

413 Our author has used this example again in "Phocion," p. 742 B.

414 Namely in § xxvii. where παῤῥησια is discussed.

414 Specifically in § xxvii. where παῤῥησια is discussed.

415 Contrary to the severe training he ought to undergo, well expressed by Horace, "De Arte Poetica," 412-414.

415 Instead of the tough training he should go through, as Horace puts it in "De Arte Poetica," 412-414.

416 Reading with Hercher ἀποτυμπανίζοντος και στρεβλοῦντος. This was Ptolemy Physcon.

416 Reading with Hercher, beating and distorting. This was Ptolemy Physcon.

417 "Unus ex Alexandri adulatoribus: memoratus Curtio viii. 5, 6."—Wyttenbach.

417 "One of Alexander's flatterers: mentioned in Curtius viii. 5, 6."—Wyttenbach.

418 A common proverb among the ancients. See "Conjugal Precepts," § xl.; Erasmus, "Adagia," pp. 1222, 1838.

418 A well-known saying from ancient times. See "Conjugal Precepts," § xl.; Erasmus, "Adagia," pp. 1222, 1838.

419 A line out of Æschylus' "Myrmidons." Quoted again by our author, "Of Love," § v.

419 A line from Æschylus' "Myrmidons." Cited again by our author, "Of Love," § v.

420 Cleopatra.

Cleopatra.

421 Homer, "Odyssey," x. 329. They are the words of Circe to Odysseus. But the line was suspected even by old grammarians, and is put in brackets in modern editions of the "Odyssey."

421 Homer, "Odyssey," x. 329. These are Circe's words to Odysseus. However, even ancient grammarians questioned this line, and it is enclosed in brackets in modern editions of the "Odyssey."

422 See Lucretius, iv. 1079-1085.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Lucretius, iv. 1079-1085.

423 So Pliny, "Hist. Nat." xxv. 95: "Remedio est (cicutæ), priusquam perveniat ad vitalia, vini natura excalfactoria: sed in vino pota irremediabilis existimatur."

423 So Pliny, "Hist. Nat." xxv. 95: "The remedy (for hemlock) is a naturally warming wine, before it reaches the vital organs; but once consumed with wine, it is considered irreparable."

424 Assigned to Pittacus by our author, "Septem Sapientum Convivium," § ii.

424 Given to Pittacus by our author, "Septem Sapientum Convivium," § ii.

425 So Wyttenbach, who reads ἐνστάσεις, and translates, "et libertate loquendi in nobis reprehendendis utitur, quando nos cupiditatibus morbisque animi nostri non indulgere, sed resistere, volumus."

425 So Wyttenbach, who reads ἐνστάσεις, and translates, "and uses the freedom of speech to criticize us when we want to resist our desires and the illnesses of our minds, not indulge in them."

426 "Phœnissæ," 469-472.

"Phœnissæ," 469-472.

427 Like Juvenal's "Græculus esuriens in cælum, jusseris, ibit."—Juvenal, iii, 78.

427 Like Juvenal's "The greedy little Greek will go to the skies if you order him to."—Juvenal, iii, 78.

428 These are two successive lines found three times in Homer, "Iliad," xiv. 195, 196; xviii. 426, 427; "Odyssey," v. 89, 90. The two lines are in each case spoken by one person.

428 These are two consecutive lines found three times in Homer's works, "Iliad," xiv. 195, 196; xviii. 426, 427; "Odyssey," v. 89, 90. Each time, the lines are spoken by one person.

429 Probably lines from "The Flatterer" of Menander.

429 Probably lines from "The Flatterer" by Menander.

430 From the "Ino" of Euripides.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ From the "Ino" by Euripides.

431 From the "Erechtheus" of Euripides.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ From "Erechtheus" by Euripides.

432 We know from Athenæus, p. 420 D, that Apelles and Arcesilaus were friends.

432 We learn from Athenæus, p. 420 D, that Apelles and Arcesilaus were friends.

433 An allusion to Hesiod, "Works and Days," 235. Cf. Horace, "Odes," iv. 5. 23.

433 A reference to Hesiod, "Works and Days," 235. See Horace, "Odes," iv. 5. 23.

434 See the beautiful story of Baucis and Philemon, Ovid, "Metamorphoses," viii. 626-724: "Cura pii dis sunt, et qui coluere coluntur."

434 Check out the beautiful story of Baucis and Philemon in Ovid's "Metamorphoses," viii. 626-724: "Cura pii dis sunt, et qui coluere coluntur."

435 Compare Terence, "Andria," 43, 44. So too Seneca, "De Beneficiis," ii. 10: "Hæc enim beneficii inter duos lex est: alter statim oblivisci debet dati, alter accepti nunquam. Lacerat animum et premit frequens meritorum commemoratio."

435 Compare Terence, "Andria," 43, 44. Also Seneca, "De Beneficiis," ii. 10: "This is the rule for benefits between two people: one should forget what they gave immediately, and the other should never forget what they received. The constant reminder of favors damages the spirit and weighs heavily."

436 A similar story about the Samians and Lacedæmonians is told by Aristotle, "Œconom." ii. 9.

436 A similar story about the Samians and Spartans is told by Aristotle, "Œconom." ii. 9.

437 A line from Euripides, "Iphigenia in Aulis," 407.

437 A line from Euripides, "Iphigenia in Aulis," 407.

438 Also in "Conjugal Precepts," § xxix.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Also in "Conjugal Guidelines," __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__

439 See Persius, iii. 21, 22, with Jahn's Note.

439 See Persius, iii. 21, 22, with Jahn's Note.

440 See "On Love," § xxi.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See "On Love," __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__

441 "Auri plumbique oppositio fere proverbialis est. Petronius, 'Satyricon,' 43. Plane fortunæ filius: in manu illius plumbum aureum fiebat."—Wyttenbach. The passage about the Lydian chariot is said to be by Pindar in our author, "Nicias," p. 523 D.

441 "The contrast between gold and lead is almost proverbial. Petronius, 'Satyricon,' 43. Clearly the son of fortune: in his hand, lead becomes gold."—Wyttenbach. The section about the Lydian chariot is attributed to Pindar in our source, "Nicias," p. 523 D.

442 Wyttenbach compares Seneca, "Epist." cxxiii. p. 495: "Horum sermo multum nocet: nam etiamsi non statim officit, semina in animo relinquit, sequiturque nos etiam cum ab illis discesserimus, resurrecturum postea malum."

442 Wyttenbach compares Seneca, "Epist." cxxiii. p. 495: "This kind of talk is very harmful: even if it doesn't immediately cause harm, it leaves seeds in the mind and continues to affect us even after we have parted ways with it, and the trouble will rise again later."

443 Compare Cicero, "De Amicitia," xxvi.: "Assentatio, quamvis perniciosa sit, nocere tamen nemini potest, nisi ei, qui eam recipit atque ea delectatur. Ita fit, ut is assentatoribus patefaciat aures suas maxime, qui ipse sibi assentetur et se maxime ipse delectet."

443 Compare Cicero, "On Friendship," xxvi.: "Flattery, although harmful, can only hurt the one who accepts it and enjoys it. Therefore, a flatterer can really get through to someone who flatters themselves and delights in their own approval."

444 Compare § i.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare

445 Compare our Author, "Quaestiones Convivalium," viii. p. 717 F.

445 Compare our Author, "Questions at the Banquet," viii. p. 717 F.

446 So Horace, "Satires," i. 2, 24: "Dum vitant stulti vitia in contraria currunt."

446 So Horace, "Satires," i. 2, 24: "While fools try to avoid one flaw, they run into the opposite."

447 Homer, "Iliad," xiv. 84, 85.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," XIV. 84, 85.

448 Compare Cicero, "De Officiis," i. 25: "Omnis autem animadversio et castigatio contumelia vacare debet: neque ad ejus, qui punitur aliquem aut verbis fatigat, sed ad reipublicæ utilitatem referri."

448 Compare Cicero, "De Officiis," i. 25: "Any punishment or reprimand should be free of insult; it should not be directed at the person being punished or exhausted by words, but should serve the good of the state."

449 "Iliad," xi. 654.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xi. 654.

450 "Iliad," xvi. 33-35.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xvi. 33-35.

451 Cf. Plutarch, "Phocion," p. 746 D.

451 See Plutarch, "Phocion," p. 746 D.

452 A proverb of persons on the brink of destruction. Wells among the ancients were uncovered.

452 A saying for those about to face ruin. In ancient times, wells were left uncovered.

453 "Iliad," ii. 215, of Thersites. As to Theagenes, see Seneca, "De Ira," ii. 23.

453 "Iliad," ii. 215, about Thersites. For Theagenes, refer to Seneca, "De Ira," ii. 23.

454 Literally, "brings a cloud over fair weather."

454 Literally, "casts a shadow on sunny days."

455 The MSS. have Lydian. Lysian Dionysus is also found in Pausanias, ix. 16. Lyæus is suggested by Wyttenbach, and read by Hercher. Lysius or Lyæus will both be connected with λύω, and so refer to Dionysus as the god that looses or frees us from care. See Horace, "Epodes," ix. 37, 38.

455 The MSS. have Lydian. The Lydian Dionysus is also mentioned in Pausanias, ix. 16. Lyæus is suggested by Wyttenbach and read by Hercher. Lysius or Lyæus both relate to λύω, referring to Dionysus as the god who releases or frees us from worry. See Horace, "Epodes," ix. 37, 38.

456 Compare Juvenal, iii. 73, 74: "Sermo Promptus et Isæo torrentior."

456 Compare Juvenal, iii. 73, 74: "The speech is quick and more rushing than Isaeus."

457 "Orestes," 667.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Orestes," 667.

458 Euripides, "Ion," 732.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Ion," 732.

459 "Anabasis," ii. 6, 11.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Anabasis," ii. 6, 11.

460 Perhaps by Euripides.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Maybe by Euripides.

461 "Olynth." ii. p. 8 C; "Pro Corona," 341 C.

461 "Olynth." ii. p. 8 C; "Pro Corona," 341 C.

462 Homer, "Iliad," ix. 108, 109. They are the words of Nestor to Agamemnon.

462 Homer, "Iliad," ix. 108, 109. These are Nestor's words to Agamemnon.

463 See Herodotus, i. 30-32.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Herodotus, 1. 30-32.

464 See Plato's "Symposium," p. 215 E.

464 See Plato's "Symposium," p. 215 E.

465 See Plato, "Epist." iv. p. 321 B.

465 See Plato, "Epist." iv. p. 321 B.

466 See our author, "Apophthegmata," p. 179 C.

466 Check out our author, "Apophthegmata," p. 179 C.

467 Compare Horace, "Satires," i. 1. 7, 8: "Quid enim, concurritur: horæ Momento cita mors venit aut victoria læta."

467 Compare Horace, "Satires," i. 1. 7, 8: "What is it? We rush: in a moment, death comes swiftly or joyful victory."

468 And so being dainty. See Athenæus, ii. ch. 76.

468 And so being selective. See Athenæus, ii. ch. 76.

469 We see from this and other places that the mountebanks and quacks of the Middle Ages and later times existed also among the ancients. Human nature in its great leading features is ever the same. "Omne ignotum pro magnifico est."

469 We can see from this and other sources that the con artists and frauds of the Middle Ages, as well as later periods, also existed in ancient times. Human nature, in its main aspects, remains constant. "Everything unknown is taken for great."

470 "Laws," p. 729 C.

"Laws," p. 729 C.

471 Homer, "Odyssey," i. 157; iv. 70; xvii. 592.

471 Homer, "Odyssey," i. 157; iv. 70; xvii. 592.

472 Ptolemy V., Epiphanes. The circumstances are related by Polybius, xv. 29; xvii. 35.

472 Ptolemy V., Epiphanes. The details are discussed by Polybius, xv. 29; xvii. 35.

473 See "Acharnians," 501, 502.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See "Acharnians," 501, 502.

474 Thucydides, i. 70: καὶ ἅμα, εἴπερ τινὲς και ἄλλοι, νομίζομεν ἄξιοι εἷναι τοῖς πέλας ψόγον ἐπενεγκεῖν.

474 Thucydides, i. 70: And at the same time, if anyone else, we believe, are worthy of criticism from those nearby.

475 See our Author, "Apophthegmata," p. 190 E.

475 Check out our Author, "Apophthegmata," p. 190 E.

476 A line of Euripides, quoted again in "How a Man may be benefited by his Enemies," § iv.

476 A line from Euripides, mentioned again in "How a Man may Be Benefited by His Enemies," § iv.

477 Homer, "Iliad," xi. 313.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 11.313.

478 Do. viii. 234, 235.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Do. 8.

479 Do. ix. 461.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Do. ix. 461.

480 "Iliad," xiii. 116-119.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xiii. 116-119.

481 Do. v. 171, 172.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Do. v. 171, 172.

482 Euripides, "Phœnissæ," 1688.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Phoenician Women," 1688.

483 Euripides, "Hercules Furens," 1250.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Mad Hercules," 1250.

484 "Iliad," v. 800. Athene is the speaker.

484 "Iliad," v. 800. Athena is the speaker.

485 A play by Sophocles, now only in fragments, relating the life of Achilles in the island of Scyros, the scene of his amour with Deidamia, the daughter of Lycomedes, by whom he became the father of Pyrrhus.

485 A play by Sophocles, now existing only in fragments, tells the story of Achilles on the island of Scyros, the setting for his romance with Deidamia, the daughter of Lycomedes, with whom he became the father of Pyrrhus.

486 Thucydides, ii. 64. Quoted again in "On Shyness," § xviii.

486 Thucydides, ii. 64. Quoted again in "On Shyness," § xviii.

487 See also "De Audiendo," § x.

487 Also check out "De Audiendo," § x.

488 πότους comes in rather curiously here. Can any other word lurk under it?

488 “ποτούς” appears here in a pretty interesting way. Could there be another word hidden beneath it?

489 "Phœnissæ," 528, 529.

"Phoenicians," 528, 529.

490 Homer, "Iliad," vi. 347.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," Book 6, Line 347.

491 Do. vi. 326.

Do. vi. 326.

492 Homer, "Iliad," ix. 109, 110.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," Book 9, verses 109-110.

493 In Dindorf's "Poetæ Scenici Græci," Fragment 152.

493 In Dindorf's "Greek Dramatic Poets," Fragment 152.

494 As it is not quite clear why Achilles should have been angry about his supper, διὰ τὸ δειπνὸν, apropos of the context, Wyttenbach ingeniously suggests, as this lost play of Sophocles was called Συν δεῖπνον, that Plutarch may have written ἐν τῷ Δείπνῳ.

494 It's not really clear why Achilles was mad about his dinner, διὰ τὸ δειπνὸν. In relation to the context, Wyttenbach cleverly suggests that since this lost play by Sophocles was called Συν δεῖπνον, Plutarch may have written ἐν τῷ Δείπνῳ.

495 Compare "How One may be aware of one's Progress in Virtue," § xi.

495 Compare "How one can notice their growth in virtue," § xi.

496 "Ductum e proverbiali dictione βαλόντα ἐκφεύγειν, emisso telo aufugere."—Wyttenbach.

496 "To be drawn from a proverbial saying, to escape as if shot from a bow."—Wyttenbach.


HOW A MAN MAY BE BENEFITED BY HIS ENEMIES.

§ i. I am well aware, Cornelius Pulcher, that you prefer the mildest manners in public life, by which you can be at once most useful to the community, and most agreeable in 202private life to those who have any dealings with you. But since it is difficult to find any region without wild beasts, though it is related of Crete;497 and hitherto there has been no state that has not suffered from envy, rivalry, and strife, the most fruitful seeds of hostility; (for, even if nothing else does, our friendships involve us in enmities, as Chilo498 the wise man perceived, who asked the man who told him he had no enemy, whether he had a friend either), it seems to me that a public man ought not only to examine the whole question of enemies in its various ramifications, but also to listen to the serious remark of Xenophon,499 that a sensible man will receive profit even from his enemies. The ideas therefore that lately occurred to me to deliver, I have now put together nearly in the identical words and send them to you, with the exception of some matter also in "Political Precepts,"500 a treatise which I have often noticed in your hands.

§ i. I know, Cornelius Pulcher, that you prefer a gentle approach in public life, as it allows you to be both helpful to the community and pleasant in 202private life to those you interact with. However, since it’s hard to find any place without challenges, even if Crete is said to be one; 497 and so far, no state has been free from jealousy, competition, and conflict, which are the main sources of hostility; (because even if nothing else, our friendships can lead to enmities, as Chilo498 the wise man pointed out when he asked someone who claimed to have no enemies if they had a friend), it seems to me that a public figure should not only consider the whole topic of enemies in its different aspects but also heed the thoughtful observation made by Xenophon,499 that a wise person can gain from their enemies. Therefore, I have compiled the ideas I recently thought of into nearly the same words and am sending them to you, except for some content also found in "Political Precepts,"500 a work I’ve often seen you with.

§ ii. People in old times were well satisfied if they were not injured by strange and wild beasts, and that was the only motive of their fights with them, but those of later days have by now learnt to make use of them, for they feed on their flesh, and clothe themselves with their wool, and make medical use of their gall and beestings, and turn their hides into shields, so that we might reasonably fear, if beasts failed man, that his life would become brutish, and wild, and void of resources. Similarly since all others are satisfied with not being injured by their enemies, but the sensible will also (as Xenophon says) get profit out of them, we must not be incredulous, but seek a method and plan how to obtain this advantage, seeing that life without an enemy is impossible. The husbandman cannot cultivate every tree, nor can the hunter tame every kind of animal, so both seek means to derive profit according to their several necessities, the one from his barren trees, the other from his wild animals. Sea-water also is undrinkable and brackish, but it feeds fish, and is a sort of vehicle to convey and transport travellers anywhere. The Satyr, when he 203saw fire for the first time, wished to kiss it and embrace it, but Prometheus warned him,

§ ii. In ancient times, people were just happy if they weren’t hurt by wild animals, and that was their only reason for fighting them. But nowadays, people have learned to utilize them; they eat their meat, wear their wool, use their gall and stings for medicine, and turn their hides into shields. It's reasonable to think that if animals stopped helping humans, life would become brutish, wild, and lacking in resources. Similarly, while most people are content with just avoiding harm from their enemies, sensible individuals will also, as Xenophon says, find ways to benefit from them. We shouldn't be skeptical, but rather look for a method and plan to gain this advantage, since life without an enemy is unthinkable. A farmer can’t grow every type of tree, nor can a hunter tame every kind of animal, so both look for ways to benefit according to their needs—one from his unproductive trees and the other from his wild animals. Sea water is also undrinkable and salty, but it nourishes fish and serves as a means of transport for travelers. The Satyr, when he 203 saw fire for the first time, wanted to kiss and hug it, but Prometheus warned him,

"Goat, you will definitely grieve your loss of beard."501

For fire burns whoever touches it, but it also gives light and warmth, and is an instrument of art to all those who know how to use it.502 Consider also in the case of the enemy, if he is in other respects injurious and intractable, he somehow or other gives us a handle to make use of him by, and so is serviceable. And many things are unpleasant and detestable and antagonistic to those to whom they happen, but you must have noticed that some use even illnesses as a period of rest for the body, and others by excessive toil have strengthened and trained their bodily vigour, and some have made exile and the loss of money a passage to leisure and philosophy, as did Diogenes and Crates. And Zeno, when he heard of the wreck of the ship which contained all his property, said, "Thou hast done well, Fortune, to confine me to my threadbare cloak."503

Fire burns anyone who touches it, but it also provides light and warmth and serves as a tool for those who know how to use it.502 Similarly, when it comes to an enemy, even if they are harmful and difficult in other ways, they somehow give us a way to make use of them, which can be helpful. Many things are unpleasant, detestable, and can oppose those who experience them, but you may have noticed that some people use illnesses as a chance to rest their bodies, while others have strengthened and trained their physical strength through hard work. Some have turned exile and financial loss into opportunities for leisure and philosophy, like Diogenes and Crates. And when Zeno learned about the shipwreck that lost all his possessions, he said, "Well done, Fortune, for confining me to my worn-out cloak."503

For as those animals that have the strongest and healthiest stomachs eat and digest serpents and scorpions, and some even feed on stones and shells, which they convert into nourishment by the strength and heat of their stomachs, while fastidious people out of health almost vomit if offered bread and wine, so foolish people spoil even their friendships, while the wise know how to turn to account even their enmities.

For just as the animals with the strongest and healthiest stomachs can eat and digest snakes and scorpions, and some even consume stones and shells, using the strength and heat of their stomachs to turn them into nourishment, while picky individuals nearly throw up at the thought of bread and wine, foolish people ruin even their friendships, while the wise know how to make the best of even their enemies.

§ iii. In the first place then it seems to me that what is most injurious in enmity may become most useful to those that pay attention to it? To what do I refer? Why, to the way in which your enemy ever wide awake pries into all your affairs, and analyzes your whole life, trying to get a handle against you somewhere, able not only to look through a tree, like Lynceus,504 or through stones and shells, 204but through your friend and domestic and every intimate acquaintance, as far as possible detecting your doings, and digging and ferreting into your designs. For our friends are ill and often die without our knowing anything about it through our delay and carelessness, but we almost pry into even the dreams of our enemies; and our enemy knows even more than we do ourselves of our diseases and debts and differences with our wives.505 But they pay most attention to our faults and hunt them out: and as vultures follow the scent of putrid carcases, and cannot perceive sound and wholesome ones, so the diseases and vices and crimes of life attract the enemy, and on these those that hate us pounce, these they attack and tear to pieces. Is not this an advantage to us? Certainly it is. For it teaches us to live warily and be on our guard, and neither to do or say anything carelessly or without circumspection, but ever to be vigilant by careful mode of living that we give no handle to an enemy. For the cautiousness that thus represses the passions and follows reason implants a care and determination to live well and without reproach. For as those states that have been sobered by wars with their neighbours and continual campaigns love the blessings of order and peace, so those people who are compelled to lead a sober life owing to their enemies, and to be on their guard against carelessness and negligence, and to do everything with an eye to utility, imperceptibly glide into a faultless mode of life, and tone down their character, even without requiring much assistance from precepts. For those who always remember the line,

§ iii. First of all, it seems to me that what is most harmful in enmity can also be quite useful for those who pay attention to it. What do I mean? Well, I’m talking about how your enemy is always alert, snooping into all your business and analyzing your entire life, looking for any weakness they can exploit. They can see through a tree, like Lynceus,504 or through stones and shells, 204 but they also scrutinize your friends and family, trying to uncover your activities, digging into your plans. Our friends often get sick or even die without us knowing because we delay or neglect to check in, yet we pry into even our enemies’ dreams; our enemies know more about our issues, debts, and marital problems than we do ourselves.505 They focus on our faults and are on the lookout for them: just like vultures track the scent of decaying bodies and can’t find healthy ones, so too do the flaws, vices, and crimes in our lives draw the attention of enemies, who leap at the chance to attack and tear us apart. Isn’t this an advantage for us? Absolutely. It teaches us to live cautiously and be on guard, never doing or saying anything carelessly or without thought, always staying vigilant through careful living to avoid giving our enemies any ammunition. The caution that restrains passions and follows reason instills a desire and determination to live well and without shame. Just as states that have been tempered by wars with their neighbors and constant battles value the blessings of order and peace, so too do people who are forced to live soberly because of their enemies, staying alert against carelessness and always acting with purpose, gradually slip into a faultless way of life, refining their character, often without needing much help from rules. For those who always remember the line,

"Ah! how happy Priam and his sons would be,"506

are by it diverted from and learn to shun all such things as their enemies would rejoice and laugh at. Again we see actors507 and singers on the stage oftentimes slack and remiss, and not taking sufficient pains about their performances in the theatres when they have it all to themselves; but when there is a competition and contest with 205others, they not only wake up but tune their instruments, and adjust their chords, and play on the flute with more care. Similarly whoever knows that his enemy is antagonistic to his life and character, pays more attention to himself, and watches his behaviour more carefully, and regulates his life. For it is peculiar to vice to be more afraid of enemies than friends in regard to our faults. And so Nasica, when some expressed their opinion that the Roman Republic was now secure, since Carthage was rased to the ground and Achaia reduced to slavery, said, "Nay rather we are now in a critical position, since we have none left to fear or respect."

are diverted from it and learn to avoid all those things that their enemies would celebrate and mock. Again, we see actors507 and singers on stage often being lazy and careless, not putting enough effort into their performances in theaters when they have the spotlight all to themselves; but when there’s competition and a contest with 205others, they not only perk up but also tune their instruments, adjust their chords, and play the flute with more attention. Similarly, anyone who knows that their enemy is a threat to their life and character pays more attention to themselves, monitors their behavior more closely, and regulates their life. For it is typical of vice to be more afraid of enemies than friends when it comes to our faults. And so, Nasica, when some argued that the Roman Republic was now safe because Carthage had been destroyed and Achaia had been subdued, said, "No, rather we are now in a dangerous position because we have no one left to fear or respect."

§ iv. Consider also that very philosophical and witty answer of Diogenes to the man who asked, "How shall I avenge myself on my enemy?" "By becoming a good and honest man."508 Some people are terribly put about if they see their enemies' horses in a good condition, or hear their dogs praised; if they see their farm well-tilled, their garden well-kept, they groan aloud. What a state think you then they would be in, if you were to exhibit yourself as a just man, sensible and good, in words excellent, in deeds pure, in manner of life decorous, "reaping fruit from the deep soil of the soul, where good counsels grow."509 Pindar says510 "those that are conquered are reduced to complete silence:" but not absolutely, not all men, only those that see they are outdone by their enemies in industry, in goodness, in magnanimity, in humanity, in kindnesses; these, as Demosthenes says, "stop the tongue, block up the mouth, choke people, and make them silent."511

§ iv. Also consider Diogenes' clever and philosophical reply to the man who asked, "How can I get back at my enemy?" He said, "By becoming a good and honest person."508 Some people get really upset when they see their enemies' horses looking good or hear their dogs getting compliments; when they notice their rival's farm is well-cultivated or their garden is nicely maintained, they groan loudly. Just imagine how they would react if you showed yourself to be a just person—wise, kind, with great words, pure actions, and a decent way of living, "reaping the rewards from the rich soil of the soul, where good thoughts flourish."509 Pindar says510 "those who are beaten are left completely speechless:" but not everyone, only those who realize they're being outperformed by their enemies in hard work, goodness, nobility, compassion, and kindness; these, as Demosthenes puts it, "silence the voice, shut the mouth, choke people, and render them mute."511

"Be better than the negative: it's within your control." __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

If you wish to vex the man who hates you, do not abuse him by calling him a pathick, or effeminate, or intemperate, or a low fellow, or illiberal; but be yourself a man, and temperate, and truthful, and kind and just in all your 206dealings with those you come across. But if you are tempted to use abuse, mind that you yourself are very far from what you abuse him for, dive down into your own soul, look for any rottenness in yourself, lest someone suggest to you the line of the tragedian,

If you want to annoy someone who dislikes you, don't insult him by calling him weak, or feminine, or reckless, or a low-life, or stingy; instead, be a man yourself, and be moderate, honest, kind, and fair in all your 206 dealings with everyone you encounter. But if you feel like insulting him, make sure you aren't guilty of the very things you're accusing him of—reflect on your own character, look for any flaws within yourself, so that no one can quote the line from the tragedian to you,

"You treat others, while you are sick yourself." 513

If you say your enemy is uneducated, increase your own love of learning and industry; if you call him coward, stir up the more your own spirit and manliness; and if you say he is wanton and licentious, erase from your own soul any secret trace of the love of pleasure. For nothing is more disgraceful or more unpleasant than slander that recoils on the person who sets it in motion; for as the reflection of light seems most to injure weak eyes, so does censure when it recoils on the censurer, and is borne out by the facts. For as the north-east wind attracts clouds, so does a bad life draw upon itself rebukes.

If you call your enemy uneducated, focus more on your own love of learning and hard work; if you label him a coward, boost your own courage and masculinity; and if you claim he’s reckless and immoral, eliminate any sneaky desire for pleasure from your own heart. Because nothing is more embarrassing or unpleasant than slander that bounces back on the person who instigated it; just like bright light can hurt weak eyes, criticism can sting when it comes back to the critic, especially when proven by the facts. Just as the northeast wind brings in clouds, a bad life invites its own criticisms.

§ v. Whenever Plato was in company with people who behaved in an unseemly manner, he used to say to himself, "Am I such a person as this?"514 So he that censures another man's life, if he straightway examines and mends his own, directing and turning it into the contrary direction, will get some advantage from his censure, which will be otherwise idle and unprofitable. Most people laugh if a bald-pate or hump-back jeer and mock at others who are so too: it is quite as ridiculous to jeer and mock if one lies open to retort oneself, as Leo of Byzantium showed in his answer to the hump-back who jeered at him for weakness of eyes, "You twit me with an infirmity natural to man, while you yourself carry your Nemesis on your back."515 And so do not abuse another as an adulterer, if you yourself are mad after boys: nor as a spendthrift, if you yourself are niggardly. Alcmæon said to Adrastus, "You are near kinsman to a woman that slew her husband." What 207was his reply? He retaliated on him with the appropriate retort, "But you killed with your own hand the mother that bare you."516 And Domitius said to Crassus, "Did you not weep for the lamprey that was bred in your fishpond, and died?" To which Crassus replied, "Did you weep, when you buried your three wives?" He therefore that intends to abuse others must not be witty and noisy and impudent, but a man that does not lie open to counter-abuse and retort, for the god seems to have enjoined upon no one the precept "Know thyself" so much as on the person who is censorious, to prevent people saying just what they please, and hearing what don't please them. For such a one is wont, as Sophocles517 says, "idly letting his tongue flow, to hear against his will, what he willingly says ill of others."

§ v. Whenever Plato was around people acting inappropriately, he would think to himself, "Am I like this?"514 So, if someone criticizes another person’s life but immediately looks at and improves their own, changing it for the better, they will gain something positive from their criticism, which would otherwise be pointless and unhelpful. Most people find it amusing when someone who's bald or hunchbacked mocks others who are similar; it’s just as foolish to mock when you’re in a position to be mocked yourself. Leo of Byzantium illustrated this when he responded to a hunchback who made fun of his poor eyesight, saying, "You mock me for a weakness that affects us all, while you carry your own misfortune on your back."515 Likewise, don’t insult someone as an adulterer if you yourself are infatuated with boys; nor as a wasteful spender if you’re greedy. Alcmæon told Adrastus, "You’re closely related to a woman who killed her husband." What was his reply? He shot back with a fitting response, "But you killed your own mother."516 And Domitius said to Crassus, "Didn’t you cry for the lamprey that was born in your pond and died?" Crassus replied, "Did you cry when you buried your three wives?" Therefore, anyone who plans to insult others shouldn’t be clever, loud, or brazen, but should be someone who isn’t vulnerable to counterattacks. It seems that no one has been given the advice "Know thyself" quite as much as the critic, to keep people from saying whatever they want and hearing what they don’t want to hear. Such a person tends to, as Sophocles517 puts it, "speak without restraint, only to hear against their will what they actively criticize in others."

§ vi. This use and advantage then there is in abusing one's enemy, and no less arises from being abused and ill-spoken of oneself by one's enemies. And so Antisthenes518 said well that those who wish to lead a good life ought to have genuine friends or red-hot enemies; for the former deterred you from what was wrong by reproof, the latter by abuse. But since friendship has nowadays become very mealy-mouthed in freedom of speech, voluble in flattery and silent in rebuke, we can only hear the truth from our enemies. For as Telephus519 having no surgeon of his own, submitted his wound to be cured by his enemy's spear, so those who cannot procure friendly rebuke must content themselves with the censure of an enemy that hates them, reprehending and castigating their vices, and regard not the animus of the person, but only his matter. For as he who intended to kill the Thessalian Prometheus520 208only stabbed a tumour, and so lanced it that the man's life was saved, and he was rid of the tumour by its bursting, so oftentimes abuse, suddenly thrust on a man in anger or hatred, has cured some disease in his soul which he was ignorant of or neglected. But most people when they are abused do not consider whether the abuse really belongs to them properly, but look round to see what abuse they can heap on the abuser, and, as wrestlers get smothered with the dust of the arena, do not wipe off the abuse hurled at themselves, but bespatter others, and at last get on both sides grimy and discoloured. But if anyone gets a bad name from an enemy, he ought to clear himself of the imputation even more than he would remove any stain on his clothes that was pointed out to him; and if it be wholly untrue, yet he ought to investigate what originated the charge, and to be on his guard and be afraid lest he had unawares done something very near akin to what was imputed to him. As Lacydes, the king of the Argives, by the way he wore his hair and by his mincing walk got charged with effeminacy: and Pompey's scratching his head with one finger was construed in the same way, though both these men were very far from effeminacy or wantonness. And Crassus was accused of an intrigue with one of the Vestal Virgins, because he wished to purchase from her a pleasant estate, and therefore frequently visited her and waited upon her. And Postumia, from her readiness to laugh and talk somewhat freely with men, got accused and even had to stand her trial for incest,521 but was, however, acquitted of that charge: but Spurius Minucius the Pontif ex Maximus, when he pronounced her innocent, urged her not to be freer in her words than she was in her life. And though Themistocles522 was guiltless of treason, his intimacy with Pausanias, and the letters and messages that frequently passed between them, laid him under suspicion.

§ vi. There's both use and benefit in turning the tables on your enemies, and the same comes from being insulted and slandered by them. As Antisthenes518 wisely said, those who want to live a good life should have true friends or fierce enemies; the former will discourage you from wrongdoing through honest critique, while the latter do it through insults. However, since friendships today have become overly polite, full of flattery, and lacking in honest feedback, we often hear the truth from our enemies. Just as Telephus519 had no surgeon, so he let his enemy's spear heal his wound, those who can't find supportive criticism must settle for a harsh judgment from those who dislike them, focusing on the content rather than the intent. Just like the person who intended to kill the Thessalian Prometheus520 accidentally hit a tumor, saving his life in the process, the harsh words thrown at someone in anger can sometimes reveal and cure an unseen flaw in their character. Yet, most people, when insulted, don’t reflect on whether the criticism is warranted. Instead, they look around for ways to retaliate, and like wrestlers in a dusty arena, they end up muddying themselves and others with insults. If someone earns a bad reputation from an enemy, they should strive to clear their name with more effort than they would use to clean a stain on their clothes; if the accusation is false, they should also explore what might have led to the claim, remaining cautious and aware that they may have done something similar without realizing it. For instance, Lacydes, the Argive king, was accused of being effeminate due to his hairstyle and delicate walk, and Pompey was similarly misinterpreted for scratching his head with one finger, even though neither was at all effeminate or lascivious. Crassus faced rumors of an affair with a Vestal Virgin simply because he wanted to buy a nice property from her and frequently visited her. Postumia was accused of incest for being chatty and friendly with men and had to stand trial, but was ultimately acquitted; however, Spurius Minucius the Pontifex Maximus urged her to maintain her modesty in speech as she had in her actions. Lastly, though Themistocles522 was innocent of treason, his close relationship with Pausanias and their frequent correspondence put him under suspicion.

§ vii. Whenever therefore any false charge is made against us, we ought not merely to despise and neglect it as false, but to see what word or action, either in jest or earnest, has made the charge seem probable, and this we 209must for the future be earnestly on our guard against and shun. For if others falling into unforeseen trouble and difficulties teach us what is expedient, as Merope says,

§ vii. So whenever someone makes a false accusation against us, we shouldn't just dismiss it as untrue, but should consider what we said or did, whether in jest or seriousness, that might have made the accusation seem credible. This we 209 must be careful about and avoid in the future. Because if we learn from others who encounter unexpected troubles and challenges, as Merope says,

"Fortune has made me wise, though she has taken" My dear ones as wages, "__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

why should we not take an enemy, and pay him no wages, to teach us, and give us profit and instruction, in matters which had escaped our notice? For an enemy has keener perception than a friend, for, as Plato524 says, "the lover is blind as respects the loved one," and hatred is both curious and talkative. Hiero was twitted by one of his enemies for his foul breath, so he went home and said to his wife, "How is this? You never told me of it." But she being chaste and innocent replied, "I thought all men's breath was like that."525 Thus perceptible and material things, and things that are plain to everybody, are sooner learnt from enemies than from friends and intimates.

Why shouldn't we use an enemy, without having to pay them, to teach us and give us insights into things we might have overlooked? An enemy often sees things more clearly than a friend, because, as Plato524 says, "the lover is blind to the faults of the loved one," while hatred is both inquisitive and outspoken. Hiero was ridiculed by one of his enemies for having bad breath, so he went home and asked his wife, "Why didn't you ever tell me about this?" She, being pure and innocent, replied, "I thought all men's breath was like that."525 Therefore, obvious and tangible issues are often recognized more quickly through enemies than through friends and close ones.

§ viii. Moreover to keep the tongue well under control, no small factor in moral excellence, and to make it always obedient and submissive to reason, is not possible, unless by practice and attention and painstaking a man has subdued his worst passions, as for example anger. For such expressions as "a word uttered involuntarily," and "escaping the barrier of the teeth,"526 and "words darting forth spontaneously," well illustrate what happens in the case of ill-disciplined souls, ever wavering and in an unsettled condition through infirmity of temper, through unbridled fancy, or through faulty education. But, according to divine Plato,527 though a word seems a very trivial matter, the heaviest penalty follows upon it both from gods and men. But silence can never be called to account, is not only not thirsty, to borrow the language of Hippocrates, but when abused is dignified and Socratic, or rather Herculean, if indeed it was Hercules who said,

§ viii. Additionally, keeping the tongue well in check, which is crucial for moral excellence, and ensuring it always obeys and submits to reason, is impossible unless a person practices and diligently works to tame their worst impulses, like anger. Phrases like "a word spoken unintentionally" and "breaking past the barrier of the teeth,"526 and "words shooting out spontaneously," vividly illustrate what happens with undisciplined souls, who are constantly unstable and unsettled due to a weak temper, unrestrained imagination, or poor education. However, according to the wise Plato,527 even though a word may seem insignificant, it can lead to serious consequences from both the gods and other people. But silence can never be judged; it is not only "unquenchable," borrowing Hippocrates' phrase, but when misused, it carries a tone of dignity that is both Socratic and, more fittingly, Herculean, if indeed it was Hercules who said,

"He paid as little attention to sharp words as he would to flies." 528

210Not more dignified and noble than this is it to keep silent when an enemy reviles you, "as one swims by a smooth and mocking cliff," but in practice it is better. If you accustom yourself to bear silently the abuse of an enemy, you will very easily bear the attack of a scolding wife, and will remain undisturbed when you hear the sharp language of a friend or brother, and will be calm and placid when you are beaten or have something thrown at your head by your father or mother. For Socrates put up with Xanthippe, a passionate and forward woman, which made him a more easy companion with others, as being accustomed to submit to her caprices; and it is far better to train and accustom the temper to bear quietly the insults and rages and jeers and taunts of enemies and estranged persons, and not to be distressed at it.

210There’s nothing more dignified and noble than staying silent when someone insults you, "like someone swimming past a smooth and mocking cliff," but in reality, it’s more effective. If you train yourself to quietly endure the insults of an enemy, you’ll find it much easier to handle the complaints of a nagging partner, you’ll stay unaffected by harsh words from friends or family, and you’ll remain calm even if your parents scold you or throw things at you. Socrates tolerated Xanthippe, a passionate and outspoken woman, which helped him become easier to get along with others, as he was used to putting up with her mood swings. It’s much better to teach and condition yourself to calmly accept the insults, rages, jeers, and taunts from enemies and those who are estranged, so you aren’t disturbed by it.

§ ix. Thus then must we exhibit in our enmities meekness and forbearance, and in our friendships still more simplicity and magnanimity and kindness. For it is not so graceful to do a friend a service, as disgraceful to refuse to do so at his request; and not to revenge oneself on an enemy when opportunity offers is generous. But the man who sympathizes with his enemy in affliction, and assists him in distress, and readily holds out a helping hand to his children and family and their fortunes when in a low condition, whoever does not admire such a man for his humanity, and praise his benevolence,

§ ix. So, we should show humility and patience in our conflicts, and even more honesty, generosity, and kindness in our friendships. It's not as honorable to do a favor for a friend as it is disgraceful to refuse their request. Also, not seeking revenge against an enemy when the chance arises is a sign of generosity. But the person who feels compassion for their enemy in tough times, helps them when they’re in trouble, and offers support to their family when they’re down – who wouldn’t admire such a person for their kindness and commend their goodwill?

"He has a black heart made of unbreakable material." Or iron or bronze.529

When Cæsar ordered the statues of Pompey that had been thrown down to be put up again,530 Cicero said, "You have set up again Pompey's statues, and in so doing have erected statues to yourself." We ought not therefore to be niggardly in our praise and honour of an enemy that deserves a good name. For he who praises another receives on that account greater praise himself, and is the more credited on another occasion when he finds fault, as not having any personal ill-feeling against the man, but only 211disapproving of his act; and what is most noble and advantageous, the man who is accustomed to praise his enemies, and not to be vexed or malignant at their prosperity, is as far as possible from envying the good fortune of his friends, and the success of his intimates. And yet what practice will be more beneficial to our minds, or bring about a happier disposition, than that which banishes from us all jealousy and envy? For as in war many necessary things, otherwise bad, are customary and have as it were the sanction of law, so that they cannot be abolished in spite of the injury they do, so enmity drags along in its train hatred, and envy, and jealousy, and malignity, and revenge, and stamps them on the character. Moreover knavery, and deceit, and villainy, that seem neither bad nor unfair if employed against an enemy, if they once get planted in the mind are difficult to dislodge; and eventually from force of habit get used also against friends, unless they are forewarned and forearmed through their previous acquaintance with the tricks of enemies. If then Pythagoras,531 accustoming his disciples to abstain from all cruelty and inhumanity to the brute creation, did right to discountenance bird-fowling, and to buy up draughts of fishes and bid them be thrown into the water again, and to forbid killing any but wild animals, much more noble is it, in dissensions and differences with human beings, to be a generous, just and true enemy, and to check and tame all bad and low and knavish propensities, that in all intercourse with friends a man may keep the peace and abstain from doing an injury. Scaurus was an enemy and accuser of Domitius, but when one of Domitius' slaves came to him to reveal some important matters which were unknown to Scaurus, he would not hear him, but seized him and sent him back to his master. And when Cato was prosecuting Murena for canvassing, and was getting together his evidence, he was accompanied as was usual by people who watched what he was doing,532 and would often ask him if he intended that day to get together his witnesses and open the case, and if he said "No," they believed him and went 212their way. All this is the greatest proof of the credit which was reposed in Cato, but it is better and more important, that we should accustom ourselves to deal justly even with our enemies, and then there will be no fear that we should ever act unjustly and treacherously to our friends and intimates.

When Caesar ordered the statues of Pompey that had been knocked down to be put back up,530 Cicero remarked, "You have restored Pompey's statues, and in doing so, you've effectively built statues to yourself." We shouldn't be too eager in our praise and honor of an enemy who deserves a good reputation. Someone who praises another gains greater recognition themselves and is more respected when they criticize later, as it's clear they hold no personal grudge against the person, only disapproval of their actions; and what's most admirable and beneficial is that a person who is used to praising their enemies, rather than being resentful or hateful toward their success, is less likely to feel envy towards the good fortune of their friends and the achievements of those close to them. And what practice could be more advantageous for our minds, or create a more positive attitude than one that eliminates all jealousy and envy? Just as many things that are otherwise considered wrong become accepted in war and are somewhat legitimized, so too does enmity bring along feelings of hatred, envy, jealousy, malice, and a desire for revenge, marking their presence on a person's character. Furthermore, dishonesty, deceit, and wrongdoing that may seem justified when directed at an enemy, once ingrained in a person’s mind, are hard to remove; and eventually, out of habit, these tendencies will also be directed toward friends unless they are forewarned and aware of the tricks used by enemies. Therefore, if Pythagoras,531 trained his students to avoid all cruelty toward animals, rightfully condemning bird-catching and purchasing fish to return them to the water, and allowing the killing only of wild animals, then it is even more honorable, in conflicts and disagreements with humans, to be a fair, just, and honest adversary, and to suppress all low and deceitful impulses, so that in all interactions with friends, one can maintain peace and avoid causing harm. Scaurus was an enemy and accuser of Domitius, but when one of Domitius's slaves came to him to disclose important information that Scaurus didn't know, he refused to listen and sent the slave back to his master. When Cato was prosecuting Murena for electioneering and was gathering evidence, he was usually followed by people observing his actions,532 who often asked if he intended to gather his witnesses and present the case that day; if he replied "No," they believed him and went on their way. All of this demonstrates the great trust placed in Cato, but it is even more crucial that we train ourselves to act justly towards our enemies, ensuring that we have no fear of acting unjustly and treacherously towards our friends and close associates.

§ x. But since, as Simonides says, "all larks must have their crests,"533 and every man's nature contains in it pugnacity and jealousy and envy, which last is, as Pindar says, "the companion of empty-headed men," one might get considerable advantage by purging oneself of those passions against enemies, and by diverting them, like sewers, as far as possible from companions and friends.534 And this it seems the statesmanlike Onomademus had remarked, for being on the victorious side in a disturbance at Chios, he urged his party not to expel all of the different faction, but to leave some, "in order," he said, "that we may not begin to quarrel with our friends, when we have got entirely rid of our enemies." So too our expending these passions entirely on our enemies will give less trouble to our friends. For it ought not to be, as Hesiod535 says, that "potter envies potter, and singer envies singer, and neighbour neighbour," and cousin cousin, and brother brother, "if hastening to get rich" and enjoying prosperity. But if there is no other way to get rid of strife and envy and quarrels, accustom yourself to be vexed at your enemies' good fortune, and sharpen and accentuate on them your acerbity. For as judicious gardeners think they produce finer roses and violets by planting alongside of them garlic and onions, that any bitter or strong elements may be transferred to them, so your enemy's getting and attracting your envy and malignity will render you kinder and more agreeable to your prosperous friends. And so let us be rivals of our enemies for glory or office or righteous gain, not only being vexed if they get ahead of us, but also carefully observing all the steps by which they get ahead, and trying to outdo 213them in industry, and hard work, and soberness, and prudence; as Themistocles said Miltiades' victory at Marathon would not let him sleep.536 For he who thinks his enemy gets before him in offices, or advocacies, or state affairs, or in favour with his friends or great men, if from action and emulation he sinks into envy and despondency, makes his life become idle and inoperative. But he who is not blinded by hate,537 but a discerning spectator of life and character and words and deeds, will perceive that most of what he envies comes to those who have them from diligence and prudence and good actions, and exerting himself in the same direction he will increase his love of what is honourable and noble, and will eradicate his vanity and sloth.

§ x. But as Simonides says, "all larks must have their crests,"533 every person has within them a tendency towards aggression, jealousy, and envy. Pindar notes that envy is "the companion of empty-headed men." Therefore, one can gain a lot by freeing oneself from these feelings towards enemies and redirecting them, like sewage, as far away as possible from friends and companions.534 It seems that Onomademus, a wise statesman, recognized this when he was on the winning side during a conflict in Chios. He advised his group not to expel all members of the opposing faction but to leave some behind, saying, "so that we don’t end up quarreling with our friends after getting rid of our enemies." By directing these negative feelings only at our enemies, we will cause less trouble for our friends. As Hesiod535 points out, it shouldn't be the case that "potter envies potter, and singer envies singer, and neighbor envies neighbor," and cousin envies cousin, and brother envies brother, "if they are rushing to get rich" and enjoying prosperity. But if there’s no other way to eliminate strife, envy, and arguments, train yourself to feel annoyed by your enemies’ good fortune and sharpen your bitterness towards them. Just as skilled gardeners believe that planting garlic and onions alongside roses and violets produces finer blooms by transferring any bitter qualities, allowing your envy and resentment to focus on your enemies will make you kinder and more pleasant to your successful friends. So let’s compete with our enemies for glory, position, or rightful gain, not just feeling irritated if they succeed, but also closely watching how they get ahead and striving to outwork them with diligence, effort, and prudence—like Themistocles said, Miltiades' victory at Marathon kept him from sleeping.536 Those who think their enemy is advancing in jobs, influence, or favor with friends or powerful people, and allow themselves to fall into envy and despair from striving and competition, will lead idle and unproductive lives. In contrast, those who aren’t blinded by hatred,537 but rather are keen observers of life, character, words, and actions, will realize that most of what they envy is gained through hard work, diligence, and good deeds. By emulating those successful traits, they will foster their appreciation for what is honorable and noble while eliminating their own vanity and laziness.

§ xi. But if our enemies seem to us to have got either by flattery, or fraud, or bribery, or venal services, ill-got and discreditable power at court or in state, it ought not to trouble us but rather inspire pleasure in us, when we compare our own liberty and purity and independence of life. For, as Plato538 says, "all the gold above or below the earth is not of equal value with virtue." And we ought ever to remember the precept of Solon, "We will not exchange our virtue for others' wealth."539 Nor will we give up our virtue for the applause of banqueting theatres, nor for honours and chief seats among eunuchs and harlots, nor to be monarchs' satraps; for nothing is to be desired or noble that comes from what is bad. But since, as Plato540 says, "the lover is blind as respects the loved one," and we notice more what our enemies do amiss, we ought not to let either our joy at their faults or our grief at their success be idle, but in either case we ought to reflect, how we may become better than them by avoiding their errors, and by imitating their virtues not come short of them.

§ xi. If it seems to us that our enemies have gained their power through flattery, deceit, bribery, or corrupt services—power that is undeserved and disreputable in court or politics—it shouldn’t trouble us. Instead, it should bring us joy when we compare it to our own freedom, integrity, and independence. As Plato538 states, "no amount of gold, whether above or below the earth, holds the same value as virtue." We should always remember Solon’s principle, "We will not trade our virtue for someone else's wealth."539 We won’t sacrifice our virtue for the praise of feasting halls, nor for titles and prime seats among eunuchs and courtesans, nor to become the rulers' subordinates; nothing that comes from something corrupt is worthy or admirable. However, since, as Plato540 points out, "the lover is blind to their beloved’s flaws," and we are more aware of our enemies' mistakes, we shouldn’t let our joy in their failures or our sadness at their success go to waste. Instead, in both situations, we should consider how we can rise above them by avoiding their mistakes and emulating their virtues, aiming to not fall short of them.

497 So Pliny, viii. 83: "In Creta Insula non vulpes ursive, atque omnino millum maleficum animal præter phalangium."

497 So Pliny, viii. 83: "On the island of Crete, there are no running foxes or any other harmful animal except for the rat."

498 See the same remark of Chilo, "On Abundance of Friends," § vi.

498 Check out the same comment by Chilo, "On Having Plenty of Friends," § vi.

499 "Œconom." i. 15.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Econ." p. 15.

500 A treatise of Plutarch still extant.

A surviving work by Plutarch.

501 A line from a lost Satyric Play of Æschylus, called "Prometheus Purphoros."

501 A line from a lost Satyric play by Æschylus, titled "Prometheus Purphoros."

502 So fire is called πάντεχνον in Æschylus, "Prometheus Desmotes," 7.

502 So fire is called "all-powerful" in Æschylus, "Prometheus Bound," 7.

503 Compare Seneca, "De Animi Tranquillitate," cap. xiii.: "Zeno noster cum omnia sua audiret submersa, Jubet, inquit, me fortuna expeditius philosophari."

503 Compare Seneca, "De Animi Tranquillitate," cap. xiii.: "Our Zeno, when he saw everything he had submerged, said, 'Fortune is prompting me to think more clearly.'"

504 See Horace, "Epistles," i. I. 28; Pausanias, iv. 2.

504 See Horace, "Epistles," i. I. 28; Pausanias, iv. 2.

505 See Plautus, "Trinummus," 205-211.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Plautus, "Trinummus," 205-211.

506 Homer, "Iliad," i. 255.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," Book 1, line 255.

507 Literally "the artists of Dionysus." We know what they were from our author's "Quæstiones Romanæ," § 107: διὰ τί τοὺς περὶ τὸν Διόνυσον τεχνίτας ἱστρίωνας ῾Ρωμαῖοι καλοῦσιν;

507 Literally "the artists of Dionysus." We know what they were from our author's "Quæstiones Romanæ," § 107: διὰ τί τοὺς περὶ τὸν Διόνυσον τεχνίτας ἱστρίωνας ῾Ρωμαῖοι καλοῦσιν;

508 Compare "De Audiendis Poetis," § iv.

508 Compare "De Audiendis Poetis," § iv.

509 Æschylus, "Septem contra Thebas," 593, 594.

509 Aeschylus, "Seven Against Thebes," 593, 594.

510 Pindar, "Fragm." 253.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Pindar, "Fragment." 253.

511 Demosthenes, "De Falsa Legatione," p. 406.

511 Demosthenes, "On the False Embassy," p. 406.

512 Euripides, "Orestes," 251.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Orestes," 251.

513 A line from Euripides. Quoted also "De Adulatore et Amico," § xxxii.

513 A line from Euripides. Also quoted in "De Adulatore et Amico," § xxxii.

514 Compare "De Audiendo," §vi. See also Horace, "Satires," i, 4. 136, 137.

514 See "De Audiendo," §vi. Also check Horace, "Satires," i, 4. 136, 137.

515 The story is somewhat differently told, "Quæst. Conviv.," Lib. ii. § ix.

515 The story is told a bit differently in "Questions at the Banquet," Book II, § ix.

516 From a lost play of Euripides.

516 From a lost play by Euripides.

517 In some lost play. Compare Hesiod, "Works and Days," 719-721; Terence, "Andria," 920.

517 In some missing play. See Hesiod, "Works and Days," 719-721; Terence, "Andria," 920.

518 The sentiment is assigned to Diogenes twice elsewhere by our author, namely, "How One may be aware of one's Progress in Virtue," § xi., and "How One may discern a Flatterer from a Friend," § xxxvi.

518 The sentiment is attributed to Diogenes two more times by our author, specifically, "How to Know Your Progress in Virtue," § xi., and "How to Tell a Flatterer from a Friend," § xxxvi.

519 See Propertius, ii. 1. 63, 64; Ovid, "Metamorphoses," xii. 112; xiii. 171; "Tristia," v. 2. 15, 16; "Remedia Amoris," 47, 48; Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 221.

519 See Propertius, ii. 1. 63, 64; Ovid, "Metamorphoses," xii. 112; xiii. 171; "Tristia," v. 2. 15, 16; "Remedia Amoris," 47, 48; Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 221.

520 "Jason Pheræus cognomine Prometheus dictus est. Vide Ciceronem, 'Nat. Deor.' iii. 29; Plinium, vii. 51; Valerium Maximum, i. 8, Extem. 6."—Wytttenbach.

520 "Jason, known as Pheræus and also called Prometheus. See Cicero, 'Nat. Deor.' iii. 29; Pliny, vii. 51; Valerius Maximus, i. 8, Extern. 6."—Wytttenbach.

521 She was a Vestal Virgin. See Livy, iv. 44.

521 She was a Vestal Virgin. See Livy, iv. 44.

522 See Thucydides, i. 135, 136.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Thucydides, i. 135, 136.

523 From a lost play of Euripides. Compare the proverb, παθήματα μαθήματα.

523 From a lost play by Euripides. Compare the saying, πάθημα μαθήματα.

524 "Laws," v. p. 731 E.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Laws," v. p. 731 E.

525 Told again "Reg. et Imperator. Apophthegm.," p. 175 B.

525 Told again "Reg. et Imperator. Apophthegm.," p. 175 B.

526 A favourite image of Homer, employed "Iliad," iv. 350; xiv. 83; "Odyssey," i. 64; xxiii. 70.

526 A favorite image of Homer, used in "Iliad," iv. 350; xiv. 83; "Odyssey," i. 64; xxiii. 70.

527 "Laws," xi. p. 935 A. Quoted again "On Talkativeness," § vii.

527 "Laws," xi. p. 935 A. Quoted again "On Talkativeness," § vii.

528 See Pausanias, v. 14.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Check Pausanias, v. 14.

529 From a Fragment of Pindar.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ From a piece by Pindar.

530 See Suetonius, "Divus Julius," 75: "Sed et statuas L. Sullæ atque Pompeii a plebe disjectas reposuit."

530 See Suetonius, "Divus Julius," 75: "But he also restored the statues of L. Sulla and Pompey that had been destroyed by the public."

531 Compare our author, "Quaestiones Convivalium," viii. p. 729 E.

531 Check out our author, "Questions of the Banquet," viii. p. 729 E.

532 No doubt in the interest of the defendant. See our author, "Cato Minor," p. 769 B.

532 Clearly in the interest of the defendant. See our author, "Cato Minor," p. 769 B.

533 A Greek proverb, see Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 921.

533 A Greek saying, see Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 921.

534 So Cicero, "Nat. Deor." ii. 56: "In ædibus architecti avertunt ab oculis naribusque dominorum ea quæ profluentia necessario tætri essent aliquid habitura."

534 So Cicero, "Nat. Deor." ii. 56: "In the houses, architects hide from the eyes and noses of the owners things that would necessarily be unpleasant."

535 "Works and Days," 23-26. Our "Two of a trade seldom agree."

535 "Works and Days," 23-26. "People in the same profession rarely get along."

536 Compare "How One may be aware of one's Progress in Virtue," § xiv.

536 Check out "How One Can Recognize Their Progress in Virtue," § xiv.

537 For as the English proverb says, "Hatred is blind as well as love."

537 As the English saying goes, "Hatred is just as blind as love."

538 "Laws," v. p. 728 A.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Laws," p. 728 A.

539 Quoted more fully "How One may be aware of one's Progress in Virtue," § vi.

539 Quoted in full: "How One Can Recognize Their Progress in Virtue," § vi.

540 "Laws," v. p. 731 E. See also above, § vii.

540 "Laws," v. p. 731 E. See also above, § vii.


ON TALKATIVENESS.541

§ i. Philosophy finds talkativeness a disease very difficult and hard to cure. For its remedy, conversation, requires hearers: but talkative people hear nobody, for they are ever prating. And the first evil this inability to keep silence produces is an inability to listen. It is a self-chosen deafness of people who, I take it, blame nature for giving us one tongue and two ears. If then the following advice of Euripides to a foolish hearer was good,

§ i. Philosophy sees talkativeness as a tough disease to cure. The solution, conversation, needs listeners: but talkative people don’t really listen because they’re always talking. The first issue caused by their inability to stay quiet is that they can’t listen. It’s a self-imposed deafness among those who, I think, complain about nature giving us one mouth and two ears. If the following advice from Euripides to a foolish listener was sound,

"I can't fill one that can't hold anything," "Encouraging wisdom in an unwise person;"

one might more justly say to a talkative man, or rather about a talkative man,

one might more accurately say about a chatty person,

"I can't fill one that won't take anything, "Pumping up smart advice for a foolish person;"

or rather deluging with words one that talks to those who don't listen, and listens not to those who talk. Even if he does listen for a short time, talkativeness hurries off what is said like the retiring sea, and anon brings it up again multiplied with the approaching tide. The portico at Olympia that returns many echoes to one utterance is called seven-voiced,542 and if the slightest utterance catches the ear of talkativeness, it at once echoes it all round,

or rather drowning in words someone who talks to those who don’t listen, and doesn’t pay attention to those who do talk. Even if he listens for a little while, his excessive talking rushes away what was said like the retreating sea, and soon brings it back, multiplied with the incoming tide. The portico at Olympia that reflects many echoes from one sound is called seven-voiced,542 and if the slightest remark grabs the attention of talkativeness, it immediately echoes everywhere.

"Shifting the mind's connections that remained untouched before." 543

For their ears can certainly have no passages leading to the brain but only to the tongue. And so while other people retain what they hear, talkative people lose it altogether, and, being empty-headed, they resemble empty vessels, and go about making much noise.544

For their ears definitely don’t connect to the brain but only to the tongue. So while most people remember what they hear, chatty people forget it entirely, and being air-headed, they’re like empty containers, just making a lot of noise.544

215§ ii. If however it seems that no attempt at cure has been left untried, let us say to the talkative person,

215§ ii. If it appears that every possible effort to fix the situation has been made, let's talk to the person who can't stop talking,

"Be quiet, kid; staying silent has many benefits;"

two of the first and foremost of which are hearing and being heard, neither of which can happen to talkative people, for however they desire either so unhappy are they that they must desist from it. For in all other diseases of the soul, as love of money, love of glory, or love of pleasure, people at any rate attain the desired object: but it is the cruel fate of talkative people to desire hearers but not to get them, for everyone flees from them with headlong speed; and if people are sitting or walking about in any public place,545 and see one coming they quickly pass the word to one another to shift quarters. And as when there is dead silence in any assembly they say Hermes has joined the company, so when any prater joins some drinking party or social gathering of friends, all are silent, not wishing to give him a chance to break in, and if he uninvited begin to open his mouth, they all, "like before a storm at sea, when Boreas is blowing a gale round some headland," foreseeing tossing about and nausea, disperse. And so it is their destiny to find neither willing table-companions, nor messmates when they are travelling by land or by sea, but only such as cannot help themselves; for such a fellow is always at you, plucking hold of your clothes or chin, or giving you a dig in the ribs with his elbow. "Most valuable are the feet in such a conjuncture," according to Archilochus, nay according to the wise Aristotle himself. For he being bothered with a talkative fellow, and wearied out with his absurd tales, and his frequent question, "Is not this wonderful, Aristotle?" "Not at all," said he, "but it is wonderful that anyone with a pair of legs stops here to listen to you." And to another such fellow, who said after a long rigmarole, "Did I weary you, philosopher, by my chatter?" "Not you, by Zeus," said he, "for I paid no attention to you." For 216even if talkative people force you to listen,546 the mind can give them only its outward ears to deluge, while it unfolds and pursues some other thoughts within; so they find neither hearers to attend to them, nor credit them. They say those that are prone to Venus are commonly barren: so the prating of talkative people is ineffectual and fruitless.

Two of the most important things are hearing and being heard, which talkative people can't experience. No matter how much they want it, they always end up unable to achieve it. In other matters of the soul, like the love of money, fame, or pleasure, people manage to get what they want. But for talkative individuals, it's a cruel fate; they seek listeners but can’t find any, as everyone rushes away from them. If people are gathered in a public space, and see one of these chatterers coming, they quickly warn each other to change places. Just like in an assembly where there’s suddenly a deep silence and people say Hermes has shown up, when a chatterbox joins a social gathering, everyone goes quiet, not wanting to give them a chance to speak up. If the talker begins to speak uninvited, the others disperse quickly, like people before a storm at sea, knowing they’ll face turbulence and discomfort. This is why they struggle to find companions at mealtime or travel, only attracting those who have no choice. Such a person will always be grabbing your clothes, pinching your chin, or poking you in the ribs with their elbow. "Feet are most valuable in such a situation," as Archilochus said, and even Aristotle himself would agree. Once bothered by a chatty person and annoyed by their ridiculous stories, when asked, "Isn't this amazing, Aristotle?" he replied, "Not at all; it's remarkable that anyone with legs stops to listen to you." To another such person, who after a long ramble asked, "Did I tire you out with my talk, philosopher?" Aristotle answered, "Not you, by Zeus, because I wasn’t paying attention." Even if talkative people force you to listen, your mind can only lend them its outer ears while thinking about something else entirely. So they find neither listeners who truly pay attention nor anyone who believes them. It's said that those who indulge in romantic pursuits often end up unfulfilled; similarly, the ramblings of talkative people are ineffective and pointless.

§ iii. And yet nature has fenced and barricaded in us nothing so much as the tongue, having put the teeth before it as a barrier, so that if, when reason holds tight her "glossy reins,"547 it hearken not, nor keep within bounds, we may check its intemperance, biting it till the blood comes. For Euripides tells us that, not from unbolted houses or store-rooms, but "from unbridled mouths the end is misfortune."548 But those persons who think that houses without doors and open purses are no good to their possessors, and yet keep their mouths open and unshut, and allow their speech to flow continually like the waves of the Euxine,549 seem to regard speech as of less value than anything. And so they never get believed, though credit is the aim of every speech; for to inspire belief in one's hearers is the proper end of speech, but praters are disbelieved even when they tell the truth. For as corn stowed away in a granary is found to be larger in quantity but inferior in quality, so the speech of a talkative man is increased by a large addition of falsehood, which destroys his credit.

§ iii. Yet nature has really protected us with our tongues, placing our teeth as a barrier in front of them. This way, if our reason isn’t in control of our words, we can rein in our excessive speech by biting our tongues until it bleeds. Euripides tells us that misfortune doesn't come from unlocked houses or storage rooms, but "from unbridled mouths." Those who believe that homes without doors and open wallets do no good still keep their mouths wide open, letting their words spill out endlessly like waves of the Euxine. They seem to treat speech as less valuable than anything else. Consequently, they’re not trusted, even though gaining trust is the goal of any speech; the real purpose of speaking is to inspire belief in the listeners, but ramblers are doubted even when they speak the truth. Just as grain stored in a granary is found in greater amounts but of lower quality, the talkative person's speech is filled with a lot of untruths, which ruins their credibility.

§ iv. Then again every man of modesty and propriety would avoid drunkenness, for anger is next door neighbour to madness as some think,550 but drunkenness lives in the same house: or rather drunkenness is madness, more short-lived indeed, but more potent also through volition, for it is self-chosen. Nor is drunkenness censured for anything so much as its intemperate and endless talk.

§ iv. Again, any man with modesty and decency would steer clear of drunkenness, because anger is thought by some to be close to madness,550 but drunkenness actually resides in the same house: or rather, drunkenness is a form of madness, shorter in duration but also more intense because it's a choice. Drunkenness is criticized mainly for the excessive and endless talking that comes with it.

"Wine makes a sensible person start to sing, And softly laugh, and even makes him dance."551

And yet there is no harm in all this, in singing and laughing and dancing. But the poet adds—

And yet there's nothing wrong with all of this, with singing and laughing and dancing. But the poet adds—

"And it makes you say what’s better left unsaid." __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

This is indeed dreadful and dangerous. And perhaps the poet in this passage has solved that problem of the philosophers, and stated the difference between being under the influence of wine and being drunk, mirth being the condition of the former, foolish talk of the latter. For as the proverb tells us, "What is in the heart of the sober is on the tongue of the drunken."553 And so Bias, being silent at a drinking bout, and jeered at by some young man in the company as stupid, replied, "What fool could hold his tongue in liquor?" And at Athens a certain person gave an entertainment to the king's ambassadors, and at their desire contrived to get the philosophers there too, and as they were all talking together and comparing ideas, and Zeno alone was silent, the strangers greeted him and pledged him, and said, "What are we to tell the king about you, Zeno?" And he replied, "Nothing, but that there is an old man at Athens that can hold his tongue at a drinking bout." So profound and mysterious and sober is silence, while drunkenness is talkative: for it is void of sense and understanding, and so is loquacious. And so the philosophers define drunkenness to be silly talk in wine. Drinking therefore is not censured, if silence go with it, but foolish prating turns being under the influence of wine into drunkenness. And the drunken man prates only in his cups; but the talkative man prates everywhere, in the market-place, in the theatre, out walking, by night and by day. If he is your doctor, he is more trouble to you than your disease: if he is on board ship with you, he disgusts you more than sea-sickness; if he praises you, he is more fulsome than blame. It is more pleasure associating with bad men who have tact than with good men who prate. 218Nestor indeed in Sophocles' Play, trying by his words to soothe exasperated Ajax, said to him mildly,

This is truly terrible and risky. The poet in this passage might have figured out the philosophers' dilemma, explaining the difference between being tipsy and being drunk, with the former being lighthearted and the latter leading to silly chatter. As the saying goes, "What’s in the heart of the sober is on the tongue of the drunk." 553 Bias, remaining quiet at a drinking party and being mocked by a young man for being dull, responded, "What fool can keep quiet when he’s had some drinks?" In Athens, someone hosted a gathering for the king's ambassadors and, at their request, invited the philosophers as well. While everyone was chatting and exchanging ideas, only Zeno stayed silent. The guests acknowledged him and raised a toast, asking, "What should we tell the king about you, Zeno?" He replied, "Just that there’s an old man in Athens who can stay quiet at a drinking party." Silence is so deep, mysterious, and sober, while drunkenness brings mindless chatter. Philosophers define drunkenness as meaningless talk while drinking. Thus, drinking isn’t criticized if it’s accompanied by silence, but aimless babbling turns being tipsy into drunkenness. The drunk only babbles when he’s drinking; the talkative person chats everywhere—in the market, at the theater, during walks, day and night. If he’s your doctor, he’s more of a nuisance than your illness; if he’s on a ship with you, he’s more annoying than seasickness; when he praises you, it’s more excessive than criticism. Associating with skilled bad people is more enjoyable than being around good people who yap. 218 Nestor, trying to calm the irritated Ajax in Sophocles' Play, spoke to him gently,

"I don't blame you, because even though your words are harsh, Your actions are good.

but we cannot feel so to the talkative man, for his want of tact in words destroys and undoes all the grace of his actions.

but we can’t feel the same about the talkative person, because their lack of tact in speech ruins and undermines all the elegance of their actions.

§ v. Lysias wrote a defence for some accused person, and gave it him, and he read it several times, and came to Lysias in great dejection and said, "When I first perused this defence, it seemed to me wonderful, but when I read it a second and third time, it seemed altogether dull and ineffective. Then Lysias laughed, and said, "What then? Are you going to read it more than once to the jury?" And yet do but consider the persuasiveness and grace of Lysias' style;554 for he "I say was a great favourite with the dark-haired Muses."555 And of the things which have been said of Homer the truest is that he alone of all poets has survived the fastidiousness of mankind, as being ever new and still at his acme as regards giving pleasure, and yet saying and proclaiming about himself, "I hate to spin out a plain tale over and over again,"556 he avoids and fears that satiety which lies in ambush for every narrative, and takes the hearer from one subject to another, and relieves by novelty the possibility of being surfeited. But the talkative worry one's ears to death with their tautologies, as people scribble the same things over and over again on palimpsests.557

§ v. Lysias wrote a defense for someone accused and gave it to him. He read it several times and returned to Lysias feeling very down, saying, "The first time I read this defense, it seemed amazing, but after I read it a second and third time, it felt completely dull and ineffective." Lysias laughed and replied, "So, are you planning to read it to the jury more than once?" You have to admire the persuasive and elegant style of Lysias; 554 he truly was a favorite of the dark-haired Muses.555 As for Homer, it’s been said that he is the only poet who has withstood people’s picky tastes, always feeling fresh and still at the peak of pleasure-giving, while also remarking, "I can't stand repeating a simple story over and over again,"556 as he avoids and fears the boredom that every story faces, shifting the listener from one topic to another and refreshing their interest with novelty. However, those who talk too much wear on your patience with their repetitions, like people who keep rewriting the same things over and over on old manuscripts.557

§ vi. Let us remind them then first of this, that just as in the case of wine, which was intended for pleasure and mirth, those who compel people to drink it neat and in large quantities bring some into a disgusting condition of drunkenness, so with speech, which is the pleasantest social tie amongst 219mankind, those who make a bad and ill-advised use of it render it unpleasing and unfit for company, paining those whom they think to gratify, and become a laughing-stock to those who they think admire them, and objectionable to those who they think love them. As then he cannot be a favourite of the goddess who with Aphrodite's charmed girdle558 repels and drives away those who associate with him, so he who with his speech bores and disgusts one is without either taste or refinement.

§ vi. Let’s remind them of this: just like with wine, which is meant for enjoyment and fun, forcing people to drink it straight and in large amounts leads to a nasty state of drunkenness. The same goes for speech, the best social bond among 219 people. Those who misuse it in a foolish and unthoughtful way make it unpleasant and unsuitable for social settings, hurting those they believe they are pleasing, becoming a joke to those they think admire them, and becoming unappealing to those who they think care for them. Just as someone cannot be favored by the goddess if they repulse those around them with Aphrodite's magical girdle558, someone who bores and disgusts others with their speech lacks both taste and refinement.

§ vii. Of all other passions and disorders some are dangerous, some hateful, some ridiculous, but in talkativeness all these elements are combined. For praters are jeered at for their commonplaces, and hated when they bring bad news, and run into danger when they reveal secrets. And so Anacharsis, when he was feasted by Solon and lay down to sleep, and was observed with his left hand on his private parts, and his right hand on his mouth, for he thought his tongue needed the stronger restraint, was right in his opinion. For it would be difficult to find as many men who have been ruined by venereal excesses as cities and leading states that have been undone by the utterance of a secret. When Sulla was besieging Athens, and had no time to waste there, "for he had other fish to fry,"559 as Mithridates was ravaging Asia, and the party of Marius was again in power at Rome, some old men in a barber's shop happened to observe to one another that the Heptachalcon was not well guarded, and that their city ran a great risk of being captured at that point, and some spies who overheard this conversation reported it to Sulla. And he at once marched up his forces, and about midnight entered the city with his army, and all but rased it to the ground, and filled it with slaughter and dead bodies, insomuch that the Ceramicus ran with blood: and he was thus savage against the Athenians for their words rather than their deeds, for they had spoken ill of him and his wife Metella, jumping on to the walls and calling out in a jeering way,

§ vii. Among all the different passions and issues, some are dangerous, some are despised, and some are just silly, but talkativeness has all these aspects rolled into one. People mock chatterboxes for their clichés, resent them when they bring bad news, and they often get into trouble for revealing secrets. Anacharsis, when he was hosted by Solon and laid down to sleep, was seen with his left hand over his private parts and his right hand over his mouth because he believed his tongue needed the strictest control, which he was right about. It's hard to find as many people who have been ruined by sexual excesses as there are cities and major states that have fallen apart due to secrets being spoken out loud. When Sulla was besieging Athens and couldn't spare much time there, "for he had other fish to fry,"559 since Mithridates was ravaging Asia and the Marius faction was back in power in Rome, some old men in a barber shop happened to mention that the Heptachalcon wasn't well defended, putting their city at serious risk of being overtaken. Some spies overheard this conversation and reported it to Sulla. He immediately mobilized his troops, entered the city around midnight with his army, and nearly leveled it to the ground, filling it with slaughter and corpses until the Ceramicus ran with blood. He was brutal against the Athenians more for their words than their actions, as they had spoken badly about him and his wife Metella, mocking him while shouting from the walls.

"Sulla is a mulberry scattered with barley flour,"

220and much similar banter. Thus they drew down upon themselves for words, which, as Plato560 says, are a very small matter, a very heavy punishment.561 The prating of one man also prevented Rome from becoming free by the removal of Nero. For it was only the night before the tyrant was to be murdered, and all preparations had been made, when he that was to do the deed going to the theatre, and seeing someone in chains near the doors who was about to be taken before Nero, and was bewailing his sad fortune, went up close to him and whispered, "Pray only, good sir, that to-day may pass by, to-morrow you will owe me many thanks." He guessing the meaning of the riddle, and thinking, I take it, "he is a fool who gives up what is in his hand for a remote contingency,"562 preferred certain to honourable safety. For he informed Nero of what the man had said, and he was immediately arrested, and torture, and fire, and scourging were applied to him, who denied now in his necessity what before he had divulged without necessity.

220and a lot of similar talk. So, they brought upon themselves words that, as Plato560 says, are a trivial thing but a severe punishment.561 The chatter of one person also stopped Rome from being free by getting rid of Nero. It was just the night before the tyrant was supposed to be killed, and all the plans had been set, when the one meant to carry out the act went to the theater. There, he saw someone in chains near the entrance who was about to be presented to Nero and was lamenting his unfortunate situation. He approached the man and whispered, "Just hope that today goes by quickly; tomorrow you'll owe me a big thank you." The man, guessing the meaning behind the riddle and thinking, "it’s foolish to trade what you have for an uncertain future,"562 chose certain safety over honorable risk. He then informed Nero of what the man had said, leading to the man's immediate arrest, where he was subjected to torture, fire, and whipping, denying under duress what he had previously revealed without pressure.

§ viii. Zeno the philosopher,563 that he might not against his will divulge any secrets when put to the torture, bit off his tongue, and spit it at the tyrant. Famous also was the reward which Leæna had for her taciturnity.564 She was the mistress of Harmodius and Aristogiton, and, although a woman, participated in their hopes of success in the conspiracy against the tyrants: for she had revelled in the glorious cup of love, and had been initiated in their secrets through the god. When then they had failed in their attempt and been put to death, and she was examined and bidden to reveal the names of the other conspirators, she refused to do so, and held out to the end, showing that those famous men in loving such a one as her had done nothing unworthy of them. And the Athenians erected to her 221memory a bronze lioness without a tongue, and placed it near the entrance to the Acropolis, signifying her dauntless courage by the nobleness of that animal, and by its being without a tongue her silence and fidelity. For no spoken word has done as much good as many unspoken ones. For at some future day we can give utterance if we like to what has been not said, but a word once spoken cannot be recalled, but flies about and runs all round the world. And this is the reason, I take it, why men teach us to speak, but the gods teach us to be silent, silence being enjoined on us in the mysteries and in all religious rites. Thus Homer has described the most eloquent Odysseus, and Telemachus, and Penelope, and the nurse, as all remarkable for their taciturnity. You remember the nurse saying,

§ viii. Zeno the philosopher,563 to avoid revealing any secrets under torture, bit off his tongue and spat it at the tyrant. Leæna is also known for her silence.564 She was the lover of Harmodius and Aristogiton and, despite being a woman, shared in their hopes for success in the conspiracy against the tyrants. She had enjoyed the glorious experience of love and had been initiated into their secrets through divine influence. When their attempt failed and they were executed, she was interrogated and told to name the other conspirators, but she refused and remained loyal to the end, showing that those renowned men had made a worthy choice in loving someone like her. The Athenians honored her memory with a bronze lioness without a tongue at the entrance of the Acropolis, symbolizing her fearless courage through the nobility of the animal and her silence and loyalty through its lack of a tongue. For no spoken word has done as much good as many unspoken ones. We can express what hasn’t been said at some point in the future, but a word once spoken cannot be taken back; it spreads and travels all over the world. This is likely why people teach us to speak, but the gods teach us to be silent, as silence is emphasized in mysteries and all religious ceremonies. Homer portrayed Odysseus, Telemachus, Penelope, and the nurse as all known for their quietness. You remember the nurse saying,

"I'll keep it strong as the heart of oak or steel."565

And Odysseus sitting by Penelope,

And Odysseus sitting with Penelope,

"Even though he felt pity in his heart for her deep sadness, His eyes, like horn or steel, stood impassive. "Behind their eyelids, he hides his restrained tears."566

So great control had he over all his body, and so much were all his members under the sway and rule of reason, that he commanded his eyes not to weep, his tongue not to speak, and his heart not to tremble or quake.567

He had such control over his entire body, and every part of him was so influenced by reason, that he could tell his eyes not to cry, his tongue not to speak, and his heart not to shake or quiver.567

"His heart stayed so calm and passive,"568

reason penetrating even to the irrational instincts, and making spirit and blood obedient and docile to it. Such also were most of his companions, for though they were dashed to the ground and dragged along by the Cyclops, they said not a word about Odysseus, nor did they show the stake of wood that had been put into the fire and prepared to put out Polyphemus' eye, but they would rather have been eaten alive than divulge secrets, such wonderful 222self-control and fidelity had they.569 And so it was not amiss of Pittacus, when the king of Egypt sent him a victim, and bade him take from it the best and worst piece of it, to pull out the tongue and send that to the king, as being the instrument of the greatest blessings and withal the greatest mischiefs.

reason reaching even to the irrational instincts, making spirit and blood compliant and submissive to it. Most of his companions were like this too; even when they were thrown to the ground and dragged along by the Cyclops, they didn't say a word about Odysseus, nor did they reveal the piece of wood that had been set on fire and prepared to blind Polyphemus. They would rather have been eaten alive than expose their secrets; such remarkable self-control and loyalty they had. And it was quite fitting of Pittacus when the king of Egypt sent him a sacrificial animal and asked him to take the best and worst parts of it, to pull out the tongue and send that to the king, as it was the source of both the greatest blessings and the greatest harms.

§ ix. So Ino in Euripides, speaking plainly about herself, says she knows "how to be silent when she should, and to speak when speech is safe."570 For those who have enjoyed a truly noble and royal education learn first to be silent and then to speak. So the famous king Antigonus, when his son asked him, "When are we going to shift our quarters?" answered, "Are you afraid that you only will not hear the trumpet?" Was he afraid then to entrust a secret to him, to whom he intended one day to leave his kingdom? Nay rather, it was to teach him to be close and guarded on such matters. Metellus571 also, the well-known veteran, when questioned somewhat similarly about an expedition, said, "If I thought my coat knew the secret, I would strip it off and throw it into the fire." And Eumenes, when he heard that Craterus was marching against him, told none of his friends, but pretended that it was Neoptolemus; for his soldiers despised Neoptolemus, but they admired the glory and loved the virtue of Craterus; and no one but Eumenes knew the truth, and they engaged and were victorious, and unwittingly killed Craterus, and only recognized his dead body. So great a part did silence play in the battle, concealing the name of the enemy's general: so that Eumenes' friends marvelled more than found fault at his not having told them the truth. And if anyone should receive blame in such a case, it is better to be censured when one has done well by keeping one's counsel, rather than to have to accuse others through having come to grief by trusting them.

§ ix. In Euripides, Ino straightforwardly says she knows "when to be silent and when it's safe to speak." For those who have received a truly noble and royal education, the first lesson is to be quiet, followed by learning when to speak. When King Antigonus was asked by his son, "When are we going to move?" he replied, "Are you worried you won't hear the trumpet?" He wasn’t afraid to share a secret with the son he planned to leave his kingdom to; rather, he wanted to teach him to be discreet and cautious about such matters. Similarly, the well-known veteran Metellus responded when asked about a mission, "If I thought my coat knew the secret, I would take it off and throw it in the fire." Eumenes, upon learning that Craterus was marching against him, kept it to himself and told his friends it was Neoptolemus instead. His soldiers looked down on Neoptolemus but respected and admired Craterus. Only Eumenes knew the truth; they went into battle, won, and unknowingly killed Craterus, only recognizing his dead body afterward. Silence played a huge role in concealing the name of the enemy's general, so Eumenes' friends were more amazed than critical about his decision not to tell them the truth. If anyone were to be blamed in such a situation, it is better to receive criticism for having kept one's confidence when it resulted in doing well, rather than to blame others after suffering from misplaced trust.

§ x. But, generally speaking, who has the right to blame the person who has not kept his secret? For if it was not to be known, it was not well to tell another person of it at 223all, and if you divulged your secret yourself and expected another person to keep it, you had more faith in another than in yourself. And so should he be such another as yourself you are deservedly undone, and should he be a better man than yourself, your safety is more than you could have reckoned on, as it involved finding a man more to be trusted than yourself. But you will say, He is my friend. Yes, but he has another friend, whom he reposes confidence in as much as you do in your friend, and that other friend has one of his own, and so on, so that the secret spreads in many quarters from inability to keep it close in one. For as the unit never deviates from its orbit, but (as its name signifies) always remains one, but the number two contains within it the seeds of infinity, for when it departs from itself it becomes plurality at once by doubling, so speech confined in one person's breast is truly secret, but if it be communicated to another it soon gets noised abroad. And so Homer calls words "winged," for as he that lets a bird go from his hands cannot easily get it back again, so he that lets a word go from his mouth cannot catch or stop it, but it is borne along "whirling on swift wings," and dispersed from one person to another. When a ship scuds before the gale the mariners can stop it, or at least check its course with cables and anchors, but when the spoken word once sails out of harbour, so to speak, there is no roadstead or anchorage for it, but borne along with much noise and echo it dashes its utterer on the rocks, and brings him into imminent danger of shipwreck,

§ x. But, generally speaking, who has the right to judge someone for not keeping a secret? If it wasn’t meant to be shared, then it was a mistake to tell anyone in the first place. If you decide to share your secret and expect someone else to keep it, you’re placing more trust in them than in yourself. If they are just like you, you’re asking for trouble, and if they’re better than you, then you’re counting on finding someone more trustworthy than yourself. But you might argue, “He’s my friend.” Yes, but he has another friend, and he trusts that friend just as much as you trust him. That friend also has his own friends, and so it goes on, leading to the secret being spread around because it can't be kept hidden by just one person. Just as a single unit doesn’t stray from its orbit and remains one, the number two carries within it the potential for infinity; when it breaks away from itself, it immediately becomes multiple. So, a secret kept by one person remains a true secret, but once it's shared, it quickly gets out. That’s why Homer referred to words as "winged," because just like you can’t easily catch a bird once you let it go, the same goes for words once they’re spoken. They take off "spreading on swift wings," getting passed from one person to another. When a ship is racing before the wind, sailors can stop it, or at least slow it down with cables and anchors, but once a spoken word sails out of port, there’s no way to contain it — it rushes forward with noise and echoes, crashing its speaker into the rocks and putting them in serious danger of a shipwreck.

"As someone might set fire to Ida's woods" With a small flashlight, it's like telling one person something. "Is soon the property of all the citizens." __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

§ xi. The Roman Senate had been discussing for several days a secret matter, and there was much doubt and suspicion about it. And one of the senator's wives, discreet in other matters but a very woman in curiosity, pressed her husband close, and entreated him to tell her what the secret was; she vowed and swore she would not divulge it, and did not refrain from shedding tears at her not being trusted. And he, nothing loth to convince her of her folly, 224said, "Your importunity, wife, has prevailed, listen to a dreadful and portentous matter. It has been told us by the priests that a lark has been seen flying in the air with a golden helmet and spear: it is this portent that we are considering and discussing with the augurs, as to whether it be a good or bad omen. But say nothing about it." Having said these words he went into the Forum. But his wife seized on the very first of her maids that entered the room, and smote her breast, and tore her hair, and said, "Alas! for my husband and country! What will become of us?" wishing and teaching her maid to say, "Whatever's up?" So when she inquired she told her all about it, adding that refrain common to all praters, "Tell no one a word about it." The maid however had scarce left her mistress when she told one of her fellow-servants who was doing little or nothing, and she told her lover who happened to call at that moment. So the news spread to the Forum so quickly that it got the start of its original author, and one of his friends meeting him said, "Have you only just left your house?" "Only just," he replied. "Didn't you hear the news?" said his friend. "What news?" said he. "Why, that a lark has been seen flying in the air with a golden helmet and spear, and the Senate are met to discuss the portent." And he smiled and said to himself, "You are quick, wife, for the tale to get before me to the Forum!" Then meeting some of the Senators he disabused them of their panic. But to punish his wife, he said when he got home, "You have undone me, wife: for the secret has got abroad from my house, so that I must be an exile from my country for your inability to keep a secret." And on her trying to deny it, and saying, "Were there not three hundred Senators that heard of it as well as you? Might not one of them have divulged it?" he replied, "Stuff o' your three hundred! It was at your importunity that I invented the story, to put you to the test!" This fellow tested his wife warily and cunningly, as one pours water, and not wine or oil, into a leaky vessel. And Fabius,573 the friend of Augustus, hearing 225the Emperor in his old age mourning over the extinction of his family, how two of his daughter Julia's sons were dead, and how Posthumus Agrippa, the only remaining one, was in exile through false accusation,574 and how he was compelled to put his wife's son575 into the succession to the Empire, though he pitied Agrippa and had half a mind to recall him from banishment, repeated the Emperor's words to his wife, and she to Livia.576 And Livia bitterly upbraided Augustus, if he meant recalling his grandson, for not having done so long ago, instead of bringing her into hatred and hostility with the heir to the Empire. When Fabius came in the morning as usual into the Emperor's presence, and said, "Hail, Cæsar!" the Emperor replied, "Farewell,577 Fabius." And he understanding the meaning of this straightway went home, and sent for his wife, and said, "The Emperor knows that I have not kept his secret, so I shall kill myself." And his wife replied, "You have deserved your fate, since having been married to me so long you did not remember and guard against my incontinence of speech, but suffer me to kill myself first." So saying she took his sword, and slew herself first.

§ xi. The Roman Senate had been discussing a secret matter for several days, creating a lot of doubt and suspicion. One senator's wife, normally discreet but very curious, pressed her husband to reveal the secret. She swore she wouldn’t tell anyone and even cried over not being trusted. He, eager to show her the foolishness of her persistence, 224 said, "Your insistence, my wife, has won. Listen to a serious and ominous matter. The priests have reported that a lark was seen flying in the air with a golden helmet and spear. This is the sign we are discussing with the augurs to determine if it’s a good or bad omen. But don’t say anything about it." After saying this, he went into the Forum. His wife immediately grabbed the first maid who entered the room, beat her chest, tore her hair, and cried, "Oh! For my husband and country! What will happen to us?" while encouraging her maid to say, "What’s going on?" When the maid asked, she spilled everything, adding the usual phrase of all gossipers, "Don’t tell anyone." However, as soon as the maid left her, she told one of her fellow servants who wasn’t busy, and that servant told her lover who happened to visit at that moment. The news spread to the Forum so quickly that it reached the original source before he did, and a friend met him and said, "Did you just leave your house?" "Just now," he replied. "Didn’t you hear the news?" his friend asked. "What news?" he replied. "That a lark has been seen flying in the air with a golden helmet and spear, and the Senate is meeting to discuss the omen." He smiled to himself, thinking, "You’re quick, wife, for the story to get to the Forum before me!" Then, when he met some Senators, he reassured them about their panic. But to punish his wife, he said when he got home, "You’ve betrayed me, wife: the secret has leaked from our house, and now I must face exile from my country because you can’t keep a secret." When she tried to deny it, arguing, "Didn't three hundred Senators hear it too? Couldn’t one of them have let it slip?" he replied, "To hell with your three hundred! It was at your insistence that I made up this story to test you!" This guy tested his wife carefully and cleverly, like pouring water, not wine or oil, into a leaky vessel. And Fabius,573 a friend of Augustus, hearing 225 the Emperor in his old age lamenting the demise of his family—how two of his daughter Julia's sons had died, and how Posthumus Agrippa, the last one left, was in exile due to false accusations,574 and how he was forced to appoint his wife's son575 as his successor, even though he sympathized with Agrippa and was inclined to bring him back from exile—repeated the Emperor's words to his wife, who then passed them on to Livia.576 Livia angrily reproached Augustus for not recalling his grandson sooner, instead of causing her to be at odds with the heir to the Empire. The next morning, when Fabius entered the Emperor's presence and said, "Hail, Cæsar!" the Emperor replied, "Farewell,577 Fabius." Understanding the implication, he quickly returned home, summoned his wife, and said, "The Emperor knows I’ve leaked his secret, so I’m going to kill myself." His wife replied, "You deserve this fate, since after being married to me for so long, you didn't remember to guard against my loose tongue, but now I will die first." With that, she took his sword and killed herself first.

§ xii. That was a good answer therefore that the comic poet Philippides made to king Lysimachus, who greeted him kindly, and said to him,578 "What shall I give you of all my possessions?" "Whatever you like, O king, except your secrets." And talkativeness has another plague attached to it, even curiosity: for praters wish to hear much that they may have much to say, and most of all do they gad about to investigate and pry into secrets and hidden things, providing as it were an antiquated stock of rubbish579 for their twaddle, in fine like children who cannot580 hold ice in their hands, and yet are unwilling to let it go,581 or rather taking secrets to their bosoms and embracing them as if 226they were so many serpents, that they cannot control, but are sure to be gnawed to death by. They say that garfish and vipers burst in giving life to their young, so secrets by coming out ruin and destroy those who cannot keep them. Seleucus Callinicus having lost his army and all his forces in a battle against the Galati, threw off his diadem, and fled on a swift horse with an escort of three or four of his men a long day's journey by bypaths and out-of-the-way tracks, till faint and famishing for want of food he drew rein at a small farmhouse, where by chance he found the master at home, and asked for some bread and water. And he supplied him liberally and courteously not only with what he asked for but with whatever else was on the farm, and recognized the king, and being very joyful at this opportunity of ministering to the king's necessities, he could not contain himself, nor dissemble like the king who wished to be incognito, but he accompanied him to the road, and on parting from him, said, "Farewell, king Seleucus." And he stretching out his right hand, and drawing the man to him as if he was going to kiss him, gave a sign to one of his escort to draw his sword and cut the man's head off;

§ xii. That was a smart response from the comic poet Philippides when King Lysimachus greeted him warmly and asked, 578 "What can I give you from all my possessions?" "Anything you want, O king, except your secrets." And being talkative has another downside: curiosity. People who love to chatter want to hear a lot so they can say even more, and they especially like to snoop and dig into secrets and hidden matters, accumulating an outdated collection of nonsense579 for their gossip, much like children who can't580 keep ice in their hands but don't want to let it go,581 or rather, they embrace secrets as if 226 they were a bunch of serpents they can't control, but will surely be consumed by. It's said that garfish and vipers burst open when giving life to their young, just like secrets can ruin and destroy those who can't keep them. Seleucus Callinicus, having lost his army and all his forces in a battle against the Galatians, threw off his crown and fled on a fast horse with three or four of his men, traveling a long day's journey through back roads and less-traveled paths. When he was weak and starving from lack of food, he stopped at a small farmhouse, where he happened to find the owner at home, and asked for some bread and water. The man generously and kindly gave him not just what he asked for, but everything else that was available on the farm. He recognized the king, and filled with joy at the chance to help him, he couldn't contain himself or pretend like the king who wanted to remain anonymous; instead, he accompanied him to the road and, as they parted, said, "Farewell, King Seleucus." As he stretched out his right hand and pulled the man close as if to kiss him, he signaled to one of his escort to draw his sword and behead the man;

"And at his command, the head rolled in the dust."582

Whereas if he had been silent then, and kept his counsel for a time, as the king afterwards became prosperous and great, he would have received, I take it, greater favour for his silence than for his hospitality. And yet he had I admit some excuse for his want of reticence, namely hope and joy.

If he had stayed quiet back then and held back his thoughts for a while, as the king later became successful and powerful, I believe he would have gained more favor for his silence than for his hospitality. Still, I must admit he had some reason for his lack of restraint—hope and joy.

§ xiii. But most talkative people have no excuse for ruining themselves. As for example in a barber's shop one day there was some conversation about the tyranny of Dionysius, that it was as hard as adamant and invincible, and the barber laughed and said, "Fancy your saying this to me, who have my razor at his throat most days!" And Dionysius hearing this had him crucified. Barbers indeed are generally a talkative race, for people fond of prating flock to them and sit in their shops, so that they pick up the habit from their customers. It was a witty answer 227 therefore of king Archelaus,583 when a talkative barber put the towel round his neck, and asked him, "How shall I shave you, O king?" "Silently," said the monarch. It was a barber that first spread the news of the great reverse of the Athenians in Sicily, having heard of it at the Piræus from a slave that had escaped from the island. He at once left his shop, and ran into the city at full speed, "that no one else should reap the fame, and he come in the second,"584 of carrying the news into the town. And an uproar arising, as was only to be expected, the people assembled in the ecclesia, and began to investigate the origin of the rumour. So the barber was dragged up and questioned, but knew not the person's name who had told him, so was obliged to refer its origin to an anonymous and unknown person. Then anger filled the theatre, and the multitude cried out, "Torture the cursed fellow, put him to the rack: he has fabricated and concocted this news: who else heard it? who credits it?" The wheel was brought, the poor fellow stretched on it. Meantime those came up who had brought the news, who had escaped from the carnage in Sicily. Then all the multitude dispersed to weep over their private sorrows, and abandoned the poor barber, who remained fastened to the wheel. And when released late in the evening he actually asked the executioner, if they had heard how Nicias the General was slain. So invincible and incorrigible a vice does habit make talkativeness to be.

§ xiii. But most talkative people have no reason to ruin themselves. For example, one day in a barber's shop, there was a discussion about the tyranny of Dionysius, describing it as hard as stone and unbeatable. The barber laughed and said, "Can you believe you're saying this to me, who has my razor at his throat most days?" When Dionysius heard this, he had the barber crucified. Barbers tend to be quite chatty since people who love to talk flock to them and sit in their shops, so they pick up the habit from their customers. It was a clever reply from King Archelaus when a chatterbox barber put a towel around his neck and asked, "How shall I shave you, O king?" "Silently," the king replied. It was a barber who first spread the news of the Athenians’ devastating defeat in Sicily, having heard about it at the Piraeus from a slave who had escaped from the island. He immediately left his shop and rushed into the city, "so no one else could claim the glory of bringing the news." 584 As expected, an uproar broke out, and the people gathered in the assembly to investigate the source of the rumor. The barber was brought forward and questioned, but he didn't know the name of the person who had told him, so he had to say it was from an anonymous source. Anger filled the theater, and the crowd shouted, "Torture the wretched fellow, put him on the rack: he must have made up this news! Who else heard it? Who believes it?" The wheel was brought in, and the poor guy was strapped to it. Meanwhile, those who had truly escaped the slaughter in Sicily arrived. Then the entire crowd broke up to mourn their personal losses, leaving the barber still tied to the wheel. When he was finally released late in the evening, he actually asked the executioner if they had heard how General Nicias was killed. Such an unbreakable and stubborn vice does habit make of talkativeness.

§ xiv. And yet, as those that drink bitter and strong-smelling physic are disgusted even with the cups they drink it out of, so those that bring evil tidings are disliked and hated by their hearers. Wittily therefore has Sophocles described the conversation between Creon and the guard.

§ xiv. And yet, just as people who take bitter and powerful medicine are put off by the cups they drink from, those who bring bad news are disliked and hated by their listeners. Sophocles cleverly captured the exchange between Creon and the guard.

"G. Are you upset in your ears or in your mind?" C. Why do you define the source of sorrow this way? G. The one who acts troubles your mind, but I trouble your ears."585

However those that tell the tale grieve us as well as those 228that did the deed: and yet there is no means of checking or controlling the running tongue. At Lacedæmon the temple of Athene Chalciœcus586 was broken into, and an empty flagon was observed lying on the ground inside, and a great concourse of people came up and discussed the matter. And one of the company said, "If you will allow me, I will tell you what I think about this flagon. I cannot help being of opinion that these sacrilegious wretches drank hemlock, and brought wine with them, before commencing their nefarious and dangerous work: that so, if they should fail to be detected, they might depart in safety, drinking the wine neat as an antidote to the hemlock: whereas should they be caught in the act, before they were put to the torture they would die of the poison easily and painlessly." When he had uttered these words, the idea seemed so ingenious and farfetched that it looked as if it could not emanate from fancy, but only from knowledge of the real facts. So the crowd surrounded this man, and asked him one after the other, "Who are you? Who knows you? How come you to know all this?" And at last he was convicted in this way, and confessed that he was one of those that had committed the sacrilege. And were not the murderers of Ibycus similarly captured? They were sitting in the theatre, and some cranes flew over their heads, and they laughed and whispered to one another, "Behold the avengers of Ibycus." And this being overheard by some who sat near, as Ibycus had now been some time missing and inquired after, they laid hold of this remark, and reported it to the magistrates. And so they were convicted and dragged off to punishment, being brought to justice not by the cranes but by their own inability to hold their tongues, being compelled by some Fury or Vengeance as it were to divulge the murder.587 For as in the body there is an attraction to sore and suffering parts from neighbouring parts, so the tongue of talkative persons, ever suffering from inflammation and a throbbing pulse, attracts and draws to it secret and hidden things. And so the tongue ought to be fenced in, and have reason ever before 229it, as a bulwark, to prevent its tripping: that we may not seem to be more silly than geese, of whom it is said that, when they fly from Cilicia over Mt. Taurus which swarms with eagles, they carry in their mouths a large stone, which they employ as a gag or bridle for their scream, and so they cross over by night unobserved.

However, those who tell the story sadden us just as much as those who committed the act: and still there’s no way to stop or control a running mouth. At Lacedæmon, the temple of Athene Chalciœcus was broken into, and an empty flask was seen lying on the ground inside, which drew a large crowd that began discussing the situation. One of the people there said, “If you don’t mind, I’d like to share my thoughts about this flask. I can’t help but think that these sacrilegious people consumed hemlock and brought wine with them before starting their wicked and risky work: so if they didn’t get caught, they could leave safely, drinking the wine straight as an antidote to the hemlock. But if they got caught in the act, they would easily and painlessly die from the poison before they could be tortured.” As he spoke, his idea seemed so clever and outlandish that it looked like it couldn’t have come from imagination but from actual knowledge. The crowd gathered around him, asking one by one, “Who are you? Who knows you? How do you know all this?” Eventually, he was exposed this way and admitted that he was one of those who committed the sacrilege. The murderers of Ibycus were captured in a similar way, sitting in a theater when some cranes flew overhead. They laughed and whispered to each other, “Look, the avengers of Ibycus.” This got overheard by some nearby, and since Ibycus had been missing for a while and was being searched for, they took note of this comment and reported it to the authorities. So, they were found guilty and dragged off for punishment, brought to justice not by the cranes but by their own inability to keep quiet, seemingly compelled by some Fury or Vengeance to reveal the murder. For just like in the body, where there’s a pull to sore and suffering parts from nearby ones, the tongues of talkative people, always inflamed with excitement, attract and draw out secret and hidden things. Therefore, the tongue should be kept in check, always keeping reason in front of it, like a fortress, to prevent it from stumbling: so we don’t appear more foolish than geese, which are said to carry a large stone in their mouths when flying over Cilicia and the eagle-filled Mt. Taurus, using it as a gag or bridle for their screams, allowing them to cross over unnoticed at night.

§ xv. Now if anyone were to ask who is the worst and most abandoned man, no one would pass over the traitor, or mention anyone else. It was as the reward of treason that Euthycrates roofed his house with Macedonian wood, as Demosthenes tells us; and that Philocrates got a large sum of money, and spent it on women and fish; and it was for betraying Eretria that Euphorbus and Philagrus got an estate from king Philip. But the talkative man is an unhired and officious traitor, not of horses588 or walls, but of secrets which he divulges in the law courts, in factions, in party-strife, no one thanking him for his pains; but should anyone listen to him he thinks he is the obliged party. So that what was said to a man who rashly and indiscriminately squandered away all his means and bestowed them on others,

§ xv. If anyone were to ask who the most despicable and abandoned man is, no one would overlook the traitor or mention anyone else. It was because of treason that Euthycrates built his house with Macedonian wood, as Demosthenes tells us; and Philocrates received a large sum of money, which he spent on women and fish; and for betraying Eretria, Euphorbus and Philagrus got land from King Philip. But the chatty person is an uninvited and meddling traitor, not of horses or walls, but of secrets that he reveals in court, within factions, and in party disputes, with no one appreciating his efforts; yet if anyone pays attention to him, he believes he is the lucky one. So, what was said to a man who recklessly and indiscriminately wasted all his resources and gave them to others,

"It's not kindness in you, but illness." This urge to give, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

is appropriate also to the prater, "You don't communicate to us all this out of friendship or goodwill, but it is a disease in you, this itch for talking and prating."

is also fitting for the chatterbox, "You don't share all this with us out of friendship or kindness, but because you have this compulsion to talk and ramble."

§ xvi. But all this must not be looked upon merely as an indictment against talkativeness, but an attempt to cure it: for we overcome the passions by judgement and practice, but judgement is the first step. For no one is wont to shun, and eradicate from his soul, what he does not dislike. And we dislike the passions only when we discern by reason the harm and shame that results to us by indulging them. As we see every day in the case of talkative people: if they wish to be loved, they are hated; if they desire to please, they bore; when they think they are admired, they are really laughed at; they spend, and get no gain from so 230 doing; they injure their friends, benefit their enemies, and ruin themselves. So that the first cure and remedy of this disorder will be to reckon up the shame and trouble that results from it.

§ xvi. However, this shouldn't just be seen as a critique of being talkative, but rather as an effort to address it: we manage our emotions through judgment and practice, with judgment being the first step. No one typically avoids or removes from their mind what they don't find unpleasant. We only dislike our emotions when we recognize the damage and embarrassment they cause us by giving in to them. We notice this every day with talkative individuals: if they want to be liked, they are often disliked; if they aim to be charming, they end up boring people; when they think they're being admired, they are actually being laughed at; they spend energy without any real benefit; they harm their friends, help their foes, and ultimately damage themselves. Therefore, the initial step towards healing this issue is to acknowledge the shame and problems that come from it.

§ xvii. In the next place we must consider the opposite virtue to talkativeness, always listening to and having on our lips the encomiums passed upon reserve, and remembering the decorum sanctity and mysterious power of silence, and ever bearing in mind that terse and brief speakers, who put the maximum of matter into the minimum of words, are more admired and esteemed and thought wiser590 than unbridled windbags. And so Plato591 praises, and compares to clever javelin-men, such as speak tersely, compressedly, and concisely. And Lycurgus by using his citizens from boyhood to silence taught them to perfection their brevity and terseness. For as the Celtiberians make steel of iron only after digging down deep in the soil, and carefully separating the iron ore, so Laconian oratory has no rind,592 but by the removal of all superfluous matter goes home straight to the point like steel. For its sententiousness,593 and pointed suppleness in repartee, comes from the habit of silence. And we ought to quote such pointed sayings especially to talkative people, such neatness and vigour have they, as, for example, what the Lacedæmonians said to Philip, "[Remember] Dionysius at Corinth."594 And again, when Philip wrote to them, "If I invade Laconia, I will drive you all out of house and home," they only wrote back, "If." And when king Demetrius was indignant and cried out, "The Lacedæmonians have only sent me one ambassador," the ambassador was not frightened but said, "Yes, one to one man." Certainly among the ancients men of few words were admired. So the Amphictyones did not write extracts from the Iliad or Odyssey, or the Pæans of 231Pindar, in the temple of Pythian Apollo at Delphi, but "Know thyself," "Not too much of anything,"595 and "Be a surety, trouble is near;"596 so much did they admire compactness and simplicity of speech, combining brevity with shrewdness of mind. And is not the god himself short and concise in his oracles? Is he not called Loxias,597 because he prefers ambiguity to longwindedness? And are not those who express their meaning by signs without words wonderfully praised and admired? As Heraclitus, when some of the citizens asked him to give them his opinion about concord, got on the platform, and took a cup of cold water, and put some barley-meal in it, and stirred it up with penny-royal, thus showing them that it is being content with anything, and not needing costly dainties, that keeps cities in peace and concord. Scilurus, the king of the Scythians, left eighty sons, and on his death-bed asked for a bundle of sticks, and bade his sons break it when it was tied together, and when they could not, he took the sticks one by one and easily broke them all up: thus showing them that their harmony and concord would make them strong and hard to overthrow, while dissension would make them feeble and insecure.

§ xvii. Next, we need to think about the opposite virtue of talking too much: always listening and keeping in mind the praises of modesty. We should remember the dignity, sacredness, and mysterious power of silence, and always recognize that speakers who convey a lot with few words are more respected and considered wiser590 than those who are just full of hot air. Plato591 even praises those who speak briefly and concisely, likening them to skilled javelin throwers. Likewise, Lycurgus trained his citizens from childhood to value silence, perfecting their brevity and conciseness. Just as the Celtiberians make steel from iron by digging deep and carefully separating the ore, Laconian speech cuts straight to the point, removing all unnecessary content. Its sharpness593 and quick-wittedness come from the practice of silence. We should especially share such sharp sayings with talkative people; they have a certain neatness and energy, like the Lacedæmonians' response to Philip, "Remember Dionysius at Corinth."594 When Philip threatened, "If I invade Laconia, I will drive you out of your homes," they simply replied, "If." When King Demetrius was upset that the Lacedæmonians sent only one ambassador, that ambassador calmly said, "Yes, one to one man." Indeed, in ancient times, those who spoke little were admired. The Amphictyones didn’t inscribe passages from the Iliad or Odyssey or Pindar’s Pæans in the temple of Pythian Apollo at Delphi; instead, they chose succinct phrases like "Know thyself," "Not too much of anything,"595 and "Be a guarantor, trouble is near;"596 showcasing their admiration for compactness and simplicity in speech, blending brevity with keen insight. Isn’t the god himself direct and succinct in his prophecies? Isn’t he known as Loxias,597 for favoring ambiguity over lengthy discourse? And don’t we greatly admire those who convey meaning through gestures without words? For example, when some citizens asked Heraclitus to share his thoughts on harmony, he stepped up, took a cup of cold water, added some barley-meal, and stirred it with pennyroyal, illustrating that being content with simple things, rather than needing lavish treats, maintains peace and unity in communities. Scilurus, the king of the Scythians, had eighty sons, and on his deathbed, he asked for a bundle of sticks, told his sons to break it while tied together, which they couldn’t do, then broke them easily one by one to show them that their unity would make them strong and hard to defeat, while discord would leave them weak and vulnerable.

§ xviii. If then anyone were continually to recollect and repeat these or similar terse sayings, he would probably cease to be pleased with idle talk. As for myself, when I consider of what importance it is to attend to reason, and to keep to one's purpose, I confess I am quite put out of countenance by the example of the slave of Pupius Piso the orator. He, not wishing to be annoyed by their prating, ordered his slaves merely to answer his questions, and not say a word more. On one occasion wishing to pay honour to Clodius who was then in power, he ordered him to be invited to his house, and provided for him no doubt a sumptuous entertainment. At the time fixed all the guests were present except Clodius, for whom they waited, and the host frequently sent the slave who used to invite guests to see if he was coming, but when evening came, and he was now quite despaired of, he said to his slave, "Did you 232not invite him?" "Certainly," said the slave. "Why then has he not come?" said the master. "Because he declined," said the slave. "Why then did you not tell me of it at once?" said the master. "Because you never asked me," said the slave. This was a Roman slave. But an Athenian slave "while digging will tell his master on what terms peace was made." So great is the force of habit in all matters. And of it we will now speak.

§ xviii. If someone were to continuously remember and repeat these or similar short sayings, they would probably stop enjoying idle chatter. Personally, when I think about how important it is to focus on reason and stick to one’s goals, I can’t help but feel embarrassed by the example of Pupius Piso’s slave, the orator. Not wanting to be bothered by their chatter, he instructed his slaves to only answer his questions and not say anything more. One time, wanting to honor Clodius, who was in power at the moment, he had him invited to his home and surely prepared an extravagant feast for him. When the time came, all the guests were present except Clodius, so the host kept sending the slave who invited guests to check if he was coming. But as evening arrived and it seemed hopeless, he asked his slave, "Did you 232 not invite him?" "Of course," replied the slave. "Then why hasn’t he shown up?" asked the master. "Because he declined," said the slave. "Why didn’t you tell me right away?" the master asked. "Because you never asked me," the slave answered. This was a Roman slave. But an Athenian slave "will tell his master about the terms of peace while digging." Such is the power of habit in all situations. And that is what we will discuss now.

§ xix. For it is not by applying bit or bridle that we can restrain the talkative person, we must master the disease by habit. In the first place then, when you are in company and questions are going round, accustom yourself not to speak till all the rest have declined giving an answer. For as Sophocles says, "counsel is not like a race;" no more are question and answer. For in a race the victory belongs to him who gets in first, but in company, if anyone has given a satisfactory answer, it is sufficient by assenting and agreeing to his view to get the reputation of being a pleasant fellow; and if no satisfactory answer is given, then to enlighten ignorance and supply the necessary information is well-timed and does not excite envy. But let us be especially on our guard that, if anyone else is asked a question, we do not ourselves anticipate and intercept him in giving an answer. It is indeed perhaps nowhere good form, if another is asked a favour, to push him aside and undertake to grant it ourselves; for we shall seem so to upbraid two people at once, the one who was asked as not able to grant the favour, and the other as not knowing how to ask in the right quarter. But especially insulting is such forwardness and impetuosity in answering questions. For he that anticipates by his own answer the person that was asked the question seems to say, "What is the good of asking him? What does he know about it? In my presence nobody else ought to be asked about these matters." And yet we often put questions to people, not so much because we want an answer, as to elicit from them conversation and friendly feeling, and from a wish to fit them for company, as Socrates drew out Theætetus and Charmides. For it is all one to run up and kiss one who wishes to be kissed by another, or to divert to oneself the attention that he was bestowing on another, as to intercept another person's233 answers, and to transfer people's ears, and force their attention, and fix them on oneself; when, even if he that was asked declines to give an answer, it will be well to hold oneself in reserve, and only to meet the question modestly when one's turn comes, so framing one's answer as to seem to oblige the person who asked the question, and as if one had been appealed to for an answer by the other. For if people are asked questions and cannot give a satisfactory answer they are with justice excused; but he who without being asked undertakes to answer a question, and anticipates another, is disagreeable even if he succeeds, while, if his answer is unsatisfactory, he is ridiculed by all the company, and his failure is a source of the liveliest satisfaction to them.

§ xix. We can't control a talkative person with just rules; we need to overcome the habit. First, when you're with others and questions are being asked, train yourself to wait until everyone else has chosen not to answer. As Sophocles says, "counsel isn't a race;" and neither are questions and answers. In a race, winning goes to the first one to finish, but in conversation, if someone provides a good answer, you can just agree with them to be seen as friendly. If no one gives a good answer, sharing your knowledge at the right moment is appreciated and won't cause jealousy. We must be careful not to interrupt someone else when they're asked something. It’s generally poor etiquette to push someone aside when they’re being asked for help, as it implies that the person asked can't help and that the asker doesn't know where to go for assistance. Being overly eager to answer questions is particularly rude. If you jump in with an answer before the person asked has a chance to respond, it suggests, "Why ask them? They don’t know anything. No one else should speak in my presence." However, we often ask questions not just for answers, but to spark conversation and build camaraderie, helping others feel included, like Socrates did with Theætetus and Charmides. It’s just as inappropriate to grab attention or interrupt someone who is about to give an answer as it is to distract someone wanting to be kissed by another. If the person asked declines to respond, it’s best to stay reserved and wait your turn, responding in a way that shows you’re helping the person who asked, as if you were specifically called on for the answer. If someone is asked a question and can't answer, they’re usually excused fairly; however, if someone unprompted jumps in to answer, they're annoying even if they’re right, and if their response is poor, everyone else laughs at them, finding great enjoyment in their failure.

§ xx. The next thing to practise oneself to in answering the questions put to one,—a point to which the talkative person ought to pay the greatest attention,—is not through inadvertence to give serious answers to people who only challenge you to talk in fun and sport. For some people concoct questions not for real information, but simply for amusement and to pass the time away, and propound them to talkative people, just to have them on. Against this we must be on our guard, and not rush into conversation too hastily, or as if we were obliged for the chance, but we must consider the character of the inquirer and his purpose. When it seems that he really desires information, we should accustom ourselves to pause, and interpose some interval between the question and answer; during which time the questioner can add anything if he chooses, and the other can reflect on his answer, and not be in too great a hurry about it, nor bury it in obscurity, nor, as is frequently the case in too great haste, answer some other question than that which was asked. The Pythian Priestess indeed was accustomed to utter some of her oracles at the very moment before the question was put: for the god whom she serves "understands the dumb, and hears the mute."598 But he that wishes to give an appropriate answer must carefully consider both the question and the mind of the questioner, lest it be as the proverb expresses it,

§ xx. The next thing to practice when answering questions is something that talkative people should pay close attention to: don’t accidentally give serious answers to people who are just joking around. Some people ask questions not for real information but simply for fun and to kill time, especially to engage talkative individuals. We need to be cautious about this and not jump into conversations too quickly, as if we’re grateful for the opportunity. Instead, we should consider who’s asking and why they’re asking. When it seems they genuinely want information, we should train ourselves to pause and put some space between the question and our answer. This allows the questioner the chance to elaborate if they want and gives us a moment to think about our response, so we’re not rushed or vague, nor do we end up answering a different question than the one asked. The Pythian Priestess was known to deliver some of her oracles just before the questions were even asked, as the god she serves "understands the dumb and hears the mute."598 But anyone wanting to give a fitting answer must carefully think about both the question and the mindset of the questioner to avoid the mistake mentioned in the proverb.

"I asked for shovels, but they gave me buckets instead."599

Besides we ought to check this greediness and hunger for words, that it may not seem as if we had a flood on our tongue which was dammed up, but which we were only too glad to discharge600 on a question being put. Socrates indeed so repressed his thirst, that he would not allow himself to drink after exercise in the gymnasium, till he had first drawn from the well one bucket of water and poured it on to the ground, that he might accustom his irrational part to wait upon reason.

Besides, we should control this greed for words, so it doesn’t seem like we have a flood of speech held back, just waiting to be released when a question is asked. Socrates truly managed his thirst so well that he wouldn’t let himself drink after exercising in the gym until he first drew a bucket of water from the well and poured it out on the ground, training his irrational side to wait for reason.

§ xxi. There are moreover three kinds of answers to questions, the necessary, the polite, and the superfluous. For instance, if anyone asked, "Is Socrates at home?" one, as if backward and disinclined to answer, might say, "Not at home;" or, if he wished to speak with Laconic brevity, might cut off "at home," and simply say "No;" as, when Philip wrote to the Lacedæmonians to ask if they would receive him in their city, they sent him back merely a large "No." But another would answer more politely, "He is not at home, but with the bankers," and if he wished to add a little more, "he expects to see some strangers there." But the superfluous prater, if he has read Antimachus of Colophon,601 says, "He is not at home, but with the bankers, waiting for some Ionian strangers, about whom he has had a letter from Alcibiades who is in the neighbourhood of Miletus, staying with Tissaphernes the satrap of the great king, who used long ago to favour the Lacedæmonian party, but now attaches himself to the Athenians for Alcibiades' sake, for Alcibiades desires to return to his country, and so has succeeded in changing the views of Tissaphernes." And then he will go over the whole of the Eighth Book of Thucydides, and deluge the man, till before he is aware Miletus is captured, and Alcibiades is in exile the second time. In such a case most of all ought we to curtail talkativeness, by following 235the track of a question closely, and tracing out our answer according to the need of the questioner with the same accuracy as we describe a circle. When Carneades was disputing in the gymnasium before the days of his great fame, the superintendent of the gymnasium sent to him a message to bid him modulate his voice (for it was of the loudest), and when he asked him to fix a standard, the superintendent replied not amiss, "The standard of the person talking with you." So the meaning of the questioner ought to be the standard for the answer.

§ xxi. There are three types of answers to questions: necessary, polite, and excessive. For example, if someone asks, "Is Socrates at home?" one person, being reluctant to respond, might simply say, "Not at home;" or, if trying to be succinct, might just say "No," omitting "at home," like when Philip wrote to the Spartans asking if they would accept him in their city, and they replied with just a large "No." Another person might respond more politely, saying, "He is not at home, but with the bankers," and if they wanted to elaborate a bit more, they might add, "He expects to see some visitors there." But the overly talkative individual, if they read Antimachus of Colophon,601 might say, "He is not at home, but with the bankers, waiting for some Ionian visitors, about whom he received a letter from Alcibiades, who is near Miletus, staying with Tissaphernes, the satrap of the great king, who used to support the Spartans but now sides with the Athenians for Alcibiades' sake, as Alcibiades wants to return to his country and has been able to change Tissaphernes' mind." Then they would go on to discuss the entirety of the Eighth Book of Thucydides, overwhelming the listener until, before they know it, Miletus has fallen, and Alcibiades is exiled for the second time. In such cases, we should definitely minimize verbosity by closely following the intent of the question and crafting our response with the same precision as describing a circle. When Carneades was debating in the gymnasium before his rise to great fame, the gymnasium supervisor sent him a message asking him to lower his voice (since it was quite loud), and when Carneades asked for a guideline, the supervisor aptly replied, "The guideline is the person you are talking to." Thus, the intent of the questioner should be the standard for the answer.

§ xxii. Moreover as Socrates urged his disciples to abstain from such food as tempted them to eat when they were not hungry, and from such drinks as tempted them to drink when they were not thirsty, so the talkative person ought to be afraid most of such subjects of conversation as he most delights in and repeats ad nauseam, and to try and resist their influence. For example, soldiers are fond of descriptions about war, and thus Homer introduces Nestor frequently narrating his prowess and glorious deeds. And generally speaking those who have been successful in the law courts, or beyond their hopes been favourites of kings and princes, are possessed, as it were by some disease, with the itch for frequently recalling and narrating, how they got on and were advanced, what struggles they underwent, how they argued on some famous occasion, how they won the day either as plaintiffs or defendants, what panegyrics were showered upon them. For joy is much more inclined to prate than the well-known sleeplessness represented in comedies, frequently rousing itself, and finding something fresh to relate. And so at any excuse they slip into such narratives. For not only,

§ xxii. Just as Socrates encouraged his students to avoid food that tempted them to eat when they weren’t hungry, and drinks that tempted them to drink when they weren’t thirsty, a talkative person should be cautious of the topics they enjoy discussing the most and tend to repeat ad nauseam, and should try to resist their pull. For instance, soldiers love stories about war, which is why Homer often has Nestor recounting his heroic actions and achievements. Generally, those who have found success in the courts, or who have unexpectedly gained the favor of kings and nobles, seem to be afflicted with a kind of obsession, constantly recalling and sharing how they succeeded, what challenges they faced, how they argued in a notable case, how they triumphed as plaintiffs or defendants, and what praises were heaped upon them. Joy is much more prone to chatter than the well-known insomnia depicted in comedies, always waking up and finding something new to share. They seize any opportunity to slip into such stories. For not only,

"Wherever someone itches, that's where their hand goes,"602

but also delight has a voice of its own, and leads about the tongue in its train, ever wishing to fortify it with memory. Thus lovers spend most of their time in conversations that revive the memory of their loves; and if they cannot talk to human beings about them, they talk about them to inanimate objects, as, "O dearest bed," and,

but also joy has its own voice, guiding the tongue along, always wanting to strengthen it with memories. So, lovers often spend time having conversations that bring back memories of their love; and if they can’t talk to others about it, they talk to inanimate objects, saying things like, "O dearest bed," and,

"O happy lamp, Bacchis considers you a god, If she believes that, then you really are "The greatest god."

The talkative person therefore is merely as regards words a white line,603 but he that is especially inclined to certain subjects should be especially on his guard against talking about them, and should avoid such topics, since from the pleasure they give him they may entice him to be very prolix and tedious. The same is the case with people in regard to such subjects as they think they are more experienced in and acquainted with than others. For such a one, being self-appreciative and fond of fame, "spends most of the day in that particular branch of study in which he chances to be proficient."604 Thus he that is fond of reading will give his time to research; the grammarian his to syntax; and the traveller, who has wandered over many countries, his to geography. We must therefore be on our guard against our favourite topics, for they are an enticement to talkativeness, as its wonted haunts are to an animal. Admirable therefore was the behaviour of Cyrus in challenging his companions, not to those contests in which he was superior to them, but to those in which he was inferior, partly that he might not give them pain through his superiority, partly for his own benefit by learning from them. But the talkative person acts just contrary, for if any subject is introduced from which he might learn something he did not know, this he rejects and refuses, not being able to earn a good deal by a short silence,605 but he rambles round the subject and babbles out stale and commonplace rhapsodies. As one amongst us, who by chance had read two or three of the books of Ephorus,606 bored everybody, and dispersed every social party, by always narrating the 237particulars of the battle of Leuctra and its consequences, so that he got nicknamed Epaminondas.

The talkative person is basically just a blank slate when it comes to words,603 but someone who is particularly interested in certain topics should be careful about discussing them and should steer clear of those subjects. The enjoyment they bring might tempt him to be overly verbose and boring. The same goes for people regarding topics they believe they understand better than others. Such a person, being self-satisfied and seeking recognition, "spends most of the day in that specific area of study in which he happens to excel."604 So, someone who loves reading will dedicate their time to research, the grammarian will focus on syntax, and the traveler, who has been to many places, will study geography. We need to be cautious about our favorite subjects, as they can lure us into being chatty, similar to how familiar places draw in an animal. Cyrus's response was praiseworthy because he challenged his companions not in areas where he excelled but in those where he was less skilled, partly to avoid hurting them with his superiority and partly for his own gain by learning from them. The talkative person, however, does the opposite; when a topic comes up from which he could learn something new, he dismisses it, unable to gain much from a brief silence,605 and instead rambles on and spews out tired and clichéd rants. For example, one among us, who happened to read a couple of books by Ephorus,606 bored everyone and disrupted every gathering by constantly recounting the details of the battle of Leuctra and its aftermath, earning him the nickname Epaminondas.

§ xxiii. Nevertheless this is one of the least of the evils of talkativeness, and we ought even to try and divert it into such channels as these, for prating is less of a nuisance when it is on some literary subject. We ought also to try and get some persons to write on some topic, and so discuss it by themselves. For Antipater the Stoic philosopher,607 not being able or willing it seems to dispute with Carneades, who inveighed vehemently against the Stoic philosophy, writing and filling many books of controversy against him, got the nickname of Noisy-with-the-pen; and perhaps the exercise and excitement of writing, keeping him very much apart from the community, might make the talkative man by degrees better company to those he associated with; as dogs, bestowing their rage on sticks and stones, are less savage to men. It will also be very advantageous for such to mix with people better and older than themselves, for they will accustom themselves to be silent by standing in awe of their reputation. And withal it will be well, when we are going to say something, and the words are on our lips, to reflect and consider, "What is this word that is so eager for utterance? To what is this tongue marching? What good will come of speaking now, or what harm of silence?" For we ought not to drop words as we should a burden that pressed upon us, for the word remains still after it has been spoken just the same; but men speak either on their own behalf if they want something, or to benefit those that hear them, or, to gratify one another, they season everyday life with speech, as one seasons food with salt. But if words are neither useful to the speaker, nor necessary for the hearer, nor contain any pleasure or charm, why are they spoken? For words may be idle and useless as well as deeds. And besides all this we must ever remember as most important the dictum of Simonides, that he had often repented he had spoken, but never that he had been silent: while as to the power and strength of practice consider how men by much toil and painstaking will get rid even of a cough or hiccough. And silence is 238not only never thirsty, as Hippocrates says, but also never brings pain or sorrow.

§ xxiii. Still, this is one of the less serious downsides of being chatty, and we should even try to steer it toward topics like this because chatting is less annoying when it's about something literary. We should also encourage some people to write about certain topics and discuss them among themselves. Antipater, the Stoic philosopher, not able or willing, it seems, to argue with Carneades—who harshly criticized Stoic philosophy—wrote and filled many books arguing against him, earning the nickname Noisy-with-the-pen; and perhaps the act and energy of writing, which kept him mostly away from the community, might gradually make the talkative person better company for others. Just like dogs that direct their aggression at sticks and stones tend to be less aggressive towards humans. It will also be very beneficial for them to associate with people who are older and more accomplished, as they will learn to be quiet by respecting their reputation. Furthermore, when we are about to say something and the words are on our lips, we should pause and think: "What is this word so eager to be spoken? What is this tongue trying to say? What good will come from speaking now, or what harm from staying silent?" We shouldn't just let words spill out like a burden we need to drop, since words linger even after they've been spoken; people speak for their own benefit if they want something, or to help those who hear them, or to enrich everyday life with conversation like one seasons food with salt. But if words aren’t helpful for the speaker, necessary for the listener, or enjoyable in any way, then why are they even spoken? Because words can be as idle and pointless as actions. And above all, we must always remember the important saying of Simonides, who often regretted speaking but never regretted being silent: also, consider how much effort people will go through just to get rid of a cough or hiccup. And silence is 238 not only never thirsty, as Hippocrates says, but it also never causes pain or sorrow.

541 Or Garrulity, Chattering, Prating. It is Talkativeness in a bad sense.

541 Or Garrulity, Chattering, Prating. It is talking too much in a negative way.

542 Or Heptaphonos. See Pausanias, v. 21.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Or Heptaphonos. See Pausanias, v. 21.

543 Some unknown poet's words. I suppose they mean driving one mad, making one "Like sweet bells jangled, out of tune and harsh."

543 Some unknown poet's words. I guess they refer to making someone crazy, making one "Like sweet bells jangled, out of tune and harsh."

544 So our English proverb, "Empty vessels make the greatest sound."

544 So our English saying, "Empty containers make the loudest noise."

545 Literally in a semi-circular place. It is not quite clear whether the front seats of the theatre are meant, or, as I have taken it, more generally, of some public place for entertainment or meeting, some promenade or piazza.

545 Literally in a semi-circular area. It’s not entirely clear if it refers to the front seats of the theater or, as I've interpreted it, more broadly to some public space for entertainment or gathering, like a promenade or plaza.

546 Reading ἀκοὔειν, which seems far the best reading.

546 Reading Listening, which seems to be the best interpretation.

547 Homer, "Iliad," v. 226; "Odyssey," vi. 81.

547 Homer, "Iliad," v. 226; "Odyssey," vi. 81.

548 "Bacchæ," 385-387.

"Bacchæ," 385-387.

549 See Ovid, "Tristia," iv. 4, 55-58.

549 See Ovid, "Tristia," iv. 4, 55-58.

550 For example, Horace, "Epistles," i. 2, 62: "Ira furor brevis est" I read ὁμότοιχος with Mez.

550 For instance, Horace, "Epistles," i. 2, 62: "Anger is a brief madness" I read ὁμότοιχος with Mez.

551 Homer, "Odyssey," xiv. 463-465.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Odyssey," XIV. 463-465.

552 Ibid. 466.

Ibid.

553 Compare the German proverb, "Thought when sober, said when drunk"—"Nuchtern gedacht, voll gesagt."

553 Compare the German saying, "Thought when sober, said when drunk"—"Nuchtern gedacht, voll gesagt."

554 Cf. Quintilian, x. 1, 78: "His ætate Lysias major, subtilis atque elegans et quo nihil, si oratori satis est docere, quæras perfectius. Nihil enim est inane, nihil arcessitum; puro tamen fonti quam magno flumini propior." Cf. ix. 4, 17.

554 See Quintilian, x. 1, 78: "In his time, Lysias was older, refined, and elegant, and you won't find anything more perfect if you just want an orator to teach. There's nothing superficial, nothing forced; however, it's closer to a pure spring than to a great river." See ix. 4, 17.

555 Somewhat like Pindar, "Pyth." i. 1. 1, 2.

555 Similar to Pindar, "Pyth." i. 1. 1, 2.

556 "Odyssey," xii. 452, 453.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," 12. 452, 453.

557 See Cicero, "Ad Fam." vii. 18; Catullus, xxii. 5, 6.

557 See Cicero, "Ad Fam." vii. 18; Catullus, xxii. 5, 6.

558 See "Iliad," xiv. 214-217.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See "Iliad," xiv. 214-217.

559 "Allusio ad Homericum ἐπεἱ πόνος ἄλλος ἐπείγει."—Xylander.

559 "Reference to Homeric ἐπεἱ pain another urges."—Xylander.

560 "Laws," xi. p. 935 A.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Laws," xi. p. 935 A.

561 So true are the words of Æschylus, γλώσσῃ ματαίᾳ ζημία προστρίβεται.—"Prom." 329.

561 The words of Æschylus are so true, “An empty tongue brings nothing but loss.” —"Prom." 329.

562 Our "A bird in the hand is worth two in the bush."

562 Our "A bird in the hand is better than two in the bush."

563 "Non Citticus, sed Eleates. v. Cic. Tuscul. ii. 22, et Nat. Deor. 3, 33."—Reiske.

563 "Not Citticus, but Eleates. See Cicero, Tusculans II.22, and On the Nature of the Gods III.33."—Reiske.

564 See Pausanias, i. 23. Leæna means "lioness." On the conspiracy see Thucydides, vi. 54-59.

564 See Pausanias, i. 23. Leæna means "lioness." For details on the conspiracy, check Thucydides, vi. 54-59.

565 Homer, "Odyssey," xix. 494. Plutarch quotes from memory. The nurse's name was Euryclea.

565 Homer, "Odyssey," xix. 494. Plutarch quotes from memory. The nurse was named Euryclea.

566 Odyssey," xix. 210-212. Quoted again "On Moral Virtue," § iv.

566 Odyssey," xix. 210-212. Quoted again "On Moral Virtue," § iv.

567 Literally bark. See "Odyssey," xx. 13, 16.

567 Literally bark. See "Odyssey," xx. 13, 16.

568 "Odyssey," xx. 23.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," xx. 23.

569 See "Odyssey," ix. Κυκλώπεια.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See "Odyssey," ix. Κυκλώπεια.

570 Euripides, "Ino." Fragment, 416.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Ino." Fragment, 416.

571 "Significat Q. Cæcilium Metellum, de quo Liv. xl. 45, 46."—Reiske.

571 "Significat Q. Cæcilium Metellum, about which Liv. xl. 45, 46."—Reiske.

572 Euripides, "Ino." Fragm. 415. Compare St. James, iii. 5, 6.

572 Euripides, "Ino." Fragm. 415. Compare St. James, 3:5-6.

573 Fabius Maximus. So Tacitus, "Annals," i. 5, who relates this story somewhat differently.

573 Fabius Maximus. So Tacitus, "Annals," i. 5, who tells this story in a slightly different way.

574 See Tacitus, "Annals," i. 3. As to his fate, see "Annals," i. 6.

574 See Tacitus, "Annals," i. 3. For information on his fate, see "Annals," i. 6.

575 Tiberius Nero, who actually did succeed Augustus.

575 Tiberius Nero, who effectively became the successor of Augustus.

576 The Emperor's wife.

The Emperor's wife.

577 So it is in § xii. But perhaps here it means, "I wish you had more sense, Fabius!"

577 So it is in § xii. But maybe here it means, "I wish you were smarter, Fabius!"

578 Adopting the reading of Reiske.

Following Reiske's interpretation.

579 Reading φορυτοῦ or φορυτῶν, as Wyttenbach.

579 Reading φορυτοῦ or φορυτῶν, as Wyttenbach.

580 Reading κατέχειν δύνανται with Reiske.

580 Reading they can hold can with Reiske.

581 See Sophocles, Fragm. 162.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Refer to Sophocles, Fragm. 162.

582 Homer, "Iliad," x. 457.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," x. 457.

583 Compare "Moralia," p. 177 A; Horace, "Satires," i. 7. 3: "Omnibus et lippis notum et tonsoribus."

583 Compare "Moralia," p. 177 A; Horace, "Satires," i. 7. 3: "Known to everyone and their barbers."

584 Homer, "Iliad," xxii. 207.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 22.207.

585 Sophocles, "Antigone," 317-319.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Sophocles, "Antigone," 317-319.

586 See Pausanias, iii. 17; iv. 15; x. 5.

586 See Pausanias, iii. 17; iv. 15; x. 5.

587 Compare the idea of the people of Melita, Acts xxviii. 4.

587 Compare the view of the people of Melita, Acts xxviii. 4.

588 An Allusion to Dolon in Homer, "Iliad," x., 374, sq. according to Xylander.

588 A Reference to Dolon in Homer, "Iliad," x., 374, sq. as noted by Xylander.

589 Quoted again by our author in his "Publicola," p. 105 B., and assigned to Epicharmus.

589 Cited once more by our author in "Publicola," p. 105 B., and attributed to Epicharmus.

590 So Shakspere has taught us, "Brevity is the soul of wit."—Hamlet, Act ii Sc. 2.

590 So Shakespeare has taught us, "Being concise is the essence of cleverness."—Hamlet, Act ii Sc. 2.

591 "In Protagora."—Xylander.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "In Protagoras."—Xylander.

592 That is, is all kernel. See passim our author's "Apophthegmata Laconica."

592 That is, it's all essence. Refer to our author's "Apophthegmata Laconica" throughout.

593 Or, apophthegmatic nature.

Or, wise saying.

594 Dionysius the younger, tyrant of Syracuse, was expelled, and afterwards kept a school at Corinth. That is the allusion. It would be like saying "Remember Napoleon at St. Helena."

594 Dionysius the younger, the tyrant of Syracuse, was kicked out and later ran a school in Corinth. That's the reference. It would be like saying, "Think of Napoleon on St. Helena."

595 See Pausanias, x. 24.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Check Pausanias, x. 24.

596 See Plato, "Charmides," 165 A.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Plato, "Charmides," 165 A.

597 A title applied to Apollo first by Herodotus, i. 91, from his ambiguous (λοξά) oracles.

597 A title given to Apollo first by Herodotus, i. 91, because of his unclear (λοξά) oracles.

598 Part of the words of an oracle of the Pythian Priestess, slightly changed. The whole oracle may be seen in Herodotus, i. 47.

598 Some of the words from an oracle of the Pythian Priestess, with minor adjustments. You can find the complete oracle in Herodotus, i. 47.

599 Proverb of cross purposes.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Proverb of mixed signals.

600 Reading ἐξερᾰσθαι with Dübner.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading ἐξερᾰσθαι with Dübner.

601 Catullus calls him "tumidus," i.e. long-winded, 95, 10. See also Propertius, iii. 34-32. He was a Greek poet, a contemporary of Socrates and Plato, and author of a Thebaid. Pausanias mentions him, viii. 25; ix. 35.

601 Catullus calls him "tumid," meaning long-winded, 95, 10. See also Propertius, iii. 34-32. He was a Greek poet, a contemporary of Socrates and Plato, and the author of a Thebaid. Pausanias mentions him, viii. 25; ix. 35.

602 The mediæval proverb, Ubi dolor ibi digitus.

602 The medieval saying, Where there is pain, there is a finger.

603 A proverbial expression for having no judgment. See Sophocles, Fragm. 307; Plato, "Charmides," 154 B; Erasmus, "Adagia." So we say a person's mind is a blank sheet on a subject he knows nothing about.

603 A common saying for lacking judgment. See Sophocles, Fragm. 307; Plato, "Charmides," 154 B; Erasmus, "Adagia." So we say a person's mind is like a blank sheet when it comes to a topic they know nothing about.

604 Euripides, Fragm. 202. Quoted also by Plato, "Gorgias," 484 E.

604 Euripides, Fragm. 202. Quoted also by Plato, "Gorgias," 484 E.

605 Reading with Reiske, μισθὸν αὑτῷ δοῦναι τῷ μικρὸν σιωπῆσαι μὴ δυνάμενος.

605 Reading with Reiske, to pay himself a wage to stay quiet, unable to do so.

606 A celebrated Greek historian, and pupil of Isocrates. See Cicero, "De Oratore," ii. 13.

606 A famous Greek historian and student of Isocrates. See Cicero, "De Oratore," ii. 13.

607 Of Tarsus. See Cicero, "De Officiis," iii. 12.

607 From Tarsus. See Cicero, "De Officiis," iii. 12.


ON CURIOSITY.608

§ i. If a house is dark, or has little air, is in an exposed position, or unhealthy, the best thing will probably be to leave it; but if one is attached to it from long residence in it, one can improve it and make it more light and airy and healthy by altering the position of the windows and stairs, and by throwing open new doors and shutting up old ones. So some towns have been altered for the better, as my native place,609 which did lie to the west and received the rays of the setting sun from Parnassus, was they say turned to the east by Chæron. And Empedocles the naturalist is supposed to have driven away the pestilence from that district, by having closed up a mountain gorge that was prejudicial to health by admitting the south wind to the plains. Similarly, as there are certain diseases of the soul that are injurious and harmful and bring storm and darkness to it, the best thing will be to eject them and lay them low by giving them open sky, pure air and light, or, if that cannot be, to change and improve them some way or other. One such mental disease, that immediately suggests itself to one, is curiosity, the desire to know other people's troubles, a disease that seems neither free from envy nor malignity.

§ i. If a house is dark, lacks fresh air, is in a vulnerable location, or is unhealthy, it’s probably best to move on; but if you’re attached to it due to long time spent there, you can make it brighter, airier, and healthier by changing the placement of the windows and stairs, opening new doors, and closing old ones. In the same way, some towns have been improved, like my hometown, 609, which originally faced west and caught the rays of the setting sun from Parnassus, but they say it was turned to face east by Chæron. Empedocles, the naturalist, is believed to have driven away the plague from that area by sealing off a mountain pass that was unhealthy due to the south wind spreading into the plains. Similarly, just as there are certain harmful diseases of the mind that bring chaos and darkness, it’s best to eliminate them and restore clarity by providing open skies, fresh air, and light, or if that’s not possible, to somehow change and improve them. One such mental issue that comes to mind is curiosity—the urge to know about other people's problems—which seems to have elements of envy and malice.

"Malicious wretch, why are you so eager to mark" "Why do you notice your neighbor's faults but not your own?"610

Shift your view, and turn your curiosity so as to look inwards: if you delight to study the history of evils, you have copious material at home, "as much as there is water in the Alizon, or leaves on the oak," such a quantity of faults will you find in your own life, and passions in your soul, 239and shortcomings in your duty. For as Xenophon says611 good managers have one place for the vessels they use in sacrificing, and another for those they use at meals, one place for their farm instruments, and another for their weapons of war, so your faults arise from different causes, some from envy, some from jealousy, some from cowardice, some from meanness. Review these, consider these; bar up the curiosity that pries into your neighbours' windows and passages, and open it on the men's apartments, and women's apartments, and servant's attics, in your own house. There this inquisitiveness and curiosity will find full vent, in inquiries that will not be useless or malicious, but advantageous and serviceable, each one saying to himself,

Shift your perspective and direct your curiosity inward: if you enjoy exploring the history of wrongs, you've got plenty of material right at home, "as much as there is water in the Alizon, or leaves on the oak," you'll find a vast number of faults in your own life, passions in your soul, 239 and shortcomings in your duty. As Xenophon points out, good managers have one place for the vessels they use for sacrifices and another for those they use for meals, one place for their farming tools and another for their weapons. Similarly, your faults come from different sources: some from envy, some from jealousy, some from cowardice, and some from meanness. Reflect on these, take a good look at them; shut out the curiosity that snoops into your neighbors' lives, and redirect it toward the men’s quarters, women’s quarters, and servants’ areas in your own home. There, this curiosity and inquisitiveness will have plenty of room to roam, engaging in inquiries that will be beneficial and constructive, with each person saying to themselves,

"What have I done wrong? What did I do?" What should I have done that I didn't do?

§ ii. And now, as they say of Lamia that she is blind when she sleeps at home, for she puts her eyes on her dressing-table, but when she goes out she puts her eyes on again, and has good sight, so each of us turns, like an eye, our malicious curiosity out of doors and on others, while we are frequently blind and ignorant about our own faults and vices, not applying to them our eyes and light. So that the curious man is more use to his enemies than to himself, for he finds fault with and exposes their shortcomings, and shows them what they ought to avoid and correct, while he neglects most of his affairs at home, owing to his excitement about things abroad. Odysseus indeed would not converse with his mother till he had learnt from the seer Tiresias what he went to Hades to learn; and after receiving that information, then he turned to her, and asked questions about the other women, who Tyro was, and who the fair Chloris, and why Epicaste612 had died, "having fastened a noose with a long drop to the lofty beam."613 But we, while very remiss and ignorant and careless about ourselves, know all about the pedigrees 240of other people, that our neighbour's grandfather was a Syrian, and his grandmother a Thracian woman, and that such a one owes three talents, and has not paid the interest. We even inquire into such trifling matters as where somebody's wife has been, and what those two are talking in the corner about. But Socrates used to busy himself in examining the secret of Pythagoras' persuasive oratory, and Aristippus, meeting Ischomachus at the Olympian games, asked him how Socrates conversed so as to have so much influence over the young men, and having received from him a few scraps and samples of his style, was so enthusiastic about it that he wasted away, and became quite pale and lean, thirsty and parched, till he sailed to Athens and drew from the fountain-head, and knew the wonderful man himself and his speeches and philosophy, the object of which was that men should recognize their faults and so get rid of them.

§ ii. And now, as people say about Lamia that she’s blind when she’s at home because she takes her eyes off and puts them on her dressing table, but when she goes out, she puts her eyes back on and can see just fine, each of us turns, like an eye, our spiteful curiosity outward onto others while we often remain blind and unaware of our own faults and flaws, not giving them our attention and insight. So, the curious person is more helpful to their enemies than to themselves, as they criticize and highlight others’ weaknesses, showing them what they should avoid and improve, while neglecting most of their own issues at home due to their excitement about things happening elsewhere. Odysseus didn’t talk to his mother until he had learned from the prophet Tiresias what he went to the underworld to find out; after getting that information, he turned to her and asked about the other women, who Tyro was, who the beautiful Chloris was, and why Epicaste612 died “having tied a noose with a long drop to the high beam.”613 But we, while being very careless, ignorant, and negligent about ourselves, know everything about other people's backgrounds—like that our neighbor's grandfather was Syrian and his grandmother was a Thracian, or that someone owes three talents and hasn’t paid the interest. We even indulge in trivial matters like where someone’s wife has been or what those two are whispering about in the corner. But Socrates used to focus on unraveling the secrets of Pythagoras’ persuasive speech, and when Aristippus met Ischomachus at the Olympic games, he asked him how Socrates managed to influence young men so much. After receiving a few tips and examples of his style, he became so excited that he wasted away, growing pale and thin, thirsty and parched, until he sailed to Athens to learn directly from the source and knew the remarkable man himself, along with his speeches and philosophy, which aimed for people to recognize their own faults and thus eliminate them.

§ iii. But some men cannot bear to look upon their own life, so unlovely a spectacle is it, nor to throw and flash on themselves, like a lantern, the reflection of reason; but their soul being burdened with all manner of vices, and dreading and shuddering at its own interior, sallies forth and wanders abroad, feeding and fattening its malignity there. For as a hen, when its food stands near its coop,614 will frequently slip off into a corner and scratch up,

§ iii. But some people can't stand to look at their own lives because it's such an unpleasant sight, nor can they shine the light of reason on themselves like a lantern. Instead, their souls, weighed down by all kinds of vices and afraid of what they find inside, go out into the world and seek to feed and grow their negativity there. It's similar to a hen that, when its food is close to its coop, will often sneak off to a corner and scratch around,

"Where I think some poor little grain shows up on the manure heap,"

so curious people neglecting conversation or inquiry about common matters, such as no one would try and prevent or be indignant at their prying into, pick out the secret and hidden troubles of every family. And yet that was a witty answer of the Egyptian, to the person who asked him, "What he was carrying wrapped up;" "It was wrapped up on purpose that you should not know." And you too, Sir, I would say to a curious person, why do you pry into what is hidden? If it were not something bad it would not be hidden. Indeed it is not usual to go into a strange house without knocking at the door, and nowadays there are porters, but in old times there were knockers on doors 241to let the people inside know when anyone called, that a stranger might not find the mistress or daughter of the house en déshabille, or one of the slaves being corrected, or the maids bawling out. But the curious person intrudes on all such occasions as these, although he would be unwilling to be a spectator, even if invited, of a well-ordered family: but the things for which bars and bolts and doors are required, these he reveals and divulges openly to others. Those are the most troublesome winds, as Aristo says, that blow up our clothes: but the curious person not only strips off the garments and clothes of his neighbours, but breaks through their walls, opens their doors, and like the wanton wind, that insinuates itself into maidenly reserve, he pries into and calumniates dances and routs and revels.

Curious people ignore conversations or questions about everyday topics—things that no one would try to stop or be upset about if they pried into—and instead focus on uncovering the hidden troubles of every family. Yet, that was a clever reply from the Egyptian to someone who asked him, "What are you carrying wrapped up?" He said, "It's wrapped up on purpose so you won't know." And to you, sir, I would ask a curious person: why do you delve into what's hidden? If it weren't something bad, it wouldn't be hidden. It's not common to enter a stranger's house without knocking first, and nowadays we have porters, but in the past, there were knockers on doors 241to alert the people inside that someone was calling, so a stranger wouldn't catch the mistress or daughter of the house unprepared, or a slave being punished, or maids loudly arguing. However, the curious person intrudes in all these situations, even though they wouldn’t want to witness firsthand—even if invited—a well-run family. Yet, they freely expose and disclose those things for which bars and bolts and doors are needed. Those are the most bothersome winds, as Aristo says, that lift our clothes: but the curious person not only strips away the garments and clothes of their neighbors but also breaks down walls, opens doors, and like an insistent wind that intrudes upon modesty, pries into and spreads gossip about dances, parties, and celebrations.

§ iv. And as Cleon is satirized in the play615 as having "his hands among the Ætolians, but his soul in Peculation-town," so the soul of the curious man is at once in the mansions of the rich, and the cottages of the poor, and the courts of kings, and the bridal chambers of the newly married; he pries into everything, the affairs of foreigners, the affairs of princes, and sometimes not without danger. For just as if one were to taste aconite to investigate its properties, and kill oneself before one had discovered them, so those that pry into the troubles of great people ruin themselves before they get the knowledge they desire; even as those become blind who, neglecting the wide and general diffusion all over the earth of the sun's rays, impudently attempt to gaze at its orb and penetrate to its light. And so that was a wise answer of Philippides the Comic Poet, when King Lysimachus asked him on one occasion, "What would you like to have of mine?" "Anything, O king, but your secrets." For the pleasantest and finest things to be got from kings are public, as banquets, and riches, and festivities, and favours: but come not near any secret of theirs, pry not into it. There is no concealment of the joy of a prosperous monarch, or of his laugh when he is in a playful mood, or of any tokens of his goodwill and favour; but dreadful is what he conceals, his gloominess, his sternness, his reserve, his store of latent wrath, his 242meditation on stern revenge, his jealousy of his wife, or suspicion of his son, or doubt about the fidelity of a friend. Flee from this cloud that is so black and threatening, for when its hidden fury bursts forth, you will not fail to hear its thunder and see its lightning.

§ iv. Just like Cleon is mocked in the play615 for having "his hands among the Ætolians, but his soul in Corruption-town," the curious person finds their soul in the mansions of the rich, the homes of the poor, the courts of kings, and the boudoirs of the newlyweds; they pry into everything, from the lives of foreigners to the affairs of rulers, often risking their own safety. It's like tasting poison to learn about it and dying before you get any useful information. Those who dig into the issues of powerful individuals often destroy themselves before gaining the insight they seek; just like those who become blind for ignoring the sunlight's widespread presence and foolishly attempt to gaze directly at the sun. Philippides the Comic Poet gave a wise response when King Lysimachus once asked him, "What would you like to have from me?" He replied, "Anything, O king, but your secrets." The best things you can get from kings are public ones: feasts, wealth, celebrations, and favors—not their secrets. There's no hiding the joy of a successful king, his laughter during good times, or signs of his goodwill, but what he hides can be terrible—his sadness, harshness, restraint, repressed anger, jealousy of his wife, suspicion of his son, or doubts about a friend's loyalty. Stay away from that ominous and dark cloud; when its hidden rage is unleashed, you will definitely hear its thunder and see its lightning.

§ v. How shall you flee from it? Why, by dissipating and distracting your curiosity, by turning your soul to better and pleasanter objects: examine the phenomena of sky, and earth, and air, and sea. Are you by nature fond of gazing at little or great things? If at great, turn your attention to the sun, consider its rising and setting: view the changes of the moon, like the changes of our mortal life, see how it waxes and wanes,

§ v. How can you escape from it? You can do this by redirecting and distracting your curiosity, focusing your mind on better and more enjoyable things: look at the wonders of the sky, the earth, the air, and the sea. Are you naturally drawn to small things or big things? If you prefer the big, pay attention to the sun, think about its rising and setting: observe the changes of the moon, which reflect the ups and downs of our life, and see how it grows and shrinks.

"At first, it looks small and faint." Until it reveals its complete and glorious form, And when it has reached its peak, "Once more it diminishes, becomes small, and vanishes." 616

These are indeed Nature's secrets, but they bring no trouble on those that study them. But if you decline the study of great things, inspect with curiosity smaller matters, see how some plants flourish, are green and gay, and exhibit their beauty, all the year round, while others are sometimes gay like them, at other times, like some unthrift, run through their resources entirely, and are left bare and naked. Consider again their various shapes, how some produce oblong fruits, others angular, others smooth and round. But perhaps you will not care to pry into all this, since you will find nothing bad. If you must then ever bestow your time and attention on what is bad, as the serpent lives but in deadly matter, go to history, and turn your eye on the sum total of human misery. For there you will find "the falls of men, and murders of their lives,"617 rapes of women, attacks of slaves, treachery of friends, mixing of poisons, envyings, jealousies, "shipwrecks of families," and dethroning of princes. Sate and cloy your243self on these, you will by so doing vex and enrage none of your associates.

These are indeed Nature's secrets, but they don't cause any trouble for those who study them. If you choose not to explore great things, take a closer look at the smaller ones. Notice how some plants thrive, staying green and vibrant, showcasing their beauty all year long, while others occasionally flourish but eventually exhaust their resources and become bare. Consider their different shapes; some produce long fruits, others are angular, and some are smooth and round. But maybe you don't want to dig into all of this since you'll find nothing negative. If you must spend your time and energy on something bad, like a serpent that thrives only on poison, look to history and observe the sum of human suffering. There you'll see "the falls of men and murders of their lives,"617 rapes of women, assaults on slaves, betrayals of friends, poisonings, envy, jealousy, "shipwrecks of families," and the overthrow of princes. Indulge yourself in these topics, and you won’t annoy any of your friends.

§ vi. But it seems curiosity does not rejoice in stale evils, but only in fresh and recent ones, gladly viewing the spectacle of tragedies of yesterday, but backward in taking part in comic and festive scenes. And so the curious person is a languid and listless hearer to the narrator of a marriage, or sacrifice, or solemn procession, he says he has heard most of all that before, bids the narrator cut it short and come to the point; but if his visitor tell him of the violation of some girl, or the adultery of some married woman, or the disputes and intended litigation of brothers, he doesn't go to sleep then, nor pretend want of leisure,

§ vi. It seems that curiosity doesn't get excited about old tragedies, but rather about new and recent ones. People enjoy watching the dramas from yesterday but are less interested in participating in joyful or festive events. So, when someone narrates a marriage, a sacrifice, or a solemn procession, the curious listener tends to be disinterested and impatient, saying they’ve heard it all before and asking the storyteller to get to the important part. However, if the storyteller shares news about the violation of a girl, or the infidelity of a married woman, or the conflicts and planned lawsuits among brothers, the listener is wide awake and fully engaged.

"But he perks up his ears and asks for more."

And indeed those lines,

And those lines,

"Unfortunately! how much faster to mortals' ears" "Do bad news travel faster than good news?"

are truly said of curious people. For as cupping-glasses take away the worst blood, so the ears of curious people attract only the worst reports; or rather, as cities have certain ominous and gloomy gates, through which they conduct only condemned criminals, or convey filth and night soil, for nothing pure or holy has either ingress into or egress from them, so into the ears of curious people goes nothing good or elegant, but tales of murders travel and lodge there, wafting a whiff of unholy and obscene narrations.

are truly said of curious people. Just like cupping glasses remove the worst blood, curious people's ears only pick up the worst gossip; or rather, similar to cities that have dark and foreboding gates, through which they let in only condemned criminals or carry away waste, nothing pure or sacred enters or leaves them. The ears of curious individuals welcome nothing good or refined, only stories of murders that linger there, bringing a hint of unholy and crude narratives.

"And in my house, it's always heard alone." The sound of crying;

this is to the curious their one Muse and Siren, this the sweetest note they can hear. For curiosity desires to know what is hidden and secret; but no one conceals his good fortune, nay sometimes people even pretend to have such advantages as they do not really possess. So the curious man, eager to hear a history of what is bad, is possessed by the passion of malignity, which is brother to envy and jealousy. For envy is pain at another's blessings, and malignity is joy at another's misfortunes: and both proceed from the same savage and brutish vice, ill-nature.

this is for the curious, their one Muse and Siren, this the sweetest sound they can hear. Curiosity wants to uncover what is hidden and secret; yet no one hides their good fortune, and sometimes people even pretend to have benefits they don’t actually have. So, the curious person, eager to hear a story about what is bad, is driven by the desire for malice, which is akin to envy and jealousy. Envy is the pain felt at someone else's blessings, and malice is the pleasure taken in another's misfortunes: both stem from the same cruel and brutal flaw, bad character.

244§ vii. But so unpleasant is it to everybody to have his private ills brought to light, that many have died rather than acquaint the doctors with their secret ailments. For suppose Herophilus, or Erasistratus, or even Æsculapius himself during his sojourn on earth, had gone with their drugs and surgical instruments from house to house, to inquire what man had a fistula in ano, or what woman had a cancer in her womb;—and yet their curiosity would have been professional618—who would not have driven them away from their house, for not waiting till they were sent for, and for coming without being asked to spy out their neighbours' ailments? But curious people pry into these and even worse matters, not from a desire to heal them, but only to expose them to others, which makes them deservedly hated. For we are not vexed and mortified with custom-house officers when they levy toll on goods bona fide imported, but only when they seek for contraband articles, and rip up bags and packages: and yet the law allows them to do even this, and sometimes it is injurious to them not to do so. But curious people abandon and neglect their own affairs, and are busy about their neighbours' concerns. Seldom do they go into the country, for they do not care for its quiet and stillness and solitude, but if once in a way they do go there, they look more at their neighbours' vines than their own, and inquire how many cows of their neighbour have died, or how much of his wine has turned sour, and when they are satisfied on these points they soon return to town again. But the genuine countryman does not willingly listen to any rumour that chances to come from the town, for he quotes the following lines,

244§ vii. But it’s so unpleasant for everyone to have their personal issues exposed that many people would rather die than share their private health problems with doctors. Imagine if Herophilus, or Erasistratus, or even Asclepius himself, while he was alive, went door to door with their medical tools, asking who had a fistula or which woman had cancer. Even though their curiosity would be professional618—who wouldn’t send them away for coming without being invited and snooping into their neighbors' health issues? Yet, nosy people dig into these and even worse topics, not out of a wish to help, but just to gossip about others, which rightfully earns them disdain. We don't get annoyed by customs officials when they collect tariffs on legitimate goods, only when they look for contraband and rip apart bags and packages. The law permits them to do so, and sometimes it's actually harmful if they don’t. However, nosy individuals ignore their own problems and focus instead on those of their neighbors. They rarely go to the countryside because they don’t appreciate its peace and tranquility, but if they do venture there, they’re more interested in their neighbors' crops than their own. They ask about how many cows a neighbor lost or how much wine has spoiled, and once they’ve satisfied their curiosity, they quickly head back to town. The true country dweller, on the other hand, doesn’t care for gossip coming from the city, for he quotes the following lines,

"Even with a shovel in hand, he’ll explain the terms." On which peace was reached: all these things The cursed guy walks around and snoops into.

§ viii. But curious people shun the country as stale and dull and too quiet, and push into warehouses and markets and harbours, asking, "Any news? Were you not in the market in the forenoon?" and sometimes receiving for answer, "What then? Do you think things in the town change every three hours?" Notwithstanding if any245one brings any news, he'll get off his horse, and embrace him, and kiss him, and stand to listen. If however the person who meets him says he has no news, he will say somewhat peevishly, "No news, Sir? Have you not been in the market? Did you not pass by the officers' quarters? Did you exchange no words with those that have just arrived from Italy?" To stop such people the Locrian authorities had an excellent rule; they fined everyone coming from abroad who asked what the news was. For as cooks pray for plenty of meat, and fishmongers for shoals of fish, so curious people pray for shoals of trouble, and plenty of business, and innovations and changes, that they may have something to hunt after and tittle-tattle about. Well also was it in Charondas, the legislator of the people of Thurii,619 to forbid any of the citizens but adulterers and curious persons to be ridiculed on the stage. Adultery itself indeed seems to be only the fruit of curiosity about another man's pleasures, and an inquiring and prying into things kept close and hidden from the world; while curiosity is a tampering with and seduction of and revealing the nakedness of secrets.620

§ viii. But curious people avoid the countryside because they find it boring, quiet, and lifeless, and they crowd into warehouses, markets, and docks, asking, "Any news? Weren't you at the market this morning?" Sometimes the response is, "So what? Do you think everything in town changes every three hours?" However, if someone does bring news, he will get off his horse, hug him, kiss him, and stand ready to listen. If the person he meets says he has no news, he will impatiently reply, "No news, Sir? Haven't you been to the market? Didn’t you pass by the officers' quarters? Did you not speak with anyone who just arrived from Italy?" To keep these people in check, the Locrian authorities had an effective rule: they fined anyone coming from abroad who asked about the news. Just as cooks pray for abundant meat and fishmongers for plentiful fish, curious people hope for a lot of drama, business, and change, so they have something to chase after and gossip about. It was also true in Charondas, the lawgiver of the people of Thurii,619 that only adulterers and nosy individuals were allowed to be mocked on stage. Adultery seems to stem from curiosity about someone else's pleasures and a desire to pry into things kept secret from the world, while curiosity involves meddling with, seducing, and exposing the hidden truths.620

§ ix. As it is likely that much learning will produce wordiness, and so Pythagoras enjoined five years' silence on his scholars, calling it a truce from words,621 so defamation of character is sure to go with curiosity. For what people are glad to hear they are glad to talk about, and what they eagerly pick up from others they joyfully retail to others. And so, amongst the other mischiefs of curiosity, the disease runs counter to their desires; for all people fight shy of them, and conceal their affairs from them, and neither care to do or say anything in their presence, but defer consultations, and put off investigations, till such people are out of the way; and if, when some secret is just about to be uttered, or some important business is 246just about to be arranged, some curious man happen to pop in, they are mum at once and reserved, as one puts away fish if the cat is about; and so frequently things seen and talked about by all the rest of the world are unknown only to them. For the same reason the curious person never gets the confidence of anybody. For we would rather entrust our letters and papers and seals to slaves and strangers than to curious friends and intimates. The famous Bellerophon,622 though he carried letters against his life, opened them not, but abstained from reading the letter to the king, as he had refused to sell his honour to Proetus' wife, so great was his continence.623 For curiosity and adultery both come from incontinence, and to the latter is added monstrous folly and insanity. For to pass by so many common and public women, and to intrude oneself on some married woman,624 who is sure to be more costly, and possibly less pretty to boot, is the acme of madness. Yet such is the conduct of curious people. They neglect many gay sights, fail to hear much that would be well worth hearing, lose much fine sport and pastime, to break open private letters, to put their ears to their neighbour's walls, and to whisper to their slaves and women-servants, practices always low, and frequently dangerous.

§ ix. Since it’s likely that extensive learning can lead to excessive talk, Pythagoras required his students to remain silent for five years, considering it a break from words,621 and so reputation damage often accompanies curiosity. People love discussing what they’re eager to hear, and they happily share what they pick up from others. Thus, among the many negative aspects of curiosity, it goes against their wishes; people tend to avoid them, keeping their personal matters hidden, and don’t feel comfortable saying or doing anything in their presence. They postpone discussions and hold off on investigations until such individuals are gone. If a curious person suddenly interrupts just as a secret is about to be revealed or an important matter is about to be settled, everyone immediately clams up, like someone hiding fish from a cat. Often, what everyone else knows and discusses is completely unknown to them. For this reason, the curious person never gains anyone's trust. We’d rather confide our letters, documents, and seals to strangers than to nosy friends and acquaintances. The famous Bellerophon,622 even though he carried letters that could jeopardize his life, did not open them and refrained from reading the letter to the king, choosing to uphold his honor against Proetus' wife, demonstrating remarkable self-control.623 Both curiosity and infidelity stem from a lack of self-control, with infidelity adding to it a degree of foolishness and madness. It’s madness to overlook numerous attractive and available partners and instead pursue a married woman,624 who will likely be more expensive and perhaps less attractive as well. Yet this is how curious people behave. They pass up many enjoyable experiences, miss out on things worth listening to, and lose out on fun activities just to pry open private letters, listen through their neighbors’ walls, and gossip with their servants, actions that are always degrading and often perilous.

§ x. It will be exceedingly useful, therefore, to deter the curious from these propensities, for them to remember their past experience. Simonides used to say that he occasionally opened two chests for rewards and thanks that he had by him, and found the one full for rewards, but the one for thanks always empty.625 So if anyone were to open occasionally the stores that curiosity had amassed, and observe what a cargo there was of useless and idle and unlovely things, perhaps the sight of all this poor stuff would inspire him with disgust. Suppose someone, in studying the writings of the ancients, were to pick out only their worst passages, and compile them into a volume, 247as Homer's imperfect lines, and the solecisms of the tragedians, and Archilochus' indecent and bitter railings against women, by which he so exposed himself, would he not be worthy of the curse of the tragedian,

§ x. It would be really helpful, then, to discourage curiosity about these tendencies by reflecting on past experiences. Simonides used to say that he sometimes opened two chests—one for rewards and one for thanks—and found the rewards chest full, but the thanks chest always empty.625 So if someone were to occasionally open the stores that curiosity had gathered and see how much useless, idle, and unattractive stuff was there, perhaps they'd feel disgusted by the sight of all this junk. Imagine if someone, while studying ancient writings, only picked out their worst passages and compiled them into a book, like Homer’s flawed lines, the mistakes of the tragedians, and Archilochus' rude and harsh insults against women, which made him look so bad; wouldn’t that person deserve the curse of the tragedian?

"Do you want to perish, compiler of your neighbors' problems?"

And independently of such a curse, the piling up of other people's misdoings is indecent and useless, and like the town which Philip founded and filled with the vilest and most dissolute wretches, and called Rogue Town. Curious persons, indeed, making a collection of the faults and errors and solecisms, not of lines or poems but of people's lives, render their memory a most inelegant and unlovely register of dark deeds. Just as there are in Rome some people who care nothing for pictures and statues, or even handsome boys or women exposed for sale, but haunt the monster-market, and make eager inquiries about people who have no calves, or three eyes, or arms like weasels, or heads like ostriches, and look about for some

And regardless of such a curse, stacking up other people's wrongdoings is inappropriate and pointless, much like the town that Philip established and filled with the most despicable and immoral people, which he named Rogue Town. It's odd how some people collect faults and mistakes, not of poems or verses but of people's lives, creating a really unattractive and unappealing record of dark actions. Just like there are folks in Rome who have no interest in paintings or sculptures, or even attractive boys or women for sale, but instead crowd around the monster market, eagerly asking about people who are missing calves, or have three eyes, or arms like weasels, or heads like ostriches, and then look around for some

"Unnatural monster like the Minotaur," __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

and for a time are greatly captivated with them, but if anyone continually gazes at such sights, they will soon give him satiety and disgust; so let those who curiously inquire into the errors and faults of life, and disgraces of families, and disorders in other people's houses, first remember what little favour or advantage such prying has brought them on previous occasions.

and for a while are really fascinated by them, but if someone keeps staring at such things, they will quickly lead to boredom and disgust; so let those who are curious about the mistakes and faults of life, the shame of families, and the chaos in other people's lives, first think about what little benefit or advantage this kind of snooping has ever given them in the past.

§ xi. Habit will be of the utmost importance in stopping this propensity, if we begin early to practise self-control in respect to it, for as the disease increases by habit and degrees, so will its cure, as we shall see when we discuss the necessary discipline. In the first place, let us begin with the most trifling and unimportant matters. What hardship will it be when we walk abroad not to read the epitaphs on graves, or what detriment shall we suffer by not glancing at the inscriptions on walls in the public walks? Let us reflect that there is nothing useful or pleasant for us in these notices, which only record that so-and-so248 remembered so-and-so out of gratitude, and, "Here lies the best of friends," and much poor stuff of that kind;627 which indeed do not seem to do much harm, except indirectly, to those that read them, by engendering the practice of curiosity about things immaterial. And as huntsmen do not allow the hounds to follow any scent and run where they please, but check and restrain them in leashes, keeping their sense of smell pure and fresh for the object of their chase, that they may the keener dart on their tracks, "following up the traces of the unfortunate beasts by their scent," so we must check and repress the sallies and excursions of the curious man to every object of interest, whether of sight or hearing, and confine him to what is useful. For as eagles and lions on the prowl keep their claws sheathed that they may not lose their edge and sharpness, so, when we remember that curiosity for learning has also its edge and keenness, let us not entirely expend or blunt it on inferior objects.

§ xi. Developing habits will be crucial in curbing this tendency if we start practicing self-control early on. Just as the issue worsens with habit and over time, so will the solution, as we’ll see when we discuss the necessary discipline. First, let's begin with the most trivial and insignificant things. What hardship is it to walk outside and not read the epitaphs on graves? What harm do we face by not glancing at the inscriptions on walls along public paths? We should realize that there’s nothing useful or enjoyable in these messages, which merely state that someone remembered someone else out of gratitude, like “Here lies the best of friends,” and other similar phrases; 248 these don’t seem to cause much harm, except indirectly, to those who read them, by fostering a curiosity about irrelevant things. Just as hunters keep their dogs from following any scent and running off on their own, but rather check and restrain them on leashes to keep their sense of smell sharp and focused on the chase, we too must rein in our curiosity toward any interesting object, whether it’s something we see or hear, and limit ourselves to what is truly useful. Just as eagles and lions protect their claws to maintain their sharpness, we should also remember that our curiosity for knowledge has its own edge and intensity, and we shouldn't waste or dull it on lesser matters.

§ xii. Next let us accustom ourselves when we pass a strange house not to look inside at the door, or curiously inspect the interior, as if we were going to pilfer something, remembering always that saying of Xenocrates, that it is all one whether one puts one's feet or eyes in another person's house. For such prying is neither honourable, nor comely, nor even agreeable.

§ xii. Next, let's get into the habit of not peeking inside a strange house when we walk by, or looking around the interior as if we're planning to steal something. We should always remember Xenocrates' saying that it doesn't matter whether we put our feet or our eyes in someone else's home. Such snooping is neither respectable, nor appropriate, nor even pleasant.

"Stranger, you'll see unexpected sights."

For such is generally the condition inside houses, utensils kicking about, maids lolling about, no work going on, nothing to please the eye; and moreover such side glances, and stray shots as it were, distort the soul, and are unhandsome, and the practice is a pernicious one. When Diogenes saw Dioxippus, a victor at Olympia, driving up in his chariot and unable to take his eyes off a handsome woman who was watching the procession, but still turning round and casting sheep's eyes at her, he said, "See you yon athlete straining his neck to look at a girl?" And similarly you may see curious people twisting and straining 249their necks at every spectacle alike, from the habit and practice of turning their eyes in all directions. And I think the senses ought not to rove about, like an ill-trained maid, when sent on an errand by the soul, but to do their business, and then return quickly with the answer, and afterwards to keep within the bounds of reason, and obey her behests. But it is like those lines of Sophocles,

For this is usually the state inside homes: things scattered everywhere, maids lounging around, no work being done, nothing pleasing to the eye; and on top of that, those glances and wandering looks can distort the soul, are unattractive, and the habit is harmful. When Diogenes saw Dioxippus, an Olympic champion, arriving in his chariot and unable to take his eyes off a beautiful woman watching the parade while still turning around and glancing at her, he remarked, "Do you see that athlete straining his neck to look at a girl?" Similarly, you can observe curious people twisting and straining 249their necks at every spectacle, due to the habit of looking around in every direction. I believe the senses shouldn't wander aimlessly like an untrained maid sent on an errand by the soul, but should do their job and quickly return with the answer, then remain within the limits of reason and follow her commands. But it's like those lines of Sophocles,

"Then the Ænianian's horses ran off, Unmanageable indeed; __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

for so the senses not having, as we said, right training and practice, often run away, and drag reason along with them, and plunge her into unlawful excesses. And so, though that story about Democritus is false, that he purposely destroyed his eyesight by the reflection from burning-glasses (as people sometimes shut up windows that look into the street), that they might not disturb him by frequently calling off his attention to external things, but allow him to confine himself to purely intellectual matters, yet it is very true in every case that those who use the mind most are least acted upon by the senses. And so the philosophers erected their places for study as far as possible from towns, and called Night the time propitious to thought,629 thinking quiet and withdrawal from worldly distractions a great help towards meditating upon and solving the problems of life.

For the senses, lacking proper training and practice, often take over and pull reason along, leading it into reckless behavior. Although the story about Democritus is not true—claiming he intentionally blinded himself with reflections from burning glasses to avoid distractions from the outside world—we find that it's often true that those who engage their minds the most are less influenced by their senses. This is why philosophers built their study spaces far from cities and considered Night the best time for contemplation, believing that a peaceful environment away from distractions greatly aids in reflecting on and resolving life's challenges.

§ xiii. Moreover, when men are abusing and reviling one another in the market-place, it is not very difficult or tiresome not to go near them; or if a tumultuous concourse of people crowd together, to remain seated; or to get up and go away, if you are not master of yourself. For you will gain no advantage by mixing yourself up with curious people: but you will derive the greatest benefit from putting a force upon your inclinations, and bridling your curiosity, and accustoming it to obey reason. Afterwards it will be well to extend the practice still further, and not to go to the theatre when some fine piece is performing, and if your friends invite you to see some dancer or actor to decline, and, if there is some shouting 250in the stadium and hippodrome, not even to turn your head to look what is up. For as Socrates advised people to abstain from food that made them eat when they were not hungry, and from drinks that made them drink when they were not thirsty, so ought we also to shun and flee from those objects of interest, whether to eye or ear, that master us and attract us when we stand in no need of them. Thus Cyrus would not look at Panthea, but when Araspes told him that her beauty was well worth inspection, he replied, "For that very reason must I the more abstain from seeing her, for if at your persuasion I were to pay her a visit, perhaps she would persuade me to visit her again when I could ill spare the time, so that I might neglect important business to sit with her and gaze on her charms."630 Similarly Alexander would not see the wife of Darius, who was reputed to be very beautiful, but visited her mother who was old, and would not venture to look upon the young and handsome queen. We on the contrary peep into women's litters, and hang about their windows, and think we do no harm, though we thus make our curiosity a loop-hole631 for all manner of vice.

§ xiii. Moreover, when people are insulting and shouting at each other in the marketplace, it’s not very hard or draining to avoid them; or if a chaotic crowd gathers, you can stay seated; or you can get up and leave if you can't control yourself. You won't benefit from getting involved with nosy people; instead, you'll gain the most by pushing back against your urges, keeping your curiosity in check, and training it to follow reason. After that, it’s wise to take this practice further and skip the theatre when a great show is on, and if your friends invite you to watch a dancer or actor, politely say no. And if there's yelling in the stadium or hippodrome, don’t even turn your head to see what’s happening. Just as Socrates advised people to avoid food that made them eat when they weren’t hungry and drinks that made them drink when they weren’t thirsty, we should also steer clear of those things that catch our attention, whether by sight or sound, that control us and draw us in when we don’t need them. Thus, Cyrus wouldn’t look at Panthea, but when Araspes told him that her beauty was worth seeing, he replied, "For that very reason, I must avoid seeing her even more, because if I visit her at your urging, she might convince me to come back again when I really can’t spare the time, causing me to neglect important matters just to sit with her and admire her beauty." Similarly, Alexander wouldn't look at Darius's wife, who was known to be very beautiful, but he did visit her old mother instead and avoided gazing at the young and attractive queen. In contrast, we peek into women's carriages and loiter around their windows, thinking we’re not doing any harm, even as we allow our curiosity to create an opening for all sorts of wrongdoing.

§ xiv. Moreover, as it is of great help to fair dealing sometimes not to seize some honest gain, that you may accustom yourself as far as possible to flee from unjust gains, and as it makes greatly for virtue to abstain sometimes from your own wife, that you may not ever be tempted by another woman, so, applying the habit to curiosity, try not to see and hear at times all that goes on in your own house even, and if anyone wishes to tell you anything about it give him the go-by, and decline to hear him. For it was nothing but his curiosity that involved Œdipus in his extreme calamities: for it was to try and find out his extraction that he left Corinth and met Laius, and killed him, and got his kingdom, and married his own mother, and when he then seemed at the acme of felicity, he must needs make further inquiries about himself; and though his wife tried to prevent him, he none the less com251pelled the old man that had been an eye-witness of the deed to tell him all the circumstances of it, and though he long suspected how the story would end, yet when the old man cried out,

§ xiv. Additionally, it can be very helpful in fair dealings to sometimes forgo honest gains, allowing yourself to become accustomed to avoiding unjust profits. Likewise, it benefits your character to occasionally abstain from your own wife to prevent being tempted by another woman. Similarly, when it comes to curiosity, try not to see or hear everything that happens in your own home. If someone wants to share information about it, brush them off and choose not to listen. After all, it was mere curiosity that led Œdipus to extreme misfortune: in his quest to uncover his origins, he left Corinth, encountered Laius, killed him, gained the throne, and married his own mother. When he appeared to be at the height of happiness, he still felt compelled to dig deeper into his past; despite his wife trying to stop him, he insisted on making the old man who witnessed his deeds reveal all the details. Even though he had long suspected how the story would end, when the old man shouted,

"Unfortunately, the awful story I have to share,"

so inflamed was he with curiosity and trembling with impatience, that he replied,

so fired up was he with curiosity and shaking with impatience, that he replied,

"I need to listen as well, so I will hear it now." 632

So bitter-sweet and uncontrollable is the itch of curiosity, like a sore, shedding its blood when lanced. But he that is free from this disease, and calm by nature, being ignorant of many unpleasant things, may say,

So bitter-sweet and uncontrollable is the itch of curiosity, like a sore, bleeding when it's pricked. But someone who is free from this affliction and naturally calm, unaware of many unpleasant things, might say,

"Holy oblivion of all human troubles, What wisdom do you bring!"633

§ xv. We ought therefore also to accustom ourselves, when we receive a letter, not to be in a tremendous hurry about breaking the seal, as most people are, even tearing it open with their teeth if their hands are slow; nor to rise from our seat and run up to meet him, if a messenger comes; and if a friend says, "I have some news to tell you," we ought to say, "I had rather you had something useful or advantageous to tell me." When I was on one occasion lecturing at Rome, one of my audience was the well-known Rusticus, whom the Emperor Domitian afterwards had put to death through envy of his glory, and a soldier came in in the middle and brought him a letter from the Emperor, and silence ensuing, and I stopping that he might have time to read his letter, he would not, and did not open it till I had finished my lecture, and the audience had dispersed; so that everybody marvelled at his self-control. But whenever anyone who has power feeds his curiosity till it is strong and vehement, he can no longer easily control it, when it hurries him on to illicit acts, from force of habit; and such people open their friends' letters, thrust themselves in at private meetings, become spectators of rites 252they ought not to witness, enter holy grounds they ought not to, and pry into the lives and conversations of kings.

§ xv. We should also train ourselves, when we receive a letter, not to rush to break the seal like most people do, even tearing it open with their teeth if their hands are too slow; nor should we get up from our seat and dash over to greet a messenger who arrives; and if a friend says, "I have some news for you," we should respond, "I’d rather you had something useful or helpful to share." One time while I was lecturing in Rome, one of my audience members was the well-known Rusticus, who was later executed by Emperor Domitian out of envy for his success. During my lecture, a soldier came in and brought him a letter from the Emperor, and when silence fell, I paused so he could read it, but he chose not to open it until I finished my lecture and the audience had left; everyone was amazed by his self-control. However, when someone in power lets their curiosity grow strong and overwhelming, they find it hard to manage it when it pushes them toward inappropriate actions, out of habit; such people end up opening their friends’ letters, intruding into private meetings, witnessing rituals 252 they should not see, entering sacred places they shouldn’t, and spying on the lives and discussions of kings.

§ xvi. Indeed tyrants themselves, who must know all things, are made unpopular by no class more than by their spies634 and talebearers. Darius in his youth, when he mistrusted his own powers, and suspected and feared everybody, was the first who employed spies; and the Dionysiuses introduced them at Syracuse: but in a revolution they were the first that the Syracusans took and tortured to death. Indeed informers are of the same tribe and family as curious people. However informers only investigate wicked acts or plots, but curious people pry into and publish abroad the involuntary misfortunes of their neighbours. And it is said that impious people first got their name from curiosity, for it seems there was a mighty famine at Athens, and those people that had wheat not producing it, but grinding it stealthily by night in their houses, some of their neighbours went about and noticed the noise of the mills grinding, and so they got their name.635 This also is the origin of the well-known Greek word for informer, (Sycophant, quasi Fig-informer), for when the people were forbidden to export figs, those who informed against those who did were called Fig-informers. It is well worth the while of curious people to give their attention to this, that they may be ashamed of having any similarity or connection in habit with a class of people so universally hated and disliked as informers.

§ xvi. In fact, tyrants themselves, who should be aware of everything, are most disliked by their spies634 and gossipers. Darius, in his younger days, uncertain of his own abilities and suspicious of everyone, was the first to use spies; and the Dionysiuses brought them to Syracuse. But during a revolution, the Syracusans were the first to capture and torture them. Informers are just like nosy people. However, informers only dig into wicked deeds or plots, while nosy people invade and spread the private misfortunes of their neighbors. It’s said that impious people were named from their curiosity, as there was a severe famine in Athens, and those with wheat would secretly grind it at night in their homes. Some nosy neighbors heard the grinding of the mills, which led to this name.635 This is also where the well-known Greek word for informer, (Sycophant, quasi Fig-informer), comes from; when the people were banned from exporting figs, those who reported on anyone who did were called Fig-informers. It’s worth noting for nosy people to consider this, so they may feel ashamed for sharing any similarity or connection with a group of people that is universally hated and disliked, like informers.

608 Jeremy Taylor has largely borrowed from this Treatise in his "Holy Living," chap. ii. § v. Of Modesty.

608 Jeremy Taylor has mostly taken inspiration from this Treatise in his "Holy Living," chap. ii. § v. Of Modesty.

609 Chæronea in Bœotia.

Chæronea in Boeotia.

610 Lines from some comic poet, no doubt.

610 Lines from a comic poet, for sure.

611 "Œconomicus," cap. viii.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Economicus," ch. 8.

612 The mother of Œdipus, better known as "Jocasta."

612 The mother of Oedipus, more commonly known as "Jocasta."

613 Homer, "Odyssey," xi. 278. Epicaste hung herself.

613 Homer, "Odyssey," xi. 278. Epicaste committed suicide.

614 "οἰκίσκῳ corrigit Valekenarius ad Herodot. p. 557."—Wyttenbach.

614 "corrects in a small house Valekenarius to Herodotus. p. 557."—Wyttenbach.

615 Aristophanes, "Equites," 79.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Aristophanes, "Knights," 79.

616 Sophocles, Fragm. 713. The lines are quoted more fully by our author in his "Lives," p. 911. There are there four preceding lines that compare human life to the moon's changes.

616 Sophocles, Fragm. 713. The lines are quoted more fully by our author in his "Lives," p. 911. There are four previous lines that compare human life to the phases of the moon.

617 Æschylus, "Supplices," 937.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Aeschylus, "Supplices," 937.

618 All three being eminent doctors.

All three are renowned doctors.

619 "Intelligo Charondam."—Xylander.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Intelligo Charondam."—Xylander.

620 Plutarch wants to show that curiosity and adultery are really the same vice in principle. Hence his imagery here. Jeremy Taylor has very beautifully dealt with this passage, "Holy Living," chap. ii. § v. I cannot pretend to his felicity of language. Thus Plutarch makes adultery mere curiosity, and curiosity a sort of adultery in regard to secrets. A profoundly ethical and moral view. Compare § ix.

620 Plutarch wants to show that curiosity and adultery are really the same flaw at their core. That's what his imagery is about here. Jeremy Taylor has beautifully explored this passage in "Holy Living," chap. ii. § v. I can't match his eloquence. So, Plutarch equates adultery with simple curiosity, and curiosity as a kind of adultery concerning secrets. It's a deep reflection on ethics and morality. Compare § ix.

621 Compare Lucian's ἐχεγλωττία, after ἐχεχειρία (armistice), Lexiph. 9.

621 Compare Lucian's ἐχεγλωττία, after ἐχεχειρία (armistice), Lexiph. 9.

622 See the story in Homer, "Iliad," vi. 155 sq.

622 Check out the story in Homer's "Iliad," vi. 155 sq.

623 Or self-control.

Or self-control.

624 Literally, some woman shut up, or enclosed.

624 Literally, some woman kept quiet, or closed in.

625 See also our author's "On those who are punished by the Deity late," § xi.

625 Check out our author's "On those who are punished by the Deity late," § xi.

626 See Euripides, Fragm., 389. Also Plutarch's "Theseus," cap. xv.

626 See Euripides, Fragm., 389. Also Plutarch's "Theseus," chapter 15.

627 Plutarch rather reminds one, in his evident contempt for Epitaphs, of the cynic who asked, "Where are all the bad people buried?" Where indeed?

627 Plutarch seems to reflect a clear disdain for Epitaphs, similar to the cynic who questioned, "Where are all the bad people buried?" Where exactly?

628 Sophocles, "Electra," 724, 725.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Sophocles, "Electra," 724, 725.

629 euphronê, a stock phrase for night, is here defined.

629 euphronê, a common term for night, is defined here.

630 "Historia exstat initio libri quinti Cyropædiæ."—Reiske.

630 "The history is found at the beginning of the fifth book of the Cyropedia."—Reiske.

631 Literally, "slippery and prone to." For the metaphor of "slippery" compare Horace, "Odes," i. 19-8, "Et vultus nimium lubricus adspici."

631 Literally, "slippery and likely to." For the metaphor of "slippery," compare Horace, "Odes," i. 19-8, "Et vultus nimium lubricus adspici."

632 This and the line above are in Sophocles, "Œdipus Tyrannus," 1169, 1170.

632 This and the line above are from Sophocles' "Oedipus Tyrannus," lines 1169, 1170.

633 Euripides, "Orestes," 213.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Orestes," 213.

634 Literally, ears.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Seriously, ears.

635 The paronomasia is as follows. The word for impious people is supposed to mean listeners to mills grinding.

635 The wordplay is as follows. The term for impious people is thought to mean listeners to mills grinding.


ON SHYNESS.636

§ i. Some of the things that grow on the earth are in their nature wild and barren and injurious to the growth 253of seeds and plants, yet those who till the ground consider them indications not of a bad soil but of a rich and fat one;637 so also there are passions of the soul that are not good, yet are as it were offshoots of a good disposition, and one likely to improve with good advice. Among these I class shyness, no bad sign in itself, though it affords occasion to vice. For the modest oftentimes plunge into the same excesses as the shameless, but then they are pained and grieved at them, and not pleased like the others. For the shameless person is quite apathetic at what is disgraceful, while the modest person is easily affected even at the very appearance of it. Shyness is in fact an excess of modesty. And thus it is called shamefacedness, because the face exhibits the changes of the mind. For as dejection is defined to be the grief that makes people look on the ground, so shamefacedness is that shyness that cannot look people in the face. And so the orator said the shameless person had not pupils638 in his eyes but harlots. The bashful person on the other hand shows his delicacy and effeminacy of soul in his countenance, and palliates his weakness, which exposes him to defeat at the hands of the impudent, by the name of modesty. Cato used to say he was better pleased with those lads that blushed than with those that turned pale, rightly teaching us to fear censure more than labour,639 and suspicion than danger. However we must avoid too much timidity and fear of censure, since many have played the coward, and abandoned noble ventures, more from fear of a bad name than of the dangers to be undergone, not being able to bear a bad reputation.

§ i. Some of the things that grow on the earth are naturally wild, unproductive, and harmful to the growth of seeds and plants. However, those who cultivate the land see them not as a sign of poor soil, but as an indication of rich and fertile ground;637 similarly, there are emotions in the soul that aren't good, yet they can be seen as signs of a good disposition that has the potential to improve with good guidance. I categorize shyness among these emotions; it's not a bad sign in itself, even though it can lead to wrongdoing. Modest people often find themselves falling into the same excesses as those who are shameless, but they feel pained and upset by their actions, unlike the latter, who feel no shame. A shameless person is indifferent to disgrace, while a modest person is easily disturbed by even the appearance of it. Shyness is, in fact, an excess of modesty. That's why it’s called shamefacedness, as the face reflects the changing emotions of the mind. Just as dejection is described as the sorrow that makes people look down, shamefacedness is the shyness that prevents someone from meeting others’ gaze. Thus, the orator mentioned that the shameless person has not pupils in his eyes, but harlots. On the other hand, the bashful person reveals his sensitivity and weakness of spirit through his expression, masking his vulnerability— which makes him susceptible to the bold—under the guise of modesty. Cato often said he preferred boys who blushed over those who turned pale, rightly teaching us to fear criticism more than hard work,639 and suspicion more than actual danger. Nonetheless, we must steer clear of excessive timidity and fear of criticism, as many have acted cowardly and abandoned noble pursuits more out of fear of a bad reputation than the dangers they faced, unable to tolerate being thought poorly of.

§ ii. As we must not disregard their weakness, so neither again must we praise that rigid and stubborn insensibility, "that recklessness and frantic energy to rush anywhere, that seemed like a dog's courage in Anaxarchus."640 But we must contrive a harmonious blending of the two, that shall remove the shamelessness of pertinacity, and the weakness of excessive modesty; seeing its cure is

§ ii. While we shouldn't overlook their weaknesses, we also shouldn't admire that inflexible and stubborn insensitivity, "that recklessness and frantic energy to rush anywhere, that seemed like a dog's courage in Anaxarchus."640 Instead, we need to find a balanced mix of the two that eliminates the shamelessness of stubbornness and the weakness of excessive modesty; recognizing that its solution is

difficult, and the correction of such excesses not without danger. For as the husbandman, in rooting up some wild and useless weed, at once plunges his spade vigorously into the ground, and digs it up by the root, or burns it with fire, but if he has to do with a vine that needs pruning, or some apple-tree, or olive, he puts his hand to it very carefully, being afraid of injuring any sound part; so the philosopher, eradicating from the soul of the young man that ignoble and untractable weed, envy, or unseasonable avarice, or amputating the excessive love of pleasure, may bandage and draw blood, make deep incision, and leave scars: but if he has to apply reason as a corrective to a tender and delicate part of the soul, such as shyness and bashfulness, he is careful that he may not inadvertently root up modesty as well. For nurses who are often rubbing the dirt off their infants sometimes tear their flesh and put them to torture. We ought not therefore, by rubbing off the shyness of youths too much, to make them too careless and contemptuous; but as those that pull down houses close to temples prop up the adjacent parts, so in trying to get rid of shyness we must not eradicate with it the virtues akin to it, as modesty and meekness and mildness, by which it insinuates itself and becomes part of a man's character, flattering the bashful man that he has a nature courteous and civil and affable, and not hard as flint or self-willed. And so the Stoics from the outset verbally distinguished shame and shyness from modesty, that they might not by identity of name give the vice opportunity to inflict harm. But let it be granted to us to use the words indiscriminately, following indeed the example of Homer. For he said,

It's challenging to correct these issues without causing harm. Just like a gardener who aggressively digs up a wild, useless weed, plunging his spade into the ground to uproot it or burning it away, if he encounters a vine that needs pruning or a fruit tree like an apple or olive, he approaches it carefully, mindful not to damage any healthy parts. Similarly, when a philosopher works to eliminate envy, excessive greed, or the extreme love of pleasure from a young person's soul, he may cause some pain, make deep cuts, and leave scars. But when he needs to apply reason to a sensitive part of the soul, like shyness or bashfulness, he must be careful not to inadvertently destroy the related virtue of modesty. Nurses, while cleaning off dirt from babies, sometimes cause them harm by injuring their delicate skin. Therefore, we should avoid excessively rubbing off the shyness in young people, which could lead them to become careless and disrespectful. Like builders who support the structures near temples when tearing down nearby houses, when addressing shyness, we must also protect the virtues associated with it, such as modesty, meekness, and gentleness. These virtues help it integrate into a person's character, giving the shy individual the impression of being courteous, civil, and approachable rather than harsh or obstinate. The Stoics clearly distinguished between shame and shyness from modesty, so they wouldn’t allow the vice to cause any harm through confusion of terms. However, let’s allow ourselves to use these words interchangeably, following the example of Homer. For he said,

"Modesty can both help and hurt men;"641

and he did well to mention the harm it does first. For it becomes advantageous only through reason's curtailing its excess, and reducing it to moderate proportions.

and he was right to point out the damage it causes first. Because it only becomes beneficial when reason limits its excess and brings it down to a manageable level.

§ iii. In the first place, then, the person who is afflicted with shyness ought to be persuaded that he suffers from an injurious disease, and that nothing injurious 255 can be good: nor must he be wheedled and tickled with the praise of being called a nice and jolly fellow rather than being styled lofty and dignified and just; nor, like Pegasus in Euripides, "who stooped and crouched lower than he wished"642 to take up his rider Bellerophon, must he humble himself and grant whatever favours are asked him, fearing to be called hard and ungentle. They say that the Egyptian Bocchoris, who was by nature very severe, had an asp sent him by Isis, which coiled round his head, and shaded him from above, that he might judge righteously. Bashfulness on the contrary, like a dead weight on languid and effeminate persons, not daring to refuse or contradict anybody, makes jurors deliver unjust verdicts, and shuts the mouth of counsellors, and makes people say and do many things against their wish; and so the most headstrong person is always master and lord of such, through his own impudence prevailing against their modesty. So bashfulness, like soft and sloping ground, being unable to repel or avert any attack, lies open to the most shameful acts and passions. It is a bad guardian of youth, as Brutus said he didn't think that person had spent his youth well who had not learnt how to say No. It is a bad duenna of the bridal bed and of women's apartments, as the penitent adultress in Sophocles said to her seducer,

§ iii. First of all, someone who suffers from shyness needs to be convinced that it is a harmful condition, and nothing harmful can be good. They shouldn’t be flattered with compliments about being a nice and cheerful person over being seen as noble, dignified, and just. Nor should they, like Pegasus in Euripides, who "stooped and crouched lower than he wished"642 to carry his rider Bellerophon, lower themselves and comply with every request for fear of being seen as harsh or unkind. It is said that the Egyptian Bocchoris, who was naturally very stern, received an asp from Isis that wrapped around his head, providing shade so he could judge fairly. In contrast, bashfulness acts like a dead weight on timid and weak individuals, making them too afraid to refuse or contradict anyone, resulting in jurors issuing unfair verdicts, silencing advisors, and forcing people to say and do things they don’t want to do. Consequently, the most assertive person can easily dominate those who lack confidence because their boldness overcomes the others’ modesty. Bashfulness, like soft, sloping ground, cannot fend off or defend against any attack, leaving it vulnerable to the most disgraceful acts and desires. It is a poor guide for youth; as Brutus said, one hasn’t spent their youth wisely if they haven’t learned to say No. It is a terrible guardian of the marriage bed and women’s private quarters, just as the penitent adulteress in Sophocles said to her seducer,

"You convinced and encouraged me to sin."643

Thus shyness, being first seduced by vice,644 leaves its citadel unbarred, unfortified, and open to attack. By gifts people ensnare the worse natures, but by persuasion and playing upon their bashfulness people often seduce even good women. I pass over the injury done to worldly affairs by bashfulness causing people to lend to those whose credit is doubtful, and to go security against their wish, for though they commend that saying, "Be a surety, trouble is at hand,"645 they cannot apply it when business is on hand.

Thus, shyness, initially tempted by vice,644 leaves its stronghold unguarded, weak, and exposed to attack. People use gifts to trap those with worse tendencies, but through persuasion and playing on their shyness, they often seduce even good women. I won't dwell on the harm caused to worldly matters by shyness, which leads people to lend to those with questionable credit and to act as guarantors against their better judgment, because while they may acknowledge the saying, "Being a surety brings trouble,"645 they struggle to implement it when business is at stake.

§ iv. It would not be easy to enumerate how many this vice has ruined. When Creon said to Medea,

§ iv. It wouldn't be easy to count how many lives this vice has destroyed. When Creon said to Medea,

"Lady, it's better now to earn your hate, Than through my softness afterwards to groan, "646

he uttered a pregnant maxim for others; for he himself was overcome by his bashfulness, and granted her one day more, and so was the undoing of his family. And some, when they suspected murder or poison, have failed through it to take precautions for their safety. Thus perished Dion, not ignorant that Callippus was plotting against him, but ashamed to be on his guard against a friend and host. So Antipater, the son of Cassander, having invited Demetrius to supper, and being invited back by him for the next day, was ashamed to doubt another as he had been trusted himself, and went, and got his throat cut after supper. And Polysperchon promised Cassander for a hundred talents to murder Hercules, the son of Alexander by Barsine, and invited him to supper, and, as the stripling suspected and feared the invitation, and pleaded as an excuse that he was not very well, Polysperchon called on him, and addressed him as follows, "Imitate, my lad, your father's good-nature and kindness to his friends, unless indeed you fear us as plotting against you." The young man was ashamed to refuse any longer, so he went with him, and some of those at the supper-party strangled him. And so that line of Hesiod,647

He shared a meaningful saying for others, but himself was held back by shyness, giving her one more day, which led to his family's downfall. Some have found themselves in danger, suspecting murder or poison, yet failed to take steps to protect themselves. So Dion met his end, knowing Callippus was plotting against him, but too embarrassed to guard himself against a friend and host. Similarly, Antipater, the son of Cassander, invited Demetrius for dinner, and when he was invited back the next day, he felt ashamed to doubt someone who had trusted him. He went and ended up getting his throat cut after dinner. Polysperchon promised Cassander a hundred talents to kill Hercules, Alexander's son by Barsine, and invited him to dinner. Hercules, suspicious of the invitation and claiming he wasn't feeling well, was confronted by Polysperchon, who said, "Be like your father, kind and generous to friends, unless you really think we’re out to get you." The young man felt too embarrassed to refuse any longer, so he went, and some at the dinner party strangled him. And thus that line of Hesiod, 647

"Invite your friend to dinner, not your enemy."

is not ridiculous, as some say, or stupid advice, but wise. Show no bashfulness in regard to an enemy, and do not suppose him trustworthy, though he may seem so.648 For if you invite you will be invited back, and if you entertain others you will be entertained back to your hurt, if you let the temper as it were of your caution be weakened by shame.

is not ridiculous, as some say, or foolish advice, but wise. Don't be shy when it comes to an enemy, and don’t think of them as trustworthy, even if they appear to be.648 Because if you invite someone in, you can expect them to invite you back, and if you host others, you'll find yourself hosted in ways that might hurt you, especially if you let your guard down because of embarrassment.

§ v. As then this disease is the cause of much mischief, we must try and exterminate it by assiduous effort, beginning first, as people are wont to do in other matters, with small and easy things. For example, if anyone pledge you to drink with him at a dinner when you have had enough, do not be bashful, or do violence to nature, but 257put the cup down without drinking. Again, if somebody else challenge you to play at dice with him in your cups, be not bashful or afraid of ridicule, but imitate Xenophanes, who, when Lasus of Hermione called him coward because he would not play at dice with him, admitted that he was a great coward and had no courage for what was ignoble. Again, if you meet with some prating fellow who attacks you and sticks to you, do not be bashful, but get rid of him, and hasten on and pursue your undertaking. For such flights and repulses, keeping you in practice in trying to overcome your bashfulness in small matters, will prepare you for greater occasions. And here it is well to record a remark of Demosthenes. When the Athenians were going to help Harpalus, and to war against Alexander, all of a sudden Philoxenus, who was Alexander's admiral, was sighted in the offing. And the populace being greatly alarmed, and speechless for fear, Demosthenes said, "What will they do when they see the sun, if they cannot lift their eyes to face a lamp?" And what will you do in important matters, if the king desires anything, or the people importune you, if you cannot decline to drink when your friend asks you, or evade the onset of some prating fellow, but allow the trifler to waste all your time, from not having nerve to say, "I will see you some other time, I have no leisure now."649

§ v. This disease causes a lot of trouble, so we need to work hard to get rid of it, starting with the small and simple things, as people usually do in other cases. For example, if someone encourages you to drink more at dinner when you've had enough, don't hesitate or go against your better judgment; just put the cup down without drinking. Similarly, if someone challenges you to a dice game while you're drinking, don't feel shy or worry about what others might think. Instead, be like Xenophanes, who admitted he was a coward when Lasus of Hermione called him one for refusing to play. Also, if you encounter a talkative person who bothers you and won’t leave you alone, don’t be shy—just get away from them and keep focused on what you’re doing. These small victories in overcoming your shyness will prepare you for bigger challenges. It's worth noting something Demosthenes said. When the Athenians were about to support Harpalus and go to war against Alexander, suddenly Philoxenus, Alexander's admiral, appeared in the distance. The crowd was terrified and struck dumb with fear. Demosthenes remarked, "What will they do when they see the sun if they can't even look at a lamp?" So, what will you do when serious matters arise, if, when the king asks something or when people pressure you, you can't refuse a drink from a friend or sidestep a persistent talker? Don’t let the trivial person waste your time just because you lack the courage to say, "I'll catch you later; I'm busy right now."649

§ vi. Moreover, the use and practice of restraining one's bashfulness in small and unimportant matters is advantageous also in regard to praise. For example, if a friend's harper sings badly at a drinking party, or an actor hired at great cost murders650 Menander, and most of the party clap and applaud, I find it by no means hard, or bad manners, to listen silently, and not to be so illiberal as to praise contrary to one's convictions. For if in such matters you are not master of yourself, what will you do if your friend reads a poor poem, or parades a speech stupidly and ridiculously written?651 You will praise it of course, and join the flatterers in loud applause. But how then will you 258find fault with your friend if he makes mistakes in business? How will you be able to correct him, if he acts improperly in reference to some office, or marriage, or the state? For I cannot indeed assent to the remark of Pericles to his friend, who asked him to bear false witness in his favour even to the extent of perjury, "I am your friend as far as the altar." He went too far. But he that has long accustomed himself never to go against his convictions in praising a speaker, or clapping a singer, or laughing at a dull buffoon, will never go to this length, nor say to some impudent fellow in such matters, "Swear on my behalf, bear false witness, pronounce an unjust verdict."

§ vi. Additionally, practicing restraint in situations that provoke embarrassment, especially in trivial matters, is beneficial when it comes to giving praise. For instance, if a friend’s musician performs poorly at a party, or if an expensive actor butchers a performance of Menander, and most people applaud enthusiastically, I believe it's perfectly acceptable to remain silent and not praise what goes against my honest opinion. If you can't control your reactions in these minor situations, how will you respond when your friend shares a bad poem or delivers a foolishly written speech? You'll naturally give false praise and join the crowd in cheering. But how can you then criticize your friend if they make mistakes in their work? How will you correct them if they mess up in their job, their marriage, or their role in the community? I can't agree with Pericles' response to his friend who asked him to falsely testify on his behalf, even to the point of perjury: "I am your friend as far as the altar." That's going too far. However, someone who has consistently refrained from going against their true feelings when praising a speaker, applauding a singer, or laughing at a dull clown would never stoop to such dishonesty or tell someone brazen to, "Lie for me, bear false witness, or give an unfair judgment."

§ vii. So also we ought to refuse people that want to borrow money of us, from being accustomed to say No in small and easily refused matters. Thus Archelaus, king of the Macedonians, being asked at supper for a gold cup by a man who thought Receive the finest word in the language, bade a boy give it to Euripides,652 and gazing intently on the man said to him, "You are fit to ask, and not to receive, and he is fit to receive without asking." Thus did he make judgement and not bashfulness the arbiter of his gifts and favours. Yet we oftentimes pass over our friends who are both deserving and in need, and give to others who continually and impudently importune us, not from the wish to give but from the inability to say No. So the older Antigonus, being frequently annoyed by Bion, said, "Give a talent to Bion and necessity." Yet he was of all the kings most clever and ingenious at getting rid of such importunity. For on one occasion, when a Cynic asked him for a drachma, he replied, "That would be too little for a king to give;"653 and when the Cynic rejoined, "Give me then a talent," he met him with, "That would be too much for a Cynic to receive."654 Diogenes indeed 259used to go round begging to the statues in the Ceramicus, and when people expressed their astonishment said he was practising how to bear refusals. And we must practise ourselves in small matters, and exercise ourselves in little things, with a view to refusing people who importune us, or would receive from us when inconvenient, that we may be able to avoid great miscarriages. For no one, as Demosthenes says,655 if he expends his resources on unnecessary things, will have means for necessary ones. And our disgrace is greatly increased, if we are deficient in what is noble, and abound in what is trivial.

§ vii. We should also turn down people who ask to borrow money from us, getting used to saying no to small and easily declined requests. For example, Archelaus, the king of the Macedonians, when asked at dinner for a gold cup by someone who believed that Receive was the best word in the language, instructed a boy to give it to Euripides,652 and while staring intently at the man, told him, "You are fit to ask, not to receive, and he is fit to receive without asking." This way, he allowed judgment and not shyness to decide his gifts and favors. Yet, we often overlook our friends who truly deserve and need help, and instead give to others who constantly and shamelessly pester us, not out of a genuine desire to give, but due to our inability to say no. Antigonus, the elder, who was frequently bothered by Bion, once said, "Give a talent to Bion and necessity." Still, he was the cleverest and most resourceful of kings when it came to dealing with such asks. One time, when a Cynic requested a drachma, he replied, "That would be too little for a king to give;"653 and when the Cynic countered, "Then give me a talent," he responded, "That would be too much for a Cynic to receive."654 Diogenes used to go around asking for help from the statues in the Ceramicus, and when people were surprised, he said he was practicing how to handle refusals. We need to train ourselves in small matters and practice with little things so that we can turn down people who annoy us or want something from us when it's inconvenient, helping us to avoid major mistakes. For as Demosthenes warns,655 if someone spends their resources on unnecessary things, they won't have what they need for the essentials. And our shame grows if we lack what is noble while having plenty of what is trivial.

§ viii. But bashfulness is not only a bad and inconsiderate manager of money, but also in more important matters makes us reject expediency and reason. For when we are ill we do not call in the experienced doctor, because we stand in awe of the family one; and instead of the best teachers for our boys we select those that importune us;656 and in our suits at law we frequently refuse the aid of some skilled advocate, to oblige the son of some friend or relative, and give him a chance to make a forensic display; and lastly, you will find many so-called philosophers Epicureans or Stoics, not from deliberate choice or conviction, but simply from bashfulness, to have the same views as their friends and acquaintances. Since this is the case, let us accustom ourselves betimes in small and everyday matters to employ no barber or fuller merely from bashfulness, nor to put up at a sorry inn, when a better is at hand, merely because the innkeeper has on several occasions been extra civil to us, but for the benefit of the habit to select the best even in a small matter; as the Pythagoreans were careful never to put their left leg across the right, nor to take an even number instead of an odd, all other matters being indifferent. We must accustom ourselves also, at a sacrifice or marriage or any entertainment of that kind, not to invite the person who greets us and runs up to meet us, but the friend who is serviceable to us. For he that has thus practised and trained himself will be difficult to catch tripping, nay even unassailable, in greater matters.

§ viii. But shyness is not only a poor and thoughtless way to manage money, but it also leads us to ignore practicality and reason in more significant matters. For when we're sick, we often avoid calling the experienced doctor because we're intimidated by the family doctor; and instead of choosing the best teachers for our boys, we pick those who pressure us; 656 and in our legal cases, we often decline the assistance of a skilled advocate to favor the son of a friend or relative, giving him a chance to show off in court; and finally, you'll find many so-called philosophers—Epicureans or Stoics—who adhere to these beliefs not out of thoughtful choice or conviction, but simply out of shyness, adopting the same views as their friends and acquaintances. Since this is how things are, let’s train ourselves early on, in small and everyday matters, to avoid choosing a barber or laundry service just because we feel shy, or to settle for an inferior inn when a better option is available, just because the innkeeper has been particularly kind to us. We should develop the habit of always selecting the best, even in small matters; like the Pythagoreans, who were careful never to cross their left leg over their right or to choose an even number instead of an odd, viewing all other aspects as neutral. We must also get used to, during a sacrifice, wedding, or similar gathering, inviting the friend who is truly helpful to us rather than the person who just greets and rushes towards us. Because one who practices and trains themselves in this way will find it hard to make mistakes, even in more significant matters.

260§ ix. Let so much suffice for practice. And of useful considerations the first is that which teaches and reminds us, that all passions and maladies of the soul are accompanied by the very things which we think we avoid through them. Thus infamy comes through too great love of fame, and pain comes from love of pleasure, and plenty of work to the idle, and to the contentious defeats and losses of lawsuits. And so too it is the fate of bashfulness, in fleeing from the smoke of ill-repute, to throw itself into the fire of it.657 For the bashful, not venturing to say No to those that press them hard, afterwards feel shame at just rebuke, and, through standing in awe of slight blame, frequently in the end incur open disgrace. For if a friend asks some money of them, and through bashfulness they cannot refuse, a little time after they are disgraced by the facts becoming known;658 or if they have promised to help friends in a lawsuit, they turn round and hide their diminished heads, and run away from fear of the other side. Many also, who have accepted on behalf of a daughter or sister an unprofitable offer of marriage at the bidding of bashfulness, have afterwards been compelled to break their word, and break off the match.

260§ ix. Let that be enough for practice. One key point to consider is that all the passions and troubles of the soul come with the very things we think we're avoiding by experiencing them. For example, shame comes from an excessive desire for fame, pain arises from the pursuit of pleasure, and idle people end up with plenty of work, while those who are argumentative face defeats and losses in lawsuits. Similarly, those who are shy, in trying to escape the embarrassment of a bad reputation, end up jumping into it. For the shy, not being able to say No to those who pressure them leads to feelings of shame after a justified criticism, and out of fear of minor blame, they often end up suffering public disgrace. For instance, if a friend asks them for some money and their shyness prevents them from refusing, they soon find themselves humiliated when the truth comes out; or if they promise to help friends in a lawsuit, they might end up hiding in shame and running away from the other party. Many also, who have accepted a poor marriage proposal for a daughter or sister out of shyness, have later had to break their promises and end the engagement.

§ x. He that said all the dwellers in Asia were slaves to one man because they could not say the one syllable No, spoke in jest and not in earnest; but bashful persons, even if they say nothing, can by raising or dropping their eyebrows decline many disagreeable and unpleasant acts of compliance. For Euripides says, "Silence is an answer to wise men,"659 but we stand more in need of it to inconsiderate persons, for we can talk over the sensible. And indeed it is well to have at hand and frequently on our lips the sayings660 of good and famous men to quote to those who importune us, as that of Phocion to Antipater, "You cannot have me both as a friend and flatterer;" or his remark to the Athenians, when they applauded him 261and bade him contribute to the expenses of a festival, "I am ashamed to contribute anything to you, till I have paid yonder person my debts to him," pointing out his creditor Callicles. For, as Thucydides says, "It is not disgraceful to admit one's poverty, but it is very much so not to try to mend it."661 But he who through stupidity or softness is too bashful to say to anyone that importunes him,

§ x. The person who said that everyone in Asia was a slave to one man because they couldn’t say the single word No was joking, not serious; however, shy people, even if they say nothing, can avoid many unpleasant requests by simply raising or lowering their eyebrows. As Euripides said, "Silence is an answer to wise men,"659 but we actually need it more with thoughtless people, as we can easily talk circles around the sensible ones. It’s useful to have phrases660 from wise and famous individuals at our fingertips to quote to those who pressure us, like Phocion’s response to Antipater: "You can’t have me both as a friend and a flatterer," or his comment to the Athenians when they applauded him and asked him to contribute to a festival, "I’m embarrassed to give anything to you until I’ve settled my debts to that guy," as he pointed to his creditor Callicles. Because, as Thucydides says, "It’s not shameful to acknowledge one’s poverty, but it is very shameful not to try to improve it."661 But someone who is too shy to express to anyone who pressures them…

"Stranger, there’s no silver white in my caves,"

but goes bail for him as it were through his promises,

but vouches for him, so to speak, based on his promises,

"Is held back by chains not made of brass but of shame."662

But Persæus,663 when he lent a sum of money to one of his friends, had the fact duly attested by a banker in the market-place, remembering belike that line in Hesiod,664

But Persæus,663 when he lent some money to a friend, had it properly recorded by a banker in the marketplace, perhaps recalling that line in Hesiod,664

"Even to a brother, smiling, bring your witness."

And he wondering and saying, "Why all these legal forms, Persæus?" he replied, "Ay, verily, that my money may be paid back in a friendly way, and that I may not have to use legal forms to get it back." For many, at first too bashful to see to security, have afterwards had to go to law, and lost their friend.665

And he wondered out loud, "Why all these legal formalities, Persæus?" He replied, "Yes, exactly, so that my money can be returned amicably, and I won't have to resort to legal action to get it back." Many people, who were initially too shy to ensure their security, later ended up in court and lost their friend.665

§ xi. Plato again, giving Helicon of Cyzicus a letter for Dionysius, praised the bearer as a man of goodness and moderation, but added at the end of the letter, "I write you this about a man, an animal by nature apt to change." But Xenocrates, though a man of austere character, was prevailed upon through his bashfulness to recommend to Polysperchon by letter, one who was no good man as the event showed; for when the Macedonian welcomed him, and inquired if he wanted any money, he asked for a talent, and Polysperchon gave it him, but wrote to Xenocrates advising him for the future to be more careful in the choice of people he recommended. But Xenocrates knew not the fellow's true character; we on the other 262hand very often when we know that such and such men are bad, yet give them testimonials and money, doing ourselves injury, and not getting any pleasure for it, as people do get in the company of whores and flatterers, but being vexed and disgusted at the importunity that has upset and forced our reason. For the line

§ xi. Plato, once again, gave Helicon of Cyzicus a letter for Dionysius, praising him as a person of integrity and restraint. However, he added at the end of the letter, "I’m telling you this about a man, an individual by nature prone to change." Meanwhile, Xenocrates, despite being a very serious person, was persuaded by his shyness to recommend someone to Polysperchon via a letter; this person turned out to be no good, as later revealed. When the Macedonian welcomed him and asked if he needed any money, he requested a talent, which Polysperchon gave him. However, he wrote to Xenocrates, advising him to be more careful in his future recommendations. Xenocrates didn't realize the man’s true nature; on the other hand, we often know that certain people are bad, yet still give them endorsements and money. This harms us without any benefit, unlike the pleasure people derive from the company of whores and flatterers; instead, we feel irritated and disgusted by their insistence that has disturbed and clouded our judgment. For the line

"I know what I'm about to do is wrong,"666

is especially applicable to people that importune us, when one is going to perjure oneself, or deliver an unjust verdict, or vote for a measure that is inexpedient, or borrow money for someone who will never pay it back.

is especially relevant to people who pressure us, when someone is about to lie under oath, or hand down an unfair judgment, or vote for a measure that doesn’t make sense, or lend money to someone who will never pay it back.

§ xii. And so repentance follows more closely upon bashfulness than upon any emotion, and that not afterwards, but in the very act. For we are vexed with ourselves when we give, and ashamed when we perjure ourselves, and get ill-fame from our advocacies, and are put to the blush, when we cannot fulfil our promises. For frequently, from inability to say No, we promise impossibilities to persevering applicants, as introductions at court, and audiences with princes, from reluctance or want of nerve to say, "The king does not know us, others have his regard far more." But Lysander, when he was out of favour with Agesilaus, though he was thought to have very great influence with him owing to his great reputation, was not ashamed to dismiss suitors, and bid them go and pay their court to others who had more influence with the king. For not to be able to do everything carries no disgrace with it, but to undertake and try and force your way to what you are unable to do, or unqualified by nature for, is in addition to the disgrace incurred a task full of trouble.

§ xii. Repentance comes more quickly after embarrassment than after any other feeling, and not just later, but right in the moment. We feel annoyed with ourselves when we make commitments, and we feel ashamed when we break promises, gaining a bad reputation from our support of certain causes, and we blush when we fail to keep our word. Often, because we find it hard to say No, we promise the impossible to persistent requesters, like introductions at court and meetings with princes, out of reluctance or a lack of courage to say, "The king doesn't know us; others have his favor much more." But Lysander, even when he had fallen out of favor with Agesilaus, was not ashamed to turn away suitors, telling them to seek out others who had more influence with the king, despite being thought to have significant clout due to his great reputation. It is not disgraceful to be unable to do everything; the real shame lies in trying to force your way into things you cannot do, or for which you are naturally unsuited, which adds not only to the disgrace but also makes the effort troublesome.

§ xiii. To take another element into consideration, all seemly and modest requests we ought readily to comply with, not bashfully but heartily, whereas in injurious or unreasonable requests we ought ever to remember the conduct of Zeno, who, meeting a young man he knew walking very quietly near a wall, and learning from him that he was trying to get out of the way of a friend who wanted him to perjure himself on his behalf, said to him, "O stupid fellow, what do you tell me? Is he not afraid or ashamed to 263press you to what is not right? And dare not you stand up boldly against him for what is right?" For he that said "villainy is no bad weapon against villainy"667 taught people the bad practice of standing on one's defence against vice by imitating it; but to get rid of those who shamelessly and unblushingly importune us by their own effrontery, and not to gratify the immodest in their disgraceful desires through false modesty, is the right and proper conduct of sensible people.

§ xiii. To consider another point, we should readily agree to all reasonable and modest requests, not hesitantly but wholeheartedly. However, when faced with harmful or unreasonable requests, we ought to remember Zeno’s example. He encountered a young man who was quietly standing by a wall and learned that the young man was trying to avoid a friend who wanted him to lie for his benefit. Zeno said to him, "Oh, come on, what are you telling me? Isn’t he afraid or embarrassed to push you into something wrong? And shouldn’t you stand up confidently for what is right?" The person who said, "dishonesty is not a bad tactic against dishonesty" taught the wrong idea that we should defend ourselves against wrongdoing by copying it. Instead, we should rid ourselves of those who shamelessly pressure us with their boldness and not fulfill the indecent requests of others through false modesty. This is the proper behavior for sensible individuals.

§ xiv. Moreover it is no great task to resist disreputable and low and worthless fellows who importune you, but some send such off with a laugh or a jest, as Theocritus did, who, when two fellows in the public baths, one a stranger, the other a well-known thief, wanted to borrow his scraper,668 put them both off with a playful answer, "You, sir, I don't know, and you I know too well." And Lysimache,669 the priestess of Athene Polias at Athens, when some muleteers that bore the sacred vessels asked her to give them a drink, answered, "I hesitate to do so from fear that you would make a practice of it." And when a certain young man, the son of a distinguished officer, but himself effeminate and far from bold, asked Antigonus for promotion, he replied, "With me, young man, honours are given for personal prowess, not for the prowess of ancestors."

§ xiv. It's not too difficult to stand up to shady and worthless people who annoy you, but some just send them away with a laugh or a joke, like Theocritus did. When two guys in the public baths, one a stranger and the other a known thief, asked to borrow his scraper,668 he replied playfully, "I don't know you, and I know him too well." Similarly, Lysimache,669 the priestess of Athene Polias in Athens, when some muleteers carrying sacred vessels asked her for a drink, answered, "I'm hesitant to do that because I fear you might make it a habit." And when a certain young man, the son of a distinguished officer but himself soft and lacking courage, asked Antigonus for a promotion, he replied, "In my eyes, honors are awarded based on personal achievement, not family background."

§ xv. But if the person that importunes us be famous or a man of power, for such persons are very hard to move by entreaty or to get rid of when they come to sue for your vote and interest, it will not perhaps be easy or even necessary to behave as Cato, when quite a young man, did to Catulus. Catulus was in the highest repute at Rome, and at that time held the office of censor, and went to Cato, who then held the office of quæstor, and tried to beg off someone whom he had fined, and was urgent and even violent in his petitions, till Cato at last lost all patience, and said, "To have you, the censor, removed by my officers against your will, Catulus, would not be a seemly thing for you." So Catulus felt ashamed, and went off in a rage. But see 264whether the answers of Agesilaus and Themistocles are not more modest and in better form. Agesilaus, when he was asked by his father to pronounce sentence contrary to the law, said, "Father, I was taught by you even from my earliest years to obey the laws, so now I shall obey you and do nothing contrary to law." And Themistocles, when Simonides asked him to do something unjust, replied, "Neither would you be a good poet if your lines violated the laws of metre, nor should I be a good magistrate if I gave decisions contrary to law."

§ xv. But if the person asking us for something is well-known or powerful, it can be very difficult to change their mind or to shake them off when they come to seek your vote and support. It might not be easy or even necessary to act like Cato did when he was young with Catulus. Catulus was highly respected in Rome and was serving as censor at the time. He approached Cato, who was a quæstor then, and tried to persuade him to let go of a fine he had imposed on someone. He was insistent and even aggressive in his requests until Cato finally lost his patience and said, "For you, the censor, to be taken away by my officers against your will, Catulus, would not be appropriate." Catulus felt embarrassed and left in anger. But look at 264whether the responses from Agesilaus and Themistocles are more humble and well-expressed. When Agesilaus was asked by his father to make a ruling that went against the law, he said, "Father, you taught me from a young age to follow the laws, so now I will obey you and do nothing unlawful." And when Simonides asked Themistocles to do something unjust, he replied, "You wouldn’t be a good poet if your verses broke the rules of meter, and I wouldn’t be a good magistrate if I made decisions that went against the law."

§ xvi. And yet it is not on account of want of metrical harmony in respect to the lyre, to borrow the words of Plato, that cities quarrel with cities and friends with friends, and do and suffer the worst woes, but on account of deviations670 from law and justice. And yet some, who themselves pay great attention to melody and letters and measures, do not think it wrong for others to neglect what is right in magistracies and judicial sentences and business generally. One must therefore deal with them in the following manner. Does an orator ask a favour of you when you are acting as juryman, or a demagogue when you are sitting in council? Say you will grant his request if he first utter a solecism, or introduce a barbarism into his speech; he will refuse because of the shame that would attach itself to him; at any rate we see some that will not in a speech let two vowels come together. If again some illustrious and distinguished person importune you to something bad, bid him come into the market-place dancing or making wry faces, and if he refuse you will have an opportunity to speak, and ask him which is more disgraceful, to utter a solecism and make wry faces, or to violate the law and one's oath, and contrary to justice to do more for a bad than for a good man. Nicostratus the Argive, when Archidamus offered him a large sum of money and any Lacedæmonian bride he chose if he would deliver up Cromnum, said Archidamus could not be a descendant of Hercules, for he travelled about and killed evil-doers, whereas Archidamus tried to make evil-doers of 265the good. In like manner, if a man of good repute tries to force and importune us to something bad, let us tell him that he is acting in an ignoble way, and not as his birth and virtue would warrant.

§ xvi. Yet, it’s not due to a lack of rhythm in music, to quote Plato, that cities fight each other and friends fall out, and do and endure the worst misfortunes, but rather because of departures670 from law and justice. Some people, who pay great attention to melody, literature, and structure, don’t think it’s wrong for others to ignore what’s right in government positions, court decisions, and business matters. Therefore, one must approach them in the following way. If an orator requests a favor from you while you are serving as a juror, or a politician while you are in a council meeting, tell them you’ll grant their request if they first make a grammatical error or use an incorrect term in their speech; they’ll refuse because of the embarrassment it would cause them; in fact, we see some who won’t even let two vowels come together in a speech. If some respected individual pressures you into doing something wrong, tell them to come into the public square dancing or making silly faces, and if they refuse, you’ll have the chance to ask them which is more disgraceful: to make a grammatical mistake and act foolishly, or to break the law and one’s oath, and unjustly do more for a bad person than for a good one. Nicostratus the Argive, when Archidamus offered him a large sum of money and any Spartan bride he wanted in exchange for surrendering Cromnum, said Archidamus couldn’t be a descendant of Hercules, who traveled around to punish wrongdoers, while Archidamus was trying to turn good people into wrongdoers. Similarly, if a reputable man tries to pressure us into doing something wrong, let’s tell him that he’s acting in a dishonorable way, not in line with his heritage and virtue.

§ xvii. But in the case of people of no repute you must see whether you can persuade the miser by your importunity to lend you money without a bond, or the proud man to yield you the better place, or the ambitious man to surrender some office to you when he might take it himself. For truly it would seem monstrous that, while such remain firm and inflexible and unmoveable in their vicious propensities, we who wish to be, and profess to be, men of honour and justice should be so little masters of ourselves as to abandon and betray virtue. For indeed, if those who importune us do it for glory and power, it is absurd that we should adorn and aggrandize others only to get infamy and a bad name ourselves; like unfair umpires in the public games, or like people voting only to ingratiate themselves, and so bestowing improperly offices and prizes671 and glory on others, while they rob themselves of respect and fair fame. And if we see that the person who importunes us only does so for money, does it not occur to one that it is monstrous to be prodigal of one's own fame and reputation merely to make somebody else's purse heavier? Why the idea must occur to most people, they sin with their eyes open; like people who are urged hard to toss off big bumpers, and grunt and groan and make wry faces, but at last do as they are told.

§ xvii. But when dealing with people of no reputation, you need to see if you can convince the greedy person to lend you money without any agreement, or the arrogant person to give up a better position, or the ambitious person to hand over a role they could take themselves. It truly seems outrageous that while these individuals remain steadfast and unyielding in their bad habits, those of us who aspire to be seen as honorable and just should be so weak as to give up and betray our virtues. If those who press us do it for glory and power, it’s ridiculous for us to lift others up only to earn disgrace and a bad reputation ourselves; like unfair referees in public games, or like people who vote solely to win favor, improperly giving offices and rewards671 and recognition to others while sacrificing our own respect and good reputation. And if we realize that the person begging us only wants money, isn’t it shocking to be so careless with our own fame and reputation just to fill someone else's wallet? This thought must cross most people’s minds; they willingly make a fool of themselves, like those pushed hard to down large drinks, who grunt and groan and grimace but eventually do as they're told.

§ xviii. Such weakness of mind is like a temperament of body equally susceptible to heat and cold; for if such people are praised by those that importune them they are overcome and yield at once, whereas they are mortally afraid of the blame and suspicions of those whose desires they do not comply with. But we ought to be stout and resolute in either case, neither yielding to bullying nor cajolery. Thucydides indeed tells us, since envy necessarily follows ability, that "he is well advised who incurs envy in matters of the highest importance."672 But we, thinking it 266difficult to escape envy, and seeing that it is altogether impossible not to incur blame or give offence to those we live with, shall be well advised if we prefer the hatred of the perverse to that of those who might justly find fault with us for having iniquitously served their turn. And indeed we ought to be on our guard against praise from those who importune us, which is sure to be altogether insincere, and not to resemble swine, readily allowing anyone that presses to make use of us from our pleasure at itching and tickling, and submitting ourselves to their will. For those that give their ears to flatterers differ not a whit from such as let themselves be tripped up at wrestling, only their overthrow and fall is more disgraceful; some forbearing hostility and reproof in the case of bad men, that they may be called merciful and humane and compassionate; and others on the contrary persuaded to take up unnecessary and dangerous animosities and charges by those who praise them as the only men, the only people that never flatter, and go so far as to entitle them their mouthpieces and voices. Accordingly Bio673 compared such people to jars, that you could easily take by the ears and turn about at your will. Thus it is recorded that the sophist Alexinus in one of his lectures said a good many bad things about Stilpo the Megarian, but when one of those that were present said, "Why, he was speaking in your praise only the other day," he replied, "I don't doubt it; for he is the best and noblest of men." Menedemus on the contrary, having heard that Alexinus674 frequently praised him, replied, "But I always censure him, for that man is bad who either praises a bad man or is blamed by a good." So inflexible and proof was he against such flattery, and master of that advice which Hercules in Antisthenes675 gave, when he ordered his sons to be grateful to no one that praised them; which meant nothing else than that they should not be dumbfoundered at it, nor flatter again those who praised them. Very apt, I take it, 267was the remark of Pindar to one who told him that he praised him everywhere and to all persons, "I am greatly obliged to you, and will make your account true by my actions."

§ xviii. Such weakness of mind is like a body that can't handle heat and cold; if these people are praised by those who pressure them, they are quickly swayed and give in, yet they are terrified of criticism and suspicion from those whose wishes they don't fulfill. However, we should be strong and firm in both situations, neither giving in to pressure nor flattery. Thucydides tells us, since envy inevitably follows success, that "he is wise who invites envy in matters of great importance."672 But we, believing it’s hard to avoid envy and realizing that it’s impossible to not be blamed or upset those around us, would be wise to choose the disdain of the wicked over that of those who might fairly criticize us for unfairly serving their interests. Indeed, we should be cautious of praise from those who pressure us, as it's likely to be entirely insincere, and shouldn't resemble swine, readily allowing anyone who pushes to use us just because we enjoy being flattered and scratched, thus submitting to their desires. Those who listen to flatterers are no different than those who let themselves be tripped up in a wrestling match, but their defeat is even more shameful; some avoid conflict and criticism from bad people just so they can be seen as merciful and compassionate; meanwhile, others are persuaded to take on unnecessary and risky grudges and accusations by those who praise them as the only ones who never flatter, even going so far as to call them their spokespersons. Accordingly, Bio673 compared such individuals to jars that can easily be grabbed by the ears and turned around at will. It is recorded that the sophist Alexinus, in one of his lectures, spoke badly about Stilpo the Megarian, but when someone in the audience pointed out, "He was just praising you the other day," he replied, "I don't doubt it; for he is the best and noblest of men." In contrast, Menedemus, hearing that Alexinus674 often praised him, responded, "But I always criticize him, for a bad person is one who either praises a bad person or is blamed by a good one." He was so steadfast against such flattery, following the advice that Hercules gave in Antisthenes675, which was to not be grateful to anyone who praised them; this meant they should not be awestruck by it nor continue to flatter those who praised them. Very fitting, I believe, 267 was Pindar's response to someone who told him they praised him everywhere, saying, "I am very grateful to you, and I will prove your statement true by my actions."

§ xix. A useful precept in reference to all passions is especially valuable in the case of the bashful. When they have been overcome by this infirmity, and against their judgement have erred and been confounded, let them fix it in their memories, and, remembering the pain and grief it gave them, let them recall it to their mind and be on their guard for a very long time. For as travellers that have stumbled against a stone, or pilots that have been wrecked off a headland, if they remember these occurrences, not only dread and are on their guard continually on those spots, but also on all similar ones; so those that frequently remember the disgrace and injury that bashfulness brought them, and its sorrow and anguish, will in similar cases be on their guard against their weakness, and will not readily allow themselves to be subjugated by it again.

§ xix. A helpful rule regarding all emotions is especially important for those who are shy. When they let this weakness take over them and, against their better judgment, make mistakes and feel embarrassed, they should remember it clearly and, by recalling the pain and sadness it caused them, remain cautious for a long time. Just like travelers who have tripped over a stone or sailors who have been shipwrecked near a cliff, if they keep these experiences in mind, they will not only fear and stay alert in those specific situations but will also be cautious in similar ones. Similarly, those who often remember the shame and hurt caused by their shyness and its accompanying sadness will be more vigilant in similar situations and won’t easily let themselves be overcome by it again.

636 Or bashfulness, shamefacedness, what the French call mauvaise honte.

636 Or shyness, embarrassment, what the French call mauvaise honte.

637 Shakespeare puts all this into one line: "Most subject is the fattest soil to weeds."—2 Henry IV., A. iv. Sc. iv.

637 Shakespeare puts all this into one line: "The most fertile ground is the easiest for weeds."—2 Henry IV., A. iv. Sc. iv.

638 Or girls. κόρη means both a girl, and the pupil of the eye.

638 Or girls. κόρη refers to both a girl and the pupil of the eye.

639 So Wyttenbach.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ So Wyttenbach.

640 These lines are quoted again "On Moral Virtue," § vi.

640 These lines are quoted again in "On Moral Virtue," § vi.

641 "Iliad," xxiv. 44, 45.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xxiv. 44, 45.

642 Euripides, "Bellerophon," Fragm., 313.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Bellerophon," Fragment 313.

643 Soph., Fragm., 736.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Soph., Fragm., 736.

644 Surely it is necessary to read προδιαφθαρẽισα τῷ ἀκολάστῳ.

644 Surely, it is necessary to read προδιαφθαρẽισα τῷ ἀκολάστῳ.

645 See Plato, "Charmides," 165 A.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Plato, "Charmides," 165 A.

646 Euripides, "Medea," 290, 291.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Medea," 290, 291.

647 "Works and Days," 342.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Works and Days," 342.

648 Reading with Wyttenbach, μήδ᾽ ὑπόλαβε πιστεύειν, δοκοῦντα.

648 Reading with Wyttenbach, don’t assume you understand everything, thinking you do.

649 See Horace's very amusing "Satire," i. ix., on such tiresome fellows.

649 Check out Horace's really funny "Satire," i. ix., about those annoying people.

650 ὲπιτρίβω is used in the same sense by Demosthenes, p. 288.

650 ἐπιτρίβω is used in the same sense by Demosthenes, p. 288.

651 On such social pests see Juvenal, i. 1-14.

651 For insights on these social nuisances, refer to Juvenal, i. 1-14.

652 See Pausanias, i. 2. Euripides left Athens about 409 B.C., and took up his abode for good in Macedonia at the court of Archelaus, where he died 406 B.C.

652 See Pausanias, i. 2. Euripides left Athens around 409 B.C. and permanently settled in Macedonia at the court of Archelaus, where he died in 406 B.C.

653 For a drachma was only worth 6 obols, or 9¾d. of our money, nearly = Roman denarius.

653 Because a drachma was only worth 6 obols, or 9¾d. in our currency, which is close to a Roman denarius.

654 A talent was 6,000 drachmæ, or 36,000 obols, about £243 15s. of our money.

654 A talent was 6,000 drachmas, or 36,000 obols, around £243.75 in today's currency.

655 "Olynth." iii. p. 33, § 19.

655 "Olynth." iii. p. 33, § 19.

656 Compare "On Education," § vii.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare "On Education," __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__

657 Our "Out of the frying-pan into the fire." Cf. "Incidit in Scyllam cupiens vitare Charybdim."

657 Our "Out of the frying pan and into the fire." Compare "He runs into Scylla wanting to avoid Charybdis."

658 By their having to borrow themselves.

658 By needing to rely on others.

659 Fragm. 947.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Frag. 947.

660 Or apophthegms, of which Plutarch and Lord Verulam have both left us collections.

660 Or short sayings, of which Plutarch and Lord Verulam have both given us collections.

661 Thucydides, ii. 40. Pericles is the speaker.

661 Thucydides, ii. 40. Pericles is speaking.

662 A slightly-changed line from Euripides' "Pirithous," Fragm. 591. Quoted correctly "On Abundance of Friends," § vii.

662 A slightly-changed line from Euripides' "Pirithous," Fragm. 591. Quoted correctly "On Abundance of Friends," § vii.

663 "Zenonis discipulus."—Reiske.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Zenon's student." —Reiske.

664 "Works and Days," 371.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Works and Days," 371.

665 Cf. Shakspere, "Hamlet," i. iii. 76.

665 See Shakspere, "Hamlet," i. iii. 76.

666 Euripides, "Medea," 1078.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Medea," 1078.

667 Our "Set a thief to catch a thief."

667 Our "It takes a criminal to catch a criminal."

668 Or strigil. See Otto Jahn's note on Persius, v. 126.

668 Or strigil. See Otto Jahn's note on Persius, v. 126.

669 "Forsitan illa quam nominat Pausanias, i. 27."—Reiske.

669 "Maybe it’s the one Pausanias mentions, i. 27."—Reiske.

670 Literally "want of tune in." We cannot well keep up the metaphor. Compare with this passage, "That virtue may be taught," § ii.

670 Literally "lacking rhythm." We can’t really maintain the metaphor. Compare this passage, "That virtue may be taught," § ii.

671 Literally "crowns."

"crowns."

672 Thucydides, ii. 64. Pericles is the speaker. Quoted again in "How one may discern a flatterer from a friend," § xxxv.

672 Thucydides, ii. 64. Pericles is the speaker. Quoted again in "How to tell a flatterer from a friend," § xxxv.

673 "Est Bio Borysthenita, de quo vide Diog. Laërt."—Reiske.

673 "It's about the Borysthenita, see Diogenes Laertius."—Reiske.

674 "De Alexino Eleo vide Diog. Laërt., ii. 109. Nostri p. 1063, 3."—Reiske.

674 "See the work on Alexinus in Diogenes Laertius, ii. 109. Our edition p. 1063, 3."—Reiske.

675 Antisthenes wrote a book called "Hercules." See Diogenes Laertius, vi. 16.

675 Antisthenes wrote a book titled "Hercules." See Diogenes Laertius, vi. 16.


ON RESTRAINING ANGER.

A DIALOGUE BETWEEN SYLLA AND FUNDANUS.

§ i. Sylla. Those painters, Fundanus, seem to me to do well who, before giving the finishing touches to their paintings, lay them by for a time and then revise them; because by taking their eyes off them for a time they gain by frequent inspection a new insight, and are more apt to detect minute differences, that continuous familiarity would have hidden. Now since a human being cannot so separate himself from himself for a time, and make a break in his continuity, and then approach himself again—and that is perhaps the chief reason why a man is a worse judge of himself than of others—the next best thing will be for a man to inspect his friends after an interval, and likewise offer himself to their scrutiny, not to see whether he has aged quickly, or whether his bodily condition is better or268 worse, but to examine his moral character, and see whether time has added any good quality, or removed any bad one. On my return then to Rome after an absence of two years, and having been with you now five months, I am not at all surprised that there has been a great increase and growth in those good points which you formerly had owing to your admirable nature; but when I see how gentle and obedient to reason your former excessive impetuosity and hot temper has become, it cannot but occur to me to quote the line,

§ i. Sylla. Those painters, Fundanus, seem to me to be doing well who, before adding the finishing touches to their paintings, set them aside for a while and then revise them; because by stepping away for a time, they gain new insights through repeated observation and are more likely to notice small details that constant exposure would have obscured. Since a person can’t truly detach themselves from who they are and take a break from their own continuity, which may be the main reason why someone judges themselves more poorly than others, the next best thing is to examine one’s friends after a break and also allow them to assess you—not to see if you’ve aged or if your physical condition has improved or worsened, but to evaluate your moral character, and to find out if time has added any good qualities or taken away any bad ones. So, upon returning to Rome after being away for two years, and having spent five months with you now, I’m not surprised at all to see a significant growth in the good qualities you always had due to your wonderful nature; but when I notice how gentle and receptive to reason you’ve become, compared to your previous excessive impulsiveness and temper, I can’t help but recall the line,

"Wow, he has become so much more gentle!"676

And this mildness has not wrought in you sloth or weakness, but like cultivation of the soil it has produced a smoothness and depth fit for action, instead of the former impetuosity and vehemence. And so it is clear that your propensity to anger has not been effaced by any declining vigour or through some chance, but has been cured by good precepts. And indeed, for I will tell you the truth, when our friend Eros677 reported this change in you to me, I suspected that owing to goodwill he bare witness not of the actual state of the case, but of what was becoming to all good and virtuous men, although, as you know, he can never be persuaded to depart from his real opinion to ingratiate himself with anyone. But now he is acquitted of false witness, and do you, as your journey gives you leisure, narrate to me the mode of cure you employed to make your temper so under control, so natural, gentle and obedient to reason.

And this gentleness hasn't made you lazy or weak, but like cultivating the soil, it has created a smoothness and depth that are ready for action, rather than the old impulsiveness and intensity. So it's clear that your tendency to anger hasn't faded due to a loss of energy or by chance, but has been addressed by good advice. Honestly, when our friend Eros677 told me about this change in you, I suspected that he wasn't sharing the actual reality but rather what he thought would be fitting for all good and virtuous people. As you know, he can never be swayed from his true opinion to please anyone. But now he has been proven truthful, so please, as you have time during your journey, tell me how you managed to gain such control over your temper, making it so calm, gentle, and in line with reason.

Fundanus. Most friendly Sylla, take care that you do not in your goodwill and affection to me rest under any misconception of my real condition. For it is possible that Eros, not being able always himself to keep his temper in its place in the obedience that Homer speaks of,678 but sometimes carried away by his hatred of what is bad, may think me grown milder than I really am, as in changes of the scale in music the lowest notes become the highest.

Fundanus. Dear Sylla, please make sure that your kindness and affection for me don’t lead you to misunderstand my true situation. It’s possible that Eros, unable to always maintain his temper as Homer describes,678 may sometimes, moved by his disdain for evil, perceive me as being gentler than I actually am, just like in music, where the lowest notes can shift to become the highest.

Sylla. Neither of these is the case, Fundanus, but oblige me by doing as I ask.

Sylla. That's not what I meant, Fundanus, but please do me a favor and do what I'm asking.

269§ ii. Fundanus. One of the excellent precepts then of Musonius that I remember, Sylla, is this, that those who wish to be well should diet themselves all their life long. For I do not think we must employ reason as a cure, as we do hellebore, by purging it out with the disease, but we must retain it in the soul, to restrain and govern the judgement. For the power of reason is not like physic, but wholesome food, which co-operates with good health in producing a good habit of body in those by whom it is taken. But admonition and reproof, when passion is at its height and swelling, does little or no good, but resembles very closely those strong-smelling substances, that are able to set on their legs again those that have fallen in epileptic fits, but cannot rid them of their disease. For although all other passions, even at the moment of their acme, do in some sort listen to reason and admit it into the soul, yet anger does not, for, as Melanthius says,

269§ ii. Fundanus. One of the great lessons from Musonius that I remember, Sylla, is that those who want to be healthy should maintain a good diet throughout their lives. I don’t believe we should use reason like a medicine, purging it away with the illness; instead, we should keep it in our minds to control and guide our judgment. The power of reason is not like medicine; it’s more like nutritious food that works together with good health to create a healthy state in those who consume it. However, advice and criticism, when emotions are running high and intense, are mostly ineffective and resemble strong-smelling substances that can help someone who has collapsed from an epileptic fit but can’t actually cure them. While most emotions, even at their peak, can somewhat listen to reason and allow it into the mind, anger does not; as Melanthius points out,

"It does awful things when it disturbs the mind."

for it absolutely turns reason out of doors, and bolts it out, and, like those persons who burn themselves and houses together, it makes all the interior full of confusion and smoke and noise, so that what would be advantageous can neither be seen nor heard. And so an empty ship in a storm at open sea would sooner admit on board a pilot from without, than a man in a tempest of rage and anger would listen to another's advice, unless his own reason was first prepared to hearken. But as those who expect a siege get together and store up supplies, when they despair of relief from without, so ought we by all means to scour the country far and wide to derive aids against anger from philosophy, and store them up in the soul: for, when the time of need comes, we shall find it no easy task to import them. For either the soul doesn't hear what is said without because of the uproar, if it have not within its own reason (like a boatswain as it were) to receive at once and understand every exhortation; or if it does hear, it despises what is uttered mildly and gently, while it is exasperated by harsh censure. For anger being haughty and self-willed and hard to be worked upon by another, like a270 fortified tyranny, must have someone born and bred within it679 to overthrow it.

for it completely shuts reason out and locks it away, and just like those people who set fire to themselves and their homes, it fills the mind with chaos, confusion, and noise, making it impossible to see or hear what could be helpful. So, just as a ship caught in a storm at sea would more readily accept a pilot from outside, a person caught in a fit of rage is unlikely to heed another's advice unless their own reason is first prepared to listen. But just as those who anticipate a siege gather supplies when they lose hope of outside help, we should make every effort to search widely for philosophical tools to combat anger and store them in our minds: because, when we really need them, it won't be easy to bring them in. Either the mind doesn't hear what's being said due to the uproar if it doesn't have its own reasoning (like a boatswain) to receive and understand each piece of encouragement right away; or if it does hear, it dismisses the gentle advice while being riled up by harsh criticism. Anger, being proud, stubborn, and resistant to external influence, is like a fortified tyranny and needs someone born and raised within it to bring it down.

§ iii. Now long-continued anger, and frequent giving way to it, produces an evil disposition of soul, which people call irascibility, and which ends in passionateness, bitterness, and peevishness, whenever the mind becomes sore and vexed at trifles and querulous at everyday occurrences, like iron thin and beaten out too fine. But when the judgement checks and suppresses at once the rising anger, it not only cures the soul for the moment, but restores its tone and balance for the future. It has happened to myself indeed twice or thrice, when I strongly fought against anger, that I was in the same plight as the Thebans, who after they had once defeated the Lacedæmonians, whom they had hitherto thought invincible, never lost a battle against them again. I then felt confident that reason can win the victory. I saw also that anger is not only appeased by the sprinkling of cold water, as Aristotle attested, but is also extinguished by the action of fear; aye, and, as Homer tells us, anger has been cured and has melted away in the case of many by some sudden joy. So that I came to the conclusion that this passion is not incurable for those who wish to be cured. For it does not arise from great and important causes, but banter and joking, a laugh or a nod, and similar trifles make many angry, as Helen by addressing her niece,

§ iii. Long-term anger, especially when frequently indulged, leads to a harmful state of mind known as irritability. This ultimately results in emotional outbursts, bitterness, and grumpiness when the mind becomes easily upset by minor annoyances and petty issues, as if it were thin iron that’s been hammered too finely. However, when reason immediately checks and suppresses rising anger, it not only provides a temporary remedy for the mind but also restores its composure and balance for the future. I’ve personally experienced this a couple of times when I actively resisted anger; I found myself in a situation similar to the Thebans, who, after defeating the Lacedæmonians—whom they previously saw as unbeatable—never lost to them again. In those moments, I felt assured that reason can prevail. I also realized that anger can be soothed not just by splashing cold water, as Aristotle suggested, but can also be extinguished by fear; and, as Homer depicted, sudden joy has calmed anger for many. Thus, I concluded that this emotion isn’t unmanageable for those who seek to overcome it. It doesn’t stem from significant causes but often arises from teasing, jokes, a laugh, a nod, and other trivial things that can easily upset many, just like Helen when she spoke to her niece.

"Electra, a young woman for quite a while now,"680

provoked her to reply,

made her respond,

"Your wisdom blossoms late, since before You left your house in shame; 681

and Callisthenes incensed Alexander, by saying, when a huge cup was brought to him, "I will not drink to Alexander till I shall require the help of Æsculapius."

and Callisthenes angered Alexander by saying, when a large cup was presented to him, "I won’t drink to Alexander until I need the help of Æsculapius."

§ iv. As then it is easy to put out a flame kindled in the hair of hares and in wicks and rubbish, but if it once gets hold of things solid and thick, it quickly destroys and consumes them, "raging amidst the lofty work of the 271carpenters," as Æschylus682 says; so he that observes anger in its rise, and sees it gradually smoking and bursting forth into fire from some chatter or rubbishy scurrility, need have no great trouble with it, but can frequently smother it merely by silence and contempt. For as a person puts out a fire by bringing no fuel to it, so with respect to anger, he that does not in the beginning fan it, and stir up its rage in himself, keeps it off and destroys it. And so, though Hieronymus has given us many useful sayings and precepts, I am not pleased with his remark that there is no perception of anger in its birth, but only in its actual developement, so quick is it. For none of the passions when stirred up and set in motion has so palpable a birth and growth as anger. As indeed Homer skilfully shows us, where he represents Achilles as seized at once with grief, when word was brought him of Patroclus' death, in the line,

§ iv. It's easy to put out a fire that starts in the hair of hares or in wicks and trash, but once it grabs hold of something solid and thick, it quickly destroys everything in its path, "raging amidst the lofty work of the carpenters," as Æschylus says; similarly, someone who notices anger when it first appears and sees it slowly smoldering and erupting into flames from some gossip or trivial insults doesn't need to worry too much about it, as they can often extinguish it just by remaining silent and dismissive. Just like putting out a fire by not providing fuel, with anger, if you don't stoke it or feed into its rage at the start, you can keep it at bay and eliminate it. Although Hieronymus has given us many helpful sayings and teachings, I don't agree with his claim that there is no awareness of anger in its beginning, but only when it fully develops, as it's so quick. None of the emotions get stirred up and grow as clearly as anger does. Homer skillfully illustrates this, showing Achilles being instantly overwhelmed with grief when he hears the news of Patroclus' death in the line,

"That’s what he said, and a dark cloud of sorrow surrounded him;"683

whereas he represents him as waxing angry with Agamemnon slowly, and as inflamed by his many words, which if either of them684 had abstained from, their quarrel would not have attained such growth and magnitude. And so Socrates, as often as he perceived any anger rising in him against any of his friends, "setting himself like some ocean promontory to break the violence of the waves," would lower his voice, and put on a smiling countenance, and give his eye a gentler expression, by inclining in the other direction and running counter to his passion, thus keeping himself from fall and defeat.

whereas he depicts him as becoming angry with Agamemnon gradually, stirred up by his many words. If either of them684 had held back, their conflict would not have grown so large. So, whenever Socrates noticed any anger rising in him against his friends, he would "stand firm like a coastal cliff to break the force of the waves," lower his voice, put on a smile, and soften his gaze by turning his head in the other direction, countering his feelings to prevent himself from stumbling and being defeated.

§ v. For the first way, my friend, to overcome anger, like the putting down of some tyrant, is not to obey or listen to it when it bids you speak loud, and look fierce, and beat yourself, but to remain quiet, and not to make the passion more intense, as one would a disease, by tossing about and crying out. In love affairs indeed, such things as revellings, and serenadings, and crowning the loved 272one's door with garlands, may indeed bring some pleasant and elegant relief.

§ v. The first way, my friend, to deal with anger, like taking down a tyrant, is not to obey or listen to it when it tells you to shout, act fierce, or lash out at yourself. Instead, stay calm and don’t make the emotion stronger, like one would with a sickness, by flailing around and screaming. In romantic situations, celebrations, serenades, and decorating the loved one's door with garlands can indeed provide some enjoyable and graceful relief. 272

"I went, but I didn’t ask who she was or whose she was," I just kissed her doorpost. If that’s the case, I admit to committing a crime. I plead guilty to it. 685

In the case of mourners also giving up to weeping and wailing takes away with the tears much of the grief. But anger on the contrary is much more fanned by what angry persons do and say. It is best therefore to be calm, or to flee and hide ourselves and go to a haven of quiet, when we feel the fit of temper coming upon us as an epileptic fit, that we fall not, or rather fall not on others, for it is our friends that we fall upon most and most frequently. For we do not love all, nor envy all, nor fear all men; but nothing is untouched or unassailed by anger; for we are angry with friends and enemies, parents and children, aye, and with the gods, and beasts, and even things inanimate, as was Thamyris,

When mourners start to cry and wail, their tears often relieve a lot of their sadness. But anger, on the other hand, only gets stronger with what angry people do and say. It’s best to stay calm or to escape and find a quiet space when we feel a fit of anger coming on, much like an epileptic seizure, so we don't lash out or, rather, don’t lash out at others. It's usually our friends who bear the brunt of our anger most often. We don’t love everyone, envy everyone, or fear everyone; however, nothing is off-limits when it comes to anger. We get angry with our friends and enemies, parents and children, and even with the gods, animals, and even inanimate things, like Thamyris did.

"Shattering his gold-trimmed horn, shattering the music" Of well-compacted lyre; __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

and Pandarus, who called down a curse upon himself, if he did not burn his bow "after breaking it with his hands."687 And Xerxes inflicted stripes and blows on the sea, and sent letters to Mount Athos, "Divine Athos, whose top reaches heaven, put not in the way of my works stones large and difficult to deal with, or else I will hew thee down, and throw thee into the sea." For anger has many formidable aspects, and many ridiculous ones, so that of all the passions it is the most hated and despised. It will be well to consider both aspects.

and Pandarus, who cursed himself if he didn’t burn his bow "after breaking it with his hands."687 And Xerxes punished the sea with whips and blows, sending letters to Mount Athos, "Divine Athos, whose peak touches the sky, do not obstruct my plans with large and hard-to-move stones, or I will cut you down and throw you into the sea." Anger has many intimidating sides and plenty of absurd ones, making it the most hated and scorned of all the emotions. It’s important to reflect on both sides.

§ vi. To begin then, whether my process was wrong or right I know not, but I began my cure of anger by noticing its effects in others, as the Lacedæmonians study the nature of drunkenness in the Helots. And in the first place, as Hippocrates tells us that disease is most dangerous in which the face of the patient is most unlike himself, so observing that people beside themselves with anger 273change their face, colour, walk, and voice, I formed an impression as it were of that aspect of passion, and was very disgusted with myself if ever I should appear so frightful and like one out of his mind to my friends and wife and daughters, not only wild and unlike oneself in appearance, but also with a voice savage and harsh, as I had noticed in some688 of my acquaintance, who could neither preserve for anger their ordinary behaviour, or demeanour, or grace of language, or persuasiveness and gentleness in conversation. Caius Gracchus, indeed, the orator, whose character was harsh and style of oratory impassioned, had a pitch-pipe made for him, such as musicians use to heighten or lower their voices by degrees, and this, when he was making a speech, a slave stood behind him and held, and used to give him a mild and gentle note on it, whereby he lowered his key, and removed from his voice the harsh and passionate element, charming and laying the heat of the orator,

§ vi. So, to start, I’m not sure if my approach was right or wrong, but I started managing my anger by observing how it affected others, similar to how the Spartans study the behavior of the Helots when they’re drunk. First off, as Hippocrates points out, the most dangerous illnesses are those where the patient no longer resembles themselves. I noticed that people who are out of control with anger change their appearance, color, demeanor, and voice. This made me recognize that aspect of passion, and I felt really uneasy at the thought of appearing so frightening and out of my mind in front of my friends, wife, and daughters. I didn’t want to be wild and unrecognizable, but also to have a voice that was harsh and aggressive, as I had seen in some of my acquaintances who lost their usual composure, behavior, eloquence, and gentleness in conversations when they were angry. Caius Gracchus, the orator, who was known for his harsh character and passionate speaking style, even had a pitch pipe made for himself, like musicians use to adjust their voices. During his speeches, a slave would stand behind him with the pitch pipe, giving him a soft and gentle note that helped him lower his pitch and soften the harshness of his voice, calming the intensity of his oratory.

"As shepherds' wax-joined reeds sound musical" With sleep-inducing strain.689

For myself if I had some elegant and sprightly companion, I should not be vexed at his showing me a looking-glass in my fits of anger, as they offer one to some after a bath to little useful end. For to behold oneself unnaturally distorted in countenance will condemn anger in no small degree. The poets playfully tell us that Athene when playing on the pipe was rebuked thus by a Satyr,

For me, if I had a classy and lively friend, I wouldn’t be annoyed at them showing me a mirror when I’m angry, like how people sometimes show it to someone after a bath, which doesn’t really help. Because seeing yourself all twisted in the face will definitely make you question your anger. The poets humorously say that Athene was scolded by a Satyr while playing the flute,

"That look really doesn't suit you, put on your armor," "Put down your pipes and fix your face,"

and though she paid no attention to him, yet afterwards when she saw her face in a river, she felt vexed and threw her pipes away, although art had made melody a compensation for her unsightliness. And Marsyas, it seems, by a sort of mouthpiece forcibly repressed the violence of his breath, and tricked up and hid the contortion of his face,

and although she ignored him, later when she saw her reflection in a river, she felt annoyed and tossed aside her pipes, even though her art had turned her lack of beauty into something beautiful. And Marsyas, it seems, used a kind of mouthpiece to suppress the harshness of his breath and cleverly disguised the twisted expression on his face,

"Put bright gold around his messy hair," And a thong is tied behind his open mouth.

274Now anger, that puffs up and distends the face so as to look ugly, utters a voice still more harsh and unpleasant,

274Now anger, which makes the face puff up and look ugly, produces a voice that's even harsher and more unpleasant,

"Adjusting the mind's thoughts quietly before."

They say that the sea is cleansed when agitated by the winds it throws up tangle and seaweed; but the intemperate and bitter and vain words, which the mind throws up when the soul is agitated, defile the speakers of them first of all and fill them with infamy, as always having those thoughts within their bosom and being defiled with them, but only giving vent to them in anger. And so for a word which is, as Plato styles it, "a very small matter," they incur a most heavy punishment, for they get reputed to be enemies, and evil speakers, and malignant in disposition.

They say that the sea is cleaned when it’s stirred up by the wind, which tosses out debris and seaweed; but the rash, bitter, and arrogant words that come from an agitated mind defile the speaker first and fill them with shame, as they carry those thoughts within them and are tainted by them, only expressing them out of anger. And so, for a word that Plato describes as "a very small matter," they face severe consequences, as they become seen as enemies, slanderers, and mean-spirited.

§ vii. Seeing and observing all this, it occurs to me to take it as a matter of fact, and record it for my own general use, that if it is good to keep the tongue soft and smooth in a fever, it is better to keep it so in anger. For if the tongue of people in a fever be unnatural, it is a bad sign, but not the cause of their malady; but the tongue of angry people, being rough and foul, and breaking out into unseemly speeches, produces insults that work irremediable mischief, and argue deep-rooted malevolence within. For wine drunk neat does not exhibit the soul in so ungovernable and hateful a condition as temper does: for the outbreaks of the one smack of laughter and fun, while those of the other are compounded with gall: and at a drinking-bout he that is silent is burdensome to the company and tiresome, whereas in anger nothing is more highly thought of than silence, as Sappho advises,

§ vii. Seeing and observing all this, I think it's a good idea to note for my own reference that while it's helpful to keep the tongue soft and smooth during a fever, it's even more important to do so when angry. The tongue of someone with a fever may not be normal, which is a bad sign, but it’s not the root cause of their illness. However, an angry person's tongue is rough and foul, often leading to inappropriate outbursts that cause serious harm and reveal deep-seated malice. Drinking straight alcohol doesn’t reveal the soul in as uncontrolled and hateful a state as anger does; outbursts from drinking seem more like fun and laughter, whereas those fueled by anger are filled with bitterness. In a drinking gathering, someone who stays quiet can be a burden and tiresome, but in anger, silence is highly valued, just as Sappho advises.

"When anger is active in the brain Your idly-barking tongue restrain.

§ viii. And not only does the consideration of all this naturally arise from observing ourselves in the moments of anger, but we cannot help seeing also the other properties of rage, how ignoble it is, how unmanly, how devoid of dignity and greatness of mind! And yet to most people its noise seems vigour, its threatening confidence, and its obstinacy force of character; some even not wisely entitle its savageness magnanimity, and its implacability firmness,275 and its morosity hatred of what is bad. For their actions and motions and whole demeanour argue great littleness and meanness, not only when they are fierce with little boys, and peevish with women, and think it right to treat dogs and horses and mules with harshness, as Ctesiphon the pancratiast thought fit to kick back a mule that had kicked him, but even in the butcheries that tyrants commit their littleness of soul is apparent in their savageness, and their suffering in their action, so that they are like the bites of serpents, that, when they are burnt and smart with pain, violently thrust their venom on those that have hurt them. For as a swelling is produced in the flesh by a heavy blow, so in softest souls the inclination to hurt others gets its greater strength from greater weakness. Thus women are more prone to anger than men, and people ill than people well, and old men than men in their prime, and the unfortunate than the prosperous; the miser is most prone to anger with his steward, the glutton with his cook, the jealous man with his wife, the vain man when he is spoken ill of; and worst of all are those "men who are too eager in states for office, or to head a faction, a manifest sorrow," to borrow Pindar's words. So from the very great pain and suffering of the soul there arises mainly from weakness anger, which is not like the nerves of the soul, as some one defined it, but like its strainings and convulsions when it is excessively vehement in its thirst for revenge.

§ viii. Not only do we naturally come to these thoughts from observing ourselves when we're angry, but we also can't ignore the other traits of rage: how unworthy it is, how unmanly, and how lacking in dignity and greatness of spirit! Yet, for most people, its noise seems like strength, its threatening attitude feels like confidence, and its stubbornness is taken as a sign of strong character; some even foolishly label its brutality as bravery, its unforgiving nature as determination, and its morose behavior as a hatred for what is wrong. Their actions, body language, and overall demeanor show great pettiness and mean-spiritedness, especially when they are harsh with little boys, irritable with women, and think it acceptable to treat animals like dogs, horses, and mules with cruelty, just like Ctesiphon the pancratiast who kicked back at a mule that kicked him. Even in the brutal acts committed by tyrants, their small-mindedness is revealed in their savagery and suffering, making them act like a snake that, when wounded, randomly strikes back at those who hurt it. Just as a swelling forms in flesh from a strong blow, the desire to harm others in the most sensitive souls grows stronger from deeper weakness. Thus, women are more inclined to anger than men, the sick more than the healthy, the elderly more than those in their prime, and the unfortunate more than the fortunate; the miser is most angry with his steward, the glutton with his cook, the jealous man with his wife, and the vain man when he is criticized; and worst of all are those "men who are too eager for power in government or to lead a faction, a clear sign of distress," to quote Pindar. Therefore, the profound pain and suffering of the soul largely stem from weakness, leading to anger, which is not truly like the nerves of the soul, as someone once defined it, but rather like its struggles and convulsions when it is excessively driven by a desire for revenge.

§ ix. Such bad examples as these were not pleasant to look at but necessary, but I shall now proceed to describe people who have been mild and easy in dealing with anger, conduct gratifying either to see or hear about, being utterly disgusted690 with people who use such language as,

§ ix. These bad examples were unpleasant to witness but unavoidable. Now, I will describe people who have been calm and easy in managing their anger, with behavior that's pleasing to observe or hear about, completely repulsed690 by those who use such language as,

"You're talking about a man who has been wronged: can a man bear this?"

and,

and,

"Place your heel on his neck and smash his head against the ground,"

and other provoking expressions such as these, by which some not well have transferred anger from the woman's 276side of the house to the man's. For manliness in all other respects seems to resemble justice, and to differ from it only in respect to gentleness, with which it has more affinities. For it sometimes happens to worse men to govern better ones, but to erect a trophy in the soul against anger (which Heraclitus says it is difficult to contend against, for whatever it wishes is bought at the price of the soul), is a proof of power so great and victorious as to be able to apply the judgement as if it were nerves and sinews to the passions. So I always try to collect and peruse the remarks on this subject not only of the philosophers, who foolish691 people say had no gall in their composition, but still more of kings and tyrants. Such was the remark of Antigonus to his soldiers, when they were abusing him near his tent as if he were not listening, so he put his staff out, and said, "What's to do? can you not go rather farther off to run me down?" And when Arcadio the Achæan, who was always railing against Philip, and advising people to flee

and other provoking statements like these, through which some have unfairly shifted anger from the woman's side of the house to the man's. Manliness in all other ways seems to reflect justice and only differs from it in terms of gentleness, with which it shares more similarities. Sometimes, worse individuals end up leading better ones, but being able to create an inner strength against anger (which Heraclitus claims is hard to fight against, since it demands a high price from the soul) is a sign of incredible power that can apply judgment as if it were the nerves and sinews controlling emotions. So, I always try to gather and study the comments on this topic not just from philosophers, whom foolish people say lacked any edge, but even more so from kings and tyrants. Such was the comment from Antigonus to his soldiers when they were criticizing him near his tent, as if he couldn't hear them; he extended his staff and said, "What's going on? Can't you find a better place to talk behind my back?" And when Arcadio the Achæan, who constantly criticized Philip, advised people to run away.

"To a country where they didn't know Philip,"

visited Macedonia afterwards on some chance or other, the king's friends thought he ought to be punished and the matter not looked over; but Philip treated him kindly, and sent him presents and gifts, and afterwards bade inquiry to be made as to what sort of account of him Arcadio now gave to the Greeks; and when all testified that the fellow had become a wonderful praiser of the king, Philip said, "You see I knew how to cure him better than all of you." And at the Olympian games when there was defamation of Philip, and some of his suite said to him, that the Greeks ought to smart for it, because they railed against him when they were treated well by him, he replied, "What will they do then if they are treated badly by me?" Excellent also was the behaviour of Pisistratus to Thrasybulus, and of Porsena to Mucius, and of Magas to Philemon. As to Magas, after he had been publicly jeered at by Philemon in one of his comedies at the theatre in the following words,

visited Macedonia later due to some chance encounter, the king's friends felt he should be punished and not overlooked; however, Philip treated him kindly and sent him gifts and presents. He later asked for an inquiry into what kind of opinion Arcadio was now sharing with the Greeks; when everyone confirmed that the guy had become an enthusiastic supporter of the king, Philip said, "You see, I knew how to fix him better than all of you." During the Olympic games, when there was slander against Philip, some of his entourage suggested that the Greeks should suffer for it since they insulted him even when he treated them well. He responded, "What will they do then if I treat them poorly?" The actions of Pisistratus towards Thrasybulus, Porsena towards Mucius, and Magas towards Philemon were also commendable. Regarding Magas, after he was publicly mocked by Philemon in one of his theatrical comedies with the words,

277 "Magas, the king has written you a letter, Unhappy Magas, since you can't read,

after having taken Philemon, who had been cast on shore by a storm at Parætonium, he commanded one of his soldiers only to touch his neck with the naked sword and then to go away quietly, and dismissed him, after sending him a ball and some dice as if he were a silly boy. And Ptolemy on one occasion, flouting a grammarian for his ignorance, asked him who was the father of Peleus, and he answered, "I will tell you, if you tell me first who was the father of Lagus." This was a jeer at the obscure birth of the king, and all his courtiers were indignant at it as an unpardonable liberty; but Ptolemy said, "If it is not kingly to take a flout, neither is it kingly to give one." And Alexander was more savage than usual in his behaviour to Callisthenes and Clitus. So Porus, when he was taken captive, begged Alexander to use him as a king. And on his inquiring, "What, nothing more?" he replied "No. For everything is included in being used as a king." So they call the king of the gods Milichius,692 while they call Ares Maimactes;693 and punishment and torture they assign to the Erinnyes and to demons, not to the gods or Olympus.

after taking Philemon, who had washed ashore due to a storm at Parætonium, he ordered one of his soldiers to lightly touch his neck with a bare sword and then quietly leave. He then dismissed him, giving him a ball and some dice as if he were just a silly boy. One time, Ptolemy, mocking a grammarian for his ignorance, asked him who the father of Peleus was. The grammarian replied, "I'll tell you, but first tell me who the father of Lagus is." This was a jab at the king's uncertain lineage, and all his courtiers were outraged, considering it an unforgivable insult. But Ptolemy said, "If it's unkingly to take a jab, it's also unkingly to deliver one." Meanwhile, Alexander was especially harsh in his treatment of Callisthenes and Clitus. When Porus was captured, he asked Alexander to treat him like a king. Upon Alexander's question, "What, nothing more?" he answered, "No. Because everything is included in being treated like a king." They refer to the king of the gods as Milichius,692 while they call Ares Maimactes;693 and they assign punishment and torture to the Erinnyes and demons, not to the gods or Olympus.

§ x. As then a certain person passed the following remark on Philip when he had razed Olynthus to the ground, "He certainly could not build such another city," so we may say to anger, "You can root up, and destroy, and throw down, but to raise up and save and spare and tolerate is the work of mildness and moderation, the work of a Camillus, a Metellus, an Aristides, a Socrates; but to sting and bite is to resemble the ant and horse-fly. For, indeed, when I consider revenge, I find its angry method to be for the most part ineffectual, since it spends itself in biting the lips and gnashing the teeth, and in vain attacks, and in railings coupled with foolish threats, and eventually resembles children running races, who from feebleness ridiculously tumble down before they reach the goal they are hastening to. So that speech of the Rhodian to a 278lictor of the Roman prætor who was shouting and talking insolently was not inapt, "It is no matter to me what you say, but what your master thinks."694 And Sophocles, when he had introduced Neoptolemus and Eurypylus as armed for the battle, gives them this high commendation,695

§ x. One time, someone remarked about Philip after he had destroyed Olynthus, saying, "He definitely can't build another city like that." Similarly, we can say to anger, "You can tear down and destroy, but building up, saving, sparing, and being tolerant require gentleness and moderation—those are the qualities of Camillus, Metellus, Aristides, and Socrates. To sting and bite is more like the behavior of an ant or a horse-fly. When I think about revenge, I see that its angry approach is mostly ineffective. It ends up just gnashing teeth and futilely attacking, much like children racing each other who fall down from exhaustion before they reach their goal. So, the Rhodian's comment to a 278lictor of the Roman prætor, who was shouting and being rude, was quite fitting: "I don’t care what you say, but rather what your master thinks."694 And Sophocles, when introducing Neoptolemus and Eurypylus ready for battle, gives them this great praise,695

"They rushed into the middle of armed warriors."

Some barbarians indeed poison their steel, but bravery has no need of gall, being dipped in reason, but rage and fury are not invincible but rotten. And so the Lacedæmonians by their pipes turn away the anger of their warriors, and sacrifice to the Muses before commencing battle, that reason may abide with them, and when they have routed a foe do not follow up the victory,696 but relax their rage, which like small daggers they can easily take back. But anger kills myriads before it is glutted with revenge, as happened in the case of Cyrus and Pelopidas the Theban. But Agathocles bore mildly the revilings of those he was besieging, and when one of them cried out, "Potter, how are you going to get money to pay your mercenaries?" he replied laughingly, "Out of your town if I take it." And when some of those on the wall threw his ugliness into the teeth of Antigonus, he said to them, "I thought I was rather a handsome fellow." But after he had taken the town, he sold for slaves those that had flouted him, protesting that, if they insulted him again, he would bring the matter before their masters. I have noticed also that hunters and orators are very unsuccessful when they give way to anger.697 And Aristotle tells us that the friends of Satyrus stopped up his ears with wax when he was to plead a cause, that he might not make any confusion in the case through rage at the abuse of his enemies. And does it not frequently happen with ourselves that a slave who has offended escapes punishment, because they abscond in fear of our threats and harsh words? What nurses then say to children, "Give up crying, and you shall have it," may usefully be applied to anger, thus, "Do not be in a hurry, or bawl out, or be vehement, and you will sooner 279and better get what you want." For a father, seeing his boy trying to cut or cleave something with a knife, takes the knife from him and does it himself: and similarly a person, taking revenge out of the hand of passion, does himself safely and usefully and without harm punish the person who deserves punishment, and not himself instead, as anger often does.

Some people do poison their weapons, but true bravery doesn’t involve malice; it's rooted in reason. Rage and fury aren't unbreakable—they crumble. This is why the Spartans use music to calm their warriors and honor the Muses before going into battle, aiming to keep rationality on their side. Once they’ve defeated an enemy, they don’t pursue further revenge; instead, they relax their anger, which they can easily retract, much like small daggers. But anger can cause countless deaths before satisfying its thirst for revenge, as seen in the stories of Cyrus and Pelopidas the Theban. On the other hand, Agathocles took insults from those he besieged with composure. When one of them shouted, “Potter, how will you pay your mercenaries?” he responded with a laugh, “From your city, if I capture it.” Likewise, when someone on the wall insulted Antigonus about his looks, he replied, “I thought I was quite good-looking.” After he took the city, he sold the ones who had mocked him into slavery, claiming that if they insulted him again, he would report them to their masters. I’ve also noticed that hunters and speakers often fail when they let anger take over. Aristotle mentioned that friends of Satyrus would plug his ears with wax before he spoke in court to avoid causing chaos due to rage from enemy insults. Isn’t it common for us to notice that a servant who has offended often escapes punishment simply by fleeing from our threats and angry words? What nurses say to crying children—“Stop crying, and you’ll get it”—can be wisely applied to anger as well: “Don’t rush, shout, or be forceful, and you’ll get what you want more effectively.” For example, if a father sees his son struggling to cut something with a knife, he takes it away and does it for him. In a similar way, when someone takes control of revenge away from passion, they can ensure that the one who deserves punishment is dealt with safely and effectively without harming themselves in the process, which anger often leads to.

§ xi. Now though all the passions need such discipline as by exercise shall tame and subdue their unreasoning and disobedient elements, yet there is none which we ought to keep under by such discipline so much as the exhibition of anger to our servants. For neither envy, nor fear, nor rivalry come into play between them and us; but our frequent displays of anger to them, creating many offences and faults, make us to slip as if on slippery ground owing to our autocracy with our servants, which no one resists or prevents. For it is impossible to check irresponsible power so as never to break out under the influence of passion, unless one wields power with much meekness, and refuses to listen to the frequent complaints of one's wife and friends charging one with being too easy and lax with one's servants. And by nothing have I been more exasperated against them, as if they were being ruined for want of correction. At last, though late, I got to see that in the first place it is better to make them worse by forbearance, than by bitterness and anger to distort oneself for the correction of others. In the next place I observed that many for the very reason that they were not corrected were frequently ashamed to be bad, and made pardon rather than punishment the commencement of their reformation, aye, and made better slaves to some merely at their nod silently and cheerfully than to others with all their beatings and brandings, and so I came to the conclusion that reason gets better obeyed than temper, for it is not as the poet said,

§ xi. While all passions require some level of control through practice to manage their unreasonable and rebellious aspects, the one we need to restrain the most is our anger towards our servants. Unlike envy, fear, or rivalry, our anger creates many grievances and mistakes, causing us to slip up in our authority over them, a power that goes unchallenged. It's impossible to completely control unchecked power when it flares up due to passion, unless we exercise that power with great humility and choose not to heed the constant complaints from our spouse and friends about being too lenient with our servants. I've often found myself getting frustrated with them, feeling as if they were failing because I didn’t correct them enough. Eventually, I realized that it’s better to tolerate their flaws than to let bitterness and anger twist my character while trying to correct them. I also noticed that many, precisely because they weren’t punished, would often feel ashamed of their bad behavior and preferred forgiveness as a way to reform. Indeed, some would become better servants just through a simple nod of approval, silently and willingly, rather than through harsh treatment and punishment. This led me to conclude that reason is followed more readily than anger. As the poet said,

"Where there is fear, there is also self-respect."

but it is just the other way about, for self-respect begets that kind of fear that corrects the behaviour. But perpetual and pitiless beating produces not so much repentance for wrong-doing as contrivances to continue in it without detection. In the third place, ever remembering and reflecting 280within myself that, just as he that teaches us the use of the bow does not forbid us to shoot but only to miss the mark, so it will not prevent punishment altogether to teach people to do it in season, and with moderation, utility, and decorum, I strive to remove anger most especially by not forbidding those who are to be corrected to speak in their defence, but by listening to them. For the interval of time gives a pause to passion, and a delay that mitigates it, and so judgement finds out both the fit manner and adequate amount of punishment. Moreover he that is punished has nothing to allege against his correction, if he is punished not in anger but only after his guilt is brought home to him. And the greatest disgrace will not be incurred, which is when the servant seems to speak more justly than the master. As then Phocion, after the death of Alexander, to stop the Athenians from revolting and believing the news too soon, said to them, "Men of Athens, if he is dead to-day, he will certainly also be dead to-morrow and the next day," so I think the man who is in a hurry to punish anyone in his rage ought to consider with himself, "If this person has wronged you to-day, he will also have wronged you to-morrow and the next day; and there will be no harm done if he shall be punished somewhat late; whereas if he shall be punished at once, he will always seem to you to have been innocent, as has often happened before now." For which of us is so savage as to chastise and scourge a slave because five or ten days before he over-roasted the meat, or upset the table, or was somewhat tardy on some errand? And yet these are the very things for which we put ourselves out and are harsh and implacable, immediately after they have happened and are recent. For as bodies seem greater in a mist, so do little matters in a rage. We ought therefore to consider such arguments as these at once, and if, when there is no trace of passion left, the matter appear bad to calm and clear reason, then it ought to be taken in hand, and the punishment ought not to be neglected or abandoned, as we leave food when we have lost our appetites. For nothing causes people to punish so much when their anger is fierce, as that when it is appeased they do not punish at all, but forget the matter entirely, and resemble lazy rowers,281 who lie in harbour when the sea is calm, and then sail out to their peril when the wind gets up. So we, condemning reason for slackness and mildness in punishing, are in a hurry to punish, borne along by passion as by a dangerous gale. He that is hungry takes his food as nature dictates, but he that punishes should have no hunger or thirst for it, nor require anger as a sauce to stimulate him to it, but should punish when he is as far as possible from having any desire for it, and has to compel his reason to it. For we ought not, as Aristotle tells us slaves in his time were scourged in Etruria to the music of the flute, to go headlong into punishing with a desire and zest for it, and to delight in punishing, and then afterwards to be sorry at it—for the first is savage, and the last womanish—but we should without either sorrow or pleasure chastise at the dictates of reason, giving anger no opportunity to interfere.

But it’s actually the opposite, because self-respect creates a type of fear that corrects behavior. However, constant and merciless punishment leads not to true remorse for wrongdoing but rather to schemes for continuing those wrongs without getting caught. Moreover, always keeping in mind 280that just as someone teaching us to use a bow doesn’t stop us from shooting but only from missing the target, teaching people to act appropriately and moderately won’t completely eliminate punishment. I aim to reduce anger, especially by allowing those who need correction to speak in their defense and by listening to them. Taking a moment to pause allows passion to cool down and gives time for better judgment, which helps determine the right way and amount of punishment. Also, a person being punished can’t argue against their correction if the punishment is not delivered in anger but comes after they acknowledge their guilt. The worst embarrassment occurs when a servant seems more justified than the master. Just as Phocion told the Athenians, after Alexander’s death, to calm down and not rush to conclusions, I believe the person who is quick to punish in anger should remind themselves, “If this person wronged you today, they will likely do the same tomorrow and the next day; there’s no harm in waiting a bit to punish them. If you punish immediately, it will seem to you that they were innocent, as has often happened before.” What kind of person is so cruel as to beat a slave for something that happened five or ten days ago, like overcooking meat, knocking over a table, or being a bit late on an errand? Yet, these are the exact reasons we get upset and act harshly right after they happen. Just like objects appear larger in fog, small issues can seem huge in anger. We should consider arguments like these right away, and if, after the anger fades, a situation still appears bad to a calm and clear mind, then it deserves attention, and the punishment shouldn’t be ignored or dismissed, just as we don’t abandon food when we lose our appetite. For nothing drives people to punish more fiercely than anger, yet when that anger subsides, they might forget the issue altogether, much like lazy rowers who stay in the harbor when the sea is calm, only to set out at their own risk once the wind picks up. Thus, while we criticize reason for being too lenient and slow to punish, we rush to punish, pushed by passion like a dangerous storm. A hungry person eats when nature calls, but someone who punishes shouldn’t act out of desire or thirst for it, nor should they require anger to motivate them; they should punish when they are as far away as possible from wanting to do so and have to force themselves to reason it out. We shouldn’t, as Aristotle suggested, rush headlong into punishment with eagerness and enjoyment, only to feel regret afterward—because the first is cruel, and the last is weak. Instead, we should discipline without either sorrow or pleasure, guided solely by reason, allowing no room for anger to interfere.

§ xii. But this perhaps will not appear a cure of anger so much as a putting away and avoiding such faults as men commit in anger. And yet, though the swelling of the spleen is only a symptom of fever, the fever is assuaged by its abating, as Hieronymus tells us. Now when I contemplated the origin of anger itself, I observed that, though different persons fell into it for different reasons, yet in nearly all of them was the idea of their being despised and neglected to be found. So we ought to help those who try to get rid of anger, by removing as far as possible from them any action savouring of contempt or contumely, and by looking upon their anger as folly or necessity, or emotion, or mischance, as Sophocles says,

§ xii. But this might not seem like a way to cure anger so much as a way to set aside and avoid the mistakes people make in anger. Still, even though the swelling of the spleen is just a sign of fever, the fever eases when it goes down, as Hieronymus points out. When I thought about where anger comes from, I noticed that, although different people get angry for various reasons, almost all of them feel that they are being disrespected or overlooked. Therefore, we should support those trying to overcome anger by minimizing any actions that might seem contemptuous or insulting, and by viewing their anger as foolishness, necessity, emotion, or bad luck, as Sophocles says.

"In those who are unfortunate, O king, "No mind remains stable, but they all lose their balance."698

And so Agamemnon, ascribing to Ate his carrying off Briseis, yet says to Achilles,

And so Agamemnon, blaming Ate for taking Briseis from him, still says to Achilles,

"I want to make you happy in return and give" Complete satisfaction.699

For suing is not the action of one who shews his contempt, and when he that has done an injury is humble he removes 282all idea of slighting one. But the angry person must not expect this, but rather take to himself the answer of Diogenes, who, when it was said to him, "These people laugh at you," replied, "But I am not one to be laughed at," and not think himself despised, but rather despise the person who gave the offence, as acting from weakness, or error, or rashness, or heedlessness, or illiberality, or old age, or youth. Nor must we entertain such notions with regard to our servants and friends. For they do not despise us as void of ability or energy, but owing to our evenness and good-nature, some because we are mild, and others presuming on our affection for them. But as it is we not only fly into rages with wife and slaves and friends, as if we were slighted by them, but we also frequently, from forming the same idea of being slighted, fall foul of innkeepers and sailors and muleteers, and are vexed at dogs that bark and asses that are in our way: like the man who was going to beat an ass-driver, but when he cried out he was an Athenian, he said to the ass, "You are not an Athenian anyway," and beat it with many stripes.

Suing isn’t something someone does out of contempt, and when the person who caused the harm shows humility, it removes all sense of being slighted. But someone who’s angry shouldn’t expect this; instead, they should remember the response from Diogenes, who, when told, “These people are laughing at you,” replied, “But I am not someone to be laughed at.” They shouldn’t think they’re being looked down on but rather see the person who offended them as acting out of weakness, mistake, rashness, carelessness, meanness, age, or youth. We shouldn’t have these thoughts about our servants and friends either. They don’t look down on us as if we lack ability or energy, but due to our calm and kind demeanor—some because we are gentle, and others because they take our affection for granted. In reality, we often get angry with our wives, servants, and friends as if they’ve insulted us, and we also tend to lash out at innkeepers, sailors, and mule drivers, getting annoyed with barking dogs and donkeys in our way. It’s like the guy who was about to beat a donkey driver, and when the driver yelled that he was an Athenian, the man replied to the donkey, “You’re not an Athenian anyway,” and then beat it mercilessly.

§ xiii. Moreover those continuous and frequent fits of anger that gather together in the soul by degrees, like a swarm of bees or wasps, are generated within us by selfishness and peevishness, luxury and softness. And so nothing causes us to be mild to our servants and wife and friends so much as easiness and simplicity, and the learning to be content with what we have, and not to require a quantity of superfluities.

§ xiii. Additionally, those ongoing and frequent bursts of anger that build up in the soul over time, like a swarm of bees or wasps, are created within us by selfishness and irritability, indulgence and comfort. Therefore, nothing makes us kinder to our servants, partners, and friends as much as being easygoing and straightforward, along with learning to be satisfied with what we have, without needing a lot of excess.

"Someone who doesn’t like their meat if it’s overcooked" Or overcooked, or under-roasted, or undercooked, And never praises it, no matter how it's presented.

but will not drink unless he have snow to cool his drink, nor eat bread purchased in the market, nor touch food served on cheap or earthenware plates, nor sleep upon any but a feather bed that rises and falls like the sea stirred up from its depths, and with rods and blows hastens his servants at table, so that they run about and cry out and sweat as if they were bringing poultices to sores, he is slave to a weak querulous and discontented mode of life, and, like one who has a continual cough or various ailments, whether he is aware of it or not, he is in an283 ulcerous and catarrh-like condition as regards his proneness to anger. We must therefore train the body to contentment by plain living, that it may be easily satisfied: for they that require little do not miss much; and it is no great hardship to begin with our food, and take it silently whatever it is, and not by being choleric and peevish to thrust upon ourselves and friends the worst sauce to meat, anger.

but will not drink unless he has snow to cool his drink, nor eat bread bought in the market, nor touch food served on cheap or clay plates, nor sleep on anything but a feather bed that rises and falls like the sea in a storm. He rushes his servants at the table with rods and blows, making them run around and shout and sweat as if they were bringing poultices to wounds. He is a slave to a whiny, dissatisfied way of life, and like someone with a chronic cough or various ailments, whether he realizes it or not, he is in an283 ulcerous and congested state when it comes to his tendency to get angry. We must therefore train the body to be content with simple living so that it can be easily satisfied: for those who need little don’t miss much; and it’s not too hard to start with our food, accepting whatever it is quietly, and not by being irritable and cranky thrust upon ourselves and our friends the worst flavor to a meal, anger.

"There couldn't be a more unpleasant dinner" __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

than that wherein the servants are beaten, and the wife scolded, because something is burnt or smoked or not salt enough, or because the bread is too cold. Arcesilaus was once entertaining some friends and strangers, and when dinner was served, there was no bread, through the servants having neglected to buy any. In such a case as this which of us would not have broken the walls with vociferation? But he only smiled and said, "How unfit a sage is to give an entertainment!" And when Socrates once took Euthydemus home with him from the wrestling-school, Xanthippe was in a towering rage, and scolded, and at last upset the table, and Euthydemus rose and went away full of sorrow. But Socrates said to him, "Did not a hen at your house the other day fly in and act in the very same way? And we did not put ourselves out about it." We ought to receive our friends with gaiety and smiles and welcome, not knitting our brows, or inspiring fear and trembling in the attendants. We ought also to accustom ourselves to the use of any kind of ware at table, and not to stint ourselves to one kind rather than another, as some pick out a particular tankard or horn, as they say Marius did, out of many, and will not drink out of anything else; and some act in the same way with regard to oil-flasks and scrapers,701 being content with only one out of all, and so, if such an article is broken or lost, they are very much put out about it, and punish with severity. He then that is prone to anger should not use rare and dainty things, such as choice cups and seals and precious stones: for if they are lost they put a man beside 284himself much more than the loss of ordinary and easily got things would do. And so when Nero had got an eight-cornered tent constructed, a wonderful object both for its beauty and costliness, Seneca said to him, "You have now shown yourself to be poor, for if you should lose this, you will not be able to procure such another." And indeed it did so happen that the tent was lost by shipwreck, but Nero bore its loss patiently, remembering what Seneca had said. Now this easiness about things generally makes a man also easy and gentle to his servants, and if to them, then it is clear he will be so to his friends also, and to all that serve under him in any capacity. So we observe that newly-purchased slaves do not inquire about the master who has bought them, whether he is superstitious or envious, but only whether he is a bad-tempered man: and generally speaking we see that neither can men put up with chaste wives, nor wives with loving husbands, nor friends with one another, if they be ill-tempered to boot. So neither marriage nor friendship is bearable with anger, though without anger even drunkenness is a small matter. For the wand of Dionysus punishes sufficiently the drunken man, but if anger be added it turns wine from being the dispeller of care and inspirer of the dance into a savage and fury. And simple madness can be cured by Anticyra,702 but madness mixed with anger is the producer of tragedies and dreadful narratives.

than that where the servants are punished, and the wife is upset, because something is burnt, smoked, or not salty enough, or because the bread is too cold. Arcesilaus once had some friends and strangers over, and when dinner was served, there was no bread because the servants forgot to buy any. In a situation like this, who among us wouldn’t have blown up? But he just smiled and said, "How unfit a sage is to host a dinner!" And when Socrates took Euthydemus home from the wrestling school, Xanthippe was furious, scolded, and eventually overturned the table, causing Euthydemus to leave feeling sad. But Socrates said to him, "Didn’t a hen at your house the other day come in and act the same way? And we didn’t let that bother us." We should greet our friends with joy and smiles, rather than frowns, creating fear and anxiety among the attendants. We should also train ourselves to use all kinds of utensils at the table and not limit ourselves to just one type, as some specifically choose a particular tankard or mug—like Marius allegedly did—from many options, refusing to drink from anything else. Others do the same with oil flasks and scrapers, sticking to just one choice, so when such an item breaks or is lost, they become very upset and react harshly. So, those prone to anger shouldn’t use rare and delicate things, like fancy cups and precious stones; if they lose them, it bothers them much more than losing ordinary items would. When Nero had a beautiful and expensive eight-sided tent built, Seneca told him, "You've now shown yourself to be poor because if you lose this, you won’t be able to get another." And indeed, the tent was lost in a shipwreck, but Nero accepted the loss calmly, remembering Seneca's words. This easygoing attitude towards material things generally makes a person easygoing and kind to their servants, and if they are to their servants, it’s clear they will be the same with their friends and everyone else they interact with. Newly purchased slaves don’t ask about their master’s character—whether they’re superstitious or envious—but only whether they are easily angered. Overall, we see that neither men can tolerate chaste wives, nor wives loving husbands, nor friends among each other if they’re ill-tempered. So, neither marriage nor friendship is sustainable with anger; without anger, even drunkenness is tolerable. For Dionysus’ staff adequately punishes a drunkard, but if anger is added, it turns wine—which should ease worries and inspire dance—into something savage and frenzied. Simple madness can be treated with Anticyra, but madness mixed with anger leads to tragedies and horrifying tales.

§ xiv. So we ought to give anger no vent, either in jest, for that draws hatred to friendliness; or in discussion, for that turns love of learning into strife; or on the judgement-seat, for that adds insolence to power; or in teaching, for that produces dejection and hatred of learning: or in prosperity, for that increases envy; or in adversity, for that deprives people of compassion, when they are peevish and run counter to those who condole with them, like Priam,

§ xiv. We shouldn't let anger out, whether joking around, because that breeds hatred instead of friendship; or in discussions, since that changes a love for learning into conflict; or in court, as that adds arrogance to authority; or in teaching, as that leads to discouragement and resentment towards learning; or in good times, because that fuels jealousy; or in tough times, as that robs people of compassion when they become irritable and push away those who try to support them, like Priam.

A plague on you, all you useless losers, Do you have no problems at home, that you come here? To empathize with me?703

285Good temper on the other hand is useful in some circumstances, adorns and sweetens others, and gets the better of all peevishness and anger by its gentleness. Thus Euclides,704 when his brother said to him in a dispute between them, "May I perish, if I don't have my revenge on you!" replied, "May I perish, if I don't persuade you!" and so at once turned and changed him. And Polemo, when a man reviled him who was fond of precious stones and quite crazy for costly seal-rings, made no answer, but bestowed all his attention on one of his seal-rings, and eyed it closely; and he being delighted said, "Do not look at it so, Polemo, but in the light of the sun, and it will appear to you more beautiful." And Aristippus, when there was anger between him and Æschines, and somebody said, "O Aristippus, where is now your friendship?" replied, "It is asleep, but I will wake it up," and went to Æschines, and said to him, "Do I seem to you so utterly unfortunate and incurable as to be unworthy of any consideration?" And Æschines replied, "It is not at all wonderful that you, being naturally superior to me in all things, should have been first to detect in this matter too what was needful."

285On the other hand, having a good temper is helpful in some situations, enhances others, and overcomes all irritability and anger with its kindness. For example, Euclides,704 when his brother told him in an argument, "I swear I’ll get my revenge on you!" responded, "I swear I’ll convince you!" and immediately turned the situation around. Similarly, Polemo, when someone insulted him—who was obsessed with precious stones and expensive seal rings—didn't respond at all but focused intently on one of his seal rings, examining it closely. The person, pleased, said, "Don’t look at it like that, Polemo; check it out in the sunlight, and it’ll look even more beautiful." And when Aristippus had a falling out with Æschines, and someone remarked, "Oh Aristippus, where is your friendship now?" he replied, "It’s just sleeping, but I’ll wake it up." He then approached Æschines and asked, "Do I come across as so unfortunate and hopeless that I don’t deserve any consideration?" Æschines responded, "It’s not surprising that you, being naturally better than me in every way, were the first to notice what was necessary in this situation."

"For not just a woman, but also a young child" Tickling the prickly boar with a gentle touch, "Will knock him down quicker than an athlete."

But we that tame wild beasts and make them gentle, and carry in our arms young wolves and lions' whelps, inconsistently repel our children and friends and acquaintances in our rage, and let loose our temper like some wild beast on our servants and fellow-citizens, speciously trying to disguise it not rightly under the name of hatred of evil, but it is, I suppose, as with the other passions and diseases of the soul, we cannot get rid of any of them by calling one prudence, and another liberality, and another piety.

But we who train wild animals to be gentle and hold young wolves and lion cubs in our arms, inconsistently push away our children, friends, and acquaintances in our anger, unleashing our tempers like a wild beast on our servants and fellow citizens. We try to disguise it as a righteous hatred of evil, but I suppose, like the other passions and ailments of the soul, we can't get rid of any of them just by labeling one as prudence, another as generosity, and yet another as piety.

§ xv. And yet, as Zeno said the seed was a mixture and compound drawn from all the faculties of the soul, so anger seems a universal seed from all the passions. For it is drawn from pain and pleasure and haughtiness, and from envy it gets its property of malignity—and it is even 286worse than envy,705 for it does not mind its own suffering if it can only implicate another in misery—and the most unlovely kind of desire is innate in it, namely the appetite for injuring another. So when we go to the houses of spendthrifts we hear a flute-playing girl early in the morning, and see "the dregs of wine," as one said, and fragments of garlands, and the servants at the doors reeking of yesterday's debauch; but for tokens of savage and peevish masters these you will see by the faces, and marks, and manacles of their servants: for in the house of an angry man

§ xv. And yet, as Zeno said, the seed is a mix and compound drawn from all the parts of the soul, so anger appears to be a universal seed from all the emotions. It's taken from pain and pleasure and pride, and from envy, it gains its trait of malice—and it's even 286worse than envy,705 because it doesn’t care about its own suffering as long as it can drag another into misery—and the most unattractive desire that comes with it is the urge to hurt someone else. So when we visit the homes of spendthrifts, we hear a flute-playing girl early in the morning, and see "the dregs of wine," as someone put it, and bits of garlands, and the servants at the doors smelling of yesterday's party; but to see signs of angry and grumpy masters, you can tell by the expressions, marks, and shackles of their servants: for in the house of an angry man

"The only music ever heard is wailing,"

stewards being beaten within, and maids tortured, so that the spectators even in their jollity and pleasure pity these victims of passion.

stewards being beaten inside, and maids tortured, so that the spectators, even in their joy and enjoyment, feel sorry for these victims of passion.

§ xvi. Moreover those to whom it happens through their genuine hatred of what is bad to be frequently overtaken by anger, can abate its excess and acerbity by giving up their excessive confidence in their intimates. For nothing swells the anger more, than when a good man is detected of villainy, or one who we thought loved us falls out and jangles with us. As for my own disposition, you know of course how mightily it inclines to goodwill and belief in mankind. As then people walking on empty space,706 the more confidently I believe in anybody's affection, the more sorrow and distress do I feel if my estimate is a mistaken one. And indeed I could never divest myself of my ardour and zeal in affection, but as to trusting people I could perhaps use Plato's caution as a curb. For he said he so praised Helicon the mathematician, because he was by nature a changeable animal, but that he was afraid of those that were well educated in the city, lest, being human beings and the seed of human beings, they should reveal by some trait or other the weakness of human nature. But Sophocles' line,

§ xvi. Furthermore, those who genuinely hate what is wrong and often find themselves overcome by anger can reduce its intensity and bitterness by letting go of their excessive trust in their close friends. Nothing fuels anger more than discovering that a good person has acted wrongly, or when someone we thought cared about us ends up in conflict with us. As for me, you know well how much I lean towards goodwill and trust in people. Just like someone walking on thin air,706 the more I believe in someone's affection, the more pain and distress I feel if that belief turns out to be misguided. Indeed, I could never shake off my enthusiasm and passion for love, but when it comes to trusting people, I could perhaps take a hint from Plato's caution as a restraint. He admired Helicon the mathematician because he was inherently unpredictable, but he was wary of those well-educated individuals in the city, fearing that, being human, they might inadvertently expose some flaw of human nature. Yet, as Sophocles says,

"Look at most human actions, you'll see they're low."

seems to trample on human nature and lower its merits too 287much. Still such a peevish and condemnatory verdict as this has a tendency to make people milder in their rage, for it is the sudden and unexpected that makes people go distracted. And we ought, as Panætius somewhere said, to imitate Anaxagoras, and as he said at the death of his son, "I knew that I had begotten a mortal," so ought every one of us to use the following kind of language in those contretemps that stir up our anger, "I knew that the slave I bought was not a philosopher," "I knew that the friend I had was not perfect," "I knew that my wife was but a woman." And if anyone would also constantly put to himself that question of Plato, "Am I myself all I should be?" and look at home instead of abroad, and curb his propensity to censoriousness, he would not be so keen to detect evil in others, for he would see that he stood in need of much allowance himself. But now each of us, when angry and punishing, quote the words of Aristides and Cato, "Do not steal, Do not tell lies," and "Why are you lazy?" And, what is most disgraceful of all, we blame angry people when we are angry ourselves, and chastise in temper faults that were committed in temper, unlike the doctors who

seems to trample on human nature and undermine its worth too 287much. Yet, a harsh and judgmental perspective like this tends to soften people’s anger because it’s the sudden and unexpected that drives people to distraction. We should, as Panætius once said, follow Anaxagoras's example. When faced with the death of his son, he remarked, "I knew that I had brought a mortal into this world." Similarly, we should remind ourselves in those moments that ignite our anger, "I knew that the servant I hired wasn't a philosopher," "I knew that the friend I had wasn't perfect," "I knew that my wife is just a woman." And if anyone regularly asks themselves Plato's question, "Am I all I should be?" and focuses on their own faults instead of pointing fingers, they wouldn’t be so eager to find flaws in others, realizing they have plenty of their own shortcomings to account for. But nowadays, each of us, when we're angry and punishing, quote Aristides and Cato saying, "Do not steal, Do not lie," and "Why are you lazy?" What’s even more shameful is that we criticize angry people when we ourselves are angry, scolding others for faults committed in anger, unlike doctors who

"Use a strong medicine to cleanse the bitter bile."

for we rather increase and aggravate the disease. Whenever then I busy myself with such considerations as these, I try also to curtail my curiosity. For to scrutinize and pry into everything too minutely, and to overhaul every business of a servant, or action of a friend, or pastime of a son, or whisper of a wife, produces frequent, indeed daily, fits of anger, caused entirely by peevishness and harshness of character. Euripides says that the Deity

for we just end up making the problem worse. So whenever I find myself caught up in thoughts like these, I also try to rein in my curiosity. Because examining and digging into everything too closely, and keeping tabs on a servant’s work, a friend’s actions, a son’s hobbies, or a wife’s gossip, often leads to frequent, even daily, bursts of anger that stem entirely from irritability and a harsh nature. Euripides says that the Deity

"In big matters, it intervenes, but in small matters, it lets go." To wealth;"707

but I am of opinion that a prudent man should commit nothing to fortune, nor neglect anything, but should put some things in his wife's hands to manage, others in the 288hands of his servants, others in the hands of his friends, (as a governor has his stewards, and financiers, and controllers), while he himself superintends the most important and weighty matters. For as small writing strains the eyes, so small matters even more strain and bother people, and stir up their anger, which carries this evil habit to greater matters. Above all I thought that saying of Empedocles, "Fast from evil,"708 a great and divine one, and I approved of those promises and vows as not ungraceful or unphilosophical, to abstain for a year from wine and Venus, honouring the deity by continence, or for a stated time to give up lying, taking great heed to ourselves to be truthful always whether in play or earnest. With these I compared my own vow, as no less pleasing to the gods and holy, first to abstain from anger for a few days, like spending days without drunkenness or even without wine at all, offering as it were wineless offerings of honey.709 Then I tried for a month or two, and so in time made some progress in forbearance by earnest resolve, and by keeping myself courteous and without anger and using fair language, purifying myself from evil words and absurd actions, and from passion which for a little unlovely pleasure pays us with great mental disturbance and the bitterest repentance. In consequence of all this my experience, and the assistance of the deity, has made me form the view, that courtesy and gentleness and kindliness are not so agreeable, and pleasant, and delightful, to any of those we live with as to ourselves, that have those qualities.710

but I believe that a wise person should leave nothing to chance and should be diligent in their responsibilities. They should delegate some tasks to their wife, others to their servants, and still others to their friends, similar to how a governor assigns duties to stewards, financiers, and controllers, while they oversee the most important and serious matters. Just as tiny text strains the eyes, small issues can aggravate and annoy people, stirring up their anger and bringing this bad attitude into larger concerns. I particularly appreciated the saying of Empedocles, "Fast from evil," as profound and significant, and I found value in making promises, like abstaining for a year from wine and romantic encounters to honor the divine through self-discipline, or setting a specific time to avoid lying, always striving for honesty whether in jest or seriousness. I compared this to my own intention, which I felt was equally pleasing to the gods and sacred: to refrain from anger for a few days, similar to going days without drinking or entirely without wine, offering sweet gestures as a substitute for traditional offerings. I then attempted this for a month or two, gradually progressing in patience through strong determination, maintaining courtesy and composure, and speaking kindly, cleansing myself of harmful words, ridiculous actions, and the fleeting pleasure of passions that often lead to significant mental turmoil and deep remorse. Because of all this, my experiences along with divine support have led me to believe that kindness, gentleness, and warmth are not only agreeable and pleasant for those around us but even more enjoyable for us who embody those qualities.

676 Homer, "Iliad," xxii. 373.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 22.373.

677 Alluded to again "On the tranquillity of the mind," § i.

677 Mentioned again in "On the calmness of the mind," § i.

678 The allusion is to Homer's "Odyssey," xx. 23.

678 The reference is to Homer's "Odyssey," xx. 23.

679 Reading ἐξ ἑαυτοῦ with Reiske.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading from himself with Reiske.

680 Euripides, "Orestes," 72.

Euripides, "Orestes," 72.

681 Euripides, "Orestes," 99.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Orestes," 99.

682 Fragment 361.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Fragment 361.

683 Homer, "Iliad," xvii. 591.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 17.591.

684 The reading of the MSS. is αὐτῶν.

684 The reading of the manuscripts is theirs.

685 Lines of Callimachus. φλιήν is the admirable emendation of Salmasius.

685 Lines of Callimachus. φλιήν is the excellent correction suggested by Salmasius.

686 Sophocles, "Thamyras," Fragm. 232.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Sophocles, "Thamyras," Fragment 232.

687 "Iliad," v. 214-216.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," v. 214-216.

688 Reading ἐνίοις, as Wyttenbach suggests.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading sometimes, as Wyttenbach suggests.

689 Aeschylus, "Prometheus," 574, 575.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Aeschylus, "Prometheus," 574, 575.

690 It will be seen I adopt the reading and punctuation of Xylander.

690 As you can see, I’ve taken Xylander's reading and punctuation.

691 This is the reading of Reiske and Dübner.

691 This is the interpretation of Reiske and Dübner.

692 That is mild. Zeus is so called, Pausanias, i. 37; ii. 9, 20.

692 That is mild. Zeus is referred to as such, Pausanias, i. 37; ii. 9, 20.

693 That is, fierce, furious. It will be seen I adopt the suggestion of Reiske.

693 That is, intense, angry. You'll notice I took Reiske's suggestion.

694 Literally "is silent about." It is like the saying about Von Moltke that he can be silent in six or seven languages.

694 Literally "doesn't say anything." It's like the saying about Von Moltke that he can be quiet in six or seven languages.

695 Adopting Reiske's reading.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Adopting Reiske's interpretation.

696 Compare Pausanias, iv. 8.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare Pausanias 4.8.

697 Dübner puts this sentence in brackets.

697 Dübner puts this sentence in brackets.

698 Sophocles, "Antigone," 563, 564.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Sophocles, "Antigone," 563, 564.

699 Homer, "Iliad," xix. 138.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 19.138.

700 Homer, "Odyssey," xx. 392.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Odyssey," xx. 392.

701 Or strigils.

Or strigils.

702 Anticyra was famous for its hellebore, which was prescribed in cases of madness. See Horace, "Satires," ii. 3. 82, 83.

702 Anticyra was known for its hellebore, which was used to treat madness. See Horace, "Satires," ii. 3. 82, 83.

703 Homer, "Iliad," xxiv. 239, 240.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," Book 24, lines 239, 240.

704 A philosopher of Megara, and disciple of Socrates. Compare our author, "De Fraterno Amore," § xviii.

704 A philosopher from Megara and a student of Socrates. See our author, "De Fraterno Amore," § xviii.

705 So Reiske. Dübner reads φόβου. The MSS. have φόνου, which Wyttenbach retains, but is evidently not quite satisfied with the text. Can φθόνου—ἑτερον be an account of ἐπιχαιρεκακια?

705 So Reiske. Dübner reads φόβου. The manuscripts have φόνου, which Wyttenbach keeps, but he’s clearly not completely satisfied with the text. Can φθόνου—ἑτερον be an explanation of ἐπιχαιρεκακια?

706 Up in the clouds. Cf. ἀεροβατέω.

706 Up in the clouds. See ἀεροβατέω.

707 Horace, remembering these lines no doubt, says "De Arte Poetica," 191, 192,

707 Horace, recalling these lines for sure, states in "De Arte Poetica," 191, 192,

"Let no god intervene unless a worthy avenger ties the knot." Incidents.

708 It is quite likely that the delicious poet Robert Herrick borrowed hence his "To starve thy sin not bin, That is to keep thy Lent." For we know he was a student of the "Moralia" when at the University of Cambridge.

708 It’s very likely that the talented poet Robert Herrick took inspiration from this for his line, "To starve thy sin not bin, That is to keep thy Lent." We know he studied the "Moralia" while at the University of Cambridge.

709 See Æschylus, "Eumenides," 107. Sophocles, "Œdipus Colonæus," 481. See also our author's "De Sanitate Præcepta," § xix.

709 See Æschylus, "Eumenides," 107. Sophocles, "Œdipus Colonæus," 481. Also check our author's "De Sanitate Præcepta," § xix.

710 Jeremy Taylor has closely imitated parts of this Dialogue in his "Holy Living," chapter iv. sect. viii., "Twelve remedies against anger, by way of exercise," "Thirteen remedies against anger, by way of consideration." Such a storehouse did he make of the "Moralia."

710 Jeremy Taylor has closely mimicked parts of this Dialogue in his "Holy Living," chapter iv. section viii., "Twelve remedies for anger, through practice," "Thirteen remedies for anger, through contemplation." He created a significant resource from the "Moralia."


ON CONTENTEDNESS OF MIND.711

PLUTARCH SENDS GREETING TO PACCIUS.

§ i. It was late when I received your letter, asking me to write to you something on contentedness of mind, and on those things in the Timæus that require an accurate explanation. And it so fell out that at that very time our friend Eros was obliged to set sail at once for Rome, having received a letter from the excellent Fundanus, urging haste according to his wont. And not having as much time as I could have wished to meet your request, and yet not thinking for one moment of letting my messenger go to you entirely empty-handed, I copied out the notes that I had chanced to make on contentedness of mind. For I thought that you did not desire this discourse merely to be treated to a subject handled in fine style, but for the real business of life. And I congratulate you that, though you have friendships with princes, and have as much forensic reputation as anybody, yet you are not in the same plight as the tragic Merops, nor have you like him by the felicitations of the multitude been induced to forget the sufferings of humanity; but you remember, what you have often heard, that a patrician's slipper712 is no cure for the gout, nor a costly ring for a whitlow, nor a diadem for the headache. For how can riches, or fame, or power at court help us to ease of mind or a calm life, unless we enjoy them when present, but are not for ever pining after them when absent? And what else causes this but the long exercise and practice of reason, which, when the unreasoning and emotional part of the soul breaks out of bounds, curbs it quickly, and does not allow it to be carried away headlong from its actual position? And as Xenophon713 advised that we should remember and honour the gods most especially in prosperity, that so, when we should be in any strait, we might confidently call upon them as already our well-wishers290 and friends; so sensible men would do well before trouble comes to meditate on remedies how to bear it, that they may be the more efficacious from being ready for use long before. For as savage dogs are excited at every sound, and are only soothed by a familiar voice, so also it is not easy to quiet the wild passions of the soul, unless familiar and well-known arguments be at hand to check its excitement.

§ i. It was late when I got your letter asking me to write something about being content and on the topics in the Timæus that need a clear explanation. Just at that moment, our friend Eros had to leave for Rome right away because he received a letter from the great Fundanus, urging him to hurry as he usually does. With not enough time to fully respond to your request, and not wanting my messenger to go to you completely empty-handed, I copied the notes I had made on being content. I figured you didn’t want this discussion just for its polished style but for its practical value in life. I'm glad to see that, even with connections to powerful people and a strong reputation in legal matters, you're not like the tragic Merops, swayed by the praise of others to forget human suffering; instead, you remember, as you've heard often, that a patrician's slipper712 doesn’t cure gout, nor does a fancy ring fix a whitlow, nor a crown relieve a headache. How can wealth, fame, or political power bring us peace of mind or a calm life unless we enjoy them while we have them, instead of constantly longing for what we lack? What causes this longing but long practice in reasoning, which quickly restrains the unruly and emotional parts of our soul from going out of control? Just as Xenophon713 advised us to honor the gods especially when we are prosperous, so that when we face difficulties, we can confidently call on them as our supporters and friends; sensible people should prepare for difficulties before they arrive, finding ways to cope that will be effective because they are thought through in advance. Just as wild dogs get agitated at every sound and can only be calmed by a familiar voice, it’s also tough to calm the wild emotions of the soul without ready and familiar arguments to tame its frenzy.

§ ii. He then that said, that the man that wished to have an easy mind ought to have little to do either public or private, first of all makes ease of mind a very costly article for us, if it is to be bought at the price of doing nothing, as if he should advise every sick person,

§ ii. He then said that anyone who wants to have peace of mind should keep themselves busy with little public or private involvement. This makes peace of mind a very expensive thing for us, especially if it comes at the cost of doing nothing, as if he were advising every sick person,

"Lie still, you poor soul, in bed."714

And indeed stupor is a bad remedy for the body against despair,715 nor is he any better physician of the soul who removes its trouble and anxiety by recommending a lazy and soft life and a leaving our friends and relations and country in the lurch. In the next place, it is false that those that have little to do are easy in mind. For then women would be easier in mind than men, since they mostly stay at home in inactivity, and even now-a-days it is as Hesiod says,716

And indeed, being numb isn't a good solution for the body against despair,715 and neither is someone a better healer of the soul who eases its pain and stress by suggesting a lazy and easy life while abandoning our friends, family, and homeland. Furthermore, it's not true that those who have little to do have peace of mind. If that were the case, women would be more at ease than men, as they often stay at home in idleness, and even today, as Hesiod says,716

"The North Wind doesn't come close to a tender-skinned girl;"

yet griefs and troubles and unrest, proceeding from jealousy or superstition or ambition or vanity, inundate the women's part of the house with unceasing flow. And Laertes, though he lived for twenty years a solitary life in the country,

yet grief, troubles, and unrest, arising from jealousy, superstition, ambition, or vanity, continuously flood the women's part of the house. And Laertes, although he spent twenty years living alone in the country,

"With an elderly woman to take care of him, He properly placed his food and drinks on board, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

and fled from his country and house and kingdom, yet had sorrow and dejection718 as a perpetual companion with leisure. And some have been often thrown into sad unrest merely from inaction, as the following,

and ran away from his country, home, and kingdom, but still had sadness and disappointment718 as constant companions along with leisure. Some have often found themselves in deep sorrow simply due to idleness, as shown below,

"But swift Achilles, born of Zeus, son of Peleus, Sat by the fast-moving ships and simmered, 291Nor did I often attend the esteemed council, Nor did I ever join the battle, but longed inside, Though staying in his tent, ready for battle.719

And full of emotion and distress at this state of things he himself says,

And filled with emotion and distress over this situation, he himself says,

"A useless burden on the earth, I sit." Beside the ships.

So even Epicurus thinks that those who are desirous of honour and glory should not rust in inglorious ease, but use their natural talents in public life for the benefit of the community at large, seeing that they are by nature so constituted that they would be more likely to be troubled and afflicted at inaction, if they did not get what they desired. But he is absurd in that he does not urge men of ability to take part in public life, but only the restless. But we ought not to estimate ease or unrest of mind by our many or few actions, but by their fairness or foulness. For the omission of fair actions troubles and distresses us, as I have said before, quite as much as the actual doing of foul actions.

Even Epicurus believes that those who seek honor and glory shouldn’t waste away in unremarkable comfort, but should use their natural talents in public life to benefit the community, since they are naturally inclined to feel troubled and disturbed by inactivity if they don't achieve what they want. However, he is misguided in suggesting that only the restless individuals should engage in public life. Instead, we shouldn't measure our peace or unrest by how many actions we take, but by the quality of those actions. As I've mentioned before, neglecting to perform good actions can trouble and distress us just as much as committing bad actions.

§ iii. As for those who think that one kind of life is especially free from trouble, as some think that of farmers, others that of bachelors, others that of kings, Menander sufficiently exposes their error in the following lines:

§ iii. As for those who believe that one type of life is completely free from problems—some think it's the life of farmers, others the life of bachelors, and still others the life of kings—Menander clearly reveals their mistake in the following lines:

"Phania, I believed that the wealthy who don't need to borrow, Don't groan at night, and don't cry out, 'Woe is me,' Kicked around in this harsh world, "But they may enjoy sweet and gentle sleep."

He then goes on to remark that he saw the rich suffering the same as the poor,

He then goes on to say that he saw the rich suffering just like the poor,

"Trouble and life are really quite similar." With a luxurious or glorious life Trouble loves company, and in a life of poverty "Stays with it until the end."

But just as people on the sea, timid and prone to sea-sickness, think they will suffer from it less on board a merchantman than on a boat, and for the same reason shift their quarters to a trireme, but do not attain anything by these changes, for they take with them their timidity and qualmishness, so changes of life do not remove the sorrows and troubles 292of the soul; which proceed from want of experience and reflection, and from inability or ignorance rightly to enjoy the present. These afflict the rich as well as the poor; these trouble the married as well as the unmarried; these make people shun the forum, but find no happiness in retirement; these make people eagerly desire introductions at court, though when got they straightway care no more about them.

But just like people at sea, who are nervous and easily seasick, think they’ll be less affected on a merchant ship than on a small boat, and for the same reason might move to a trireme, they don’t actually change anything because they carry their anxiety and nausea with them. Likewise, changes in life don’t remove the pains and troubles 292 of the soul; those come from lacking experience and self-reflection, and from the inability or ignorance to truly enjoy the present. These issues plague both the rich and the poor; they trouble the married as well as the single; they push people to avoid public life, yet they don’t find happiness in solitude; they make people eager for connections at court, but once they have them, they quickly lose interest.

"People who are ill tend to be irritable in their struggles and necessities."721

For the wife bothers them, and they grumble at the doctor, and they find the bed uneasy, and, as Ion says,

For the wife annoys them, they complain about the doctor, they find the bed uncomfortable, and, as Ion says,

"The friend who visits them tests their patience, And yet, they don't want him to leave.

But afterwards, when the illness is over, and a sounder condition supervenes, health returns and makes all things pleasant and acceptable. He that yesterday loathed eggs and cakes of finest meal and purest bread will to-day eat eagerly and with appetite coarsest bread with a few olives and cress.

But later, when the illness is gone and a healthier state comes about, health returns and makes everything enjoyable and acceptable. The person who yesterday couldn’t stand the finest eggs and cakes, as well as the purest bread, will today eagerly eat even the coarsest bread with a few olives and cress.

§ iv. Such contentedness and change of view in regard to every kind of life does the infusion of reason bring about. When Alexander heard from Anaxarchus of the infinite number of worlds, he wept, and when his friends asked him what was the matter, he replied, "Is it not a matter for tears that, when the number of worlds is infinite, I have not conquered one?" But Crates, who had only a wallet and threadbare cloak, passed all his life jesting and laughing as if at a festival. Agamemnon was troubled with his rule over so many subjects,

§ iv. This sense of contentment and shift in perspective about all kinds of life comes from the influence of reason. When Alexander learned from Anaxarchus about the endless number of worlds, he cried. When his friends asked him what was wrong, he said, "Isn't it sad that, with an infinite number of worlds, I've not conquered even one?" Yet Crates, who only had a bag and a worn-out cloak, spent his entire life joking and laughing as if he were at a party. Agamemnon struggled with the burden of ruling over so many subjects,

"You gaze at Agamemnon, Atreus' son, Whom Zeus has immersed forever in a mass Of endless worries.722

But Diogenes when he was being sold sat down and kept jeering at the auctioneer, and would not stand up when he bade him, but said joking and laughing, "Would you tell a fish you were selling to stand up?" And Socrates in prison played the philosopher and discoursed with his 293friends. But Phäethon,723 when he got up to heaven, wept because nobody gave to him his father's horses and chariot. As therefore the shoe is shaped by the foot, and not the foot by the shoe, so does the disposition make the life similar to itself. For it is not, as one said, custom that makes the best life seem sweet to those that choose it, but it is sense that makes that very life at once the best and sweetest. Let us cleanse therefore the fountain of contentedness, which is within us, that so external things may turn out for our good, through our putting the best face on them.

But Diogenes, when he was being sold, sat down and kept mocking the auctioneer, refusing to stand up when he asked him to. He joked and laughed, saying, "Would you tell a fish you were selling to stand up?" And Socrates, in prison, played the philosopher and talked with his friends. But Phaethon, when he reached heaven, cried because no one gave him his father's horses and chariot. Just like a shoe is shaped by the foot, and not the other way around, our disposition shapes our life to match it. It's not just habit that makes the best life seem enjoyable to those who choose it; it's our understanding that makes that life both the best and the sweetest. So let's cleanse the source of our contentment, which is within us, so that external things can turn out for our good by putting the best spin on them.

"Events will unfold as they will; there's no point in worrying about it." When we're angry at them, he is the happiest. "Who wisely makes the best use of them." 724

§ v. Plato compared human life to a game at dice, wherein we ought to throw according to our requirements, and, having thrown, to make the best use of whatever turns up. It is not in our power indeed to determine what the throw will be, but it is our part, if we are wise, to accept in a right spirit whatever fortune sends, and so to contrive matters that what we wish should do us most good, and what we do not wish should do us least harm. For those who live at random and without judgement, like those sickly people who can stand neither heat nor cold, are unduly elated by prosperity, and cast down by adversity; and in either case suffer from unrest, but 'tis their own fault, and perhaps they suffer most in what are called good circumstances. Theodorus, who was surnamed the Atheist, used to say that he held out arguments with his right hand, but his hearers received them with their left; so awkward people frequently take in a clumsy manner the favours of fortune; but men of sense, as bees extract honey from thyme which is the strongest and driest of herbs,725 so from the least auspicious circumstances frequently derive advantage and profit.

§ v. Plato compared human life to a dice game, where we should roll according to our needs, and once we roll, make the best out of whatever comes up. We can’t control what the roll will be, but if we’re wise, we should accept whatever fortune brings us with the right attitude and arrange things so that what we want brings us the most good, and what we don’t want causes us the least harm. Those who live randomly and without judgment, like those who can’t handle either heat or cold, get too excited by good times and too upset by bad times; in both situations, they’re restless, but it’s their own fault, and they might suffer the most when things seem good. Theodorus, nicknamed the Atheist, used to say that he presented his arguments with his right hand, but his listeners received them with their left; similarly, clumsy people often mishandle the benefits of fortune. In contrast, sensible individuals, like bees gathering honey from thyme, which is one of the toughest and driest herbs,725 can often find advantage and gain even in the least favorable situations.

§ vi. We ought then to cultivate such a habit as this, 294like the man who threw a stone at his dog, and missed it, but hit his step-mother, and cried out, "Not so bad." Thus we may often turn the edge of fortune when things turn not out as we wish. Diogenes was driven into exile; "not so bad;" for his exile made him turn philosopher. And Zeno of Cittium,726 when he heard that the only merchantman he had was wrecked, cargo and all, said, "Fortune, you treat me handsomely, since you reduce me to my threadbare cloak and piazza."727 What prevents our imitating such men as these? Have you failed to get some office? You will be able to live in the country henceforth, and manage your own affairs. Did you court the friendship of some great man, and meet with a rebuff? You will live free from danger and cares. Have you again had matters to deal with that required labour and thought? "Warm water will not so much make the limbs soft by soaking," to quote Pindar,728 as glory and honour and power make "labour sweet, and toil to be no toil."729 Or has any bad luck or contumely fallen on you in consequence of some calumny or from envy? The breeze is favourable that will waft you to the Muses and the Academy, as it did Plato when his friendship with Dionysius came to an end. It does indeed greatly conduce to contentedness of mind to see how famous men have borne the same troubles with an unruffled mind. For example, does childlessness trouble you? Consider those kings of the Romans, none of whom left his kingdom to a son. Are you distressed at the pinch of poverty? Who of the Bœotians would you rather prefer to be than Epaminondas, or of the Romans than Fabricius? Has your wife been seduced? Have you never read that inscription at Delphi,

§ vi. We should develop a habit like this, 294 similar to the guy who threw a stone at his dog and missed, hitting his step-mother instead, and simply said, "Not so bad." In this way, we can often soften our misfortune when things don’t go as we planned. Diogenes was exiled; he thought, "not so bad," because his exile led him to become a philosopher. Zeno of Cittium,726 when he heard that the only ship he owned was wrecked along with its cargo, remarked, "Fortune, you treat me well, since you’ve reduced me to my old cloak and my piazza."727 What stops us from following the example of such people? Did you miss out on a job? Now you can live in the countryside and manage your own affairs. Did you seek the friendship of an important person and get turned down? You’ll live free from danger and worries. Have you had to deal with tasks that required effort and thought? "Warm water doesn’t just soften limbs by soaking," to quote Pindar,728 "glory and honor and power make hard work feel fulfilling." 729 Or did bad luck or insults come your way because of slander or jealousy? There’s a favorable wind that can take you to the Muses and the Academy, just like it did for Plato when his friendship with Dionysius ended. It truly helps to find peace of mind by seeing how famous individuals managed similar struggles with calmness. For instance, are you troubled by not having children? Think about those Roman kings, none of whom passed their kingdoms to a son. Are you worried about being poor? Who in Bœotia would you rather be than Epaminondas, or in Rome than Fabricius? Has your wife been unfaithful? Have you never read that inscription at Delphi,

"King Agis of land and sea set me up;"

and have you not heard that his wife Timæa was seduced by Alcibiades, and in her whispers to her handmaidens called the child that was born Alcibiades? Yet this did not prevent Agis from being the most famous and greatest 295of the Greeks. Neither again did the licentiousness of his daughter prevent Stilpo from leading the merriest life of all the philosophers that were his contemporaries. And when Metrocles reproached him with her life, he said, "Is it my fault or hers?" And when Metrocles answered, "Her fault, but your misfortune," he rejoined, "How say you? Are not faults also slips?" "Certainly," said he. "And are not slips mischances in those matters wherein we slip?" Metrocles assented. "And are not mischances misfortunes in those matters wherein we mischance?" By this gentle and philosophical argument he demonstrated the Cynic's reproach to be an idle bark.

and have you not heard that his wife Timæa was seduced by Alcibiades, and in her whispers to her handmaidens called the child that was born Alcibiades? Yet this did not stop Agis from being the most famous and greatest 295 of the Greeks. Likewise, the promiscuity of his daughter did not stop Stilpo from living the happiest life of all the philosophers of his time. When Metrocles criticized him about her lifestyle, he said, "Is it my fault or hers?" When Metrocles replied, "Her fault, but your misfortune," he responded, "What do you mean? Are not faults also mistakes?" "Certainly," he answered. "And are not mistakes misfortunes in those situations where we err?" Metrocles agreed. "And are not misfortunes disasters in those situations where we have misfortunes?" With this gentle and philosophical argument, he showed that the Cynic's criticism was meaningless.

§ vii. But most people are troubled and exasperated not only at the bad in their friends and intimates, but also in their enemies. For railing and anger and envy and malignity and jealousy and ill-will are the bane of those that suffer from those infirmities, and trouble and exasperate the foolish: as for example the quarrels of neighbours, and peevishness of acquaintances, and the want of ability in those that manage state affairs. By these things you yourself seem to me to be put out not a little, as the doctors in Sophocles, who

§ vii. But most people are disturbed and frustrated not only by the flaws in their friends and close ones but also in their enemies. Complaining, anger, envy, malice, jealousy, and hostility are the curses for those suffering from these flaws, and they annoy and frustrate the foolish as well. For instance, consider the fights between neighbors, the irritability of acquaintances, and the incompetence of those in charge of public affairs. It seems to me that you are bothered by these things quite a bit, just like the doctors in Sophocles, who

"Use a harsh remedy to get rid of the bitter bile,"730

so vexed and bitter are you at people's weaknesses and infirmities, which is not reasonable in you. Even your own private affairs are not always managed by simple and good and suitable instruments, so to speak, but very frequently by sharp and crooked ones. Do not think it then either your business, or an easy matter either, to set all these things to rights. But if you take people as they are, as the surgeon uses his bandages and instruments for drawing teeth, and with cheerfulness and serenity welcome all that happens, as you would look upon barking dogs as only following their nature, you will be happier in the disposition you will then have than you will be distressed at other people's disagreeableness and shortcomings. For you will forget to make a collection of disagreeable things,731 which 296now inundate, as some hollow and low-lying ground, your littleness of mind and weakness, which fills itself with other people's bad points. For seeing that some of the philosophers censure compassion to the unfortunate (on the ground that it is good to help our neighbours, and not to give way to sentimental sympathy in connection with them), and, what is of more importance, do not allow those that are conscious of their errors and bad moral disposition to be dejected and grieved at them, but bid them cure their defects without grief at once, is it not altogether unreasonable, look you, to allow ourselves to be peevish and vexed, because all those who have dealings with us and come near us are not good and clever? Let us see to it, dear Paccius, that we do not, whether we are aware of it or not, play a part, really looking732 not at the universal defects of those that approach us, but at our own interests through our selfishness, and not through our hatred of evil. For excessive excitement about things, and an undue appetite and desire for them, or on the other hand aversion and dislike to them, engender suspiciousness and peevishness against persons, who were, we think, the cause of our being deprived of some things, and of being troubled with others. But he that is accustomed to adapt himself to things easily and calmly is most cheerful and gentle in his dealings with people.

You're really annoyed and bitter about people's flaws and shortcomings, which isn't reasonable. Even your own personal matters aren't always handled by straightforward and good methods, but often by tricky and twisted ones. Don’t think it’s your job or that it’s easy to fix everything. Instead, if you accept people as they are, like a surgeon uses bandages and tools for pulling teeth, and you face everything with a positive attitude, welcoming all that happens as you would see barking dogs just following their nature, you’ll find yourself happier than you would be upset over other people's annoyances and failures. You’ll stop gathering a list of unpleasant things, which now flood your mind and weakness, filling it with other people's flaws. Some philosophers criticize compassion for the unfortunate, saying it’s good to help others without indulging in sentimental sympathy, and more importantly, they advise those aware of their mistakes not to dwell on them but to fix them without grief. So, isn’t it unreasonable for us to be irritable and upset because not everyone around us is good and capable? Let’s make sure, dear Paccius, that we don’t unwittingly act, focusing not on universal flaws in those who come near us but rather on our own interests out of selfishness, rather than a real concern about evil. Getting overly excited about things or having excessive desire for them, or conversely, feeling aversion and dislike, leads to suspicion and irritability towards people we think are the reason we’re missing out on things or dealing with difficulties. But someone who’s used to adapting easily and calmly to situations is the most cheerful and gentle in their interactions with others.

§ viii. Wherefore let us resume our argument. As in a fever everything seems bitter and unpleasant to the taste, but when we see others not loathing but fancying the very same eatables and drinkables, we no longer find the fault to be in them but in ourselves and our disease, so we shall cease to blame and be discontented with the state of affairs, if we see others cheerfully and without grief enduring the same. It also makes for contentedness, when things happen against our wish, not to overlook our many advantages and comforts, but by looking at both good and bad to feel that the good preponderate. When our eyes are dazzled with things too bright we turn them away, and ease them by looking at flowers or grass, while we keep the eyes of our mind strained on disagreeable things, and force 297them to dwell on bitter ideas, well-nigh tearing them away by force from the consideration of pleasanter things. And yet one might apply here, not unaptly, what was said to the man of curiosity,733

§ viii. So, let’s get back to our discussion. Just like when you have a fever and everything tastes bitter and unpleasant, when we see others enjoying the same foods and drinks we dislike, we stop blaming them and start realizing the issue is with ourselves and our condition. Similarly, we’ll be less likely to complain or feel unhappy about our situation if we observe others happily dealing with the same challenges. It also helps to be content when things don’t go our way if we focus on our many blessings and comforts, recognizing that the positives outweigh the negatives. When we’re overwhelmed by things that are too bright, we naturally look away to ease our eyes by focusing on flowers or grass, yet we often keep our minds fixated on unpleasant thoughts, forcing ourselves to dwell on negative ideas instead of considering more pleasant ones. And still, one might recall what was said to the man who was curious,733

"Malicious wretch, why are you so eager to mark" "Why do you see your neighbor's mistakes, but not your own?"

Why on earth, my good sir, do you confine your view to your troubles, making them so vivid and acute, while you do not let your mind dwell at all on your present comforts? But as cupping-glasses draw the worst blood from the flesh, so you force upon your attention the worst things in your lot: acting not a whit more wisely than that Chian, who, selling much choice wine to others, asked for some sour wine for his own supper; and one of his slaves being asked by another, what he had left his master doing, replied, "Asking for bad when good was by." For most people overlook the advantages and pleasures of their individual lives, and run to their difficulties and grievances. Aristippus, however, was not such a one, for he cleverly knew as in a scale to make the better preponderate over the worse. So having lost a good farm, he asked one of those who made a great show of condolence and sympathy, "Have you not only one little piece of ground, while I have three fields left?" And when he admitted that it was so, he went on to say, "Ought I not then to condole with you rather than you with me?" For it is the act of a madman to distress oneself over what is lost, and not to rejoice at what is left; but like little children, if one of their many playthings be taken away by anyone, throw the rest away and weep and cry out, so we, if we are assailed by fortune in some one point, wail and mourn and make all other things seem unprofitable in our eyes.

Why on earth, my good sir, do you focus solely on your troubles, making them so vivid and sharp, while you ignore your current comforts? Just like cupping glasses pull the worst blood from the flesh, you force your attention to the worst aspects of your situation: you’re no wiser than that Chian, who, while selling fine wine to others, asked for sour wine for his own dinner; and when one of his slaves was asked by another what he had left his master doing, he replied, "Asking for bad wine when good is right there." Most people overlook the advantages and joys of their lives and gravitate toward their troubles and grievances. However, Aristippus was not like that; he skillfully knew how to let the better things outweigh the worse. After losing a good farm, he asked one of those who feigned sympathy, "Don't you only have one small piece of land, while I still have three fields left?" When the other admitted this was true, he continued, "Shouldn't I be the one to sympathize with you instead?" It's foolish to dwell on what you've lost and not to celebrate what remains; like little children, if one of their many toys is taken away, they throw the rest aside and weep, so we, if fortune strikes at one point, wail and mourn and make everything else seem worthless in our eyes.

§ ix. Suppose someone should say, What blessings have we? I would reply, What have we not? One has reputation, another a house, another a wife, another a good friend. When Antipater of Tarsus was reckoning up on his death-bed his various pieces of good fortune, he did not 298even pass over his favourable voyage from Cilicia to Athens. So we should not overlook, but take account of everyday blessings, and rejoice that we live, and are well, and see the sun, and that no war or sedition plagues our country, but that the earth is open to cultivation, the sea secure to mariners, and that we can speak or be silent, lead a busy or an idle life, as we choose. We shall get more contentedness from the presence of all these blessings, if we fancy them as absent, and remember from time to time how people ill yearn for health, and people in war for peace, and strangers and unknown in a great city for reputation and friends, and how painful it is to be deprived of all these when one has once had them. For then each of these blessings will not appear to us only great and valuable when it is lost, and of no value while we have it. For not having it cannot add value to anything. Nor ought we to amass things we regard as valuable, and always be on the tremble and afraid of losing them as valuable things, and yet, when we have them, ignore them and think little of them; but we ought to use them for our pleasure and enjoyment, that we may bear their loss, if that should happen, with more equanimity. But most people, as Arcesilaus said, think it right to inspect minutely and in every detail, perusing them alike with the eyes of the body and mind, other people's poems and paintings and statues, while they neglect to study their own lives, which have often many not unpleasing subjects for contemplation, looking abroad and ever admiring other people's reputations and fortunes, as adulterers admire other men's wives, and think cheap of their own.

§ ix. If someone were to ask, "What blessings do we have?" I would respond, "What don’t we have?" One person has a good reputation, another has a house, someone else has a spouse, and another has a great friend. When Antipater of Tarsus was reflecting on his good fortune on his deathbed, he didn’t even skip over the good fortune of his journey from Cilicia to Athens. We shouldn’t overlook, but rather acknowledge our daily blessings and be grateful that we are alive, healthy, seeing the sun, and that our country isn’t troubled by war or unrest. The fields are open for farming, the seas are safe for sailors, and we have the freedom to speak or remain silent, to be busy or relaxed, as we choose. We’ll find more contentment in all these blessings if we imagine them as absent and occasionally remember how much people long for health in illness, peace in conflict, and reputation and friends when alone in a big city—and how painful it is to lose them once we’ve had them. Because of this, we should recognize that these blessings only seem great and valuable when they’re gone, and that they're taken for granted while we have them. Not having them doesn’t add value to anything. We shouldn’t hoard what we consider valuable and live in constant fear of losing them, only to neglect them when they're ours. Instead, we should enjoy them so that if we ever lose them, we can accept that loss with more ease. Yet most people, as Arcesilaus said, believe it's right to scrutinize and appreciate in detail the works of others—like poems, paintings, and statues—while they overlook their own lives, which often offer many pleasing subjects for reflection. They gaze outward, constantly admiring the reputations and fortunes of others, just as unfaithful spouses admire other men’s wives while undervaluing their own.

§ x. And yet it makes much for contentedness of mind to look for the most part at home and to our own condition, or if not, to look at the case of people worse off than ourselves, and not, as most people do, to compare ourselves with those who are better off. For example, those who are in chains think those happy who are freed from their chains, and they again freemen, and freemen citizens, and they again the rich, and the rich satraps, and satraps kings, and kings the gods, content with hardly anything short of hurling thunderbolts and lightning. And so they ever299 want something above them, and are never thankful for what they have.

§ x. Yet, it's very helpful for our peace of mind to focus mostly on our own lives and circumstances, or if not, to look at those who are worse off than we are, instead of comparing ourselves to those who have more. For instance, people in chains see those who are free as happy, and free people see citizens as happier, and citizens look at the wealthy, and the wealthy see satraps, and satraps see kings, and kings consider the gods, who seem to be satisfied only with the power to throw thunderbolts and lightning. So, they always want something beyond what they have, and are never grateful for their own blessings.

"I don't care about the wealth of golden Gyges,"

and,

and,

"I never had envy or desire." To be a god or to love a powerful empire, "All those things are far out of my sight."

But this, you will say, was the language of a Thasian. But you will find others, Chians or Galatians or Bithynians, not content with the share of glory or power they have among their fellow-citizens, but weeping because they do not wear senators' shoes; or, if they have them, that they cannot be prætors at Rome; or, if they get that office, that they are not consuls; or, if they are consuls, that they are only proclaimed second and not first. What is all this but seeking out excuses for being unthankful to fortune, only to torment and punish oneself? But he that has a mind in sound condition, does not sit down in sorrow and dejection if he is less renowned or rich than some of the countless myriads of mankind that the sun looks upon, "who feed on the produce of the wide world,"734 but goes on his way rejoicing at his fortune and life, as far fairer and happier than that of myriads of others. In the Olympian games it is not possible to be the victor by choosing one's competitors. But in the race of life circumstances allow us to plume ourselves on surpassing many, and to be objects of envy rather than to have to envy others, unless we pit ourselves against a Briareus or a Hercules. Whenever then you admire anyone carried by in his litter as a greater man than yourself, lower your eyes and look at those that bear the litter. And when you think the famous Xerxes happy for his passage over the Hellespont, as a native of those parts735 did, look too at those who dug through Mount Athos under the lash, and at those whose ears and noses were cut off because the bridge was broken by the waves, consider their state of mind also, for they think your life and fortunes happy. Socrates, when he heard one of his friends saying, "How 300dear this city is! Chian wine costs one mina,736 a purple robe three, and half a pint of honey five drachmæ," took him to the meal market, and showed him half a peck of meal for an obol, then took him to the olive market, and showed him a peck of olives for two coppers, and lastly showed him that a sleeveless vest737 was only ten drachmæ. At each place Socrates' friend exclaimed, "How cheap this city is!" So also we, when we hear anyone saying that our affairs are bad and in a woful plight, because we are not consuls or governors, may reply, "Our affairs are in an admirable condition, and our life an enviable one, seeing that we do not beg, nor carry burdens, nor live by flattery."

But you'll say this was the perspective of someone from Thasos. Yet you'll find others, from Chios, Galatia, or Bithynia, who aren’t satisfied with their share of glory or power among their peers. They lament because they don’t wear the shoes of senators; or, if they do have them, they’re upset that they can’t be praetors in Rome; or, if they achieve that position, they're unhappy that they aren't consuls; or, if they are consuls, they complain about being second instead of first. What is all of this but searching for reasons to be ungrateful to fortune, only to torment and punish themselves? But a person with a clear mind doesn’t wallow in sorrow and gloom just because they are less famous or wealthy than some of the countless people the sun shines upon, "who feed on the produce of the wide world,"734 but moves forward with joy in their fortune and life, which are much better and happier than those of countless others. In the Olympic games, you can’t become a champion by choosing your competitors. But in the race of life, circumstances let us take pride in surpassing many and being envied rather than being envious of others, unless we compare ourselves to someone like Briareus or Hercules. So whenever you admire someone being carried in a litter as a greater person than yourself, lower your gaze and look at those who carry the litter. And when you think Xerxes was lucky for crossing the Hellespont, just as a local did, consider also those who were forced to dig through Mount Athos under the whip, and those whose ears and noses were cut off because the bridge was destroyed by waves. Reflect on their state of mind, for they see your life and fortunes as fortunate. When Socrates heard one of his friends say, "How dear this city is! Chian wine costs one mina,736 a purple robe three, and half a pint of honey five drachmæ," he took him to the grain market and showed him half a peck of grain for an obol, then took him to the olive market and showed him a peck of olives for two coppers, and finally showed him that a sleeveless vest737 only cost ten drachmæ. At each place, Socrates' friend exclaimed, "How cheap this city is!" Similarly, when we hear anyone saying our situation is dire just because we aren’t consuls or governors, we can respond, "Our affairs are in excellent condition, and our life is enviable, considering that we do not beg, carry burdens, or live by flattery."

§ xi. But since through our folly we are accustomed to live more with an eye to others than ourselves, and since nature is so jealous and envious that it rejoices not so much in its own blessings as it is pained by those of others, do not look only at the much-cried-up splendour of those whom you envy and admire, but open and draw, as it were, the gaudy curtain of their pomp and show, and peep within, you will see that they have much to trouble them, and many things to annoy them. The well-known Pittacus,738 whose fame was so great for fortitude and wisdom and uprightness, was once entertaining some guests, and his wife came in in a rage and upset the table, and as the guests were dismayed he said, Every one of you has some trouble, and he who has mine only is not so bad off.

§ xi. But since we often care more about how others see us than how we see ourselves, and since nature has a way of being jealous and envious, finding less joy in its own blessings and more pain in the prosperity of others, don’t just focus on the flashy success of those you envy and admire. Instead, pull back the extravagant curtain of their show and take a closer look; you’ll find that they have their own troubles and annoyances. The well-known Pittacus,738 who was famous for his courage, wisdom, and integrity, once had some guests over when his wife stormed in, furious, and knocked over the table. As the guests looked on in shock, he said, "Everyone here has their own issues, and whoever has mine isn't so badly off."

"Happy is he regarded at the forum, But when he opens the door to his own house Three times unfortunate; for his wife controls everything, Still rules over him and is constantly arguing. "He has many sorrows that I know nothing about."

Many such cases are there, unknown to the public, for family pride casts a veil over them, to be found in wealth and glory and even in royalty.

Many such cases exist, unknown to the public, as family pride covers them up, found in wealth, fame, and even royalty.

"O joyful son of Atreus, child of fate, Blessed be your fate;"739

congratulation like this comes from an external view, from a halo of arms and horses and the pomp of war, but the inward voice of emotion testifies against all this vain glory;

Congratulations like this come from an outside perspective, from a display of arms and horses and the spectacle of war, but the inner voice of emotion speaks out against all this empty glory;

301A heavy fate has been placed on me by Zeus. The son of Cronos.740

And,

And,

"Old man, I believe your situation is one to be envied, Like any man who is free from danger "Lives his life unnoticed and in obscurity."741

By such reflections as these one may wean oneself from that discontent with one's fortune, which makes one's own condition look low and mean from too much admiring one's neighbour's.

By reflecting on thoughts like these, one can detach oneself from the dissatisfaction with their own situation, which causes them to see their life as insignificant and unworthy by overly admiring their neighbor's.

§ xii. Another thing, which is a great hindrance to peace of mind, is not to proportion our desires to our means, but to carry too much sail, as it were, in our hopes of great things and then, if unsuccessful, to blame destiny and fortune, and not our own folly. For he is not unfortunate who wishes to shoot with a plough, or hunt the hare with an ox; nor has he an evil genius opposed to him, who does not catch deer with fishing nets, but merely is the dupe of his own stupidity and folly in attempting impossibilities. Self-love is mainly to blame, making people fond of being first and aspiring in all matters, and insatiably desirous to engage in everything. For people not only wish at one and the same time to be rich, and learned, and strong, and boon-companions, and agreeable, and friends of kings, and governors of cities, but they are also discontented if they have not dogs and horses and quails and cocks of the first quality. Dionysius the elder was not content with being the most powerful monarch of his times, but because he could not beat Philoxenus the poet in singing, or surpass Plato in dialectics, was so angry and exasperated that he put the one to work in his stone quarries, and sent the other to Ægina and sold him there. Alexander was of a different spirit, for when Crisso the famous runner ran a race with him, and seemed to let the king outrun him on purpose, he was greatly displeased. Good also was the spirit of Achilles in Homer, who, when he said,

§ xii. Another thing that greatly disrupts our peace of mind is when we don’t match our desires with our means, instead trying to push too hard with our hopes for greatness. When things don’t go our way, we blame fate and fortune rather than our own foolishness. It’s not bad luck if someone wants to accomplish impossible tasks, like trying to shoot with a plow or hunt a hare with an ox; it’s just their own ignorance. People aren’t unlucky if they can’t catch deer with fishing nets, but are simply misled by their own stupidity in attempting the impossible. Self-love is the main issue here, leading people to want to be first in everything, constantly pushing to do it all. People wish to be wealthy, knowledgeable, strong, fun to be around, charming, connected to royalty, and in charge of cities, and they are unhappy if they don’t have the best dogs, horses, quails, and roosters. Dionysius the Elder wasn’t satisfied being the most powerful ruler of his time; he grew so frustrated he couldn’t out-sing the poet Philoxenus or outsmart Plato that he forced one into labor in his quarries and sold the other in Ægina. In contrast, Alexander had a different attitude. When the famous runner Crisso seemed to let him win a race on purpose, he was very displeased. Achilles in Homer also showed a similar spirit when he said,

"None of the Achaean warriors can compete" For me in battle,

302added,

added,

"Yet in the council chamber" "Others here are better than me."742

And when Megabyzus the Persian visited the studio of Apelles, and began to chatter about art, Apelles stopped him and said, "While you kept silence you seemed to be somebody from your gold and purple, but now these lads that are grinding colours are laughing at your nonsense." But some who think the Stoics only talk idly, in styling their wise man not only prudent and just and brave but also orator and general and poet and rich man and king, yet claim for themselves all those titles, and are indignant if they do not get them. And yet even among the gods different functions are assigned to different personages; thus one is called the god of war, another the god of oracles, another the god of gain, and Aphrodite, as she has nothing to do with warlike affairs, is despatched by Zeus to marriages and bridals.

And when Megabyzus the Persian visited Apelles’ studio and started talking about art, Apelles interrupted him and said, “When you were quiet, you looked important with your gold and purple, but now the guys grinding colors are laughing at your nonsense.” However, some people think the Stoics only talk aimlessly, calling their wise man not just smart, just, and brave, but also an orator, general, poet, wealthy person, and king. They claim those titles for themselves and get upset if they don’t receive them. Yet even among the gods, different roles are given to different figures; one is known as the god of war, another as the god of prophecies, another as the god of wealth, and Aphrodite, since she has nothing to do with war, is sent by Zeus to handle marriages and weddings.

§ xiii. And indeed there are some pursuits which cannot exist together, but are by their very nature opposed. For example oratory and the study of the mathematics require ease and leisure; whereas political ability and the friendship of kings cannot be attained without mixing in affairs and in public life. Moreover wine and indulgence in meat make the body indeed strong and vigorous, but blunt the intellect; and though unremitting attention to making and saving money will heap up wealth, yet despising and contemning riches is a great help to philosophy. So that all things are not within any one's power, and we must obey that saying inscribed in the temple of Apollo at Delphi, Know thyself,743 and adapt ourselves to our natural bent, and not drag and force nature to some other kind of life or pursuit. "The horse to the chariot, and the ox to the plough, and swiftly alongside the ship scuds the dolphin, while he that meditates destruction for the boar must find a staunch hound."744 But he that chafes and is grieved that he is not at one and the same time "a lion reared on the mountains, exulting in his strength,"745 and a little Maltese 303lap-dog746 reared in the lap of a rich widow, is out of his senses. And not a whit wiser is he who wishes to be an Empedocles, or Plato, or Democritus, and write about the world and the real nature of things, and at the same time to be married like Euphorion to a rich wife, or to revel and drink with Alexander like Medius; and is grieved and vexed if he is not also admired for his wealth like Ismenias, and for his virtue like Epaminondas. But runners are not discontented because they do not carry off the crowns of wrestlers, but rejoice and delight in their own crowns. "You are a citizen of Sparta: see you make the most of her." So too said Solon:

§ xiii. Some pursuits simply can't coexist because they're naturally opposed. For instance, oratory and the study of mathematics require ease and free time; on the other hand, political skills and friendships with powerful people come from being involved in public life and affairs. Additionally, while wine and rich food can strengthen the body, they dull the mind; and though constant focus on making and saving money can accumulate wealth, looking down on riches greatly aids philosophical thinking. Not everything is under anyone's control, and we should heed the saying inscribed at the temple of Apollo at Delphi, Know thyself,743 and align ourselves with our natural inclinations rather than force ourselves into different lifestyles or pursuits. "The horse to the chariot, the ox to the plow, and alongside the ship swiftly swims the dolphin, while anyone who intends to hunt the boar must rely on a good hound."744 But someone who is frustrated and upset about not being both "a lion raised in the mountains, reveling in his strength,"745 and a little Maltese 303lapdog746 spoiled by a wealthy widow has lost their mind. Equally foolish is the one who wants to be an Empedocles, Plato, or Democritus and write about the universe and the nature of reality while also being married to a rich spouse like Euphorion or partying and drinking with Alexander like Medius; and then gets upset if they're not also admired for their wealth like Ismenias or their virtue like Epaminondas. Runners don't lament not winning wrestling crowns; they take joy in their own victories. "You are a citizen of Sparta: make the most of it." So too said Solon:

"We won’t compromise our values for their money, For virtue never fades, but wealth can fly away, "And flits from one person to another."

And Strato the natural philosopher, when he heard that Menedemus had many more pupils than he had, said, "Is it wonderful at all that more wish to wash than to be anointed?" And Aristotle, writing to Antipater, said, "Not only has Alexander a right to plume himself on his rule over many subjects, but no less legitimate is satisfaction at entertaining right opinions about the gods." For those that think so highly of their own walk in life will not be so envious about their neighbours'. We do not expect a vine to bear figs, nor an olive grapes, yet now-a-days, with regard to ourselves, if we have not at one and the same time the privilege of being accounted rich and learned, generals and philosophers, flatterers and outspoken, stingy and extravagant, we slander ourselves and are dissatisfied, and despise ourselves as living a maimed and imperfect life. Furthermore, we see that nature teaches us the same lesson.747 For as she provides different kinds of beasts with different kinds of food, and has not made all carnivorous, or seed-pickers, or root-diggers, so she has given to mankind various means of getting a livelihood, "one by keeping sheep, another by ploughing, another by fowling,"748 and another by catching the fish of the sea. 304We ought each therefore to select the calling appropriate for ourselves and labour energetically in it, and leave other people to theirs, and not demonstrate Hesiod as coming short of the real state of things when he said,

And Strato, the natural philosopher, when he heard that Menedemus had many more students than he did, said, "Is it surprising that more people want to wash than to be anointed?" And Aristotle, writing to Antipater, said, "Not only does Alexander have the right to take pride in ruling over many subjects, but it's equally valid to feel satisfied about having the right beliefs about the gods." Those who hold their own way of life in such high regard won't be so envious of their neighbors. We don't expect a vine to bear figs or an olive tree to produce grapes, yet nowadays, when it comes to ourselves, if we can't simultaneously be seen as rich and educated, generals and philosophers, flatterers and straight-talkers, stingy and extravagant, we criticize ourselves and feel dissatisfied, viewing our lives as incomplete and imperfect. Moreover, we see that nature teaches us the same lesson. For just as she provides different kinds of animals with different kinds of food, and hasn't made all of them carnivorous, seed-eaters, or root-diggers, she's given humanity various ways to make a living—"one by keeping sheep, another by ploughing, another by fowling," and another by catching fish from the sea. We should each choose the path that's right for us and work hard at it, letting others do the same, and not claim that Hesiod was wrong when he said,

"Potter is angry with potter, smith with smith." 749

For not only do people envy those of the same trade and manner of life, but the rich envy the learned, and the famous the rich, and advocates sophists, aye, and freemen and patricians admire and think happy comedians starring it at the theatres, and dancers, and the attendants at kings' courts, and by all this envy give themselves no small trouble and annoyance.

People not only envy others in the same profession and lifestyle, but the wealthy envy the educated, the famous envy the wealthy, and both advocates and sophists, as well as commoners and nobles, admire and believe that comedians performing in theaters, dancers, and court attendants lead happy lives. Through all this envy, they create themselves significant trouble and frustration.

§ xiv. But that every man has in himself the magazines of content or discontent, and that the jars containing blessings and evils are not on the threshold of Zeus,750 but lie stored in the mind, is plain from the differences of men's passions. For the foolish overlook and neglect present blessings, through their thoughts being ever intent on the future; but the wise make the past clearly present to them through memory. For the present giving only a moment of time to the touch, and then evading our grasp, does not seem to the foolish to be ours or to belong to us at all. And like that person751 painted as rope-making in Hades and permitting an ass feeding by to eat up the rope as fast as he makes it, so the stupid and thankless forgetfulness of most people comes upon them and takes possession of them, and obliterates from their mind every past action, whether success, or pleasant leisure, or society, or enjoyment, and breaks the unity of life which arises from the past being blended with the present; for detaching to-day from both yesterday and to-morrow, it soon makes every event as if it had never happened from lack of memory. For as those in the schools, who deny the growth of our bodies by reason of the continual flux of substance, make each of us in theory different from himself and another man, so those who do not keep or recall to their memory former things, but let them drift, actually empty them305selves daily, and hang upon the morrow, as if what happened a year ago, or even yesterday and the day before yesterday, had nothing to do with them, and had hardly occurred at all.

§ xiv. But every person has within them the sources of either happiness or unhappiness, and the jars filled with blessings and troubles are not at the doorstep of Zeus,750 but are stored in the mind, which is clear from how people's emotions differ. The foolish overlook and ignore the blessings they have now because they are always focused on the future; however, the wise bring the past into sharp focus through their memories. The present only offers a fleeting moment, and then slips away from us, which makes it seem to the foolish like it doesn’t belong to them at all. Just like that person751 depicted as continually making rope in Hades while allowing a donkey passing by to eat it as quickly as he produces it, the forgetfulness of most people rushes in and takes over, erasing from their minds every past experience, whether it was a success, a joyful time, companionship, or pleasure. This disrupts the continuity of life that arises from past experiences merging with the present; by separating today from both yesterday and tomorrow, it makes every event feel as if it never occurred due to a lack of memory. Just as those in academic circles who deny physical growth due to the constant change of substances describe each person theoretically as different from themselves and like another person, those who fail to remember or reflect on their past experiences, allowing them to fade away, actually empty themselves305 daily, and rely on the future, as if events from a year ago, or even from yesterday and the day before, have no relevance to them and hardly happened at all.

§ xv. This is one great hindrance to contentedness of mind, and another still greater is whenever, like flies that slide down smooth places in mirrors, but stick fast in rough places or where there are cracks, men let pleasant and agreeable things glide from their memory, and pin themselves down to the remembrance of unpleasant things; or rather, as at Olynthus they say beetles, when they get into a certain place called Destruction-to-beetles, cannot get out, but fly round and round till they die, so men will glide into the remembrance of their woes, and will not give themselves a respite from sorrow. But, as we use our brightest colours in a picture, so in the mind we ought to look at the cheerful and bright side of things, and hide and keep down the gloomy, for we cannot altogether obliterate or get rid of it. For, as the strings of the bow and lyre are alternately tightened and relaxed, so is it with the order of the world; in human affairs there is nothing pure and without alloy. But as in music there are high and low notes, and in grammar vowels and mutes, but neither the musician nor grammarian decline to use either kinds, but know how to blend and employ them both for their purpose, so in human affairs which are balanced one against another,—for, as Euripides says,

§ xv. One major obstacle to being content is when, like flies that slide easily over smooth surfaces but get stuck in rough spots or cracks, people let go of happy and pleasant memories while clinging to negative ones. Or, just like in Olynthus, where beetles trapped in a place called Destruction-to-beetles can’t escape and keep circling until they die, people often find themselves stuck in their sorrows without allowing themselves a break from the pain. However, just as we choose our brightest colors for a painting, we should focus on the positive and uplifting aspects of life and try to suppress the gloomy ones, even though we can't completely erase them. Similar to how the strings of a bow and lyre are alternately tightened and loosened, life is filled with a mix of good and bad. In human experiences, nothing is purely one way or the other. Just as music has both high and low notes, and grammar includes vowels and consonants—neither musicians nor grammarians ignore either type but learn to mix and use both for their purposes—in human experiences, we see a balance between opposites. As Euripides puts it,

"There is no good without bad in the world, "But everything is mixed in the right proportions,"—

we ought not to be disheartened or despondent; but as musicians drown their worst music with the best, so should we take good and bad together, and make our chequered life one of convenience and harmony. For it is not, as Menander says,

we shouldn't be discouraged or downhearted; just like musicians blend their worst music with the best, we should embrace both the good and the bad, turning our mixed lives into something convenient and harmonious. For it is not, as Menander says,

"From the moment any man is born, he is a genius." "Be his friend, a good guide for him in life,"

but it is rather, as Empedocles states, two fates or genii take hold of each of us when we are born and govern us. "There were Chthonia and far-seeing Heliope, and cruel Deris, and grave Harmonia, and Callisto, and Æschra, and306 Thoosa, and Denæa, and charming Nemertes, and Asaphea with the black fruit."

but it is more like, as Empedocles says, two fates or spirits grab hold of each of us when we're born and guide our lives. "There were Chthonia and far-seeing Heliope, and cruel Deris, and serious Harmonia, and Callisto, and Æschra, and306 Thoosa, and Denæa, and charming Nemertes, and Asaphea with the black fruit."

§ xvi. And as752 at our birth we received the mingled seeds of each of these passions, which is the cause of much irregularity, the sensible person hopes for better things, but expects worse, and makes the most of either, remembering that wise maxim, Not too much of anything. For not only will he who is least solicitous about to-morrow best enjoy it when it comes, as Epicurus says, but also wealth, and renown, and power and rule, gladden most of all the hearts of those who are least afraid of the contrary. For the immoderate desire for each, implanting a most immoderate fear of losing them, makes the enjoyment of them weak and wavering, like a flame under the influence of a wind. But he whom reason enables to say to fortune without fear or trembling,

§ xvi. Just like when we were born, we received mixed seeds of each of these passions, which leads to a lot of inconsistencies. A sensible person hopes for better outcomes but prepares for worse and makes the best of either, keeping in mind the wise saying, Not too much of anything. For not only will the person who worries the least about tomorrow truly enjoy it when it arrives, as Epicurus suggests, but also wealth, fame, power, and authority bring the most joy to those who are least afraid of losing them. The excessive desire for each, combined with a fear of losing them, makes the enjoyment of them weak and unstable, like a flame being blown about by the wind. But the one who can face fortune with confidence, without fear or hesitation,

"If you have anything good to offer, I’ll gladly accept it, "But if you let me down, it doesn't bother me much."

he can enjoy the present with most zest through his confidence, and absence of fear of the loss of what he has, which would be unbearable. For we may not only admire but also imitate the behaviour of Anaxagoras, which made him cry out at the death of his son, "I knew I had begot a mortal," and apply it to every contingency. For example, "I know that wealth is ephemeral and insecure; I know that those who gave power can take it away again; I know that my wife is good, but still a woman; and that my friend, since a human being, is by nature a changeable animal, to use Plato's expression." For such a prepared frame of mind, if anything happens unwished for but not unexpected, not admitting of such phrases as "I shouldn't have dreamed of it," or "I expected quite a different lot," or "I didn't look for this," abates the violent753 beatings and palpitations of the heart, and quickly causes wild unrest to subside. Carneades indeed reminds us that in great matters the unexpected makes the sum total of grief and dejection. Certainly the kingdom of Macedonia was many times smaller than the Roman Empire, but when 307Perseus lost Macedonia, he not only himself bewailed his wretched fate, but seemed to all men the most unfortunate and unlucky of mankind; yet Æmilius who conquered him, though he had to give up to another the command both by land and sea, yet was crowned, and offered sacrifice, and was justly esteemed happy. For he knew that he had taken a command which he would have to give up, but Perseus lost his kingdom without expecting it. Well also has the poet754 shown the power of anything that happens unexpectedly. For Odysseus wept bitterly at the death of his dog, but was not so moved when he sat by his wife who wept, for in the latter case he had come fully determined to keep his emotion under the control of reason, whereas in the former it was against his expectation, and therefore fell upon him as a sudden blow.

He can enjoy the present more fully because he's confident and not afraid of losing what he has, which would be unbearable. We can not only admire but also imitate the behavior of Anaxagoras, who cried out at his son’s death, "I knew I had brought a mortal into the world," and apply this mindset to every situation. For instance, "I know that wealth is fleeting and unstable; I know that those who give power can take it away; I know that my wife is good, but she’s still a woman; and that my friend, being human, is inherently changeable," to use Plato's term. This kind of prepared mindset helps to manage unexpected but inevitable events, avoiding thoughts like "I shouldn't have dreamed of this," "I expected a different outcome," or "I didn't see this coming." This approach reduces the intense stress and anxiety that can arise and quickly calms the restless heart. Carneades reminds us that in significant matters, the unexpected amplifies grief and despair. Certainly, the kingdom of Macedonia was much smaller than the Roman Empire, but when Perseus lost Macedonia, he not only mourned his unfortunate fate but also appeared to everyone as the most unfortunate person alive. In contrast, Æmilius, who defeated him, despite having to hand over command to someone else, was crowned, offered sacrifices, and was rightly regarded as happy. He understood that he would have to surrender command one day, whereas Perseus unexpectedly lost his kingdom. The poet has also illustrated the impact of unexpected events. For Odysseus, the death of his dog made him weep bitterly, but he was less affected when he sat with his wife, who was crying, because in that situation, he had come prepared to keep his emotions in check. The death of his dog, however, caught him off guard and hit him like a sudden blow.

§ xvii. And since generally speaking some things which happen against our will pain and trouble us by their very nature, while in the case of most we accustom ourselves and learn to be disgusted with them from fancy, it is not unprofitable to counteract this to have ever ready that line of Menander,

§ xvii. And since, in general, some things that happen against our wishes naturally cause us pain and distress, while with most things we get used to them and learn to be annoyed by them out of habit, it’s helpful to have that line from Menander always ready to counteract this.

"You only suffer fear in your imagination."

For what, if they touch you neither in soul nor body, are such things to you as the low birth of your father, or the adultery of your wife, or the loss of some prize or precedence, since even by their absence a man is not prevented from being in excellent condition both of body and soul. And with respect to the things that seem to pain us by their very nature, as sickness, and anxieties, and the deaths of friends and children, we should remember, that line of Euripides,

For what are things like your father's low status, your wife's infidelity, or the loss of a prize or position to you, if they don’t affect you at all, either physically or mentally? Even without these, a person can still be in great shape both physically and mentally. Regarding the things that seem to naturally cause us pain, like illness, anxiety, and the deaths of friends and children, we should remember that line from Euripides,

"Alas! And why alas? We only suffer." What humans should expect."

For no argument has so much weight with emotion when it is borne down with grief, as that which reminds it of the common and natural necessity to which man is exposed owing to the body, the only handle which he gives to fortune, for in his most important and influential part755 he is 308secure against external things. When Demetrius captured Megara, he asked Stilpo if any of his things had been plundered, and Stilpo answered, "I saw nobody carrying off anything of mine."756 And so when fortune has plundered us and stripped us of everything else, we have that within ourselves

For no argument carries as much emotional weight when it is weighed down by grief as the one that reminds us of the common and natural necessity we all face due to our physical existence, the only thing we can control in life. In his most crucial and impactful aspect755 he is 308 safe from external influences. When Demetrius took Megara, he asked Stilpo if any of his belongings had been stolen, and Stilpo replied, "I didn’t see anyone taking anything of mine."756 So, when fortune has robbed us and taken everything else, we still have what is within ourselves.

"Which the Achæans were never able to take from us." 757

So that we ought not altogether to abase and lower nature, as if she had no strength or stability against fortune; but on the contrary, knowing that the rotten and perishable part of man, wherein alone he lies open to fortune, is small, while we ourselves are masters of the better part, wherein are situated our greatest blessings, as good opinions and teaching and virtuous precepts, all which things cannot be abstracted from us or perish, we ought to look on the future with invincible courage, and say to fortune, as Socrates is supposed to have said to his accusers Anytus and Melitus before the jury, "Anytus and Melitus can kill me, but they cannot hurt me." For fortune can afflict us with disease, take away our money, calumniate us to the people or king, but cannot make a good and brave and high-souled man bad and cowardly and low and ignoble and envious, nor take away that disposition of mind, whose constant presence is of more use for the conduct of life than the presence of a pilot at sea. For the pilot cannot make calm the wild wave or wind, nor can he find a haven at his need wherever he wishes, nor can he await his fate with confidence and without trembling, but as long as he has not despaired, but uses his skill, he scuds before the gale, "lowering his big sail, till his lower mast is only just above the sea dark as Erebus," and sits at the helm trembling and quaking. But the disposition of a wise man gives calm even to the body, mostly cutting off the causes of diseases by temperance and plain living and moderate exercise; but if some beginning of trouble arise from without, as we avoid a sunken rock, so he passes by it with furled sail, as Asclepiades puts it; but if some unexpected 309 and tremendous gale come upon him and prove too much for him, the harbour is at hand, and he can swim away from the body, as from a leaky boat.

We shouldn’t completely dismiss or underestimate nature, as if it has no power or stability against fate. On the contrary, we must realize that the decaying and fragile aspect of humanity, which makes us vulnerable to fortune, is minor. Meanwhile, we are in control of our better qualities, where our greatest blessings lie—like good opinions, education, and virtuous teachings. These elements can't be taken from us or destroyed. Therefore, we should face the future with unshakeable courage and tell fortune, much like Socrates reportedly did to his accusers Anytus and Melitus before the jury, "Anytus and Melitus can kill me, but they cannot harm me." Fortune may bring illness, take our money, or slander us to the people or the king, but it cannot turn a good, brave, noble, and high-minded person into a bad, cowardly, lowly, and envious one, nor can it strip away that mindset, which is more essential for navigating life than having a pilot at sea. A pilot can’t calm the wild waves or winds, nor can he find shelter wherever he desires, or face his destiny confidently and without fear. But as long as he doesn’t lose hope and uses his skills, he can navigate through the storm, "shortening his sail until the lower mast is barely above the dark sea," all while at the helm, trembling. However, the mindset of a wise person brings calm to the body, primarily reducing the causes of sickness through moderation, simple living, and moderate exercise. If any trouble arises from the outside, he avoids it like a submerged rock, passing it by with furled sails, as Asclepiades states; but if an unexpected and fierce storm strikes and overwhelms him, the harbor is nearby, and he can escape from the body like he would from a sinking boat.

§ xviii. For it is the fear of death, and not the desire of life, that makes the foolish person to hang to the body, clinging to it, as Odysseus did to the fig-tree from fear of Charybdis that lay below,

§ xviii. Because it’s the fear of death, not the desire for life, that makes a foolish person cling to their body, just like Odysseus clung to the fig tree out of fear of the Charybdis lurking below,

"Where the wind wouldn't let him stay or sail,"

so that he was displeased at this, and afraid of that. But he who understands somehow or other the nature of the soul, and reflects that the change it will undergo at death will be either to something better or at least not worse, he has in his fearlessness of death no small help to ease of mind in life. For to one who can enjoy life when virtue and what is congenial to him have the upper hand, and that can fearlessly depart from life, when uncongenial and unnatural things are in the ascendant, with the words on his lips,

so that he was unhappy about this and worried about that. But someone who understands the nature of the soul and realizes that the change it will go through at death will either be for the better or at least not worse finds that this understanding helps ease their mind about death. For someone who can truly enjoy life when virtue and what resonates with them are in charge, and who can bravely leave life behind when unpleasant and unnatural things take over, with the words on their lips,

"The deity will set me free, when I choose to,"758

what can we imagine could befall such a man as this that would vex him and wear him and harass him? For he who said, "I have anticipated you, O fortune, and cut off all your loopholes to get at me," did not trust to bolts or keys or walls, but to determination and reason, which are within the power of all persons that choose. And we ought not to despair or disbelieve any of these sayings, but admiring them and emulating them and being enthusiastic about them, we ought to try and test ourselves in smaller matters with a view to greater, not avoiding or rejecting that self-examination, nor sheltering ourselves under the remark, "Perhaps nothing will be more difficult." For inertia759 and softness are generated by that self-indulgence which ever occupies itself only with the easiest tasks, and flees from the disagreeable to what is most pleasant. But the soul that accustoms itself to face steadily sickness and grief and exile, and calls in reason to its help in each case, will find in what appears so sore and 310dreadful much that is false, empty, and rotten, as reason will show in each case.

What can we imagine could happen to a man like this that would trouble him, wear him down, and harass him? For he who said, "I've outsmarted you, Fortune, and closed off all your ways to get to me," relied not on bolts or keys or walls, but on determination and reason, which are within the reach of anyone who chooses. We shouldn't despair or dismiss any of these sayings. Instead, we should admire them, emulate them, and get excited about them. We ought to test ourselves in smaller situations to prepare for bigger challenges, not avoiding or rejecting self-examination, nor hiding behind the thought, "Perhaps nothing will be more difficult." Because inertia and laziness come from that self-indulgence which only engages in the easiest tasks and runs away from what’s unpleasant to seek comfort in the most enjoyable. But the soul that trains itself to confront illness, grief, and exile head-on, and seeks reason as its ally in each situation, will discover that what seems so painful and dreadful often contains much that is false, empty, and rotten, as reason will reveal in each case.

§ xix. And yet many shudder at that line of Menander,

§ xix. And yet many tremble at that line of Menander,

"No one can say, I won't suffer this or that,"

being ignorant how much it helps us to freedom from grief to practise to be able to look fortune in the face with our eyes open, and not to entertain fine and soft fancies, like one reared in the shade on many hopes that always yield and never resist. We can, however, answer Menander's line,

being unaware of how much it helps us to be free from grief by practicing the ability to face fortune head-on with our eyes wide open, rather than indulging in delicate and comforting illusions, like someone raised in the shade on countless hopes that always bend and never push back. Nevertheless, we can respond to Menander's line,

"No one can say, 'I won't go through this or that.'"

for a man can say, "I will not do this or that, I will not lie, I will not play the rogue, I will not cheat, I will not scheme." For this is in our power, and is no small but great help to ease of mind. As on the contrary

for a man can say, "I won't do this or that, I won't lie, I won't be dishonest, I won't cheat, I won't plot." Because this is within our control, and it's a significant aid to peace of mind. On the other hand

"The awareness of having committed wrong actions,"760

like a sore in the flesh, leaves in the mind a regret which ever wounds it and pricks it. For reason banishes all other griefs, but itself creates regret when the soul is vexed with shame and self-tormented. For as those who shudder in ague-fits or burn in fevers feel more trouble and distress than those who externally suffer the same from cold or heat, so the grief is lighter which comes externally from chance, but that lament,

like a sore on the skin, leaves a regret in the mind that continually hurts and irritates. Reason may dismiss all other pains, but it creates regret when the soul is troubled by shame and self-inflicted torment. Just as those who shake with chills or burn with fevers experience more discomfort and distress than those who suffer externally from cold or heat, the sorrow that comes from chance is lighter, but that lament,

"No one is to blame for this but me."

coming from within on one's own misdeeds, intensifies one's bitterness by the shame felt. And so neither costly house, nor quantity of gold, nor pride of race, nor weighty office, nor grace of language, nor eloquence, impart so much calm and serenity to life, as a soul pure from evil acts and desires, having an imperturbable and undefiled character as the source of its life; whence good actions flow, producing an enthusiastic and cheerful energy accompanied by loftiness of thought, and a memory sweeter and more lasting than that hope which Pindar says is the support of old age. Censers do not, as Carneades said, after they are emptied, long retain their sweet smell; but in the mind of the wise man good actions always leave a fresh and fragrant memory, by which joy is watered and flourishes, and 311despises those who wail over life and abuse it as a region of ills, or as a place of exile for souls in this world.

Feeling shame about one’s own wrongdoings only makes one’s bitterness worse. It turns out that no expensive home, amount of gold, pride in ancestry, high office, eloquence, or command of language can bring as much peace and tranquility to life as a soul that is free from evil deeds and desires, possessing a calm and untainted character that serves as the foundation of its existence. From this steadiness springs good actions, which generate an enthusiastic and joyful energy, accompanied by lofty thoughts, and a memory that is sweeter and more enduring than the hope that Pindar describes as the comfort of old age. As Carneades said, incense does not hold its pleasant scent for long after it's burned; yet in the mind of a wise person, good deeds always leave a fresh and delightful memory, nurturing joy and allowing it to thrive, and 311looks down on those who lament life and view it merely as a land of suffering or as an exile for souls in this world.

§ xx. I am very taken with Diogenes' remark to a stranger at Lacedæmon, who was dressing with much display for a feast, "Does not a good man consider every day a feast?" And a very great feast too, if we live soberly. For the world is a most holy and divine temple, into which man is introduced at his birth, not to behold motionless images made by hands, but those things (to use the language of Plato) which the divine mind has exhibited as the visible representations of invisible things, having innate in them the principle of life and motion, as the sun moon and stars, and rivers ever flowing with fresh water, and the earth affording maintenance to plants and animals. Seeing then that life is the most complete initiation into all these things, it ought to be full of ease of mind and joy; not as most people wait for the festivals of Cronos761 and Dionysus and the Panathenæa and other similar days, that they may joy and refresh themselves with bought laughter, paying actors and dancers for the same. On such occasions indeed we sit silently and decorously, for no one wails when he is initiated, or groans when he beholds the Pythian games, or when he is drinking at the festival of Cronos:761 but men shame the festivals which the deity supplies us with and initiates us in, passing most of their time in lamentation and heaviness of heart and distressing anxiety. And though men delight in the pleasing notes of musical instruments, and in the songs of birds, and behold with joy the animals playing and frisking, and on the contrary are distressed when they roar and howl and look savage; yet in regard to their own life, when they see it without smiles and dejected, and ever oppressed and afflicted by the most wretched sorrows and toils and unending cares, they do not think of trying to procure alleviation and ease. How is this? Nay, they will not even listen to others' exhortation, which would enable them to acquiesce in the present without repining, and to remember the past with thankfulness, and to meet the future hopefully and cheerfully without fear or suspicion.

§ xx. I'm really struck by Diogenes' comment to a stranger in Lacedæmon, who was dressing up extravagantly for a feast, "Doesn't a good person see every day as a feast?" And what a great feast it can be if we live simply. The world is a sacred and divine temple, where people enter at birth, not to witness static statues created by human hands, but to see things (to borrow Plato's words) that the divine mind has shown as visible representations of invisible realities, containing the essence of life and motion, like the sun, moon, and stars, along with rivers constantly flowing with fresh water, and the earth providing for plants and animals. Since life is the ultimate initiation into all these wonders, it should be filled with peace of mind and joy; not like most people who wait for the festivals of Cronos761 and Dionysus, and the Panathenæa and other similar days, to enjoy themselves and refresh with purchased laughter, paying performers for entertainment. During these times, we sit quietly and respectfully, as no one cries during initiation, or groans while watching the Pythian games, or while drinking at the festival of Cronos:761 but people demean the festivals that the divine offers us and initiates us into, spending most of their time in lamentation, heaviness of heart, and distressing anxiety. Even though people find joy in the delightful sounds of music, the songs of birds, and watching animals play, they become upset when they roar and howl or act fierce; yet when it comes to their own lives, seeing it devoid of smiles and weighed down by endless sorrows, struggles, and worries, they don’t even think about seeking relief or ease. Why is that? In fact, they won’t even pay attention to others' encouragement, which could help them find contentment in the present without complaining, remember the past with gratitude, and face the future with hope and cheerfulness, without fear or suspicion.

711 Or cheerfulness, or tranquillity of mind. Jeremy Taylor has largely borrowed again from this treatise in his "Holy Living," ch. ii. § 6, "Of Contentedness in all Estates and Accidents."

711 Or happiness, or peace of mind. Jeremy Taylor has significantly drawn from this work in his "Holy Living," ch. ii. § 6, "Of Contentedness in all Estates and Accidents."

712 Reading with Salmasius κάλτιος πατρίκιος.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading with Salmasius Calltius Patrician.

713 "Locus Xenophontis est Cyropæd.," l. i. p. 52.—Reiske.

713 "The location of Xenophon's works is Cyropædia," l. i. p. 52.—Reiske.

714 Euripides, "Orestes," 258.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Orestes," 258.

715 So Wyttenbach, Dübner. Vulgo ἀναισθησίας—ἀπονία.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ So Wyttenbach, Dübner. Commonly anesthesia—anesthesia.

716 "Works and Days," 519.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Works and Days," 519.

717 "Odyssey," i. 191, 192.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," i. 191, 192.

718 I read κατηφείαν.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ I read κατηφείαν.

719 "Iliad," i. 488-492.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," pp. 488-492.

720 "Iliad," xviii. 104.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 18.104.

721 Euripides, "Orestes," 232.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Orestes," 232.

722 Homer, "Iliad," x. 88, 89.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 10. 88, 89.

723 The story of Phäethon is a very well-known one, and is recorded very fully by Ovid in the "Metamorphoses," Book ii.

723 The tale of Phaethon is a well-known one and is fully detailed by Ovid in "Metamorphoses," Book ii.

724 Euripides, "Bellerophon." Fragm. 298.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Bellerophon." Frag. 298.

725 Supplying φυτῶν with Reiske.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Supplying plants with Reiske.

726 In Cyprus. Zeno was the founder of the Stoics.

726 In Cyprus. Zeno was the founder of the Stoic philosophy.

727 Zeno and his successors taught in the Piazza at Athens called the Painted Piazza. See Pausanias, i. 15.

727 Zeno and his followers taught in the square in Athens known as the Painted Porch. See Pausanias, i. 15.

728 Pindar, Nem. iv. 6.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Pindar, Nem. 4.6.

729 Euripides, "Bacchæ," 66.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Bacchae," 66.

730 Quoted again by our author "On Restraining Anger," § xvi.

730 Quoted again by our author "On Controlling Anger," § xvi.

731 As will be seen, I follow Wyttenbach's guidance in this very corrupt passage, which is a true crux.

731 As you will see, I follow Wyttenbach's advice in this very flawed passage, which is a real puzzle.

732 Reading δεδορκότες.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading

733 See "On Curiosity," § i.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See "On Curiosity," __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__

734 Simonides.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Simonides.

735 See Herodotus, vii. 56.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Herodotus, 7.56.

736 A mina was 100 drachmæ (i.e. £4. 1s. 3d.), and 600 obols.

736 A mina was 100 drachmas (i.e. £4. 1s. 3d.), and 600 obols.

737 A slave's ordinary dress.

A slave's everyday clothing.

738 One of the Seven Wise Men.

One of the Seven Sages.

739 Homer, "Iliad," iii. 182.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," III. 182.

740 Homer, "Iliad," ii. 111.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 2.111.

741 Words of Agamemnon to the House Porter. Euripides, "Iphigenia in Aulis," 17-19.

741 Words of Agamemnon to the House Porter. Euripides, "Iphigenia in Aulis," 17-19.

742 "Iliad," xviii. 105, 106.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xviii. 105, 106.

743 See Pausanias, x. 24.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Refer to Pausanias, x. 24.

744 Pindar, Fragm., 258. Quoted "On Moral Virtue," § xii.

744 Pindar, Fragm., 258. Quoted in "On Moral Virtue," § xii.

745 Homer, "Iliad," xvii. 61; "Odyssey," vi. 130.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 17.61; "Odyssey," 6.130.

746 A famous breed of dogs from the island Melita, near Dalmatia. See Pliny, "Hist. Nat.," iii. 26, extr. § 30; xxx. 5, extr. § 14.

746 A well-known breed of dogs from the island of Malta, near Dalmatia. See Pliny, "Hist. Nat.," iii. 26, extr. § 30; xxx. 5, extr. § 14.

747 That Non omnia possumus omnes.

That Non omnia possumus omnes.

748 Pindar, "Isthm.," i. 65-70.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Pindar, "Isthm.," 1. 65-70.

749 Hesiod, "Works and Days," 25. Our "two of a trade seldom agree."

749 Hesiod, "Works and Days," 25. Our "people who do the same job rarely see eye to eye."

750 An allusion to "Iliad," xxiv. 527-533.

750 A reference to "Iliad," xxiv. 527-533.

751 Ocnus. See Pausanias, x. 29.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Ocnus. See Pausanias, 10.29.

752 So Wyttenbach, who reads Ὡς δὲ τούτων.

752 So Wyttenbach, who reads as follows.

753 Reading οἷα with Reiske.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading as Reiske stated.

754 Homer to wit.

Homer, for example.

755 The soul.

The soul.

756 The reading here is rather doubtful. That I have adopted is Reiske's and Wyttenbach's.

756 The interpretation here is quite uncertain. The one I've chosen is from Reiske and Wyttenbach.

757 "Iliad," v. 484.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," v. 484.

758 Euripides, "Bacchæ," 498. Compare Horace, "Epistles," i. xvi. 78, 79.

758 Euripides, "Bacchae," 498. Compare Horace, "Epistles," i. xvi. 78, 79.

759 Reading with Dübner ἀργίαν. Reiske has ἀτονίαν.

759 Reading with Dübner's "sloth." Reiske has "weakness."

760 Euripides, "Orestes," 396.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Orestes," 396.

761 The Saturnalia (as the Romans called this feast) was well known as a festival of merriment and license.

761 The Saturnalia (as the Romans referred to this celebration) was widely recognized as a festival of joy and freedom.


ON ENVY AND HATRED.

§ i. Outwardly there seems no difference between hatred and envy, but they seem identical. For generally speaking, as vice has many hooks, and is swayed hither and thither by the passions that hang on it, there are many points of contact and entanglement between them, for as in the case of illnesses there is a sympathy between the various passions. Thus the prosperous man is equally a source of pain to hate and envy. And so we think benevolence the opposite of both these passions, being as it is a wish for our neighbour's good, and we think hate and envy identical, for the desire of both is the very opposite of benevolence. But since their similarities are not so great as their dissimilarities, let us investigate and trace out these two passions from their origin.

§ i. On the surface, hatred and envy appear to be the same, but they seem indistinguishable. Generally speaking, since vice has many hooks and is influenced variously by the emotions attached to it, there are many points of contact and overlap between them, much like how different emotions can be connected in cases of illness. Therefore, a successful person can be a source of pain for both those who hate and those who envy. We then see kindness as the opposite of both of these feelings, as it involves wishing well for our neighbor, while hate and envy share a common desire that is the complete opposite of kindness. However, since their similarities are not as significant as their differences, let’s explore and define these two emotions from their origins.

§ ii. Hatred then is generated by the fancy that the person hated is either bad generally or bad to oneself. For those who think they are wronged naturally hate those who they think wrong them, and dislike and are on their guard against those who are injurious or bad to others;762 but people envy merely those they think prosperous. So envy seems illimitable, being, like ophthalmia, troubled at everything bright, whereas hatred is limited, since it settles only on what seems hostile.

§ ii. Hatred arises from the belief that the person being hated is either generally bad or specifically bad to oneself. People who feel wronged tend to hate those they believe have wronged them, and they are wary and dislike those who harm others;762 but people only envy those they see as successful. Therefore, envy seems boundless, similar to an eye condition that is irritated by anything bright, while hatred is more limited, as it is directed only at what appears to be hostile.

§ iii. In the second place people feel hatred even against the brutes; for some hate cats and beetles and toads and serpents. Thus Germanicus could not bear the crowing or sight of a cock, and the Persian magicians kill their mice, not only hating them themselves but thinking them hateful to their god, and the Arabians and Ethiopians abominate them as much. Whereas we envy only human beings.

§ iii. Secondly, people even feel hatred toward animals; some dislike cats, beetles, toads, and snakes. For example, Germanicus couldn't stand the crowing or sight of a rooster, and the Persian magicians kill mice, not only because they hate them but also because they believe they are offensive to their god. Likewise, the Arabs and Ethiopians despise them just as much. In contrast, we only envy other human beings.

§ iv. Indeed among the brutes it is not likely that there should be any envy, for they have no conception of prosperity or adversity, nor have they any idea of reputation or 313want of reputation, which are the things that mainly excite envy; but they hate one another, and are hostile to one another, and fight with one another to the death, as eagles and dragons, crows and owls, titmice and finches, insomuch that they say that even the blood of these creatures will not mix, and if you try to mix it it will immediately separate again. It is likely also that there is strong hatred between the cock and the lion, and the pig and the elephant, owing to fear. For what people fear they naturally hate. We see also from this that envy differs from hatred, for the animals are capable of the one, but not of the other.

§ iv. In fact, among animals, it's unlikely that there is any envy, as they have no understanding of success or failure, nor do they grasp the concept of reputation or the lack thereof, which are the main triggers for envy. However, they do hate each other, are hostile toward one another, and will fight to the death, just like eagles and dragons, crows and owls, titmice and finches. People even say that the blood of these creatures won't mix, and if you try to mix it, it will separate right away. It's also likely that there's a deep hatred between the rooster and the lion, and the pig and the elephant, driven by fear. People naturally hate what they fear. This shows us that envy is different from hatred, because animals can feel one but not the other.

§ v. Moreover envy against anyone is never just, for no one wrongs another by his prosperity, though that is what he is envied for; but many are hated with justice, for we even think others763 worthy of hatred, if they do not flee from such, and are not disgusted and vexed at them. A great indication of this is that some people admit they hate many, but declare they envy nobody. Indeed hatred of evil is reckoned among praiseworthy things; and when some were praising Charillus, the nephew of Lycurgus and king of Sparta, for his mildness and gentleness, his colleague said, "How can Charillus be good, who is not even harsh to the bad?" And so the poet described the bodily defects of Thersites at much length, whereas he expressed his vile moral character most shortly and by one remark, "He was most hateful both to Achilles and Odysseus."764 For to be hated by the most excellent is the height of worthlessness. But people deny that they are envious, and, if they are charged with being so, they put forward ten thousand pleas, saying they are angry with the man or fear him or hate him, suggesting any other passion than envy, and concealing it as the only disorder of the soul which is abominable.

§ v. Moreover, being envious of someone is never justified, because no one wrongs another simply by being successful, even if that's what makes them envied. However, many people are justly hated because we believe others763 deserve that hatred if they don't distance themselves from wrongdoing and aren't bothered or upset by it. A clear sign of this is that some people admit to hating many, but claim they envy nobody. In fact, hatred of evil is considered a good thing; and when some praised Charillus, the nephew of Lycurgus and king of Sparta, for his kind and gentle nature, his colleague remarked, "How can Charillus be good, if he's not even harsh to the wicked?" Similarly, the poet elaborated on Thersites' physical flaws at great length but summed up his terrible character with a single line: "He was most hated by both Achilles and Odysseus."764 To be despised by the most commendable individuals is the ultimate indication of worthlessness. Yet, people deny they feel envy, and when accused of it, they come up with countless excuses, claiming they are either angry with the person, afraid of them, or dislike them, attributing any emotion to their feelings except envy, which they conceal as the only truly disgraceful disorder of the soul.

§ vi. Of necessity then these two passions cannot, like plants, be fed and nourished and grow on the same roots; for they are by nature different.765 For we hate people more as they grow worse, but they are envied only the 314more the more they advance in virtue. And so Themistocles, when quite a lad, said he had done nothing remarkable, for he was not yet envied. For as insects attack most ripe corn and roses in their bloom, so envy fastens most on the good and on those who are growing in virtue and good repute for moral character. Again extreme badness intensifies hatred. So hated indeed and loathed were the accusers of Socrates, as guilty of extreme vileness, by their fellow-citizens, that they would neither supply them with fire, nor answer their questions, nor touch the water they had bathed in, but ordered the servants to pour it away as polluted, till they could bear this hatred no longer and hung themselves. But splendid and exceptional success often extinguishes envy. For it is not likely that anyone envied Alexander or Cyrus, after their conquests made them lords of the world. But as the sun, when it is high over our heads and sends down its rays, makes next to no shadow, so at those successes that attain such a height as to be over its head envy is humbled, and retires completely dazzled. So Alexander had none to envy him, but many to hate him, by whom he was plotted against till he died. So too misfortunes stop envy, but they do not remove hatred. For people hate their enemies even when they lie prostrate at their feet, but no one envies the unfortunate. But the remark of one of the sophists of our day is true, that the envious are very prone to pity; so here too there is a great difference between these two passions, for hatred abandons neither the fortunate nor unfortunate, whereas envy is mitigated in the extreme of either fortune.

§ vi. Necessarily, these two feelings cannot, like plants, thrive and grow from the same roots because they are inherently different.765 We hate people more as they get worse, but they are envied more the more they excel in virtue. Themistocles, even as a young boy, remarked that he had done nothing noteworthy because he wasn’t yet envied. Just like insects attack ripe corn and blooming roses, envy mainly targets the good and those who are growing in virtue and reputation for moral character. Conversely, extreme wickedness amplifies hatred. The accusers of Socrates were so hated and reviled by their fellow citizens for their extreme vileness that they were denied fire, refused answers to their questions, and told their servants to dispose of the water they had used for bathing as if it were polluted, until they could no longer endure this hatred and took their own lives. However, remarkable and exceptional success often diminishes envy. It's unlikely that anyone envied Alexander or Cyrus after their conquests made them rulers of the world. Just as the sun, when high above, casts little shadow, at such heights of achievement, envy is humbled and retreats completely overwhelmed. Alexander had no one to envy him but plenty who hated him, leading to plots against him until his death. Similarly, misfortunes may halt envy, but they don’t eliminate hatred. People can hate their enemies even when they’re down, but no one envies the unfortunate. There’s truth in the saying of one of today's sophists that the envious are very prone to pity; thus, there’s a significant difference between these two emotions. Hatred doesn’t abandon either the fortunate or the unfortunate, while envy diminishes in extreme circumstances of either fortune.

§ vii. Let as look at the same again from opposite points of view. Men put an end to their enmity and hatred, either if persuaded they have not been wronged, or if they come round to the view that those they hated are good men and not bad, or thirdly if they receive a kindness. For, as Thucydides says, the last favour conferred, even though a smaller one, if it be seasonable, outweighs a greater offence.766 Yet the persuasion that they have not been wronged does not put an end to envy, for people envy although absolutely persuaded that they have not been wronged; and the two 315other cases actually increase envy; for people look with an evil eye even more on those they think good, as having virtue, which is the greatest blessing; and if they are treated kindly by the prosperous it grieves them, for they envy both their will and power to do kindnesses, the former proceeding from their goodness, the latter from their prosperity, but both being blessings. Thus envy is a passion altogether different from hatred, seeing that what abates the one pains and exasperates the other.

§ vii. Let's look at this from different perspectives. People end their conflicts and hatred either when they are convinced they haven't been wronged, when they realize that those they disliked are actually good people, or when they experience a kindness. As Thucydides says, the most recent favor, even if small, if timely, can outweigh a greater offense.766 However, believing that they haven't been wronged doesn't eliminate envy, since people can feel envious even when they're sure they haven't been wronged. The other two situations can actually increase envy; people tend to look with resentment at those they see as virtuous, viewing their goodness as the greatest blessing. Additionally, if they receive kindness from those who are doing well, it only frustrates them further because they envy both the desire and ability of the fortunate to show kindness—both coming from their goodness and prosperity, which are blessings. Therefore, envy is a completely different emotion from hatred, as what minimizes one can intensify the other.

§ viii. Let us now look at the intent of each of these passions. The intent of the person who hates is to do as much harm as he can, so they define hatred to be a disposition and intent on the watch for an opportunity to do harm. But this is altogether foreign to envy.767 For those who envy their relations and friends would not wish them to come to ruin, or fall into calamity, but are only annoyed at their prosperity; and would hinder, if they could, their glory and renown, but they would not bring upon them irremediable misfortunes: they are content to remove, as in the case of a lofty house, what stands in their light.

§ viii. Now let's examine the purpose of each of these emotions. The goal of someone who hates is to cause as much harm as possible, so hatred is understood as a mindset focused on finding opportunities to inflict damage. However, this is completely different from envy.767 Those who envy their family and friends don't actually want them to suffer or face disaster; they just feel bothered by their success. They would like to diminish their fame and achievements if they could, but they wouldn't want to cause them lasting misfortune: they're simply satisfied to remove, like blocking the sunlight from a tall house, what obstructs their view.

762 ἄλλως MSS. Wyttenbach ἄλλων. Malo ἄλλοις.

762 other MSS. Wyttenbach others. Malo others.

763 So Wyttenbach.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ So Wyttenbach.

764 Homer, "Iliad," ii. 220.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," ii. 220.

765 So Wyttenbach. The reading in this passage is very doubtful.

765 So Wyttenbach. The interpretation of this passage is quite uncertain.

766 Thucydides, i. 42.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Thucydides, i. 42.

767 Reading ἄπεστιν ὅλως. Οἱ γὰρ φθονοῦντες. What can be made of πολλοὺς here?

767 Reading is completely absent. Those who are envious. What can be understood by many here?


HOW ONE CAN PRAISE ONESELF WITHOUT EXCITING ENVY.

§ i. To speak to other people about one's own importance or ability, Herculanus, is universally declared to be tiresome and illiberal, but in fact not many even of those who censure it avoid its unpleasantness. Thus Euripides, though he says,

§ i. Talking to others about one's own significance or talent, Herculanus, is generally considered annoying and unkind, but in reality, not many of those who criticize it truly steer clear of its awkwardness. Therefore, Euripides, although he says,

"If people had to buy words, No one would want to brag about themselves. But since you can get words sans any payment From above, everyone delights When talking about the truth or lies about himself, For he can do it without facing any consequences;

yet uses much tiresome boasting, intermixing with the passion and action of his plays irrelevant matter about himself. Similarly Pindar says, that "to boast unseason316ably is to play an accompaniment to madness,"768 yet he does not cease to talk big about his own merit, which indeed is well worthy of encomium, who would deny it? But those who are crowned in the games leave it to others to celebrate their victories, to avoid the unpleasantness of singing their own praises. So we are with justice disgusted at Timotheus769 for trumpeting his own glory inelegantly and contrary to custom in the inscription for his victory over Phrynis, "A proud day for you, Timotheus, was it when the herald cried out, 'The Milesian Timotheus is victorious over the son of Carbo and his Ionic notes.'" As Xenophon says, "Praise from others is the pleasantest thing a man can hear,"770 but to others a man's self-praise is most nauseous. For first we think those impudent who praise themselves, since modesty would be becoming even if they were praised by others; secondly, we think them unjust in giving themselves what they ought to receive from others; thirdly, if we are silent we seem to be vexed and to envy them, and if we are afraid of this imputation, we are obliged to heap praise upon them contrary to our real opinion, and to bear them out, undertaking a task more befitting gross flattery than honour.

yet he uses a lot of annoying bragging, mixing in irrelevant stuff about himself with the passion and action of his plays. Similarly, Pindar says that "to boast unseasonably is to play an accompaniment to madness," yet he doesn’t stop talking highly of his own worth, which is indeed deserving of praise—who would deny that? But those who win at the games let others celebrate their victories to avoid the awkwardness of singing their own praises. So, it's understandable that we are rightfully annoyed with Timotheus for ungracefully boasting about his own glory against tradition in the inscription for his victory over Phrynis: "A proud day for you, Timotheus, was it when the herald cried out, 'The Milesian Timotheus is victorious over the son of Carbo and his Ionic notes.'" As Xenophon says, "Praise from others is the most pleasant thing a man can hear," but to others, self-praise is most off-putting. First, we think those who brag about themselves are shameless, since modesty would be fitting even if they were praised by others. Second, we consider them unfair for giving themselves what they should receive from others. Third, if we stay silent, we seem annoyed and envious of them, and if we fear this impression, we feel obligated to shower them with praise against our true feelings, taking on a role better suited for hollow flattery than genuine honor.

§ ii. And yet, in spite of all this, there are occasions when a statesman may venture to speak in his own praise, not to cry up his own glory and merit, but when the time and matter demand that he should speak the truth about himself, as he would about another; especially when it is mentioned that another has done good and excellent things,771 there is no need for him to suppress the fact that he has done as well. For such self-praise bears excellent fruit, since much more and better praise springs from it as from seed. For the statesman does not ask for reputation as a reward or consolation, nor is he merely pleased at its attending upon his actions, but he values it because credit and character give him opportunities to do good on a larger scale. For it is both easy and pleasant to benefit those who 317believe in us and are friendly to us, but it is not easy to act virtuously against suspicion and calumny, and to force one's benefits on those that reject them. Let us now consider, if there are any other reasons warranting self-praise in a statesman, what they are, that, while we avoid vain glory and disgusting other people, we may not omit any useful kind of self-praise.

§ ii. And yet, despite all this, there are times when a politician might choose to talk about his own achievements, not to boast about his glory and worth, but when the situation calls for him to honestly discuss himself, as he would about someone else; especially when it's said that another person has done good and admirable things,771 he shouldn't hold back from acknowledging that he has done just as well. This kind of self-praise can lead to great results, as it often produces even more and better praise, like seeds sprouting. The politician doesn't seek a reputation as a reward or consolation, nor is he merely happy to have it accompany his actions; he values it because having a good reputation and character offers him chances to do good on a bigger scale. It’s both easy and rewarding to help those who believe in us and support us, but it’s not easy to act rightly when faced with doubt and slander, and to push our help onto those who refuse it. Now let’s examine if there are any additional reasons that justify a politician’s self-praise, so that we can avoid arrogance and irritating others but not miss out on any beneficial form of self-praise.

§ iii. That is vain glory then when men seem to praise themselves that they may call forth the laudation of others; and it is especially despised because it seems to proceed from ambition and an unseasonable opinion of oneself. For as those who cannot obtain food are forced to feed on their own flesh against nature, and that is the end of famine, so those that hunger after praise, if they get no one else to praise them, disgrace themselves by their anxiety to feed their own vanity. But when, not merely content with praising themselves, they vie with the praise of others, and pit their own deeds and actions against theirs, with the intent of outshining them, they add envy and malignity to their vanity. The proverb teaches us that to put our foot into another's dance is meddlesome and ridiculous; we ought equally to be on our guard against intruding our own panegyric into others' praises out of envy and spite, nor should we allow others either to praise us then, but we should make way for those that are being honoured, if they are worthy of honour, and even if they seem to us undeserving of honour and worthless, we ought not to strip them of their praise by self-laudation, but by direct argument and proof that they are not worthy of all these encomiums. It is plain then that we ought to avoid all such conduct as this.

§ iii. That is vain glory when people seem to praise themselves just to get others to praise them too; it is especially looked down upon because it appears to come from ambition and an exaggerated view of oneself. Just as those who can't find food are forced to eat their own flesh out of desperation, people who crave praise will embarrass themselves by their anxiety to feed their own vanity if they can’t get anyone else to acknowledge them. But when they’re not just satisfied with self-praise and start competing with others’ praise, trying to outshine them, they add jealousy and malice to their vanity. The saying teaches us that stepping into someone else's spotlight is annoying and foolish; we should also be careful not to insert our own praise into others' acknowledgments out of envy and resentment. We shouldn’t even allow others to praise us then; instead, we should step aside for those who deserve recognition. Even if we think someone is unworthy of praise, we shouldn’t undermine them with self-approval, but rather debate and prove that they don't deserve all those compliments. It’s clear that we should avoid all such behavior.

§ iv. But self-praise cannot be blamed, if it is an answer to some charge or calumny, as those words of Pericles, "And yet you are angry with such a man as me, a man I take it inferior to no one either in knowledge of what should be done, or in ability to point out the same, and a lover of my country to boot, and superior to bribes."772 For not only did he avoid all swagger and vain-glory and ambition in talking thus loftily about himself, but he also exhi318bited the spirit and greatness of his virtue, which could abase and crush envy because it could not be abased itself. For people will hardly condemn such men, for they are elevated and cheered and inspired by noble self-laudation such as this, if it have a true basis, as all history testifies. Thus the Thebans, when their generals were charged with not returning home, and laying down their office of Bœotarchs when their time had expired, but instead of that making inroads into Laconia, and helping Messene, hardly acquitted Pelopidas, who was submissive and suppliant, but for Epaminondas,773 who gloried in what he had done, and at last said that he was ready to die, if they would confess that he had ravaged Laconia, and restored Messene, and made Arcadia one state, against the will of the Thebans, they would not pass sentence upon him, but admired his heroism, and with rejoicing and smiles set him free. So too we must not altogether find fault with Sthenelus in Homer saying,

§ iv. But self-praise can’t be criticized if it’s a response to some accusation or slander, like Pericles' words, "And yet you are angry with someone like me, a man who I believe is no less knowledgeable about what needs to be done, or less capable of pointing it out, and a lover of my country to boot, who also refuses bribes."772 He not only avoided all arrogance, vanity, and ambition in speaking so highly of himself, but also showed the spirit and greatness of his virtue, which could bring down and crush envy because it could not be brought down itself. People rarely condemn such individuals because they are uplifted, encouraged, and inspired by noble self-praise like this, if it’s based in truth, as all of history shows. Similarly, the Thebans, when their generals were accused of not returning home and relinquishing their Bœotarch positions when their term ended, instead of making incursions into Laconia and aiding Messene, hardly exonerated Pelopidas, who was humble and pleading, but rather Epaminondas,773 who took pride in his actions, and in the end, declared that he was ready to die if they would admit that he had ravaged Laconia, restored Messene, and unified Arcadia against the wishes of the Thebans; they did not pass judgment on him but admired his bravery, and with joy and smiles, set him free. Similarly, we shouldn’t completely condemn Sthenelus in Homer saying,

"We think we're much better than our fathers,"774

when we remember the words of Agamemnon,

when we remember the words of Agamemnon,

"What's up? You son of the fearless horse-tamer Tydeus, Why are you crouching in fear and watching from a distance? The battle lines? How different you are from your father!775

For it was not because he was defamed himself, but he stood up for his friend776 that was abused, the occasion giving him a reasonable excuse for self-commendation. So too the Romans were far from pleased at Cicero's frequently passing encomiums upon himself in the affair of Catiline, yet when Scipio said they ought not to try him (Scipio), since he had given them the power to try anybody, they put on garlands, and accompanied him to the Capitol, and sacrificed with him. For Cicero was not compelled to praise himself, but only did so for glory, whereas the danger in which Scipio stood removed envy from him.

For it wasn't that he was being slandered himself, but he defended his friend776 who was being mistreated, which gave him a good reason to commend himself. Similarly, the Romans weren’t happy with Cicero constantly praising himself during the Catiline affair, but when Scipio suggested they shouldn’t put him on trial (since he had given them the authority to trial anyone), they celebrated him with garlands and accompanied him to the Capitol to make sacrifices with him. Cicero wasn’t forced to praise himself, but did it for the sake of glory, while Scipio’s situation spared him from jealousy.

§ v. And not only on one's trial and in danger, but also in misfortune, is tall talk and boasting more suitable than in prosperity. For in prosperity people seem to clutch as it were at glory and enjoy it, and so gratify their ambition; 319but in adversity, being far from ambition owing to circumstances, such self-commendation seems to be a bearing up and fortifying the spirit against fortune, and an avoidance altogether of that desire for pity and condolence, and that humility, which we often find in adversity. As then we esteem those persons vain and without sense who in walking hold themselves very erect and with a stiff neck, yet in boxing or fighting we commend such as hold themselves up and alert, so the man struggling with adversity, who stands up straight against his fate, "in fighting posture like some boxer,"777 and instead of being humble and abject becomes through his boasting lofty and dignified, seems to be not offensive and impudent, but great and invincible. This is why, I suppose, Homer has represented Patroclus modest and without reproach in prosperity, yet at the moment of death saying grandiloquently,

§ v. Not only during one's trial and in danger, but also in tough times, talking big and boasting is more fitting than when times are good. In prosperity, people seem to grab hold of glory and enjoy it, satisfying their ambitions; 319 but in adversity, far from ambition due to their circumstances, self-praise appears to be a way of holding up and strengthening the spirit against misfortune, as well as an avoidance of the desire for pity and sympathy, and the humility often seen when facing challenges. Just as we view those who walk around upright and stiff-necked as vain and foolish, we commend those who stand tall and alert in a boxing ring or during a fight. Similarly, a person battling adversity who stands tall against their fate, "in fighting posture like some boxer,"777 and instead of being humble and submissive, becomes proud and dignified through boasting, doesn’t come off as rude or arrogant, but rather as great and invincible. This is likely why Homer portrays Patroclus as humble and without reproach in good times, yet at the moment of death, speaking grandly,

"Had twenty warriors fought me like you," Everyone had fallen to my triumphant spear.778

And Phocion, though in other respects he was gentle, yet after his sentence exhibited his greatness of soul to many others, and notably to one of those that were to die with him, who was weeping and wailing, to whom he said, "What! are you not content to die with Phocion?"

And Phocion, although he was gentle in other ways, showed his strength of character to many people after his sentence. Notably, he spoke to one of the men who was going to die with him, who was crying and mourning. He said, "What! Aren't you happy to die with Phocion?"

§ vi. Not less, but still more, lawful is it for a public man who is wronged to speak on his own behalf to those who treat him with ingratitude. Thus Achilles generally conceded glory to the gods, and modestly used such language as,

§ vi. Not less, but even more, it's acceptable for a public figure who feels wronged to speak up for himself to those who show him ingratitude. For example, Achilles often acknowledged the gods' glory and humbly expressed himself like this:

"If Zeus ever "Will allow me to sack the well-built town of Troy;"779

but when insulted and outraged contrary to his deserts, he utters in his rage boastful words,

but when he is insulted and wronged unfairly, he responds in his anger with arrogant words,

"I got off my ships and sacked twelve towns,"780

and,

and,

"For they will never have the courage to face my helmet." When it shines nearby.781

320For frank outspokenness, when it is part of one's defence, admits of boasting. It was in this spirit no doubt that Themistocles, who neither in word nor deed had given any offence, when he saw the Athenians were tired of him and treating him with neglect, did not abstain from saying, "My good sirs, why do you tire of receiving benefits so frequently at the same hands?" and782 "When the storm is on you fly to me for shelter as to a tree, but when fine weather comes again, then you pass by and strip me of my leaves."

320Being openly honest, especially when defending oneself, can come off as bragging. It was probably in this mindset that Themistocles, who had neither spoken nor acted in a way that caused any offense, remarked when he noticed the Athenians were getting tired of him and treating him with indifference, "My good sirs, why do you get tired of receiving help so often from the same people?" and782 "When the storm hits, you come to me for shelter like I'm a tree, but when the weather is nice again, you just walk by and strip me of my leaves."

§ vii. They then that are wronged generally mention what they have done well to those who are ungrateful. And the person who is blamed for what he has done well is altogether to be pardoned, and not censured, if he passes encomiums on his own actions: for he is in the position of one not scolding but making his defence. This it was that made Demosthenes' freedom of speech splendid, and prevented people being wearied out by the praise which in all his speech On the Crown he lavished on himself, pluming himself on those embassies and decrees in connection with the war with which fault had been found.

§ vii. Those who feel wronged often highlight their good deeds to those who don't appreciate it. If someone is criticized for their good actions, they should be forgiven rather than condemned, especially if they're defending themselves instead of complaining. This is what made Demosthenes' eloquence remarkable; it kept people engaged despite the self-praise he expressed throughout his speech On the Crown, where he took pride in his roles and decisions related to the war, which were often criticized.

§ viii. Not very unlike this is the grace of antithesis, when a person shows that the opposite of what he is charged with is base and low. Thus Lycurgus when he was charged at Athens with having bribed an informer to silence, replied, "What kind of a citizen do you think me, who, having had so long time the fingering of your public money, am detected in giving rather than taking unjustly?" And Cicero, when Metellus told him that he had destroyed more as a witness than he had got acquitted as an advocate, answered, "Who denies that my honesty is greater than my eloquence?" Compare such sayings of Demosthenes as, "Who would not have been justified in killing me, had I tried in word only to impair the ancient glory of our city?"783 And, "What think you these wretches would have said, if the states had departed, when I was curiously discussing these points?"784 And indeed the whole of that speech On the Crown most ingeniously introduces his own 321praises in his antitheses, and answers to the charges brought against him.

§ viii. This is similar to the grace of antithesis, where someone demonstrates that the accusation against them is actually base and low. For example, when Lycurgus was accused in Athens of bribing an informer to keep quiet, he responded, "What kind of citizen do you think I am, who, after having control over your public funds for so long, is caught giving rather than taking unjustly?" Similarly, Cicero replied to Metellus, who claimed he had harmed more as a witness than he had helped as a lawyer, with, "Who says my honesty isn't greater than my eloquence?" Consider Demosthenes' remarks, like, "Who wouldn’t have been justified in killing me if I had only tried to tarnish the ancient glory of our city?"783 And, "What do you think those wretches would have said if the states had fallen apart while I was carefully discussing these matters?"784 In fact, the entirety of that speech On the Crown cleverly weaves in his own praises through antitheses, addressing the accusations made against him.

§ ix. However it is worth while to notice in his speech that he most artistically inserts praise of his audience in the remarks about himself, and so makes his speech less egotistical and less likely to raise envy. Thus he shows how the Athenians behaved to the Eubœans and to the Thebans, and what benefits they conferred on the people of Byzantium and on the Chersonese, claiming for himself only a subordinate part in the matter. Thus he cunningly insinuates into the audience with his own praises what they will gladly hear, for they rejoice at the enumeration of their successes,785 and their joy is succeeded by admiration and esteem for the person to whom the success was due. So also Epaminondas, when Meneclidas once jeered at him as thinking more of himself than Agamemnon ever did, replied, "It is your fault then, men of Thebes, by whose help alone I put down the power of the Lacedæmonians in one day."

§ ix. However, it’s important to notice in his speech that he skillfully includes praise for his audience when talking about himself, making his speech seem less self-centered and less likely to provoke envy. He illustrates how the Athenians treated the Eubœans and Thebans, as well as the benefits they provided to the people of Byzantium and the Chersonese, claiming only a minor role in these events. In doing so, he cleverly inserts praises that the audience will happily hear, since they take pride in their achievements,785 leading to admiration and respect for the person responsible for those successes. Similarly, when Meneclidas once mocked Epaminondas for being more self-important than Agamemnon, he responded, "Then it’s your fault, men of Thebes, since it was only with your help that I defeated the Lacedæmonians in a single day."

§ x. But since most people very much dislike and object to a man's praising himself, but if he praises some one else are on the contrary often glad and readily bear him out, some are in the habit of praising in season those that have the same pursuits business and characters as themselves, and so conciliate and move the audience in their own favour; for the audience know at the moment such a one is speaking that, though he is speaking about another, yet his own similar virtue is worthy of their praise.786 For as one who throws in another's teeth things of which he is guilty himself must know that he upbraids himself most, so the good in paying honour to the good remind those who know their character of themselves, so that their hearers cry out at once, "Are not you such a one yourself?" Thus Alexander honouring Hercules, and Androcottus again honouring Alexander, got themselves honoured on the same grounds. Dionysius on the contrary pulling Gelon to pieces, and calling him the Gelos787 of Sicily, was not aware that through his envy he was weakening the importance and dignity of his own authority.

§ x. Most people really dislike and object to someone praising themselves, but if they praise someone else, people are often pleased and readily support them. Some individuals have a habit of praising those who share similar goals, careers, and traits, which helps them win over the audience. The audience realizes that even though the speaker is talking about someone else, their own similar qualities are also commendable. 786 Just like someone who criticizes another for faults they themselves possess ends up condemning themselves, those who honor goodness remind their audience of their own virtues, prompting the listeners to think, "Aren't you that kind of person too?" For instance, Alexander honored Hercules, and Androcottus in turn honored Alexander, which earned them recognition for the same reasons. In contrast, Dionysius, by tearing Gelon apart and labeling him the Gelos787 of Sicily, failed to realize that his jealousy was undermining the significance and respect of his own authority.

322§ xi. These things then a public man must generally know and observe. But those that are compelled to praise themselves do so less offensively if they do not ascribe all the honour to themselves, but, being aware that their glory will be tiresome to others, set it down partly to fortune, partly to the deity. So Achilles said well,

322§ xi. These are the things a public figure should generally understand and keep in mind. However, those who feel the need to praise themselves come across as less annoying if they don’t take all the credit themselves. Instead, recognizing that their achievements might bore others, they attribute part of their success to luck and part to the divine. As Achilles wisely said,

"Since the gods have allowed us to kill this hero."788

Well also did Timoleon, who erected a temple at Syracuse to the goddess of Fortune after his success, and dedicated his house to the Good Genius. Excellently again did Pytho of Ænos, (when he came to Athens after killing Cotys, and when the demagogues vied with one another in praising him to the people, and he observed that some were jealous and displeased,) in coming forward and saying, "Men of Athens, this is the doing of one of the gods, I only put my hands to the work." Sulla also forestalled envy by ever praising fortune, and eventually he proclaimed himself as under the protection of Aphrodite.789 For men would rather ascribe their defeat to fortune than the enemy's valour, for in the former case they consider it an accident, whereas in the latter case they would have to blame themselves and set it down to their own shortcomings. So they say the legislation of Zaleucus pleased the Locrians not least, because he said that Athene visited him from time to time, and suggested to him and taught him his laws, and that none of those he promulgated were his own idea and plan.

Timoleon also did well; he built a temple in Syracuse for the goddess of Fortune after his victory and dedicated his home to the Good Genius. Pytho of Ænos, after killing Cotys and arriving in Athens, noticed the demagogues competing to praise him, and seeing some were jealous and unhappy, spoke up, saying, "Men of Athens, this is the work of one of the gods; I merely contributed my hands to the effort." Sulla also preempted envy by constantly praising fortune and even declared himself under the protection of Aphrodite.789 People prefer to attribute their defeats to fortune rather than the enemy's bravery, because if they blame fortune, they see it as a mere accident. But if they admit the enemy was braver, they would have to hold themselves accountable for their own failures. So, they say the laws of Zaleucus were particularly pleasing to the Locrians because he claimed that Athene visited him occasionally, guiding and teaching him his laws, insisting that none of his laws were entirely his own idea and design.

§ xii. Perhaps this kind of remedy by talking people over must be contrived for those who are altogether crabbed or envious; but for people of moderation it is not amiss to qualify excessive praise. Thus if anyone should praise you as learned, or rich, or influential, it would be well to bid him not talk about you in that strain, but say that you were good and harmless and useful. For the person that acts so does not introduce his own praise but transfers it, nor does he seem to rejoice in people passing encomiums upon him, but rather to be vexed at their praising him inappropriately and on wrong grounds, and he seems to 323hide bad traits by better ones, not wishing to be praised, but showing how he ought to be praised. Such seems the intent of such words as the following, "I have not fortified the city with stones or bricks, but if you wish to see how I have fortified it, you will find arms and horses and allies."790 Still more in point are the last words of Pericles. For as he was dying, and his friends very naturally were weeping and wailing, and reminded him of his military services and his power, and the trophies and victories and towns he had won for Athens, and was leaving as a legacy, he raised himself up a little and blamed them as praising him for things common to many, and some of them the results of fortune rather than merit, while they had passed over the best and greatest of his deeds and one peculiarly his own, that he had never been the cause of any Athenian's wearing mourning. This gives the orator an example, if he be a good man, when praised for his eloquence, to transfer the praise to his life and character, and the general who is admired for his skill and good fortune in war to speak with confidence about his gentleness and uprightness. And again, if any very extravagant praise is uttered, such as many people use in flattery which provokes envy, one can reply,

§ xii. Maybe this type of talk-it-out remedy is meant for those who are completely grouchy or jealous; but for those who are moderate, it’s not a bad idea to tone down excessive compliments. So if someone calls you knowledgeable, wealthy, or influential, it would be wise to ask them not to speak of you in that way, but instead to say you are good, kind, and helpful. The person who does this isn’t seeking their own praise but redirecting it; they don’t seem to enjoy being praised for inappropriate reasons but are instead annoyed that others are recognizing them based on the wrong criteria. They appear to cover up their flaws with better qualities, not wanting to be praised, but instead showing how they truly deserve to be acknowledged. This seems to align with statements like, "I haven’t fortified the city with stones or bricks, but if you want to see how I've strengthened it, look at the arms, horses, and allies.”790 Even more relevant are the final words of Pericles. While he was dying, and his friends were understandably crying and recalling his military achievements and power, as well as the trophies, victories, and cities he had secured for Athens, which he was leaving as a legacy, he raised himself slightly and criticized them for praising him for things that are common to many, some of which were more a result of luck than skill. They overlooked his greatest accomplishment—he had never caused any Athenian to wear mourning. This serves as an example for an orator, if they are a good person, when receiving praise for their eloquence, to shift the recognition to their character and integrity, and for a general admired for their skill and good fortune in war to confidently highlight their kindness and honesty. Similarly, if someone expresses overly extravagant praise, like what many people use in flattery that incites jealousy, one can respond,

I'm not a god; why do you compare me To the immortals? __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

If you really know me, praise my integrity, or my sobriety, or my kindheartedness, or my philanthropy. For even envy is not reluctant to give moderate praise to one that deprecates excessive praise, and true panegyric is not lost by people refusing to accept idle and false praise. So those kings who would not be called gods or the sons of gods, but only fond of their brothers or mother, or benefactors,792 or dear to the gods, did not excite the envy of those that honoured them by those titles, that were noble but still such as men might claim. Again, people dislike those writers or speakers who entitle themselves wise, but they wel324come those who content themselves with saying that they are lovers of philosophy, and have made some progress, or use some such moderate language about themselves as that, which does not excite envy. But rhetorical sophists, who expect to hear "Divine, wonderful, grand," at their declamations, are not even welcomed with "Pretty fair, so so."

If you really know me, appreciate my integrity, my sobriety, my kindness, or my philanthropy. Even envy can acknowledge someone who downplays excessive praise, and genuine admiration isn't diminished by people who refuse to accept empty flattery. So those kings who don't want to be called gods or the sons of gods, but only fond of their siblings or parents, or benefactors, or dear to the gods, didn’t provoke the envy of those who honored them with titles that, while noble, are still within the reach of humanity. On the other hand, people dislike writers or speakers who call themselves wise, but they welcome those who simply say they love philosophy and have made some progress, or who speak about themselves in a way that doesn’t stir up envy. However, rhetorical sophists who expect to hear "Divine, wonderful, grand" at their speeches aren't even met with "Pretty good, okay."

§ xiii. Moreover, as people anxious not to injure those who have weak eyes, draw a shade over too much light, so some people make their praise of themselves less glaring and absolute, by pointing out some of their small defects, or miscarriages, or errors, and so remove all risk of making people offended or envious. Thus Epeus, who boasts very much of his skill in boxing, and says very confidently,

§ xiii. Just as people who want to avoid hurting those with weak eyes dim the bright light, some individuals tone down their self-praise by highlighting minor flaws, mistakes, or errors, which reduces the chance of offending or making others jealous. For example, Epeus, who talks a lot about his boxing skills and expresses his confidence,

"I can crush your body and break your bones,"793

yet says,

yet says,

"Isn't it enough that I'm lacking in combat skills?"794

But Epeus is perhaps a ridiculous instance, excusing his bragging as an athlete by his confession of timidity and want of manliness. But agreeable and graceful is that man who mentions his own forgetfulness, or ignorance, or ambition, or eager desire for knowledge and conversation. Thus Odysseus of the Sirens,

But Epeus is maybe a silly example, justifying his boasting as an athlete by admitting he’s timid and lacks manliness. But likable and charming is the person who talks about their own forgetfulness, ignorance, ambition, or strong desire for knowledge and conversation. So it is with Odysseus and the Sirens,

"My heart was inclined to listen to them, I nodded to my friends to release me. 795

And again of the Cyclops,

And again of the Cyclops,

"I did not listen (it would have been much better), I wanted to see the Cyclops and to experience His hospitality. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

And generally speaking the admixture with praise of such faults as are not altogether base and ignoble stops envy. Thus many have blunted the point of envy by admitting and introducing, when they have been praised, their past poverty and straits, aye, and their low origin. So Agathocles pledging his young men in golden cups beautifully chased, ordered some earthenware pots to be brought in, and said, "See the fruits of perseverance, labour, and bravery! Once I produced pots like these, but now golden cups." 325For Agathocles it seems was so low-born and poor that he was brought up in a potter's shop, though afterwards he was king of almost all Sicily.

And generally speaking, mixing in praise for faults that aren't completely low and despicable helps reduce envy. Many have softened feelings of envy by mentioning their past struggles and humble beginnings when they receive compliments. For example, Agathocles, while drinking from beautifully crafted golden cups with his young men, asked for some earthen pots to be brought in and said, "See the rewards of perseverance, hard work, and courage! I once made pots like these, but now I have golden cups." 325 It seems Agathocles was so poor and low-born that he grew up in a potter's shop, yet he later became king of almost all of Sicily.

§ xiv. These are external remedies against self-praise. There are other internal ones as it were, such as Cato applied, when he said "he was envied, because he had to neglect his own affairs, and lie awake every night for the interests of his country." Compare also the following lines,

§ xiv. These are external solutions to self-praise. There are also internal ones, like the ones Cato used when he said "he was envied because he had to ignore his own matters and stay awake every night for the sake of his country." Also, consider the following lines,

"How should I brag? Who could have easily been Enlisted among the many in the military, And had a fortune that matched the wisest;"797

and,

and,

"I hesitate to waste the benefits of my past efforts," "I don't reject all the work I'm doing right now." __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

For as it is with house and farm, so also is it with glory and reputation, people for the most part envy those who have got them easily or for nothing, not those who have bought them at the cost of much toil and danger.

For just as it is with homes and land, it is also true for fame and reputation; most people envy those who have acquired them easily or without effort, not those who have earned them through hard work and risk.

§ xv. Since then we can praise ourselves not only without causing pain or envy but even usefully and advantageously, let us consider, that we may not seem to have only that end in view but some other also, if we might praise ourselves to excite in our hearers emulation and ambition. For Nestor, by reciting his battles and acts of prowess, stirred up Patroclus and nine others to single combat with Hector. For the exhortation that adds deed to word and example and proper emulation is animating and moving and stimulating, and with its impulse and resolution inspires hope that the things we aim at are attainable and not impossible. That is why in the choruses at Lacedæmon the old men sing,

§ xv. Since then, we can confidently praise ourselves without causing pain or envy, and even do it in a helpful and beneficial way. Let's consider that we might want to have more than one goal in mind; for example, we could praise ourselves to inspire our listeners to feel ambitious and competitive. Nestor, by recounting his battles and heroic deeds, motivated Patroclus and nine others to challenge Hector to a duel. The encouragement that combines action with words and serves as an example is energizing, moving, and stimulating, and it instills hope that what we strive for is achievable and not out of reach. That’s why, in the choruses at Lacedæmon, the elderly sing,

"We used to be young, energetic, and strong,"

and then the boys,

and then the guys,

"We will be much stronger than we are now,"

and then the youths,

and then the young people,

"We're strong now, take a look if you want."

326 In this wise and statesmanlike manner did the legislator exhibit to the young men the nearest and dearest examples of what they should do in the persons of those who had done so.

326 In this thoughtful and diplomatic way, the legislator showed the young men the closest and most important examples of what they should do through the actions of those who had already done it.

§ xvi. Moreover it is not amiss sometimes, to awe and repress and take down and tame the impudent and bold, to boast and talk a little big about oneself. As Nestor did, to mention him again,

§ xvi. Also, it's not a bad idea to sometimes intimidate, control, and humble the bold and arrogant, to brag a bit about oneself. Just like Nestor did, to mention him again,

"For I have mingled before now with better men." "More than both of you, and they never looked down on me." 798

So also Aristotle told Alexander that not only had they that were rulers over many subjects a right to think highly of themselves, but also those that had right views about the gods. Useful too against our enemies and foes is the following line,

So Aristotle also told Alexander that those who rule over many subjects not only have the right to think highly of themselves, but so do those who have the right beliefs about the gods. The following line is also useful against our enemies and foes,

"Unlucky are those whose sons meet me." 799

Compare also the remark of Agesilaus about the king of the Persians, who was called great, "How is he greater than me, if he is not also more upright?" And that also of Epaminondas to the Lacedæmonians who were inveighing against the Thebans, "Anyhow we have made you talk at greater length than usual." But these kind of remarks are fitting for enemies and foes; but our boasting is also good on occasion for friends and fellow-citizens, not only to abate their pride and make them more humble, but also when they are in fear and dejection to raise them up again and give them confidence. Thus Cyrus talked big in perils and on battle-fields, though at other times he was no boaster. And the second Antigonus, though he was on all other occasions modest and far from vanity, yet in the sea-fight off Cos, when one of his friends said to him, "See you not how many more ships the enemy have got than we have?" answered, "How many do you make me equal to then?" This Homer also seems to have noticed. For he has represented Odysseus, when his comrades were dreadfully afraid of the noise and whirlpool of Charybdis, reminding them of his former cleverness and valour;

Compare the comment from Agesilaus about the Persian king, who was called great: "How is he greater than me if he’s not also more honorable?" And Epaminondas’ response to the Lacedæmonians who were criticizing the Thebans: "At least we’ve made you talk longer than usual." Such remarks are appropriate for enemies and rivals; however, boasting can also be beneficial among friends and fellow citizens. It's not just to reduce their pride and humble them but also to lift their spirits and restore their confidence when they feel scared or down. For example, Cyrus spoke boldly in dangerous situations and on battlefields, even though he wasn’t a braggart at other times. Similarly, the second Antigonus, who was usually modest and not vain, replied during the sea battle off Cos when one of his friends pointed out the enemy’s greater number of ships, saying, "How many do you count me equal to then?" Homer seems to note this as well. He portrays Odysseus reminding his terrified comrades of his previous cleverness and bravery when they were scared of the noise and whirlpool of Charybdis;

"We're no worse off than we were when the Cyclops" 327 He forcibly held us in his empty cave; But even then, thanks to my courage and judgment, And yes, we did escape.800

For such is not the self-praise of a demagogue or sophist, or of one that asks for clapping or applause, but of one who makes his valour and experience a pledge of confidence to his friends. For in critical conjunctures the reputation and credit of one who has experience and capacity in command plays a great part in insuring safety.

For this is not the self-promotion of a demagogue or a clever speaker, nor is it someone seeking admiration or applause, but rather someone who uses their bravery and experience as a promise of trust to their friends. In crucial moments, the reputation and credibility of someone with experience and skill in leadership are key to ensuring safety.

§ xvii. As I have said before, to pit oneself against another's praise and reputation is by no means fitting for a public man: however, in important matters, where mistaken praise is injurious and detrimental, it is not amiss to confute it, or rather to divert the hearer to what is better by showing him the difference between true and false merit. Anyone would be glad, I suppose, when vice was abused and censured, to see most people voluntarily keep aloof from it; but if vice should be well thought of, and honour and reputation come to the person who promoted its pleasures or desires, no nature is so well constituted or strong that it would not be mastered by it. So the public man must oppose the praise not of men but of bad actions, for such praise is corrupting, and causes people to imitate and emulate what is base as if it were noble. But it is best refuted by putting it side by side with the truth: as Theodorus the tragic actor is reported to have said once to Satyrus the comic actor, "It is not so wonderful to make an audience laugh as to make them weep and cry." But what if some philosopher had answered him, "To make an audience weep and cry is not so noble a thing as to make them forget their sorrows." This kind of self-laudation benefits the hearer, and changes his opinion. Compare the remark of Zeno in reference to the number of Theophrastus' scholars, "His is a larger body, but mine are better taught." And Phocion, when Leosthenes was still in prosperity, being asked by the orators what benefit he had conferred on the city, replied, "Only this, that during my period of office there has been no funeral oration, but all 328the dead have been buried in their fathers' sepulchres." Wittily also did Crates parody the lines,

§ xvii. As I’ve mentioned before, competing against someone else's praise and reputation isn't really appropriate for someone in public life. However, when it comes to significant issues where misguided praise can cause harm, it's necessary to counter it or to guide the listener towards what’s better by illustrating the difference between real and false merit. I think anyone would appreciate it if people distanced themselves from vice when it's criticized; but if vice is regarded positively and fame and respect are given to those who indulge its pleasures or desires, there's no one strong enough by nature to resist it. Therefore, a public figure must challenge not the praise of individuals but the praise for bad actions, because such praise is corrupting and leads others to imitate and pursue what is immoral as if it were worthy. The best way to counter such praise is by contrasting it with the truth: as Theodorus the tragic actor supposedly told Satyrus the comic actor, "It’s not so remarkable to make an audience laugh as it is to make them weep." But what if a philosopher countered by saying, "Making an audience weep isn't as noble as helping them forget their sorrow?" This kind of self-praise benefits the listener and shifts their perspective. Consider Zeno’s comment about the number of Theophrastus' students: "His group is larger, but mine are better educated." And Phocion, when Leosthenes was thriving, was asked by orators what benefit he'd brought to the city; he replied, "Just this: during my time in office, there hasn't been a single funeral speech, and all 328 the dead have been laid to rest in their family graves." Crates also humorously parodied the lines,

"Eating, indulgence, and the pleasures of love" Are all I value,

with

with

"Learning and the great things the Muses teach us" "Are all I value."

Such self-praise is good and useful and teaches people to admire and love what is valuable and expedient instead of what is vain and superfluous. Let so much suffice on the question proposed.

Such self-praise is beneficial and instructive, encouraging people to appreciate and love what is valuable and practical instead of what is worthless and unnecessary. That should be enough on the topic at hand.

§ xviii. It remains to me now to point out, what our subject next demands and calls for, how everyone may avoid unseasonable self-praise. For there is a wonderful incentive to talking about oneself in self-love, which is frequently strongly implanted in those who seem to have only moderate aspirations for fame. For as it is one of the rules to preserve good health to avoid altogether places where sickness is, or to exercise the greatest precaution if one must go there, so talking about oneself has its slippery times and places that draw it on on any pretext. For first, when others are praised, as I said before, ambition makes people talk about themselves, and a certain desire and impulse for fame which is hard to check bites and tickles that ambition, especially if the other person is praised for the same things or less important things than the hearer thinks he is a proficient in. For as hungry people have their appetite more inflamed and sharpened by seeing others eat, so the praise of one's neighbours makes those who eagerly desire fame to blaze out into jealousy.

§ xviii. Now, I need to highlight what our topic demands next: how everyone can avoid unnecessary self-praise. There’s a strong urge to talk about oneself due to self-love, which often affects those who seem to have only modest ambitions for recognition. Just as it's important for good health to avoid places where illness is present or to take extreme precautions if one must go there, discussing oneself can lead to slippery moments and situations that encourage it under any excuse. First, when others receive praise, as I mentioned earlier, ambition pushes people to talk about themselves, driven by a hard-to-control desire for recognition. This urge is particularly strong if someone else is praised for the same or less significant accomplishments than what the listener believes they excel in. Just as hungry people’s appetites are heightened when they see others eating, praise for one's peers can ignite jealousy in those who are eager for fame.

§ xix. In the second place the narration of things done successfully and to people's mind entices many unawares to boasting and bragging in their joy; for falling into conversation about their victories, or success in state affairs, or their words or deeds commended by great men, they cannot keep themselves within bounds. With this kind of self-laudation you may see that soldiers and sailors are most taken. To be in this state of mind also frequently happens to those who have returned from important posts and responsible duties, for in their mention of illustrious329 men and men of royal rank they insert the encomiums they have passed on themselves, and do not so much think they are praising themselves as merely repeating the praises of others about themselves. Others think their hearers do not detect them at all of self-praise, when they recount the greeting and welcome and kindness they have received from kings and emperors, but only imagine them to be enumerating the courtesy and kindliness of those great personages. So we must be very much on our guard in praising others to free ourselves from all suspicion of self-love and self-recommendation, and not to seem to be really praising ourselves "under pretext of Patroclus."801

§ xix. Secondly, the way people share their achievements and what resonates with others often leads them to brag and boast in their happiness. When they start talking about their victories, successes in government, or the praise they've received from influential figures, they struggle to hold back. This kind of self-praise is especially common among soldiers and sailors. It also often happens to those who have returned from significant roles and responsibilities, as they bring up notable figures and royalty while sneaking in compliments about themselves, not realizing they're praising themselves but thinking they're just repeating the compliments others have given them. Some believe their audience doesn’t see through their self-praise when they talk about the warm receptions and kindness they received from kings and emperors, and instead think they're just listing the graciousness of these important people. Therefore, we need to be very careful when praising others to avoid any hints of self-love and self-promotion, and not appear to be genuinely praising ourselves "under the pretext of Patroclus."801

§ xx. Moreover that kind of conversation that mainly consists of censuring and running down others is dangerous as giving opportunity for self-laudation to those who pine for fame. A fault into which old men especially fall, when they are led to scold others and censure their bad ways and faulty actions, and so extol themselves as being remarkably the opposite. In old men we must allow all this, especially if to age they add reputation and merit, for such fault-finding is not without use, and inspires those who are rebuked with both emulation and love of honour.802 But all other persons must especially avoid and fear that roundabout kind of self-praise. For since generally speaking censuring one's neighbours is disagreeable and barely tolerable and requires great wariness, he that mixes up his own praise with blame of another, and hunts for fame by defaming another, is altogether tiresome and inspires disgust, for he seems to wish to get credit through trying to prove others unworthy of credit.

§ xx. Furthermore, that type of conversation that mainly involves criticizing and belittling others is risky because it gives a chance for self-promotion to those who crave attention. This is a mistake that older individuals often make when they are inclined to scold others and condemn their bad behavior and mistakes, thus elevating themselves as being the exact opposite. We can excuse this in older people, especially if their age comes with respect and achievements, as this kind of fault-finding isn’t without purpose and motivates those who are criticized to strive and aspire to honor.802 However, others should particularly steer clear of and be wary of this indirect form of self-praise. Generally speaking, criticizing one’s neighbors is unpleasant and only barely acceptable, and it requires a lot of caution. Those who mix their own praise with criticism of others, seeking recognition by disparaging someone else, are simply tiresome and evoke disgust, as they seem to want to gain credit by proving others unworthy of it.

§ xxi. Furthermore, as those that are naturally prone and inclined to laughter must be especially on their guard against tickling and touching, such as excites that propensity by contact with the smoothest parts of the body, so those that have a great passion for reputation ought to be especially advised to abstain from praising themselves when they are praised by others. For a person ought to blush when praised, and not to be past blushing from 330impudence, and ought to check those who extol him too highly, and not to rebuke them for praising him too little; though very many people do so, themselves prompting and reminding their praisers of others of their own acts and virtues, till by their own praise they spoil the effect of the praise that others give them. For some tickle and puff themselves up by self-praise, while others, malignantly holding out the small bait of eulogy, provoke others to talk about themselves, while others again ask questions and put inquiries, as was done to the soldier in Menander, merely to poke fun at him;

§ xxi. Moreover, just as those who are naturally inclined to laughter need to be particularly careful about being tickled or touched—since it can trigger that feeling through contact with the smoothest areas of their body—those who are passionate about their reputation should avoid self-praise when others compliment them. A person should feel embarrassed when receiving praise and shouldn’t be shameless about it; they should discourage excessive flattery from others rather than criticize them for not praising enough. However, many people do the opposite by suggesting and reminding their admirers of their own accomplishments and virtues, ultimately undermining the appreciation they receive. Some puff themselves up through self-praise, while others, with malicious intent, dangle minor compliments to provoke discussion about themselves. Others still, like the soldier in Menander, ask questions and make inquiries just to mock him;

"'How did you get this wound?' 'Sir, from a javelin.'" 'How on Earth?' 'I was on A scaling ladder secured to a wall. I seriously show them my wound, "But they just laugh at me."

§ xxii. As regards all these points then we must be on our guard as much as possible not to launch out into praise of ourselves, or yield to it in consequence of questions put to us to draw us. And the best caution and security against this is to pay attention to others who praise themselves, and to consider how disagreeable and objectionable the practice is to everybody, and that no other conversation is so offensive and tiring. For though we cannot say that we suffer any other evil at the hands of those who praise themselves, yet being naturally bored by the practice, and avoiding it, we are anxious to get rid of them and breathe again; insomuch that even the flatterer and parasite and needy person in his distress finds the rich man or satrap or king praising himself hard to bear and wellnigh intolerable; and they say that having to listen to all this is paying a very large shot to their entertainment, like the fellow in Menander;

§ xxii. When it comes to all these points, we need to be very careful not to praise ourselves or to give in to it when asked questions that might lead us that way. The best way to avoid this is to pay attention to others who do praise themselves and notice how unpleasant and annoying it is to everyone. No other type of conversation is as offensive and exhausting. Even if we can’t pinpoint any direct harm from those who boast, we naturally find it tiresome and want to escape. Even a flatterer or someone in need finds it hard to tolerate a rich person, ruler, or king who keeps talking about their own achievements. They would say that listening to all that is like paying a hefty price for their entertainment, similar to the character in Menander.

"To listen to their silly__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ clichés and military chatter, Like this arrogant loudmouth boasts, "It kills me; I get skinny even at their feasts."

For as we may use this language not only about soldiers or men who have newly become rich,804 who spin us a long 331yarn of their great and grand doings, being puffed up with pride and talking big about themselves; if we remember that the censure of others always follows our self-praise, and that the end of this vain-glory is a bad repute, and that, as Demosthenes says,805 the result will be that we shall only tire our hearers, and not be thought what we profess ourselves to be, we shall cease talking about ourselves, unless by so doing we can bestow great benefit on ourselves or our hearers.

For we might use this language not just about soldiers or newly wealthy men,804 who boast endlessly about their impressive achievements, filled with pride and talking themselves up; if we remember that the criticism of others often follows our self-praise, and that the result of this vanity is a bad reputation, and that, as Demosthenes says,805 the outcome will be that we merely bore our listeners and won't be seen as what we claim to be, we will stop talking about ourselves, unless doing so can really benefit us or our audience.

768 Pindar, "Olymp." ix. 57, 58.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Pindar, "Olymp." ix. 57, 58.

769 Mentioned by Pausanias, iii. 12; viii. 50.

769 Referenced by Pausanias, iii. 12; viii. 50.

770 "Memorabilia," ii. l. 31.

"Memorabilia," vol. ii, p. 31.

771 Reading as Wyttenbach suggests, μάλιστα δὲ ὅταν λέγηται τὰ ἄλλῳ πεπραγμένα sq.

771 Reading as Wyttenbach suggests, especially when it is said that the other things have been accomplished. sq.

772 Thucydides, ii. 60.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Thucydides, 2.60.

773 See Pausanias, ix. 14, 15.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Pausanias, ix. 14, 15.

774 Homer, "Iliad," iv. 405.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," IV. 405.

775 Homer, "Iliad," iv. 370, 371.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," Book 4, lines 370-371.

776 Diomede.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Diomede.

777 Sophocles, "Trachiniæ," 442.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Sophocles, "Trachiniæ," 442.

778 Homer, "Iliad," xvi. 847, 848. Plutarch only quotes the first line. I have added the second for the English reader, as necessary for the sense.

778 Homer, "Iliad," xvi. 847, 848. Plutarch only cites the first line. I included the second line for the English reader, as it's needed for the overall meaning.

779 Homer, "Iliad," i. 128, 129.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 1. 128, 129.

780 "Iliad," ix. 328.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," Book 9, Line 328.

781 "Iliad," xvi. 70, 71.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 16. 70, 71.

782 So Wyttenbach.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ So Wyttenbach.

783 Demosthenes, "De Corona," p. 260.

783 Demosthenes, "On the Crown," p. 260.

784 "De Corona," p. 307.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "On the Crown," p. 307.

785 After Wyttenbach.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ After Wyttenbach.

786 After Wyttenbach.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ After Wyttenbach.

787 That is, laughing-stock. A play on the word Gelon.

787 In other words, a laughingstock. A play on the word Gelon.

788 Homer, "Iliad," xxii. 379. He speaks of Hector.

788 Homer, "Iliad," xxii. 379. He is talking about Hector.

789 Others take it "as fortune's favourite."

789 Others see it "as luck's favorite."

790 Words of Demosthenes, "De Corona," p. 325. Plutarch condenses them.

790 Words of Demosthenes, "De Corona," p. 325. Plutarch summarizes them.

791 Homer, "Odyssey," xvi. 187.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Odyssey," 16.187.

792 Titles of the Ptolemies, Philadelphus Philometor, Euergetes.

792 Titles of the Ptolemies, Philadelphus, Philometor, Euergetes.

793 Homer, "Iliad," xxiii. 673.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 23.673.

794 Ibid. 670.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source. 670.

795 Homer, "Odyssey," xii. 192-194.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Odyssey," book 12, lines 192-194.

796 Ibid. ix. 228, 229.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source. ix. 228, 229.

797 Fragments from the "Philoctetes" of Euripides.

797 Fragments from the "Philoctetes" by Euripides.

798 Homer, "Iliad," i. 260, 261.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," Book 1, lines 260-261.

799 Homer, "Iliad," vi. 127.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," VI. 127.

800 Homer, "Odyssey," xii. 209-212.

Homer, "Odyssey," xii. 209-212.

801 An allusion to Homer, "Iliad," xix. 302.

801 A reference to Homer, "Iliad," xix. 302.

802 Adopting the reading of Dübner.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Taking Dübner's view.

803 Adopting the reading of Salmasius.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Embracing Salmasius' perspective.

804 Nouveaux riches, novi homines.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ New money, new people.

805 Demosthenes, "De Corona," p. 270.

805 Demosthenes, "On the Crown," p. 270.


ON THOSE WHO ARE PUNISHED BY THE DEITY LATE.

A discussion between Patrocleas, Plutarch, Timon, and Olympicus.

A conversation between Patrocleas, Plutarch, Timon, and Olympicus.

§ i. When Epicurus had made these remarks, Quintus, and before any of us who were at the end of the porch806 could reply, he went off abruptly. And we, marvelling somewhat at his rudeness, stood still silently but looked at one another, and then turned and pursued our walk as before. And Patrocleas was the first to speak. "Are we," said he, "to leave the question unanswered, or are we to reply to his argument in his absence as if he were present?" Then said Timon, "Because he went off the moment he had thrown his missile at us, it would not be good surely to leave it sticking in us; for we are told that Brasidas plucked the javelin that had been thrown at him out of his body, and with it killed the hurler of it; but there is of course no need for us to avenge ourselves so on those that have launched on us an absurd or false argument, it will be enough to dislodge the notion before it gets fixed in us." Then said I, "Which of his words has moved you 332most? For the fellow seemed to rampage about, in his anger and abusive language, with a long disconnected and rambling rhapsody drawn from all sources, and at the same time inveighed against Providence."

§ i. After Epicurus made these comments, Quintus suddenly left before any of us at the end of the porch806. We were taken aback by his rudeness, standing silently and exchanging glances before continuing our walk as before. Patrocleas was the first to break the silence. "Are we," he asked, "going to leave the question unanswered, or should we respond to his argument as if he were still here?" Timon replied, "Since he left right after throwing his verbal attack at us, it wouldn’t be wise to just leave it hanging; we’ve heard that Brasidas removed the javelin lodged in his own body and then killed the one who threw it. However, we don’t need to go that far in responding to those who present us with absurd or false arguments; it’s enough for us to challenge the idea before it takes root in us." I then asked, "Which of his words impacted you 332 the most? He seemed to rant angrily and abusively, rambling on with bits from everywhere while also attacking Providence."

§ ii. Then said Patrocleas, "The slowness and delay of the deity in punishing the wicked used to seem807 to me a very dreadful thing, but now in consequence of his speech I come as it were new and fresh to the notion. Yet long ago I was vexed when I heard that line of Euripides,

§ ii. Then Patroclus said, "The slowness of the gods in punishing the wicked always seemed to me a really terrible thing, but now, because of his words, I feel like I'm seeing it in a whole new way. Still, I was really bothered when I first heard that line from Euripides,

"He does delay; that’s just how the Deity is." In nature. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

For indeed it is not fitting that the deity should be slow in anything, and least of all in the punishment of the wicked, seeing that they are not slow or sluggish in doing evil, but are hurried by their passions into crime at headlong speed. Moreover, as Thucydides809 says, when punishment follows as closely as possible upon wrong-doing, it blocks up the road at once for those who would follow up their villainy if it were successful. For no debt so much as that of justice paid behind time damps the hopes and dejects the mind of the wronged person, and aggravates the audacity and daring of the wrong-doer; whereas the punishment that follows crime immediately not only checks future outbreaks but is also the greatest possible comfort to the injured. And so I am often troubled when I consider that remark of Bias, who told, it seems, a bad man that he was not afraid that he would escape punishment, but that he would not live to see it. For how did the Messenians who were killed long before derive any benefit from the punishment of Aristocrates? For he had been guilty of treason at the battle of The Great Trench, but had reigned over the Arcadians for more than twenty years without being found out, but afterwards was detected and paid the penalty, but they were no longer alive.810 Or what consolation was brought to the people of Orchomenus, who lost their sons and friends and relatives in consequence of the treason of 333Lyciscus, by the disease which settled upon him long afterwards and spread all over his body? For he used to go and dip and soak his feet in the river, and uttered imprecations and prayed that they might rot off if he was guilty of treason or crime. Nor was it permitted to the children's children of those that were slain to see at Athens the tearing out of their graves the bodies of those atrocious criminals that had killed them, and the carrying them beyond their borders. And so it seems strange in Euripides using the following argument to deter people from vice:

For surely it isn’t appropriate for the divine to be slow in any matter, especially in punishing the wicked, since they are not slow or lazy when doing evil; rather, they are rushed by their desires into wrongdoing at breakneck speed. Furthermore, as Thucydides809 points out, when punishment closely follows wrongdoing, it effectively blocks the path for those who would consider continuing their villainy if they were successful. There’s no debt as burdensome as justice delivered late, which dims the hopes and brings down the spirits of the victim while emboldening the wrongdoer; on the other hand, immediate punishment not only curbs future offenses but also provides the greatest possible solace to the harmed. I often feel troubled when I reflect on Bias's comment, where he told a wicked man that he wasn’t concerned about escaping punishment, but rather that he wouldn’t live to see it. How did the Messenians who were killed long before benefit from the punishment of Aristocrates? He had committed treason at the battle of The Great Trench but ruled over the Arcadians for over twenty years without being discovered; only later was he caught and punished, but by then, the victims were no longer alive.810 What comfort was there for the people of Orchomenus, who lost sons, friends, and family due to the treachery of 333Lyciscus, from the illness that struck him long after and spread throughout his body? He used to go and soak his feet in the river, cursing himself and praying for them to rot off if he was guilty of treason or crime. And the descendants of those who were killed were not allowed to witness in Athens the exhumation of the bodies of those monstrous criminals who had killed their kin, nor the removal of their remains beyond the borders. So it seems odd that Euripides would use the following argument to deter people from vice:

"Don't worry, because revenge won't come right away." Your heart, or that of any guilty soul, But it moves quietly and slowly, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "And when their time comes, will the wicked be caught."

This is no doubt the very reason why the wicked incite and cheer themselves on to commit lawless acts, for crime shows them a fruit visible and ripe at once, but a punishment late, and long subsequent to the enjoyment."

This is undoubtedly why the wicked encourage each other to commit illegal acts, because crime offers them immediate and visible rewards, while punishment comes later and follows long after the thrill.

§ iii. When Patrocleas had said thus much, Olympicus interfered, "There is another consideration, Patrocleas, the great absurdity involved in these delays and long-suffering of the deity. For the slowness of punishment takes away belief in providence, and the wicked, observing that no evil follows each crime except long afterwards, attribute it when it comes to mischance, and look upon it in the light more of accident than punishment, and so receive no benefit from it, being grieved indeed when the misfortune comes, but feeling no remorse for what they have done amiss. For, as in the case of a horse, the whipping or spurring that immediately follows upon a stumble or some other fault is a corrective and brings him to his duty, but pulling and backing him with the bit and shouting at him long afterwards seems to come from some other motive than a desire to teach him, for he is put to pain without being shown his fault; so the vice which each time it stumbles or offends is at once punished and checked by correction is most likely812 to come to itself and be humble 334and stand in awe of the deity, as one that beholds men's acts and passions and does not punish behind time; whereas that justice that, according to Euripides, "steals on silently and with slow foot," and falls upon the wicked some time or other, seems to resemble more chance than providence by reason, of its uncertainty, delay, and irregularity. So that I do not see what benefit there is in those mills of the gods that are said to grind late,813 since they obscure the punishment, and obliterate the fear, of evil-doing."

§ iii. When Patroclus had said this, Olympicus interrupted, "There's another point, Patroclus, the ridiculousness of these delays and the long suffering of the deity. The slow pace of punishment undermines belief in divine oversight. Those who do wrong see that no negative consequences follow their actions right away, so when they do face misfortune later, they think of it as bad luck rather than punishment. They experience pain when bad luck arrives but don’t feel guilty about their misdeeds. It's like a horse: if he stumbles and is immediately spanked or kicked, he learns and behaves better. But if you pull on the reins and shout at him much later, it seems like you're doing it for some other reason than to teach him. He feels hurt without understanding what he did wrong. Similarly, vice that is quickly punished and corrected is more likely to learn humility and respect for the deity, who watches human actions and emotions and doesn’t delay punishment. But that justice, as Euripides puts it, "creeps in silently with slow steps," and strikes the wicked eventually, appears more like chance than divine oversight due to its unpredictability, delays, and irregularities. So, I don’t see the benefit in those gods' mills that are said to grind slowly,813 because they obscure punishment and remove the fear of wrongdoing."

§ iv. When Olympicus had done speaking, and I was musing with myself on the matter, Timon said, "Am I to put the finishing touch of difficulty on our subject, or am I to let him first contend earnestly against these views?" Then said I, "Why should we bring up the third wave814 and drown the argument, if he is not able to refute or evade the charges already brought? To begin then with the domestic hearth, as the saying is,815 let us imitate that cautious manner of speaking about the deity in vogue among the Academic philosophers, and decline to speak about these things as if we thoroughly understood them. For it is worse in us mortals than for people ignorant of music to discuss music, or for people ignorant of military matters to discuss the art of war, to examine too closely into the nature of the gods and demons, like people with no knowledge of art trying to get at the intention of artists from opinion and fancy and probabilities. For if816 it is no easy matter for anyone not a professional to conjecture why the surgeon performed an operation later rather than sooner, or why he ordered his patient to take a bath to-day rather than yesterday, how is it easy or safe for a mortal to say anything else about the deity than that he knows best the time to cure vice, and applies to each his punishment as the doctor administers a drug, and that a punishment not of the same magnitude, or applied at the same time, in all cases. For that the cure of the soul, which is called justice, is the greatest of all arts is testified 335by Pindar as well as by ten thousand others, for he calls God, the ruler and lord of all things, the greatest artificer as the creator of justice, whose function it is to determine when, and how, and how far, each bad man is to be punished. And Plato says that Minos, the son of Zeus, was his father's pupil in this art, not thinking it possible that any one could succeed in justice, or understand how to succeed in it, without he had learned or somehow got that science. For the laws which men make are not always merely reasonable, nor is their meaning always apparent, but some injunctions seem quite ridiculous, for example, the Ephors at Lacedæmon make proclamation, directly they take office, that no one is to let his moustache grow, but that all are to obey the laws, that they be not grievous to them. And the Romans lay a light rod on the bodies of those they make freemen, and when they make their wills, they nominate some as their heirs, while to others they sell the property, which, seems strange. But strangest of all is that ordinance of Solon, that the citizen who, when his city is in faction, will not side with either party is to lose his civic rights. And generally one might mention many absurdities in laws, if one did not know the mind of the legislator, or understand the reason for each particular piece of legislation. How is it wonderful then, if human affairs are so difficult to comprehend, that it is no easy task to say in connection with the gods, why they punish some offenders early, and others late?

§ iv. Once Olympicus finished speaking, and I was reflecting on the topic, Timon asked, "Should I complicate our discussion even further, or should I let him first argue against these ideas?" I replied, "Why should we introduce a new layer of complexity814 and complicate the debate if he can't address the issues already raised? Let's start with the basics, as they say,815 and adopt the cautious way of discussing the divine that’s popular among the Academic philosophers, avoiding claims of complete understanding on these topics. It’s worse for us humans to overly scrutinize the nature of gods and demons than it is for those who know nothing about music to discuss music, or for those ignorant of military matters to talk about warfare, similar to those with no artistic background trying to decipher an artist’s intentions based only on assumptions and opinions. If it's already difficult for a layperson to guess why a surgeon might choose to operate later rather than sooner, or why he advised a patient to bathe today instead of yesterday, how can it be easy or safe for a mortal to suggest anything about the divine beyond the fact that the deity knows best when to address wrongdoing, administering each punishment like a doctor with medicine, and not treating all cases the same way or at the same time? The notion that the cure of the soul, which we call justice, is the highest of arts is supported 335 by Pindar and many others, who call God the supreme creator of justice, responsible for deciding when, how, and to what extent each wrongdoer should be punished. Plato even suggests that Minos, son of Zeus, was his father's student in this craft, implying that no one could truly grasp justice or how to achieve it without having learned that skill. Laws made by humans aren't always entirely logical, and their intent isn't always clear; some rules seem downright absurd. For instance, when the Ephors of Sparta take office, they publicly announce that nobody should grow a mustache, all while enforcing laws to ensure they aren't burdensome. Then there are the Romans, who lightly strike the bodies of those they grant freedom, and specify heirs in their wills, while selling property to others, which seems odd. But the most peculiar rule is Solon’s decree that a citizen who refuses to side with either faction during civil strife will lose their civic rights. Generally, one could point out numerous absurdities in laws if one didn’t understand the legislator's intent or the rationale for each specific law. So, is it really surprising that if human matters are so complex, it’s not easy to determine why some offenders are punished by the gods early, while others are punished later?

§ v. This is not a pretext for evading the subject, but merely a request for lenient judgement, that our discourse, looking as it were for a haven and place of refuge, may rise to the difficulty with greater confidence basing itself on probability. Consider then first that, according to Plato, god, making himself openly a pattern of all things good, concedes human virtue, which is in some sort a resemblance to himself, to those who are able to follow him. For all nature, being in disorder, got the principle of change and became order817 by a resemblance to and participation in the nature and virtue of the deity. The same Plato also tells us that nature put eyesight into us, in order that 336the soul by beholding and admiring the heavenly bodies might accustom itself to welcome and love harmony and order, and might hate disorderly and roving propensities, and avoid aimless reliance on chance, as the parent of all vice and error. For man can enjoy no greater blessing from god than to attain to virtue by the earnest imitation of the noblest qualities of the divine nature. And so he punishes the wicked leisurely and long after, not being afraid of error or after repentance through punishing too hastily, but to take away from us that eager and brutish thirst for revenge, and to teach us that we are not to retaliate on those that have offended us in anger, and when the soul is most inflamed and distorted with passion and almost beside itself for rage, like people satisfying fierce thirst or hunger, but to imitate the mildness and long-suffering of the deity, and to avenge ourselves in an orderly and decent manner, only when we have taken counsel with time long enough to give us the least possible likelihood of after repentance. For it is a smaller evil, as Socrates said, to drink dirty water when excessively thirsty, than, when one's mind is disturbed and full of rage and fury, before it is settled and becomes pure, to glut our revenge on the person of a relation and kinsman. For it is not the punishment that follows as closely as possible upon wrong-doing, as Thucydides said,818 but that which is more remote, that observes decorum. For as Melanthius says of anger,

§ v. This isn’t an excuse to avoid the topic; it’s just a request for leniency so that our discussion, seeking a safe haven, can tackle the issues more confidently based on reasonable assumptions. First, consider that according to Plato, God openly serves as a model for all good things and grants human virtue, which resembles Him to those who can follow His example. As all of nature is in chaos, it gained the principle of change and became orderly by mirroring and participating in the nature and virtue of the divine. Plato also tells us that nature gave us sight so that the soul, by observing and appreciating the heavenly bodies, could learn to welcome and love harmony and order while hating disorderly tendencies and avoiding random chance, which brings about all vice and error. No greater blessing can man receive from God than to achieve virtue by sincerely imitating the finest qualities of the divine nature. Thus, He punishes the wicked slowly and after a long time, not out of fear of making mistakes or regretting hasty punishment, but to remove our savage thirst for revenge and to teach us not to retaliate against those who have wronged us in anger, especially when our soul is fired up with passion and almost out of control with rage, like someone desperate to quench an intense thirst or hunger. Instead, we should emulate the gentleness and patience of the divine, and seek revenge only in an orderly and civilized way after we've taken enough time to avoid any chance of later regret. As Socrates said, it's the lesser evil to drink dirty water when you're extremely thirsty than to satisfy our rage by taking revenge on a relative before our mind is calm and clear. As Thucydides pointed out, it’s not the punishment that falls immediately after wrongdoing but rather the one that comes later, which maintains decorum. As Melanthius remarked about anger,

"Terrible things happen when it unsettles the mind,"819

so also reason acts with justice and moderation, when it banishes rage and passion. So also people are made milder by the example of other men, as when they hear that Plato, when he held his stick over his slave to correct him, waited some time, as he himself has told us, to compose his anger; and that Archytas, having learned of some wrong or disorderly action on the part of some of his farm labourers, knowing that at the time he was in a very great rage and highly incensed at them, did nothing to them, but merely departed, saying, "You may thank your stars that I am in 337a rage with you." If then the remembrance of the words and recorded acts of men abates the fierceness and intensity of our rage, much more likely is it that we (observing that the deity, though without either fear or repentance in any case, yet puts off his punishments and defers them for some time) shall be reserved in our views about such matters, and shall think that mildness and long-suffering which the god exhibits a divine part of virtue, reforming a few by speedy punishment, but benefiting and correcting many by a tardy one.

Reason operates with justice and moderation when it pushes aside anger and passion. People also become gentler by witnessing the behavior of others, like when Plato, while raising his stick to correct his slave, paused for a moment—just as he recounted—to calm his anger. Similarly, Archytas, upon discovering some wrongdoing by his farm laborers, chose not to act in his intense rage; instead, he left, saying, "You can thank your lucky stars that I'm not angry with you." If remembering the words and actions of others can lessen the intensity of our anger, then it makes even more sense that we should hold back our judgments since the divine, despite not feeling fear or remorse, still postpones punishment for a time. This should encourage us to see the patience and restraint demonstrated by the divine as a vital part of virtue, correcting a few through swift punishment while benefiting and reforming many through a delayed response.

§ vi. Let us consider in the second place that punishments inflicted by men for offences regard only retaliation, and, when the offender is punished, stop and go no further; so that they seem to follow offences yelping at them like a dog, and closely pursuing at their heels as it were. But it is likely that the deity would look at the state of any guilty soul that he intended to punish, if haply it might turn and repent, and would give820 time for reformation to all whose vice was not absolute and incurable. For knowing how great a share of virtue souls come into the world with, deriving it from him, and how strong and lasting is their nobility of nature, and how it breaks out into vice against its natural disposition through the corruption of bad habits and companions, and afterwards in some cases reforms itself, and recovers its proper position, he does not inflict punishment on all persons alike; but the incorrigible he at once removes from life and cuts off, since it is altogether injurious to others, but most of all to a man's own self, to live in perpetual vice, whereas to those who seem to have fallen into wrong-doing, rather from ignorance of what was good than from deliberate choice of what was bad, he gives time to repent. But if they persist in vice he punishes them too, for he has no fear that they will escape him. Consider also how many changes take place in the life and character of men, so that the Greeks give the names τρόπος and ἦθος to the character, the first word meaning change, and the latter the immense force and power of habit. I think also that the ancients called Cecrops half man and half dragon821 338not because, as some say, he became from a good king wild and dragon-like, but contrariwise because he was originally perverse and terrible, and afterwards became a mild and humane king. And if this is uncertain, at any rate we know that Gelon and Hiero, both Sicilians, and Pisistratus the son of Hippocrates, though they got their supreme power by bad means, yet used it for virtuous ends, and though they mounted the throne in an irregular way, yet became good and useful princes. For by good legislation and by encouraging agriculture they made the citizens earnest and industrious instead of scoffers and chatterers. As for Gelon, after fighting valiantly and defeating the Carthaginians in a great battle, he would not conclude with them the peace they asked for until they inserted an article promising to cease sacrificing their sons to Cronos. And Lydiades was tyrant in Megalopolis, yet in the very height of his power changing his ideas and being disgusted with injustice, he restored their old constitution to the citizens,822 and fell gloriously, fighting against the enemy in behalf of his country. And if any one had slain prematurely Miltiades the tyrant of the Chersonese, or had prosecuted and got a conviction against Cimon for incest with his sister, or had deprived Athens of Themistocles for his wantonness and revellings and outrages in the market, as in later days Athens lost Alcibiades, by an indictment, should we not have had to go without the glory of Marathon, and Eurymedon, and beautiful Artemisium, "where the Athenian youth laid the bright base of liberty?"823 For great natures produce nothing little, nor can their energy and activity rust owing to their keen intellect, but they toss to and fro as at sea till they come to a settled and durable character. As then one inexperienced in farming, seeing a spot full of thick bushes and rank growth, full of wild beasts and streams and mud, would not think much of it, while to one who has learnt how to discriminate and discern between different kind of soils all these are various tokens of the richness and goodness of the land, so great natures break out into many strange excesses, which exasperate us at first beyond bearing, so that we think it right to cut off such offenders and 339stop their career at once, whereas a better judge, seeing the good and noble even in these, waits for age and the season which nature appoints for gathering fruit to bring sense and virtue.

§ vi. Let's consider next that punishments people impose for offenses are really just about retaliation; they begin and end when the offender is punished. It’s as if these punishments bark at the offenses and closely follow at their heels. However, it's likely that a deity would assess the condition of any guilty soul he intends to punish, hoping they might turn and repent. He would allow820 time for change for anyone whose wrongdoing is not absolute and hopeless. Knowing how much virtue souls are born with, derived from him, and how strong and lasting their noble nature is, he recognizes how it can succumb to vice due to bad habits and companions. He also understands that sometimes, this nature reforms itself and returns to its original state. Thus, he doesn’t punish everyone equally; he removes the incorrigible immediately, as living in constant vice harms not just others but most of all oneself. For those who seem to have strayed due to ignorance rather than willfully choosing wrong, he gives them time to repent. But if they continue in their vice, he punishes them as well, knowing they can’t escape him. Also, consider how many changes occur in people's lives and characters, so the Greeks use the terms τρόπος and ἦθος to describe character, with the first meaning change and the second the immense strength of habit. I also think the ancients referred to Cecrops as half man and half dragon821 338 not because, as some say, he turned wild and dragon-like from being a good king, but rather because he was initially wicked and frightening and later became gentle and humane. Even if this is uncertain, we know that Gelon and Hiero, both from Sicily, and Pisistratus, the son of Hippocrates, though they gained their power through corrupt means, still used it for virtuous purposes. Even though they took the throne in irregular ways, they became good and helpful rulers. Through good laws and support for agriculture, they turned citizens from being scoffers and gossipers into earnest and hardworking individuals. For Gelon, after bravely fighting and defeating the Carthaginians in a significant battle, refused to agree to the peace deal they sought until they included a clause promising to stop sacrificing their sons to Cronos. Lydiades was a tyrant in Megalopolis, yet at the peak of his power, he changed his views and, disillusioned with injustice, restored the old governance to the citizens,822 and died gloriously while fighting for his country. If someone had killed Miltiades, the tyrant of Chersonese, or had prosecuted and convicted Cimon for incest with his sister, or had ousted Themistocles from Athens for his wild behavior and misdeeds in the marketplace, as Athens later lost Alcibiades through prosecution, would we have had to forgo the glory of Marathon, and Eurymedon, and the beautiful Artemisium, "where the Athenian youth laid the bright foundation of liberty?"823 Great souls don’t produce anything trivial; their energy and vigor can’t stagnate due to their sharp intellect. Instead, they thrash about like the sea until they develop a steady and lasting character. Just as someone inexperienced in farming, seeing a plot overrun with thick bushes, wild beasts, and muddy streams, might dismiss it, while someone skilled in discerning soil types recognizes these as signs of the land's richness and potential, great souls often display many strange excesses that initially frustrate us to the point that we think it’s correct to eliminate such offenders and halt their actions immediately. In contrast, a wiser judge, seeing the good and noble aspects even in these behaviors, waits for maturity and the season that nature designates for reaping fruit, allowing sense and virtue to emerge.

§ vii. So much for this point. Do you not think also that some of the Greeks did well to adopt that Egyptian law which orders a pregnant woman condemned to death not to suffer the penalty till after she has given birth?" "Certainly," said all the company. I continued, "Put the case not of a woman pregnant, but of a man who can in process of time bring to light and reveal some secret act or plan, point out some unknown evil, or devise some scheme of safety, or invent something useful and necessary, would it not be better to defer his execution, and wait the result of his meditation? That is my opinion, at least." "So we all think," said Patrocleas. "Quite right," said I. "For do but consider, had Dionysius had vengeance taken on him at the beginning of his tyranny, none of the Greeks would have dwelt in Sicily, which was laid waste by the Carthaginians. Nor would the Greeks have dwelt in Apollonia, or Anactorium, or the peninsula of the Leucadians, had not Periander's chastisement been postponed for a long time. I think also that Cassander's punishment was deferred that Thebes might be repeopled. And of the mercenaries that plundered this very temple most crossed over into Sicily with Timoleon, and after they had conquered the Carthaginians and put down their authority, perished miserably, miserable wretches that they were. For no doubt the deity makes use of some wicked men, as executioners, to punish others, and so I think he crushes as it were most tyrants. For as the gall of the hyena and rennet of the seal, both nasty beasts in all other respects, are useful in certain diseases, so when some need sharp correction, the deity casts upon them the implacable fury of some tyrant, or the savage ferocity of some prince, and does not remove the bane and trouble till their fault be got rid of and purged. Such a potion was Phalaris to the Agrigentines, and Marius to the Romans. And to the people of Sicyon the god distinctly foretold that their city needed a scourge, when they took away from the Cleonæans (as if he was a Sicyonian) the lad Teletias, who was crowned340 in the Pythian games, and tore him to pieces. As for the Sicyonians, Orthagoras became their tyrant, and subsequently Myro and Clisthenes, and these three checked their wanton outbreaks; but the Cleonæans, not getting such a cure, went to ruin. You have of course heard Homer's lines,

§ vii. So much for this point. Don’t you think some of the Greeks made a smart move by adopting that Egyptian law that says a pregnant woman who’s sentenced to death shouldn’t face her punishment until after she gives birth?" "Absolutely," everyone agreed. I continued, "Imagine instead of a pregnant woman, we’re talking about a man who, over time, could uncover some secret action or plan, highlight some hidden danger, come up with a safety strategy, or invent something valuable and necessary. Wouldn’t it be better to delay his execution and see what he comes up with? That’s my view, at least." "And we all agree," Patrocleas said. "Exactly," I responded. "Just think, if Dionysius had been punished at the start of his tyranny, none of the Greeks would have lived in Sicily, which was devastated by the Carthaginians. Nor would they have settled in Apollonia, Anactorium, or the Leucadian peninsula if Periander's punishment hadn’t been postponed for a long time. I also believe Cassander’s punishment was delayed to allow Thebes to repopulate. Most of the mercenaries who looted this very temple ended up crossing into Sicily with Timoleon, and after defeating the Carthaginians and ending their control, they met a miserable end, poor souls. Without a doubt, the deity uses some wicked individuals, as executioners, to punish others, and in doing so, I think he destroys many tyrants. Just as the bile from a hyena and the rennet from a seal, both nasty creatures otherwise, are useful in certain ailments, when some need a harsh lesson, the deity brings upon them the relentless fury of a tyrant or the savage brutality of a ruler, and doesn’t remove the source of their suffering until their wrongdoing has been corrected and purged. Phalaris was such a remedy for the Agrigentines, and Marius for the Romans. The god clearly indicated to the people of Sicyon that their city needed a punishment when they took Teletias, who was crowned at the Pythian games, from the Cleonæans (as if he were one of them), and tore him to pieces. As for the Sicyonians, Orthagoras became their tyrant, followed by Myro and Clisthenes, and these three restrained their reckless behavior; but the Cleonæans, lacking such a cure, fell into ruin. You’ve certainly heard Homer's lines,

"'From a bad father came a son who was much better, Excelling in all virtues;'824

and yet that son of Copreus never performed any brilliant or notable action: but the descendants of Sisyphus and Autolycus and Phlegyas nourished in the glory and virtues of great kings. Pericles also sprang of a family under a curse,825 and Pompey the Great at Rome was the son of Pompeius Strabo, whose dead body the Roman people cast out and trampled upon, so great was their hatred of him. How is it strange then, since the farmer does not cut down the thorn till he has taken his asparagus, nor do the Libyans burn the twigs till they have gathered the ledanum, that god does not exterminate the wicked and rugged root of an illustrious and royal race till it has produced its fit fruit? For it would have been better for the Phocians to have lost ten thousand of the oxen and horses of Iphitus, and for more gold and silver to have gone from Delphi, than that Odysseus and Æsculapius should not have been born, nor those others who from bad and wicked men became good and useful."

and yet that son of Copreus never did anything remarkable or noteworthy: but the descendants of Sisyphus, Autolycus, and Phlegyas thrived in the glory and virtues of great kings. Pericles also came from a family under a curse,825 and Pompey the Great in Rome was the son of Pompeius Strabo, whose dead body the Roman people threw out and trampled on, so deep was their hatred for him. So, is it really surprising that, just as a farmer doesn't cut down the thornbush until after he harvests his asparagus, nor do the Libyans burn the twigs until they have collected the ledanum, God doesn’t wipe out the wicked and stubborn root of an illustrious and royal family until it has borne its rightful fruit? Because it would have been better for the Phocians to lose ten thousand of Iphitus's oxen and horses, and for more gold and silver to leave Delphi, than for Odysseus and Æsculapius not to be born, or for those others who emerged from bad and wicked men to become good and useful.

§ viii. "And do you not all think that it is better that punishment should take place at the fitting time and in the fitting manner rather than quickly and on the spur of the moment? Consider the case of Callippus, who with the very dagger with which he slew Dion, pretending to be his friend, was afterwards slain by his own friends. And when Mitius the Argive was killed in a tumult, a brazen statue in the market-place fell on his murderer and killed him during the public games. And of course, Patrocleas, you know all about Bessus the Pæonian, and about Aristo the Œtæan leader of mercenaries." "Not I, by Zeus," said Patrocleas, "but I should like to hear." "Aristo," I 341continued, "at the permission of the tyrants removed the necklace of Eriphyle826 which was hung up in this temple, and took it to his wife as a present; but his son being angry with his mother for some reason or other, set the house on fire, and burnt all that were in it. As for Bessus, it seems he had killed his father, though his crime was long undiscovered. But at last going to sup with some strangers, he knocked down a nest of swallows, pricking it with his lance, and killed all the young swallows. And when the company said, as it was likely they would, 'Whatever makes you act in such a strange manner?' 'Have they not,' he replied, 'been long bearing false witness against me, crying out that I had killed my father?' And the company, astonished at his answer, laid the matter before the king, and the affair was inquired into, and Bessus punished."

§ viii. "Do you all agree that it's better for punishment to happen at the right time and in the right way rather than quickly and impulsively? Take the example of Callippus, who used the same dagger with which he killed Dion, pretending to be his friend, only to be killed by his own friends later. And when Mitius the Argive was killed in a riot, a bronze statue in the marketplace fell on his murderer and killed him during the public games. And of course, Patrocleas, you're aware of Bessus the Pæonian and Aristo, the Œtæan leader of mercenaries." "Not me, by Zeus," Patrocleas replied, "but I'm interested in hearing." "Aristo," I 341 continued, "with the tyrants' permission, removed the necklace of Eriphyle826 that was displayed in this temple and gave it to his wife as a gift; but his son got angry with his mother for some reason and set their house on fire, killing everyone inside. As for Bessus, he apparently killed his father, though his crime went unnoticed for a long time. Eventually, while dining with some strangers, he knocked down a nest of swallows with his lance, killing all the young ones. When the others asked, understandably, 'Why are you acting so strangely?' he replied, 'Haven't they been falsely accusing me for ages, yelling that I had killed my father?' The group, surprised by his response, reported the incident to the king, and an investigation was conducted, leading to Bessus's punishment."

§ ix. "These cases," I continued, "we cite supposing, as has been laid down, that there is a deferring of punishment to the wicked; and, for the rest, I think we ought to listen to Hesiod, who tells us—not like Plato, who asserts that punishment is a condition that follows crime—that it is contemporaneous with it, and grows with it from the same source and root. For Hesiod says,

§ ix. "In these cases," I went on, "we assume, as it has been said, that punishment for the wicked is postponed; and beyond that, I believe we should pay attention to Hesiod, who tells us—not like Plato, who claims that punishment comes after crime—that it actually happens at the same time and develops alongside it from the same origin. Because Hesiod says,

"Bad advice is the worst for the one giving it;"827

and,

and,

"Those who scheme harm against others bring" It started on his own head.828

The cantharis is said to have in itself the antidote to its own sting, but wickedness, creating its own pain and torment, pays the penalty of its misdeeds not afterwards but at the time of its ill-doing. And as every malefactor about to pay the penalty of his crime in his person bears his cross, so vice fabricates for itself each of its own torments, being the terrible author of its own misery in life, wherein in addition to shame it has frequent fears and fierce passions and endless remorse and anxiety. But some are just 342like children, who, seeing malefactors in the theatres in golden tunics and purple robes with crowns on and dancing, admire them and marvel at them, thinking them happy, till they see them goaded and lashed and issuing fire from their gaudy but cheap garments.829 For most wicked people, though they have great households and conspicuous offices and great power, are yet being secretly punished before they are seen to be murdered or hurled down rocks, which is rather the climax and end of their punishment than the punishment itself. For as Plato tells us that Herodicus the Selymbrian having fallen into consumption, an incurable disease, was the first of mankind to mix exercise with the art of healing, and so prolonged his own life and that of others suffering from the same disease, so those wicked persons who seem to avoid immediate punishment, receive a longer and not slower punishment, not later but extending over a wider period; for they are not punished in their old age, but rather grow old in perpetual punishment. I speak of course of long time as a human being, for to the gods all the period of man's life is as nothing, and so to them 'now and not thirty years ago' means no more than with us torturing or hanging a malefactor in the evening instead of the morning would mean; especially as man is shut up in life as in a prison from which there is no egress or escape, and though doubtless during his life he has much feasting and business and gifts and favours and amusement, yet, just like people playing at dice or draughts in a prison, the rope is all the time hanging over his head."830

The cantharis is said to have the antidote to its own sting, but wickedness, which creates its own pain and suffering, pays the price for its wrongdoings not later, but at the moment it commits them. Just as every wrongdoer carries their burden before facing the consequences of their crime, vice creates its own torment, being the terrible source of its own misery in life. In addition to shame, it experiences frequent fears, intense passions, and endless remorse and anxiety. However, some people are like children, who, seeing wrongdoers in theaters dressed in gold tunics and purple robes with crowns, admire them and think they’re happy until they see them whipped and tormented, bursting into flames from their flashy but cheap clothing. Most wicked people, despite having grand households, prominent positions, and great power, are secretly punished long before they are visibly destroyed or thrown down cliffs, which is more the climax and conclusion of their punishment rather than the punishment itself. As Plato tells us about Herodicus of Selymbria, who fell ill with consumption, an incurable disease, he was the first to combine exercise with healing and thus prolonged his own life and that of others suffering from the same affliction. Similarly, those wicked people who seem to escape immediate punishment face a longer and more gradual form of punishment, one that extends over a longer period rather than occurring later; they are not punished merely in their old age, but instead grow old under constant punishment. I refer, of course, to what time means for humans, because for the gods, the span of a person's life is insignificant; to them, 'now and not thirty years ago' is no different than us executing a wrongdoer in the evening rather than the morning. Especially since humans are trapped in life like prisoners without any way out or escape, and although they enjoy plenty of feasting, work, gifts, favors, and entertainment during their lives, it’s akin to people playing dice or checkers in a prison, always under the threat of a noose hanging over their heads.

§ x. "And indeed what prevents our asserting that people in prison under sentence of death are not punished till their heads are cut off, or that the person who has taken hemlock, and walks about till he feels it is getting into his legs, suffers not at all till he is deprived of sensation by the freezing and curdling of his blood, if we consider the last moment of punishment all the punishment, and ignore all the intermediate sufferings and fears and anxiety and remorse, the 343destiny of every guilty wretch? That would be arguing that the fish that has swallowed the hook is not caught, till we see it boiled by the cook or sliced at table. For every wrong-doer is liable to punishment, and soon swallows the pleasantness of his wrong-doing like a bait, while his conscience still vexes and troubles him,

§ x. "Isn't it true that we could say people on death row aren’t really punished until their heads are cut off? Or that someone who has taken hemlock and is walking around until they feel it affecting their legs isn't suffering at all until they lose sensation from their blood freezing and curdling? If we only consider the final moment of punishment as the whole punishment, ignoring the suffering, fear, anxiety, and remorse in between, is that the ultimate fate of every guilty person? That would be like claiming that a fish that has swallowed a hook isn’t caught until we see it cooked or served at the table. Every wrongdoer faces punishment and soon swallows the allure of their wrongdoing like bait, while their conscience continues to torment them."

"As the swift tuna darts through the sea."

For the recklessness and audacity of vice is strong and rampant till the crime is committed, but afterwards, when the passion subsides like a storm, it becomes timid and dejected and a prey to fears and superstitions. So that Stesichorus in his account of Clytæmnestra's dream may have represented the facts and real state of the case, where he says, "A dragon seemed to appear to her with its lofty head smeared all over with blood, and out of it seemed to come king Orestes the grandson of Plisthenes." For visions in dreams, and apparitions during the day, and oracles, and lightning, and whatever is thought to come from the deity, bring tempests of apprehension to the guilty. So they say that one time Apollodorus in a dream saw himself flayed by the Scythians, and then boiled, and that his heart out of the caldron spoke to him in a low voice and said, "I am the cause of this;" and at another time he dreamed that he saw his daughters running round him in a circle all on fire and in flames. And Hipparchus the son of Pisistratus, a little before his death, dreamt that Aphrodite threw some blood on his face out of a certain phial. And the friends of Ptolemy Ceraunus dreamed that he was summoned for trial by Seleucus, and that the judges were vultures and wolves, who tore his flesh and distributed it wholesale among his enemies. And Pausanias at Byzantium, having sent for Cleonice a free-born maiden, intending to outrage her and pass the night with her, being seized with some alarm or suspicion killed her, and frequently saw her in his dreams saying to him, "Come near for judgement, lust is most assuredly a grievous bane to men," and as this apparition did not cease, he sailed, it seems, to Heraclea to the place where the souls of the dead could be summoned, and by propitiations and sacrifices called up the soul of the maiden, and she appeared to him344 and told him that this trouble would end when he got to Lacedæmon, and directly he got there he died."831

For the boldness and recklessness of wrongdoing are strong and widespread until the crime is committed, but afterward, when the intensity fades like a storm, it turns timid and depressed, becoming vulnerable to fears and superstitions. So, Stesichorus in his account of Clytæmnestra's dream might have accurately captured the reality of the situation when he wrote, "A dragon seemed to appear to her with its high head covered in blood, and from it came king Orestes, the grandson of Plisthenes." Because visions in dreams, sightings during the day, oracles, lightning, and anything thought to come from the divine create storms of fear for the guilty. They say that once Apollodorus dreamed he was skinned by the Scythians and then boiled, and that his heart from the pot spoke softly to him, saying, "I am the cause of this;" and at another time, he dreamed he saw his daughters circling around him, all on fire and engulfed in flames. And Hipparchus, son of Pisistratus, shortly before his death, dreamed that Aphrodite splashed some blood on his face from a certain vial. And friends of Ptolemy Ceraunus dreamed that he was called to trial by Seleucus, where the judges were vultures and wolves, who tore his flesh apart and shared it among his enemies. And Pausanias in Byzantium, after calling for Cleonice, a free-born maiden, intending to take advantage of her and spend the night with her, became overwhelmed with fear or suspicion and killed her. He frequently saw her in his dreams saying to him, "Come near for judgment; lust is truly a serious curse to men." And since this vision didn’t go away, he appears to have sailed to Heraclea, where the souls of the dead can be summoned, and through rituals and sacrifices, he called up the soul of the maiden, who appeared to him344 and told him that his troubles would end when he reached Lacedæmon, and as soon as he got there, he died."831

§ xi. "And so, if nothing happens to the soul after death, but that event is the end of all enjoyment or punishment, one would be rather inclined to say that the deity was lax and indulgent in quickly punishing the wicked and depriving them of life. For even if we were to say that the wicked had no other trouble in a long life, yet, when their wrong-doing was proved to bring them no profit or enjoyment, no good or adequate return for their many and great anxieties, the consciousness of that would be quite enough to throw832 their mind off its balance. So they record of Lysimachus that he was so overcome by thirst that he surrendered himself and his forces to the Getæ for some drink, but after he had drunk and bethought him that he was now a captive, he said, "Alas! How guilty am I for so brief a gratification to lose so great a kingdom!" And yet it is very difficult to resist a necessity of nature. But when a man, either for the love of money, or for political place or power, or carried away by some amorous propensity, does some lawless and dreadful deed, and, after his eager desire is satisfied, sees in process of time that only the base and terrible elements of his crime remain, while nothing useful, or necessary, or advantageous has flowed from it, is it not likely that the idea would often present itself to him that, moved by vain-glory, or for some illiberal and unlovely pleasure, he had violated the greatest and noblest rights of mankind, and had filled his life with shame and trouble? For as Simonides used to say playfully that he always found his money-chest full but his gratitude-chest empty,833 so the wicked contemplating their own vice soon find out that their gratification is joyless and hopeless,834 and ever attended by fears and griefs and gloomy memories, and suspicions about the future, and distrust about the present. Thus we hear Ino, repenting for what she had done, saying on the stage,

§ xi. "So, if nothing happens to the soul after death, and that moment marks the end of all pleasure or punishment, one might argue that the deity is lenient and overly forgiving in swiftly punishing the wicked and taking their lives. Even if we claim that the wicked faced no other troubles throughout a long life, when their wrongdoing proves to yield no benefits or enjoyment, no worthy or sufficient return for their countless and significant worries, just the awareness of that would be enough to destabilize832 their minds. They record about Lysimachus that he was so overwhelmed by thirst that he surrendered himself and his forces to the Getæ for a drink, but after quenching his thirst and realizing he was now a captive, he lamented, "Oh no! How guilty am I for that brief pleasure that cost me my kingdom!" And yet, it's very hard to resist a basic human need. But when a person, driven by the desire for money, power, or some romantic impulsivity, commits a terrible and unlawful act, and later finds that only the negative and dreadful aspects of their crime remain—while nothing beneficial, necessary, or advantageous has come from it—isn't it likely they would often reflect on how, motivated by vanity or for some unworthy pleasure, they violated the most important and noble rights of humanity and filled their lives with shame and distress? Just as Simonides humorously noted that he always found his money-chest full but his gratitude-chest empty,833 the wicked, pondering their own vices, soon realize that their gratification is devoid of joy and hope,834 always accompanied by fears, sorrows, dark memories, and doubts about the future, along with distrust in the present. Thus we hear Ino, regretting her actions, say on stage,

345 "Dear women, I wish I could now live For the first time, the house of Athamas, "Not guilty of any of my terrible actions!"835

It is likely that the soul of every wicked person will meditate in this way, and consider how it can escape the memory of its ill-deeds, and lay its conscience to sleep, and become pure, and live another life over again from the beginning. For there is no confidence, or reality, or continuance, or security, in what wickedness proposes to itself, unless by Zeus we shall say that evil-doers are wise, but wherever the greedy love of wealth or pleasure or violent envy dwells with hatred and malignity, there will you also see and find stationed superstition, and remissness for labour, and cowardice in respect to death, and sudden caprice in the passions, and vain-glory and boasting. Those that censure them frighten them, and they even fear those that praise them as wronged by their deceit, and as most hostile to the bad because they readily praise those they think good. For as in the case of ill-tempered steel the hardness of vice is rotten, and its strength easily shattered. So that in course of time, understanding their real selves, they are vexed and disgusted with their past life and abhor it. For if a bad man who restores property entrusted to his care, or becomes surety for a friend, or contributes very generously and liberally to his country out of love of glory or honour, at once repents and is sorry for what he has done from the fickleness and changeableness of his mind; and if men applauded in the theatres directly afterwards groan, their love of glory subsiding into love of money; shall we suppose that those who sacrificed men to tyrannies and conspiracies as Apollodorus did, or that those who robbed their friends of money as Glaucus the son of Epicydes did,836 never repented, or loathed themselves, or regretted their past misdeeds? For my part, if it is lawful to say so, I do not think evil-doers need any god or man to punish them, for the marring and troubling of all their life by vice is in itself adequate punishment."

It’s likely that the soul of every wicked person will reflect in this way, thinking about how it can escape the memory of its wrongdoings, silence its conscience, become pure, and relive another life from the start. Because there’s no trust, reality, consistency, or security in what wickedness promises itself, unless we claim, by Zeus, that wrongdoers are wise. But wherever greed for wealth or pleasure, or violent envy mixed with hatred and malice exists, there you will also notice superstition, laziness towards work, and cowardice about death, along with sudden mood swings, vanity, and boasting. Those who criticize them scare them, and they even fear those who praise them as enemies due to their deception, since they often praise those they consider good. Just like how the hardness of bad steel is compromised, the strength of vice is fragile. Over time, realizing their true selves, they become annoyed and disgusted with their past and detest it. For if a bad person who returns property entrusted to them, or acts as a guarantor for a friend, or generously contributes to their country out of a desire for glory or honor, immediately regrets and feels sorry for their actions due to the fickleness of their mind; and if those who received applause in theaters soon after groan, as their desire for glory shifts to a desire for money; shall we think that those who sacrificed people to tyrants and conspiracies like Apollodorus, or those who stole from friends like Glaucus, the son of Epicydes,836 never regretted, hated themselves, or felt sorry for their past wrongs? For my part, if it’s appropriate to say so, I believe wrongdoers don’t need a god or any person to punish them, because the disruption and trouble caused by vice in their lives is punishment enough."

§ xii. "But consider now whether I have not spoken too long." Then Timon said, "Perhaps you have, considering 346what remains and the time it will take. For now I am going to start the last question, as if it were a combatant in reserve, since the other two questions have been debated sufficiently. For as to the charge and bold accusation that Euripides brings against the gods, for visiting the sins of the parents upon the children, consider that even those of us who are silent agree with Euripides. For if the guilty were punished themselves there would be no further need to punish the innocent, for it is not fair to punish even the guilty twice for the same offence, whereas if the gods through easiness remit the punishment of the wicked, and exact it later on from the innocent, they do not well to compensate for their tardiness by injustice. Such conduct resembles the story told of Æsop's coming to this very spot,837 with money from Crœsus, to offer a splendid sacrifice to the god, and to give four minæ to each of the Delphians. And some quarrel or difference belike ensuing between him and the Delphians here, he offered the sacrifice, but sent the money back to Sardis, as though the Delphians were not worthy to receive that benefit, so they fabricated against him a charge of sacrilege, and put him to death by throwing him headlong down yonder rock called Hyampia. And in consequence the god is said to have been wroth with them, and to have brought dearth on their land, and all kinds of strange diseases, so that they went round at the public festivals of the Greeks, and invited by proclamation whoever wished to take satisfaction of them for Æsop's death. And three generations afterwards came Idmon838 a Samian, no relation of Æsop's, but a descendant of those who had purchased Æsop as a slave at Samos, and by giving him satisfaction the Delphians got rid of their trouble. And it was in consequence of this, they say, that the punishment of those guilty of sacrilege was transferred from Hyampia to Nauplia.839 And even great lovers of Alexander, as we are, do not praise his destroying the city of the Branchidæ and putting everybody in it to death because their great-grandfathers betrayed the 347temple at Miletus.840 And Agathocles, the tyrant of Syracuse, laughing and jeering at the Corcyræans for asking him why he wasted their island, replied, "Because, by Zeus, your forefathers welcomed Odysseus." And when the people of Ithaca likewise complained of his soldiers carrying off their sheep, he said, "Your king came to us, and actually put out the shepherd's eye to boot."841 And is it not stranger still in Apollo punishing the present inhabitants of Pheneus, by damming up the channel dug to carry off their water,842 and so flooding the whole of their district, because a thousand years ago, they say, Hercules carried off to Pheneus the oracular tripod? and in telling the Sybarites that the only end of their troubles would be propitiating by their ruin on three occasions the wrath of Leucadian Hera? And indeed it is no long time since the Locrians have ceased sending maidens843 to Troy,

§ xii. "But think about whether I’ve been talking for too long." Then Timon replied, "Maybe you have, given what’s left to discuss and how much time it will take. I’m about to tackle the last question, as if it were a contestant waiting in reserve since the other two have been discussed enough. Regarding the serious accusations Euripides makes against the gods for punishing children for their parents' sins, even those of us who stay silent agree with him. If the guilty were punished directly, there would be no need to punish the innocent. It’s unfair to punish the guilty twice for the same crime. However, if the gods, out of leniency, postpone punishing the wicked and then punish the innocent instead, they are failing to make up for their delays with justice. This behavior is similar to the story of Æsop coming to this spot,837 with money from Crœsus, intending to make a grand sacrifice to the god and give four minæ to each of the Delphians. When a dispute arose between him and the Delphians, he completed the sacrifice but sent the money back to Sardis, suggesting that the Delphians didn't deserve such a gift. Consequently, they accused him of sacrilege and killed him by throwing him off the rock known as Hyampia. As a result, the god is said to have punished them, bringing famine and various strange diseases upon their land, prompting them to announce at public festivals that anyone wishing to avenge Æsop's death could come forward. Three generations later, Idmon838 a Samian, unrelated to Æsop but descended from those who had bought Æsop as a slave on Samos, managed to appease the Delphians and relieve them of their troubles. Because of this, they say, the punishment for sacrilege was moved from Hyampia to Nauplia.839 Even those of us who admire Alexander do not condone his destruction of the city of the Branchidæ and the slaughter of its people because their ancestors betrayed the temple in Miletus.840 Likewise, Agathocles, the tyrant of Syracuse, mocked the Corcyræans for asking him why he devastated their island, saying, "Because, by Zeus, your ancestors welcomed Odysseus." And when the people of Ithaca complained about his soldiers stealing their sheep, he replied, "Your king came to us and even blinded the shepherd." 841 Isn’t it even more bizarre that Apollo punishes the current residents of Pheneus by blocking the channel they dug to drain their water,842 flooding their entire area just because, they say, Hercules carried off the oracle's tripod to Pheneus a thousand years ago? Is it any stranger than telling the Sybarites that their troubles will only end if they appease the anger of Leucadian Hera through their ruin three times? Indeed, it wasn’t long ago that the Locrians stopped sending maidens843 to Troy,

"Who is without a shirt and barefoot," Like slave girls, in the early morning, swept Around Athene's altar all bare, Until old age came upon them with its burdens,

all because Ajax violated Cassandra. Where is the reason or justice in all this? Nor do we praise the Thracians who to this day, in honour of Orpheus, mark their wives;844 nor the barbarians on the banks of the Eridanus who, they say, wear mourning for Phäethon. And I think it would be still more ridiculous if the people living at the time Phäethon perished had neglected him, and those who lived five or ten generations after his tragic death had begun the practice of wearing mourning and grieving for him. And yet this would be only folly, there would be nothing dreadful or fatal about it, but what should make the anger of the gods subside at once and then afterwards, like some rivers, burst out against others till they completely ruin them?

all because Ajax violated Cassandra. Where's the reason or fairness in all this? We don't praise the Thracians who, to this day, honor Orpheus by marking their wives;844 nor do we commend the barbarians living along the banks of the Eridanus who supposedly mourn for Phäethon. I think it would be even more absurd if the people who lived when Phäethon died had ignored him, and those who came five or ten generations later started the practice of mourning and grieving for him. While that would be foolish, it wouldn't be anything horrifying or serious. So why do the gods' anger calm down for a moment, only to then surge against others until they’re completely destroyed?

348§ xiii. Directly he left off, fearing that if he began again he would introduce more and greater absurdities, I asked him, "Well, do you believe all this to be true?" And he replied, "If not all, but only some, of it is true, do you not think that the subject presents the same difficulty?" "Perhaps," said I, "it is as with those in a raging fever, whether they have few or many clothes on the bed they are equally hot or nearly so, yet to ease them we shall do well to remove some of the clothes; but let us waive this point, if you don't like the line of argument, though a good deal of what you have said seems myth and fable, and let us recall to our minds the recent festival in honour of Apollo called Theoxenia,845 and the noble share in it which the heralds expressly reserve for the descendants of Pindar, and how grand and pleasant it seemed to you." "Who could help being pleased," said he, "with such a delightful honour, so Greek and breathing the simple spirit of antiquity, had he not, to use Pindar's own phrase, 'a black heart forged when the flame was cold?'" "I pass over then," said I, "the similar proclamation at Sparta, 'After the Lesbian singer,' in honour and memory of old Terpander, for it is a similar case. But you yourselves certainly lay claim to be better than other Bœotians as descended from Opheltes,846 and than other Phocians because of your ancestor Daiphantus,847 and you were the first to give me help and assistance in preserving for the Lycormæ and Satilæi their hereditary privilege of wearing crowns as descendants of Hercules, when I contended that we ought to confirm the honours and favours of the descendants of Hercules more especially because, though he was such a benefactor to the Greeks, he had had himself no adequate favour or return." "You remind me," he said, "of a noble effort, and one well worthy of a philosopher." "Dismiss then," said I, "my dear fellow, your vehement accusation against the gods, and do not be so vexed that some of a bad or evil stock are punished by them, or else do not joy in and approve of the honour paid to descent 349from a good stock. For it is unreasonable, if we continue to show favour to a virtuous stock, to think punishment wrong in the case of a criminal stock, or that it should not correspond with the adequate reward of merit. And he that is glad to see the descendants of Cimon honoured at Athens, but is displeased and indignant that the descendants of Lachares or Aristo are in exile, is too soft and easy, or rather too fault-finding and peevish with the gods, accusing them if the descendants of a bad and wicked man are fortunate, and accusing them also if the progeny of the bad are wiped off the face of the earth; thus finding fault with the deity alike, whether the descendants of the good or bad father are unfortunate."

348§ xiii. As soon as he stopped talking, worried that if he continued he would only create more ridiculousness, I asked him, "So, do you believe any of this is true?" He answered, "If not everything, but just some of it is true, doesn’t that create the same problem?" "Maybe," I replied, "it's like those with a high fever; whether there are few or many blankets on the bed, they're still hot or almost equally so. But to help them, we should at least remove some blankets. Let’s set aside that point if you find the argument unappealing, though much of what you've said sounds like myth and fable, and let’s think about the recent festival honoring Apollo called Theoxenia,845 and the distinguished role that the heralds specifically reserve for the descendants of Pindar, and how great and delightful it seemed to you." "Who wouldn't be pleased," he said, "with such an amazing honor, so distinctly Greek and embodying the pure essence of antiquity, unless he had, to borrow Pindar’s words, 'a black heart forged when the flame was cold?'" "Let's skip," I suggested, "the similar announcement made in Sparta, 'After the Lesbian singer,' honoring and remembering old Terpander, since it’s a similar case. But you certainly claim to be better than other Bœotians because you descend from Opheltes,846 and better than other Phocians thanks to your ancestor Daiphantus,847 and you were the first to help me ensure that the Lycormæ and Satilæi could keep their hereditary right to wear crowns as descendents of Hercules, given that I argued that we should particularly confirm the honors and favors of Hercules's descendants, especially since he was such a benefactor to the Greeks but received no adequate recognition in return." "You remind me," he said, "of a noble endeavor, truly worthy of a philosopher." "So, then," I said, "please let go of your harsh criticism against the gods, and don’t be so upset that some from a bad lineage are punished by them, or else don’t revel in and support the honors given to those from a good lineage. Because it’s unreasonable, if we still show favor to a virtuous lineage, to think a punishment is unjust for a criminal lineage, or that it shouldn’t match the appropriate reward for merit. And anyone who is glad to see the descendants of Cimon honored in Athens but is angry and upset that the descendants of Lachares or Aristo are in exile is being too soft or rather too critical and cranky with the gods, blaming them whether the descendants of a bad person are lucky or whether the descendants of the bad are wiped off the face of the earth; thus, finding fault with the deity regardless of whether the descendants of a good or bad father are unfortunate." 349

§ xiv. "Let these remarks," I continued, "be your bulwarks as it were against those excessively bitter and railing accusations. And taking up again as it were the initial clue to our subject, which as it is about the deity is dark and full of mazes and labyrinths, let us warily and calmly follow the track to what is probable and plausible, for certainty and truth are things very difficult to find even in every-day life. For example, why are the children of those that have died of consumption or dropsy bidden to sit with their feet in water till the dead body is burnt? For that is thought to prevent the disease transferring itself to them. Again, when a she-goat takes a bit of eringo into her mouth, why do the whole herd stand still, till the goatherd comes up and takes it out of her mouth? There are other properties that have connection and communication, and that transfer themselves from one thing to another with incredible848 quickness and over immense distances. But we marvel more at intervals of time than place. And yet is it more wonderful that Athens should have been smitten with a plague849 that started in Arabia, and of which Pericles died and Thucydides fell sick, than that, when the Delphians and Sybarites became wicked, vengeance should have fallen on their descendants.850 For properties have relations and connections between ends and 350beginnings, and although the reason of them may not be known by us, they silently perform their errand."

§ xiv. "Let these comments," I continued, "serve as your defenses against those harsh and bitter accusations. And picking up again on the initial thread of our discussion, which is about the deity and is complex and full of twists and turns, let us cautiously and calmly explore what seems likely and reasonable, because certainty and truth are really hard to find even in everyday life. For instance, why are the children of those who have died of consumption or dropsy told to keep their feet in water until the body is cremated? It's believed that this prevents them from catching the disease. Similarly, when a female goat puts a bit of eringo in her mouth, why does the entire herd remain still until the goatherd comes to take it out? There are other properties that have links and connections, transferring from one thing to another with astonishing speed and over great distances. Yet, we are more astonished by time intervals than by distance. And isn’t it more astonishing that Athens was struck by a plague that originated in Arabia, which led to Pericles' death and Thucydides' illness, than the idea that when the Delphians and Sybarites became wicked, retribution fell upon their descendants? For properties have relationships and connections between their beginnings and ends, and while we may not understand the reasons behind them, they fulfill their purpose quietly."

§ xv. "Moreover the public punishments of cities by the gods admits of a just defence. For a city is one continuous entity, a sort of creature that never changes from age, or becomes different by time, but is ever sympathetic with and conformable to itself, and is answerable for whatever it does or has done for the public weal, as long as the community by its union and federal bonds preserves its unity. For he that would make several, or rather any quantity of, cities out of one by process of time would be like a person who made one human being several, by regarding him now as an old man, now as a young man, now as a stripling. Or rather this kind of reasoning resembles the arguments of Epicharmus, from whom the sophists borrowed the piled-up method of reasoning,851 for example, he incurred the debt long ago, so he does not owe it now, being a different person, or, he was invited to dinner yesterday, but he comes uninvited to-day, for he is another person. And yet age produces greater changes in any individual than it does commonly in cities. For any one would recognize Athens again if he had not seen it for thirty years, for the present habits and feelings of the people there, their business, amusements, likes and dislikes, are just what they were long ago; whereas a man's friend or acquaintance meeting him after some time would hardly recognize his appearance, for the change of character easily introduced by every thought and deed, feeling and custom, produce a wonderful strangeness and novelty in the same person. And yet a man is reckoned to be the same person from birth to death, and similarly we think it right for a city always remaining the same to be liable to reproach for the ill deeds of its former inhabitants, on the same principle as it enjoys its ancient glory and power; or shall we, without being aware of it, throw everything into Heraclitus' river, into which he says a person cannot step twice,852 since nature is ever changing and altering everything?"

§ xv. "Furthermore, the public punishments imposed on cities by the gods can be justified. A city is a single, continuous entity, like a creature that doesn’t change with age or differ over time; it remains consistent and responsible for its actions for the common good, as long as the community maintains its unity through shared bonds. Anyone who attempts to divide a city into separate parts over time is like someone trying to split a single person into several by viewing them at different ages—sometimes as an old person, sometimes as a young one, and sometimes as a teenager. This kind of reasoning is similar to the arguments made by Epicharmus, from which the sophists took their convoluted rationale851—for instance, he incurred a debt long ago, so he doesn’t owe it now because he’s a different person, or he was invited to dinner yesterday but comes uninvited today, as he is a different person. Yet, aging transforms individuals more profoundly than it typically transforms cities. Anyone would recognize Athens even after not seeing it for thirty years, as its current customs, experiences, interests, and dislikes remain unchanged; on the other hand, a person’s friend or acquaintance would likely struggle to recognize them after some time due to the profound changes in character introduced by various thoughts, actions, emotions, and habits, which can create a striking unfamiliarity in the same individual. Still, a person is considered the same from birth to death, and similarly, it seems reasonable to hold a city accountable for the wrongdoings of its past inhabitants, just as it takes pride in its ancient glory and power. Or should we unknowingly let everything flow into Heraclitus’ river, which he claimed one cannot step into twice,852 since nature is always changing and transforming everything?"

351§ xvi. "If then a city is one continuous entity, so of course is a race that starts from one beginning, that can trace back intimate union and similarity of faculties, for that which is begot is not, like some production of art, unlike the begetter, for it proceeds from him, and is not merely produced by him, so that it appropriately receives his share, whether that be honour or punishment. And if I should not seem to be trifling, I should say that the bronze statue of Cassander melted down by the Athenians, and the body of Dionysius thrown out of their territory by the Syracusans after his death, were treated more unjustly than punishing their posterity would have been. For there was none of the nature of Cassander in the statue, and the soul of Dionysius had left his dead body before this outrage, whereas Nysæus and Apollocrates,853 Antipater and Philip,854 and similarly other sons of wicked parents had innate in them a good deal of their fathers, and that no listless or inactive element, but one by which they lived and were nourished, and by which their ideas were controlled. Nor is it at all strange or absurd that some should have their fathers' characteristics. And to speak generally, as in surgery whatever is useful is also just, and that person would be ridiculous who should say it was unjust to cauterize the thumb when the hip-joints were in pain, and to lance the stomach when the liver was inflamed, or when oxen were tender in their hoofs to anoint the tips of their horns, so he that looks for any other justice in punishment than curing vice, and is dissatisfied if surgery is employed to one part to benefit another, as surgeons open a vein to relieve ophthalmia, can see nothing beyond the evidence of the senses, and does not remember that even a schoolmaster by correcting one lad admonishes others, and that by decimation a general makes his whole army obey. And so not only by one part to another comes benefit, but also to the soul through the soul, even more often than to the body through the body, come certain dispositions, and vices or improvement of character. For just as it is likely in the case of the body that the same feelings and changes will take place, so the soul, being worked upon by fancies, naturally 352becomes better or worse according as it has more confidence or fear."

351§ xvi. "If a city is a single, unified entity, then a race that comes from a common origin is also a unified whole, sharing deep connections and similar traits. What is created is not like an artwork that differs from its creator; it truly stems from the creator and rightfully inherits their share, whether that’s praise or blame. To avoid being trivial, I’d say that the melting down of the bronze statue of Cassander by the Athenians and the expulsion of Dionysius' body by the Syracusans after his death were unjust actions, more so than punishing their descendants would have been. The statue held none of Cassander's essence, and Dionysius' soul had departed before this insult occurred. In contrast, Nysæus and Apollocrates,853 Antipater and Philip,854 as well as other children of immoral parents, inherently carry a significant part of their fathers within them. This isn't a passive or inactive inheritance; it’s something that sustains them and shapes their thoughts. It's neither surprising nor unreasonable for some to inherit traits from their fathers. Generally speaking, just as in surgery, where what’s beneficial is also just, it would be absurd for someone to argue that it’s unjust to cauterize a thumb when the hip is hurting or to lance the stomach when the liver is inflamed, or to treat hooves on cattle by applying salve to their horns. Similarly, anyone who seeks a different kind of justice in punishment than correcting a wrong, and who is displeased when a specific treatment benefits another part, like a surgeon opening a vein to cure eye issues, sees only what their senses show them. They forget that even a teacher, by correcting one student, instructs others, and that a general can enforce discipline on his whole army through decimation. Benefits can flow not just from one part to another, but also to the soul through the soul, often more so than to the body through the body, impacting dispositions, vices, or character improvement. Just as it’s likely that the body experiences similar feelings and changes, the soul can also be influenced by thoughts, becoming better or worse based on levels of confidence or fear."

§ xvii. While I was thus speaking, Olympicus interposed, and said, "You seem in your argument to assume the important assumption of the permanence of the soul." I replied, "You too concede it, or rather did concede it. For that the deity deals with everyone according to his merit has been the assumption of our argument from the beginning." Then said he, "Do you think that it follows, because the gods notice our actions and deal with us accordingly, that souls are either altogether imperishable, or for some time survive dissolution?" Then said I, "Not exactly so, my good sir, but is the deity so little and so attached to trifles, if we have nothing divine in ourselves, nothing resembling him, nothing lasting or sure, but that we all do fade as a leaf, as Homer855 says, and die after a brief life, as to take the trouble—like women that tend and cultivate their gardens of Adonis856 in pots—to create souls to flourish in a delicate body having no stability only for a day, and then to be annihilated at once857 by any occasion? And if you please, leaving the other gods out of the question, consider the case of our god here.858 Does it seem likely to you that, if he knew that the souls of the dead perish immediately, and glide out of their bodies like mist or smoke, he would enjoin many propitiatory offerings for the departed and honours for the dead, merely cheating and beguiling those that believed in him? For my own part, I shall never abandon my belief in the permanence of the soul, unless some second Hercules859 shall come and take away the tripod of the Pythian Priestess, and abolish and destroy the oracle. For as long as many such oracles are still given, as was said to be given to Corax of Naxos formerly, it is impious to declare that the soul dies." Then said Patrocleas, "What oracle do you refer to? Who was this Corax? To me both the occurrence and name are quite strange." "That cannot be," said 353I, "but I am to blame for using the surname instead of the name. For he that killed Archilochus in battle was called Calondes, it seems, but his surname was Corax. He was first rejected by the Pythian Priestess, as having slain a man sacred to the Muses, but after using many entreaties and prayers, and urging pleas in defence of his act, he was ordered to go to the dwelling of Tettix, and appease the soul of Archilochus. Now this place was Tænarum, for there they say Tettix the Cretan had gone with a fleet and founded a city, and dwelt near the place where departed souls were conjured up. Similarly also, when the Spartans were bidden by the oracle to appease the soul of Pausanias, the necromancers were summoned from Italy, and, after they had offered sacrifice, they got the ghost out of the temple."

§ xvii. While I was speaking, Olympicus jumped in and said, "Your argument seems to assume that the soul is permanent." I replied, "You also agree with this, or at least you did. The idea that the divine treats everyone based on their worth has been part of our argument from the start." Then he asked, "Do you think it follows that because the gods notice our actions and respond accordingly, the souls are either completely imperishable or survive for a time after death?" I responded, "Not exactly, my good sir. But do you really believe that the deity is so trivial and fixated on minor details that if we have nothing divine within us, nothing that resembles him, nothing enduring or certain, and we all just fade like a leaf, as Homer855 says, dying after a short life, would he go through the trouble—like women tending their gardens of Adonis856 in pots—to create souls that only flourish in a fragile body for one day before being instantly wiped out857 by any chance event? And if you would, let's set aside the other gods for a moment and consider our own god here.858 Do you really believe that if he knew the souls of the dead vanish immediately and slip out of their bodies like mist or smoke, he would require numerous offerings for the departed and honors for the dead, merely deceiving those who believe in him? Personally, I will never give up my belief in the soul's permanence unless a second Hercules859 comes along and takes away the tripod of the Pythian Priestess, abolishing and destroying the oracle. As long as oracles like the one given to Corax of Naxos are still being delivered, it is wrong to claim that the soul dies." Then Patrocleas said, "What oracle are you talking about? Who was Corax? Both the event and the name are completely unfamiliar to me." "That can't be," I said, "but I'm to blame for using the surname instead of the name. The one who killed Archilochus in battle was named Calondes, but his surname was Corax. He was initially rejected by the Pythian Priestess for killing a man sacred to the Muses, but after much pleading and presenting a defense for his actions, he was told to go to the dwelling of Tettix and appease the soul of Archilochus. This place was Tænarum, since it is said that Tettix the Cretan went there with a fleet, founded a city, and lived near where departed souls were summoned. Also, when the Spartans were ordered by the oracle to appease the soul of Pausanias, they brought in necromancers from Italy and, after they made sacrifices, they managed to bring the ghost out of the temple."

§ xviii. "It is one and the same argument," I continued, "that confirms the providence of the deity and the permanence of the soul of man, so that you cannot leave one if you take away the other. And if the soul survives after death, it makes the probability stronger that rewards or punishments will be assigned to it. For during life the soul struggles, like an athlete, and when the struggle is over, then it gets its deserts. But what rewards or punishments the soul gets when by itself in the unseen world for the deeds done in the body has nothing to do with us that are alive, and is perhaps not credited by us, and certainly unknown to us; whereas those punishments that come on descendants and on the race are evident to all that are alive, and deter and keep back many from wickedness. For there is no more disgraceful or bitter punishment than to see our children in misfortune through our faults, and if the soul of an impious or lawless man could see after death, not his statues or honours taken from him, but his children or friends or race in great adversity owing to him, and paying the penalty for his misdeeds, no one would ever persuade him, could he come to life again, to be unjust and licentious, even for the honours of Zeus. I could tell you a story on this head, which I recently heard, but I hesitate to do so, lest you should regard it only as a myth; I confine myself therefore to probability." "Pray don't," said Olympicus, "let us have your story." And as the others made354 the same request, I said, "Permit me first to finish my discourse according to probability, and then, if you like, I will set my myth a going, if it is a myth.

§ xviii. "It's the same argument," I continued, "that supports the idea of a higher power and the existence of the human soul, meaning you can't have one without the other. If the soul lives on after death, it strengthens the idea that it will receive rewards or punishments. During our lives, the soul struggles like an athlete, and once the struggle is over, it gets what it deserves. However, what happens to the soul in the afterlife for the actions taken in the body is irrelevant to us who are alive, and it's likely unknown to us. On the other hand, the punishments that affect future generations are clear to everyone and often discourage many from doing wrong. There’s nothing more disgraceful or painful than seeing our children suffer because of our mistakes. If the soul of a wicked or lawless person could see after death—not the statues or honors taken away from them, but their children or loved ones in great distress because of their actions—then no one could convince them, if they could come back to life, to act unjustly, even for the honors of Zeus. I have a story related to this that I recently heard, but I'm hesitant to share it in case you think it's just a myth; so I'll stick to what’s plausible first." "Please do share," said Olympicus, "we want to hear your story." And as others echoed the same request, I replied, "Let me first finish my argument based on what’s likely, and then, if you want, I’ll share my story, whether it’s a myth or not."

§ xix. Bion says the deity in punishing the children of the wicked for their fathers' crimes is more ridiculous than a doctor administering a potion to a son or grandson for a father's or grandfather's disease. But the cases, though in some respects similar and like, are in others dissimilar. For to cure one person of a disease does not cure another, nor is one any better, when suffering from ophthalmia or fever, by seeing another anointed or poulticed. But the punishments of evil-doers are exhibited to everybody for this reason, that it is the function of justice, when it is carried out as reason dictates, to check some by the punishment of others. So that Bion did not see in what respect his comparison touched our subject. For sometimes, when a man falls into a grievous but not incurable malady, which afterwards by intemperance and negligence ruins his constitution and kills him, is not his son, who is not supposed to be suffering from the same malady but only to have a predisposition for it, enjoined to a careful manner of living by his medical man, or friend, or intelligent trainer in gymnastics, or honest guardian, and recommended to abstain from fish and pastry, wine and women, and to take medicine frequently, and to go in for training in the gymnasiums, and so to dissipate and get rid of the small seeds of what might be a serious malady, if he allowed it to come to a head? Do we not indeed give advice of this kind to the children of diseased fathers or mothers, bidding them take care and be cautious and not to neglect themselves, but at once to arrest the first germ, of the malady, nipping it in the bud while removable, and before it has got a firm footing in the constitution?" "Certainly we do," said all the company. "We are not then," I continued, "acting in a strange or ridiculous but in a necessary and useful way, in arranging their exercise and food and physic for the sons of epileptic or atrabilious or gouty people, not when they are ill, but to prevent their becoming so. For the offspring of a poor constitution does not require punishment, but it does require medical treatment and care, and if any one stigmatizes this, because it curtails pleasure and involves some self-denial355 and pain, as a punishment inflicted by cowardice and timidity, we care not for his opinion. Can it be right to tend and care for the body that has an hereditary predisposition to some malady, and are we to neglect the growth and spread in the young character of hereditary taint of vice, and to dally with it, and wait till it be plainly mixed up with the feelings, and, to use the language of Pindar, "produce malignant fruit in the heart?"

§ xix. Bion claims that it's more absurd for a deity to punish the children of the wicked for their parents' wrongdoings than for a doctor to give a remedy to a son or grandson suffering from a father's or grandfather's illness. However, while there are some similarities between the two situations, they are also quite different. Treating one person for an illness doesn’t cure another, nor does one feel any better about having an eye infection or a fever just because they see someone else receiving treatment. The punishments for wrongdoers are made public for a reason: it's the role of justice, when applied rationally, to deter some by punishing others. Thus, Bion missed the point of his analogy in relation to our topic. For sometimes, when a person develops a severe but treatable illness that later worsens due to carelessness and negligence, leading to their death, isn’t it the case that their son, who isn’t necessarily suffering from the same illness but might be at risk, is advised by a doctor, friend, fitness trainer, or responsible guardian to live carefully? They are often told to avoid certain foods and vices, take medication regularly, and engage in physical training to eliminate the potential sources of a serious illness before it can fully develop. Don’t we give this kind of advice to the children of parents with diseases, urging them to be cautious and not to neglect themselves, to tackle the early signs of illness while they can still be managed? "Certainly, we do," everyone in the room agreed. "Therefore," I continued, "we're not acting in a strange or ridiculous manner, but rather in a necessary and helpful way by organizing exercise, diet, and medical care for the children of those who suffer from epilepsy, melancholy, or gout, not simply when they are sick but to prevent them from becoming ill. Children from poorly constituted lineages need care, not punishment. If someone criticizes this because it limits pleasure and requires some discipline and discomfort, viewing it as a punishment born from fear, we're indifferent to their opinion. Is it right to nurture a body that has a hereditary vulnerability to disease, yet to ignore the development and spread of inherited vices in young character, instead allowing it to grow until it becomes deeply rooted and, as Pindar puts it, "bears poisonous fruit in the heart?"

§ xx. Or is the deity in this respect no wiser than Hesiod, who exhorts and advises, "not to beget children on our return from a sad funeral, but after a banquet with the gods,"860 as though not vice or virtue only, but sorrow or joy and all other propensities, came from generation, to which the poet bids us come gay and agreeable and sprightly. But it is not Hesiod's function, or the work of human wisdom, but it belongs to the deity, to discern and accurately distinguish similarities and differences of character, before they become obvious by resulting in crime through the influence of the passions. For the young of bears and wolves and apes manifest from their birth the nature innate in them in all its naked simplicity; whereas mankind, under the influence of customs and opinions and laws, frequently conceal their bad qualities and imitate what is good, so as altogether to obliterate and escape from the innate taint of vice, or to be undetected for a long time, throwing the veil of craft round their real nature, so that we are scarce conscious of their villainy till we feel the blow or smart of some unjust action, so that we are in fact only aware that there is such a thing as injustice when men act unjustly, or as vice when men act viciously, or as cowardice when men run away, just as if one were to suppose that scorpions had a sting only when they stung us, or that vipers were venomous only when they bit us, which would be a very silly idea. For every bad man is not bad only when he breaks out into crime, but he has the seeds of vice in his nature, and is only vicious in act when he has opportunity and means, as opportunity makes the thief steal,861 and the tyrant violate the laws. But the deity is 356not ignorant of the nature and disposition of every man, inasmuch as by his very nature he can read the soul better than the body, and does not wait to punish violence in the act, or shamelessness in the tongue, or lasciviousness in the members. For he does not retaliate upon the wrong-doer as having been ill-treated by him, nor is he angry with the robber as having been plundered by him, nor does he hate the adulterer as having himself suffered from his licentiousness, but it is to cure him that he often punishes the adulterous or avaricious or unjust man in embryo, before he has had time to work out all his villainy, as we try to stop epileptic fits before they come on.

§ xx. Or is the deity in this case no wiser than Hesiod, who advises us not to have children right after a sad funeral, but instead after a feast with the gods, as if not only vice and virtue, but also sorrow and joy, and all other tendencies, come from birth, to which the poet encourages us to approach cheerfully and playfully. However, it's not Hesiod's job, nor is it the work of human wisdom; it’s the deity's role to recognize and accurately differentiate character traits before they become evident through actions driven by emotions. Young bears, wolves, and apes show their inherent nature from birth in all its raw simplicity; on the other hand, humans often hide their flaws under the influence of culture, opinions, and laws, pretending to be good to erase the stain of their inherent vices or to evade detection for a long time, masking their true self so effectively that we barely recognize their wickedness until we experience the pain of some unjust act. We only realize that injustice exists when people act unjustly, or that vice exists when people commit wrongs, or that cowardice exists when people flee, much like thinking scorpions are only dangerous when they sting us, or that vipers are venomous only when they bite, which would be quite foolish. Every bad person isn’t just bad when they commit a crime; the seeds of vice are already within them, and they only act on their bad nature when they have the opportunity, just as opportunity makes a thief steal, and a tyrant break the law. But the deity is 356not unaware of each person’s nature and disposition, as He can read souls more accurately than bodies and does not wait to punish violence when it happens or shamelessness in speech, or lewdness in actions. He doesn’t retaliate against the wrongdoer for being wronged, nor does He get angry at the thief for being robbed, nor does He hate the adulterer for being harmed by their behavior; rather, He often punishes the budding adulterer, greedy person, or unjust individual before they can fully manifest their wickedness, just as we try to prevent epileptic seizures before they occur.

§ xxi. Just now we were dissatisfied that the wicked were punished late and tardily, whereas at present we find fault with the deity for correcting the character and disposition of same before they commit crime, from our ignoring that the future deed may be worse and more dreadful than the past, and the hidden intention than the overt act; for we are not able fully to understand the reasons why it is better to leave some alone in their ill deeds, and to arrest others in the intention; just as no doubt medicine is not appropriate in the case of some patients, which would be beneficial to others not ill, but yet perhaps in a more dangerous condition still. And so the gods do not visit all the offences of parents on their children, but if a good man is the son of a bad one, as the son of a sickly parent is sometimes of a good constitution, he is exempt from the punishment of his race, as not being a participator in its viciousness. But if a young man imitates his vicious race it is only right that he should inherit the punishment of their ill deeds, as he would their debts. For Antigonus was not punished for Demetrius, nor, of the old heroes,862 Phyleus for Augeas, or Nestor for Neleus, for though their sires were bad they were good, but those whose nature liked and approved the vices of their ancestors, these justice punished, taking vengeance on their similarity in viciousness. For as the warts and moles and freckles of parents often skip a generation, and reappear in the grandsons and granddaughters, and as a Greek woman, 357that had a black baby and so was accused of adultery, found out that she was the great granddaughter of an Ethiopian,863 and as the son of Pytho the Nisibian who recently died, and who was said to trace his descent to the Sparti,864 had the birthmark on his body of the print of a spear the token of his race, which though long dormant had come up again as out of the deep, so frequently earlier generations conceal and suppress the mental idiosyncrasies and passions of their race, which afterwards nature causes to break out in other members of the family, and so displays the family bent either to vice or virtue."

§ xxi. Right now, we’re unhappy that the wicked are punished slowly and too late, yet at the same time, we criticize the deity for trying to change the character and mindset of these individuals before they commit any crimes. This shows our ignorance that future actions could be worse and more terrible than past ones, and that what’s hidden in one’s intentions can be more significant than what’s openly done. We can’t fully grasp why it’s better to let some people keep doing their wrongs while stopping others in their tracks. It’s similar to how certain medications work for some patients but are unsuitable for others, perhaps those who are in even more serious situations. Thus, the gods don’t punish all of a parent’s wrongdoing on their children. If a good person happens to be the child of a bad one—just as a healthy child can be born to a sickly parent—they may escape the punishment associated with their lineage, as they don’t share in its wickedness. However, if a young man imitates his corrupt family, it’s fair for him to inherit the consequences of their wrongdoings, just as he would their debts. For example, Antigonus wasn’t punished for Demetrius, nor were the old heroes, 862 Phyleus for Augeas, or Nestor for Neleus; even though their fathers were bad, they were good. But those who embrace and approve of their ancestors' vices deserve to face justice for their shared corruption. It’s like how warts, moles, and freckles from parents can skip a generation and later reappear in grandchildren. Take the Greek woman who had a black baby and was accused of adultery, only to discover she was a great-granddaughter of an Ethiopian. 863 Also, there was the son of Pytho the Nisibian, who just died and claimed descent from the Sparti; he bore a birthmark resembling a spear—a sign of his lineage—which had lain dormant but resurfaced, similar to how earlier generations hide and suppress their family’s mental traits and passions, only for nature to eventually reveal them through different family members, showcasing either a tendency toward vice or virtue.

§ xxii. When I had said thus much I was silent, but Olympicus smiled and said, "We do not praise you, lest we should seem to forget your promised story, as though what you had advanced was adequate proof enough, but we will give our opinion when we have heard it." Then I began as follows. "Thespesius of Soli, an intimate friend of that Protogenes865 who lived in this city with us for some time, had been very profligate during the early part of his life, and had quickly run through his property, and for some time owing to his straits had given himself up to bad practices, when repenting of his old ways, and following the pursuit of riches, he resembled those profligate husbands that pay no attention to their wives while they live with them, but get rid of them, and then, after they have married other men, do all they can wickedly to seduce them. Abstaining then from nothing dishonourable that could bring either enjoyment or gain, in no long time he got together no great amount of property, but a very great reputation for villainy. But what most damaged his character was the answer he received from the oracle of Amphilochus.866 For he sent it seems a messenger to consult the god whether he would live the rest of his life better, and the answer was he would do better after his death. And indeed this happened in a sense not long after. For he fell headlong down from a great height, and though he had received no wound 358nor even a blow, the fall did for him, but three days after (just as he was about to be buried) he recovered. He soon picked up his strength again, and went home, and so changed his manner of life that people would hardly credit it. For the Cilicians say that they know nobody who was in those days more fairdealing in business, or more devout to the deity, or more disagreeable to his enemies, or more faithful to his friends; insomuch that all who had any dealings with him desired to hear the reason of this change, not thinking that so great a reformation of character could have proceeded from chance, and their idea was correct, as his narrative to Protogenes and others of his great friends showed. For he told them that, when his soul left the body, the change he first underwent was as if he were a pilot thrown violently into the sea out of a ship. Then raising himself up a little, he thought he recovered the power of breathing again altogether, and looked round him in every direction, as if one eye of the soul was open. But he saw none of the things he had ever seen before, but stars enormous in size and at immense distance from one another, sending forth a wonderful and intense brightness of colour, so that the soul was borne along and moved about everywhere quickly and easily, like a ship is fair weather. But omitting most of the sights he saw, he said that the souls of the dead mounted into the air, which yielded to them and formed fiery bubbles, and then, when each bubble quietly broke, they assumed human forms, light in weight but with different kinds of motion, for some leapt about with wonderful agility and darted straight upwards, while others like spindles flitted round all together in a circle, some in an upward direction, some in a downward, with mixed and confused motion, hardly stopping at all, or only after a very long time. As to most of these he was ignorant who they were, but he saw two or three that he knew, and tried to approach them and talk with them, but they would not listen to him, and did not seem to be in their right minds, but out of their senses and distraught, avoiding every sight and touch, and at first turned round and round alone, but afterwards meeting many other souls whirling round and in the same condition as themselves, they moved about promiscuously with no particular object in view, and uttered359 inarticulate sounds, like yells, mixed with wailing and terror. Other souls in the upper part of the air seemed joyful, and frequently approached one another in a friendly way, and avoided those troubled souls, and seemed to mark their displeasure by keeping themselves to themselves, and their joy and delight by extension and expansion. At last he said he saw the soul of a relation, that he thought he knew but was not quite sure, as he died when he was a boy, which came up to him and said to him, "Welcome, Thespesius." And he wondering, and saying that his name was not Thespesius but Aridæus, the soul replied, "That was your old name, but henceforth it will be Thespesius. For assuredly you are not dead, but by the will of the gods are come here with your intellect, for the rest of your soul you have left in the body like an anchor; and as a proof of what I say both now and hereafter notice that the souls of the dead have no shadow and do not move their eyelids." Thespesius, on hearing these words, pulled himself somewhat more together again, and began to use his reason, and looking more closely he noticed that an indistinct and shadow-like line was suspended over him, while the others shone all round and were transparent, but were not all alike; for some were like the full-moon at its brightest, throwing out one smooth even and continuous colour, others had spots or light marks here and there, while others were quite variegated and strange to the sight, with black spots like snakes, while others again had dim scratches.

§ xxii. After I finished speaking, I fell silent, but Olympicus smiled and said, "We won't praise you yet, so we don't seem to forget your promised story, as if what you said was enough proof. We'll share our thoughts after we hear it." Then I began, "Thespesius of Soli, a close friend of Protogenes, who lived here with us for some time, was quite reckless in his early life. He quickly squandered his wealth, and because of his struggles, he turned to bad habits. But after regretting his past ways and seeking wealth, he acted like those irresponsible husbands who ignore their wives while living with them, only to try to seduce them back after marrying someone else. He didn't avoid anything shameful for the sake of pleasure or gain, and before long, he didn't accumulate much wealth but gained a notorious reputation for villainy. However, what really damaged his character was the response he got from the oracle of Amphilochus. He sent a messenger to ask the god if he would live the rest of his life better, and the answer was that he would do better after his death. And this came true in a way shortly after. He fell from a great height, and although he suffered no wounds or even a bruise, the fall nearly killed him. But three days later, just as he was about to be buried, he recovered. He quickly regained his strength and returned home, changing his way of life so much that people could hardly believe it. The Cilicians say they knew no one more trustworthy in business, more devoted to the gods, more unpleasant to his enemies, or more loyal to his friends; so everyone who interacted with him wanted to know why he had changed so drastically, thinking no such transformation could happen by mere chance. Their suspicions were correct, as evidenced by his accounts to Protogenes and other close friends. He explained that when his soul left his body, the first change he experienced was similar to being thrown overboard from a ship into the sea. After a brief moment, he felt like he could breathe again and looked around, as if one part of his soul was awake. But he didn’t see anything familiar; instead, he saw gigantic stars spaced far apart, radiating an incredible and vivid light, allowing his soul to move swiftly and easily, like a ship in calm waters. Skipping over most of the sights he witnessed, he mentioned that the souls of the dead ascended into the air, which yielded under them and formed fiery bubbles. When each bubble popped quietly, the souls took on human forms, light yet with different types of movement; some jumped around with remarkable agility, shooting straight up, while others spiraled about in circles, some going up and some going down, moving in a mixed and chaotic manner, hardly stopping or only pausing for a very long time. He didn’t recognize most of them, but he did see a couple of familiar faces and tried to approach them to talk, but they ignored him. They seemed out of their minds, preoccupied and disoriented, initially spinning alone, but soon joining many other souls in the same state, moving aimlessly, making inarticulate sounds that mixed screams with cries of fear. Other souls floating higher in the air appeared joyful and often came together amicably, steering clear of the troubled souls, and demonstrated their displeasure by keeping to themselves while expressing their joy through expansion and connection. Eventually, he saw the soul of a relative who he thought he recognized but wasn’t sure about, as he had died when Thespesius was a boy. The soul approached him and said, "Welcome, Thespesius." He was surprised and insisted his name was Aridæus, but the soul responded, "That was your old name; from now on, it will be Thespesius. For you are not dead; by the will of the gods, you are here using your intellect while the rest of your soul remains anchored in your body. As proof of my words, notice that the souls of the dead lack shadows and don't blink." Upon hearing this, Thespesius gathered himself and began to think more clearly. Looking closer, he saw a vague, shadow-like line hanging over him, while others around him glowed brightly and were transparent, but not all were the same; some were like a full moon at its brightest, radiating a smooth, consistent color, others had flecks or light marks scattered, while some were quite varied and strange-looking, with black spots reminiscent of snakes, and others bore faint scratches.

Then the kinsman of Thespesius (for there is nothing to prevent our calling the souls by the name of the persons), pointed out everything, and told him that Adrastea, the daughter of Necessity and Zeus, was placed in the highest position to punish all crimes, and no criminal was either so great or so small as to be able to escape her either by fraud or violence. But, as there were three kinds of punishment, each had its own officer and administering functionary. "For speedy Vengeance undertakes the punishment of those that are to be corrected at once in the body and through their bodies, and she mildly passes by many offences that only need expiation; but if the cure of vice demands further pains, then the deity hands over such criminals after death to Justice, and those whom Justice360 rejects as altogether incurable, Erinnys (the third and fiercest of Adrastea's officers), pursues as they are fleeing and wandering about in various directions, and with pitiless severity utterly undoes them all, and thrusts them down to a place not to be seen or spoken about. And, of all these punishments, that which is administered in this life by Vengeance is most like those in use among the barbarians. For as among the Persians they pluck off and scourge the garments and tiaras of those that are to be punished, while the offenders weep and beg them to cease, so most punishments by fine or bodily chastisement have no sharp touch, nor do they reach vice itself, but are only for show and sentiment. And whoever goes from this world to that incorrigible and impure, Justice takes him aside, naked as he is in soul, and unable to veil or hide or conceal his villainy, but descried all round and in all points by everybody, and shows him first to his good parents, if such they were, to let them see what a wretch he is and how unworthy of his ancestors; but if they were wicked too, seeing them punished and himself being seen by them, he is chastised for a long time till he is purged of each of his bad propensities by sufferings and pains, which as much exceed in magnitude and intensity all sufferings in the flesh, as what is real is more vivid than a dream. But the scars and marks of the stripes for each bad propensity are more visible in some than in others. Observe also, he continued, the different and various colours of the souls. That dark dirty-brown colour is the pigment of illiberality and covetousness, and the blood-red the sign of cruelty and savageness, and where the blue is there sensuality and love of pleasure are not easily eradicated, and that violet and livid colour marks malice and envy, like the dark liquid ejected by the cuttle fish. For as during life vice produces these colours by the soul being acted upon by passions and reacting upon the body, so here it is the end of purification and correction when they are toned down, and the soul becomes altogether bright and one colour. But as long as these colours remain, there are relapses of the passions accompanied by palpitation and throbbing of the heart, in some faint and soon suppressed, in others more violent and lasting. And some of these souls by being again and again corrected361 recover their proper disposition and condition, while others again by their violent ignorance and excessive love of pleasure867 are carried into the bodies of animals; for one by weakness of reasoning power, and slowness of contemplation, is impelled by the practical element in him to generation, while another, lacking an instrument to satisfy his licentiousness, desires to gratify his passions immediately, and to get that gratification through the medium of the body; for here there is no real fruition, but only an imperfect shadow and dream of incomplete pleasure."

Then the relative of Thespesius (since there’s no harm in calling the souls by the names of the individuals), pointed out everything and mentioned that Adrastea, the daughter of Necessity and Zeus, was in the highest position to punish all crimes, and no criminal was so great or so small as to escape her by either deceit or force. However, there were three types of punishment, each with its own officer and function. "Quick Vengeance takes on the punishment of those who need immediate correction in their bodies, while she passes over many offenses that only require atonement; but if the correction of vice demands more effort, then after death the deity hands those criminals over to Justice. Those whom Justice rejects as completely hopeless are pursued by Erinnys (the third and most fierce of Adrastea's officers), who relentlessly chases them down as they flee and wander, and mercilessly destroys them all, casting them into a place that should neither be seen nor spoken of. Of all these punishments, the ones administered in this life by Vengeance are most similar to those used among barbarians. Just as in Persia they strip and whip the garments and tiaras of those being punished, while the offenders weep and plead for mercy, most punishments involving fines or physical punishment lack real impact; they do not address the vice itself but are merely for show and sentiment. Anyone who leaves this world unrepentant and impure, Justice takes aside, bare as he is in spirit, unable to hide or obscure his wrongdoing, made visible to everyone. He is first shown to his good parents, if they existed, to let them see what a miserable person he has become and how unworthy he is of his ancestors; but if they were wicked too, seeing them punished while he is seen by them, he suffers for a long time until he is cleansed of each bad impulse through agony and pain, which far exceed in intensity all physical suffering, as reality is more vivid than a dream. The scars and marks of punishment for each bad impulse are more apparent in some than in others. He went on to point out the different colors of souls. That dark, dirty-brown color represents stinginess and greed, the blood-red signifies cruelty and savagery, while the blue indicates that sensuality and love of pleasure are hard to eradicate; the violet and livid color denotes malice and envy, like the dark ink ejected by a cuttlefish. Just as in life, vice produces these colors by the soul being influenced by emotions and reacting with the body, so here, it marks the end of purification and correction when these colors are subdued, and the soul becomes completely bright and uniform. However, as long as these colors remain, there are relapses of passions accompanied by heart palpitations; in some cases, these are faint and easily subdued, while in others they are more intense and last longer. Some of these souls, through repeated correction, regain their proper state and condition, while others, through their extreme ignorance and excessive love of pleasure, are reborn into the bodies of animals; one, lacking reasoning strength and being slow to contemplate, is driven by his practical side toward procreation, while another, without a way to satisfy his desires, seeks immediate gratification through the physical form; for here, there is no true fulfillment, only an imperfect shadow and a dream of incomplete pleasure."

After he had said this, Thespesius' kinsman hurried him at great speed through immense space, as it seemed to him, though he travelled as easily and straight as if he were carried on the wings of the sun's rays. At last he got to an extensive and bottomless abyss, where his strength left him, as he found was the case with the other souls there: for keeping together and making swoops, like birds, they flitted all round the abyss, but did not venture to pass over it. To internal view it resembled the caverns of Bacchus, being beautiful throughout868 with trees and green foliage and flowers of all kinds, and it breathed a soft and gentle air, laden with scents marvellously pleasant, and producing the effect that wine does on those who are topers; for the souls were elevated by its fragrance, and gay and blithe with one another: and the whole spot was full of mirth and laughter, and such songs as emanate from gaiety and enjoyment. And Thespesius' kinsman told him that this was the way Dionysus went up to heaven by, and by which he afterwards took up Semele, and it was called the place of Oblivion. But he would not let Thespesius stay there, much as he wished, but forcibly dragged him away, instructing and telling him that the intellect was melted and moistened by pleasure, and that the irrational and corporeal element being watered and made flesh stirs up the memory of the body, from which comes a yearning and strong desire for generation, so called from being an inclination to the earth,869 when the soul is weighed down with moisture.

After he said this, Thespesius' relative rushed him through what felt like vast space, though he moved as smoothly and directly as if he were riding on sunbeams. Eventually, he reached a vast and bottomless abyss, where he felt his strength fade, just like the other souls around him: they swooped and glided like birds all around the abyss, but didn’t dare to cross it. To the eye, it looked like the caves of Bacchus, beautifully adorned with trees, lush greenery, and flowers of every kind, filled with a gentle, soft breeze that carried wonderfully pleasant scents, creating an effect similar to that of wine on heavy drinkers; the souls were uplifted by its fragrance, joyful and carefree with each other: the entire place was brimming with merriment, laughter, and songs that flowed from happiness and enjoyment. Thespesius' relative told him this was the path Dionysus took to reach heaven and where he later brought Semele, and it was called the place of Oblivion. But he wouldn’t let Thespesius stay there, no matter how much he wanted to, instead forcibly pulling him away, explaining that the mind becomes soft and weakened by pleasure, and that the physical and irrational aspects, when nourished and made fleshy, stir memories of the body, leading to a yearning and strong desire for reproduction, aptly called an inclination toward the earth, when the soul is weighed down with moisture.

362Next Thespesius travelled as far in another direction, and seemed to see a great crater into which several rivers emptied themselves, one whiter than the foam of the sea or snow, another like the purple of the rainbow, and others of various hues whose brightness was apparent at some distance, but when he got nearer the air became thinner and the colours grew dim, and the crater lost all its gay colours but white. And he saw three genii sitting together in a triangular position, mixing the rivers together in certain proportions. Then the guide of Thespesius' soul told him, that Orpheus got as far as here, when he came in quest of the soul of his wife,870 and from not exactly remembering what he had seen spread a false report among mankind, that the oracle at Delphi was common to Apollo and Night, though Apollo had no communion with Night: but this, pursued the guide, is an oracle common to Night and the Moon, that utters forth its oracular knowledge in no particular part of the world, nor has it any particular seat, but wanders about everywhere in men's dreams and visions. Hence, as you see, dreams receive and disseminate a mixture871 of simple truth with deceit and error. But the oracle of Apollo you do not know, nor can you see it, for the earthiness of the soul does not suffer it to soar upwards, but keeps it down in dependence on the body. And taking him nearer his guide tried to show him the light from the tripod, which, as he said, shone as far as Parnassus through the bosom of Themis, but though he desired to see it he could not for its brightness, but as he passed by he heard the shrill voice of a woman speaking in verse several things, among others, he thought, telling the time of his death. That, said the genius, was the voice of the Sibyl, who sang about the future as she was being borne about in the Orb of the moon. Though desirous then to hear more, he was conveyed into another direction by the violent motion of the moon, as if he had been in the eddies of a whirlpool, so that he heard very little more, only a prophecy about Mt. Vesuvius and that Dicæarchia872 would be destroyed by fire, and a short piece about the 363Emperor then reigning,873 that "though he was good he would lose his empire through sickness."

362Next, Thespesius traveled in another direction and came across a huge crater where several rivers flowed into it. One river was whiter than sea foam or snow, another resembled the purple of a rainbow, and others displayed various bright colors. From a distance, their brilliance was clear, but as he got closer, the air became thinner, and the colors faded, leaving only white in the crater. He saw three genies sitting together in a triangular arrangement, mixing the rivers in specific proportions. Then, the guide of Thespesius' soul told him that Orpheus had come this far while searching for his wife's soul,870 and due to not fully remembering what he had seen, he spread a false rumor that the oracle at Delphi belonged to both Apollo and Night, even though Apollo had no connection with Night. However, the guide continued, this oracle is shared by Night and the Moon, and it reveals its prophetic knowledge not in one specific location but wanders through people’s dreams and visions everywhere. Thus, as you see, dreams convey a mix871 of simple truth along with lies and errors. But you do not know the oracle of Apollo, nor can you see it, because the heaviness of the soul prevents it from rising, keeping it dependent on the body. As he got closer, his guide attempted to show him the light from the tripod, which, as he described, shone all the way to Parnassus through Themis’s embrace. But even though he wanted to see it, he couldn’t because of its brightness. As he passed by, he heard the piercing voice of a woman speaking verses about various things, and among them, he thought he heard her mention the time of his death. "That," said the genie, "was the voice of the Sibyl, who sang about the future while being carried in the Moon’s realm." Although he wanted to hear more, he was suddenly pulled in another direction by the moon’s fierce movement, like being caught in a whirlpool, so he heard very little else—only a prophecy about Mt. Vesuvius and that Dicæarchia872 would be consumed by fire, along with a brief mention of the 363Emperor at that time,873 that "even though he was good, he would lose his empire due to illness."

After this Thespesius and his guide turned to see those that were undergoing punishment. And at first they saw only distressing and pitiable sights, but after that, Thespesius, little expecting it, found himself among his friends and acquaintances and kinsfolk who were being punished, and undergoing dreadful sufferings and hideous and bitter tortures, and who wept and wailed to him. And at last he descried his father coming up out of a certain gulf covered with marks and scars, stretching out his hands, and not allowed to keep silence, but compelled by those that presided over his torture to confess that he had been an accursed wretch and poisoned some strangers that had gold, and during his lifetime had escaped the detection of everybody; but had been found out here, and his guilt brought home to him, for which he had already suffered much, and was being dragged on to suffer more. So great was his consternation and fear that he did not dare to intercede or beg for his father's release, but wishing to turn and flee he could no longer see his gentle and kind guide, but he was thrust forward by some persons horrible to look at, as if some dire necessity compelled him to go through with the business, and saw that the shades of those that had been notorious criminals and punished in their life-time were not so severely tortured here or like the others, but had an incomplete874 though toilsome punishment for their irrational passions.875 Whereas those who under the mask and show of virtue had lived all their lives in undetected vice were forced by their torturers with labour and pain to turn their souls inside out, unnaturally wriggling and writhing about, like the sea-scolopendras who, when they have swallowed the hook, turn themselves inside out; but some of them their torturers flayed and crimped so as to show their various inward vices which were only skinned over, which were deep in their soul the 364principal part of man. And he said he saw other souls, like snakes two or three or even more twined together, devouring one another in malignity and malevolence for what they had suffered or done in life. He said also that there were several lakes running parallel, one of boiling gold, another most cold of lead, another hard of iron, and several demons were standing by, like smiths, who lowered down and drew up by turns with instruments the souls of those whose criminality lay in insatiable cupidity. For when they were red-hot and transparent through their bath in the lake of gold, the demons thrust them into the lake of lead and dipped them in that; and when they got congealed in it and hard as hail, they dipped them into the lake of iron, and there they became wonderfully black, and broken and crushed by the hardness of the iron, and changed their appearance, and after that they were dipped again in the lake of gold, after suffering, he said, dreadful agony in all these changes of torment. But he said those souls suffered most piteously of all that, when they seemed to have escaped justice, were arrested again, and these were those whose crimes had been visited on their children or descendants. For whenever one of these latter happened to come up, he fell into a rage and cried out, and showed the marks of what he had suffered, and upbraided and pursued the soul of the parent, that wished to fly and hide himself but could not. For quickly did the ministers of torture pursue them, and hurry them back again to Justice,876 wailing all the while on account of their fore-knowledge of what their punishment would be. And to some of them he said many of their posterity clung at once, and just like bees or bats stuck to them, and squeaked and gibbered877 in their rage at the memory of what they had suffered owing to them. Last of all he saw the souls of those that were to come into the world a second time, forcibly moulded and transformed into various kinds of animals by artificers appointed for the very purpose with instruments and blows, who broke off all the limbs of some, and only wrenched off some of others, and polished others down or 365annihilated them altogether, to fit them for other habits and modes of life. Among them he saw the soul of Nero tortured in other ways, and pierced with red-hot nails. And the artificers having taken it in hand and converted it into the semblance of a Pindaric viper, which gets its way to life by gnawing through its mother's womb, a great light, he said, suddenly shone, and a voice came out of the light, ordering them to change it into something milder, so they devised of it the animal that croaks about lakes and marshes, for he had been punished sufficiently for his crimes, and now deserved some favour at the hands of the gods, for he had freed Greece, the noblest nation of his subjects and the best-beloved of the gods.878 So much did Thespesius behold, but as he intended to return a horrible dread came upon him. For a woman, marvellous in appearance and size, took hold of him and said to him, "Come here that you may the better remember everything you have seen." And she was about to strike him with a red-hot iron pin, such as the encaustic painters use,879 when another woman prevented her; and he was suddenly sucked up, as through880 a pipe, by a strong and violent wind, and lit upon his own body, and woke up and found that he was close to his tomb.

After this, Thespesius and his guide turned to see those who were being punished. At first, they only saw distressing and pitiable sights, but soon, Thespesius, unexpectedly, found himself among his friends, acquaintances, and family members who were being punished, experiencing horrible suffering and unbearable tortures, crying and wailing to him. Eventually, he saw his father emerging from a dark pit, covered in marks and scars, reaching out his hands, forced to confess by his torturers that he had been a wretched person who poisoned strangers with gold and had escaped detection during his life; but now, in this place, his guilt was clear, for which he had already suffered much and was being dragged to endure more. Overwhelmed by fear and panic, he didn't dare to plead for his father’s release, and wanting to turn and flee, he could no longer see his gentle and kind guide. Instead, he was pushed forward by terrifying figures, as if some dreadful necessity compelled him to continue. He noticed that the souls of those notorious criminals who had been punished in life were not tortured as harshly here as the others but faced a lesser, though still taxing, punishment for their irrational desires. Meanwhile, those who had lived undetected lives of vice under the guise of virtue were forced by their tormentors to expose their souls, writhing unnaturally, like sea scorpions that turn themselves inside out after swallowing a hook. Some of their torturers even flayed and contorted them to reveal the hidden vices buried deep in their souls, the very essence of humanity. He described seeing other souls entangled like snakes, devouring each other in malice and spite for what they had suffered or done in life. He also observed several parallel lakes: one of boiling gold, another of icy lead, and another of hard iron. Several demons, resembling smiths, stood by, lowering and pulling up the souls of those whose sin lay in insatiable greed. When they were glowing red and transparent from the lake of gold, the demons would plunge them into the lake of lead, hardening them into forms as tough as hail; then they would dip them into the lake of iron, turning them jet black, and crushing them under the iron's hardness, altering their appearance further. After all this torment, they would again be dipped into the lake of gold, enduring horrific pain through all these transformations. He noted that those who suffered the worst were those who seemed to have evaded justice but were caught again, particularly those whose crimes had repercussions for their children or descendants. Whenever one of these descendants appeared, they would fall into a rage, crying out and showing the signs of their own suffering, blaming and pursuing the soul of the parent, who wished to flee but could not. The torturers quickly pursued them, forcing them back to Justice, all the while lamenting because they knew what punishment awaited them. He said that many of their descendants clung to them like bees or bats, squeaking and chattering in their fury over what they had suffered because of those parents. Finally, he saw the souls of those destined to return to the world, forcibly shaped and transformed into various kinds of animals by designated artisans using tools and strikes, who either broke off limbs or polished some down or completely annihilated them to fit new habits and lifestyles. Among them, he noticed the soul of Nero being tortured in unique ways, pierced with red-hot nails. The craftsmen took it and transformed it into a Pindaric viper, which comes to life by gnawing through its mother’s womb. Suddenly, a great light appeared, and a voice came from the light, commanding them to turn it into something gentler. Thus, they created a creature that croaks in swamps and marshes, as he had suffered enough for his crimes and now deserved some mercy from the gods for having liberated Greece, the noblest nation among his subjects and favored by the gods. Thespesius beheld all this, but as he intended to return, an overwhelming dread gripped him. A woman, remarkable in appearance and size, grabbed him and said, "Come here so you can better remember everything you’ve seen." She was about to strike him with a red-hot iron pin, like those used by encaustic painters, when another woman intervened; then he was suddenly pulled up, as if through a pipe, by a strong and fierce wind, landing back in his own body. He woke up to find himself right by his tomb.

806 In the temple at Delphi, the scene of the discussion, as we see later on, §§ vii. xii.

806 In the temple at Delphi, where the discussion takes place, as we will see later on, §§ vii. xii.

807 Reading ἐδόκει with Reiske.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading seemed right with Reiske.

808 Euripides, "Orestes," 420. Cf. "Ion," 1615.

808 Euripides, "Orestes," 420. See also "Ion," 1615.

809 Thucydides, iii. 38.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Thucydides, vol. III, p. 38.

810 See the circumstances in Pausanias, iv. 17 and 22.

810 Check out the details in Pausanias, iv. 17 and 22.

811 Compare Petronius, "Satyricon," 44: "Dii pedes lanatos habent." Compare also "Tibullus," i. 9. 4: "Sera tamen tacitis Pœna venit pedibus."

811 Compare Petronius, "Satyricon," 44: "The gods have hairy feet." Also see "Tibullus," i. 9. 4: "Yet punishment comes quietly on delayed feet."

812 Reading μάλιστα (for μόλις) with Wyttenbach.

812 Reading especially (instead of just) with Wyttenbach.

813 An allusion to the proverb Ὄψε θεῶν ἀλέουσι μύλοι, ἀλέουσι δὲ λεπτά. See Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 1864.

813 A reference to the proverb Ὄψε θεῶν ἀλέουσι μύλοι, ἀλέουσι δὲ λεπτά. See Erasmus, "Adagia," p. 1864.

814 Cf. Plato, "Republic," 472 A.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Plato, "Republic," 472A.

815 See Note, "On Abundance of Friends," § ii.

815 See Note, "On Having Many Friends," § ii.

816 Reading εἰ γὰρ.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading if indeed.

817 Or a world.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Or a world.

818 See above, § ii.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See above, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__

819 Quoted also in "On restraining Anger," § ii.

819 Also quoted in "On Controlling Anger," § ii.

820 It seems necessary to read either πορίζειν with Mez, or ὁρίζειν with Wyttenbach.

820 It appears necessary to read either πορίζειν with Mez or ὁρίζειν with Wyttenbach.

821 Compare Aristophanes, "Vespæ," 438.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare Aristophanes, "Vespae," 438.

822 See Pausanias, viii. 27.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Check Pausanias, viii. 27.

823 Pindar.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Pindar.

824 Homer, "Iliad," xv. 641, 642.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," Book 15, lines 641, 642.

825 See Thucydides, i. 127.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Thucydides, 1.127.

826 See Pausanias, v. 17; viii. 24; ix. 41; x. 29.

826 See Pausanias, v. 17; viii. 24; ix. 41; x. 29.

827 Hesiod, "Works and Days," 266.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Hesiod, "Works and Days," 266.

828 Ibid. 265. Compare Pausanias, ii. 9; Ovid, A. A. i. 655, 656.

828 Same source, 265. Compare Pausanias, ii. 9; Ovid, A. A. i. 655, 656.

829 "Significat martyres Christianos, in tunica molesta fumantes."—Reiske.

829 "It signifies Christian martyrs, in uncomfortable clothing, smoking."—Reiske.

830 Like the sword of Damocles. See Horace, "Odes," iii. 1. 17, 21.

830 Like the sword of Damocles. See Horace, "Odes," iii. 1. 17, 21.

831 See also Pausanias, iii. 17.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See also Pausanias, III. 17.

832 Surely ἄν ἀνατρέποι must be read.

832 Surely ἄν ἀνατρέποι must be read.

833 Compare "On Curiosity," § x.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare "On Curiosity," § x.

834 The reading is very doubtful. I adopt ἡδονῆς μὲν εὐθὑς κενιν χάριν, ἐλπίδος ἔρημον εὑρίσκουσι.

834 The reading is quite uncertain. I take on ἡδονῆς μὲν εὐθὑς κενιν χάριν, ἐλπίδος ἔρημον εὑρίσκουσι.

835 Euripides, "Ino."

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Ino."

836 See Herodotus, vi. 86; Juvenal, xiii, 199-207.

836 See Herodotus, vi. 86; Juvenal, xiii, 199-207.

837 The company are in the temple at Delphi, be it remembered.

837 The company is in the temple at Delphi, just so you remember.

838 Called Iadmon in Herodotus, ii. 134, where this story is also told.

838 Called Iadmon in Herodotus, ii. 134, where this story is also told.

839 Wyttenbach suggests Daulis.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Wyttenbach suggests Daulis.

840 To Xerxes.

To Xerxes.

841 The allusion is to the well-known story of Odysseus and the Cyclops Polyphemus, who is supposed to have dwelt in the island of Sicily, where Agathocles was tyrant.

841 The reference is to the famous tale of Odysseus and the Cyclops Polyphemus, who is believed to have lived on the island of Sicily, where Agathocles was a tyrant.

842 See Pausanias, viii. 14.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Pausanias, viii. 14.

843 Two were to be sent for 1,000 continuous years. So the Oracle.

843 Two were to be sent for 1,000 consecutive years. So the Oracle.

844 See Pausanias ix. 30; Herodotus, v. 6.

844 See Pausanias ix. 30; Herodotus, v. 6.

845 See Pausanias, vii. 27; Athenæus, 372 A.

845 See Pausanias, vii. 27; Athenæus, 372 A.

846 A former king of Thebes. See Pausanias, ix. 5.

846 A previous king of Thebes. See Pausanias, ix. 5.

847 Called Daiphantes, Pausanias, x. 1.

847 Known as Daiphantes, Pausanias, x. 1.

848 Reading ἀπίστοις with Xylander.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading ἀπίστοις with Xylander.

849 The famous plague. See Thucydides, ii. 47-54.

849 The well-known plague. See Thucydides, ii. 47-54.

850 The allusion is to the circumstances mentioned in § xii.

850 The reference is to the situations described in § xii.

851 "Videtur idem cum sorita esse."—Reiske.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Seems the same as sorita."—Reiske.

852 Compare our author, "De EI apud Delphos," § xviii. See also Seneca, "Epist.," lviii. p. 483; and Plato, "Cratylus," 402 A.

852 Check out our author, "De EI apud Delphos," § xviii. Also, see Seneca, "Epist.," lviii. p. 483; and Plato, "Cratylus," 402 A.

853 Sons of Dionysius.

Sons of Dionysus.

854 Sons of Cassander.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Sons of Cassander.

855 "Iliad," vi. 146-149.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," vi. 146-149.

856 Compare Plato, "Phædrus," 276 B. These gardens of Adonis were what we might call flowerpot gardens. See Erasmus, "Adagia."

856 Compare Plato, "Phaedrus," 276 B. These Adonis gardens were what we might refer to as flowerpot gardens. See Erasmus, "Adagia."

857 εὐθὺς seems the best reading, ἀεὶ is flat.

857 “Immediately” seems to be the best choice, “Always” is straightforward.

858 Apollo.

Apollo.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__

860 Hesiod, "Works and Days," 735, 736.

860 Hesiod, "Works and Days," 735, 736.

861 Compare the French Proverb, "L'occasion fait le larron." And Juvenal's "Nemo repente fuit turpissimus."

861 Compare the French proverb, "Opportunity makes a thief," and Juvenal's "No one suddenly becomes base."

862 So Reiske very ingeniously.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ So Reiske smartly.

863 A rather far-fetched pedigree.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ An unlikely background.

864 See Pausanias, viii. 11; ix. 5, 10. See also Ovid, "Metamorphoses," Book iii. 100-130.

864 See Pausanias, viii. 11; ix. 5, 10. Also check out Ovid, "Metamorphoses," Book iii. 100-130.

865 Compare "On Love," § ii.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare "On Love," § 2.

866 At Mallus, in Cilicia. See Pausanias, i. 34.

866 At Mallus, in Cilicia. See Pausanias, i. 34.

867 Reading φιληδονίασ with Reiske.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading φιληδονίασ with Reiske.

868 Reading διαπεποικιλμένον ὄν with Wyttenbach.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading colorful being with Wyttenbach.

869 A paronomasia on γένεσις as if ἐπὶ γὴν νεῦσις. We cannot English it.

869 A play on words with γένεσις as if it means ἐπὶ γὴν νεῦσις. We can’t translate it into English.

870 Eurydice.

Eurydice.

871 "μιγνύμενον, Turn, et Bong.," Reiske. Surely the right reading.

871 "mixing, Turn, et Bong.," Reiske. This must be the correct reading.

872 Latin Puteoli.

Puteoli, Italy.

873 Vespasian. See Suetonius, "Vespasian," ch. 24, as to the particulars of his death.

873 Vespasian. See Suetonius, "Vespasian," ch. 24, for details about his death.

874 The reading is very doubtful. I have followed Wyttenbach in reading τριβομένην τριβὴν ἀτελῆ.

874 The reading is quite uncertain. I've gone along with Wyttenbach in reading τριβομένην τριβὴν ἀτελῆ.

875 Such as that of the Danaides. So Wyttenbach.

875 Like that of the Danaides. This is according to Wyttenbach.

876 Adopting the arrangement of Wyttenbach.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Following Wyttenbach's setup.

877 Compare Homer, "Odyssey," xxiv. 5-10.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Compare Homer, "Odyssey," 24. 5-10.

878 See Pausanias, vii. 17, for a sneaking kindness for Nero.

878 See Pausanias, vii. 17, for a sneaky affection for Nero.

879 See Athenæus, 687 B.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Refer to Athenæus, 687 B.

880 Reading διὰ with Reiske.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading with Reiske.

AGAINST BORROWING MONEY.

§ i. Plato in his Laws881 does not permit neighbours to use one another's water, unless they have first dug for themselves as far as the clay, and reached ground that is unsuitable for a well. For clay, having a rich and compact nature, absorbs the water it receives, and does not let it pass through. But he allows people that cannot make a well of their own to use their neighbour's water, for the law ought to relieve necessity. Ought there not also to 366be a law about money, that people should not borrow of others, nor go to other people's sources of income, until they have first examined their own resources at home, and collected, as by drops, what is necessary for their use? But nowadays from luxury and effeminacy and lavish expenditure people do not use their own resources, though they have them, but borrow from others at great interest without necessity. And what proves this very clearly is the fact that people do not lend money to the needy, but only to those who, wanting an immediate supply, bring a witness and adequate security for their credit, so that they can be in no actual necessity of borrowing.882

§ i. In his Laws881, Plato states that neighbors shouldn't use each other's water unless they've first dug to the clay and found ground that won't work for a well. Clay, being dense and rich, absorbs the water it receives and doesn't let it flow through. However, he allows those who can't dig their own well to use their neighbor's water because the law should alleviate need. Shouldn’t there also be a law about money, saying that people shouldn't borrow from others or tap into other people's income sources until they've first checked their own resources at home and gathered what's necessary for their use, little by little? Yet today, due to luxury, indulgence, and extravagant spending, people don’t use their own resources even when they have them; instead, they borrow from others at high interest without any real need. What makes this very clear is that people don’t lend money to those in genuine need, but only to those who, needing a quick fix, can provide a witness and sufficient collateral for their credit, ensuring they aren’t truly desperate to borrow.882

§ ii. Why pay court to the banker or trader? Borrow from your own table. You have cups, silver dishes, pots and pans. Use them in your need. Beautiful Aulis or Tenedos will furnish you with earthenware instead, purer than silver, for they will not smell strongly and unpleasantly of interest, a kind of rust that daily soils your sumptuousness, nor will they remind you of the calends and the new moon, which, though the most holy of days, the money-lenders make ill-omened and hateful. For those who instead of selling them put their goods out at pawn cannot be saved even by Zeus the Protector of Property: they are ashamed to sell, they are not ashamed to pay interest on their goods when out at pawn. And yet the famous Pericles made the ornament of Athene, which weighed forty talents of fine gold, removable at will, for "so," he said, "we can use the gold in war, and at some other time restore as costly a one." So should we too in our necessities, as in a siege, not receive a garrison imposed on us by a hostile money-lender, nor allow our goods to go into slavery; but stripping our table, our bed, our carriages, and our diet, of superfluities, we should keep ourselves free, intending to restore all those things again, if we have good luck.

§ ii. Why cater to the banker or trader? Rely on what you have at home. You own cups, silver dishes, pots, and pans. Use them when needed. Beautiful Aulis or Tenedos can provide you with pottery that’s better than silver, as it won’t carry the foul smell of interest, which tarnishes your wealth every day, nor will it remind you of the first of the month and the new moon—days that, though sacred, the money-lenders make sinister and detestable. Those who choose to pawn their goods instead of selling them can’t even be saved by Zeus, the Protector of Property: they’re too ashamed to sell but have no shame about paying interest on their pawned items. Yet, the renowned Pericles created an ornamental statue of Athene, weighing forty talents of fine gold, which could be removed at will because, he said, “this way, we can use the gold in wartime and later replace it with something just as valuable.” Similarly, in our times of need, like during a siege, we should refuse to accept a burden forced upon us by a greedy money-lender and not let our possessions fall into servitude. By stripping our home of unnecessary luxuries—our table, our beds, our carriages, and our food—we can remain free, planning to restore those things again when fortune smiles upon us.

§ iii. So the Roman matrons offered their gold and ornaments as first-fruits to Pythian Apollo, out of which a golden cup was made and sent to Delphi;883 and the Carthaginian matrons had their heads shorn, and with the 367hair cut off made cords for the machines and engines to be used in defence of their country.884 But we being ashamed of independence enslave ourselves to covenants and conditions, when we ought to restrict and confine ourselves to what is useful, and dock or sell useless superfluities, to build a temple of liberty for ourselves, our wives, and children. The famous Artemis at Ephesus gives asylum and security from their creditors to debtors, when they take refuge in her temple; but the asylum and sanctuary of frugality is everywhere open to the sober-minded, affording them joyful and honourable and ample space for much ease. For as the Pythian Priestess told the Athenians at the time of the Median war that the god had given them wooden walls,885 and they left the region and city, their goods and houses, and took refuge in their ships for liberty, so the god gives us a wooden table, and earthenware plate, and coarse garments, if we wish to live free. Care not for fine horses or chariots with handsome harness, adorned with gold886 and silver, which swift interest will catch up and outrun, but mounted on any chance donkey or nag flee from the hostile and tyrannical money-lender, not demanding like the Mede land and water,887 but interfering with your liberty, and lowering your status. If you pay him not, he duns you; if you offer the money, he won't have it; if you are selling anything, he cheapens the price; if you don't want to sell, he forces you; if you sue him, he comes to terms with you; if you swear, he hectors; if you go to his house, he shuts the door in your face; whereas if you stay at home, he billets himself on you, and is ever rapping at your door.

§ iii. So the Roman women offered their gold and jewelry as first gifts to Pythian Apollo, which was used to make a golden cup that was sent to Delphi;883 and the Carthaginian women cut off their hair and used the shorn locks to make cords for the machines and equipment that would defend their country.884 But we, ashamed of being independent, bind ourselves to agreements and terms, when we should instead limit ourselves to what is useful and sell or discard unnecessary luxuries, to create a temple of freedom for ourselves, our wives, and children. The famous Artemis at Ephesus offers protection and refuge for debtors when they seek sanctuary in her temple; however, the sanctuary of moderation is always open to those who are sensible, providing them with joyful and honorable ample space for ease. Just as the Pythian Priestess informed the Athenians during the Median war that the god had given them wooden walls,885 and they left their land and city, their possessions and homes, seeking safety in their ships for freedom, so the god provides us with a wooden table, an earthen plate, and simple clothes, if we wish to live freely. Don’t worry about fine horses or chariots with beautiful harnesses, adorned with gold886 and silver, which quickly become burdensome, but instead, ride any old donkey or horse to escape the cruel and oppressive money-lender, who demands not just land and water like the Medes,887 but interferes with your freedom and diminishes your worth. If you don't pay him, he harasses you; if you offer him money, he refuses it; if you're selling something, he devalues it; if you want to keep it, he pressures you to sell; if you take legal action against him, he negotiates; if you make an oath, he bullies you; if you go to his house, he slams the door in your face; but if you stay at home, he imposes himself on you and constantly knocks at your door.

§ iv. How did Solon benefit the Athenians by ordaining that debtors should no longer have to pay in person? For they are slaves to all money-lenders,888 and not to them only, what would there be so monstrous in that? but to their 368slaves, who are insolent and savage barbarians, such as Plato represents the fiery torturers and executioners in Hades who preside over the punishment of the impious. For they make the forum a hell for wretched debtors, and like vultures devour and rend them limb from limb, "piercing into their bowels,"889 and stand over others and prevent their tasting their own grapes or crops, as if they were so many Tantaluses. And as Darius sent Datis and Artaphernes to Athens with manacles and chains in their hands for their captives, so they bring into Greece boxes full of bonds and agreements, like fetters, and visit the towns and scour the country round, sowing not like Triptolemus harmless corn, but planting the toilsome and prolific and never-ending roots of debts, which grow and spread all round, and ruin and choke cities. They say that hares at once give birth and suckle and conceive again, but the debts of these knaves and barbarians give birth before they conceive; for at the very moment of giving they ask back, and take up what they laid down, and lend what they take for lending.

§ iv. How did Solon help the Athenians by deciding that debtors no longer had to pay in person? After all, they are enslaved to all moneylenders,888 and not just to them; what’s so monstrous about that? But to their 368 slaves, who are arrogant and brutal, like Plato describes the fiery torturers and executioners in Hades that oversee the punishment of the wicked. They turn the marketplace into a hell for miserable debtors, and like vultures, they feast on them, tearing them apart, "piercing into their bowels,"889 while blocking others from enjoying their own grapes or crops, making them suffer like so many Tantaluses. Just as Darius sent Datis and Artaphernes to Athens with shackles and chains for their captives, these men bring to Greece boxes filled with bonds and agreements, like chains, and travel through towns and scour the countryside, not sowing harmless seeds like Triptolemus, but planting the burdensome, prolific, and never-ending roots of debt, which spread and ruin cities. They say that hares give birth, nurse, and conceive again all at once, but the debts of these crooks and savages give birth before they conceive; for the moment they lend, they demand repayment, taking back what they just lent, and loaning what they just took.

§ v. It is a saying among the Messenians, that "there is a Pylos before Pylos, and another Pylos too." So it may be said with respect to these money-lenders, "there is interest before interest, and other interest too." Then of course they laugh at those natural philosophers who say that nothing can come of nothing, for they get interest on what neither is nor was; and they think it disgraceful to farm out the taxes, though the law allows it, while they themselves against the law exact tribute for what they lend, or rather, if one is to say the truth, defraud as they lend, for he who receives less than he signs his name for is defrauded. The Persians indeed think lying a secondary crime, but debt a principal one, for lying frequently follows upon debt, but money-lenders tell more lies, for they make fraudulent entries in their account-books, writing down that they have given so-and-so so much, when they have really given less. And the only excuse for their lying is covetousness, not necessity, not utter poverty, but insatiable greediness, the outcome of which is without enjoyment and useless to 369themselves, and fatal to their victims. For neither do they farm the fields which they rob their debtors of, nor do they inhabit their houses when they have thrust them out, nor use their tables or apparel, but first one is ruined, and then a second is hunted down, for whom the first one serves as a decoy. For the bane spreads and grows like a fire, to the destruction and ruin of all who fall into their clutches, for it consumes one after another; and the money-lender, who fans and feeds this flame to ensnare many, gets no more advantage from it but that some time after he can take his account-book and read how many he has sold up, how many turned out of house and home, and track the sources of his wealth, which is ever growing into a larger pile.

§ v. There's a saying among the Messenians that "there's a Pylos before Pylos, and another Pylos too." The same can be said about these money-lenders: "there's interest before interest, and other interest too." Naturally, they mock those philosophers who claim that nothing can come from nothing, as they profit from what neither exists nor ever existed. They find it shameful to outsource tax collection, even though the law permits it, while they themselves illegally demand exact payments for what they lend, or rather, to be honest, they cheat as they lend, because anyone who receives less than what they agreed to is being cheated. The Persians consider lying a minor offense, but debt a serious one, since lying often follows debt. However, money-lenders are the biggest liars, as they falsify their records, claiming to have lent someone a certain amount when they actually lent less. Their only justification for lying is greed, not necessity, not extreme poverty, just endless desire, which leads to a cycle of misery that benefits no one and ultimately destroys their victims. They neither farm the lands they take from their debtors nor live in the homes they force people out of, nor do they use their possessions. One person is ruined, and then another is hunted down, with the first serving as bait for the second. The damage spreads and grows like wildfire, bringing ruin to all who fall into their grasp, consuming one after another. The money-lender, who stokes and feeds this fire to ensnare many, gains no more than the ability to later look at his account book and see how many people he has dispossessed, how many turned out homeless, and track the sources of his ever-growing pile of wealth.

§ vi. And do not think I say this as an enemy proclaiming war against the money-lenders,

§ vi. And don’t think I’m saying this as an enemy declaring war on the moneylenders,

"For they never took my cows or horses,"890

but merely to prove to those who too readily borrow money what disgrace and servitude it brings with it, and what extreme folly and weakness it is. Have you anything? do not borrow, for you are not in a necessitous condition. Have you nothing? do not borrow, for you will never be able to pay back. Let us consider either case separately. Cato said to a certain old man who was a wicked fellow, "My good sir, why do you add the shame that comes from wickedness to old age, that has so many troubles of its own?" So too do you, since poverty has so many troubles of its own, not add the terrible distress that comes from borrowing money and from debt; and do not take away from poverty its only advantage over wealth, its freedom from corroding care. For the proverb that says, "I cannot carry a goat, put an ox on my shoulder," has a ridiculous ring. Unable to bear poverty, are you going to put on your back a money-lender, a weight hard to carry even for a rich man? How then, will you say, am I to maintain myself? Do you ask this, having two hands, two legs, and a tongue, in short, being a man, to love and be loved, to give and receive benefits? Can you not be a schoolmaster370 or tutor, or porter, or sailor, or make coasting voyages? Any of these ways of getting a livelihood is less disgraceful and difficult than to always have to hear, "Pay me that thou owest."

but simply to show those who too easily borrow money what shame and servitude it brings, and how foolish and weak it is. Do you have something? Don’t borrow, because you’re not in need. Do you have nothing? Don’t borrow, because you’ll never be able to repay it. Let’s look at each situation separately. Cato told a certain old man, who was a terrible person, “My good sir, why add the shame of wickedness to old age, which already has so many troubles?” Similarly, you shouldn’t add the terrible burden of borrowing money and debt to the many struggles of poverty; and don’t take away from poverty its only advantage over wealth, which is freedom from constant worry. The saying, “I can’t carry a goat; why put an ox on my back?” sounds ridiculous. If you can’t handle poverty, why add the weight of a moneylender, a burden that’s hard to bear even for a rich person? How, you might ask, am I supposed to support myself? Do you really ask this, with two hands, two legs, and a voice—being a person who can love and be loved and give and receive help? Can’t you be a schoolmaster370 or tutor, or porter, or sailor, or make coastal trips? Any of these ways to make a living is less shameful and easier than constantly hearing, “Pay me what you owe.”

§ vii. The well-known Rutilius went up to Musonius at Rome, and said to him, "Musonius, Zeus Soter, whom you imitate and emulate, does not borrow money." And Musonius smilingly answered, "Neither does he lend." For you must know Rutilius, himself a lender, was bantering Musonius for being a borrower. What Stoic inflatedness was all this! What need was there to bring in Zeus Soter? For all nature teaches the same lesson. Swallows do not borrow money, nor do ants, although nature has given them no hands, or reason, or profession. But men have intellect in excess, and so ingenious are they that they keep near them horses, and dogs, and partridges, and jackdaws. Why then do you despair, who are as impressible as a jackdaw, have as much voice as a partridge, and are as noble as a dog, of getting some person to befriend you, by looking after him, winning his affections, guarding him, fighting his battles? Do you not see how many opportunities there are both on land and sea? As Crates says,

§ vii. The well-known Rutilius approached Musonius in Rome and said to him, "Musonius, Zeus Soter, whom you admire and try to be like, doesn’t borrow money." Musonius smiled and replied, "Neither does he lend." Rutilius, who was a lender himself, was joking with Musonius for being a borrower. What Stoic pretentiousness this was! Why bring up Zeus Soter at all? Nature teaches the same thing everywhere. Swallows don’t borrow money, and neither do ants, even though nature hasn’t given them hands, reasoning, or a job. But humans have plenty of intellect, and they’re so clever that they surround themselves with horses, dogs, partridges, and jackdaws. So why do you lose hope, when you are as flexible as a jackdaw, have the same voice as a partridge, and are as loyal as a dog, in finding someone to help you by caring for them, gaining their affection, protecting them, and fighting for them? Don’t you see how many opportunities there are both on land and sea? As Crates says,

Miccylus and his wife, to prevent famine In these tough times, I saw both carding wool.

And King Antigonus asked Cleanthes, when he saw him at Athens after a long interval, "Do you still grind, Cleanthes?" And he replied, "I do, O king, but for my living, yet so as not to desert philosophy." Such was the admirable spirit of the man who, coming from the mill and kneading-trough, wrote with the hand that had baked and ground about the gods, and the moon, and stars, and the sun. But those kinds of labour are in our view servile! And so that we may appear free we borrow money, and flatter and dance attendance on slaves, and give them dinners and presents, and pay taxes as it were to them, not on account of our poverty (for no one lends money to a poor man), but from our love of lavish expenditure. For if we were content with things necessary for subsistence, the race of money-lenders would be as extinct as Centaurs and371 Gorgons are; it is luxury that has created them as much as goldsmiths, and silversmiths, and perfumers, and dyers in bright colours. For we do not owe money for bread and wine, but for estates, and slaves, and mules, and dining-rooms, and tables, and for our lavish public entertainments, in our unprofitable and thankless ambition. And he that is once involved in debt remains in it all his time, like a horse bitted and bridled that takes one rider after another, and there is no escape to green pastures and meadows, but they wander about like those demons who were driven out of heaven by the gods who are thus described by Empedocles:—

And King Antigonus asked Cleanthes, when he saw him in Athens after a long time, "Are you still working, Cleanthes?" He replied, "I am, Your Majesty, but I'm doing it for my living, while still staying true to philosophy." Such was the remarkable spirit of a man who, coming from the mill and kneading trough, wrote with the same hands that had baked and ground about the gods, the moon, the stars, and the sun. But we see those kinds of work as beneath us! To seem free, we borrow money, flatter, and cater to the wealthy, giving them dinners and gifts, and paying taxes as if they were due to them, not because we’re broke (after all, no one lends money to a poor person), but because we love to spend extravagantly. If we were satisfied with just what we needed to survive, the money-lenders would be as extinct as Centaurs and Gorgons are; it's the desire for luxury that has brought them to life, along with goldsmiths, silversmiths, perfumers, and dyers of vivid colors. We're not in debt for bread and wine but for estates, slaves, mules, dining rooms, tables, and our extravagant public entertainments, fueled by our unprofitable and thankless ambitions. Once someone falls into debt, they are stuck, like a horse in a bit and bridle, taking one rider after another, never escaping to green pastures and meadows, but wandering about like those demons cast out of heaven by the gods, as described by Empedocles:—

"Into the sea, the power of heaven pushes them," The sea pushes them back onto the land; The restless earth passes them on to the sun's rays; "The sun soon whirls them back to heaven again."

So one after another usurer or trader gets hold of the poor wretch, hailing either from Corinth, or Patræ, or Athens, till he gets set on to by them all, and torn to bits, and cut into mince-meat as it were for his interest. For as a person who is fallen into the mire must either get up out of it or remain in it, and if he turns about in it, and wallows in it, and bedabbles his body all over in it, he contracts only the greater defilement, so by borrowing from one person to pay another and changing their money-lenders they contract and incur fresh interest, and get into greater liabilities, and closely resemble sufferers from cholera, whose case does not admit of cure because they evacuate everything they are ordered to take, and so ever add to the disease. So these will not get cleansed from the disease of debt, but at regular times in the year pay their interest with pain and agony, and then immediately another creditor presents his little account, so again their heads swim and ache, when they ought to have got rid of their debts altogether, and regained their freedom.

So one after another, a loan shark or trader gets their hands on the poor person, whether they're from Corinth, Patræ, or Athens, until they get pressured by all of them and are torn apart, as if they were chopped up for someone else's gain. Just like someone who has fallen into the mud must either get up and out or stay stuck in it, if they keep rolling around in it and getting dirtier, they only end up worse off. In the same way, by borrowing from one person to pay off another and switching money lenders, they accumulate new interest and sink deeper into debt. They resemble victims of cholera, whose condition can't be treated because they reject everything prescribed to them, only making the problem worse. These individuals won’t free themselves from the burden of debt; instead, they pay their interest with distress and struggle at certain times of the year, and then right after, another creditor comes along with more bills, leaving them dizzy and in pain when they should have been able to clear their debts and regain their freedom.

§ viii. I now turn my attention to those who are rich and luxurious, and use language like the following, "Am I then to go without slaves and hearth and home?" As if any dropsical person, whose body was greatly swollen and who was very weak, should say to his doctor, "Am I then to become lean and empty?" And why not, to get well?372 And do you too go without a slave, not to be a slave yourself; and without chattels, not to be another man's chattel. Listen to a story about two vultures; one was vomiting and saying it would bring its inside up, and the other who was by said, "What harm if you do? For it won't be your inside you bring up, but that dead body we devoured lately." And so any debtor does not sell his own estate, or his own house, but his creditor's, for he has made him by law master of them. Nay, but by Zeus, says one, my father left me this field. Yes, and your father also left you liberty and a status in the community, which you ought to value more than you do. And your father begot you with hand and foot, but should either of them mortify, you pay the surgeon to cut it off. Thus Calypso clad and "dressed" Odysseus "in raiment smelling sweet,"891 like the body of an immortal, as a gift and token of her affection for him; but when his vessel was upset and he himself immersed, and owing to this wet and heavy raiment could hardly keep himself on the top of the waves, he threw it off and stripped himself, and covered his naked breast with Ino's veil,892 and "swam for it gazing on the distant shore,"893 and so saved his life, and lacked neither food nor raiment. What then? have not poor debtors storms, when the money-lender stands over them and says, Pay?

§ viii. Now I focus on those who are wealthy and indulgent, who say things like, "Do I really have to live without slaves and a home?" It's like a person who's severely swollen and weak telling their doctor, "Do I really have to be thin and empty?" And why not, if it means getting better?372 And you too should live without a slave so you won't become a slave yourself; and without possessions, so you won't end up being someone else's possession. Here’s a story about two vultures: one was vomiting and lamenting that it would bring up its insides, and the other said, "What difference does it make? You won't be bringing up your own insides, but that dead body we just ate." Similarly, any debtor doesn’t sell their own property or home, but the creditor's, since the law has made them the master of it. "But by Zeus," one might object, "my father left me this field." Yes, and your father also left you your freedom and your standing in the community, which you should value more. Your father brought you into this world with all your limbs, but if you were to lose any, you'd pay a surgeon to remove them. Just like Calypso dressed Odysseus in "sweet-smelling clothes,"891 fit for a god, as a gift to show her love; but when his ship capsized and he was thrown into the sea, struggling with those wet and heavy clothes, he stripped them off, covered his bare chest with Ino's veil,892 and "swam towards the distant shore,"893 saving himself, without lacking for food or clothing. So what? Don't poor debtors face a storm when the moneylender stands over them demanding, Pay?

"Poseidon spoke, and the clouds gathered, And whipped the sea into a frenzy, and instantly Eurus, Notus, and the windy Zephyr Blew it all together.894

Thus interest rolls on interest as wave upon wave, and he that is involved in debt struggles against the load that bears him down, but cannot swim away and escape, but sinks to the bottom, and carries with him to ruin his friends that have gone security for him. But Crates the Theban, though he had neither duns nor debts, and was only disgusted at the distracting cares of housekeeping, gave up a property worth eight talents, and assumed the philosopher's threadbare cloak and wallet, and took refuge 373in philosophy and poverty. And Anaxagoras left his sheep-farm. But why need I mention these? since the lyric poet Philoxenus, obtaining by lot in a Sicilian colony much substance and a house abounding in every kind of comfort, but finding that luxury and pleasure and absence of refinement was the fashion there, said, "By the gods these comforts shall not undo me, I will give them up," and he left his lot to others, and sailed home again. But debtors have to put up with being dunned, subjected to tribute, suffering slavery, passing debased coin, and like Phineus, feeding certain winged Harpies, who carry off and lay violent hands on their food, not at the proper season, for they get possession of their debtors' corn before it is sown, and they traffic for oil before the olives are ripe; and the money-lender says, "I have wine at such and such a price," and takes a bond for it, when the grapes are yet on the vine waiting for Arcturus to ripen them.

So, interest keeps piling on interest like waves, and someone who is deep in debt struggles under the weight that pulls them down. They can’t swim away and escape; they just sink, dragging down their friends who guaranteed their loans. But Crates the Theban, who had no bills or debts and was simply fed up with the chaotic life of managing a household, gave up a property worth eight talents, put on the worn-out cloak and bag of a philosopher, and turned to a life of philosophy and poverty. Anaxagoras also left his sheep farm. But why should I even mention these? The lyric poet Philoxenus, winning a lot that included a substantial estate and a comfortable house in a Sicilian colony, noticed that luxury and excess were the norm there. He declared, "By the gods, these comforts won’t trap me; I will let them go," and he gave his property to others and sailed back home. Meanwhile, debtors endure relentless pressure from creditors, subjected to excessive demands, living in a kind of slavery, dealing with worthless money, and like Phineus, dealing with winged Harpies that snatch away their food. They can’t even gather their harvest in time, as the Harpies seize their crops before they’re planted, trading for oil before the olives have ripened. The moneylender says, "I have wine for this price," and takes a loan for it while the grapes are still on the vine, waiting for the harvest to ripen.

881 Page 844, A. B. C.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Page 844, A. B. C.

882 Reading with Wyttenbach διδοῦσι and ἔχουσι.

882 Reading with Wyttenbach give and have.

883 See Livy, v. 25.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Livy, v. 25.

884 See Appian, lv. 26.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Appian, lv. 26.

885 See Herodotus, vii. 141-143; viii. 51.

885 See Herodotus, vii. 141-143; viii. 51.

886 Reading with Reiske κατάχρυσα.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading with Reiske gold-plated.

887 The technical term for submission to an enemy. See Pausanias, iii. 12; x. 20. Herodotus, v. 17, 18; vii. 133.

887 The technical term for surrender to an enemy. See Pausanias, iii. 12; x. 20. Herodotus, v. 17, 18; vii. 133.

888 Reading with Reiske δανεισταῖς. Perhaps ἀφανισταῖς originally came after ἀγρίοις, and got somehow displaced.

888 Reading with Reiske lenders. Maybe invisibles was originally placed after wild ones, and somehow got shifted.

889 See Homer, "Odyssey," xi. 578, 579, and context.

889 See Homer, "Odyssey," xi. 578, 579, and context.

890 Homer, "Iliad," i. 154.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Iliad," 1. 154.

891 "Odyssey," v. 264.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," v. 264.

892 "Odyssey," v. 333-375.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," v. 333-375.

893 "Odyssey," v. 439.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," v. 439.

894 "Odyssey," v. 291-295.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," v. 291-295.

WHETHER "LIVE UNKNOWN" BE A WISE PRECEPT.

§ i. He who uttered this precept895 certainly did not wish to live unknown, for he uttered it to let all the world know he was a superior thinker, and to get to himself unjust glory by exhorting others to shun glory.

§ i. The person who shared this advice895 clearly didn’t want to remain anonymous, as he stated it to make sure everyone knew he was a superior thinker and to gain undeserved praise by encouraging others to avoid seeking glory.

"I dislike the wise man because he is not wise for himself." 896

They say that Philoxenus the son of Eryxis and Gnatho the Sicilian, being exceedingly greedy where good fare was going, would blow their nose in the dishes, to disgust all others at the table, that they alone might take their fill of the choicest dishes. So those that are insatiable pursuers of glory calumniate glory to others who are their rivals, that they may get it without antagonists. In this they 374resemble rowers, who face the stern of the vessel but propel it ahead, that by the recoil from the stroke of their oars they may reach port, so those that give vent to precepts like this pursue glory with their face turned in the opposite direction. For otherwise what need was there to utter a precept like this, or to write and hand it down to posterity, if he wished to live unknown to his own generation, who did not wish to live unknown to posterity?

They say that Philoxenus, the son of Eryxis, and Gnatho the Sicilian were so greedy for good food that they would blow their noses in the dishes to disgust everyone else at the table, just so they could enjoy the best dishes alone. Similarly, those who are never satisfied with the pursuit of glory slander their rivals to claim it without competition. In this way, they resemble rowers who face the back of the boat but push it forward; the force from their oars helps them reach the destination, just like those who express ideas like this seek glory while looking the other way. After all, why would anyone need to share a lesson like this or write it down for future generations if they wanted to remain unknown in their own time, while not wishing to be forgotten by posterity?

§ ii. Look at the matter in the following way.897 Has not that "live unknown" a villainous ring, as though one had broken open graves? Is your life so disgraceful that we must all be ignorant of it? For my part I should say, Even if your life be bad do not live unknown, but be known, reform, repent; if you have virtue, be not utterly useless in life; if you are vicious, do not continue unreformed. Point out then and define to whom you recommend this precept. If to an ignorant or wicked or senseless person, you resemble one who should say to a person in a fever or delirium, "Be unknown. Don't let the doctor know your condition. Go and throw yourself into some dark place, that you and your ailments may be unknown." So you say to a vicious man, "Go off with your vice, and hide your deadly and irremediable disease from your friends, fearful to show your superstitious fears, palpitations as it were, to those who could admonish you and cure you." Our remote ancestors paid public attention to the sick, and if any one had either had or cured a similar complaint, he communicated his experience to the patient, and so they say medical art became great by these contributions from experience. We ought also in the same way to expose to everyone diseased lives and the passions of the soul, and to handle them, and to examine the condition of each,898 and say, Are you a passionate man? Be on your guard against anger. Are you of a jealous turn? Look to it. Are you in love? I myself was in love once, but I had to repent. But nowadays people deny and conceal and cloak their vices, and so fix them deeper in themselves.

§ ii. Consider the situation like this.897 Doesn’t that phrase "live unknown" sound suspicious, as if we’re digging up graves? Is your life so shameful that we all need to be kept in the dark about it? Personally, I would say, even if your life is flawed, don’t stay unknown; let yourself be known, change, and repent. If you have good qualities, don't waste your life; if you have bad habits, don’t stay uncorrected. Point out to whom you’re giving this advice. If it’s to someone ignorant, immoral, or foolish, you’re like someone telling a sick person, "Stay hidden. Don’t let the doctor know what’s wrong. Go hide away so that both you and your illness can be unknown." When you tell a bad person, "Just keep your flaws to yourself and hide your serious problems from your friends, afraid to show your irrational fears or your racing heart to those who could help you," it’s the same. Our ancestors used to pay attention to the sick; if someone had similar issues or found a cure, they would share that experience with the patient. This is how medical knowledge grew from shared experiences. We should likewise reveal to everyone our troubled lives and the struggles of the soul, analyze them, and ask each other, are you hot-tempered? Watch out for anger. Are you jealous? Be careful. Are you in love? I was in love once too, but I had to change my ways. But nowadays, people deny, hide, and disguise their faults, which only makes them worse.

§ iii. Moreover if you advise men of worth to live un375known and in obscurity, you say to Epaminondas, Do not be a general; and to Lycurgus, Do not be a legislator; and to Thrasybulus, Do not be a tyrannicide; and to Pythagoras, Do not teach; and to Socrates, Do not discourse; and first and foremost you bid yourself, Epicurus, to refrain from writing letters to your friends in Asia, and from enrolling Egyptian strangers among your disciples, and from dancing attendance on the youths of Lampsacus, and sending books to all quarters to display your wisdom to all men and all women, and leaving directions in your will about your funeral. What is the meaning of those common tables of yours? what that crowd of friends and handsome youths? Why those many thousand lines written and composed so laboriously on Metrodorus, and Aristobulus, and Chæredemus, that they may not be unknown even in death, if899 you ordain for virtue oblivion, for art inactivity, for philosophy silence, and for success that it should be speedily forgotten?

§ iii. Furthermore, if you suggest to admirable people that they should live unnoticed and in the shadows, you're essentially telling Epaminondas not to be a general; Lycurgus not to be a legislator; Thrasybulus not to be a liberator; Pythagoras not to teach; Socrates not to engage in dialogue; and, most importantly, you're telling yourself, Epicurus, not to write letters to your friends in Asia, avoid including Egyptian strangers as your students, stop attending to the youth of Lampsacus, and refrain from sending books all over to showcase your wisdom to everyone, and not to leave instructions in your will about your funeral. What’s the point of those communal meals of yours? What’s the purpose of that group of friends and attractive young men? Why write so many thousands of lines, painstakingly crafted about Metrodorus, Aristobulus, and Chæredemus, if you want virtue to be forgotten, art to be idle, philosophy to be silent, and for success to be quickly overlooked?

§ iv. But if you exclude all knowledge about life, like putting the lights out at a supper party, that you may go from pleasure to pleasure undetected,900 then "live unknown." Certainly if I am going to pass my life with the harlot Hedeia, or my days with Leontium, and spurn at virtue, and put my summum bonum in sensual gratifications, these are ends that require darkness and night, on these oblivion and ignorance are rightly cast. But if any one in nature sings the praises of the deity and justice and providence, and in morals upholds the law and society and the constitution, and in the constitution what is honourable and not expedient, why should he "live unknown"? Is it that he should instruct nobody, inspire in nobody an emulation for virtue, and be to nobody a pattern in good?901 Had Themistocles been unknown at Athens, Greece would not have repelled Xerxes; had Camillus been unknown at Rome, Rome would not have remained a state; had Plato been unknown to Dion, Sicily would not have won its freedom. And as light, I take it, makes us not only visible 376but useful to one another, so knowledge gives not only glory but impetus to virtue. Epaminondas in obscurity up to his fortieth year was no use to the Thebans, but when his merits became known and he was put into power, he saved his state from ruin, and liberated Greece from slavery, making his abilities efficacious in emergency through his reputation like the bright shining of a light. For Sophocles' words,

§ iv. But if you shut out all awareness of life, like turning off the lights at a dinner party, so you can move from one pleasure to another unnoticed,900 then "live unknown." If I am going to spend my life with the prostitute Hedeia or my days with Leontium, disregarding virtue and prioritizing sensual pleasures, those pursuits need darkness and night, and oblivion and ignorance are rightly associated with them. But if someone praises the divine, justice, and providence in nature, and supports law, society, and the constitution in morals—highlighting what is honorable rather than convenient—why should he "live unknown"? Shouldn’t he teach others, inspire them to strive for virtue, and serve as a role model for goodness?901 If Themistocles had been unknown in Athens, Greece wouldn’t have defeated Xerxes; if Camillus had been unknown in Rome, it wouldn’t have remained a state; if Plato had been unknown to Dion, Sicily wouldn’t have achieved its freedom. Just as light not only makes us visible 376 but also beneficial to one another, knowledge brings not just fame but also motivation for virtue. Epaminondas, living in obscurity until he was forty, was of no help to the Thebans, but once his talents were recognized and he gained power, he saved his state from destruction and freed Greece from oppression, making his abilities impactful in critical times through his reputation, like a shining light. For Sophocles' words,

"Brass shines brightly when it's in use, but when it's not used It becomes dull over time, and ruins the house,"902

are also appropriate to the character of a man, which gets rusty and senile by not mixing in affairs but living in obscurity. For mute inglorious ease, and a sedentary life devoted to leisure, not only injure the body but also the soul: and as hidden waters overshadowed and stagnant get foul because they have no outlet, so the innate powers of unruffled lives, that neither imbibe nor pass on anything, even if they had any useful element in them once, seem to be effete and wasted.

are also fitting for a man’s character, which becomes dull and senile from not engaging in activities and living in obscurity. A silent, undisturbed life dedicated to leisure not only harms the body but also the soul: just as stagnant, concealed waters become foul because they lack an outlet, the inherent abilities of untroubled lives, which neither absorb nor share anything, even if they once had something valuable in them, seem to become weak and wasted.

§ v. Have you never noticed how when night comes on a tired languor seizes the body, and inactive torpor overpowers the soul, and reason shrinks within itself like a fire going out, and feeling quite worn out is gently agitated by disordered fancies, only just indicating that the man is alive? But when the sun rises and scares away deceitful dreams, and brings on as it were the everyday world903 and with its light rouses and stimulates the thoughts and actions of everybody, then, as Democritus says, "men form new ideas for the day," and betake themselves to their various pursuits with mutual impetuosity, as if drawn by a strong impulse.

§ v. Have you ever noticed how when night falls, a tired heaviness takes over your body, and a sluggishness overwhelms your mind? Reason retreats like a fire dying out, and feelings of exhaustion are stirred by chaotic thoughts, barely reminding you that you're alive. But when the sun rises and chases away deceptive dreams, it seems to reintroduce you to the everyday world903 and, with its light, awakens and energizes everyone’s thoughts and actions. Then, as Democritus says, "people come up with new ideas for the day," eagerly pursuing their various activities as if propelled by a strong force.

§ vi. And I think that life itself, and the way we come into the world, is so ordained by the deity that we should know one another. For everyone comes into this great universe obscure and unknown casually and by degrees, but when he mixes with his fellows and grows to maturity he shines forth, and becomes well-known instead of obscure, 377and conspicuous instead of unknown. For knowledge is not the road to being, as some say, but being to knowledge, for being does not create but only exhibits things, as death is not the reducing of existence to non-existence, but rather the result of dissolution is obscurity. So people considering the Sun as Apollo according to hereditary and ancient institutions, call him Delius904 and Pythius; whereas the lord of the world of darkness, whether god or demon, they call Hades905 (for when we die we go into an unseen and invisible place), and the lord of dark night and idle sleep. And I think our ancestors called man himself by a word meaning light,906 because by their relationship to light all have implanted in them a strong and vehement desire to know and to be known. And some philosophers think that the soul itself is light in its essence, inferring so on other grounds and because it can least endure ignorance about facts, and hates907 everything obscure, and is disturbed at everything dark, which inspires fear and suspicion in it, whereas light is so dear and welcome to it that it thinks nothing otherwise delightful bearable without it, as indeed light makes every pleasure pastime and enjoyment gay and cheerful, like the application of some sweet and general flavour. But the man who thrusts himself into obscurity, and wraps himself up in darkness and buries himself alive, is like one who is dissatisfied with his birth, and renounces his being.

§ vi. I believe that life itself and the way we enter the world are so designed by the divine that we should get to know each other. Everyone comes into this vast universe anonymously and gradually, but as they interact with others and mature, they stand out and become well-known instead of remaining hidden, 377 and noticeable instead of unknown. Knowledge isn't the path to existence, as some suggest; rather, existence leads to knowledge because existence doesn’t create but only reveals things. Just as death isn’t simply turning existence into non-existence, but rather a type of dissolution that leads to obscurity. People refer to the Sun as Apollo based on traditional and ancient beliefs, calling him Delius904 and Pythius; meanwhile, the ruler of the dark world, whether a god or demon, is known as Hades905 (because when we die, we enter an unseen and invisible realm), the lord of the dark night and restless sleep. I think our ancestors referred to humans using a term meaning light,906 as their connection to light instilled in them a strong and intense desire to know and to be known. Some philosophers believe that the soul itself is light in its essence, reasoning this from various perspectives including its inability to tolerate ignorance and its aversion to everything obscure, feeling uneasy about anything dark, which evokes fear and suspicion. In contrast, light is so precious and inviting that it feels nothing enjoyable can be endured without it, as indeed light makes every pleasure and enjoyment bright and cheerful, like a sweet and familiar flavor. However, a person who chooses to live in obscurity, shrouded in darkness and burying themselves alive, is akin to someone who is unhappy with their existence and rejects their own being.

§ vii. And yet Pindar tells us908 that the abode of the blest is a glorious existence, where the sun shines bright through the entire night in meadows red with roses, an extensive plain full of shady trees ever in bloom never in fruit, watered by gentle purling streams, and there the blest ones pass their time away in thinking and talking about the past and present in social converse....909 But the third road is of those who have lived unholy and lawless lives, that thrusts their souls to Erebus and the bottomless pit, where sluggish streams of murky night belch forth endless darkness, which receive those that are to be punished 378and conceal them in forgetfulness and oblivion. For vultures do not always prey on the liver of wicked persons lying on the ground,910 for it is destroyed by fire or has rolled away; nor does the carrying of heavy burdens press upon and tire out the bodies of those that undergo punishment,

§ vii. And yet Pindar tells us908 that the home of the blessed is a wonderful place, where the sun shines brightly all night over meadows filled with red roses, a wide plain full of shady trees that are always in bloom but never bear fruit, watered by gentle, bubbling streams. Here, the blessed spend their time thinking and talking about the past and present in friendly conversations....909 But the third path is for those who have lived corrupt and lawless lives, which drives their souls to Erebus and the abyss, where sluggish streams of murky night spew out endless darkness, taking in those who are to be punished 378and hiding them in forgetfulness and oblivion. For vultures do not always feed on the livers of wicked people lying on the ground,910 as these are often destroyed by fire or have rolled away; nor do heavy burdens weigh down and exhaust the bodies of those who are being punished,

"For their strength is no longer made of flesh and bones,"911

nor have the dead any vestige of body that can receive the infliction of punishment that can make impression; but in reality the only punishment of those who have lived ill is infamy and obscurity and utter annihilation, which hurries them off to the dark river of oblivion,912 and plunges them into the abyss of a fathomless sea, involving them in uselessness and idleness, ignorance and obscurity.

nor do the dead have any trace of a body that can feel punishment or make an impression; in reality, the only punishment for those who lived poorly is disgrace, obscurity, and complete annihilation, which swiftly sweeps them into the dark river of oblivion,912 and submerges them into an endless abyss, trapping them in uselessness and idleness, ignorance and obscurity.

895 Probably Epicurus, as we infer from the very personal § iii.

895 Probably Epicurus, as we gather from the very personal § iii.

896 Euripides, Fragm. 930.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, Fragm. 930.

897 Reading with Wyttenbach, Ἀλλὰ τοῦτο μὲν ταύτῃ.

897 Reading with Wyttenbach, But this indeed is here.

898 Reading ἑκάστου for ἕκαστον. Reiske proposed ὲκάστων.

898 Reading each for each one. Reiske proposed each of them.

899 Reading εἰ (for ἵνα) with Xylander and Wyttenbach.

899 Reading if (for that) with Xylander and Wyttenbach.

900 Reading with Wyttenbach.

Reading with Wyttenbach.

901 Adopting the suggestion of Wyttenbach, "Forte καλοῦ, at Amiot."

901 Following Wyttenbach's suggestion, "Strong beauty, at Amiot."

902 Frag. 742.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Frag. 742.

903 "Dormiens quisque in peculiarem abest mumdum, expergefactus in communem redit."—Xylander. Compare Herrick's Poem, "Dreames."

903 "Everyone who is asleep is absent from their own world; upon waking, they return to the shared one."—Xylander. Compare Herrick's Poem, "Dreams".

904 Bright.

Bright.

905 Invisible.

Invisible.

906 φώς.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ light.

907 Reading with Wyttenbach ἐχθαίρει.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading with Wyttenbach hates.

908 Reading φησίν for φύσιν.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading φησίν for φύσιν.

909 Hiatus hic valde deflendus.

Hiatus here must be addressed.

910 As was fabled about Tityus, "Odyssey," xi. 576-579.

910 As was said about Tityus, "Odyssey," xi. 576-579.

911 "Odyssey," xi. 219.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," xi. 219.

912 So Reiske, ποταμὶν τῆς λήθης.

river of forgetfulness.


ON EXILE

§ i. They say those discourses, like friends, are best and surest that come to our refuge and aid in adversity, and are useful. For many who come forward do more harm than good in the remarks they make to the unfortunate, as people unable to swim trying to rescue the drowning get entangled with them and sink to the bottom together. Now the discourse that ought to come from friends and people disposed to be helpful should be consolation, and not mere assent with a man's sad feelings. For we do not in adverse circumstances need people to weep and wail with us like choruses in a tragedy, but people to speak plainly to us and instruct us, that grief and dejection of mind are in all cases useless and idle and senseless; and that where the circumstances themselves, when examined by the light of reason, enable a man to say to himself that his trouble is greater in fancy than in reality, it is quite ridiculous not to inquire of the body what it has suffered, nor of the mind if it is any the worse for what has happened, 379but to employ external sympathizers to teach us what our grief is.

§ i. People say that conversations, like friends, are most helpful and reliable when they support us in tough times. Many who try to help end up causing more harm than good with their comments to those who are struggling, much like someone who can't swim trying to save a drowning person only to get caught up and drown with them. The kind of conversation that should come from friends or those willing to help should offer comfort, not just agree with a person's sadness. In challenging situations, we don't need people to cry and mourn with us like a tragic chorus; we need people to speak honestly and give us guidance, reminding us that feeling sad and defeated is always pointless. When we look at our troubles through a rational lens, we often find that our worries are bigger in our imaginations than in reality. It’s quite foolish not to check in with our body about what it's experienced or with our mind about whether it's truly worse off because of what’s happened, 379 and instead rely on outside sympathizers to define our grief for us.

§ ii. Therefore let us examine alone by ourselves the weight of our misfortunes, as if they were burdens. For the body is weighed down by the burden of what presses on it, but the soul often adds to the real load a burden of its own. A stone is naturally hard, and ice naturally cold, but they do not receive these properties and impressions from without; whereas with regard to exile and loss of reputation or honours, as also with regard to their opposites, as crowns and office and position, it is not their own intrinsic nature but our opinion of them that is the gauge of their real joy or sorrow, so that each person makes them for himself light or heavy, easy to bear or hard to bear. When Polynices was asked

§ ii. So let’s take a moment to reflect on our misfortunes as if they are burdens we carry alone. The body feels weighed down by what presses upon it, but the soul often adds its own extra weight. A stone is simply hard, and ice is just cold, but they don’t gain these qualities from outside factors; when it comes to things like exile or a loss of reputation and honor, or their opposites like crowns and positions, it’s not their inherent nature that determines our real joy or sorrow, but our perception of them that decides whether we find them light or heavy, easy or difficult to bear. When Polynices was asked

"What does it mean to be an exile? Is it hard?"

he replied to the question,

he answered the question,

"Most serious, and indeed worse than just spoken." 913

Compare with this the language of Alcman, as the poet has represented him in the following lines. "Sardis, my father's ancient home, had I had the fortune to be reared in thee, I should have been dressed in gold as a priest of Cybele,914 and beaten the fine drums; but as it is my name is Alcman, and I am a citizen of Sparta, and I have learned to write Greek poetry, which makes me greater than the tyrants Dascyles or Gyges." Thus the very same thing one man's opinion makes good, like current coin, and another's bad and injurious.

Compare this with the language of Alcman, as the poet depicts him in the following lines. "Sardis, my father's ancient home, if I had been lucky enough to be raised there, I would have been dressed in gold as a priest of Cybele,914 and played the fine drums; but as it is, my name is Alcman, and I am a citizen of Sparta, and I have learned to write Greek poetry, which makes me greater than the tyrants Dascyles or Gyges." Thus, the same thing one person's opinion regards as good, like current coin, another's finds bad and harmful.

§ iii. But let it be granted that exile is, as many say and sing, a grievous thing. So some food is bitter, and sharp, and biting to the taste, yet by an admixture with it of sweet and agreeable food we take away its unpleasantness. There are also some colours unpleasant to look at, that quite confuse and dazzle us by their intensity and excessive force. If then we can relieve this by a mixture of shadow, or by diverting the eye to green or some agreeable colour, so too can we deal with misfortunes, mixing up 380with them the advantages and pleasant things we still enjoy, as wealth, or friends, or leisure, and no deficiency in what is necessary for our subsistence. For I do not think that there are many natives of Sardis who would not choose your fortune even with exile, and be content to live as you do in a strange land, rather than, like snails who have no other home than their shells, enjoy no other blessing but staying at home in ease.

§ iii. But let’s acknowledge that exile is, as many say and sing, a painful experience. Just as some foods can be bitter, sharp, and unpleasant to taste, we can soften the harshness by mixing in something sweet and enjoyable. There are also colors that are hard to look at, overwhelming us with their intensity and brightness. If we can ease this by adding some shadow or by shifting our gaze to green or another pleasant color, we can also handle misfortunes by mixing in the benefits and joys we still have, like wealth, friends, or leisure, and not lacking what we need to get by. I don't think there are many people from Sardis who wouldn't prefer your situation—even with exile—and be happy to live as you do in a foreign land, rather than, like snails with no home but their shells, enjoy nothing but the comfort of staying at home.

§ iv. As then he in the comedy that was exhorting an unfortunate friend to take courage and bear up against fortune, when he asked him "how," answered "as a philosopher," so may we also play the philosopher's part and bear up against fortune manfully. How do we do when it rains, or when the North Wind doth blow? We go to the fire, or the baths, or the house, or put on another coat: we don't sit down in the rain and cry. So too can you more than most revive and cheer yourself for the chill of adversity, not standing in need of outward aid, but sensibly using your actual advantages. The surgeon's cupping-glasses extract the worst humours from the body to relieve and preserve the rest of it, whereas the melancholy and querulous by ever dwelling on their worst circumstances, and thinking only of them, and being engrossed by their troubles, make even useful things useless to them, at the very time when the need is most urgent. For as to those two jars, my friend, that Homer915 says are stored in Heaven, one full of good fortunes, one of bad, it is not Zeus that presides as the dispenser of them, giving to some a gentle and even portion, and to others unmixed streams of evils, but ourselves. For the sensible make their life pleasanter and more endurable by mitigating their sorrows with the consideration of their blessings, while most people, like sieves, let the worst things stick to them while the best pass through.

§ iv. Just like he did in the play, encouraging a struggling friend to stay strong and deal with life's challenges, when asked "how," he replied "like a philosopher." We can also take on the philosopher's role and bravely face tough times. What do we do when it rains or when the North Wind blows? We gather around the fire, head to the baths, go indoors, or throw on an extra layer; we don’t just sit in the rain and cry. Similarly, you have the ability to lift your spirits in hard times more than most people, without needing external help, but by wisely using what you have. Just like how a surgeon uses cupping to draw out harmful substances from the body to help it heal, those who are negative and constantly focus on their problems make even helpful things ineffective, especially when they need it the most. As for those two jars, my friend, that Homer915 talks about being kept in Heaven, one filled with good fortunes and the other with bad, it's not Zeus who hands them out, giving some a gentle mix of good and bad while others receive only misfortunes; it’s us. Those who are wise make their lives happier and more bearable by softening their pain with appreciation for their blessings, while most people, like sieves, let their good moments slip away while holding onto the bad.

§ v. And so, if we fall into any real trouble or evil, we ought to get cheerfulness and ease of mind from the consideration of the actual blessings that are still left to us, mitigating outward trouble by private happiness. And as to those things which are not really evil in their nature, 381but only so from imagination and empty fancy, we must act as we do with children who are afraid of masks: by bringing them near, and putting them in their hands, and turning them about, we accustom them never to heed them at all: and so we by bringing reason to bear on it may discover the rottenness and emptiness and exaggeration of our fancy. As a case in point let us take your present exile from what you deem your country. For in nature no country, or house, or field, or smithy, as Aristo said, or surgery, is peculiarly ours, but all such things exist or rather take their name in connection with the person who dwells in them or possesses them. For man, as Plato says, is not an earthly and immovable but heavenly plant, the head making the body erect as from a root, and turned up to heaven.916 And so Hercules said well,

§ v. If we find ourselves in real trouble or facing hardships, we should find comfort and peace of mind by focusing on the actual blessings that remain with us, easing our external struggles through personal happiness. Regarding those things that aren’t truly evil but only seem so due to our imagination and unfounded fears, we should approach them like we do with children who are scared of masks: by bringing them closer, letting them hold them, and examining them, we teach them not to be afraid at all. Similarly, by applying reason, we can uncover the flaws, emptiness, and exaggerations of our fears. For example, consider your current separation from what you see as your homeland. In essence, no land, house, field, or workshop, as Aristo pointed out, truly belongs to us; rather, these things are named in relation to the person who lives in or owns them. Man, as Plato said, isn’t a fixed, earthly being but rather a celestial entity, with the head lifting the body like a root directed towards the heavens.916 And so Hercules spoke wisely,

"Am I Argive or Theban? I don't brag." To belong to just one town, every tower "That which belongs to Greece is my country."

But better still said Socrates, that he was not an Athenian or Greek, but a citizen of the world (as a man might say he was a Rhodian or Corinthian), for he did not confine himself to Sunium, or Tænarum, or the Ceraunian mountains.

But better still, Socrates said that he was not just an Athenian or Greek, but a citizen of the world (as someone might say they were from Rhodes or Corinth), because he didn’t limit himself to Sunium, or Tænarum, or the Ceraunian mountains.

"Do you see the endless expanse of sky above, "And how it cradles the earth in its gentle arms?"

These are the boundaries of our country, nor is there either exile or stranger or foreigner in these, where there is the same fire, water and air, the same rulers controllers and presidents, the sun the moon and the morning star, the same laws to all, under one appointment and ordinance the summer and winter solstices, the equinoxes, Pleias and Arcturus, the seasons of sowing and planting; where there is one king and ruler, God, who has under his jurisdiction the beginning and middle and end of everything, and travels round and does everything in a regular way in accordance with nature; and in his wake to punish all transgressions of the divine law follows Justice, whom 382all men naturally invoke in dealing with one another as fellow citizens.

These are the borders of our country, where there are no exiles, strangers, or foreigners; here, we share the same fire, water, and air, the same leaders and presidents, the sun, the moon, and the morning star, and the same laws apply to everyone. Under one appointment and ordinance, we have the summer and winter solstices, the equinoxes, the Pleiades, and Arcturus, marking the seasons for planting and harvesting. There is one king and ruler, God, who oversees the beginning, middle, and end of everything, and acts consistently according to nature. Following him, Justice punishes all violations of divine law, which all people naturally call upon when interacting with one another as fellow citizens.

§ vi. As to your not dwelling at Sardis, that is nothing. Neither do all the Athenians dwell at Colyttus, nor all the Corinthians at Craneum, nor all the Lacedæmonians at Pitane. Do you consider all those Athenians strangers and exiles who removed from Melita to Diomea, where they call the month Metageitnion,917 and keep the festival Metageitnia to commemorate their migration, and gladly and gaily accept and are content with their neighbourhood with other people? Surely you would not. What part of the inhabited world or of the whole earth is very far distant from another part, seeing that mathematicians teach us that the whole earth is a mere point compared to heaven? But we, like ants or bees, if we get banished from one ant-hill or hive are in sore distress and feel lost, not knowing or having learnt to make and consider all things our own, as indeed they are. And yet we laugh at the stupidity of one who asserts that the moon shines brighter at Athens than at Corinth, though in a sort we are in the same case ourselves, when in a strange land we look on the earth, the sea, the air, the sky, as if we doubted whether or not they were different from those we had been accustomed to. For nature makes us free and unrestrained, but we bind and confine immure and force ourselves into small and scanty space. Then too we laugh at the Persian kings, who, if the story be true, drink only of the water of the Choaspes, thus making the rest of the world waterless as far as they are concerned, but when we migrate to other places, we desire the water of the Cephisus, or we yearn for the Eurotas, or Taygetus, or Parnassus, and so make the whole world for ourselves houseless and homeless.

§ vi. As for not living in Sardis, that’s no big deal. Not all Athenians live in Colyttus, nor do all Corinthians live in Craneum, nor all Spartans in Pitane. Do you think of all those Athenians who moved from Melita to Diomea, where they celebrate the month Metageitnion,917 and hold the Metageitnia festival to remember their migration, as strangers and exiles? Surely not. What part of the inhabited world is really far from another, since mathematicians tell us that the whole earth is just a tiny point compared to heaven? But we, like ants or bees, feel deeply distressed and lost when we’re kicked out of one ant-hill or hive, not knowing how to make everything our own, even though it truly is. And yet, we laugh at the foolishness of someone who claims that the moon shines brighter in Athens than in Corinth, even though we’re in a similar situation when we find ourselves in a foreign land, regarding the earth, the sea, the air, and the sky as if we’re unsure whether they’re different from what we’re used to. Nature makes us free and unrestricted, yet we confine and limit ourselves to a small space. We also laugh at the Persian kings, who, if the story is to be believed, drink only from the water of the Choaspes, making the rest of the world seem like a desert to them. But when we move elsewhere, we crave the water of the Cephisus, or yearn for the Eurotas, Taygetus, or Parnassus, effectively turning the whole world into a place where we feel houseless and homeless.

§ vii. Some Egyptians, who migrated to Ethiopia because of the anger and wrath of their king, to those who begged them to return to their wives and children very immodestly exposed their persons, saying that they would never be in want of wives or children while so provided. It is far more becoming and less low to say that whoever 383has the good fortune to be provided with the few necessaries of life is nowhere a stranger, nowhere without home and hearth, only he must have besides these prudence and sense, as an anchor and helm, that he may be able to moor himself in any harbour. For a person indeed who has lost his wealth it is not easy quickly to get another fortune, but every city is at once his country to the man who knows how to make it such, and has the roots by which he can live and thrive and get acclimatized in every place, as was the case with Themistocles and Demetrius of Phalerum. The latter after his banishment became a great friend of Ptolemy at Alexandria, and not only passed his days in abundance, but also sent gifts to the Athenians. And Themistocles, who was publicly entertained at the king's expense, is stated to have said to his wife and children, "We should have been ruined, if we had not been ruined." And so Diogenes the Cynic to the person who said to him, "The people of Sinope have condemned you to banishment from Pontus," replied, "And I have condemned them to stay in Pontus, 'by the high cliffs of the inhospitable sea.'"918[918] And Stratonicus asked his host at Seriphus, for what offence exile was the appointed punishment, and being told that they punished rogues by exile, said, "Why then are not you a rogue, to escape from this hole of a place?" For the comic poet says they get their crop of figs down there with slings, and that the island is very barely supplied with the necessaries of life.

§ vii. Some Egyptians moved to Ethiopia due to the anger of their king. When asked by those pleading for them to return to their families, they shamelessly revealed themselves, claiming they would never lack for wives or children as long as they had what they needed. It is much more dignified and respectable to say that anyone who has the basic necessities of life is never truly a stranger or homeless; they just need to have wisdom and good judgment, like an anchor and a steering wheel, so they can settle anywhere. For someone who has lost their wealth, it’s not easy to regain fortune quickly; however, every city can become home to someone who knows how to adapt and has the means to survive and thrive, just like Themistocles and Demetrius of Phalerum. The latter became a close ally of Ptolemy in Alexandria after his exile, enjoying plenty and even sending gifts to the Athenians. Themistocles, who was hosted by the king at his expense, reportedly told his wife and children, "We would have been destroyed if we hadn’t been destroyed." Similarly, when someone told Diogenes the Cynic that the people of Sinope had exiled him from Pontus, he replied, "And I have exiled them to stay in Pontus, 'by the high cliffs of the inhospitable sea.'"918[918] Stratonicus asked his host on Seriphus why exile was the punishment, and upon learning it was for rogues, he said, "Why aren’t you a rogue, to get away from this dreadful place?" As the comic poet remarks, they have to collect their figs down there with slings, and the island barely has the essentials for life.

§ viii. For if you look at the real facts and shun idle fancy, he that has one city is a stranger and foreigner in all others. For it does not seem to such a one fair and just to leave his own city and dwell in another. "It has been your lot to be a citizen of Sparta, see that you adorn your native city," whether it be inglorious, or unhealthy, or disturbed with factions, or has its affairs in disorder. But the person whom fortune has deprived of his own city, she allows to make his home in any he fancies. That was an excellent precept of Pythagoras, "Choose the best kind of life, custom will make it easy." So too it is wise and profitable to say here, "Choose the best and pleasantest 384city, time will make it your country, and a country that will not always distract you and trouble you and give you various orders such as, 'Contribute so much money, Go on an embassy to Rome, Entertain the prefect, Perform public duties.'" If a person in his senses and not altogether silly were to think of these things, he would prefer to live in exile in some island, like Gryarus or Cinarus,

§ viii. If you look at the actual facts and avoid fanciful thinking, someone who has one city is a stranger and outsider everywhere else. It doesn’t seem fair or just for such a person to leave their own city and settle in another. "You’ve been given the chance to be a citizen of Sparta; make sure to improve your hometown," whether it’s unremarkable, unhealthy, troubled by conflict, or in disarray. But for someone who has lost their city, luck allows them to live wherever they wish. Pythagoras had a great saying: "Choose the best kind of life; habit will make it easier." Similarly, it’s wise and beneficial to say here, "Choose the best and most enjoyable 384 city; time will make it feel like home, and a home that won’t constantly distract you, bother you, or demand things like, 'Contribute money, go on a mission to Rome, host the prefect, fulfill public duties.'" If someone who is sensible, rather than completely foolish, thought about these things, they would prefer to live in exile on some island, like Gryarus or Cinarus,

"Brutal and unproductive, poorly rewarding farming,"

and that not in dejection and wailing, or using the language of those women in Simonides,

and not in sadness and crying, or using the words of those women in Simonides,

"I'm trapped by the dark, roaring sea." That foams all around,"

but he will rather be of the mind of Philip, who when he was thrown in wrestling, and turned round, and noticed the mark his body made in the dust, said, "O Hercules, what a little part of the earth I have by nature, though I desire all the world!"

but he would rather think like Philip, who when he was thrown in wrestling, turned around and saw the mark his body made in the dust, said, "O Hercules, what a tiny piece of the earth I have by nature, even though I want the whole world!"

§ ix. I think also you have seen Naxos, or at any rate Hyria, which is close here. But the former was the home of Ephialtes and Otus, and the latter was the dwelling-place of Orion. And Alcmæon, when fleeing from the Furies, so the poets tell us, dwelt in a place recently formed by the silting of the Achelous;919 but I think he chose that little spot to dwell in ease and quiet, merely to avoid political disturbances and factions, and those furies informers. And the Emperor Tiberius lived the last seven years of his life in the island of Capreæ, and the sacred governing power of the world enclosed in his breast during all that time never changed its abode. But the incessant and constant cares of empire, coming from all sides, made not that island repose of his pure and complete. But he who can disembark on a small island, and get rid of great troubles, is a miserable man, if he cannot often say and sing to himself those lines of Pindar, "To love the slender cypress, and to leave the Cretan pastures lying near Ida. I have but little land, where I grow strong, and have nothing to do with sorrow or faction,"920 or the ordinances of princes, 385or public duties in political emergencies, or state functions hard to get off.

§ ix. I believe you've seen Naxos, or at least Hyria, which is nearby. Naxos was the home of Ephialtes and Otus, while Hyria was where Orion lived. Alcmæon, when he was fleeing from the Furies, as the poets say, stayed in a spot created by the silt from the Achelous;919 but I think he chose that little place to live in peace and quiet just to avoid political chaos and conflicts, along with those pesky informants. Emperor Tiberius spent the last seven years of his life on the island of Capreæ, and the sacred power of the world that he held inside him never moved during that time. However, the constant pressures of ruling the empire from all sides did not allow that island to be a place of complete tranquility for him. Yet, anyone who can land on a small island to escape major troubles is a miserable person if they can't often recite and sing to themselves those lines from Pindar: "To love the slender cypress, and to leave the Cretan pastures lying near Ida. I have but little land, where I grow strong, and have nothing to do with sorrow or faction,"920 or with the decrees of rulers, 385or responsibilities during political crises, or complex state functions.

§ x. For if that seems a good saying of Callimachus, "Do not measure wisdom by a Persian rope," much less should we measure happiness by ropes and parasangs, and if we inhabit an island containing 200 furlongs only, and not (like Sicily) four days' sail round, ought we to wail and lament as if we were very unfortunate? For how does plenty of room bring about an easy life? Have you not heard Tantalus saying in the play,921

§ x. If Callimachus's saying, "Don't measure wisdom with a Persian rope," holds true, then we definitely shouldn't measure happiness with ropes and parasangs. And if we live on an island that's only 200 furlongs around, rather than something like Sicily, which takes four days to sail around, should we really be crying and feeling sorry for ourselves as if we were really unlucky? How does having a lot of space lead to an easier life? Haven't you heard Tantalus say in the play,921

"I plant a field that takes twelve days to walk around, The Berecyntian region,

but shortly after he says,

but soon after he says,

"My fortunes, which were once as high as heaven, Now to the ground have fallen, and do say to me, "Don’t overvalue material things."

And Nausithous leaving the spacious Hyperia because of the proximity of the Cyclopes, and migrating to an island "far from all enterprising men,"922 and living an unsocial life,

And Nausithous left the large Hyperia because the Cyclopes were nearby, moving to an island "far from all enterprising men,"922 and lived a solitary life,

"Besides men by the stormy sea,"923

yet contrived to make the life of his citizens very pleasant. And the Cyclades were first inhabited by the sons of Minos, and afterwards by the sons of Codrus and Neleus, though foolish people now think they are punished if they are exiled to them. And yet what island used as a place of exile is not of larger extent than Scillus, where Xenophon after his military service saw a comfortable old age?924 And the Academy, a small place bought for only 3,000 drachmæ,925 was the domicile of Plato and Xenocrates and Polemo, who taught and lived there all their lives, except one day every year, when Xenocrates went to Athens to grace the festival of Dionysus, so they said, and to see the new plays exhibited. And Theocritus of Chios twitted 386Aristotle with loving to live at the courts of Philip and Alexander, and preferring to dwell at the mouth of the Borborus to dwelling in the Academy. For there is a river near Pella that the Macedonians call Borborus. As to islands Homer seems to sing their praise, and recommend them to us as if on purpose, as

yet managed to make life very enjoyable for his citizens. The Cyclades were initially settled by the sons of Minos and later by the sons of Codrus and Neleus, though some foolish people today believe they are being punished if they are sent into exile there. Yet, what island used for exile is not larger than Scillus, where Xenophon enjoyed a comfortable old age after his military service?924 The Academy, a small piece of land bought for only 3,000 drachmæ,925 was the home of Plato, Xenocrates, and Polemo, who lived and taught there their entire lives except for one day every year when Xenocrates would go to Athens to celebrate the festival of Dionysus and to watch the new plays. Theocritus of Chios teased 386Aristotle for preferring to live at the courts of Philip and Alexander, choosing to stay at the mouth of the Borborus rather than in the Academy. There is a river near Pella that the Macedonians call Borborus. As for islands, Homer seems to sing their praises, endorsing them to us as if intentionally, as

"She arrived in Lemnos, the town of sacred Thoas;"926

and,

and,

"What Lesbos offers is the seat of the immortals;"927

and,

and,

"He captured high Scyros, citadel" Of Enyeus; __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

and,

and,

"And those who came from Dulichium and from __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, The sacred islands known as the Echinades, That lies across the sea opposite Elis; 929

and of the illustrious men that dwelt in islands he mentions Æolus the favourite of the gods, and Odysseus most wise, and Ajax most brave, and Alcinous most kind to strangers.

and of the famous men who lived on islands, he mentions Æolus, favored by the gods, and Odysseus, the wisest, and Ajax, the bravest, and Alcinous, the kindest to strangers.

§ xi. When Zeno learned that the only ship he had left was with all its freight lost at sea, he said, "Fortune, you deal kindly with me, confining me to my threadbare cloak and the life of a philosopher." And a man not altogether silly, or madly in love with crowds, might, I think, not blame fortune for confining him in an island, but might even praise her for relieving him from weariness and anxiety, and wanderings in foreign countries, and perils by sea, and the uproar of the forum, and for giving him truly a secure, quiet, undistracted and private life, putting him as it were inside a circle in which everything necessary for him was contained. For what island has not a house, a promenade, a bath, and fish and hares for those who love fishing and field-sports? And the greatest blessing, quiet, which others frequently pant for, you can freely enjoy.930 And whereas in the world,930 when men are playing at dice or otherwise enjoying the privacy of their homes, informers and busybodies hunt them up and pursue them from their 387houses and gardens in the suburbs, and drag them by force to the forum and court, in an island no one comes to bother one or dun one or to borrow money, or to beg one to be surety for him or canvass for him: only one's best friends and intimates come to visit one out of good will and affection, and the rest of one's life is a sort of holy retirement to whoever wishes or has learnt to live the life of leisure. But he who thinks those happy who are always scouring the country, and pass most of their lives in inns and ferryboats, is like a person who thinks the planets happier than fixed stars. And yet every planet keeps its order, rolling in one sphere, as in an island. For, as Heraclitus says, the sun will never deviate from its bounds, for if it did, the Furies, who are the ministers of Justice, would find it out.

§ xi. When Zeno found out that the only ship he had left sank with all its cargo, he said, "Fortune, you're treating me well by limiting me to my worn-out cloak and the life of a philosopher." A person who isn’t completely foolish or obsessed with crowds might not blame fortune for isolating him on an island. In fact, he might even appreciate her for freeing him from exhaustion and stress, endless travels, dangers at sea, and the chaos of public life, while providing him with a genuinely secure, peaceful, focused, and private existence—essentially placing him in a space where everything he needs is available. What island doesn’t have a home, a place to walk, a bath, and fish and game for those who enjoy fishing and hunting? And the greatest blessing—peace—something others often yearn for, you can enjoy freely.930 Meanwhile, in the outside world,930 when people are just relaxing at home or playing games, informers and nosy people track them down, dragging them from their 387houses and gardens in the suburbs to the hustle and bustle of the forum and court. In contrast, on an island, no one bothers you to collect debts, ask for loans, or pressure you to act as a guarantor. Only your closest friends and loved ones visit you out of genuine kindness and affection, while the rest of your life feels like a serene retreat for anyone who wants to embrace a leisurely lifestyle. Those who believe that people constantly traveling and spending most of their lives in inns and on ferries are the lucky ones resemble someone who thinks planets are happier than fixed stars. Yet every planet follows its own path, moving smoothly within its orbit, just like being on an island. Because, as Heraclitus says, the sun will never stray from its course; if it did, the Furies, who are the agents of Justice, would notice it.

§ xii. Let us use such and similar language, my friend, and harp upon it, to those who are banished to an island, and are debarred all access with others

§ xii. Let's talk like this, my friend, and keep going on about it, to those who are stuck on an island and cut off from everyone else.

"By the sea waves, which many keep away from." 931

But you who are not tied down to one spot, but only forbidden to live in one, have by that prohibition liberty to go to all others. Moreover to the considerations, I am not in office, or a member of the senate, or an umpire in the games, you may oppose these, I do not belong to any faction, I have no large sums to spend, I have not to dance attendance at the doors of the prefect, it is no odds to me who has got by lot the province, whether he is hot-tempered or an objectionable person. But just as Archilochus overlooked the fruitful fields and vineyards of Thasos, and abused that island as rocky and uneven, and said of it,

But you, who aren't stuck in one place and are only banned from living in one, actually have the freedom to go anywhere else. In addition, since I'm not in office, or a senator, or a referee in the games, you can challenge these points. I’m not part of any political group, I don't have a lot of money to spend, and I don't have to wait around at the prefect's door. It doesn't matter to me who got the province by chance, whether they're hot-headed or difficult. Just like Archilochus overlooked the fertile fields and vineyards of Thasos, criticizing the island for being rocky and uneven, and said of it,

"It stands like a donkey's back, topped with wild forest,"

so we, fixing our eyes only on one aspect of exile, its inglorious state, overlook its freedom from cares, its leisure, its liberty. And yet people thought the kings of Persia happy, because they passed their winter in Babylon, their summer in Media, and the pleasant season of spring at Susa. So can the exile be present at the Eleusinian mysteries, at the festival of Dionysus at Athens, at the Nemean 388games at Argos, at the Pythian games at Delphi, and can pass on and be a spectator of the Isthmian and Corinthian games, if he is fond of sight-seeing; and if not, he has leisure, can walk about, read, sleep without being disturbed, and can say like Diogenes, "Aristotle has to dine when Philip thinks fit, Diogenes can dine at any time he himself chooses," having no business, or magistrate, or prefect, to put him out of his general habits of living.

So we, focusing only on one side of exile, its unglamorous condition, overlook its freedom from worries, its relaxation, and its independence. Yet people considered the kings of Persia fortunate because they spent winter in Babylon, summer in Media, and enjoyed the pleasant spring in Susa. Likewise, an exile can attend the Eleusinian mysteries, the festival of Dionysus in Athens, the Nemean 388 games in Argos, the Pythian games in Delphi, and can continue on to watch the Isthmian and Corinthian games if they enjoy sightseeing; and if not, they have leisure time to stroll, read, and sleep without interruptions. They can declare like Diogenes, "Aristotle has to eat when Philip decides, but I can eat whenever I want," having no obligations, magistrate, or prefect to disrupt their way of life.

§ xiii. And so it is that you will find few of the wisest and most intelligent men buried in their own countries, but most (even without any compulsion) have themselves weighed anchor, and transferred their course, and removed, some to Athens, some from it. For who ever bestowed such encomium upon his country as Euripides did in the following lines?

§ xiii. And so it is that you will find few of the wisest and smartest people buried in their own countries; instead, most (even without any pressure) have set sail, changed their direction, and moved, some to Athens, some away from it. For who has ever praised his country as much as Euripides did in the following lines?

"First, we are not a race brought in from other places, But are indigenous when all other cities Are, like draftsmen, moved from one location to another, And are brought in from other places. And, ma'am, If it's not out of line to brag, We have a pleasantly balanced sky above us, A climate that's neither too hot nor too cold. And all the best things in Greece or Asia We do get our supplies as a draw here.932

And yet the author of these lines went to Macedonia, and lived all the latter part of his life at the court of Archelaus. And of course you have heard the following epitaph;

And yet the author of these lines went to Macedonia and spent the rest of his life at the court of Archelaus. And of course, you've heard the following epitaph;

"Here lies the son of Euphorion, Athenian Aeschylus, "To those whom death visited in corn-producing Gela."

For he, like Simonides before him, went to Sicily. And many have changed the commencing words of Herodotus, "This is the setting forth of the history of Herodotus of Halicarnassus" into "Herodotus of Thurii." For he migrated to Thurii, and participated in that colony. As to the divine and sacred spirit of the Muses, the poet of the Trojan war, Homer, did not many cities claim him as theirs, because he did not cry up one city only? And Hospitable Zeus has many great honours.

For he, like Simonides before him, went to Sicily. Many have changed the opening words of Herodotus, “This is the setting forth of the history of Herodotus of Halicarnassus” to “Herodotus of Thurii.” He moved to Thurii and was part of that colony. As for the divine and sacred spirit of the Muses, didn’t many cities claim the poet of the Trojan War, Homer, because he didn’t promote just one city? And Hospitable Zeus receives many great honors.

389§ xiv. And if anyone shall say that these pursued glory and honour, go to the philosophers, and their schools and lectures, consider those at the Lyceum, the Academy, the Porch, the Palladium, the Odeum. If you admire and prefer the Peripatetic school, Aristotle was a native of Stagira, Theophrastus of Eresus, Strato of Lampsacus, Glyco of Troas, Aristo of Ceos, Critolaus of Phaselis. If you prefer the Stoic school, Zeno was a native of Cittium, Cleanthes of Assus, Chrysippus of Soli, Diogenes of Babylon, Antipater of Tarsus; and the Athenian Archidemus migrated to the country of the Parthians, and left at Babylon a succession of the Stoic school. Who exiled these men? Nobody; it was their own pursuit of quiet, of which no one who is famous or powerful can get much at home, that made them teach us this by their practice, while they taught us other things by their precepts. And even nowadays most excellent and renowned persons live in strange lands, not in consequence of being expelled or banished, but at their own option, to avoid business and distracting cares, and the want of leisure which their own country would bring them. For it seems to me that the Muses aided our old writers to complete their finest and most esteemed works by calling in exile as a fellow-worker. Thus Thucydides the Athenian wrote the history of the war between the Peloponnesians and the Athenians in Thrace near the forest of Scapte, Xenophon wrote at Scillus in Elis, Philistus in Epirus, Timæus of Tauromenium at Athens, Androtion of Athens at Megara, and Bacchylides the poet933 in Peloponnesus. All these and many more, though exiled from their country, did not despair or give themselves up to dejection, but so happy was their disposition that they considered exile a resource given them by fortune, whereby they obtained universal fame after their deaths, whereas no memorial is left of those who were factious against them and banished them.

389§ xiv. And if anyone claims that these people sought glory and honor, look to the philosophers, their schools, and lectures—think of those at the Lyceum, the Academy, the Stoa, the Palladium, the Odeum. If you admire the Peripatetic school, Aristotle came from Stagira, Theophrastus from Eresus, Strato from Lampsacus, Glyco from Troas, Aristo from Ceos, and Critolaus from Phaselis. If you're more inclined to the Stoic school, Zeno was from Cittium, Cleanthes from Assus, Chrysippus from Soli, Diogenes from Babylon, and Antipater from Tarsus; the Athenian Archidemus moved to the land of the Parthians and left a succession of the Stoic school in Babylon. Who exiled these men? Nobody; it was their own desire for peace—something that few famous or powerful people can find at home—that led them to share this lesson through their actions, while teaching us other ideas through their teachings. Even today, many outstanding and respected individuals live in foreign lands, not due to expulsion or banishment, but by choice, to escape the busyness and distractions that their home country imposes. It seems to me that the Muses inspired our ancient writers to create their best and most celebrated works in exile. For instance, Thucydides the Athenian wrote the history of the war between the Peloponnesians and the Athenians in Thrace near the Scapte forest, Xenophon wrote at Scillus in Elis, Philistus in Epirus, Timæus of Tauromenium in Athens, Androtion of Athens in Megara, and Bacchylides the poet in the Peloponnesus. All these, and many more, despite being exiled from their homeland, did not lose hope or fall into despair, but were so positive in their outlook that they saw exile as an opportunity given to them by fate, allowing them to achieve widespread fame after their deaths, while no legacy remains of those who opposed them and caused their banishment.

§ xv. He therefore is ridiculous who thinks that any ignominy attaches itself to exile. What say you? Was Diogenes without glory, whom Alexander saw basking in the sun, and stopped to ask if he wanted anything, and when he 390answered, "Nothing, but that you would get a little out of my light," Alexander, astonished at his spirit, said to his friends, "If I were not Alexander, I would be Diogenes." Was Camillus without glory when banished from Rome, of which he is now accounted the second founder? And indeed Themistocles did not lose by his exile the glory he had obtained among the Greeks, but he added to it among the barbarians, and there is no one so without honour, so ignoble, who would prefer to be Leobates who indicted him rather than Themistocles the exile, or Clodius who banished Cicero rather than the banished one, or Aristophon the accuser rather than Timotheus who got driven by him from his country.

§ xv. It's laughable to think that there's any shame in being exiled. What do you think? Was Diogenes any less remarkable when Alexander saw him lounging in the sun and stopped to ask if he needed anything? When Diogenes replied, "Just that you would step out of my light," Alexander, impressed by his attitude, told his friends, "If I weren't Alexander, I would want to be Diogenes." Was Camillus any less notable when he was banished from Rome, which he is now recognized as the second founder of? In fact, Themistocles didn’t lose the respect he gained among the Greeks during his exile; he actually enhanced it among the barbarians. No one, no matter how dishonorable, would choose to be Leobates, who indicted him, over Themistocles the exile, or Clodius, who exiled Cicero, rather than the banished Cicero himself, or Aristophon, the accuser, instead of Timotheus, who was driven from his homeland by him.

§ xvi. But since a good many are moved by the lines of Euripides, who seems to bring a strong indictment against exile, let us see what it is he says in each question and answer about it.

§ xvi. But since many are influenced by the lines of Euripides, who seems to strongly criticize exile, let’s take a look at what he says in each question and answer about it.

Jocasta. What does it mean to be an exile? Is it really that painful? Polynices. It's truly terrible, even worse than it sounds. Jocasta. What does it look like? What is difficult for exiles? Polynices. The worst part is that they have no freedom. Jocasta. It's a slave's life to not be able to speak your mind! Polynices. So, one has to tolerate their masters' foolishness.934

But this is not a right or true estimate.935 For first of all, not to say out all one thinks is not the action of a slave but of a sensible man, in times and matters that require reticence and silence, as Euripides himself has said elsewhere better,

But this isn’t an accurate or true assessment.935 For starters, holding back your thoughts isn’t the behavior of a slave but of a wise person, especially in situations that call for discretion and silence, as Euripides himself has expressed better elsewhere.

"Be quiet when it's appropriate, and speak up when it's safe."

Then as for the follies of one's masters, one has to put up with them just as much in one's own country as in exile. Indeed, more frequently have the former reason to fear that the powerful in cities will act unjustly to them either through calumny or violence. But his greatest and absurdest error is that he takes away from exiles freedom of speech. It is wonderful, if Theodorus had no freedom of speech, that when Lysimachus the king said to him, "Did 391not your country cast you out because of your character?" replied, "Yes, as Semele cast out Dionysus, when unable to bear him any longer." And when he showed him Telesphorus in a cage,936 with his eyes scooped out, and his nose and ears and tongue cut off, and said to him, "This is how I treat those that act ill to me." * *937 And had not Diogenes freedom of speech, who, when he visited Philip's camp just as he was on the eve of offering battle to the Greeks, and was taken before the king as a spy, told him he had come to see his insatiable folly, who was going shortly to stake his dominions and life on a mere die. And did not Hannibal the Carthaginian use freedom of speech to Antiochus, though he was an exile, and Antiochus a king? For as a favourable occasion presented itself he urged the king to attack the enemy, and when after sacrifice he reported that the entrails forbade it, Hannibal chided him and said, "You listen rather to what flesh tells you than to the instruction of a man of experience." Nor does exile deprive geometricians or grammarians of their freedom of speech, or prevent their discussing what they know and have learnt. Why should it then good and worthy men? It is meanness everywhere that stops a man's speech, ties and gags his tongue, and forces him to be silent. But what are the next lines of Euripides?

Then when it comes to the foolishness of our leaders, we have to deal with it as much at home as in exile. In fact, those at home often have more reason to worry that the powerful in their cities will treat them unfairly, either through slander or violence. But the biggest and silliest mistake is that he thinks exiles lack freedom of speech. It’s amazing that if Theodorus had no freedom of speech, he could still respond to King Lysimachus when asked, “Didn’t your country reject you because of your character?” by answering, “Yes, just as Semele cast out Dionysus when she could no longer bear him.” And when Lysimachus showed him Telesphorus in a cage—with his eyes gouged out, and his nose, ears, and tongue cut off—and said, “This is how I deal with those who wrong me,” * * Did Diogenes not have freedom of speech either? When he visited Philip's camp just as Philip was about to go into battle against the Greeks and was brought before the king as a spy, he told him he had come to see his insatiable folly of risking his kingdom and life on a mere roll of the dice. And didn’t Hannibal the Carthaginian speak his mind to Antiochus, even though he was an exile and Antiochus was a king? When a good opportunity came up, he urged the king to attack the enemy, and when after sacrificing an animal the signs were unfavorable, Hannibal scolded him, saying, “You pay more attention to what the flesh tells you than to the advice of an experienced man.” Exile doesn’t take away the freedom of speech from mathematicians or grammarians, nor does it stop them from discussing what they know and have learned. So why should it for good and honorable people? It’s cowardice everywhere that silences a person, ties up their tongue, and forces them into silence. But what are the next lines of Euripides?

Jocasta. They say that hopes keep the hearts of exiles alive. Polynices. Hopes have a charming smile, but they still take time. 938

But this is an accusation against folly rather than exile. For it is not those who have learnt and know how to enjoy the present, but those who ever hang on the future, and hope after what they have not, that float as it were on hope as on a raft, though they never get beyond the walls.939

But this is a criticism of foolishness rather than banishment. It's not the people who have learned and know how to appreciate the present, but those who constantly dwell on the future and long for what they don't have, who float on hope like it's a raft, even though they never get beyond the walls.939

Jocasta. But didn’t your father’s friends help you at all? Polynices. Count yourself lucky! Friends are not helpful in tough times. Jocasta. Didn't your noble birth improve your situation? Polynices. It’s not good to desire. Being born didn’t provide me with any food.940

392 But it was ungrateful in Polynices thus to rail against exile as discrediting his good birth and robbing him of friends, for it was on account of his good birth that he was deemed worthy of a royal bride though an exile, and he came to fight supported by a band of friends and allies, a great force, as he himself admits a little later,

392 But it was ungrateful of Polynices to complain about exile as if it discredited his noble lineage and took away his friends. It was actually because of his noble birth that he was considered deserving of a royal bride even while in exile, and he came to fight backed by a group of friends and allies, a significant force, as he himself acknowledges shortly after.

"Many of the princes of the Danai And from Mycenae, I have with me, bestowing A sad but necessary kindness towards me."941

Nor was there any more justice in the lament of his mother:—

Nor was there any more justice in the cry of his mother:—

"I never lit the wedding torch for you." In customary marriage, neither did Ismenus. Provide you with the typical serious bath."942

She ought to have been pleased and content to hear that her son dwelt in such a palace as that at Argos, and in lamenting that the nuptial torch was not lit, and that he had not had the usual bath in the river Ismenus, as though there was no water or fire at Argos for wedded people, she lays on exile the evils really caused by pride and stupidity.

She should have been happy and satisfied to know that her son lived in such a palace as that at Argos, but instead, she mourns that the wedding torch wasn’t lit and that he hadn’t gone through the traditional bath in the river Ismenus, as if there were no water or fire at Argos for newlyweds. She places the blame for her troubles on exile, which are actually caused by pride and ignorance.

§ xvii. But exile, you will say, is a matter of reproach. It may be among fools, who also jeer at the beggar, the bald man, the dwarf, aye, and even the stranger and resident alien. But those who are not carried away in that manner admire good men, whether they are poor, or strangers or exiles. Do we not see that all men adore the temple of Theseus as well as the Parthenon and Eleusinium? And yet Theseus was an exile from Athens, though it was owing to him that Athens is now inhabited, and he was banished from a city which he did not merely dwell in, but had himself built. And what glory is left to Eleusis, if we are ashamed of Eumolpus, who migrated from Thrace, and taught the Greeks (as he still teaches them) the mysteries? And who was the father of Codrus that reigned at Athens? Was it not Melanthus, an exile from Messene? And do you not praise the answer of Antisthenes to the person who told him that his mother was a Phrygian, "So also is the mother of the gods." If you 393are twitted then with exile, why do you not answer, "The father of the glorious victor Hercules was an exile." And Cadmus, the grandfather of Dionysus, when he was sent from home to find Europa, and never came back, "though a Phœnician born he changed his country,"943 and migrated to Thebes, and became944 the grandfather of "Dionysus, who rejoices in the cry of Evoe, the exciter of women, who delights in frantic honours." As for what Æschylus obscurely hints at in the line,

§ xvii. But you may say that exile is something to be ashamed of. It might be among fools, who also mock the beggar, the bald man, the dwarf, and even the foreigner and resident alien. However, those who think clearly admire good people, whether they are poor, foreign, or exiled. Don’t we see that all people admire the temple of Theseus as well as the Parthenon and Eleusinium? Yet Theseus was an exile from Athens, even though he was the one who made Athens livable, and he was banished from a city he didn’t just live in, but had built himself. And what honor is left to Eleusis if we are ashamed of Eumolpus, who came from Thrace and taught the Greeks (as he still teaches them) the mysteries? And who was the father of Codrus, the king of Athens? Wasn't it Melanthus, an exile from Messene? And do you not admire Antisthenes' response to the person who told him that his mother was a Phrygian: "So is the mother of the gods." If you’re teased about being exiled, why not respond, "The father of the glorious hero Hercules was an exile"? And Cadmus, the grandfather of Dionysus, when he was sent away to search for Europa and never returned, "even though he was born a Phoenician, he changed his country" and moved to Thebes, eventually becoming the grandfather of "Dionysus, who rejoices in the cry of Evoe, the one who inspires women and loves wild honors." As for what Æschylus vaguely hints at in the line,

"Apollo, the pure god, banished from heaven,"

let me keep a religious silence, as Herodotus945 says. And Empedocles commences his system of philosophy as follows, "It is an ordinance of necessity, an ancient decree of the gods, when anyone stains his hands with crime and murder, the long-lived demons get hold of him, so that he wanders away from the gods for thirty thousand years. Such is my condition now, that of an exile and wanderer from the gods." In these words he not only speaks of himself, but points out that all of us men similarly are strangers and foreigners and exiles in this world. For he says, "O men, it is not blood or a compounded spirit that made the being or beginning of the soul, but it is your earth-born and mortal body that is made up of these." He calls speciously by the mildest of names the birth of the soul that has come from elsewhere a living in a strange country. But the truth is the soul is an exile and wanderer, being driven about by the divine decrees and laws, and then, as in some sea-girt island, gets joined to the body like an oyster to its shell, as Plato says, because it cannot call to mind or remember from what honour and greatness of happiness it migrated, not from Sardis to Athens, nor from Corinth to Lemnos or Scyros, but exchanging heaven and the moon for earth and life upon earth, if it shifts from place to place for ever so short a time it is put out and feels strange, and fades away like a dying plant. But although one soil is more suitable to a 394plant than another, and it thrives and grows better on such a soil, yet no situation can rob a man of his happiness or virtue or sense. It was in prison that Anaxagoras wrote his squaring of the circle, and that Socrates, even after drinking the hemlock, talked philosophically, and begged his friends to be philosophers, and was esteemed happy by them. On the other hand, Phaëthon and Tantalus, though they got up to heaven, fell into the greatest misfortunes through their folly, as the poets tell us.

let me maintain a respectful silence, as Herodotus945 says. And Empedocles starts his philosophy with these words: "It is a necessity, an ancient decree of the gods, that when anyone commits crime and murder, the long-lived demons seize him, making him wander away from the gods for thirty thousand years. This is my current state, that of an exile and wanderer from the gods." In these words, he not only reflects on himself but also highlights that we all, as humans, are similarly strangers and foreigners in this world. He states, "O men, it is not blood or a mixed spirit that creates the being or origin of the soul, but it is your earthly and mortal body that is composed of these." He cleverly refers to the soul's journey from elsewhere as living in a foreign land. However, the truth is that the soul is an exile and wanderer, compelled by divine decrees and laws, and then, as if on some island surrounded by the sea, it becomes attached to the body like an oyster to its shell, as Plato says, because it cannot remember from what honor and happiness it descended—not from Sardis to Athens, nor from Corinth to Lemnos or Scyros, but trading heaven and the moon for earth and life on earth. Even if it moves from place to place for just a brief moment, it feels out of place and withers away like a dying plant. Yet, while some soils may suit a plant better than others, helping it to thrive, no circumstance can take away a person's happiness, virtue, or awareness. Anaxagoras wrote his theory on squaring the circle while in prison, and Socrates, even after drinking the hemlock, discussed philosophical ideas and urged his friends to embrace philosophy, and they regarded him as happy. Conversely, Phaëthon and Tantalus, despite ascending to heaven, faced the greatest misfortunes because of their foolishness, as the poets tell us.

913 Euripides, "Phœnissæ," 388, 389.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Phoenician Women," 388, 389.

914 Reading βακέλας. Gallus in Latin.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Reading Bakelas. Gallus in Latin.

915 "Iliad," xxiv. 527-533.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xxiv. 527-533.

916 Plato, "Timæus," p. 90 A. Compare Ovid, "Metamorphoses," i. 84-86.

916 Plato, "Timæus," p. 90 A. Compare Ovid, "Metamorphoses," i. 84-86.

917 Derived from μετὰ, γείτον, because then people flitted and changed their neighbours.

917 Derived from μετὰ, γείτον, because at that time people moved around and changed their neighbors.

918 Euripides, "Iphigenia in Tauris," 253.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Iphigenia in Tauris," 253.

919 See also Pausanias, viii. 24.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See also Pausanias, viii. 24.

920 Pindar, Fragm. 126.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Pindar, Frag. 126.

921 Æschylus, "Niobe," Fragm. 146.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Aeschylus, "Niobe," Frag. 146.

922 "Odyssey," vi. 8. I read ἀνδρῶν as Wyttenbach.

922 "Odyssey," vi. 8. I read ανδρών as Wyttenbach.

923 "Odyssey," vi. 204.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Odyssey," vi. 204.

924 See Pausanias, v. 6.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See Pausanias, vol. 6.

925 In our money about £121 17s. 6d.

925 In our finances, it's around £121 17s. 6d.

926 "Iliad," xiv. 230.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," xiv. 230.

927 "Iliad," xxiv. 544.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 24. 544.

928 "Iliad," ix. 668.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 9.668.

929 "Iliad," ii. 625, 626.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 2. 625, 626.

930 So Reiske.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ So Reiske.

931 "Iliad," xxi. 59.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Iliad," 21. 59.

932 Euripides, Fragm. 950.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, Frag. 950.

933 Reiske suggests Βακχυλίδης ὁ Κεῖος. A very probable suggestion.

933 Reiske suggests Bacchylides the Cean. A very likely suggestion.

934 Euripides, "Phœnissæ," 388-393.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Phoenician Women," 388-393.

935 Omitting πρώτος, which probably got in from πρῶτον following, and for which Reiske conjectured ὁρᾷς ώς.

935 Skipping over the word "first," which likely slipped in from "first" that follows, and for which Reiske suggested "you see as."

936 Such as Cardinal Balue was shut up by Louis XI. in for fourteen years.

936 Cardinal Balue was locked up by Louis XI. for fourteen years.

937 The answer of Theodorus is wanting.

Theodorus's answer is missing.

938 Euripides, "Phœnissæ," 396, 397.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Phoenician Women," 396, 397.

939 That is, they never get any further.

939 In other words, they never progress any further.

940 Euripides, "Phœnissæ," 402-405.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Phoenician Women," 402-405.

941 Euripides, "Phœnissæ," 430-432.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Phoenician Women," 430-432.

942 Ibid. 344-346.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Same source. 344-346.

943 "Reading χθονὸς. "Sic mutandum censet Valckenarius."—Wyttenbach.

943 "Reading of the Underworld. "Valckenarius thinks it should be changed."—Wyttenbach.

944 Through his daughter Semele.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Through his daughter Semele.

945 Herodotus, ii. 171.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Herodotus, ii. 171.


ON FORTUNE.

§ i. "Fortune, not wisdom, rules the affairs of mortals."946 And does not justice, and fairness, and sobriety, and decorum rule the affairs of mortals? Was it of fortune or owing to fortune that Aristides persevered in his poverty, when he might have been lord of much wealth? And that Scipio after taking Carthage neither saw nor received any of the spoil? Was it of fortune or owing to fortune that Philocrates spent on harlots and fish the money he had received from Philip? And that Lasthenes and Euthycrates lost Olynthus, measuring happiness by their belly and lusts? Was it of fortune that Alexander the son of Philip not only himself abstained from the captive women, but punished others that outraged them? Was it under the influence of an evil genius and fortune that Alexander,947 the son of Priam, intrigued with the wife of his host and ran away with her, and filled two continents with war and evils? For if all these things are due to fortune, what hinders our saying that cats and goats and apes are under the influence of fortune in respect of greediness, and lust, and ribaldry?

§ i. "Luck, not wisdom, controls the lives of people." 946 But don’t justice, fairness, self-control, and decency also shape human affairs? Was it because of luck that Aristides remained poor when he could have been wealthy? And what about Scipio, who, after conquering Carthage, didn’t take any of the spoils? Was it luck that made Philocrates waste the money he got from Philip on prostitutes and seafood? And how about Lasthenes and Euthycrates, who lost Olynthus because they equated happiness with their appetites and desires? Was it luck that Alexander, the son of Philip, not only refrained from the captured women but also punished those who violated them? Was it because of some evil fate that Alexander,947 the son of Priam, schemed with his host’s wife, ran away with her, and spread war and suffering across two continents? If all of this is just due to luck, then why can’t we say that cats, goats, and monkeys are also influenced by luck when it comes to greed, desire, and debauchery?

§ ii. And if there are such things as sobriety and justice and fortitude, with what reason can we deny the existence of prudence, and if prudence exists, how can we deny the existence of wisdom? For sobriety is a kind of prudence, 395as people say, and justice also needs the presence of prudence. Nay more, we call the wisdom and prudence that makes people good in regard to pleasure self-control and sobriety, and in dangers and hardships endurance and fortitude, and in dealings between man and man and in public life equity and justice. And so, if we are to ascribe to fortune the acts of wisdom, let us ascribe justice and sobriety to fortune also, aye, and let us put down to fortune stealing, and picking pockets, and lewdness, and let us bid farewell to argument, and throw ourselves entirely on fortune, as if we were, like dust or refuse, borne along and hurried away by a violent wind. For if there be no wisdom, it is not likely that there is any deliberation or investigation of matters, or search for expediency, but Sophocles only talked nonsense when he said,

§ ii. If there are such things as sobriety, justice, and courage, then how can we reasonably deny the existence of prudence? And if prudence exists, how can we deny the existence of wisdom? Sobriety is a form of prudence, 395 as people say, and justice also requires prudence. Furthermore, we refer to the wisdom and prudence that make people good in terms of pleasure as self-control and sobriety, while in the face of danger and hardships, we use terms like endurance and courage. In interactions between individuals and in public life, we refer to equity and justice. Therefore, if we attribute acts of wisdom to chance, then we should also attribute justice and sobriety to chance as well; yes, we should even blame chance for theft, pickpocketing, and immorality, and completely abandon reason, surrendering ourselves to chance as if we were mere dust or debris, swept away by a strong wind. For if wisdom doesn't exist, it seems unlikely there would be any deliberation, investigation, or search for what is practical; Sophocles only spoke nonsense when he said,

"Whatever is sought is found, what is neglected" Escapes our notice; __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

and again in dividing human affairs,

and once more in separating human matters,

"I learn what can be taught, and I discover what can be found out." Please conduct a thorough investigation, and of the gods I request what can be gained through prayer. 949

For what can be found out or learnt by men, if everything is due to fortune? And what deliberative assembly of a state is not annulled, what council of a king is not abrogated, if all things are subject to fortune? whom we abuse as blind because we ourselves are blind in our dealings with her. Indeed, how can it be otherwise, seeing that we repudiate wisdom, which is like plucking out our eyes, and take a blind guide of our lives?

For what can people discover or learn if everything is determined by luck? And what government assembly isn’t rendered useless, what royal council isn’t disregarded, if everything is at the mercy of chance? We criticize luck as if it’s blind because we are blind in how we handle it. Honestly, how could it be any different when we reject wisdom, which is like removing our own eyesight, and choose to follow a blind guide in our lives?

§ iii. Supposing any of us were to assert that seeing is a matter of fortune, not of eyesight, nor of the eyes that give light, as Plato says, and that hearing is a matter of fortune, and not the imbibing of a current of air through the ear and brain, it would be well for us then to be on our guard against the evidence of our senses. But indeed 396nature has given us sight and hearing and taste and smell, and all other parts of the body and their functions, as ministers of wisdom and prudence. For "it is the mind that sees, and the mind that hears, everything else is deaf and blind." And just as, if there were no sun, we should have perpetual night for all the stars, as Heraclitus says, so man for all his senses, if he had no mind or reason, would be little better than the beasts. But as it is, it is not by fortune or chance that we are superior to them and masters of them, but Prometheus, that is reason, is the cause of this,

§ iii. If any of us were to claim that seeing is a matter of luck, not our eyesight or the light-giving eyes, as Plato says, and that hearing is based on fortune rather than the flow of air through our ears and brain, we would need to be cautious about trusting our senses. But indeed, 396 nature has provided us with sight, hearing, taste, smell, and all the body's other functions as tools for wisdom and judgment. For "it is the mind that sees, and the mind that hears; everything else is deaf and blind." Just as, without the sun, we would have endless night despite the stars, as Heraclitus says, a person, no matter how many senses they have, would be little better than animals without mind or reason. But as it stands, we are not superior to them or in control of them by chance or luck; rather, it is Prometheus, which symbolizes reason, that is responsible for this.

"Bringing us bulls, horses, and donkeys, "To relieve us of our hard work, and serve in return,"

as Æschylus says.950 For as to fortune and natural condition, most of the beasts are better off than we are. For some are armed with horns and tusks and stings, and as for the hedgehog, as Empedocles says, it has its back all rough with sharp bristles, and some are shod and protected by scales and fur and talons and hoofs worn smooth by use, whereas man alone, as Plato says, is left by nature naked, unarmed, unshod, and uncovered. But by one gift, that of reason and painstaking and forethought, nature compensates for all these deficiencies. "Small indeed is the strength of man, but by the versatility of his intellect he can tame the inhabitants of the sea, earth, and air."951 Nothing is more agile and swift than horses, yet they run for man; the dog is a courageous and high-spirited creature, yet it guards man; fish is most pleasant to the taste, the pig the fattest of all animals, yet both are food and delicacies for man. What is huger or more formidable in appearance than the elephant? Yet it is man's plaything, and a spectacle at public shows, and learns to dance and kneel. And all these things are not idly introduced, but to the end that they may teach us to what heights reason raises man, and what things it sets him above, and how it makes him master of everything.

as Æschylus says.950 When it comes to fortune and natural condition, many animals are better off than we are. Some are equipped with horns, tusks, and stings, and the hedgehog, as Empedocles notes, has a back covered in sharp bristles. Others have armor in the form of scales, fur, and talons or hooves worn smooth from use. In contrast, man, as Plato points out, is left by nature naked, unarmed, unshod, and exposed. However, nature compensates for all these shortcomings with one gift: the ability to reason, to work hard, and to think ahead. "Man's strength is indeed small, but through his adaptable intellect, he can tame the creatures of the sea, earth, and sky."951 Nothing is more agile and swift than horses, yet they run for man; the dog is a brave and spirited creature, yet it protects man; fish is delightful to eat, and pigs are the fattest animals, but both serve as food and treats for man. What is larger or more intimidating than the elephant? Yet it becomes man's plaything, a feature in public performances, and can be trained to dance and kneel. These examples are not presented without purpose; they illustrate how reason elevates humans, what we can rise above, and how it makes us masters of everything.

397 "For we are not good at boxing, nor are we good at wrestling, Nor yet fast runners, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

for in all these points we are less fortunate than the beasts. But by our experience and memory and wisdom and cunning, as Anaxagoras says, we make use of them, and get their honey and milk, and catch them, and drive and lead them about at our will. And there is nothing of fortune in this, it is all the result of wisdom and forethought.

For in all these ways, we're not as lucky as animals. But through our experience, memory, knowledge, and cleverness, as Anaxagoras says, we take advantage of them, getting their honey and milk, catching them, and controlling and directing them as we wish. There's nothing lucky about this; it all comes from wisdom and planning.

§ iv. Moreover the labours of carpenters and coppersmiths and house-builders and statue-makers are affairs of mortals, and we see that no success in such trades is got by fortune or chance. For that fortune plays a very small part in the life of a wise man, whether coppersmith or house-builder, and that the greatest works are wrought by art alone, is shown by the poet in the following lines:—

§ iv. Moreover, the work of carpenters, coppersmiths, builders, and sculptors are human endeavors, and we see that success in these trades doesn't come from luck or coincidence. For luck plays a minimal role in the life of a wise person, whether they are a coppersmith or a builder, and the greatest achievements are created solely through skill, as the poet illustrates in the following lines:—

"All craftsmen go out into the street, You who worship Ergane with fan-shaped baskets, Zeus' fierce-eyed daughter; __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

for Ergane954 and Athene, and not Fortune, do the trades regard as their patrons. They do indeed say that Nealces,955 on one occasion painting a horse, was quite satisfied with his painting in all other respects, but that some foam on the bridle from the horse's breath did not please him, so that he frequently tried to rub it out; at last in his anger he threw his sponge (just as it was, full of colours) at the picture, and this very wonderfully produced exactly the effect he desired. This is the only fortunate accident in art that history records. Artificers everywhere use rules and weights and measures, that none of their work may be done at random and anyhow. And indeed the arts may be considered as wisdom on a small scale, or rather as emanations from and fragments of wisdom scattered about among the 398necessities of life; as the fire of Prometheus is riddled to have been divided and scattered about in all quarters of the world. For thus small particles and fragments of wisdom, breaking up as it were and getting divided into pieces, have formed into order.

for Ergane954 and Athene, and not Fortune, the trades see as their patrons. They say that Nealces,955 once while painting a horse, was very happy with his artwork overall, but he was unhappy with some foam on the bridle from the horse's breath. He often tried to wipe it away, and finally, in frustration, he threw his sponge (full of colors) at the painting, and this surprisingly achieved exactly the effect he wanted. This is the only lucky mistake in art that history mentions. Craftspeople everywhere use rules and measurements so that none of their work is random or haphazard. The arts can indeed be seen as a small-scale form of wisdom, or rather as bits and pieces of wisdom scattered throughout life's necessities; similar to how the fire of Prometheus is said to have been divided and spread across the entire world. In this way, small fragments of wisdom, breaking apart and getting scattered, have come together in an orderly manner.

§ v. It is strange then that the arts do not require fortune to attain to their ends, and yet that the most important and complete of all the arts, the sum total of man's glory and merit, should be so completely powerless. Why, there is a kind of wisdom even in the tightening or slackening of chords, which people call music, and in the dressing of food, which we call the art of cooking, and in cleaning clothes, which we call the art of the fuller, and we teach boys how to put on their shoes and clothes generally, and to take their meat in the right hand and their bread in the left, since none of these things come by fortune, but require attention and care. And are we to suppose that the most important things which make so much for happiness do not call for wisdom, and have nothing to do with reason and forethought? Why, no one ever yet wetted earth with water and then left it, thinking it would become bricks by fortune and spontaneously, or procured wool and leather, and sat down and prayed Fortune that it might become clothes and shoes; nor does anyone getting together much gold and silver and a quantity of slaves, and living in a spacious hall with many doors, and making a display of costly couches and tables, believe that these things will constitute his happiness, and give him a painless happy life secure from changes, unless he be wise also. A certain person asked the general Iphicrates in a scolding way who he was, as he seemed neither a heavy-armed soldier, nor a bowman, nor a targeteer, and he replied, "I am the person who rule and make use of all these."

§ v. It's odd that the arts don’t need luck to achieve their goals, yet the most significant and complete of all the arts, which represents human glory and merit, seems so utterly helpless. There’s a kind of wisdom in adjusting the tightness of strings, which we call music, in preparing food, which we refer to as the art of cooking, and in washing clothes, which we identify as the craft of fullers. We teach boys how to wear their shoes and clothes properly and how to hold their meat in the right hand and their bread in the left, since none of these require luck but rather demand attention and care. Should we then assume that the most crucial aspects of happiness don't require wisdom and have nothing to do with reason and planning? After all, no one ever dampened the earth with water and assumed it would turn into bricks by chance or gathered wool and leather and prayed to luck for them to become clothes and shoes; nor does anyone, after collecting a lot of gold and silver and acquiring many slaves, believing that living in a large house with many doors and showcasing expensive couches and tables will bring happiness and a trouble-free life, unless they are also wise. There’s a story of someone confronting the general Iphicrates in a rude manner, asking who he was, since he didn’t appear to be a heavy infantryman, archer, or swordsman, and Iphicrates replied, "I'm the one who commands and utilizes all of these."

§ vi. So wisdom is neither gold, nor silver, nor fame, nor wealth, nor health, nor strength, nor beauty. What is it then? It is what can use all these well, and that by means of which each of these things becomes pleasant and esteemed and useful, and without which they are useless; and unprofitable and injurious, and a burden and disgrace to their possessor. So Hesiod's Prometheus gives very good advice to Epimetheus, "not to receive gifts from399 Olympian Zeus but to send them back,"956 meaning external things and things of fortune. For as if he urged one who knew nothing of music not to play on the pipe, or one who knew nothing of letters not to read, or one who was not used to horses not to ride, so he advised him not to take office if he were foolish, nor to grow rich if he were illiberal, nor to marry if likely to be ruled by his wife. For success beyond their merit is to foolish persons a cause of folly, as Demosthenes said,957 and good fortune beyond their merit is to those who are not sensible a cause of misfortune.958

§ vi. So, wisdom isn't gold, silver, fame, wealth, health, strength, or beauty. What is it then? It's the ability to use all these things well, and it's what makes each of them enjoyable, valued, and useful—without it, they are worthless, harmful, a burden, and a source of shame for their owner. Hesiod's Prometheus gives great advice to Epimetheus: "don’t accept gifts from 399 Olympian Zeus; instead, send them back,"956 referring to external possessions and fortunes. It's like telling someone who knows nothing about music not to play the flute, or advising someone who can't read not to open a book, or warning someone who isn't experienced with horses not to ride. Similarly, he advised Epimetheus not to take on a position if he was foolish, not to seek wealth if he was stingy, and not to marry if he might be dominated by his wife. For foolish people, achieving success they don't deserve leads to poor judgment, as Demosthenes said,957 and those who aren't wise experiencing good fortune beyond their deserts often find it leads to their downfall.958

946 A line from Chæremon.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ A quote from Chæremon.

947 Better known as Paris.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ More commonly known as Paris.

948 "Œdipus Tyrannus," 110, 111. Wyttenbach compares Terence, "Heauton Timorumenos," 675. "Nil tam difficilest, quin quærende investigari possiet."

948 "Oedipus Rex," 110, 111. Wyttenbach compares Terence, "Heauton Timorumenos," 675. "Nothing is so difficult that it can't be investigated by asking."

949 Soph., Frag. 723.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Soph., Frag. 723.

950 Æschylus, Fragm. 180. Reading ἀντιδουλα with Reiske and the MSS.

950 Aeschylus, Fragm. 180. Reading antidoula with Reiske and the manuscripts.

951 Euripides, "Æolus," Fragm. 27.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Euripides, "Aeolus," Frag. 27.

952 Homer, "Odyssey," viii. 246, 247.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Homer, "Odyssey," VIII. 246, 247.

953 Soph., Frag. 724.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Soph., Frag. 724.

954 "The Worker." Generally a title of Athene, as Pausanias, i. 24; iii. 17; v. 14; vi. 26; viii. 32; ix. 26. Gataker thinks καὶ τὴν should be expunged. Hercher omits καὶ τὴν Ἀθηνᾶν altogether.

954 "The Worker." This is usually a title for Athene, as noted by Pausanias, i. 24; iii. 17; v. 14; vi. 26; viii. 32; ix. 26. Gataker believes that καὶ τὴν should be removed. Hercher completely omits καὶ τὴν Ἀθηνᾶν.

955 So Hercher after Madvig. See Pliny, "Hist. Nat.," XXXV. 36, 20.

955 So Hercher after Madvig. See Pliny, "Hist. Nat.," XXXV. 36, 20.

956 Hesiod, "Works and Days," 86, 87.

956 Hesiod, "Works and Days," 86, 87.

957 "Olynth.," i. 23.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ "Olynth.," i. 23.

958 The whole of this essay reminds one of the well-known lines of Juvenal, twice repeated—namely, x. 365, 366; and xiv. 315, 316:—

958 This entire essay brings to mind the famous lines from Juvenal, repeated twice—specifically, x. 365, 366; and xiv. 315, 316:—

"There's no divine power if there's no wisdom; we, you," We are making, Fortune, and placing the goddess in the sky."

INDEX.

CHISWICK PRESS:--C. WHITTINGHAM AND CO., TOOKS COURT, CHANCERY LANE.



        
        
    
Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!