This is a modern-English version of The Common Law, originally written by Holmes, Oliver Wendell. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.









THE COMMON LAW

By Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.










CONVENTIONS
EVENTS

Numbers in square brackets [245] refer to original page numbers. Original footnotes were numbered page-by-page, and are collected at the end of the text. In the text, numbers in slashes (e.g./1/) refer to original footnote numbers. In the footnote section, a number such as 245/1 refers to (original) page 245, footnote 1. The footnotes are mostly citations to old English law reporters and to commentaries by writers such as Ihering, Bracton and Blackstone. I cannot give a source for decrypting the notation. To find a footnote click on the page number just above the footnote i.e. [245].

Numbers in square brackets [245] refer to original page numbers. The original footnotes were numbered on a page-by-page basis and are collected at the end of the text. In the text, numbers in slashes (e.g. /1/) refer to the original footnote numbers. In the footnote section, a number like 245/1 refers to (original) page 245, footnote 1. The footnotes mainly cite old English law reporters and commentaries by writers such as Ihering, Bracton, and Blackstone. I can't provide a source for decoding the notation. To find a footnote, click on the page number right above the footnote, i.e., [245].

There is quite a little Latin and some Greek in the original text. I have reproduced the Latin. The Greek text is omitted; its place is marked by the expression [Greek characters]. Italics and diacritical marks such as accents and cedillas are omitted and unmarked.

There’s some Latin and a bit of Greek in the original text. I’ve included the Latin. The Greek text is left out; its spot is indicated by the phrase [Greek characters]. Italics and special characters like accents and cedillas are left out and not marked.

Lecture X has two subheads—Successions After Death and Successions Inter Vivos. Lecture XI is also titled Successions Inter Vivos. This conforms to the original.

Lecture X has two subheads—Successions After Death and Successions Inter Vivos. Lecture XI is also titled Successions Inter Vivos. This conforms to the original.










CONTENTS

TABLE OF CONTENTS








LECTURE I. — EARLY FORMS OF LIABILITY.

[1] The object of this book is to present a general view of the Common Law. To accomplish the task, other tools are needed besides logic. It is something to show that the consistency of a system requires a particular result, but it is not all. The life of the law has not been logic: it has been experience. The felt necessities of the time, the prevalent moral and political theories, intuitions of public policy, avowed or unconscious, even the prejudices which judges share with their fellow-men, have had a good deal more to do than the syllogism in determining the rules by which men should be governed. The law embodies the story of a nation's development through many centuries, and it cannot be dealt with as if it contained only the axioms and corollaries of a book of mathematics. In order to know what it is, we must know what it has been, and what it tends to become. We must alternately consult history and existing theories of legislation. But the most difficult labor will be to understand the combination of the two into new products at every stage. The substance of the law at any given time pretty nearly [2] corresponds, so far as it goes, with what is then understood to be convenient; but its form and machinery, and the degree to which it is able to work out desired results, depend very much upon its past.

[1] The purpose of this book is to provide an overview of Common Law. To achieve this, we need more than just logic. While it’s important to show that a consistent system leads to a specific outcome, that's not the whole story. The essence of law has not been purely logical; it has been shaped by experience. The pressing needs of the time, the dominant moral and political theories, public policy instincts—whether acknowledged or not—even the biases shared by judges and their peers, have played a much bigger role than logic in deciding the rules that govern people. Law reflects the history of a nation's evolution over many centuries, and it can't be treated like it only contains the principles and conclusions of a math textbook. To understand what law is, we need to know what it has been and what it is likely to become. We must look to history and current legislative theories. However, the toughest challenge will be understanding how these elements combine into new outcomes at every stage. The substance of the law at any given moment closely aligns with what is deemed practical at that time, but its structure, functionality, and capacity to achieve intended results are significantly influenced by its history.

In Massachusetts today, while, on the one hand, there are a great many rules which are quite sufficiently accounted for by their manifest good sense, on the other, there are some which can only be understood by reference to the infancy of procedure among the German tribes, or to the social condition of Rome under the Decemvirs.

In Massachusetts today, while there are a lot of rules that make sense and are obviously reasonable, there are some that can only be understood by looking at the early legal practices of the German tribes or the social situation in Rome during the time of the Decemvirs.

I shall use the history of our law so far as it is necessary to explain a conception or to interpret a rule, but no further. In doing so there are two errors equally to be avoided both by writer and reader. One is that of supposing, because an idea seems very familiar and natural to us, that it has always been so. Many things which we take for granted have had to be laboriously fought out or thought out in past times. The other mistake is the opposite one of asking too much of history. We start with man full grown. It may be assumed that the earliest barbarian whose practices are to be considered, had a good many of the same feelings and passions as ourselves.

I will use the history of our law as needed to explain a concept or interpret a rule, but not beyond that. In doing so, both the writer and the reader should avoid two common mistakes. One mistake is thinking that just because an idea feels familiar and natural to us, it has always been that way. Many concepts we take for granted have been fought for or thought out over time. The other mistake is the opposite: expecting too much from history. We begin with man fully formed. It can be assumed that the earliest barbarian we consider had many of the same feelings and passions as we do today.

The first subject to be discussed is the general theory of liability civil and criminal. The Common Law has changed a good deal since the beginning of our series of reports, and the search after a theory which may now be said to prevail is very much a study of tendencies. I believe that it will be instructive to go back to the early forms of liability, and to start from them.

The first topic we’ll discuss is the overall theory of civil and criminal liability. Common Law has evolved significantly since the start of our series of reports, and the quest for a prevailing theory is largely an exploration of trends. I think it will be helpful to look at the early forms of liability and start from there.

It is commonly known that the early forms of legal procedure were grounded in vengeance. Modern writers [3] have thought that the Roman law started from the blood feud, and all the authorities agree that the German law begun in that way. The feud led to the composition, at first optional, then compulsory, by which the feud was bought off. The gradual encroachment of the composition may be traced in the Anglo-Saxon laws, /1/ and the feud was pretty well broken up, though not extinguished, by the time of William the Conqueror. The killings and house-burnings of an earlier day became the appeals of mayhem and arson. The appeals de pace et plagis and of mayhem became, or rather were in substance, the action of trespass which is still familiar to lawyers. /2/ But as the compensation recovered in the appeal was the alternative of vengeance, we might expect to find its scope limited to the scope of vengeance. Vengeance imports a feeling of blame, and an opinion, however distorted by passion, that a wrong has been done. It can hardly go very far beyond the case of a harm intentionally inflicted: even a dog distinguishes between being stumbled over and being kicked.

It’s well-known that early legal processes were based on revenge. Modern writers [3] believe that Roman law originated from blood feuds, and all experts agree that German law started this way as well. The feud eventually led to compensation, first as a choice and later as mandatory, which allowed the feud to be settled. The gradual shift towards compensation can be seen in Anglo-Saxon laws, /1/ and by the time of William the Conqueror, feuds had largely dissipated, though they weren't completely gone. The killings and arson of earlier times were replaced with legal appeals for mayhem and arson. The appeals de pace et plagis and mayhem became, or were essentially, forms of the trespass action that lawyers are still familiar with today. /2/ However, since the compensation awarded in these appeals served as an alternative to revenge, it’s reasonable to expect its scope to be limited to the range of vengeance. Revenge involves a sense of blame and a belief, however distorted by emotions, that a wrong has occurred. It typically doesn’t extend much further than intentional harm: even a dog can tell the difference between being tripped over and being kicked.

Whether for this cause or another, the early English appeals for personal violence seem to have been confined to intentional wrongs. Glanvill /3/ mentions melees, blows, and wounds,—all forms of intentional violence. In the fuller description of such appeals given by Bracton /4/ it is made quite clear that they were based on intentional assaults. The appeal de pace et plagis laid an intentional assault, described the nature of the arms used, and the length and depth of the wound. The appellor also had [4] to show that he immediately raised the hue and cry. So when Bracton speaks of the lesser offences, which were not sued by way of appeal, he instances only intentional wrongs, such as blows with the fist, flogging, wounding, insults, and so forth. /1/ The cause of action in the cases of trespass reported in the earlier Year Books and in the Abbreviatio Plaeitorum is always an intentional wrong. It was only at a later day, and after argument, that trespass was extended so as to embrace harms which were foreseen, but which were not the intended consequence of the defendant's act. /2/ Thence again it extended to unforeseen injuries. /3/

Whether for this reason or another, early English appeals for personal violence seem to have been limited to intentional wrongs. Glanvill /3/ mentions brawls, blows, and wounds—all forms of intentional violence. In the detailed description of such appeals provided by Bracton /4/, it's made clear that they were based on intentional assaults. The appeal of de pace et plagis involved an intentional assault, detailing the type of weapon used and the size and severity of the wound. The person making the appeal also had [4] to prove that they immediately raised the alarm. So when Bracton discusses lesser offenses that weren't pursued through appeals, he only references intentional wrongs, such as punches, beatings, wounds, insults, and so on. /1/ The basis for action in the cases of trespass reported in the earlier Year Books and in the Abbreviatio Plaeitorum is always an intentional wrong. It was only later, after some discussion, that trespass was expanded to include harms that were anticipated but not the intended result of the defendant's action. /2/ From there, it further broadened to unforeseen injuries. /3/

It will be seen that this order of development is not quite consistent with an opinion which has been held, that it was a characteristic of early law not to penetrate beyond the external visible fact, the damnum corpore corpori datum. It has been thought that an inquiry into the internal condition of the defendant, his culpability or innocence, implies a refinement of juridical conception equally foreign to Rome before the Lex Aquilia, and to England when trespass took its shape. I do not know any very satisfactory evidence that a man was generally held liable either in Rome /4/ or England for the accidental consequences even of his own act. But whatever may have been the early law, the foregoing account shows the starting-point of the system with which we have to deal. Our system of private liability for the consequences of a man's own acts, that is, for his trespasses, started from the notion of actual intent and actual personal culpability.

It will be evident that this sequence of development doesn’t completely align with the belief that early law focused only on external visible facts, or the damnum corpore corpori datum. It has been suggested that looking into the internal state of the defendant, whether they were guilty or innocent, indicates a level of legal understanding that was unfamiliar in Rome before the Lex Aquilia, and in England when trespass was defined. I’m not aware of any convincing evidence that a person was generally held responsible in either Rome /4/ or England for the unintended consequences of their own actions. However, regardless of what the early law was like, the previous account illustrates the foundation of the system we need to consider. Our system of private liability for the outcomes of a person's actions, meaning their trespasses, originated from the idea of actual intent and personal culpability.

The original principles of liability for harm inflicted by [5] another person or thing have been less carefully considered hitherto than those which governed trespass, and I shall therefore devote the rest of this Lecture to discussing them. I shall try to show that this liability also had its root in the passion of revenge, and to point out the changes by which it reached its present form. But I shall not confine myself strictly to what is needful for that purpose, because it is not only most interesting to trace the transformation throughout its whole extent, but the story will also afford an instructive example of the mode in which the law has grown, without a break, from barbarism to civilization. Furthermore, it will throw much light upon some important and peculiar doctrines which cannot be returned to later.

The original principles of liability for harm caused by another person or thing have been less thoroughly examined so far compared to those governing trespass, so I will spend the rest of this lecture discussing them. I will attempt to show that this liability also stems from the desire for revenge and highlight the changes that led to its current form. However, I won’t restrict myself solely to what’s necessary for that discussion because it’s not only interesting to trace this transformation in its entirety, but the narrative will also serve as an enlightening example of how the law has evolved steadily from barbarism to civilization. Additionally, it will shed light on some important and unique doctrines that we won’t be able to revisit later.

A very common phenomenon, and one very familiar to the student of history, is this. The customs, beliefs, or needs of a primitive time establish a rule or a formula. In the course of centuries the custom, belief, or necessity disappears, but the rule remains. The reason which gave rise to the rule has been forgotten, and ingenious minds set themselves to inquire how it is to be accounted for. Some ground of policy is thought of, which seems to explain it and to reconcile it with the present state of things; and then the rule adapts itself to the new reasons which have been found for it, and enters on a new career. The old form receives a new content, and in time even the form modifies itself to fit the meaning which it has received. The subject under consideration illustrates this course of events very clearly.

A very common occurrence, and one that history students know well, is this. The customs, beliefs, or needs from a primitive time create a rule or a formula. Over centuries, the custom, belief, or necessity fades away, but the rule remains. The reason behind the rule has been forgotten, and clever people start to wonder how to explain it. Some rationale is devised that seems to justify it and align it with the current situation; then the rule adjusts to the new justifications that have been found for it and embarks on a new path. The old form gains new meaning, and eventually, even the form changes to match the new interpretation it has received. The topic we’re discussing illustrates this process very clearly.

I will begin by taking a medley of examples embodying as many distinct rules, each with its plausible and seemingly sufficient ground of policy to explain it.

I will start by giving a mix of examples that represent various rules, each backed by a reasonable and seemingly valid policy explanation.

[6] A man has an animal of known ferocious habits, which escapes and does his neighbor damage. He can prove that the animal escaped through no negligence of his, but still he is held liable. Why? It is, says the analytical jurist, because, although he was not negligent at the moment of escape, he was guilty of remote heedlessness, or negligence, or fault, in having such a creature at all. And one by whose fault damage is done ought to pay for it.

[6] A man owns a wild animal with a reputation for being dangerous, which escapes and causes harm to his neighbor. He can show that the animal got away without any negligence on his part, but he is still held responsible. Why? The legal expert explains that, even though he wasn't careless at the time of the escape, he was still somewhat careless or at fault by having such a creature in the first place. So, a person whose actions lead to damage should be responsible for compensating it.

A baker's man, while driving his master's cart to deliver hot rolls of a morning, runs another man down. The master has to pay for it. And when he has asked why he should have to pay for the wrongful act of an independent and responsible being, he has been answered from the time of Ulpian to that of Austin, that it is because he was to blame for employing an improper person. If he answers, that he used the greatest possible care in choosing his driver, he is told that that is no excuse; and then perhaps the reason is shifted, and it is said that there ought to be a remedy against some one who can pay the damages, or that such wrongful acts as by ordinary human laws are likely to happen in the course of the service are imputable to the service.

A baker's employee, while driving his boss's cart to deliver hot rolls in the morning, accidentally hits another man. The boss has to cover the costs. When he questions why he should be responsible for the actions of an independent and accountable person, he’s told, from Ulpian’s time to Austin's, that it's because he was at fault for hiring someone unfit for the job. If he insists he was extremely careful in selecting his driver, he’s informed that this isn’t a valid excuse. Then perhaps the explanation changes, stating that there should be a way to get compensation from someone who can pay for the damages, or that wrongful acts likely to occur during normal service are considered the responsibility of the service.

Next, take a case where a limit has been set to liability which had previously been unlimited. In 1851, Congress passed a law, which is still in force, and by which the owners of ships in all the more common cases of maritime loss can surrender the vessel and her freight then pending to the losers; and it is provided that, thereupon, further proceedings against the owners shall cease. The legislators to whom we owe this act argued that, if a merchant embark a portion of his property upon a hazardous venture, it is reasonable that his stake should be confined to what [7] he puts at risk,—a principle similar to that on which corporations have been so largely created in America during the last fifty years.

Next, consider a situation where liability has been limited when it was previously unlimited. In 1851, Congress passed a law that is still in effect, allowing ship owners in most common cases of maritime loss to give up the vessel and her pending freight to the losers; after this, further legal action against the owners stops. The lawmakers responsible for this act argued that if a merchant invests part of his assets in a risky venture, it's fair for his financial exposure to be limited to what [7] he puts at stake—a principle similar to how corporations have been extensively established in America over the past fifty years.

It has been a rule of criminal pleading in England down into the present century, that an indictment for homicide must set forth the value of the instrument causing the death, in order that the king or his grantee might claim forfeiture of the deodand, "as an accursed thing," in the language of Blackstone.

It has been a rule of criminal pleading in England up to the present century that an indictment for homicide must state the value of the instrument that caused the death, so that the king or his grantee could claim forfeiture of the deodand, "as an accursed thing," in the words of Blackstone.

I might go on multiplying examples; but these are enough to show the remoteness of the points to be brought together.—As a first step towards a generalization, it will be necessary to consider what is to be found in ancient and independent systems of law.

I could keep giving more examples, but these are enough to demonstrate how far apart the points are that need to be connected. As a first step towards a generalization, it's important to look at what's found in ancient and independent legal systems.

There is a well-known passage in Exodus, /1/ which we shall have to remember later: "If an ox gore a man or a woman, that they die: then the ox shall be surely stoned, and his flesh shall not be eaten; but the owner of the ox shall be quit." When we turn from the Jews to the Greeks, we find the principle of the passage just quoted erected into a system. Plutarch, in his Solon, tells us that a dog that had bitten a man was to be delivered up bound to a log four cubits long. Plato made elaborate provisions in his Laws for many such cases. If a slave killed a man, he was to be given up to the relatives of the deceased. /2/ If he wounded a man, he was to be given up to the injured party to use him as he pleased. /3/ So if he did damage to which the injured party did not contribute as a joint cause. In either case, if the owner [8] failed to surrender the slave, he was bound to make good the loss. /1/ If a beast killed a man, it was to be slain and cast beyond the borders. If an inanimate thing caused death, it was to be cast beyond the borders in like manner, and expiation was to be made. /2/ Nor was all this an ideal creation of merely imagined law, for it was said in one of the speeches of Aeschines, that "we banish beyond our borders stocks and stones and steel, voiceless and mindless things, if they chance to kill a man; and if a man commits suicide, bury the hand that struck the blow afar from its body." This is mentioned quite as an every-day matter, evidently without thinking it at all extraordinary, only to point an antithesis to the honors heaped upon Demosthenes. /3/ As late as the second century after Christ the traveller Pausanias observed with some surprise that they still sat in judgment on inanimate things in the Prytaneum. /4/ Plutarch attributes the institution to Draco. /5/

There’s a famous passage in Exodus, /1/ which we’ll need to remember later: "If an ox gores a man or a woman and they die, then the ox must be stoned, and its flesh must not be eaten; but the owner of the ox will be free from liability." When we shift from the Jews to the Greeks, we see the principle of this passage developed into a comprehensive system. Plutarch, in his Solon, tells us that a dog that bit a man was to be tied to a four-cubit-long log. Plato made detailed provisions in his Laws for many similar situations. If a slave killed someone, he was to be handed over to the deceased's relatives. /2/ If he wounded a person, he was to be given to the injured party to be dealt with as they saw fit. /3/ This also applied if he caused damage without the injured party being a contributing cause. In any case, if the owner [8] failed to turn over the slave, he was required to compensate for the loss. /1/ If an animal killed a person, it was to be killed and thrown outside the borders. If an inanimate object caused death, it was to be discarded in the same way, and a purification was to be performed. /2/ Moreover, this wasn’t just an idealized construct of imagined law; in one of Aeschines' speeches, it was stated that "we banish stocks, stones, and steel—mindless and voiceless things—if they happen to kill a man; and if someone commits suicide, we bury the hand that struck the fatal blow far from the body." This is mentioned as though it were a common matter, clearly without any sense of it being extraordinary, just to highlight the contrast with the honors given to Demosthenes. /3/ Even as late as the second century after Christ, the traveler Pausanias noted with some surprise that they still judged inanimate objects at the Prytaneum. /4/ Plutarch attributes this practice to Draco. /5/

In the Roman law we find the similar principles of the noxoe deditio gradually leading to further results. The Twelve Tables (451 B.C.) provided that, if an animal had done damage, either the animal was to be surrendered or the damage paid for. /6/ We learn from Gains that the same rule was applied to the torts of children or slaves, /7/ and there is some trace of it with regard to inanimate things.

In Roman law, we see similar principles of noxoe deditio gradually leading to further outcomes. The Twelve Tables (451 B.C.) stated that if an animal caused damage, the owner had to either give up the animal or pay for the damage. /6/ Gains tells us that the same rule applied to the wrongdoings of children or slaves, /7/ and there's some evidence of it concerning inanimate objects.

The Roman lawyers, not looking beyond their own [9] system or their own time, drew on their wits for an explanation which would show that the law as they found it was reasonable. Gaius said that it was unjust that the fault of children or slaves should be a source of loss to their parents or owners beyond their own bodies, and Ulpian reasoned that a fortiori this was true of things devoid of life, and therefore incapable of fault. /1/ This way of approaching the question seems to deal with the right of surrender as if it were a limitation of a liability incurred by a parent or owner, which would naturally and in the first instance be unlimited. But if that is what was meant, it puts the cart before the horse. The right of surrender was not introduced as a limitation of liability, but, in Rome and Greece alike, payment was introduced as the alternative of a failure to surrender.

The Roman lawyers, not considering anything outside their own [9] system or their own time, used their reasoning to justify that the law as they saw it was fair. Gaius argued that it was unfair for the mistakes of children or slaves to cause losses to their parents or owners beyond their own physical bodies. Ulpian reasoned that even more so, this was true for inanimate things, which cannot be at fault. /1/ This way of addressing the issue seems to treat the right of surrender as if it were a limitation on a parent's or owner's liability, which would naturally and primarily be unlimited. However, if that was the intention, it is misguided. The right of surrender wasn't introduced as a limit on liability; rather, in both Rome and Greece, payment was established as an alternative to failing to surrender.

The action was not based, as it would be nowadays, on the fault of the parent or owner. If it had been, it would always have been brought against the person who had control of the slave or animal at the time it did the harm complained of, and who, if any one, was to blame for not preventing the injury. So far from this being the course, the person to be sued was the owner at the time of suing. The action followed the guilty thing into whosesoever hands it came. /2/ And in curious contrast with the principle as inverted to meet still more modern views of public policy, if the animal was of a wild nature, that is, in the very case of the most ferocious animals, the owner ceased to be liable the moment it escaped, because at that moment he ceased to be owner. /3/ There [10] seems to have been no other or more extensive liability by the old law, even where a slave was guilty with his master's knowledge, unless perhaps he was a mere tool in his master's hands. /1/ Gains and Ulpian showed an inclination to cut the noxoe deditio down to a privilege of the owner in case of misdeeds committed without his knowledge; but Ulpian is obliged to admit, that by the ancient law, according to Celsus, the action was noxal where a slave was guilty even with the privity of his master. /2/

The action wasn’t based, like it would be today, on the fault of the parent or owner. If it had been, it would always have been filed against the person in control of the slave or animal at the time the harm occurred, and who, if anyone, was at fault for not preventing the injury. Instead, the person who was sued was the owner at the time of the lawsuit. The action followed the guilty thing wherever it went. In a striking contrast to principles adapted to align with more modern views of public policy, if the animal was wild, meaning in the case of the most dangerous animals, the owner was no longer liable the moment it escaped, because at that moment, he no longer retained ownership. There seems to have been no other or broader liability under the old law, even when a slave acted with his master’s knowledge, unless he was just a tool in his master’s hands. Gains and Ulpian showed a tendency to limit the noxae deditio to a privilege of the owner in cases of wrongdoing committed without his knowledge; however, Ulpian had to acknowledge that under ancient law, according to Celsus, the action was noxal when a slave was guilty even with his master’s knowledge.

All this shows very clearly that the liability of the owner was merely a way of getting at the slave or animal which was the immediate cause of offence. In other words, vengeance on the immediate offender was the object of the Greek and early Roman process, not indemnity from the master or owner. The liability of the owner was simply a liability of the offending thing. In the primitive customs of Greece it was enforced by a judicial process expressly directed against the object, animate or inanimate. The Roman Twelve Tables made the owner, instead of the thing itself, the defendant, but did not in any way change the ground of liability, or affect its limit. The change was simply a device to allow the owner to protect his interest. /3/

All of this clearly shows that the owner's liability was just a way to target the slave or animal that caused the harm. In other words, the goal of the Greek and early Roman legal systems was to seek revenge on the direct offender, not to gain compensation from the master or owner. The owner's liability was essentially a liability of the offending item. In the ancient customs of Greece, this was enforced through a legal process specifically aimed at the object, whether it was alive or not. The Roman Twelve Tables made the owner, rather than the thing itself, the one being accused, but this didn't change the basis of liability or its limits. The change was merely a strategy to let the owner safeguard their interests. /3/

But it may be asked how inanimate objects came to be [11] pursued in this way, if the object of the procedure was to gratify the passion of revenge. Learned men have been ready to find a reason in the personification of inanimate nature common to savages and children, and there is much to confirm this view. Without such a personification, anger towards lifeless things would have been transitory, at most. It is noticeable that the commonest example in the most primitive customs and laws is that of a tree which falls upon a man, or from which he falls and is killed. We can conceive with comparative ease how a tree might have been put on the same footing with animals. It certainly was treated like them, and was delivered to the relatives, or chopped to pieces for the gratification of a real or simulated passion. /1/

But one might wonder how inanimate objects came to be [11] pursued like this if the goal was to satisfy the desire for revenge. Scholars have pointed to the personification of inanimate nature, which is common among primitive people and children, and there’s a lot to support this idea. Without such personification, anger towards lifeless objects would likely have been brief at best. It's interesting that one of the most common examples in the simplest customs and laws involves a tree that falls on a person or from which a person falls and is killed. We can easily imagine how a tree could be viewed similarly to animals. It certainly was treated like them, being handed over to family members or chopped up in response to a genuine or feigned passion. /1/

In the Athenian process there is also, no doubt, to be traced a different thought. Expiation is one of the ends most insisted on by Plato, and appears to have been the purpose of the procedure mentioned by Aeschines. Some passages in the Roman historians which will be mentioned again seem to point in the same direction. /2/

In the Athenian process, it’s clear that a different idea is also at play. Expiation is one of the main goals emphasized by Plato and seems to have been the intention behind the process described by Aeschines. Some excerpts from Roman historians that will be referenced later seem to suggest the same thing. /2/

Another peculiarity to be noticed is, that the liability seems to have been regarded as attached to the body doing the damage, in an almost physical sense. An untrained intelligence only imperfectly performs the analysis by which jurists carry responsibility back to the beginning of a chain of causation. The hatred for anything giving us pain, which wreaks itself on the manifest cause, and which leads even civilized man to kick a door when it pinches his finger, is embodied in the noxoe deditio and [12] other kindred doctrines of early Roman law. There is a defective passage in Gaius, which seems to say that liability may sometimes be escaped by giving up even the dead body of the offender. /1/ So Livy relates that, Brutulus Papins having caused a breach of truce with the Romans, the Samnites determined to surrender him, and that, upon his avoiding disgrace and punishment by suicide, they sent his lifeless body. It is noticeable that the surrender seems to be regarded as the natural expiation for the breach of treaty, /2/ and that it is equally a matter of course to send the body when the wrong-doer has perished. /3/

Another interesting point to note is that liability appears to have been seen as tied to the entity causing the harm, almost in a physical way. An untrained mind can only partially grasp the analysis through which legal experts trace responsibility back to the source of a chain of causation. The instinctive hatred for anything that causes us pain, which often leads even civilized people to kick a door when they stub their toe, is reflected in the noxae deditio and other related principles of early Roman law. There is a confusing passage in Gaius, which suggests that liability might sometimes be avoided by relinquishing even the dead body of the offender. /1/ Livy recounts that when Brutulus Papins caused a breach of truce with the Romans, the Samnites decided to hand him over, and after he avoided disgrace and punishment by committing suicide, they sent his lifeless body. It’s worth noting that the surrender is seen as the natural way to make amends for the breach of treaty, /2/ and it is equally expected to send the body when the wrongdoer has died. /3/

The most curious examples of this sort occur in the region of what we should now call contract. Livy again furnishes an example, if, indeed, the last is not one. The Roman Consul Postumius concluded the disgraceful peace of the Caudine Forks (per sponsionem, as Livy says, denying the common story that it was per feedus), and he was sent to Rome to obtain the sanction of the people. When there however, he proposed that the persons who had made the [13] contract, including himself, should be given up in satisfaction of it. For, he said, the Roman people not having sanctioned the agreement, who is so ignorant of the jus fetialium as not to know that they are released from obligation by surrendering us? The formula of surrender seems to bring the case within the noxoe deditio. /1/ Cicero narrates a similar surrender of Mancinus by the pater-patratus to the Numantines, who, however, like the Samnites in the former case, refused to receive him. /2/

The most intriguing examples of this type happen in what we would now refer to as contracts. Livy provides another example, if the last one isn’t already one. The Roman Consul Postumius made the disgraceful peace at the Caudine Forks (per sponsionem, as Livy mentions, contradicting the common belief that it was per feedus), and he was sent to Rome to get the approval of the people. However, when he got there, he suggested that the individuals who had entered into the [13] contract, himself included, should be surrendered to fulfill it. He argued that since the Roman people had not approved the agreement, who is so unaware of the jus fetialium that they don’t realize they are released from obligation by surrendering us? The act of surrender seems to place the situation within the noxae deditio. /1/ Cicero tells of a similar surrender of Mancinus by the pater-patratus to the Numantines, who, like the Samnites in the previous case, refused to accept him. /2/

It might be asked what analogy could have been found between a breach of contract and those wrongs which excite the desire for vengeance. But it must be remembered that the distinction between tort and breaches of contract, and especially between the remedies for the two, is not found ready made. It is conceivable that a procedure adapted to redress for violence was extended to other cases as they arose. Slaves were surrendered for theft as well as [14] for assault; /1/ and it is said that a debtor who did not pay his debts, or a seller who failed to deliver an article for which he had been paid, was dealt with on the same footing as a thief. /2/ This line of thought, together with the quasi material conception of legal obligations as binding the offending body, which has been noticed, would perhaps explain the well-known law of the Twelve Tables as to insolvent debtors. According to that law, if a man was indebted to several creditors and insolvent, after certain formalities they might cut up his body and divide it among them. If there was a single creditor, he might put his debtor to death or sell him as a slave. /3/

It might be wondered what comparison could be made between breaking a contract and those wrongs that stir feelings of revenge. However, it's important to note that the difference between torts and breach of contract, especially regarding the remedies for each, isn’t something that was clearly defined from the start. It’s possible that a system meant for addressing violence was also applied to other situations as they came up. Slaves were surrendered for theft just like they were for assault; and it’s said that a debtor who didn’t pay his debts, or a seller who failed to deliver something after being paid, was treated similarly to a thief. This reasoning, alongside the idea that legal obligations are tied to the person committing the offense, which has been mentioned, might help explain the well-known law from the Twelve Tables regarding insolvent debtors. According to that law, if a man owed money to several creditors and was unable to pay, after following certain formal procedures, they could cut up his body and share it among themselves. If there was only one creditor, he could kill his debtor or sell him as a slave.

If no other right were given but to reduce a debtor to slavery, the law might be taken to look only to compensation, and to be modelled on the natural working of self-redress. /4/ The principle of our own law, that taking a man's body on execution satisfies the debt, although he is not detained an hour, seems to be explained in that way. But the right to put to death looks like vengeance, and the division of the body shows that the debt was conceived very literally to inhere in or bind the body with a vinculum juris.

If the only right given was to turn a debtor into a slave, the law could be seen as focused solely on compensation, reflecting the natural principle of self-defense. The idea in our own legal system that taking a person's body for execution settles the debt, even if they are not held for a minute, makes sense in that context. However, the right to kill seems more like revenge, and the act of dividing the body indicates that the debt was understood very literally as being tied to or binding the body by a legal bond.

Whatever may be the true explanation of surrender in connection with contracts, for the present purpose we need not go further than the common case of noxoe deditio for wrongs. Neither is the seeming adhesion of liability to the very body which did the harm of the first importance. [15] The Roman law dealt mainly with living creatures,—with animals and slaves. If a man was run over, it did not surrender the wagon which crushed him, but the ox which drew the wagon. /1/ At this stage the notion is easy to understand. The desire for vengeance may be felt as strongly against a slave as against a freeman, and it is not without example nowadays that a like passion should be felt against an animal. The surrender of the slave or beast empowered the injured party to do his will upon them. Payment by the owner was merely a privilege in case he wanted to buy the vengeance off.

Whatever the true explanation of surrender in relation to contracts, for our current purpose, we don't need to go any further than the common case of noxae deditio for wrongs. The attachment of liability to the very entity that caused the harm is not the most important aspect. [15] Roman law primarily dealt with living beings—animals and slaves. If a person was run over, it wasn't the wagon that crushed them that was surrendered, but the ox that pulled the wagon. /1/ At this point, the idea is easy to grasp. The desire for revenge can be just as strong against a slave as it is against a free person, and there are still examples today of similar feelings directed toward an animal. Surrendering the slave or animal allowed the injured party to do as they wished with them. Payment from the owner was simply a privilege if they wanted to buy off the revenge.

It will readily be imagined that such a system as has been described could not last when civilization had advanced to any considerable height. What had been the privilege of buying off vengeance by agreement, of paying the damage instead of surrendering the body of the offender, no doubt became a general custom. The Aquilian law, passed about a couple of centuries later than the date of the Twelve Tables, enlarged the sphere of compensation for bodily injuries. Interpretation enlarged the Aquilian law. Masters became personally liable for certain wrongs committed by their slaves with their knowledge, where previously they were only bound to surrender the slave. /2/ If a pack-mule threw off his burden upon a passer-by because he had been improperly overloaded, or a dog which might have been restrained escaped from his master and bit any one, the old noxal action, as it was called, gave way to an action under the new law to enforce a general personal liability. /3/ Still later, ship-owners and innkeepers were made liable [16] as if they were wrong-doers for wrongs committed by those in their employ on board ship or in the tavern, although of course committed without their knowledge. The true reason for this exceptional responsibility was the exceptional confidence which was necessarily reposed in carriers and innkeepers. /1/ But some of the jurists, who regarded the surrender of children and slaves as a privilege intended to limit liability, explained this new liability on the ground that the innkeeper or ship-owner was to a certain degree guilty of negligence in having employed the services of bad men? This was the first instance of a master being made unconditionally liable for the wrongs of his servant. The reason given for it was of general application, and the principle expanded to the scope of the reason.

It’s easy to see that a system like the one described couldn’t last once civilization progressed significantly. The practice of buying off revenge through agreements and paying for damages instead of handing over the offender likely became widespread. The Aquilian law, introduced a couple of centuries after the Twelve Tables, broadened the scope for compensation for bodily injuries. Interpretations expanded the Aquilian law. Masters became personally liable for certain wrongs committed by their slaves with their knowledge, where they had previously only been required to surrender the slave. If a pack-mule dropped its load on someone because it was overloaded, or if a dog that could have been controlled got away from its owner and bit someone, the old noxal action was replaced by an action under the new law to ensure general personal liability. Even later on, shipowners and innkeepers were held liable as if they were the wrongdoers for actions committed by their employees on board ships or in taverns, even if they weren’t aware of it. The main reason for this unusual responsibility was the special trust placed in carriers and innkeepers. However, some legal experts, who saw the surrender of children and slaves as a way to limit liability, argued that this new liability came from the innkeeper or shipowner being somewhat negligent for hiring untrustworthy individuals. This was the first case where a master was held fully responsible for the actions of a servant. The rationale provided was widely applicable, and the principle grew with the reasoning.

The law as to ship-owners and innkeepers introduced another and more startling innovation. It made them responsible when those whom they employed were free, as well as when they were slaves. /3/ For the first time one man was made answerable for the wrongs of another who was also answerable himself, and who had a standing before the law. This was a great change from the bare permission to ransom one's slave as a privilege. But here we have the history of the whole modern doctrine of master and servant, and principal and agent. All servants are now as free and as liable to a suit as their masters. Yet the principle introduced on special grounds in a special case, when servants were slaves, is now the general law of this country and England, and under it men daily have to pay large sums for other people's acts, in which they had no part and [17] for which they are in no sense to blame. And to this day the reason offered by the Roman jurists for an exceptional rule is made to justify this universal and unlimited responsibility. /1/

The laws regarding shipowners and innkeepers introduced a new and surprising change. They became responsible not only for the actions of their enslaved workers but also for those who were free. For the first time, one person was held accountable for the wrongs committed by another who also had legal responsibility and stood before the law. This was a significant shift from just being allowed to buy back one’s slave as a privilege. Here we find the foundations of the modern legal principles of employer and employee, as well as principal and agent. Nowadays, all employees are as independent and liable to lawsuits as their employers. However, the principle that was introduced in specific situations involving enslaved workers has now become standard law in this country and England. Under this principle, people often have to pay substantial sums for actions taken by others, actions they were not involved in and for which they bear no blame. Even today, the justification initially provided by Roman legal experts for this specific rule is still used to rationalize this broad and unlimited liability.

So much for one of the parents of our common law. Now let us turn for a moment to the Teutonic side. The Salic Law embodies usages which in all probability are of too early a date to have been influenced either by Rome or the Old Testament. The thirty-sixth chapter of the ancient text provides that, if a man is killed by a domestic animal, the owner of the animal shall pay half the composition (which he would have had to pay to buy off the blood feud had he killed the man himself), and for the other half give up the beast to the complainant. /2/ So, by chapter thirty-five, if a slave killed a freeman, he was to be surrendered for one half of the composition to the relatives of the slain man, and the master was to pay the other half. But according to the gloss, if the slave or his master had been maltreated by the slain man or his relatives, the master had only to surrender the slave. /3/ It is interesting to notice that those Northern sources which Wilda takes to represent a more primitive stage of German law confine liability for animals to surrender alone. /4/ There is also a trace of the master's having been able to free himself in some cases, at a later date, by showing that the slave was no longer in [18] his possession. /1/ There are later provisions making a master liable for the wrongs committed by his slave by his command. /2/ In the laws adapted by the Thuringians from the earlier sources, it is provided in terms that the master is to pay for all damage done by his slaves. /4/

So much for one of the roots of our common law. Now let’s shift our focus to the Teutonic side. The Salic Law includes customs that probably date back too far to have been influenced by either Rome or the Old Testament. The thirty-sixth chapter of this ancient text states that if a man is killed by a domestic animal, the animal's owner must pay half the compensation they would have needed to resolve the blood feud if they had killed the man themselves, and for the other half, they must surrender the animal to the victim's relatives. /2/ Similarly, chapter thirty-five says that if a slave kills a free person, the slave must be given up for half of the compensation to the relatives of the deceased, and the master must pay the other half. However, according to the commentary, if the slave or their master had been mistreated by the deceased or their relatives, the master only needs to hand over the slave. /3/ It's interesting to note that those Northern sources which Wilda claims represent a more primitive stage of German law only require the surrender of the animal for any related liability. /4/ There is also evidence that the master could sometimes absolve themselves later by proving that the slave was no longer in their possession. /1/ Later laws make a master liable for the wrongs committed by their slave under their orders. /2/ In the laws adapted by the Thuringians from earlier sources, it specifically states that the master must compensate for all damage caused by their slaves. /4/

In short, so far as I am able to trace the order of development in the customs of the German tribes, it seems to have been entirely similar to that which we have already followed in the growth of Roman law. The earlier liability for slaves and animals was mainly confined to surrender; the later became personal, as at Rome.

In short, as far as I can see the progression of customs among the German tribes, it appears to mirror what we've already observed in the evolution of Roman law. Initially, responsibility for slaves and animals was mostly limited to surrender; later, it became personal, similar to Rome.

The reader may begin to ask for the proof that all this has any bearing on our law of today. So far as concerns the influence of the Roman law upon our own, especially the Roman law of master and servant, the evidence of it is to be found in every book which has been written for the last five hundred years. It has been stated already that we still repeat the reasoning of the Roman lawyers, empty as it is, to the present day. It will be seen directly whether the German folk-laws can also be followed into England.

The reader might start to wonder how all of this relates to our laws today. When it comes to the impact of Roman law on our legal system, particularly regarding the relationship between masters and servants, there's evidence of it in every book written over the past five hundred years. It’s already been noted that we continue to use the reasoning of Roman lawyers, even if it's lacking substance, to this day. We will soon see if the German folk laws can also be traced in England.

In the Kentish laws of Hlothhaere and Eadrie (A.D. 680) [19] it is said, "If any one's slave slay a freeman, whoever it be, let the owner pay with a hundred shillings, give up the slayer," &c. /1/ There are several other similar provisions. In the nearly contemporaneous laws of Ine, the surrender and payment are simple alternatives. "If a Wessex slave slay an Englishman, then shall he who owns him deliver him up to the lord and the kindred, or give sixty shillings for his life." /2/ Alfred's laws (A.D. 871-901) have a like provision as to cattle. "If a neat wound a man, let the neat be delivered up or compounded for." /3/ And Alfred, although two hundred years later than the first English lawgivers who have been quoted, seems to have gone back to more primitive notions than we find before his time. For the same principle is extended to the case of a tree by which a man is killed. "If, at their common work, one man slay another unwilfully, let the tree be given to the kindred, and let them have it off the land within thirty nights. Or let him take possession of it who owns the wood." /4/

In the Kentish laws of Hlothhaere and Eadrie (A.D. 680) [19] it is stated, "If anyone’s slave kills a freeman, regardless of who it is, the owner must pay a hundred shillings and hand over the slayer," &c. /1/ There are several other similar provisions. In the almost simultaneous laws of Ine, surrender and payment are straightforward alternatives. "If a Wessex slave kills an Englishman, then the owner must either turn him over to the lord and the family or pay sixty shillings for his life." /2/ Alfred's laws (A.D. 871-901) have a similar rule regarding cattle. "If a cattle injures a man, let the cattle be handed over or compensated for." /3/ And Alfred, even though he was two hundred years later than the first English lawgivers mentioned, seems to have reverted to more primitive ideas than those we find before his time. The same principle is applied in the case of a tree that causes a man’s death. "If, during their shared work, one man unintentionally kills another, the tree should be given to the family, and they must remove it from the land within thirty nights. Or let the owner of the wood take possession of it." /4/

It is not inapposite to compare what Mr. Tylor has mentioned concerning the rude Kukis of Southern Asia. "If a tiger killed a Kuki, his family were in disgrace till they had retaliated by killing and eating this tiger, or another; but further, if a man was killed by a fall from a tree, his relatives would take their revenge by cutting the tree down, and scattering it in chips." /5/

It’s reasonable to compare what Mr. Tylor said about the primitive Kukis of Southern Asia. "If a tiger killed a Kuki, his family was in disgrace until they got revenge by killing and eating that tiger or another one; and if a man died from falling out of a tree, his relatives would take their revenge by cutting down the tree and scattering it in pieces." /5/

To return to the English, the later laws, from about a hundred years after Alfred down to the collection known as the laws of Henry I, compiled long after the Conquest, [20] increase the lord's liability for his household, and make him surety for his men's good conduct. If they incur a fine to the king and run away, the lord has to pay it unless he can clear himself of complicity. But I cannot say that I find until a later period the unlimited liability of master for servant which was worked out on the Continent, both by the German tribes and at Rome. Whether the principle when established was an indigenous growth, or whether the last step was taken under the influence of the Roman law, of which Bracton made great use, I cannot say. It is enough that the soil was ready for it, and that it took root at an early day. /1/ This is all that need be said here with regard to the liability of a master for the misdeeds of his servants.

To get back to the English context, the later laws, from about a hundred years after Alfred until the collection known as the laws of Henry I, which were compiled long after the Conquest, [20] increase the lord's responsibility for his household and hold him accountable for his men's behavior. If they incur a fine from the king and run away, the lord has to pay it unless he can prove he wasn't involved. However, I can't say that I see the unlimited liability of a master for their servant, which was developed on the Continent, both by the German tribes and in Rome, until a later period. Whether this principle, once established, was a homegrown development or if the final step was influenced by Roman law, which Bracton heavily relied on, I can't say. What matters is that the environment was conducive to it, and that it took hold early on. /1/ That's all that needs to be mentioned here regarding a master's liability for their servants' wrongdoings.

It is next to be shown what became of the principle as applied to animals. Nowadays a man is bound at his peril to keep his cattle from trespassing, and he is liable for damage done by his dog or by any fierce animal, if he has notice of a tendency in the brute to do the harm complained of. The question is whether any connection can be established between these very sensible and intelligible rules of modern law and the surrender directed by King Alfred.

It is now time to show what happened with the principle as it relates to animals. Nowadays, a person is obliged, under threat of penalty, to prevent their livestock from trespassing, and they are responsible for any damage caused by their dog or any dangerous animal if they are aware of the animal's tendency to cause the harm in question. The question is whether any link can be made between these logical and clear rules of modern law and the surrender ordered by King Alfred.

Let us turn to one of the old books of the Scotch law, where the old principle still appears in full force and is stated with its reasons as then understood, /2/

Let’s look at one of the old books of Scottish law, where the old principle is still clearly presented and explained with the reasoning as it was understood back then, /2/

"Gif ane wylde or head-strang horse, carries ane man [21] against his will over an craig, or heuch, or to the water, and the man happin to drowne, the horse sall perteine to the king as escheit.

" if a wild or headstrong horse carries a man [21] against his will over a cliff, or bank, or into the water, and the man happens to drown, the horse shall belong to the king as forfeit."

"Bot it is otherwise of ane tame and dantoned horse; gif any man fulishlie rides, and be sharp spurres compelles his horse to take the water, and the man drownes, the horse sould not be escheit, for that comes be the mans fault or trespasse, and not of the horse, and the man has receaved his punishment, in sa farre as he is perished and dead; and the horse quha did na fault, sould not be escheit.

"But it's different for a tame and gentle horse; if someone foolishly rides and uses sharp spurs to force his horse to go into the water, and the man drowns, the horse shouldn't be blamed, as that is the man's fault or wrongdoing, not the horse's. The man has already faced his punishment by perishing and dying; therefore, the horse, which did nothing wrong, should not be blamed."

"The like reason is of all other beastes, quhilk slayes anie man, [it is added in a later work, "of the quhilk slaughter they haue gilt,"] for all these beasts sould be escheit." /1/

"The same reason applies to all other beasts that kill any man, [it is added in a later work, 'of which slaughter they are guilty,'] for all these beasts should be avoided." /1/

"The Forme and Maner of Baron Courts" continues as follows:—

"The Forme and Maner of Baron Courts" continues as follows:—

"It is to witt, that this question is asked in the law, Gif ane lord hes ane milne, and any man fall in the damne, and be borne down with the water quhill he comes to the quheill, and there be slaine to death with the quheill; quhither aught the milne to be eseheir or not? The law sayes thereto nay, and be this reason, For it is ane dead thing, and ane dead thing may do na fellony, nor be made escheit throw their gilt. Swa the milne in this case is not culpable, and in the law it is lawfull to the lord of the land to haue ane mylne on his awin water quhere best likes him." /2/

"It is to say that this question is asked in the law: If a lord has a mill, and a man falls into the dam and is carried down by the water until he reaches the wheel, and there is killed by the wheel; should the mill be forfeited or not? The law says no, and for this reason: it is an inanimate object, and an inanimate object cannot commit a felony, nor can it be forfeited due to their wrongdoing. Thus, the mill in this case is not at fault, and according to the law, it is lawful for the landowner to have a mill on his own water wherever he prefers." /2/

The reader will see in this passage, as has been remarked already of the Roman law, that a distinction is taken between things which are capable of guilt and those which [22] are not,—between living and dead things; but he will also see that no difficulty was felt in treating animals as guilty.

The reader will notice in this passage, as has already been pointed out about Roman law, that a distinction is made between things that can be guilty and those that cannot—between living and dead things; but they will also see that there was no issue in considering animals as guilty.

Take next an early passage of the English law, a report of what was laid down by one of the English judges. In 1333 it was stated for law, that, "if my dog kills your sheep, and I, freshly after the fact, tender you the dog, you are without recovery against me." /1/ More than three centuries later, in 1676, it was said by Twisden, J. that, "if one hath kept a tame fox, which gets loose and grows wild, he that hath kept him before shall not answer for the damage the fox doth after he hath lost him, and he hath resumed his wild nature." /2/ It is at least doubtful whether that sentence ever would have been written but for the lingering influence of the notion that the ground of the owner's liability was his ownership of the offending: thing and his failure to surrender it. When the fox escaped, by another principle of law the ownership was at an end. In fact, that very consideration was seriously pressed in England as late as 1846, with regard to a monkey which escaped and bit the plaintiff, /3/ So it seems to be a reasonable conjecture, that it was this way of thinking which led Lord Holt, near the beginning of the last century, to intimate that one ground on which a man is bound at his peril to restrain cattle from trespassing is that he has valuable property in such animals, whereas he has not dogs, for which his responsibility is less. /4/ To this day, in fact, cautious judges state the law as to cattle to be, that, "if I am the owner of an animal in which by law the [23] right of property can exist, I am bound to take care that it does not stray into the land of my neighbor." /1/

Take next an early example of English law, a report of what was established by one of the English judges. In 1333, it was stated for law that, "if my dog kills your sheep, and I immediately after the fact offer you the dog, you cannot take any legal action against me." /1/ More than three centuries later, in 1676, Twisden, J. said that, "if someone has kept a tame fox that escapes and becomes wild, the person who kept it before is not responsible for the damage the fox causes after it has escaped and reverted to its wild nature." /2/ It is at least questionable whether that statement would have ever been made without the lingering belief that the basis of the owner's liability was their ownership of the offending thing and their failure to recover it. When the fox escaped, according to another principle of law, ownership was ended. In fact, this very point was seriously argued in England as late as 1846, concerning a monkey that escaped and bit the plaintiff. /3/ Thus, it seems reasonable to think that this way of reasoning led Lord Holt, near the beginning of the last century, to suggest that one reason a person is legally required to keep their cattle from trespassing is that they have valuable property in those animals, whereas they do not have the same responsibility for dogs. /4/ To this day, careful judges state the law regarding cattle as follows: "if I am the owner of an animal that, by law, can have the right of property, I must ensure that it does not wander into my neighbor's land." /1/

I do not mean that our modern law on this subject is only a survival, and that the only change from primitive notions was to substitute the owner for the offending animal. For although it is probable that the early law was one of the causes which led to the modern doctrine, there has been too much good sense in every stage of our law to adopt any such sweeping consequences as would follow from the wholesale transfer of liability supposed. An owner is not bound at his peril to keep his cattle from harming his neighbor's person. /2/ And in some of the earliest instances of personal liability, even for trespass on a neighbor's land, the ground seems to have been the owner's negligence. /3/

I don't mean to suggest that our current laws on this topic are just a remnant of the past or that the only difference from primitive ideas is that we now hold the owner accountable instead of the offending animal. While it's likely that early laws contributed to the development of modern principles, there has been a significant amount of reason throughout the history of our laws to avoid such drastic outcomes that would result from completely shifting liability as assumed. An owner is not strictly responsible for ensuring that their livestock doesn't harm a neighbor. In some of the earliest cases of personal liability, even for trespassing on a neighbor's property, it appears that the basis was the owner's negligence.

It is the nature of those animals which the common law recognizes as the subject of ownership to stray, and when straying to do damage by trampling down and eating crops. At the same time it is usual and easy to restrain them. On the other hand, a dog, which is not the subject of property, does no harm by simply crossing the land of others than its owner. Hence to this extent the new law might have followed the old. The right of property in the [24] offending animal, which was the ancient ground of responsibility, might have been adopted safely enough as the test of a liability based on the fault of the owner. But the responsibility for damage of a kind not to be expected from such animals is determined on grounds of policy comparatively little disturbed by tradition. The development of personal liability for fierce wild animals at Rome has been explained. Our law seems to have followed the Roman.

It is typical for animals recognized by common law as owned to wander off, and when they do, they can cause damage by trampling and eating crops. However, it’s usually simple to keep them contained. On the other hand, a dog, which isn’t considered property, doesn’t cause harm just by crossing onto someone else's land. So, in this regard, the new law could have aligned with the old. The property rights concerning the [24] offending animal, which was the historical basis for responsibility, could have been safely used as a measure for liability based on the owner’s fault. Yet, the responsibility for damage that isn’t typically expected from such animals is determined more by policy than by tradition. The development of personal liability for dangerous wild animals in Rome has been clarified. Our law seems to have drawn from the Roman example.

We will now follow the history of that branch of the primitive notion which was least likely to survive,—the liability of inanimate things.

We will now explore the history of that aspect of the original idea that was least likely to endure—the responsibility of inanimate objects.

It will be remembered that King Alfred ordained the surrender of a tree, but that the later Scotch law refused it because a dead thing could not have guilt. It will be remembered, also, that the animals which the Scotch law forfeited were escheat to the king. The same thing has remained true in England until well into this century, with regard even to inanimate objects. As long ago as Bracton, /1/ in case a man was slain, the coroner was to value the object causing the death, and that was to be forfeited sa deodand "pro rege." It was to be given to God, that is to say to the Church, for the king, to be expended for the good of his soul. A man's death had ceased to be the private affair of his friends as in the time of the barbarian folk-laws. The king, who furnished the court, now sued for the penalty. He supplanted the family in the claim on the guilty thing, and the Church supplanted him.

It’s important to remember that King Alfred ordered the surrender of a tree, but later Scottish law rejected this because a lifeless object couldn’t be held guilty. It’s also worth noting that the animals forfeited under Scottish law were taken by the king. This principle continued to apply in England well into this century, even regarding inanimate objects. As far back as Bracton, if a person was killed, the coroner was to assess the object that caused the death, which would then be forfeited as deodand "for the king." This meant it was to be given to God, or in other words, to the Church, for the king, to be used for the benefit of his soul. A person’s death had stopped being a private matter for their friends, as it was in the times of the barbarian folk-laws. The king, who provided the court, now pursued the penalty. He replaced the family in their claim on the guilty item, and the Church took his place.

In Edward the First's time some of the cases remind of the barbarian laws at their rudest stage. If a man fell from a tree, the tree was deodand. /2/ If he drowned in a [25] well, the well was to be filled up. /1/ It did not matter that the forfeited instrument belonged to an innocent person. "Where a man killeth another with the sword of John at Stile, the sword shall be forfeit as deodand, and yet no default is in the owner." /2/ That is from a book written in the reign of Henry VIII., about 1530. And it has been repeated from Queen Elizabeth's time /3/ to within one hundred years, /4/ that if my horse strikes a man, and afterwards I sell my horse, and after that the man dies, the horse shall be forfeited. Hence it is, that, in all indictments for homicide, until very lately it has been necessary to state the instrument causing the death and its value, as that the stroke was given by a certain penknife, value sixpence, so as to secure the forfeiture. It is said that a steam-engine has been forfeited in this way.

In Edward the First's time, some of the cases are reminiscent of barbaric laws at their most primitive. If a man fell from a tree, the tree was considered deodand. /2/ If he drowned in a [25] well, the well had to be filled in. /1/ It didn't matter that the forfeited item belonged to an innocent person. "If a man kills another with the sword of John at Stile, the sword shall be forfeited as deodand, and yet the owner is not to blame." /2/ This comes from a book written during Henry VIII's reign, around 1530. And it has been repeated from Queen Elizabeth's time /3/ up to within the last hundred years, /4/ that if my horse injures a man, and then I sell my horse, and later the man dies, the horse will be forfeited. Because of this, in all homicide indictments, until very recently, it has been necessary to specify the item that caused the death and its value, such as stating that the injury was caused by a particular penknife worth sixpence, to ensure the forfeiture. It's said that a steam engine has been forfeited this way.

I now come to what I regard as the most remarkable transformation of this principle, and one which is a most important factor in our law as it is today. I must for the moment leave the common law and take up the doctrines of the Admiralty. In the early books which have just been referred to, and long afterwards, the fact of motion is adverted to as of much importance. A maxim of Henry Spigurnel, a judge in the time of Edward I., is reported, that "where a man is killed by a cart, or by the fall of a house, or in other like manner, and the thing in motion is the cause of the death, it shall be deodand." /5/ So it was [26] said in the next reign that "oinne illud quod mover cum eo quod occidit homines deodandum domino Regi erit, vel feodo clerici." /1/ The reader sees how motion gives life to the object forfeited.

I now want to discuss what I believe is the most significant change to this principle, which is a crucial part of our current law. For now, I have to shift from common law to the doctrines of Admiralty. In the early texts I just mentioned, and for a long time afterward, the concept of motion is highlighted as very important. A saying from Henry Spigurnel, a judge during Edward I's reign, states that "if someone is killed by a cart, or by a falling house, or in a similar way, and the moving object causes the death, it shall be considered a deodand." /5/ Similarly, it was said in the next reign that "everything that moves with what kills a person will be deemed a deodand to the King, or to the clergy." /1/ The reader can see how motion brings significance to the object that is forfeited.

The most striking example of this sort is a ship. And accordingly the old books say that, if a man falls from a ship and is drowned, the motion of the ship must be taken to cause the death, and the ship is forfeited,—provided, however, that this happens in fresh water. /2/ For if the death took place on the high seas, that was outside the ordinary jurisdiction. This proviso has been supposed to mean that ships at sea were not forfeited; /3/ but there is a long series of petitions to the king in Parliament that such forfeitures may be done away with, which tell a different story. /4/ The truth seems to be that the forfeiture took place, but in a different court. A manuscript of the reign of Henry VI., only recently printed, discloses the fact that, if a man was killed or drowned at sea by the motion of the ship, the vessel was forfeited to the admiral upon a proceeding in the admiral's court, and subject to release by favor of the admiral or the king. /5/

The most striking example of this kind is a ship. Old texts state that if a person falls overboard and drowns, the ship's motion is considered the cause of death, and the ship is forfeited, as long as this occurs in fresh water. /2/ However, if the death occurs on the open sea, that's beyond normal jurisdiction. This condition has been thought to mean that ships at sea aren’t forfeited; /3/ but there are numerous petitions to the king in Parliament asking that such forfeitures be abolished, which tells a different story. /4/ The reality seems to be that forfeiture did happen, but in a different court. A recently printed manuscript from the reign of Henry VI reveals that if someone was killed or drowned at sea due to the ship's motion, the vessel was forfeited to the admiral following a process in the admiral's court, and could be released at the discretion of the admiral or the king. /5/

A ship is the most living of inanimate things. Servants sometimes say "she" of a clock, but every one gives a gender to vessels. And we need not be surprised, therefore, to find a mode of dealing which has shown such extraordinary vitality in the criminal law applied with even more striking thoroughness in the Admiralty. It is only by supposing [27] the ship to have been treated as if endowed with personality, that the arbitrary seeming peculiarities of the maritime law can be made intelligible, and on that supposition they at once become consistent and logical.

A ship is the most alive of non-living things. People sometimes refer to a clock as “she,” but everyone assigns a gender to ships. It’s no surprise, then, that a way of handling things has demonstrated such remarkable resilience in criminal law that it’s applied even more thoroughly in Admiralty. It’s only by assuming [27] the ship has been treated as if it has its own personality that the seemingly arbitrary quirks of maritime law can be understood, and with that assumption, they suddenly make sense and become logical.

By way of seeing what those peculiarities are, take first a case of collision at sea. A collision takes place between two vessels, the Ticonderoga and the Melampus, through the fault of the Ticonderoga alone. That ship is under a lease at the time, the lessee has his own master in charge, and the owner of the vessel has no manner of control over it. The owner, therefore, is not to blame, and he cannot even be charged on the ground that the damage was done by his servants. He is free from personal liability on elementary principles. Yet it is perfectly settled that there is a lien on his vessel for the amount of the damage done, /1/ and this means that that vessel may be arrested and sold to pay the loss in any admiralty court whose process will reach her. If a livery-stable keeper lets a horse and wagon to a customer, who runs a man down by careless driving, no one would think of claiming a right to seize the horse and wagon. It would be seen that the only property which could be sold to pay for a wrong was the property of the wrong-doer.

To understand these peculiarities, let's consider a case of a collision at sea. A collision occurs between two ships, the Ticonderoga and the Melampus, due solely to the fault of the Ticonderoga. At the time, the Ticonderoga is leased to someone who has their own captain in charge, and the owner of the ship has no control over it. Therefore, the owner is not to blame, and they can't even be held responsible because the damage was caused by someone acting on their own. They aren't personally liable according to basic principles. However, it's clearly established that there is a lien on their vessel for the amount of damages caused, which means that the ship can be seized and sold to cover the loss in any admiralty court that has jurisdiction over it. If a stable owner rents out a horse and wagon to a customer who accidentally hits someone while driving recklessly, no one would think to seize the horse and wagon. It would be understood that the only property that could be sold to cover the damage would be that of the person who caused the harm.

But, again, suppose that the vessel, instead of being under lease, is in charge of a pilot whose employment is made compulsory by the laws of the port which she is just entering. The Supreme Court of the United States holds the ship liable in this instance also. /2/ The English courts would probably have decided otherwise, and the matter is settled in England by legislation. But there the court of appeal, the Privy Council, has been largely composed of common-law [28]lawyers, and it has shown a marked tendency to assimilate common-law doctrine. At common law one who could not impose a personal liability on the owner could not bind a particular chattel to answer for a wrong of which it had been the instrument. But our Supreme Court has long recognized that a person may bind a ship, when he could not bind the owners personally, because he was not the agent.

But, again, let's say the vessel, instead of being leased, is managed by a pilot whose employment is required by the laws of the port she is entering. The Supreme Court of the United States holds the ship liable in this case as well. /2/ The English courts would probably have ruled differently, and this issue is resolved in England through legislation. However, the court of appeal, the Privy Council, has been largely made up of common-law [28]lawyers, and it has shown a strong tendency to adopt common-law principles. Under common law, someone who couldn't impose personal liability on the owner couldn't hold a specific item responsible for a wrongdoing it facilitated. But our Supreme Court has long accepted that a person can hold a ship accountable, even when they couldn't hold the owners personally liable, because they weren't the agent.

It may be admitted that, if this doctrine were not supported by an appearance of good sense, it would not have survived. The ship is the only security available in dealing with foreigners, and rather than send one's own citizens to search for a remedy abroad in strange courts, it is easy to seize the vessel and satisfy the claim at home, leaving the foreign owners to get their indemnity as they may be able. I dare say some such thought has helped to keep the practice alive, but I believe the true historic foundation is elsewhere. The ship no doubt, like a sword would have been forfeited for causing death, in whosesoever hands it might have been. So, if the master and mariners of a ship, furnished with letters of reprisal, committed piracy against a friend of the king, the owner lost his ship by the admiralty law, although the crime was committed without his knowledge or assent. /2/ It seems most likely that the principle by which the ship was forfeited to the king for causing death, or for piracy, was the same as that by which it was bound to private sufferers for other damage, in whose hands soever it might have been when it did the harm.

It can be acknowledged that if this principle weren't backed by some semblance of logic, it wouldn't have lasted. The ship is the only security option for dealing with foreigners, and instead of sending one's own citizens to seek justice abroad in unfamiliar courts, it's simpler to seize the vessel and settle the claim locally, leaving the foreign owners to figure out how to get compensated on their own. I suspect that this kind of thinking has played a role in keeping the practice going, but I think the real historical basis lies elsewhere. The ship, much like a sword, would have been forfeited for causing death, regardless of who held it. Therefore, if the captain and crew of a ship, holding letters of reprisal, engaged in piracy against a royal ally, the owner would lose his ship under admiralty law, even though the crime was committed without his knowledge or consent. It seems most probable that the principle where the ship was forfeited to the king for causing death, or for piracy, was the same principle that held it accountable to private victims for other damages, no matter whose hands it was in when the harm occurred.

If we should say to an uneducated man today, "She did it and she ought to pay for it," it may be doubted [29] whether he would see the fallacy, or be ready to explain that the ship was only property, and that to say, "The ship has to pay for it," /1/ was simply a dramatic way of saying that somebody's property was to be sold, and the proceeds applied to pay for a wrong committed by somebody else.

If we were to tell an uneducated person today, "She did it and she should pay for it," it might be questioned [29] whether he would recognize the error in that statement or be prepared to explain that the ship was just property, and that saying, "The ship has to pay for it," /1/ was just a dramatic way of saying that someone's property was going to be sold, and the money from that sale would be used to make up for a wrong done by someone else.

It would seem that a similar form of words has been enough to satisfy the minds of great lawyers. The following is a passage from a judgment by Chief Justice Marshall, which is quoted with approval by Judge Story in giving the opinion of the Supreme Court of the United States: "This is not a proceeding against the owner; it is a proceeding against the vessel for an offence committed by the vessel; which is not the less an offence, and does not the less subject her to forfeiture, because it was committed without the authority and against the will of the owner. It is true that inanimate matter can commit no offence. But this body is animated and put in action by the crew, who are guided by the master. The vessel acts and speaks by the master. She reports herself by the master. It is, therefore, not unreasonable that the vessel should be affected by this report." And again Judge Story quotes from another case: "The thing is here primarily considered as the offender, or rather the offence is primarily attached to the thing." /2/

It seems that a similar way of expressing things has been enough to satisfy the minds of great lawyers. Here’s a quote from a judgment by Chief Justice Marshall, which Judge Story cites approvingly in the Supreme Court of the United States: "This is not a case against the owner; it's a case against the vessel for an offense committed by the vessel; and this offense does not become less significant and doesn't exempt her from forfeiture simply because it was done without the owner's permission and against their wishes. It's true that inanimate objects can't commit an offense. But this vessel is brought to life and set in motion by the crew, who follow the master's direction. The vessel acts and communicates through the master. It’s therefore reasonable that the vessel should be impacted by this report." And again, Judge Story cites another case: "The thing is primarily seen here as the offender, or rather the offense is primarily linked to the thing." /2/

In other words, those great judges, although of course aware that a ship is no more alive than a mill-wheel, thought that not only the law did in fact deal with it as if it were alive, but that it was reasonable that the law should do so. The reader will observe that they do not say simply that it is reasonable on grounds of policy to [30] sacrifice justice to the owner to security for somebody else but that it is reasonable to deal with the vessel as an offending thing. Whatever the hidden ground of policy may be, their thought still clothes itself in personifying language.

In other words, those great judges, while knowing that a ship is no more alive than a mill-wheel, believed that not only does the law treat it as if it were alive, but that it's reasonable for the law to do so. The reader will notice that they don’t merely claim it's reasonable for policy reasons to [30] sacrifice justice for the owner in favor of security for someone else, but that it's reasonable to treat the ship as if it were an offending entity. Whatever the underlying policy may be, their thoughts still express themselves in personifying language.

Let us now go on to follow the peculiarities of the maritime law in other directions. For the cases which have been stated are only parts of a larger whole.

Let’s now continue to explore the unique aspects of maritime law in other areas. The cases mentioned are just pieces of a bigger picture.

By the maritime law of the Middle Ages the ship was not only the source, but the limit, of liability. The rule already prevailed, which has been borrowed and adopted by the English statutes and by our own act of Congress of 1851, according to which the owner is discharged from responsibility for wrongful acts of a master appointed by himself upon surrendering his interest in the vessel and the freight which she had earned. By the doctrines of agency he would be personally liable for the whole damage. If the origin of the system of limited liability which is believed to be so essential to modern commerce is to be attributed to those considerations of public policy on which it would now be sustained, that system has nothing to do with the law of collision. But if the limit of liability here stands on the same ground as the noxoe deditio, confirms the explanation already given of the liability of the ship for wrongs done by it while out of the owner's hands, and conversely existence of that liability confirms the argument here.

Under medieval maritime law, a ship was both the source and the limit of liability. The rule was already established, which has been adopted by English laws and our own Congress in 1851. According to this rule, the owner is relieved from responsibility for wrongful acts committed by a captain he appointed once he relinquishes his interest in the vessel and the freight it has earned. According to agency laws, the owner would be personally liable for the full amount of damages. If the origins of the limited liability system, considered crucial for modern commerce, are linked to public policy reasons that still support it today, this system is not connected to collision laws. However, if the limit of liability here is grounded in the same principles as the noxoe deditio, it supports the earlier explanation of the ship's liability for wrongful acts committed while it was not in the owner’s control, and likewise, the existence of that liability reinforces the argument here.

Let us now take another rule, for which, as usual, there is a plausible explanation of policy. Freight, it is said, the mother of wages; for, we are told, "if the ship perished, [31] if the mariners were to have their wages in such cases, they would not use their endeavors, nor hazard their lives, for the safety of the ship." /1/ The best commentary on this reasoning is, that the law has recently been changed by statute. But even by the old law there was an exception inconsistent with the supposed reason. In case of shipwreck, which was the usual case of a failure to earn freight, so long as any portion of the ship was saved, the lien of the mariners remained. I suppose it would have been said, because it was sound policy to encourage them to save all they could. If we consider that the sailors were regarded as employed by the ship, we shall understand very readily both the rule and the exception. "The ship is the debtor," as was said in arguing a case decided in the time of William III. /2/ If the debtor perished, there was an end of the matter. If a part came ashore, that might be proceeded against.

Let’s discuss another rule, which, as usual, has a reasonable explanation behind it. It’s said that freight is the source of wages; because, as we’re told, "if the ship goes down, [31] if the sailors were to get their wages in such situations, they wouldn’t put in any effort or risk their lives for the safety of the ship." /1/ The best commentary on this reasoning is that the law has recently changed. However, even under the old law, there was an exception that contradicted the supposed reasoning. In the case of a shipwreck, which was a common reason for not earning freight, as long as any part of the ship was saved, the sailors still had their claim. It was probably argued that it was good policy to encourage them to save as much as possible. If we think of sailors as being employed by the ship, we’ll easily understand both the rule and the exception. "The ship is the debtor," as it was stated in a case argued during the time of William III. /2/ If the debtor was gone, that settled the issue. If part of the ship made it ashore, that could still be pursued.

Even the rule in its modern form, that freight is the mother of wages, is shown by the explanation commonly given to have reference to the question whether the ship is lost or arrive safe. In the most ancient source of the maritime law now extant, which has anything about the matter, so far as I have been able to discover, the statement is that the mariners will lose their wages when the ship is lost. /3/ In like manner, in what is said by its English [32] editor, Sir Travers Twiss, to be the oldest part of the Consulate of the Sea, /1/ we read that "whoever the freighter may be who runs away or dies, the ship is bound to pay: the mariners." /2/ I think we may assume that the vessel was bound by the contract with the sailors, much in the same way as it was by the wrongs for which it was answerable, just as the debtor's body was answerable for his debts, as well as for his crimes, under the ancient law of Rome.

Even the modern rule that freight is the source of wages shows that it’s related to whether the ship is lost or arrives safely. In the oldest known source of maritime law that I've found, it states that the sailors will lose their wages if the ship is lost. Similarly, in what Sir Travers Twiss, its English editor, claims is the oldest part of the Consulate of the Sea, it says, "whoever the freighter may be who runs away or dies, the ship is bound to pay the sailors." I believe we can assume that the vessel was bound by the contract with the sailors, just as it was accountable for the wrongs it committed, similar to how a debtor could be held liable for both debts and crimes under ancient Roman law.

The same thing is true of other maritime dealings with the vessel, whether by way of contract or otherwise. If salvage service is rendered to a vessel, the admiralty court will hold the vessel, although it has been doubted whether an action of contract would lie, if the owners were sued at law. So the ship is bound by the master's contract to carry cargo, just as in case of collision, although she was under lease at the time. In such cases, also, according to our Supreme Court, the master may bind the vessel when he cannot bind the general owners. /4/ "By custom the ship is bound to the merchandise, and the merchandise to the ship." /5/ "By the maritime law every contract of the master implies an hypothecation." /6/ It might be urged, no doubt, with force, that, so far as the usual maritime contracts are concerned, the dealing must be on the security of the ship or merchandise in many cases, and therefore [33] that it is policy to give this security in all cases; that the risk to which it subjects ship-owners is calculable, and that they must take it into account when they let their vessels. Again, in many cases, when a party asserts a maritime lien by way of contract, he has improved the condition of the thing upon which the lien is claimed, and this has been recognized as a ground for such a lien in some systems. But this is not true universally, nor in the most important cases. It must be left to the reader to decide whether ground has not been shown for believing that the same metaphysical confusion which naturally arose as to the ship's wrongful acts, affected the way of thinking as to her contracts. The whole manner of dealing with vessels obviously took the form which prevailed in the eases first mentioned. Pardessus, a high authority, says that the lien for freight prevails even against the owner of stolen goods, "as the master deals less with the person than the thing." /2/ So it was said in the argument of a famous English case, that "the ship is instead of the owner, and therefore is answerable." /3/ In many cases of contract, as well as tort, the vessel was not only the security for the debt, but the limit of the owner's liability.

The same applies to other maritime dealings involving the vessel, whether through a contract or in some other way. If salvage services are provided to a vessel, the admiralty court will hold the vessel responsible, even though there has been some debate about whether a contract action could be pursued if the owners were taken to court. Similarly, the ship is obligated by the master's contract to transport cargo, just as in cases of collision, even if it was under lease at that time. In such situations, according to our Supreme Court, the master may bind the vessel even if they cannot bind the general owners. /4/ "By custom, the ship is tied to the merchandise, and the merchandise to the ship." /5/ "Under maritime law, every master’s contract implies a hypothecation." /6/ It can be argued, with some merit, that in typical maritime contracts, the dealings often depend on the security of the ship or merchandise in many situations, and therefore [33] it is wise to provide this security in all instances; the risk it imposes on ship owners is predictable, and they need to factor it in when they charter their vessels. Moreover, in many situations, when a party asserts a maritime lien through a contract, they have improved the condition of the asset on which the lien is claimed, and this has been acknowledged as a valid reason for such a lien in some legal systems. However, this is not universally applicable, nor in the most significant cases. It is left to the reader to consider whether there is a valid reason to believe that the same confusion that arose regarding the wrongful acts of the ship also influenced thoughts about her contracts. The entire approach to dealing with vessels clearly reflected the practices seen in the initially mentioned cases. Pardessus, a respected authority, states that the lien for freight is enforceable even against the owner of stolen goods, "as the master deals with the thing more than with the person." /2/ This point was also made in the argument of a well-known English case, stating that "the ship stands in for the owner, and thus is accountable." /3/ In many instances of both contract and tort, the vessel served not only as security for the debt but also set the limit on the owner's liability.

The principles of the admiralty are embodied in its form of procedure. A suit may be brought there against a vessel by name, any person interested in it being at liberty to come in and defend, but the suit, if successful, ending in a sale of the vessel and a payment of the plaintiff's claim out of the proceeds. As long ago as the time of James I. it was said that "the libel ought to be only [34] against the ship and goods, and not against the party." /1/ And authority for the statement was cited from the reign of Henry VI., the same reign when, as we have seen, the Admiral claimed a forfeiture of ships for causing death. I am bound to say, however, that I cannot find such an authority of that date.

The principles of admiralty law are reflected in its procedural rules. A lawsuit can be filed against a specific vessel, allowing anyone with an interest in it to come forward and defend it. If the lawsuit is successful, it results in the sale of the vessel and the payment of the plaintiff's claim from the sale proceeds. As far back as the time of James I, it was stated that "the libel ought to be only [34] against the ship and goods, and not against the party." /1/ This claim was referenced from the reign of Henry VI., the same period when, as we’ve noted, the Admiral claimed forfeiture of ships for causing death. However, I must admit that I can't find any authority from that time to support this statement.

We have now followed the development of the chief forms of liability in modern law for anything other than the immediate and manifest consequences of a man's own acts. We have seen the parallel course of events in the two parents,—the Roman law and the German customs, and in the offspring of those two on English soil with regard to servants, animals, and inanimate things. We have seen a single germ multiplying and branching into products as different from each other as the flower from the root. It hardly remains to ask what that germ was. We have seen that it was the desire of retaliation against the offending thing itself. Undoubtedly, it might be argued that many of the rules stated were derived from a seizure of the offending thing as security for reparation, at first, perhaps, outside the law. That explanation, as well as the one offered here; would show that modern views of responsibility had not yet been attained, as the owner of the thing might very well not have been the person in fault. But such has not been the view of those most competent to judge. A consideration of the earliest instances will show, as might have been expected, that vengeance, not compensation, and vengeance on the offending thing, was the original object. The ox in Exodus was to be stoned. The axe in the Athenian law was to be banished. The tree, in Mr. Tylor's instance, was to be chopped to pieces. The [35] slave under all the systems was to be surrendered to the relatives of the slain man, that they might do with him what they liked. /1/ The deodand was an accursed thing. The original limitation of liability to surrender, when the owner was before the court, could not be accounted for if it was his liability, and not that of his property, which was in question. Even where, as in some of the cases, expiation seems to be intended rather than vengeance, the object is equally remote from an extrajudicial distress.

We have now tracked the development of the main forms of liability in modern law for anything other than the immediate and obvious consequences of a person's own actions. We've seen the parallel evolution in the two sources—Roman law and German customs—and in their offspring on English land concerning servants, animals, and inanimate objects. We’ve observed a single idea multiplying and branching into outcomes as different from each other as a flower is from its root. It hardly needs to be asked what that idea was. We’ve recognized that it was the wish for revenge against the offending object itself. Certainly, one could argue that many of the rules stated were derived from seizing the offending thing as security for compensation, possibly originating outside of the law. That explanation, along with the one provided here, would indicate that modern concepts of responsibility had not yet been achieved, since the owner of the item might very well not have been the person at fault. However, that has not been the view of those best qualified to assess the situation. A look at the earliest examples will demonstrate, as could be expected, that revenge, not compensation, and revenge on the offending object, was the original aim. The ox in Exodus was to be stoned. The axe in Athenian law was to be banished. The tree, in Mr. Tylor's case, was to be chopped down. The [35] slave under all systems was to be handed over to the family of the deceased, allowing them to do as they wished. /1/ The deodand was considered a cursed thing. The original limitation of liability to surrender, when the owner was present in court, cannot be justified if it is his liability, and not that of his property, that is being questioned. Even where, as in some cases, atonement seems to be intended rather than revenge, the aim is still far from an extrajudicial seizure.

The foregoing history, apart from the purposes for which it has been given, well illustrates the paradox of form and substance in the development of law. In form its growth is logical. The official theory is that each new decision follows syllogistically from existing precedents. But just as the clavicle in the cat only tells of the existence of some earlier creature to which a collar-bone was useful, precedents survive in the law long after the use they once served is at an end and the reason for them has been forgotten. The result of following them must often be failure and confusion from the merely logical point of view.

The history outlined above, aside from its intended purposes, clearly shows the contradiction between form and substance in the evolution of law. Logically, its growth seems rational. The official explanation is that each new ruling is a logical follow-up to previous ones. However, just like the collarbone in a cat indicates an earlier species that needed one, legal precedents linger long after their original purpose is gone and their reasoning is forgotten. Consequently, relying on them often leads to failures and confusion from a purely logical perspective.

On the other hand, in substance the growth of the law is legislative. And this in a deeper sense than that what the courts declare to have always been the law is in fact new. It is legislative in its grounds. The very considerations which judges most rarely mention, and always with an apology, are the secret root from which the law draws all the juices of life. I mean, of course, considerations of what is expedient for the community concerned. Every important principle which is developed by litigation is in fact and at bottom the result of more or less definitely understood views of public policy; most generally, to be sure, [36] under our practice and traditions, the unconscious result of instinctive preferences and inarticulate convictions, but none the less traceable to views of public policy in the last analysis. And as the law is administered by able and experienced men, who know too much to sacrifice good sense to a syllogism, it will be found that, when ancient rules maintain themselves in the way that has been and will be shown in this book, new reasons more fitted to the time have been found for them, and that they gradually receive a new content, and at last a new form, from the grounds to which they have been transplanted.

On the other hand, the growth of the law is essentially legislative. And this is a deeper issue than the fact that what the courts declare to be the law has always been new. It is legislative in its foundation. The very factors that judges rarely mention, and always with some hesitation, are the hidden roots from which the law derives all its vitality. I’m referring, of course, to considerations of what is best for the community involved. Every significant principle developed through litigation is fundamentally the result of more or less clearly understood views of public policy; often, under our current practice and traditions, it is the unintentional outcome of instinctive preferences and unspoken beliefs, but it can still be traced back to public policy views in the end. And since the law is administered by capable and knowledgeable individuals who understand too well to sacrifice common sense to a strict logical framework, it becomes evident that when longstanding rules endure as shown in this book, new reasons that are more suitable for the current times have been discovered for them, and they gradually acquire a new meaning, and eventually a new form, based on the contexts in which they have been placed.

But hitherto this process has been largely unconscious. It is important, on that account, to bring to mind what the actual course of events has been. If it were only to insist on a more conscious recognition of the legislative function of the courts, as just explained, it would be useful, as we shall see more clearly further on. /1/

But until now, this process has mostly been unintentional. It's important to remember what the actual sequence of events has been. Even if it’s just to emphasize a more conscious acknowledgment of the legislative role of the courts, as explained earlier, it would be beneficial, as we will understand more clearly later on. /1/

What has been said will explain the failure of all theories which consider the law only from its formal side; whether they attempt to deduce the corpus from a priori postulates, or fall into the humbler error of supposing the science of the law to reside in the elegantia juris, or logical cohesion of part with part. The truth is, that the law always approaching, and never reaching, consistency. It is forever adopting new principles from life at one end, and it always retains old ones from history at the other, which have not yet been absorbed or sloughed off. It will become entirely consistent only when it ceases to grow.

What has been said explains why all theories that view the law solely from a formal perspective fail; whether they try to derive the system from a priori principles or mistakenly believe that the science of law lies in the elegance of the law or the logical connections between its parts. The reality is that the law is always moving towards consistency but never fully achieves it. It continuously incorporates new principles from current life on one side while keeping old ones from history on the other that haven't been absorbed or eliminated yet. It will only become completely consistent when it stops evolving.

The study upon which we have been engaged is necessary both for the knowledge and for the revision of the law. [37] However much we may codify the law into a series of seemingly self-sufficient propositions, those propositions will be but a phase in a continuous growth. To understand their scope fully, to know how they will be dealt with by judges trained in the past which the law embodies, we must ourselves know something of that past. The history of what the law has been is necessary to the knowledge of what the law is.

The study we've been working on is essential for both understanding and updating the law. [37] No matter how much we turn the law into a set of seemingly complete statements, those statements will only represent a stage in ongoing development. To fully grasp their meaning and see how judges, who have been shaped by the past that the law represents, will approach them, we need to have some knowledge of that past. Understanding the history of the law is crucial to knowing what the law is today.

Again, the process which I have described has involved the attempt to follow precedents, as well as to give a good reason for them. When we find that in large and important branches of the law the various grounds of policy on which the various rules have been justified are later inventions to account for what are in fact survivals from more primitive times, we have a right to reconsider the popular reasons, and, taking a broader view of the field, to decide anew whether those reasons are satisfactory. They may be, notwithstanding the manner of their appearance. If truth were not often suggested by error, if old implements could not be adjusted to new uses, human progress would be slow. But scrutiny and revision are justified.

Once again, the process I've described involves trying to follow established precedents while also providing solid justifications for them. When we see that in major areas of the law, the various policy reasons behind different rules are actually newer ideas meant to explain what are really relics from earlier times, we have the right to revisit these popular justifications. By taking a broader perspective, we can reassess whether those justifications still hold up. They might, despite how they came about. If truth didn't often emerge from mistakes, and if old tools couldn't be repurposed for new uses, human progress would be much slower. However, examination and reevaluation are warranted.

But none of the foregoing considerations, nor the purpose of showing the materials for anthropology contained in the history of the law, are the immediate object here. My aim and purpose have been to show that the various forms of liability known to modern law spring from the common ground of revenge. In the sphere of contract the fact will hardly be material outside the cases which have been stated in this Lecture. But in the criminal law and the law of torts it is of the first importance. It shows that they have started from a moral basis, from the thought that some one was to blame.

But none of the previous points, nor the goal of highlighting the materials for anthropology found in legal history, are the main focus here. My aim is to demonstrate that the different types of liability recognized by modern law originate from the shared concept of revenge. In the area of contracts, this point will likely not matter much beyond the cases discussed in this lecture. However, in criminal law and tort law, it is crucial. It indicates that they are grounded in a moral foundation, stemming from the idea that someone is at fault.

[38] It remains to be proved that, while the terminology of morals is still retained, and while the law does still and always, in a certain sense, measure legal liability by moral standards, it nevertheless, by the very necessity of its nature, is continually transmuting those moral standards into external or objective ones, from which the actual guilt of the party concerned is wholly eliminated.

[38] It still needs to be shown that, even though we continue to use moral terminology, and the law still measures legal responsibility based on moral standards to some extent, it inevitably transforms those moral standards into external or objective ones, completely removing the actual guilt of the person involved.





LECTURE II. — THE CRIMINAL LAW.

In the beginning of the first Lecture it was shown that the appeals of the early law were directed only to intentional wrongs. The appeal was a far older form of procedure than the indictment, and may be said to have had a criminal as well as a civil aspect. It had the double object of satisfying the private party for his loss, and the king for the breach of his peace. On its civil side it was rooted in vengeance. It was a proceeding to recover those compositions, at first optional, afterwards compulsory, by which a wrong-doer bought the spear from his side. Whether, so far as concerned the king, it had the same object of vengeance, or was more particularly directed to revenue, does not matter, since the claim of the king did not enlarge the scope of the action.

At the start of the first lecture, it was shown that early legal appeals were focused solely on intentional wrongs. Appeals were an older form of legal procedure than indictments and could be seen as having both criminal and civil elements. Their dual purpose was to compensate the private individual for their loss and to satisfy the king for the disruption of his peace. On the civil side, it was rooted in revenge. It was a way to recover the payments, initially optional and later mandatory, that allowed a wrongdoer to buy their way out of the consequences. Whether this had the same revenge motive for the king or was more about generating revenue doesn't really matter, as the king's claim didn’t change the nature of the action.

It would seem to be a fair inference that indictable offences were originally limited in the same way as those which gave rise to an appeal. For whether the indictment arose by a splitting up of the appeal, or in some other way, the two were closely connected.

It seems reasonable to conclude that serious offenses were originally restricted in the same manner as those that led to an appeal. Whether the indictment resulted from breaking up the appeal or another process, the two were closely linked.

An acquittal of the appellee on the merits was a bar to an indictment; and, on the other hand, when an appeal was fairly started, although the appellor might fail to prosecute, or might be defeated by plea, the cause might still be proceeded with on behalf of the king. /1/

An acquittal of the appellee based on the facts was a barrier to an indictment; however, when an appeal was properly initiated, even if the appellant did not pursue it or was unsuccessful due to a plea, the case could still move forward on behalf of the king. /1/

[40] The presentment, which is the other parent of our criminal procedure, had an origin distinct from the appeal. If, as has been thought, it was merely the successor of fresh suit and lynch law, /1/ this also is the child of vengeance, even more clearly than the other.

[40] The presentment, which is another key aspect of our criminal procedure, originated separately from the appeal. If it's true that it was simply the successor to fresh suit and lynch law, /1/ then it too is born from vengeance, even more obviously than the other.

The desire for vengeance imports an opinion that its object is actually and personally to blame. It takes an internal standard, not an objective or external one, and condemns its victim by that. The question is whether such a standard is still accepted either in this primitive form, or in some more refined development, as is commonly supposed, and as seems not impossible, considering the relative slowness with which the criminal law has improved.

The desire for revenge implies that the person being targeted is truly and personally at fault. It uses an internal standard, rather than an objective or external one, to judge its victim. The question is whether such a standard is still accepted, either in this basic form or in some more evolved version, as is often believed, and it seems plausible given how slowly criminal law has progressed.

It certainly may be argued, with some force, that it has never ceased to be one object of punishment to satisfy the desire for vengeance. The argument will be made plain by considering those instances in which, for one reason or another, compensation for a wrong is out of the question.

It can definitely be argued strongly that one purpose of punishment has always been to satisfy the need for revenge. This point becomes clear when we look at cases where, for various reasons, making amends for a wrong is not possible.

Thus an act may be of such a kind as to make indemnity impossible by putting an end to the principal sufferer, as in the case of murder or manslaughter.

Thus, an act can be of such a nature that it makes compensation impossible by putting an end to the main victim, as in the case of murder or manslaughter.

Again, these and other crimes, like forgery, although directed against an individual, tend to make others feel unsafe, and this general insecurity does not admit of being paid for.

Again, these and other crimes, like forgery, although aimed at an individual, tend to make others feel unsafe, and this overall sense of insecurity can't be compensated for.

Again, there are cases where there are no means of enforcing indemnity. In Macaulay's draft of the Indian Penal Code, breaches of contract for the carriage of passengers, were made criminal. The palanquin-bearers of India were too poor to pay damages, and yet had to be [41] trusted to carry unprotected women and children through wild and desolate tracts, where their desertion would have placed those under their charge in great danger.

Again, there are situations where there’s no way to enforce compensation. In Macaulay's draft of the Indian Penal Code, breaking contracts for passenger transport was made a criminal offense. The palanquin bearers in India were too poor to pay damages, yet they had to be [41] trusted to carry unprotected women and children through wild and desolate areas, where abandoning them would have put those under their care in serious danger.

In all these cases punishment remains as an alternative. A pain can be inflicted upon the wrong-doer, of a sort which does not restore the injured party to his former situation, or to another equally good, but which is inflicted for the very purpose of causing pain. And so far as this punishment takes the place of compensation, whether on account of the death of the person to whom the wrong was done, the indefinite number of persons affected, the impossibility of estimating the worth of the suffering in money, or the poverty of the criminal, it may be said that one of its objects is to gratify the desire for vengeance. The prisoner pays with his body.

In all these cases, punishment is still an option. A type of pain can be inflicted on the wrongdoer that does not restore the victim to their previous situation or provide a similar benefit, but is aimed solely at causing pain. And to the extent that this punishment replaces compensation—whether due to the death of the person harmed, the countless others impacted, the difficulty in putting a monetary value on the suffering, or the criminal's lack of finances—it can be said that one of its purposes is to satisfy the desire for revenge. The prisoner pays with their body.

The statement may be made stronger still, and it may be said, not only that the law does, but that it ought to, make the gratification of revenge an object. This is the opinion, at any rate, of two authorities so great, and so opposed in other views, as Bishop Butler and Jeremy Bentham. /1/ Sir James Stephen says, "The criminal law stands to the passion of revenge in much the same relation as marriage to the sexual appetite." /2/

The statement can be made even stronger, and it can be said that not only does the law allow for, but it should also make revenge a valid goal. This is the view, at least, of two significant authorities, Bishop Butler and Jeremy Bentham, who generally have opposing viewpoints. /1/ Sir James Stephen states, "The criminal law relates to the passion of revenge much like marriage relates to the sexual appetite." /2/

The first requirement of a sound body of law is, that it should correspond with the actual feelings and demands of the community, whether right or wrong. If people would gratify the passion of revenge outside of the law, if the law did not help them, the law has no choice but to satisfy the craving itself, and thus avoid the greater evil of private [42 retribution. At the same time, this passion is not one which we encourage, either as private individuals or as lawmakers. Moreover, it does not cover the whole ground. There are crimes which do not excite it, and we should naturally expect that the most important purposes of punishment would be coextensive with the whole field of its application. It remains to be discovered whether such a general purpose exists, and if so what it is. Different theories still divide opinion upon the subject.

The first requirement for a solid legal system is that it should align with the actual feelings and demands of the community, whether those feelings are right or wrong. If people resort to fulfilling their desire for revenge outside of the law, and if the law doesn't assist them, then the law must address that desire itself to prevent the greater issue of personal retribution. However, we don’t encourage this desire, both as individuals and lawmakers. Additionally, this desire doesn't encompass everything. There are crimes that don't trigger it, and we would expect that the main goals of punishment would cover the entire scope of its application. It still needs to be determined whether such a general purpose exists and, if it does, what it is. Different theories continue to create divisions in opinion on this topic.

It has been thought that the purpose of punishment is to reform the criminal; that it is to deter the criminal and others from committing similar crimes; and that it is retribution. Few would now maintain that the first of these purposes was the only one. If it were, every prisoner should be released as soon as it appears clear that he will never repeat his offence, and if he is incurable he should not be punished at all. Of course it would be hard to reconcile the punishment of death with this doctrine.

It has been believed that the purpose of punishment is to reform the criminal; to deter the criminal and others from committing similar crimes; and that it serves as retribution. Few would argue today that the first of these purposes is the only one. If it were, every prisoner should be released as soon as it’s clear they will never commit the offense again, and if they are beyond help, they shouldn’t be punished at all. Obviously, it would be difficult to align the death penalty with this idea.

The main struggle lies between the other two. On the one side is the notion that there is a mystic bond between wrong and punishment; on the other, that the infliction of pain is only a means to an end. Hegel, one of the great expounders of the former view, puts it, in his quasi mathematical form, that, wrong being the negation of right, punishment is the negation of that negation, or retribution. Thus the punishment must be equal, in the sense of proportionate to the crime, because its only function is to destroy it. Others, without this logical apparatus, are content to rely upon a felt necessity that suffering should follow wrong-doing.

The main conflict is between the two opposing ideas. On one side is the belief that there is a deep connection between wrongdoing and punishment; on the other, that causing pain is just a means to achieve a goal. Hegel, a prominent supporter of the first view, explains it in a somewhat mathematical way: since wrongdoing is the opposite of right, punishment is the opposite of that opposite, or retribution. Therefore, punishment must be proportional to the crime, as its only purpose is to eliminate it. Others, without this logical framework, feel it is necessary for suffering to follow wrongdoing.

It is objected that the preventive theory is immoral, because it overlooks the ill-desert of wrong-doing, and furnishes [43] no measure of the amount of punishment, except the lawgiver's subjective opinion in regard to the sufficiency of the amount of preventive suffering. /1/ In the language of Kant, it treats man as a thing, not as a person; as a means, not as an end in himself. It is said to conflict with the sense of justice, and to violate the fundamental principle of all free communities, that the members of such communities have equal rights to life, liberty, and personal security. /2/

It is argued that the preventive theory is immoral because it ignores the wrongdoing's deserving punishment and provides [43] no way to measure the level of punishment other than the lawgiver's personal opinion on how much preventive suffering is adequate. /1/ In Kant's words, it treats people as objects rather than as individuals, using them as means to an end rather than recognizing their worth as ends in themselves. It is said to clash with the sense of justice and violate the fundamental principle of all free societies, which is that all members have equal rights to life, liberty, and personal security. /2/

In spite of all this, probably most English-speaking lawyers would accept the preventive theory without hesitation. As to the violation of equal rights which is charged, it may be replied that the dogma of equality makes an equation between individuals only, not between an individual and the community. No society has ever admitted that it could not sacrifice individual welfare to its own existence. If conscripts are necessary for its army, it seizes them, and marches them, with bayonets in their rear, to death. It runs highways and railroads through old family places in spite of the owner's protest, paying in this instance the market value, to be sure, because no civilized government sacrifices the citizen more than it can help, but still sacrificing his will and his welfare to that of the rest. /3/

Despite all this, most English-speaking lawyers would likely accept the preventive theory without a second thought. Regarding the claim of a violation of equal rights, it can be argued that the principle of equality only applies to individuals, not to an individual in relation to the community. No society has ever claimed it couldn’t sacrifice individual welfare for its own survival. If conscripts are needed for its army, it takes them, marching them with bayonets at their backs, even to their deaths. It builds highways and railroads through family properties despite the owner's objections, paying the market value, of course, because no civilized government sacrifices a citizen more than it has to, but it still sacrifices their will and welfare for the benefit of the majority. /3/

If it were necessary to trench further upon the field of morals, it might be suggested that the dogma of equality applied even to individuals only within the limits of ordinary dealings in the common run of affairs. You cannot argue with your neighbor, except on the admission for the [44] moment that he is as wise as you, although you may by no means believe it. In the same way, you cannot deal with him, where both are free to choose, except on the footing of equal treatment, and the same rules for both. The ever-growing value set upon peace and the social relations tends to give the law of social being the appearance of the law of all being. But it seems to me clear that the ultima ratio, not only regum, but of private persons, is force, and that at the bottom of all private relations, however tempered by sympathy and all the social feelings, is a justifiable self-preference. If a man is on a plank in the deep sea which will only float one, and a stranger lays hold of it, he will thrust him off if he can. When the state finds itself in a similar position, it does the same thing.

If we need to dig deeper into moral issues, we could suggest that the idea of equality only applies to individuals when it comes to everyday interactions. You can’t really argue with your neighbor unless you both agree, at least for that moment, that he’s as wise as you are, even if you don’t actually believe it. Similarly, when both of you have the freedom to choose, you can only interact with him on the basis of equal treatment and the same rules for everyone. The increasing value placed on peace and social relationships tends to make the laws of society seem like the laws of existence itself. However, it seems clear to me that the ultimate authority, not just of kings but of ordinary people, is force, and deep down in all personal relationships, no matter how influenced by sympathy and social feelings, is a legitimate self-preference. If a person is on a plank in the ocean that can only support one, and a stranger tries to grab it, he will push the stranger off if he can. When the state finds itself in a similar situation, it acts in the same way.

The considerations which answer the argument of equal rights also answer the objections to treating man as a thing, and the like. If a man lives in society, he is liable to find himself so treated. The degree of civilization which a people has reached, no doubt, is marked by their anxiety to do as they would be done by. It may be the destiny of man that the social instincts shall grow to control his actions absolutely, even in anti-social situations. But they have not yet done so, and as the rules of law are or should be based upon a morality which is generally accepted, no rule founded on a theory of absolute unselfishness can be laid down without a breach between law and working beliefs.

The thoughts that support the argument for equal rights also address the concerns about treating a person like an object, and similar issues. If a person lives in society, they might experience this kind of treatment. The level of civilization a society has attained is clearly shown by how they strive to treat others as they would want to be treated. It might be humanity's fate that our social instincts develop to completely dictate our actions, even in situations where people act against social norms. However, that hasn’t happened yet, and because the rules of law are or should be based on a morality that people widely accept, no rule based on the idea of total selflessness can be established without creating a gap between the law and common beliefs.

If it be true, as I shall presently try to show, that the general principles of criminal and civil liability are the same, it will follow from that alone that theory and fact agree in frequently punishing those who have been guilty [45] of no moral wrong, and who could not be condemned by any standard that did not avowedly disregard the personal peculiarities of the individuals concerned. If punishment stood on the moral grounds which are proposed for it, the first thing to be considered would be those limitations in the capacity for choosing rightly which arise from abnormal instincts, want of education, lack of intelligence, and all the other defects which are most marked in the criminal classes. I do not say that they should not be, or at least I do not need to for my argument. I do not say that the criminal law does more good than harm. I only say that it is not enacted or administered on that theory.

If it’s true, as I will soon demonstrate, that the basic principles of criminal and civil liability are the same, it follows that both theory and reality often punish people who have committed no moral wrongdoing and who couldn’t be judged by any standard that doesn’t outright ignore the unique traits of the individuals involved. If punishment were based on the moral reasons proposed for it, the first consideration would be the limitations in the ability to make the right choices due to abnormal instincts, lack of education, low intelligence, and all the other flaws that are especially evident in criminal groups. I’m not saying they shouldn’t be, or at least I don’t need to for my argument. I’m not claiming that criminal law does more good than harm. I’m simply stating that it’s not created or enforced with that idea in mind.

There remains to be mentioned the affirmative argument in favor of the theory of retribution, to the effect that the fitness of punishment following wrong-doing is axiomatic, and is instinctively recognized by unperverted minds. I think that it will be seen, on self-inspection, that this feeling of fitness is absolute and unconditional only in the case of our neighbors. It does not seem to me that any one who has satisfied himself that an act of his was wrong, and that he will never do it again, would feel the least need or propriety, as between himself and an earthly punishing power alone, of his being made to suffer for what he had done, although, when third persons were introduced, he might, as a philosopher, admit the necessity of hurting him to frighten others. But when our neighbors do wrong, we sometimes feel the fitness of making them smart for it, whether they have repented or not. The feeling of fitness seems to me to be only vengeance in disguise, and I have already admitted that vengeance was an element, though not the chief element, of punishment.

It's worth mentioning the strong argument supporting the theory of retribution, which states that the appropriateness of punishment following wrongdoing is obvious and is instinctively understood by clear-minded individuals. Upon self-reflection, it seems that this sense of appropriateness is absolute and unconditional only when it comes to others. I believe that anyone who has realized that their action was wrong and vows never to repeat it would not feel any real need or justification, in relation to a human authority alone, for suffering consequences for what they did. However, when others are involved, they might, as rational thinkers, acknowledge the necessity of punishing someone to deter others. But when our neighbors commit wrongs, we often feel justified in making them pay for it, regardless of whether they've expressed remorse. This sense of appropriateness appears to me to be merely vengeance in disguise, and I’ve previously acknowledged that vengeance is a factor, although not the primary one, in punishment.

[46] But, again, the supposed intuition of fitness does not seem to me to be coextensive with the thing to be accounted for. The lesser punishments are just as fit for the lesser crimes as the greater for the greater. The demand that crime should be followed by its punishment should therefore be equal and absolute in both. Again, a malum prohibitum is just as much a crime as a malum in se. If there is any general ground for punishment, it must apply to one case as much as to the other. But it will hardly be said that, if the wrong in the case just supposed consisted of a breach of the revenue laws, and the government had been indemnified for the loss, we should feel any internal necessity that a man who had thoroughly repented of his wrong should be punished for it, except on the ground that his act was known to others. If it was known, the law would have to verify its threats in order that others might believe and tremble. But if the fact was a secret between the sovereign and the subject, the sovereign, if wholly free from passion, would undoubtedly see that punishment in such a case was wholly without justification.

[46] But again, the supposed instinct of fairness doesn’t seem to align with what we’re trying to explain. The lighter punishments are just as appropriate for the lesser crimes as the harsher ones are for the greater crimes. Therefore, the expectation that a crime should be followed by its punishment should be equal and absolute in both cases. Additionally, a malum prohibitum is just as much a crime as a malum in se. If there’s any general reason for punishment, it should apply equally to both situations. However, it’s unlikely that anyone would argue that if the wrongdoing involved a violation of revenue laws, and the government had been compensated for the loss, we would feel any pressing need for a person who had genuinely regretted their actions to be punished, unless it was known by others. If it was known, the law would need to enforce its threats so that others would believe and fear. But if the situation were a secret between the ruler and the individual, the ruler, if completely unbiased, would certainly realize that punishment in that case was entirely unjustified.

On the other hand, there can be no case in which the law-maker makes certain conduct criminal without his thereby showing a wish and purpose to prevent that conduct. Prevention would accordingly seem to be the chief and only universal purpose of punishment. The law threatens certain pains if you do certain things, intending thereby to give you a new motive for not doing them. If you persist in doing them, it has to inflict the pains in order that its threats may continue to be believed.

On the flip side, there’s no situation where lawmakers declare certain actions illegal without wanting to stop those actions. So, it seems that preventing behavior is the main and only universal goal of punishment. The law warns you of specific consequences if you engage in certain activities, aiming to provide you with a new reason to avoid those actions. If you continue to break the law, it must enforce those consequences to maintain the credibility of its warnings.

If this is a true account of the law as it stands, the law does undoubtedly treat the individual as a means to an [47] end, and uses him as a tool to increase the general welfare at his own expense. It has been suggested above, that this course is perfectly proper; but even if it is wrong, our criminal law follows it, and the theory of our criminal law must be shaped accordingly.

If this is an accurate description of the law as it currently exists, then the law does indeed view the individual as a means to an [47] end, treating them like a tool to enhance the overall welfare at their own expense. It has been mentioned earlier that this approach may be entirely appropriate; however, even if it is incorrect, our criminal laws adhere to it, and the principles of our criminal law must be adjusted accordingly.

Further evidence that our law exceeds the limits of retribution, and subordinates consideration of the individual to that of the public well-being, will be found in some doctrines which cannot be satisfactorily explained on any other ground.

Further evidence that our law goes beyond the boundaries of punishment and prioritizes public well-being over individual concerns can be found in certain doctrines that can't be adequately explained on any other basis.

The first of these is, that even the deliberate taking of life will not be punished when it is the only way of saving one's own. This principle is not so clearly established as that next to be mentioned; but it has the support of very great authority. /1/ If that is the law, it must go on one of two grounds, either that self-preference is proper in the case supposed, or that, even if it is improper, the law cannot prevent it by punishment, because a threat of death at some future time can never be a sufficiently powerful motive to make a man choose death now in order to avoid the threat. If the former ground is adopted, it admits that a single person may sacrifice another to himself, and a fortiori that a people may. If the latter view is taken, by abandoning punishment when it can no longer be expected to prevent an act, the law abandons the retributive and adopts the preventive theory.

The first point is that even the intentional taking of a life won't be punished when it’s the only way to save one’s own life. This principle isn’t as clearly established as the next one, but it has significant support from high authority. /1/ If that is the law, it must rely on one of two reasons: either that self-preference is acceptable in the situation described, or that even if it’s unacceptable, the law can’t stop it through punishment because a threat of future death will never be a strong enough reason for someone to choose to die now to avoid that threat. If we accept the first reason, it suggests that an individual can sacrifice another for themselves, and by extension, a group can do the same. If we take the second perspective, by removing punishment when it can no longer be expected to prevent an action, the law shifts from a retributive approach to a preventive one.

The next doctrine leads to still clearer conclusions. Ignorance of the law is no excuse for breaking it. This substantive principle is sometimes put in the form of a rule of evidence, that every one is presumed to know the [48] law. It has accordingly been defended by Austin and others, on the ground of difficulty of proof. If justice requires the fact to be ascertained, the difficulty of doing so is no ground for refusing to try. But every one must feel that ignorance of the law could never be admitted as an excuse, even if the fact could be proved by sight and hearing in every case. Furthermore, now that parties can testify, it may be doubted whether a man's knowledge of the law is any harder to investigate than many questions which are gone into. The difficulty, such as it is, would be met by throwing the burden of proving ignorance on the lawbreaker.

The next doctrine leads to even clearer conclusions. Not knowing the law is not an excuse for breaking it. This principle is often expressed as a rule of evidence, where everyone is assumed to know the law. It has been defended by Austin and others, based on the difficulty of proving what someone knew. If justice requires the truth to be established, the challenge of doing so doesn’t justify avoiding the inquiry. However, it's clear that ignorance of the law should never be accepted as an excuse, even if the facts could be proven easily. Moreover, now that parties can testify, it's questionable whether a person's understanding of the law is harder to investigate than many other questions that are explored. Any difficulty should be addressed by placing the responsibility of proving ignorance on the lawbreaker.

The principle cannot be explained by saying that we are not only commanded to abstain from certain acts, but also to find out that we are commanded. For if there were such a second command, it is very clear that the guilt of failing to obey it would bear no proportion to that of disobeying the principal command if known, yet the failure to know would receive the same punishment as the failure to obey the principal law.

The principle can't just be explained by saying that we're not only told to avoid certain actions, but also to realize that we’re being told to do so. Because if there were a second command, it would be obvious that failing to follow it wouldn’t carry the same weight of guilt as disobeying the main command if we know it; still, not knowing would face the same consequences as ignoring the main law.

The true explanation of the rule is the same as that which accounts for the law's indifference to a man's particular temperament, faculties, and so forth. Public policy sacrifices the individual to the general good. It is desirable that the burden of all should be equal, but it is still more desirable to put an end to robbery and murder. It is no doubt true that there are many cases in which the criminal could not have known that he was breaking the law, but to admit the excuse at all would be to encourage ignorance where the law-maker has determined to make men know and obey, and justice to the individual is rightly outweighed by the larger interests on the other side of the scales.

The real reason behind the rule is the same one that explains why the law doesn't care about a person's specific temperament, abilities, and so on. Public policy prioritizes the collective good over the individual. It’s important that everyone shares the burden equally, but it’s even more important to end robbery and murder. It’s certainly true that there are many instances where the criminal might not have realized they were breaking the law, but allowing that excuse would only encourage ignorance when the lawmakers aim to ensure that people recognize and follow the law. Justice for the individual is rightly considered less crucial than the broader interests weighed on the other side.

[49] If the foregoing arguments are sound, it is already manifest that liability to punishment cannot be finally and absolutely determined by considering the actual personal unworthiness of the criminal alone. That consideration will govern only so far as the public welfare permits or demands. And if we take into account the general result which the criminal law is intended to bring about, we shall see that the actual state of mind accompanying a criminal act plays a different part from what is commonly supposed.

[49] If the arguments above are valid, it’s clear that the decision on punishment can’t be solely based on the personal flaws of the criminal. That aspect will only matter to the extent that it aligns with or supports the public good. When we consider the overall outcome that criminal law aims to achieve, we’ll realize that the actual mindset behind a criminal act plays a different role than people usually think.

For the most part, the purpose of the criminal law is only to induce external conformity to rule. All law is directed to conditions of things manifest to the senses. And whether it brings those conditions to pass immediately by the use of force, as when it protects a house from a mob by soldiers, or appropriates private property to public use, or hangs a man in pursuance of a judicial sentence, or whether it brings them about mediately through men's fears, its object is equally an external result. In directing itself against robbery or murder, for instance, its purpose is to put a stop to the actual physical taking and keeping of other men's goods, or the actual poisoning, shooting, stabbing, and otherwise putting to death of other men. If those things are not done, the law forbidding them is equally satisfied, whatever the motive.

For the most part, the goal of criminal law is simply to ensure people follow the rules. All laws target conditions that can be observed. Whether it achieves those conditions directly through force, like when soldiers protect a house from a mob, takes private property for public use, carries out a death sentence, or does it indirectly through people's fears, the aim is always an external outcome. When it addresses robbery or murder, for example, the goal is to stop the actual physical stealing and keeping of someone else's property, or the real acts of poisoning, shooting, stabbing, or killing others. If those actions don’t happen, the law against them is just as satisfied, no matter what the motivation is.

Considering this purely external purpose of the law together with the fact that it is ready to sacrifice the individual so far as necessary in order to accomplish that purpose, we can see more readily than before that the actual degree of personal guilt involved in any particular transgression cannot be the only element, if it is an element at all, in the liability incurred. So far from its [50] being true, as is often assumed, that the condition of a man's heart or conscience ought to be more considered in determining criminal than civil liability, it might almost be said that it is the very opposite of truth. For civil liability, in its immediate working, is simply a redistribution of an existing loss between two individuals; and it will be argued in the next Lecture that sound policy lets losses lie where they fall, except where a special reason can be shown for interference. The most frequent of such reasons is, that the party who is charged has been to blame.

Considering this purely external purpose of the law along with the fact that it is willing to sacrifice the individual as much as necessary to achieve that purpose, we can more easily see that the actual degree of personal guilt involved in any specific wrongdoing cannot be the sole factor, if it is even a factor at all, in the liability incurred. Contrary to the common belief that a person's heart or conscience should be more important in determining criminal than civil liability, it might be said that it is almost the complete opposite. Civil liability, in its immediate effect, is simply a redistribution of an existing loss between two individuals; and it will be argued in the next Lecture that sound policy leaves losses where they fall, unless a specific reason exists for interference. The most common of such reasons is that the party being charged is at fault.

It is not intended to deny that criminal liability, as well as civil, is founded on blameworthiness. Such a denial would shock the moral sense of any civilized community; or, to put it another way, a law which punished conduct which would not be blameworthy in the average member of the community would be too severe for that community to bear. It is only intended to point out that, when we are dealing with that part of the law which aims more directly than any other at establishing standards of conduct, we should expect there more than elsewhere to find that the tests of liability are external, and independent of the degree of evil in the particular person's motives or intentions. The conclusion follows directly from the nature of the standards to which conformity is required. These are not only external, as was shown above, but they are of general application. They do not merely require that every man should get as near as he can to the best conduct possible for him. They require him at his own peril to come up to a certain height. They take no account of incapacities, unless the weakness is so marked as to fall into well-known exceptions, such as infancy or madness. [51] They assume that every man is as able as every other to behave as they command. If they fall on any one class harder than on another, it is on the weakest. For it is precisely to those who are most likely to err by temperament, ignorance, or folly, that the threats of the law are the most dangerous.

It’s not meant to suggest that both criminal and civil liability aren’t based on blameworthiness. Denying this would offend the moral standards of any civilized society. In other words, a law that punished actions not considered blameworthy by the average person would be too harsh for that society to handle. What we aim to highlight is that when it comes to the part of the law focused on setting standards for behavior, we should expect to find that the criteria for liability are mostly external, and not dependent on the level of wrongdoing in an individual’s motives or intentions. This conclusion naturally stems from the nature of the standards we require conformity to. These standards are not only external, as previously mentioned, but are also broadly applicable. They don't simply require that everyone strive for the best conduct they can achieve. Instead, they demand that individuals meet a specific standard at their own risk. They disregard individual limitations unless those limitations are significant enough to fall under well-known exceptions like childhood or insanity. [51] They assume that every person is just as capable as anyone else of acting as required. If these standards affect one group more severely than another, it's the most vulnerable. This is because those who are more likely to make mistakes due to temperament, ignorance, or foolishness are the ones most at risk from legal repercussions.

The reconciliation of the doctrine that liability is founded on blameworthiness with the existence of liability where the party is not to blame, will be worked out more fully in the next Lecture. It is found in the conception of the average man, the man of ordinary intelligence and reasonable prudence. Liability is said to arise out of such conduct as would be blameworthy in him. But he is an ideal being, represented by the jury when they are appealed to, and his conduct is an external or objective standard when applied to any given individual. That individual may be morally without stain, because he has less than ordinary intelligence or prudence. But he is required to have those qualities at his peril. If he has them, he will not, as a general rule, incur liability without blameworthiness.

The connection between the idea that liability is based on blameworthiness and the existence of liability when a party is not at fault will be discussed more thoroughly in the next lecture. This idea revolves around the concept of the average person, one with ordinary intelligence and reasonable caution. Liability is understood to come from conduct that would be seen as blameworthy for this average person. However, this average person is a theoretical construct, represented by the jury when called upon, and their behavior serves as an external or objective standard when evaluating a specific individual. That individual might be morally impeccable but have less than average intelligence or caution. Nonetheless, they are expected to possess those qualities at their own risk. If they do have them, they generally won’t incur liability without some form of blameworthiness.

The next step is to take up some crimes in detail, and to discover what analysis will teach with regard to them.

The next step is to examine some crimes in detail and to see what analysis can teach us about them.

I will begin with murder. Murder is defined by Sir James Stephen, in his Digest of Criminal Law, /1/ as unlawful homicide with malice aforethought. In his earlier work, /2/ he explained that malice meant wickedness, and that the law had determined what states of mind were wicked in the necessary degree. Without the same preliminary he continues in his Digest as follows:—

I will start with murder. Murder is defined by Sir James Stephen, in his Digest of Criminal Law, /1/ as unlawful killing with intent to harm. In his earlier work, /2/ he explained that malice meant wickedness, and that the law had established what mental states were considered wicked to the required extent. Without the same introduction, he goes on in his Digest as follows:—

[52] "Malice aforethought means any one or more of the following states of mind..... "(a.) An intention to cause the death of, or grievous bodily harm to, any person, whether such person is the person actually killed or not; "(b.) Knowledge that the act which causes death will probably cause the death of, or grievous bodily harm to, some person, whether such person is the person actually killed or not, although such knowledge is accompanied by indifference whether death or grievous bodily harm is caused or not, or by a wish that it may not be caused; "(c.) An intent to commit any felony whatever; "(d.) An intent to oppose by force any officer of justice on his way to, in, or returning from the execution of the duty of arresting, keeping in custody, or imprisoning any person whom he is lawfully entitled to arrest, keep in custody, or imprison, or the duty of keeping the peace or dispersing an unlawful assembly, provided that the offender has notice that the person killed is such an officer so employed."

[52] "Malice aforethought refers to one or more of the following mental states: (a.) An intention to cause the death of, or serious injury to, any person, whether that person is the one actually killed or not; (b.) Awareness that the action causing death will likely result in the death of, or serious injury to, someone, whether that person is the one actually killed or not, even if that awareness comes with indifference to whether death or serious injury occurs, or a hope that it does not; (c.) An intent to commit any felony; (d.) An intent to use force against any law enforcement officer while they are on their way to, in, or returning from performing their duty to arrest, detain, or imprison someone they are legally allowed to arrest, detain, or imprison, or to maintain public order or disperse an unlawful gathering, provided the offender knows that the person killed is such an officer."

Malice, as used in common speech, includes intent, and something more. When an act is said to be done with an intent to do harm, it is meant that a wish for the harm is the motive of the act. Intent, however, is perfectly consistent with the harm being regretted as such, and being wished only as a means to something else. But when an act is said to be done maliciously, it is meant, not only that a wish for the harmful effect is the motive, but also that the harm is wished for its own sake, or, as Austin would say with more accuracy, for the sake of the pleasurable feeling which knowledge of the suffering caused by the act would excite. Now it is apparent from Sir James [53] Stephen's enumeration, that of these two elements of malice the intent alone is material to murder. It is just as much murder to shoot a sentry for the purpose of releasing a friend, as to shoot him because you hate him. Malice, in the definition of murder, has not the same meaning as in common speech, and, in view of the considerations just mentioned, it has been thought to mean criminal intention. /1/

Malice, in everyday language, includes intent and something more. When we say an act is done with the intent to cause harm, we mean that the desire to cause that harm is what motivates the action. Intent can coexist with a regret for the harm itself, being desired only as a means to an end. However, when we say an act is done maliciously, it means that the desire for the harmful outcome is the primary motivation, and the harm is desired for its own sake, or, as Austin would more accurately put it, for the pleasurable feeling that comes from knowing the suffering caused by the act. It’s clear from Sir James [53] Stephen's list that of these two aspects of malice, only intent is relevant to murder. It's just as much murder to shoot a sentry to free a friend as it is to shoot him out of hatred. In the context of defining murder, malice doesn't have the same meaning as in everyday language, and, considering the points made, it is understood to refer to criminal intent. /1/

But intent again will be found to resolve itself into two things; foresight that certain consequences will follow from an act, and the wish for those consequences working as a motive which induces the act. The question then is, whether intent, in its turn, cannot be reduced to a lower term. Sir James Stephen's statement shows that it can be, and that knowledge that the act will probably cause death, that is, foresight of the consequences of the act, is enough in murder as in tort.

But intent can once again be broken down into two things: the awareness that certain outcomes will result from an action, and the desire for those outcomes acting as a motivation that drives the action. The question then is whether intent can itself be simplified further. Sir James Stephen's statement indicates that it can, and that understanding that the action will likely lead to death—essentially, awareness of the consequences of the action—is sufficient for murder just as it is in tort law.

For instance, a newly born child is laid naked out of doors, where it must perish as a matter of course. This is none the less murder, that the guilty party would have been very glad to have a stranger find the child and save it. /2/

For example, a newborn is left outside without any clothes, where it is destined to die naturally. However, this is still considered murder, even if the perpetrator would have been very happy for a stranger to find the child and save it. /2/

But again, What is foresight of consequences? It is a picture of a future state of things called up by knowledge of the present state of things, the future being viewed as standing to the present in the relation of effect to cause. Again, we must seek a reduction to lower terms. If the known present state of things is such that the act done will very certainly cause death, and the probability is a matter of common knowledge, one who does the act, [54] knowing the present state of things, is guilty of murder, and the law will not inquire whether he did actually foresee the consequences or not. The test of foresight is not what this very criminal foresaw, but what a man of reasonable prudence would have foreseen.

But again, what does it mean to foresee consequences? It’s an image of a future situation created by understanding the current situation, seeing the future as related to the present like an effect is to its cause. Once more, we need to simplify things. If the known current situation is such that the action taken will definitely lead to death, and it’s widely recognized as a likelihood, then someone who carries out that action, knowing the current situation, is guilty of murder. The law won’t investigate whether that person actually foresaw the consequences or not. The standard for foresight isn’t what this particular offender foresaw, but what a reasonable person would have foreseen.

On the other hand, there must be actual present knowledge of the present facts which make an act dangerous. The act is not enough by itself. An act, it is true, imports intention in a certain sense. It is a muscular contraction, and something more. A spasm is not an act. The contraction of the muscles must be willed. And as an adult who is master of himself foresees with mysterious accuracy the outward adjustment which will follow his inward effort, that adjustment may be said to be intended. But the intent necessarily accompanying the act ends there. Nothing would follow from the act except for the environment. All acts, taken apart from their surrounding circumstances, are indifferent to the law. For instance, to crook the forefinger with a certain force is the same act whether the trigger of a pistol is next to it or not. It is only the surrounding circumstances of a pistol loaded and cocked, and of a human being in such relation to it, as to be manifestly likely to be hit, that make the act a wrong. Hence, it is no sufficient foundation for liability, on any sound principle, that the proximate cause of loss was an act.

On the other hand, there must be actual awareness of the facts that make an action dangerous. The action alone isn't enough. It's true that an action implies intention to some extent. It's a physical movement and more. A spasm isn't an action. The muscle contraction must be intentional. And just as an adult who is in control of themselves can accurately foresee the external outcome that will follow their internal effort, that outcome can be said to be intended. But the intent linked to the action stops there. Nothing would result from the action without the context. All actions, when considered apart from their surrounding circumstances, are neutral to the law. For example, bending the forefinger with a certain force is the same action whether a gun's trigger is next to it or not. It's only the surrounding circumstances of a loaded and cocked gun, and a person in a position where they're likely to be hit, that make the action wrong. Therefore, it isn't a solid basis for liability, according to any reasonable principle, that the direct cause of harm was an action.

The reason for requiring an act is, that an act implies a choice, and that it is felt to be impolitic and unjust to make a man answerable for harm, unless he might have chosen otherwise. But the choice must be made with a chance of contemplating the consequence complained of, or else it has no bearing on responsibility for that consequence. [55] If this were not true, a man might be held answerable for everything which would not have happened but for his choice at some past time. For instance, for having in a fit fallen on a man, which he would not have done had he not chosen to come to the city where he was taken ill.

The reason we require an act is that an act involves a choice, and it seems unfair and unreasonable to hold someone responsible for harm unless they could have chosen differently. However, the choice must be made with the possibility of considering the consequence in question, or else it doesn't relate to responsibility for that consequence. [55] If this weren’t the case, a person could be held accountable for everything that wouldn’t have happened if not for their choice at some earlier time. For example, for accidentally falling on someone during a seizure, which wouldn’t have happened if they hadn’t chosen to go to the city where they fell ill.

All foresight of the future, all choice with regard to any possible consequence of action, depends on what is known at the moment of choosing. An act cannot be wrong, even when done under circumstances in which it will be hurtful, unless those circumstances are or ought to be known. A fear of punishment for causing harm cannot work as a motive, unless the possibility of harm may be foreseen. So far, then, as criminal liability is founded upon wrong-doing in any sense, and so far as the threats and punishments of the law are intended to deter men from bringing about various harmful results, they must be confined to cases where circumstances making the conduct dangerous were known.

All predictions about the future and every choice regarding potential outcomes of actions depend on what is known at the time of making that choice. An action cannot be considered wrong, even if it results in harm, unless those circumstances are known or should have been known. A fear of punishment for causing harm can't serve as motivation unless the possibility of causing harm is foreseeable. Therefore, as long as criminal responsibility is based on wrongdoing in any way, and as long as the threats and penalties of the law are meant to prevent people from causing various harmful outcomes, they must only apply in situations where the circumstances that make the behavior dangerous were known.

Still, in a more limited way, the same principle applies to knowledge that applies to foresight. It is enough that such circumstances were actually known as would have led a man of common understanding to infer from them the rest of the group making up the present state of things. For instance, if a workman on a house-top at mid-day knows that the space below him is a street in a great city, he knows facts from which a man of common understanding would infer that there were people passing below. He is therefore bound to draw that inference, or, in other words, is chargeable with knowledge of that fact also, whether he draws the inference or not. If then, he throws down a heavy beam into the street, he does an act [56] which a person of ordinary prudence would foresee is likely to cause death, or grievous bodily harm, and he is dealt with as if he foresaw it, whether he does so in fact or not. If a death is caused by the act, he is guilty of murder. /1/ But if the workman has reasonable cause to believe that the space below is a private yard from which every one is excluded, and which is used as a rubbish heap, his act is not blameworthy, and the homicide is a mere misadventure.

Still, in a more limited way, the same principle applies to knowledge as it does to foresight. It's enough that he actually knew the circumstances that would have led an average person to figure out the rest of the current situation. For example, if a worker on a rooftop at noon knows that the area beneath him is a street in a big city, he knows facts from which an average person would conclude that people are passing by below. He is therefore obligated to make that conclusion, or in other words, he is responsible for knowing that fact, whether he acknowledges it or not. If he then drops a heavy beam into the street, he is committing an act [56] that a reasonable person would foresee is likely to cause death or serious injury, and he is treated as if he foresaw it, whether he actually did or not. If a death results from this act, he is guilty of murder. /1/ But if the worker has good reason to believe that the space below is a private yard where no one is allowed, and which is used as a dump, his actions are not blameworthy, and the resulting death is just an unfortunate accident.

To make an act which causes death murder, then, the actor ought, on principle, to know, or have notice of the facts which make the act dangerous. There are certain exceptions to this principle which will be stated presently, but they have less application to murder than to some smaller statutory crimes. The general rule prevails for the most part in murder.

To classify an act that causes death as murder, the person responsible should, in principle, be aware of the facts that make the act dangerous. There are certain exceptions to this principle that will be addressed shortly, but they apply less to murder than to some lesser statutory offenses. For the most part, the general rule holds true in cases of murder.

But furthermore, on the same principle, the danger which in fact exists under the known circumstances ought to be of a class which a man of reasonable prudence could foresee. Ignorance of a fact and inability to foresee a consequence have the same effect on blameworthiness. If a consequence cannot be foreseen, it cannot be avoided. But there is this practical difference, that whereas, in most cases, the question of knowledge is a question of the actual condition of the defendant's consciousness, the question of what he might have foreseen is determined by the standard of the prudent man, that is, by general experience. For it is to be remembered that the object of the law is to prevent human life being endangered or taken; and that, although it so far considers blameworthiness in punishing as not to hold a man responsible for consequences which [57] no one, or only some exceptional specialist, could have foreseen, still the reason for this limitation is simply to make a rule which is not too hard for the average member of the community. As the purpose is to compel men to abstain from dangerous conduct, and not merely to restrain them from evil inclinations, the law requires them at their peril to know the teachings of common experience, just as it requires them to know the law. Subject to these explanations, it may be said that the test of murder is the degree of danger to life attending the act under the known circumstances of the case. /1/

But also, based on the same principle, the real danger that exists under the known circumstances should be something that a reasonable person could predict. Not knowing a fact and being unable to foresee a consequence both lead to the same level of blame. If a consequence can’t be anticipated, it can’t be avoided. However, there is a practical difference: in most cases, whether someone has knowledge is based on the actual state of the defendant’s mind, while what they could have foreseen is judged by the standard of a reasonable person, meaning what is generally known or experienced. It's important to remember that the law aims to prevent endangering or taking human life; and although it takes blameworthiness into account by not holding someone responsible for consequences that no one, or only a rare expert, could have predicted, the reason for this limitation is simply to set a rule that isn't too harsh for the average person in the community. Since the goal is to make people avoid dangerous actions, not just to keep them from bad behavior, the law demands that they understand common experiences as well as it requires them to know the law. With those clarifications in mind, it can be said that the standard for murder is the level of danger to life posed by the act given the known circumstances of the case. /1/

It needs no further explanation to show that, when the particular defendant does for any reason foresee what an ordinary man of reasonable prudence would not have foreseen, the ground of exemption no longer applies. A harmful act is only excused on the ground that the party neither did foresee, nor could with proper care have foreseen harm.

It’s clear that when a specific defendant sees something that an average person with good judgment wouldn’t have expected, the reason for exemption doesn’t apply anymore. A harmful action is only excused if the person didn’t foresee it and couldn’t have foreseen it with reasonable care.

It would seem, at first sight, that the above analysis ought to exhaust the whole subject of murder. But it does not without some further explanation. If a man forcibly resists an officer lawfully making an arrest, and kills him, knowing him to be an officer, it may be murder, although no act is done which, but for his official function, would be criminal at all. So, if a man does an act with intent to commit a felony, and thereby accidentally kills another; for instance, if he fires at chickens, intending to steal them, and accidentally kills the owner, whom he does not see. Such a case as this last seems hardly to be reconcilable with the general principles which have been laid down. It has been argued somewhat as [58] follows:—The only blameworthy act is firing at the chickens, knowing them to belong to another. It is neither more nor less so because an accident happens afterwards; and hitting a man, whose presence could not have been suspected, is an accident. The fact that the shooting is felonious does not make it any more likely to kill people. If the object of the rule is to prevent such accidents, it should make accidental killing with firearms murder, not accidental killing in the effort to steal; while, if its object is to prevent stealing, it would do better to hang one thief in every thousand by lot.

At first glance, it seems that the analysis above should cover everything about murder. But it doesn't without some additional explanation. If a person forcefully resists a lawfully arresting officer and kills him, knowing he's an officer, it can still be considered murder, even if no action would be criminal without the officer's role. Similarly, if someone intends to commit a felony and accidentally kills another person, like if he shoots at chickens intending to steal them but accidentally hits the owner, whom he doesn't see, this scenario seems difficult to align with the general principles laid out. It has been argued somewhat as [58] follows:—The only blameworthy action is shooting at the chickens, knowing they belong to someone else. It is neither more nor less wrong because an accident happens afterward; striking a person who could not have been anticipated is purely an accident. The fact that the shooting is a felony doesn't increase the chances of harming people. If the goal of the rule is to prevent such accidents, then accidental killings with firearms should be considered murder, not accidental killings that occur while trying to steal. Conversely, if the aim is to stop theft, it would be more effective to execute one thief in every thousand by chance.

Still, the law is intelligible as it stands. The general test of murder is the degree of danger attending the acts under the known state of facts. If certain acts are regarded as peculiarly dangerous under certain circumstances, a legislator may make them punishable if done under these circumstances, although the danger was not generally known. The law often takes this step, although it does not nowadays often inflict death in such cases. It sometimes goes even further, and requires a man to find out present facts, as well as to foresee future harm, at his peril, although they are not such as would necessarily be inferred from the facts known.

The law is still clear as it is. The main test for murder is the level of danger involved in the actions based on the known facts. If certain actions are seen as particularly dangerous in specific situations, lawmakers can make them punishable if they occur in those situations, even if the danger wasn’t widely recognized. The law frequently takes this approach, though it doesn’t often impose the death penalty in such cases nowadays. Sometimes, it even goes further, requiring a person to be aware of current facts and predict future harm at their own risk, even if those facts wouldn’t necessarily be obvious from what’s known.

Thus it is a statutory offence in England to abduct a girl under sixteen from the possession of the person having lawful charge of her. If a man does acts which induce a girl under sixteen to leave her parents, he is not chargeable, if he had no reason to know that she was under the lawful charge of her parents, /1/ and it may be presumed that he would not be, if he had reasonable cause to believe that she was a boy. But if he knowingly abducts a girl from [59] her parents, he must find out her age at his peril. It is no defence that he had every reason to think her over sixteen. /1/ So, under a prohibitory liquor law, it has been held that, if a man sells "Plantation Bitters," it is no defence that he does not know them to be intoxicating. /2/ And there are other examples of the same kind.

Thus, it's a crime in England to abduct a girl under sixteen from the person who has legal custody of her. If a man does things that lead a girl under sixteen to leave her parents, he can't be charged if he had no reason to know that she was under the legal care of her parents, /1/ and it can be assumed he wouldn't be charged if he had reasonable cause to believe she was a boy. However, if he knowingly abducts a girl from [59] her parents, he must verify her age at his own risk. It’s not a valid defense that he had every reason to think she was over sixteen. /1/ Similarly, under a law prohibiting liquor, it’s been determined that if a man sells "Plantation Bitters," it’s not a defense that he doesn’t know they are intoxicating. /2/ There are other examples like this as well.

Now, if experience shows, or is deemed by the law-maker to show, that somehow or other deaths which the evidence makes accidental happen disproportionately often in connection with other felonies, or with resistance to officers, or if on any other ground of policy it is deemed desirable to make special efforts for the prevention of such deaths, the lawmaker may consistently treat acts which, under the known circumstances, are felonious, or constitute resistance to officers, as having a sufficiently dangerous tendency to be put under a special ban. The law may, therefore, throw on the actor the peril, not only of the consequences foreseen by him, but also of consequences which, although not predicted by common experience, the legislator apprehends. I do not, however, mean to argue that the rules under discussion arose on the above reasoning, any more than that they are right, or would be generally applied in this country.

Now, if experience shows, or is considered by lawmakers to show, that accidental deaths somehow occur disproportionately often in connection with other crimes or in resisting officers, or if there’s any other policy reason to focus on preventing such deaths, lawmakers can reasonably treat acts that, under the known circumstances, are criminal or constitute resistance to officers as having a sufficiently dangerous tendency to warrant a special ban. Therefore, the law may impose on the actor the risk not only of the consequences he could foresee, but also of consequences that, while not commonly predicted, the legislator is concerned about. However, I’m not claiming that the rules being discussed came from this reasoning, nor that they are correct, or that they would be generally applied in this country.

Returning to the main line of thought it will be instructive to consider the relation of manslaughter to murder. One great difference between the two will be found to lie in the degree of danger attaching to the act in the given state of facts. If a man strikes another with a small stick which is not likely to kill, and which he has no reason to suppose will do more than slight bodily harm, but which [60] does kill the other, he commits manslaughter, not murder. /1/ But if the blow is struck as hard as possible with an iron bar an inch thick, it is murder. /2/ So if, at the time of striking with a switch, the party knows an additional fact, by reason of which he foresees that death will be the consequence of a slight blow, as, for instance, that the other has heart disease, the offence is equally murder. /3/ To explode a barrel of gunpowder in a crowded street, and kill people, is murder, although the actor hopes that no such harm will be done. /4/ But to kill a man by careless riding in the same street would commonly be manslaughter. /5/ Perhaps, however, a case could be put where the riding was so manifestly dangerous that it would be murder.

Returning to the main line of thought, it will be helpful to consider the relationship between manslaughter and murder. One major difference between the two lies in the level of danger associated with the act in a specific situation. If someone hits another person with a small stick that is unlikely to kill and has no reason to think it will cause more than minor injury, but it does end up killing the other person, it’s manslaughter, not murder. /1/ However, if the blow is struck as hard as possible with a one-inch thick iron bar, it is murder. /2/ Similarly, if at the time of striking with a switch, the person knows an additional fact that makes them foresee that a slight blow will lead to death—like the other person having heart disease—that act is also considered murder. /3/ Exploding a barrel of gunpowder in a crowded street and killing people is murder, even if the person doing it hopes no harm will come from it. /4/ But killing someone through reckless riding in the same street would typically be regarded as manslaughter. /5/ However, there could be a situation where the riding is so obviously dangerous that it would be classified as murder.

To recur to an example which has been used already for another purpose: "When a workman flings down a stone or piece of timber into the street, and kills a man; this may be either misadventure, manslaughter, or murder, according to the circumstances under which the original act was done: if it were in a country village, where few passengers are, and he calls out to all people to have a care, it is misadventure only; but if it were in London, or other populous town, where people are continually passing, it is manslaughter, though he gives loud warning; and murder, if he knows of their passing, and gives no warning at all." /6/

To refer back to an example that has been used for a different purpose: "When a worker drops a stone or piece of wood into the street and kills someone, this could be considered either an accident, manslaughter, or murder, depending on the situation in which the act took place. If it happened in a small village with few people around, and he shouts to everyone to be careful, it's just an accident. But if it happened in London or another busy city where people are always walking by, it would be manslaughter, even if he warns loudly; and it would be murder if he knows people are passing by and doesn’t give any warning at all." /6/

The law of manslaughter contains another doctrine [61] which should be referred to in order to complete the understanding of the general principles of the criminal law. This doctrine is, that provocation may reduce an offence which would otherwise have been murder to manslaughter. According to current morality, a man is not so much to blame for an act done under the disturbance of great excitement, caused by a wrong done to himself, as when he is calm. The law is made to govern men through their motives, and it must, therefore, take their mental constitution into account.

The law of manslaughter includes another principle [61] that should be mentioned to fully understand the general principles of criminal law. This principle states that provocation can downgrade an offense that would normally be considered murder to manslaughter. According to modern morals, a person isn’t as culpable for something done in a state of intense emotional disturbance caused by a wrong done to them as they are when they are calm. The law is designed to regulate people's behavior based on their motivations, so it must consider their mental state.

It might be urged, on the other side, that, if the object of punishment is prevention, the heaviest punishment should be threatened where the strongest motive is needed to restrain; and primitive legislation seems sometimes to have gone on that principle. But if any threat will restrain a man in a passion, a threat of less than death will be sufficient, and therefore the extreme penalty has been thought excessive.

It could be argued, on the other hand, that if the goal of punishment is prevention, the toughest punishment should be threatened where the strongest incentive is needed to keep someone in check; and early laws seem to have sometimes followed that idea. However, if any threat can keep a person from acting out in anger, then a threat less than death should be enough, which is why the harshest penalty is considered excessive.

At the same time the objective nature of legal standards is shown even here. The mitigation does not come from the fact that the defendant was beside himself with rage. It is not enough that he had grounds which would have had the same effect on every man of his standing and education. The most insulting words are not provocation, although to this day, and still more when the law was established, many people would rather die than suffer them without action. There must be provocation sufficient to justify the passion, and the law decides on general considerations what provocations are sufficient.

At the same time, the objective nature of legal standards is evident here. Mitigation doesn't come from the defendant being overwhelmed with anger. It's not enough that he had reasons that would provoke the same reaction in anyone of his status and education. The most insulting words aren't considered provocation, even though many people would still choose to act rather than endure them silently, especially when the law was first established. There must be enough provocation to justify the emotional response, and the law determines, based on general principles, what counts as sufficient provocation.

It is said that even what the law admits to be "provocation does not extenuate the guilt of homicide, unless the person provoked is at the time when he does the deed [62] deprived of the power of self-control by the provocation which he has received." /1/ There are obvious reasons for taking the actual state of the defendant's consciousness into account to this extent. The only ground for not applying the general rule is, that the defendant was in such a state that he could not be expected to remember or be influenced by the fear of punishment; if he could be, the ground of exception disappears. Yet even here, rightly or wrongly, the law has gone far in the direction of adopting external tests. The courts seem to have decided between murder and manslaughter on such grounds as the nature of the weapon used, /2/ or the length of time between the provocation and the act. /3/ But in other cases the question whether the prisoner was deprived of self-control by passion has been left to the jury. /4/

It’s said that even when the law recognizes something as "provocation," it doesn’t reduce the guilt of homicide unless the person provoked is at the moment of the act [62] unable to control themselves due to the provocation they experienced." /1/ There are clear reasons to consider the actual mental state of the defendant to this extent. The only reason for not following the general rule is if the defendant was in such a state that they couldn’t be expected to remember or be influenced by the fear of punishment; if they could, the exception doesn’t apply. Yet, even in these cases, rightly or wrongly, the law has leaned toward using external criteria. The courts seem to decide between murder and manslaughter based on factors like the type of weapon used, /2/ or the time elapsed between the provocation and the act. /3/ However, in other cases, whether the defendant was unable to control their emotions due to passion has been left to the jury. /4/

As the object of this Lecture is not to give an outline of the criminal law, but to explain its general theory, I shall only consider such offences as throw some special light upon the subject, and shall treat of those in such order as seems best fitted for that purpose. It will now be useful to take up malicious mischief, and to compare the malice required to constitute that offence with the malice aforethought of murder.

As the goal of this lecture is not to provide an overview of criminal law, but to explain its general theory, I will only discuss offenses that shed some specific light on the topic, and I will address them in an order that seems most appropriate for that purpose. It will be helpful to start with malicious mischief and compare the malice needed for that offense with the malice aforethought associated with murder.

The charge of malice aforethought in an indictment for murder has been shown not to mean a state of the defendant's mind, as is often thought, except in the sense that he knew circumstances which did in fact make his conduct dangerous. It is, in truth, an allegation like that of negligence, which asserts that the party accused did not [63] come up to the legal standard of action under the circumstances in which he found himself, and also that there was no exceptional fact or excuse present which took the case out of the general rule. It is an averment of a conclusion of law which is permitted to abridge the facts (positive and negative) on which it is founded.

The accusation of malice aforethought in a murder indictment doesn’t necessarily reflect the defendant's mental state, as many believe, except in the way that he was aware of the circumstances that made his actions dangerous. In reality, it’s an assertion similar to negligence, claiming that the accused did not meet the legal standard of conduct expected given the situation he was in, and that there were no unusual factors or justifications that would exempt the case from the general rule. It’s a declaration of a legal conclusion that allows for the simplification of the underlying facts (both positive and negative) upon which it is based.

When a statute punishes the "wilfully and maliciously" injuring another's property, it is arguable, if not clear, that something more is meant. The presumption that the second word was not added without some meaning is seconded by the unreasonableness of making every wilful trespass criminal. /1/ If this reasoning prevails, maliciously is here used in its popular sense, and imports that the motive for the defendant's act was a wish to harm the owner of the property, or the thing itself, if living, as an end, and for the sake of the harm. Malice in this sense has nothing in common with the malice of murder.

When a law punishes the "willfully and maliciously" harming someone else's property, it's open to debate, if not clear, that there's more to it. The assumption that the second word was included for a reason is supported by the unreasonable idea of making every intentional trespass a crime. /1/ If this reasoning holds up, maliciously is used here in its common meaning, suggesting that the defendant intended to cause harm to the property owner, or the property itself if it's living, as a goal in itself, and for the sake of causing that harm. Malice in this context is completely different from the malice associated with murder.

Statutory law need not profess to be consistent with itself, or with the theory adopted by judicial decisions. Hence there is strictly no need to reconcile such a statute with the principles which have been explained. But there is no inconsistency. Although punishment must be confined to compelling external conformity to a rule of conduct, so far that it can always be avoided by avoiding or doing certain acts as required, with whatever intent or for whatever motive, still the prohibited conduct may not be hurtful unless it is accompanied by a particular state of feeling.

Statutory law doesn’t have to be consistent with itself or align with the theories established by court decisions. So, there’s really no requirement to align such a statute with the principles that have been outlined. However, there’s no inconsistency. While punishment should be limited to enforcing external adherence to a rule of conduct—meaning it can always be evaded by simply not doing certain things or doing what’s required, regardless of intent or motive—the behavior that’s prohibited might not be harmful unless it comes with a certain emotional state.

Common disputes about property are satisfactorily settled by compensation. But every one knows that sometimes secret harm is done by neighbor to neighbor out of [64] pure malice and spite. The damage can be paid for, but the malignity calls for revenge, and the difficulty of detecting the authors of such wrongs, which are always done secretly, affords a ground for punishment, even if revenge is thought insufficient.

Common disputes over property can usually be resolved through compensation. However, everyone knows that sometimes a neighbor harms another out of pure malice and spite. The damage can be compensated, but the malicious intent calls for revenge, and the challenge of identifying the perpetrators of these secret wrongs provides a basis for punishment, even if revenge is seen as inadequate.

How far the law will go in this direction it is hard to say. The crime of arson is defined to be the malicious and wilful burning of the house of another man, and is generally discussed in close connection with malicious mischief. It has been thought that the burning was not malicious where a prisoner set fire to his prison, not from a desire to consume the building, but solely to effect his escape. But it seems to be the better opinion that this is arson, /1/ in which case an intentional burning is malicious within the meaning of the rule. When we remember that arson was the subject of one of the old appeals which take us far back into the early law, /2/ we may readily understand that only intentional burnings were redressed in that way. /3/ The appeal of arson was brother to the appeal de pace et plagis. As the latter was founded on a warlike assault, the former supposed a house-firing for robbery or revenge, /4/ such as that by which Njal perished in the Icelandic Saga. But this crime seems to have had the same history as others. As soon as intent is admitted to be sufficient, the law is on the high-road to an external standard. A man who intentionally sets fire to his own house, which is so near to other houses that the fire will manifestly endanger them, is guilty of arson if one of the other houses is burned in consequence. /5/ In this case, an act which would not [65] have been arson, taking only its immediate consequences into account, becomes arson by reason of more remote consequences which were manifestly likely to follow, whether they were actually intended or not. If that may be the effect of setting fire to things which a man has a right to burn, so far as they alone are concerned, why, on principle, should it not be the effect of any other act which is equally likely under the surrounding circumstances to cause the same harm. /1/ Cases may easily be imagined where firing a gun, or making a chemical mixture, or piling up oiled rags, or twenty other things, might be manifestly dangerous in the highest degree and actually lead to a conflagration. If, in such cases, the crime is held to have been committed, an external standard is reached, and the analysis which has been made of murder applies here.

It's hard to say how far the law will go in this area. Arson is defined as the intentional and malicious burning of someone else's house, and it's usually discussed alongside malicious mischief. Some have argued that setting fire to one’s own prison isn’t malicious if the intent is simply to escape, not to destroy the building. However, it seems to be the consensus that this is still considered arson, where an intentional act of burning is viewed as malicious according to the law. Looking back, we can see that arson was the subject of one of the old legal appeals, a concept rooted deeply in early law, suggesting that only intentional burnings were addressed in this way. The appeal for arson was similar to the appeal for assault and battery. While the latter was founded on a violent attack, the former assumed a house was set on fire for robbery or revenge, such as in the saga of Njal from Icelandic literature. This crime seems to have evolved like others. Once intent is recognized as sufficient, the law moves toward an external standard. If someone intentionally sets fire to their house, and it's close enough to other houses that the fire clearly poses a danger to them, that person is guilty of arson if one of those houses burns as a result. In this case, an action that wouldn’t normally be considered arson based solely on its immediate results qualifies as arson due to the more distant consequences that were obviously likely to occur, whether those outcomes were intended or not. If setting fire to things one has the right to burn can lead to such consequences, why shouldn't the same principle apply to any act that could reasonably result in similar harm under the circumstances? It's easy to imagine scenarios where firing a gun, mixing chemicals, stacking oiled rags, or many other actions could pose an extreme risk and potentially cause a fire. If, in those situations, the crime is deemed committed, then an external standard is established, and the analysis applied to murder can be similarly applied here.

There is another class of cases in which intent plays an important part, for quite different reasons from those which have been offered to account for the law of malicious mischief. The most obvious examples of this class are criminal attempts. Attempt and intent, of course, are two distinct things. Intent to commit a crime is not itself criminal. There is no law against a man's intending to commit a murder the day after tomorrow. The law only deals with conduct. An attempt is an overt act. It differs from the attempted crime in this, that the act has failed to bring about the result which would have given it the character of the principal crime. If an attempt to murder results in death within a year and a day, it is murder. If an attempt to steal results in carrying off the owner's goods, it is larceny.

There is another category of cases where intent is significant, but for reasons different from those explaining the law of malicious mischief. The clearest examples of this category are criminal attempts. Intent and attempt are obviously two separate things. Simply intending to commit a crime isn’t a crime in itself. There’s no law against someone planning to commit murder the day after tomorrow. The law focuses on actions. An attempt is an action that is taken. It differs from the crime that was attempted in that the action failed to achieve the result that would have made it the main crime. If an attempt to murder leads to death within a year and a day, it is considered murder. If an attempt to steal leads to taking the owner's property, it is classified as larceny.

If an act is done of which the natural and probable [66] effect under the circumstances is the accomplishment of a substantive crime, the criminal law, while it may properly enough moderate the severity of punishment if the act has not that effect in the particular case, can hardly abstain altogether from punishing it, on any theory. It has been argued that an actual intent is all that can give the act a criminal character in such instances. /1/ But if the views which I have advanced as to murder and manslaughter are sound, the same principles ought logically to determine the criminality of acts in general. Acts should be judged by their tendency under the known circumstances, not by the actual intent which accompanies them.

If someone does something that is likely to result in a serious crime given the circumstances, the law should generally impose some sort of punishment, even if it lessens the severity if the act doesn't actually lead to that outcome in this specific case. Some argue that having a specific intent is what makes the act criminal in these situations. But if the arguments I've made about murder and manslaughter are correct, the same principles should logically apply to the criminal nature of actions overall. Actions should be evaluated based on their potential impact under the known circumstances, not merely on the intent behind them.

It may be true that in the region of attempts, as elsewhere, the law began with cases of actual intent, as those cases are the most obvious ones. But it cannot stop with them, unless it attaches more importance to the etymological meaning of the word attempt than to the general principles of punishment. Accordingly there is at least color of authority for the proposition that an act is punishable as an attempt, if, supposing it to have produced its natural and probable effect, it would have amounted to a substantive crime. /2/

It may be true that in the realm of attempts, like other areas, the law started with cases of actual intent, since those cases are the most apparent. However, it can't stop there unless it values the etymological meaning of the word "attempt" more than the general principles of punishment. Therefore, there is at least some authority for the idea that an act can be punished as an attempt if, assuming it had its natural and probable outcome, it would have qualified as a substantive crime. /2/

But such acts are not the only punishable attempts. There is another class in which actual intent is clearly necessary, and the existence of this class as well as the name (attempt) no doubt tends to affect the whole doctrine. Some acts may be attempts or misdemeanors which [67] could not have effected the crime unless followed by other acts on the part of the wrong-doer. For instance, lighting a match with intent to set fire to a haystack has been held to amount to a criminal attempt to burn it, although the defendant blew out the match on seeing that he was watched. /1/ So the purchase of dies for making counterfeit coin is a misdemeanor, although of course the coin would not be counterfeited unless the dies were used. /2/

But these actions aren't the only ones that can lead to punishment. There's another category where actual intent is clearly necessary, and the existence of this category, along with its name (attempt), definitely influences the whole concept. Some actions can be considered attempts or misdemeanors which [67] couldn't result in the crime unless additional actions are taken by the wrongdoer. For example, lighting a match with the intent to set fire to a haystack has been ruled as a criminal attempt to burn it, even though the defendant blew out the match upon realizing he was being watched. /1/ Similarly, buying dies to make counterfeit coins is a misdemeanor, even though the coins wouldn't be counterfeited unless the dies were actually used. /2/

In such cases the law goes on a new principle, different from that governing most substantive crimes. The reason for punishing any act must generally be to prevent some harm which is foreseen as likely to follow that act under the circumstances in which it is done. In most substantive crimes the ground on which that likelihood stands is the common working of natural causes as shown by experience. But when an act is punished the natural effect of which is not harmful under the circumstances, that ground alone will not suffice. The probability does not exist unless there are grounds for expecting that the act done will be followed by other acts in connection with which its effect will be harmful, although not so otherwise. But as in fact no such acts have followed, it cannot, in general, be assumed, from the mere doing of what has been done, that they would have followed if the actor had not been interrupted. They would not have followed it unless the actor had chosen, and the only way generally available to show that he would have chosen to do them is by showing that he intended to do them when he did what he did. The accompanying intent in that case renders the otherwise [68] innocent act harmful, because it raises a probability that it will be followed by such other acts and events as will all together result in harm. The importance of the intent is not to show that the act was wicked, but to show that it was likely to be followed by hurtful consequences.

In these situations, the law operates on a new principle, different from what usually governs most crimes. Generally, the reason for punishing any action must be to prevent harm that is likely to result from that action under the given circumstances. For most crimes, this likelihood is based on the natural consequences we see in everyday life. However, when an act is punished but does not naturally cause harm in those circumstances, that reason alone is not enough. The probability doesn't exist unless there are reasons to believe that the act will lead to other actions that will be harmful, even if the original act itself is not. Since no such actions have actually followed, we can't assume that they would have occurred just because the person took that action if they hadn't been stopped. They wouldn't have happened unless the person had chosen to do them, and the only way to typically demonstrate that they would have made that choice is to show that they intended to commit those actions when they performed the original act. In that case, the accompanying intent makes the otherwise [68] innocent act harmful, because it creates a likelihood that it will lead to further actions and events that will ultimately result in harm. The importance of intent is not to prove that the act was malicious, but to indicate that it was likely to lead to harmful consequences.

It will be readily seen that there are limits to this kind of liability. The law does not punish every act which is done with the intent to bring about a crime. If a man starts from Boston to Cambridge for the purpose of committing a murder when he gets there, but is stopped by the draw and goes home, he is no more punishable than if he had sat in his chair and resolved to shoot somebody, but on second thoughts had given up the notion. On the other hand, a slave who ran after a white woman, but desisted before he caught her, has been convicted of an attempt to commit rape. /1/ We have seen what amounts to an attempt to burn a haystack; but it was said in the same case, that, if the defendant had gone no further than to buy a box of matches for the purpose, he would not have been liable.

It’s clear that there are limits to this kind of liability. The law doesn’t punish every act that’s intended to lead to a crime. If someone leaves Boston for Cambridge with the plan to commit murder but is interrupted by a drawbridge and goes home instead, he wouldn’t be punished any more than if he had just sat in his chair and decided to shoot someone, only to change his mind later. On the flip side, a slave who chased after a white woman but stopped before catching her has been convicted of attempting to commit rape. We’ve established what counts as an attempt to burn a haystack; however, it was mentioned in the same case that if the defendant had only purchased a box of matches for that purpose, he wouldn’t have faced liability.

Eminent judges have been puzzled where to draw the line, or even to state the principle on which it should be drawn, between the two sets of cases. But the principle is believed to be similar to that on which all other lines are drawn by the law. Public policy, that is to say, legislative considerations, are at the bottom of the matter; the considerations being, in this case, the nearness of the danger, the greatness of the harm, and the degree of apprehension felt. When a man buys matches to fire a haystack, or starts on a journey meaning to murder at the end of it, there is still a considerable chance that he will [69] change his mind before he comes to the point. But when he has struck the match, or cocked and aimed the pistol, there is very little chance that he will not persist to the end, and the danger becomes so great that the law steps in. With an object which could not be used innocently, the point of intervention might be put further back, as in the case of the purchase of a die for coining.

Eminent judges have been confused about where to draw the line, or even how to define the principle that should dictate that line, between the two sets of cases. However, it's thought that the principle is similar to how all other legal boundaries are established. Public policy, or legislative factors, underlie the issue; in this case, the factors include the immediacy of the danger, the severity of the harm, and the level of fear involved. When someone buys matches to set a haystack on fire, or sets out on a journey intending to commit murder at the end, there is still a reasonable chance he might change his mind before reaching the outcome. But once he has struck the match or cocked and aimed the gun, the likelihood of him backing out is minimal, and the danger escalates to a point where the law must intervene. For an object that cannot be used innocently, the point of intervention could be placed even earlier, as seen in the case of buying a die for counterfeiting.

The degree of apprehension may affect the decision, as well as the degree of probability that the crime will be accomplished. No doubt the fears peculiar to a slaveowning community had their share in the conviction which has just been mentioned.

The level of fear might influence the decision, along with the likelihood that the crime will happen. Clearly, the anxieties unique to a slave-owning society contributed to the conviction that has just been mentioned.

There is one doubtful point which should not be passed over. It has been thought that to shoot at a block of wood thinking it to be a man is not an attempt to murder, /1/ and that to put a hand into an empty pocket, intending to pick it, is not an attempt to commit larceny, although on the latter question there is a difference of opinion. /2/ The reason given is, that an act which could not have effected the crime if the actor had been allowed to follow it up to all results to which in the nature of things it could have led, cannot be an attempt to commit that crime when interrupted. At some point or other, of course, the law must adopt this conclusion, unless it goes on the theory of retribution for guilt, and not of prevention of harm.

There’s one questionable point that shouldn’t be overlooked. It has been argued that shooting at a block of wood thinking it’s a person doesn’t count as an attempted murder, and that putting a hand into an empty pocket with the intent to steal isn’t considered an attempt to commit theft, although there’s some disagreement on the latter. The reasoning is that an action that couldn’t have resulted in a crime if the person had been allowed to complete it cannot be seen as an attempt when interrupted. At some point, the law has to accept this conclusion, unless it follows the idea of punishing guilt rather than preventing harm.

But even to prevent harm effectually it will not do to be too exact. I do not suppose that firing a pistol at a man with intent to kill him is any the less an attempt to murder because the bullet misses its aim. Yet there the act has produced the whole effect possible to it in the [70] course of nature. It is just as impossible that that bullet under those circumstances should hit that man, as to pick an empty pocket. But there is no difficulty in saying that such an act under such circumstances is so dangerous, so far as the possibility of human foresight is concerned, that it should be punished. No one can absolutely know, though many would be pretty sure, exactly where the bullet will strike; and if the harm is done, it is a very great harm. If a man fires at a block, no harm can possibly ensue, and no theft can be committed in an empty pocket, besides that the harm of successful theft is less than that of murder. Yet it might be said that even such things as these should be punished, in order to make discouragement broad enough and easy to understand.

But even to effectively prevent harm, it isn't helpful to be overly precise. I don't believe that shooting a gun at someone with the intent to kill them is any less an attempt at murder just because the bullet misses. The act still has the potential to cause harm in the course of nature. It's just as unlikely that the bullet would hit that person, as it is to pick an empty pocket. However, it's easy to say that such an act, in those circumstances, is dangerous enough—given the limits of human foresight—that it should be punished. No one can be completely certain, although many might have a good idea, about exactly where the bullet will land; and if harm occurs, it's significant harm. If someone fires at an inanimate object, no harm can come from it, and no theft can happen with an empty pocket, especially since the harm caused by a successful theft is less than that of murder. Still, one might argue that even actions like these should be punished to ensure the discouragement is broad and clear.

There remain to be considered certain substantive crimes, which differ in very important ways from murder and the like, and for the explanation of which the foregoing analysis of intent in criminal attempts and analogous misdemeanors will be found of service.

There are still some serious crimes to consider, which are very different from murder and similar offenses. The earlier discussion about intent in criminal attempts and related misdemeanors will be helpful in explaining these.

The type of these is larceny. Under this name acts are punished which of themselves would not be sufficient to accomplish the evil which the law seeks to prevent, and which are treated as equally criminal, whether the evil has been accomplished or not. Murder, manslaughter, and arson, on the other hand, are not committed unless the evil is accomplished, and they all consist of acts the tendency of which under the surrounding circumstances is to hurt or destroy person or property by the mere working of natural laws.

The type of these is theft. Under this term, actions are punished even if they alone wouldn’t cause the harm the law aims to prevent, and they are considered equally criminal, regardless of whether the harm has occurred or not. Murder, manslaughter, and arson, on the other hand, are only committed if the harm is actually done, and they all involve acts that, given the circumstances, tend to harm or destroy a person or property simply by the operation of natural laws.

In larceny the consequences immediately flowing from the act are generally exhausted with little or no harm to the owner. Goods are removed from his possession by [71] trespass, and that is all, when the crime is complete. But they must be permanently kept from him before the harm is done which the law seeks to prevent. A momentary loss of possession is not what has been guarded against with such severe penalties. What the law means to prevent is the loss of it wholly and forever, as is shown by the fact that it is not larceny to take for a temporary use without intending to deprive the owner of his property. If then the law punishes the mere act of taking, it punishes an act which will not of itself produce the evil effect sought to be prevented, and punishes it before that effect has in any way come to pass.

In theft, the immediate consequences of the act usually don’t cause much harm to the owner. Items are taken from their possession through [71] trespass, and that’s it; the crime is considered complete at that point. However, the items must be permanently kept from the owner before the harm that the law aims to prevent occurs. A brief loss of possession isn’t what the severe penalties are meant to guard against. What the law aims to prevent is a total and permanent loss, which is evident because it’s not considered theft to take something temporarily without the intention of denying the owner their property. So, if the law punishes simply the act of taking, it punishes an action that by itself doesn’t lead to the harmful result it seeks to prevent, and it does so before any harm has actually occurred.

The reason is plain enough. The law cannot wait until the property has been used up or destroyed in other hands than the owner's, or until the owner has died, in order to make sure that the harm which it seeks to prevent has been done. And for the same reason it cannot confine itself to acts likely to do that harm. For the harm of permanent loss of property will not follow from the act of taking, but only from the series of acts which constitute removing and keeping the property after it has been taken. After these preliminaries, the bearing of intent upon the crime is easily seen.

The reason is pretty clear. The law can't wait until the property has been used up or destroyed by someone other than the owner, or until the owner has died, to ensure that the harm it aims to prevent has actually happened. For the same reason, it can't just focus on actions that are likely to cause that harm. The permanent loss of property doesn't come from the act of taking it, but from the ongoing actions involved in removing and keeping the property after it's been taken. Once we understand this, it’s easy to see how intent relates to the crime.

According to Mr. Bishop, larceny is "the taking and removing, by trespass, of personal property which the trespasser knows to belong either generally or specially to another, with the intent to deprive such owner of his ownership therein; and perhaps it should be added, for the sake of some advantage to the trespasser, a proposition on which the decisions are not harmonious." /1/

According to Mr. Bishop, larceny is "the act of taking and moving, without permission, personal property that the person knows belongs to someone else, with the intention of depriving that owner of their ownership; and it might also be worth mentioning, to benefit the trespasser, a concept on which the rulings are not consistent." /1/

There must be an intent to deprive such owner of his [72] ownership therein, it is said. But why? Is it because the law is more anxious not to put a man in prison for stealing unless he is actually wicked, than it is not to hang him for killing another? That can hardly be. The true answer is, that the intent is an index to the external event which probably would have happened, and that, if the law is to punish at all, it must, in this case, go on probabilities, not on accomplished facts. The analogy to the manner of dealing with attempts is plain. Theft may be called an attempt to permanently deprive a man of his property, which is punished with the same severity whether successful or not. If theft can rightly be considered in this way, intent must play the same part as in other attempts. An act which does not fully accomplish the prohibited result may be made wrongful by evidence that but for some interference it would have been followed by other acts co-ordinated with it to produce that result. This can only be shown by showing intent. In theft the intent to deprive the owner of his property establishes that the thief would have retained, or would not have taken steps to restore, the stolen goods. Nor would it matter that the thief afterwards changed his mind and returned the goods. From the point of view of attempt, the crime was already complete when the property was carried off.

There has to be an intention to take away the owner's ownership, it’s said. But why? Is it because the law is more concerned about not throwing someone in prison for stealing unless they’re truly evil, rather than about not executing them for murder? That seems unlikely. The real reason is that intent indicates what probably would have happened, and if the law is going to punish at all, it must rely on probabilities, not just completed actions. The comparison with how attempts are treated is clear. Theft can be seen as an attempt to permanently deprive someone of their property, and it's punished with the same seriousness regardless of whether it was successful. If theft can be viewed in this way, then intent must have a similar role as in other attempts. An action that doesn't fully achieve the illegal outcome can still be considered wrong if there’s evidence that, without some interruption, it would have led to other actions that would complete that outcome. This can only be demonstrated by showing intent. In theft, the intention to deprive the owner of their property indicates that the thief would have kept, or wouldn’t have tried to return, the stolen items. It wouldn't matter if the thief later changed their mind and returned the items. From the perspective of an attempt, the crime was already finished when the property was taken.

It may be objected to this view, that, if intent is only a makeshift which from a practical necessity takes the place of actual deprivation, it ought not to be required where the actual deprivation is wholly accomplished, provided the same criminal act produces the whole effect. Suppose, for instance, that by one and the same motion a man seizes and backs another's horse over a precipice. The whole evil which the law seeks to prevent is the natural and manifestly [73] certain consequence of the act under the known circumstances. In such a case, if the law of larceny is consistent with the theories here maintained, the act should be passed upon according to its tendency, and the actual intent of the wrong-doer not in any way considered. Yet it is possible, to say the least, that even in such a case the intent would make all the difference. I assume that the act was without excuse and wrongful, and that it would have amounted to larceny, if done for the purpose of depriving the owner of his horse. Nevertheless, if it was done for the sake of an experiment, and without actual foresight of the destruction, or evil design against the owner, the trespasser might not be held a thief.

One might argue against this perspective by saying that if intent is just a temporary solution that fills in for actual deprivation out of practical necessity, it shouldn’t be required when the actual deprivation is fully realized, as long as the same criminal act results in the complete effect. For example, if someone grabs another person's horse and pushes it off a cliff in one single action, the full harm that the law aims to prevent is a clear and obvious result of that act given the circumstances. In such a situation, if the law regarding theft aligns with the theories being discussed, the act should be evaluated based on its potential outcome, without considering the wrongdoer's actual intent. However, it’s still possible that, even in this scenario, the intent could be crucial. I assume the act was unjustifiable and wrong, and that it would be considered theft if the intent was to deprive the owner of their horse. Yet, if the act was carried out as an experiment and without any real anticipation of destruction or ill will toward the owner, the trespasser might not be deemed a thief.

The inconsistency, if there is one, seems to be explained by the way in which the law has grown. The distinctions of the common law as to theft are not those of a broad theory of legislation; they are highly technical, and very largely dependent upon history for explanation. /1/

The inconsistency, if there is one, appears to be explained by how the law has developed. The distinctions in common law regarding theft aren't based on a broad legislative theory; they're quite technical and largely rooted in historical context for explanation. /1/

The type of theft is taking to one's own user It used to be, and sometimes still is, thought that the taking must be lucri catesa, for the sake of some advantage to the thief. In such cases the owner is deprived of his property by the thief's keeping it, not by its destruction, and the permanence of his loss can only be judged of beforehand by the intent to keep. The intent is therefore always necessary, and it is naturally stated in the form of a self-regarding intent. It was an advance on the old precedents when it was decided that the intent to deprive the owner of his property was sufficient. As late as 1815 the English judges stood only six to five in favor of the proposition [74] that it was larceny to take a horse intending to kill it for no other purpose than to destroy evidence against a friend. /1/ Even that case, however, did not do away with the universality of intent as a test, for the destruction followed the taking, and it is an ancient rule that the criminality of the act must be determined by the state of things at the time of the taking, and not afterwards. Whether the law of larceny would follow what seems to be the general principle of criminal law, or would be held back by tradition, could only be decided by a case like that supposed above, where the same act accomplishes both taking and destruction. As has been suggested already, tradition might very possibly prevail.

The type of theft involves taking something for personal use. It used to be, and sometimes still is, believed that the act must be for the purpose of gaining something for the thief. In these cases, the owner loses their property because the thief keeps it, not because it’s destroyed, and the extent of their loss can only be anticipated based on the intent to keep it. Therefore, intent is always necessary and is typically framed as a self-serving intent. It was a step forward from previous precedents when it was ruled that the intent to deprive the owner of their property was enough. As recently as 1815, English judges were narrowly divided six to five on the idea that taking a horse with the intention of killing it solely to destroy evidence against a friend constituted larceny. Even that case, however, didn’t eliminate intent as a universal measure since the destruction came after the taking, and it's an age-old principle that the criminality of the act is determined by the situation at the time of taking, not afterward. Whether larceny law would align with what seems to be the general rule in criminal law or be restrained by tradition could only be resolved by a case like the one imagined above, where the same act leads to both taking and destruction. As has been mentioned, tradition might very well prevail.

Another crime in which the peculiarities noticed in larceny are still more clearly marked, and at the same time more easily explained, is burglary. It is defined as breaking and entering any dwelling-house by night with intent to commit a felony therein. /2/ The object of punishing such a breaking and entering is not to prevent trespasses, even when committed by night, but only such trespasses as are the first step to wrongs of a greater magnitude, like robbery or murder. /3/ In this case the function of intent when proved appears more clearly than in theft, but it is precisely similar. It is an index to the probability of certain future acts which the law seeks to prevent. And here the law gives evidence that this is the true explanation. For if the apprehended act did follow, then it is no longer necessary to allege that the breaking and entering was with that intent. An indictment for burglary which charges that [75] the defendant broke into a dwelling-house and stole certain property, is just as good as one which alleges that he broke in with intent to steal. /1/

Another crime where the unique aspects of theft are even more evident and easier to understand is burglary. It's defined as breaking into any house at night with the intent to commit a felony inside. /2/ The reason for punishing such breaking and entering isn't to stop trespassing, even at night, but specifically to address those trespasses that lead to more serious crimes, like robbery or murder. /3/ In this case, the role of intent, when proven, is clearer than in theft, but it is exactly the same. It indicates the likelihood of certain future actions that the law aims to prevent. Here, the law shows that this is the correct explanation. If the intended act follows, it's no longer necessary to claim that the breaking and entering was done with that intent. An indictment for burglary that states that [75] the defendant broke into a house and stole some property is just as valid as one that claims he broke in with the intent to steal. /1/

It is believed that enough has now been said to explain the general theory of criminal liability, as it stands at common law. The result may be summed up as follows. All acts are indifferent per se.

It’s believed that enough has now been discussed to explain the general theory of criminal liability as it exists in common law. The outcome can be summarized as follows: all acts are neutral in themselves.

In the characteristic type of substantive crime acts are rendered criminal because they are done finder circumstances in which they will probably cause some harm which the law seeks to prevent.

In the typical type of serious crime, actions are considered criminal because they occur under circumstances that are likely to cause some harm that the law aims to prevent.

The test of criminality in such cases is the degree of danger shown by experience to attend that act under those circumstances.

The measure of criminality in these situations is the level of danger indicated by experience associated with that act in those circumstances.

In such cases the mens rea, or actual wickedness of the party, is wholly unnecessary, and all reference to the state of his consciousness is misleading if it means anything more than that the circumstances in connection with which the tendency of his act is judged are the circumstances known to him. Even the requirement of knowledge is subject to certain limitations. A man must find out at his peril things which a reasonable and prudent man would have inferred from the things actually known. In some cases, especially of statutory crimes, he must go even further, and, when he knows certain facts, must find out at his peril whether the other facts are present which would make the act criminal. A man who abducts a girl from her parents in England must find out at his peril whether she is under sixteen.

In such cases, the intent or actual wrongdoing of the person is completely unnecessary, and any reference to their state of mind is misleading if it implies anything more than that the circumstances surrounding the act are known to them. Even the need for knowledge has its limits. A person must discover at their own risk things that a reasonable and cautious person would have inferred from what they actually know. In some situations, particularly with statutory offenses, they must go even further, and when they know certain facts, they must determine at their own risk whether other facts exist that would make the act a crime. A person who kidnaps a girl from her parents in England must find out at their own risk whether she is under sixteen.

[76] In some cases it may be that the consequence of the act, under the circumstances, must be actually foreseen, if it is a consequence which a prudent man would not have foreseen. The reference to the prudent man, as a standard, is the only form in which blameworthiness as such is an element of crime, and what would be blameworthy in such a man is an element;—first, as a survival of true moral standards; second, because to punish what would not be blameworthy in an average member of the community would be to enforce a standard which was indefensible theoretically, and which practically was too high for that community.

[76] In some cases, the outcome of an action, given the circumstances, must be something that is actually predictable if it’s an outcome that a reasonable person would not have anticipated. The reference to the reasonable person as a standard is the only way that blameworthiness is considered a part of a crime, and what would be considered blameworthy for such a person is important;—first, as a holdover of true moral standards; second, because punishing something that would not be seen as blameworthy by an average person in the community would mean enforcing a standard that is theoretically unjustifiable and practically too high for that community.

In some cases, actual malice or intent, in the common meaning of those words, is an element in crime. But it will be found that, when it is so, it is because the act when done maliciously is followed by harm which would not have followed the act alone, or because the intent raises a strong probability that an act, innocent in itself, will be followed by other acts or events in connection with which it will accomplish the result sought to be prevented by the law.

In some instances, actual malice or intent, in the usual sense of those words, is a factor in crime. However, it turns out that when this is the case, it’s because the act, when done with malice, leads to harm that wouldn’t occur from the act alone, or because the intent increases the likelihood that an act, which is innocent by itself, will lead to other actions or events that achieve the outcome the law aims to prevent.

[77]

[77]





LECTURE III. — TORTS.—TRESPASS AND NEGLIGENCE.

The object of the next two Lectures is to discover whether there is any common ground at the bottom of all liability in tort, and if so, what that ground is. Supposing the attempt to succeed, it will reveal the general principle of civil liability at common law. The liabilities incurred by way of contract are more or less expressly fixed by the agreement of the parties concerned, but those arising from a tort are independent of any previous consent of the wrong-doer to bear the loss occasioned by his act. If A fails to pay a certain sum on a certain day, or to deliver a lecture on a certain night, after having made a binding promise to do so, the damages which he has to pay are recovered in accordance with his consent that some or all of the harms which may be caused by his failure shall fall upon him. But when A assaults or slanders his neighbor, or converts his neighbor's property, he does a harm which he has never consented to bear, and if the law makes him pay for it, the reason for doing so must be found in some general view of the conduct which every one may fairly expect and demand from every other, whether that other has agreed to it or not.

The goal of the next two lectures is to find out if there's any common basis for all liability in tort, and if there is, what that basis is. If we succeed in this attempt, it will uncover the general principle of civil liability at common law. The liabilities that arise from contracts are usually clearly defined by the agreement of the parties involved, but those that come from torts don't depend on any previous agreement by the wrongdoer to accept the consequences of their actions. For example, if A fails to pay a specific amount on a certain day or to give a lecture on a specific night after making a binding promise to do so, the damages he has to pay are based on his agreement that some or all of the losses resulting from his failure will be his responsibility. However, when A assaults or defames his neighbor or takes his neighbor's property, he causes harm that he never agreed to accept, and if the law requires him to compensate for it, the rationale for that must come from a general expectation of conduct that everyone has the right to expect from one another, regardless of whether they explicitly agreed to it or not.

Such a general view is very hard to find. The law did not begin with a theory. It has never worked one out. The point from which it started and that at which I shall [78] try to show that it has arrived, are on different planes. In the progress from one to the other, it is to be expected that its course should not be straight and its direction not always visible. All that can be done is to point out a tendency, and to justify it. The tendency, which is our main concern, is a matter of fact to be gathered from the cases. But the difficulty of showing it is much enhanced by the circumstance that, until lately, the substantive law has been approached only through the categories of the forms of action. Discussions of legislative principle have been darkened by arguments on the limits between trespass and case, or on the scope of a general issue. In place of a theory of tort, we have a theory of trespass. And even within that narrower limit, precedents of the time of the assize and jurata have been applied without a thought of their connection with a long forgotten procedure.

A comprehensive overview is quite rare. The law didn't start with a theory, and it has never developed one. The starting point and the point I will try to demonstrate it has reached are on different levels. As it moves from one to the other, it’s expected that the path won’t be straightforward and its direction might not always be clear. All we can do is highlight a trend and explain it. The trend, which is our main focus, is something to be observed from the cases. However, showing it is made much harder because, until recently, the substantive law has only been considered through the categories of actions. Discussions around legislative principles have been muddled by debates over the differences between trespass and case, or the scope of a general issue. Instead of having a theory of tort, we have a theory of trespass. And even within that more limited framework, precedents from the time of assizes and juries have been used without considering their links to long-forgotten procedures.

Since the ancient forms of action have disappeared, a broader treatment of the subject ought to be possible. Ignorance is the best of law reformers. People are glad to discuss a question on general principles, when they have forgotten the special knowledge necessary for technical reasoning. But the present willingness to generalize is founded on more than merely negative grounds. The philosophical habit of the day, the frequency of legislation, and the ease with which the law may be changed to meet the opinions and wishes of the public, all make it natural and unavoidable that judges as well as others should openly discuss the legislative principles upon which their decisions must always rest in the end, and should base their judgments upon broad considerations of policy to which the traditions of the bench would hardly have tolerated a reference fifty years ago.

Since the old ways of handling legal matters have faded away, we should be able to approach the topic more broadly. Ignorance is the best catalyst for legal reform. People are eager to talk about issues on a general level when they’ve forgotten the specific knowledge needed for detailed legal reasoning. However, the current willingness to generalize is based on more than just a lack of information. The philosophical mindset of today, the regularity of new laws, and the ease with which laws can be changed to reflect public opinions and desires all make it natural and necessary for judges and others to openly discuss the legislative principles that ultimately underpin their decisions and to base their rulings on broad policy considerations that would have been hardly tolerated by the traditions of the bench fifty years ago.

[79] The business of the law of torts is to fix the dividing lines between those cases in which a man is liable for harm which he has done, and those in which he is not. But it cannot enable him to predict with certainty whether a given act under given circumstances will make him liable, because an act will rarely have that effect unless followed by damage, and for the most part, if not always, the consequences of an act are not known, but only guessed at as more or less probable. All the rules that the law can lay down beforehand are rules for determining the conduct which will be followed by liability if it is followed by harm—that is, the conduct which a man pursues at his peril. The only guide for the future to be drawn from a decision against a defendant in an action of tort is that similar acts, under circumstances which cannot be distinguished except by the result from those of the defendant, are done at the peril of the actor; that if he escapes liability, it is simply because by good fortune no harm comes of his conduct in the particular event.

[79] The purpose of tort law is to establish the boundaries between situations where a person is responsible for the harm they’ve caused and those where they aren’t. However, it cannot allow someone to predict with certainty whether a specific action in particular circumstances will make them liable, because an action typically won’t result in liability unless it’s accompanied by damage, and most of the time, if not always, the outcomes of an action are unknown and only estimated as more or less likely. All the rules that the law can set in advance are meant to identify the behavior that would lead to liability if it results in harm—that is, the actions a person takes at their own risk. The only guidance for the future that can be derived from a ruling against a defendant in a tort case is that similar actions, in circumstances that can only be differentiated by the outcome from those of the defendant, are taken at the risk of the individual; and if they avoid liability, it’s merely due to luck that no harm resulted from their actions in that particular instance.

If, therefore, there is any common ground for all liability in tort, we shall best find it by eliminating the event as it actually turns out, and by considering only the principles on which the peril of his conduct is thrown upon the actor. We are to ask what are the elements, on the defendant's side, which must all be present before liability is possible, and the presence of which will commonly make him liable if damage follows.

If there's any common ground for all liability in tort, we'll best discover it by setting aside how the event actually unfolds and focusing only on the principles that place the risk of someone's actions on the actor. We should ask what elements need to be present on the defendant's side for liability to be possible, as well as the elements that typically make them liable if damage occurs.

The law of torts abounds in moral phraseology. It has much to say of wrongs, of malice, fraud, intent, and negligence. Hence it may naturally be supposed that the risk of a man's conduct is thrown upon him as the result of some moral short-coming. But while this notion has been [80] entertained, the extreme opposite will be found to have been a far more popular opinion;—I mean the notion that a man is answerable for all the consequences of his acts, or, in other words, that he acts at his peril always, and wholly irrespective of the state of his consciousness upon the matter.

The law of torts is filled with moral language. It talks a lot about wrongs, malice, fraud, intent, and negligence. So, it's natural to think that a person's actions carry risk because of some moral failing on their part. However, while this idea has been considered, the opposite view has actually been much more popular; namely, the belief that a person is responsible for all the outcomes of their actions, or in simpler terms, that they act at their own risk, regardless of what they are thinking or feeling about the situation.

To test the former opinion it would be natural to take up successively the several words, such as negligence and intent, which in the language of morals designate various well-understood states of mind, and to show their significance in the law. To test the latter, it would perhaps be more convenient to consider it under the head of the several forms of action. So many of our authorities are decisions under one or another of these forms, that it will not be safe to neglect them, at least in the first instance; and a compromise between the two modes of approaching the subject may be reached by beginning with the action of trespass and the notion of negligence together, leaving wrongs which are defined as intentional for the next Lecture.

To test the first idea, it makes sense to examine various terms like negligence and intent, which in moral language represent different, well-understood mindsets, and to clarify their meaning in legal terms. To explore the second idea, it might be easier to look at it through the different types of legal actions. Many of our references are decisions related to these actions, so it’s important not to overlook them, at least initially. We can find a balance between these two approaches by starting with the concept of trespass and negligence together, and saving intentional wrongs for the next lecture.

Trespass lies for unintentional, as well as for intended wrongs. Any wrongful and direct application of force is redressed by that action. It therefore affords a fair field for a discussion of the general principles of liability for unintentional wrongs at common law. For it can hardly be supposed that a man's responsibility for the consequences of his acts varies as the remedy happens to fall on one side or the other of the penumbra which separates trespass from the action on the case. And the greater part of the law of torts will be found under one or the other of those two heads.

Trespass applies to both unintentional and intentional wrongs. Any wrongful and direct use of force can be addressed by this action. This provides a solid basis for discussing the general principles of liability for unintentional wrongs in common law. It's hard to believe that a person's responsibility for the outcomes of their actions changes depending on whether the remedy falls on one side or the other of the gray area that separates trespass from the action on the case. Most of tort law can be categorized under one of these two areas.

It might be hastily assumed that the action on the case [81] is founded on the defendant's negligence. But if that be so, the same doctrine must prevail in trespass. It might be assumed that trespass is founded on the defendant's having caused damage by his act, without regard to negligence. But if that be true, the law must apply the same criterion to other wrongs differing from trespass only in some technical point; as, for instance, that the property damaged was in the defendant's possession. Neither of the above assumptions, however, can be hastily permitted. It might very well be argued that the action on the case adopts the severe rule just suggested for trespass, except when the action is founded on a contract. Negligence, it might be said, had nothing to do with the common-law liability for a nuisance, and it might be added that, where negligence was a ground of liability, a special duty had to be founded in the defendant's super se assumpsit, or public calling. /1/ On the other hand, we shall see what can be said for the proposition, that even in trespass there must at least be negligence. But whichever argument prevails for the one form of action must prevail for the other. The discussion may therefore be shortened on its technical side, by confining it to trespass so far as may be practicable without excluding light to be got from other parts of the law.

It might be quickly assumed that the action in the case [81] is based on the defendant's negligence. But if that’s the case, the same principle should apply in trespass. It could be thought that trespass is based on the defendant causing damage through their actions, regardless of negligence. However, if that’s true, then the law must use the same standard for other wrongs that differ from trespass only in minor technical details, such as the property harmed being in the defendant's possession. Yet, neither of these assumptions can be rushed into acceptance. One could argue that the action on the case follows the strict rule just mentioned for trespass, except when the action is based on a contract. It could be said that negligence has nothing to do with common-law liability for a nuisance, and it could be added that when negligence was a basis for liability, a specific duty had to stem from the defendant's own obligations or public role. /1/ On the flip side, we will explore the idea that even in trespass there must be at least some level of negligence. But whichever argument holds true for one type of action must hold true for the other. Therefore, the discussion can be streamlined on its technical side by focusing on trespass as much as possible without excluding insights that can be gained from other areas of the law.

As has just been hinted, there are two theories of the common-law liability for unintentional harm. Both of them seem to receive the implied assent of popular textbooks, and neither of them is wanting in plausibility and the semblance of authority.

As just mentioned, there are two theories regarding common-law liability for unintentional harm. Both appear to be accepted by popular textbooks, and neither lacks credibility or a sense of authority.

The first is that of Austin, which is essentially the theory of a criminalist. According to him, the characteristic [82] feature of law, properly so called, is a sanction or detriment threatened and imposed by the sovereign for disobedience to the sovereign's commands. As the greater part of the law only makes a man civilly answerable for breaking it, Austin is compelled to regard the liability to an action as a sanction, or, in other words, as a penalty for disobedience. It follows from this, according to the prevailing views of penal law, that such liability ought only to be based upon personal fault; and Austin accepts that conclusion, with its corollaries, one of which is that negligence means a state of the party's mind. /1/ These doctrines will be referred to later, so far as necessary.

The first is Austin's theory, which is basically the perspective of a criminalist. According to him, the defining feature of law, strictly speaking, is a penalty or consequence threatened and enforced by the sovereign for failing to follow the sovereign's commands. Since most of the law only makes someone liable in civil court for breaking it, Austin feels he must view this liability as a sanction, or in other words, a penalty for disobedience. This leads to the common understanding of penal law that such liability should only be based on personal wrongdoing; Austin agrees with this conclusion, along with its implications, one of which is that negligence reflects a person's state of mind. /1/ These concepts will be discussed later as needed.

The other theory is directly opposed to the foregoing. It seems to be adopted by some of the greatest common law authorities, and requires serious discussion before it can be set aside in favor of any third opinion which may be maintained. According to this view, broadly stated, under the common law a man acts at his peril. It may be held as a sort of set-off, that he is never liable for omissions except in consequence of some duty voluntarily undertaken. But the whole and sufficient ground for such liabilities as he does incur outside the last class is supposed to be that he has voluntarily acted, and that damage has ensued. If the act was voluntary, it is totally immaterial that the detriment which followed from it was neither intended nor due to the negligence of the actor.

The other theory is completely opposed to the previous one. It appears to be supported by some of the top authorities in common law and requires serious discussion before it can be dismissed in favor of any alternative opinion. According to this perspective, in simple terms, under common law, a person acts at their own risk. It can be argued as a sort of counterpoint that they are not responsible for omissions unless they have taken on a duty voluntarily. However, the main reason for the liabilities they do face outside of the last category is believed to be that they have acted voluntarily and that harm has resulted. If the action was voluntary, it doesn’t matter at all that the resulting harm was not intended or was not due to the person's negligence.

In order to do justice to this way of looking at the subject, we must remember that the abolition of the common-law forms of pleading has not changed the rules of substantive law. Hence, although pleaders now generally [83] allege intent or negligence, anything which would formerly have been sufficient to charge a defendant in trespass is still sufficient, notwithstanding the fact that the ancient form of action and declaration has disappeared.

To properly understand this perspective on the topic, we need to keep in mind that abolishing the common-law forms of pleading hasn’t altered the rules of substantive law. Therefore, even though legal pleadings now commonly state intent or negligence, anything that would have previously been enough to hold a defendant liable in trespass remains sufficient, despite the disappearance of the old form of action and declaration.

In the first place, it is said, consider generally the protection given by the law to property, both within and outside the limits of the last-named action. If a man crosses his neighbor's boundary by however innocent a mistake, or if his cattle escape into his neighbor's field, he is said to be liable in trespass quare clausum fregit. If an auctioneer in the most perfect good faith, and in the regular course of his business, sells goods sent to his rooms for the purpose of being sold, he may be compelled to pay their full value if a third person turns out to be the owner, although he has paid over the proceeds, and has no means of obtaining indemnity.

Firstly, consider the protection that the law provides to property, both within and outside the context of the last mentioned action. If someone mistakenly crosses their neighbor's boundary, even if it was an innocent error, or if their livestock accidentally wanders into a neighbor's field, they can be held liable for trespassing. If an auctioneer, acting in good faith and following normal business procedures, sells goods that were sent to him for that purpose, he may be required to pay the full value if a third party turns out to be the actual owner, even if he has already given out the proceeds and has no way to recover his losses.

Now suppose that, instead of a dealing with the plaintiff's property, the case is that force has proceeded directly from the defendant's body to the plaintiff's body, it is urged that, as the law cannot be less careful of the persons than of the property of its subjects, the only defences possible are similar to those which would have been open to an alleged trespass on land. You may show that there was no trespass by showing that the defendant did no act; as where he was thrown from his horse upon the plaintiff, or where a third person took his hand and struck the plaintiff with it. In such cases the defendant's body is file passive instrument of an external force, and the bodily motion relied on by the plaintiff is not his act at all. So you may show a justification or excuse in the conduct of the plaintiff himself. But if no such excuse is shown, and the defendant has voluntarily acted, he must answer [84] for the consequences, however little intended and however unforeseen. If, for instance, being assaulted by a third person, the defendant lifted his stick and accidentally hit the plaintiff, who was standing behind him, according to this view he is liable, irrespective of any negligence toward the party injured.

Now imagine that, instead of dealing with the plaintiff's property, the situation involves force coming directly from the defendant's body to the plaintiff's body. It's argued that since the law should care just as much about people as it does about the property of its citizens, the only defenses available are similar to those for an alleged trespass on land. You can show there was no trespass by proving the defendant didn’t do anything, like if he was thrown from his horse onto the plaintiff, or if a third person grabbed his hand and hit the plaintiff with it. In these instances, the defendant’s body is just the passive tool of an outside force, and the motion that the plaintiff is using as evidence isn’t his action at all. You can also present a justification or excuse based on the plaintiff’s own behavior. However, if no such excuse is provided and the defendant acted voluntarily, he has to take responsibility [84] for the consequences, no matter how little he intended or expected them. For example, if the defendant, while being attacked by someone else, lifted his stick and accidentally struck the plaintiff who was behind him, under this perspective, he is liable, regardless of any negligence towards the injured party.

The arguments for the doctrine under consideration are, for the most part, drawn from precedent, but it is sometimes supposed to be defensible as theoretically sound. Every man, it is said, has an absolute right to his person, and so forth, free from detriment at the hands of his neighbors. In the cases put, the plaintiff has done nothing; the defendant, on the other hand, has chosen to act. As between the two, the party whose voluntary conduct has caused the damage should suffer, rather than one who has had no share in producing it.

The arguments for the doctrine being discussed mostly come from past cases, but some believe it can also be defended as logically sound. It’s said that everyone has an absolute right to their own body and so on, free from harm from others. In the examples provided, the plaintiff hasn’t done anything; instead, the defendant has decided to take action. Between the two, the person whose voluntary choices caused the damage should be the one to face the consequences, rather than someone who played no part in creating it.

We have more difficult matter to deal with when we turn to the pleadings and precedents in trespass. The declaration says nothing of negligence, and it is clear that the damage need not have been intended. The words vi et armis and contra pacere, which might seem to imply intent, are supposed to have been inserted merely to give jurisdiction to the king's court. Glanvill says it belongs to the sheriff, in case of neglect on the part of lords of franchise, to take cognizance of melees, blows, and even wounds, unless the accuser add a charge of breach of the king's peace (nisi accusator adjiciat de pace Domini Regis infracta). /1/ Reeves observes, "In this distinction between the sheriff's jurisdiction and that of the king, we see the reason of the allegation in modern indictments and writs, vi et amis, of 'the king's crown and dignity,' 'the king's [85] peace,' and 'the peace,'—this last expression being sufficient, after the peace of the sheriff had ceased to be distinguished as a separate jurisdiction." /1/

We have a tougher issue to tackle when we look at the pleadings and precedents in trespass. The declaration doesn’t mention negligence, and it’s clear that the damage doesn’t have to be intentional. The phrases "vi et armis" and "contra pacere," which might suggest intent, are meant to have been included just to give the king's court jurisdiction. Glanvill states that it is the sheriff's responsibility, in cases of neglect by lords of franchise, to oversee melees, blows, and even wounds, unless the accuser adds a charge of breaching the king's peace (nisi accusator adjiciat de pace Domini Regis infracta). /1/ Reeves notes, "In this distinction between the sheriff's jurisdiction and that of the king, we understand the reasoning behind the allegations in modern indictments and writs, 'vi et armis,' of 'the king's crown and dignity,' 'the king's peace,' and 'the peace,'—the last expression being sufficient since the sheriff's peace is no longer recognized as a separate jurisdiction." /1/

Again, it might be said that, if the defendant's intent or neglect was essential to his liability, the absence of both would deprive his act of the character of a trespass, and ought therefore to be admissible under the general issue. But it is perfectly well settled at common law that "Not guilty" only denies the act. /2/

Again, it could be argued that if the defendant's intent or negligence was crucial to his responsibility, the lack of both would mean his action couldn't be classified as a trespass and should therefore be acceptable under the general issue. However, it is clearly established in common law that "Not guilty" only denies the action. /2/

Next comes the argument from authority. I will begin with an early and important case. /3/ It was trespass quare clausum. The defendant pleaded that he owned adjoining land, upon which was a thorn hedge; that he cut the thorns, and that they, against his will (ipso invito), fell on the plaintiff's land, and the defendant went quickly upon the same, and took them, which was the trespass complained of. And on demurrer judgment was given for the plaintiff. The plaintiff's counsel put cases which have been often repeated. One of them, Fairfax, said: "There is a diversity between an act resulting in a felony, and one resulting in a trespass.... If one is cutting trees, and the boughs fall on a man and wound him, in this case he shall have an action of trespass, &c., and also, sir, if one is shooting at butts, and his bow shakes in his hands, and kills a man, ipso invito, it is no felony, as has been said, [86] &c.; but if he wounds one by shooting, he shall have a good action of trespass against him, and yet the shooting was lawful, &c., and the wrong which the other receives was against his will, &c.; and so here, &c." Brian, another counsel, states the whole doctrine, and uses equally familiar illustrations. "When one does a thing, he is bound to do it in such a way that by his act no prejudice or damage shall be done to &c. As if I am building a house, and when the timber is being put up a piece of timber falls on my neighbor's house and breaks his house, he shall have a good action, &c.; and yet the raising of the house was lawful, and the timber fell, me invito, &c. And so if one assaults me and I cannot escape, and I in self-defence lift my stick to strike him, and in lifting it hit a man who is behind me, in this case he shall have an action against me, yet my raising my stick was lawful in self-defence, and I hit him, me invito, &c.; and so here, &C."

Next comes the argument from authority. I'll start with an early and significant case. /3/ It was a case of trespass quare clausum. The defendant claimed that he owned neighboring land where there was a thorn hedge; he cut the thorns, and they, against his will (ipso invito), fell onto the plaintiff's land. The defendant quickly went onto that land and took them, which was the trespass that was complained about. In response to a legal objection, judgment was given for the plaintiff. The plaintiff's lawyer presented cases that have often been repeated. One of them, Fairfax, said: "There’s a difference between an act that results in a felony and one that results in a trespass.... If someone is cutting down trees and a branch falls on a person and injures them, in this case, that person can sue for trespass, etc. Additionally, if someone is shooting at targets and their bow slips and accidentally kills someone, ipso invito, it’s not a felony, as has been stated, [86] etc.; but if he injures someone while shooting, that person can file a valid trespass claim against him, even though the shooting was lawful, etc., and the harm caused to the other was against his will, etc.; and so here, etc." Brian, another lawyer, laid out the entire doctrine and used equally familiar examples. "When someone does something, they must do it in a way that doesn't result in prejudice or damage to others, etc. For instance, if I'm building a house and while raising the timber, a piece falls and damages my neighbor's house, they have a valid claim, etc.; even though raising the house was lawful, and the timber fell, me invito, etc. Similarly, if someone attacks me and I have no way to escape, and I lift my stick to defend myself but accidentally hit a person behind me, that person can sue me, even though lifting my stick was lawful for self-defense, and I hit him, me invito, etc.; and so here, etc."

"Littleton, J. to the same intent, and if a man is damaged he ought to be recompensed.... If your cattle come on my land and eat my grass, notwithstanding you come freshly and drive them out, you ought to make amends for what your cattle have done, be it more or less.... And, sir, if this should be law that he might enter and take the thorns, for the same reason, if he cut a large tree, he might come with his wagons and horses to carry the trees off, which is not reason, for perhaps he has corn or other crops growing, &c., and no more here, for the law is all one in great things and small.... Choke, C. J. to the same intent, for when the principal thing was not lawful, that which depends upon it was not lawful; for when he cut the thorns and they fell on my land, [87] this falling was not lawful, and therefore his coming to take them out was not lawful. As to what was said about their falling in ipso invito, that is no plea, but he ought to show that he could not do it in any other way, or that he did all that was in his power to keep them out."

"Littleton, J. expresses a similar idea, stating that if someone causes damage, they should be compensated.... If your cattle wander onto my land and eat my grass, even if you come right away to drive them off, you still need to make up for the damage your cattle caused, no matter how much it is.... And, sir, if it were legal for one to enter and take the thorns, then for the same reason, if he cut down a large tree, he could come with his wagons and horses to take the trees away, which wouldn’t make sense, because he might have corn or other crops growing, etc., and that’s all there is to it, because the law treats big issues and small issues the same.... Choke, C. J. agrees, indicating that if the principal action was unlawful, then anything that hinges on it was also unlawful; because when he cut the thorns and they fell onto my land, [87] that falling was not lawful, and thus his attempt to take them was also not lawful. Regarding what was mentioned about their falling in ipso invito, that argument is invalid; he should demonstrate that he couldn’t handle it any other way, or that he did everything he could to keep them out."

Forty years later, /1/ the Year Books report Rede, J. as adopting the argument of Fairfax in the last case. In trespass, he says, "the intent cannot be construed; but in felony it shall be. As when a man shoots at butts and kills a man, it is not felony et il ser come n'avoit l'entent de luy tuer; and so of a tiler on a house who with a stone kills a man unwittingly, it is not felony. /2/ But when a man shoots at the butts and wounds a man, though it is against his will, he shall be called a trespasser against his intent."

Forty years later, /1/ the Year Books report Rede, J. as supporting Fairfax's argument in the last case. In trespass, he says, "the intent cannot be interpreted; but in felony it can be. For example, when a man shoots at targets and accidentally kills someone, it is not considered felony if he didn't intend to kill him; and the same goes for a tiler on a house who, by accident, kills a man with a stone; it is not felony. /2/ But when a man shoots at the targets and wounds someone, even if it's against his will, he will be considered a trespasser regardless of his intent."

There is a series of later shooting cases, Weaver v. Ward, /3/ Dickenson v. Watson, /4/ and Underwood v. Hewson, /5/ followed by the Court of Appeals of New York in Castle v. Duryee, /6/ in which defences to the effect that the damage was done accidentally and by misfortune, and against the will of the defendant, were held insufficient.

There are several subsequent shooting cases, Weaver v. Ward, /3/ Dickenson v. Watson, /4/ and Underwood v. Hewson, /5/ followed by the New York Court of Appeals in Castle v. Duryee, /6/ where defenses claiming that the damage was caused accidentally and by misfortune, and not by the defendant's intent, were deemed inadequate.

In the reign of Queen Elizabeth it was held that where a man with a gun at the door of his house shot at a fowl, and thereby set fire to his own house and to the house of his neighbor, he was liable in an action on the case generally, the declaration not being on the custom of the realm, [88] "viz. for negligently keeping his fire." "For the injury is the same, although this mischance was not by a common negligence, but by misadventure." /1/

In Queen Elizabeth's time, it was understood that if a man shot at a bird with a gun at his front door and accidentally set his own house and his neighbor's house on fire, he could be held responsible in a lawsuit. The claim wouldn't be based on the usual laws of the land, [88] "but rather for carelessly handling his fire." "The harm is the same, even though this accident wasn't due to ordinary negligence but happened by misadventure." /1/

The above-mentioned instances of the stick and shooting at butts became standard illustrations; they are repeated by Sir Thomas Raymond, in Bessey v. Olliot, /2/ by Sir William Blackstone, in the famous squib case, /3/ and by other judges, and have become familiar through the textbooks. Sir T. Raymond, in the above case, also repeats the thought and almost the words of Littleton, J., which have been quoted, and says further: "In all civil acts the law doth not so much regard the intent of the actor, as the loss and damage of the party suffering." Sir William Blackstone also adopts a phrase from Dickenson v. Watson, just cited: "Nothing but inevitable necessity" is a justification. So Lord Ellenborough, in Leame v. Bray: /4/ "If the injury were received from the personal act of another, it was deemed sufficient to make it trespass"; or, according to the more frequently quoted language of Grose, J., in the same case: "Looking into all the cases from the Year Book in the 21 H. VII. down to the latest decision on the subject, I find the principle to be, that if the injury be done by the act of the party himself at the time, or he be the immediate cause of it, though it happen accidentally or by misfortune, yet he is answerable in trespass." Further citations are deemed unnecessary.

The earlier examples of the stick and shooting at targets have become standard references; they're cited by Sir Thomas Raymond in Bessey v. Olliot, /2/ by Sir William Blackstone in the well-known squib case, /3/ and by other judges, becoming well-known through textbooks. Sir T. Raymond, in the earlier case, also echoes the ideas and nearly the words of Littleton, J., which have been quoted, and he adds: "In all civil acts, the law does not focus so much on the intent of the actor but rather on the loss and damage of the party who suffers." Sir William Blackstone also uses a phrase from Dickenson v. Watson, just mentioned: "Nothing but inevitable necessity" is a justification. Additionally, Lord Ellenborough in Leame v. Bray /4/ states: "If the injury came from someone's personal act, it was sufficient to make it trespass"; or, as commonly quoted by Grose, J., in the same case: "Reviewing all the cases from the Year Book in the 21 H. VII. up to the latest decisions on this matter, I find the principle to be that if the injury results from the act of the party himself at the moment, or he is the immediate cause, even if it happens accidentally or unexpectedly, he is still responsible for trespass." Further citations are not seen as necessary.

In spite, however, of all the arguments which may be [89] urged for the rule that a man acts at his peril, it has been rejected by very eminent courts, even under the old forms of action. In view of this fact, and of the further circumstance that, since the old forms have been abolished, the allegation of negligence has spread from the action on the case to all ordinary declarations in tort which do not allege intent, probably many lawyers would be surprised that any one should think it worth while to go into the present discussion. Such is the natural impression to be derived from daily practice. But even if the doctrine under consideration had no longer any followers, which is not the case, it would be well to have something more than daily practice to sustain our views upon so fundamental a question; as it seems to me at least, the true principle is far from being articulately grasped by all who are interested in it, and can only be arrived at after a careful analysis of what has been thought hitherto. It might be thought enough to cite the decisions opposed to the rule of absolute responsibility, and to show that such a rule is inconsistent with admitted doctrines and sound policy. But we may go further with profit, and inquire whether there are not strong grounds for thinking that the common law has never known such a rule, unless in that period of dry precedent which is so often to be found midway between a creative epoch and a period of solvent philosophical reaction. Conciliating the attention of those who, contrary to most modern practitioners, still adhere to the strict doctrine, by reminding them once more that there are weighty decisions to be cited adverse to it, and that, if they have involved an innovation, the fact that it has been made by such magistrates as Chief Justice Shaw goes far to prove that the change was politic, I [90] think I may assert that a little reflection will show that it was required not only by policy, but by consistency. I will begin with the latter.

In spite of all the arguments for the idea that a person acts at their own risk, this has been rejected by very respected courts, even in the old types of legal actions. Given this and the fact that, since the old forms have been abolished, the claim of negligence has expanded from cases to all regular claims in tort that do not imply intent, many lawyers might be surprised that anyone thinks it’s worth discussing this topic. This seems to be the common impression from daily practice. But even if the doctrine we’re talking about had no supporters left, which isn’t the case, it would still be important to have more than just everyday practice to back up our views on such a fundamental issue; it seems to me that the true principle is far from understood by everyone interested in it and can only be reached after a careful analysis of past thoughts on the matter. It might seem enough to refer to the decisions against the rule of absolute liability and show that such a rule contradicts accepted doctrines and sound policy. However, we can go further and explore whether there are strong reasons to believe that common law has never recognized such a rule, except during that dry period of rigid precedents often found between a creative era and a time of resolving philosophical reactions. By engaging the attention of those who, unlike most modern practitioners, still adhere to the strict doctrine, and reminding them again that there are significant decisions against it, and that if these decisions involve a change, the fact that they were made by judges like Chief Justice Shaw strongly suggests that the change was sensible, I think I can confidently say that a little thought will reveal that it was needed not just by policy, but by consistency. I will start with the latter.

The same reasoning which would make a man answerable in trespass for all damage to another by force directly resulting from his own act, irrespective of negligence or intent, would make him answerable in case for the like damage similarly resulting from the act of his servant, in the course of the latter's employment. The discussions of the company's negligence in many railway cases would therefore be wholly out of place, for although, to be sure, there is a contract which would make the company liable for negligence, that contract cannot be taken to diminish any liability which would otherwise exist for a trespass on the part of its employees.

The same reasoning that would hold a person accountable in a trespass case for any harm caused to another by actions directly resulting from their own behavior, regardless of negligence or intent, would also make them responsible for similar harm caused by their employee while doing their job. Therefore, discussions about the company's negligence in many railway cases would be entirely irrelevant, because, although there is a contract that makes the company liable for negligence, that contract cannot lessen any liability that would otherwise exist for a trespass committed by its employees.

More than this, the same reasoning would make a defendant responsible for all damage, however remote, of which his act could be called the cause. So long, at least, as only physical or irresponsible agencies, however unforeseen, co-operated with the act complained of to produce the result, the argument which would resolve the case of accidentally striking the plaintiff, when lifting a stick in necessary self-defence, adversely to the defendant, would require a decision against him in every case where his act was a factor in the result complained of. The distinction between a direct application of force, and causing damage indirectly, or as a more remote consequence of one's act, although it may determine whether the form of action should be trespass or case, does not touch the theory of responsibility, if that theory be that a man acts at his peril.

More than that, the same reasoning would make a defendant responsible for all damage, no matter how distant, that could be considered caused by their actions. As long as it was only physical or uncontrollable factors, regardless of how unexpected, that worked alongside the act in question to create the outcome, the argument that would rule against the defendant in a case where they accidentally hit the plaintiff while lifting a stick for necessary self-defense would also require a ruling against them in every scenario where their actions contributed to the result in question. The difference between directly applying force and causing damage indirectly, or as a further consequence of one’s actions, may determine whether the legal action should be classified as trespass or case, but it doesn't affect the underlying theory of responsibility if that theory holds that a person acts at their own risk.

[91] As was said at the outset, if the strict liability is to be maintained at all, it must be maintained throughout. A principle cannot be stated which would retain the strict liability in trespass while abandoning it in case. It cannot be said that trespass is for acts alone, and case for consequences of those acts. All actions of trespass are for consequences of acts, not for the acts themselves. And some actions of trespass are for consequences more remote from the defendant's act than in other instances where the remedy would be case.

[91] As mentioned earlier, if strict liability is going to be upheld at all, it has to be consistent. You can't have a principle that keeps strict liability for trespass but gets rid of it for case. It’s not accurate to say that trespass only deals with acts, while case focuses on the outcomes of those acts. All trespass actions are about the consequences of actions, not the actions themselves. Additionally, some trespass actions deal with consequences that are farther removed from the defendant’s action compared to other situations where the remedy would be case.

An act is always a voluntary muscular contraction, and nothing else. The chain of physical sequences which it sets in motion or directs to the plaintiff's harm is no part of it, and very generally a long train of such sequences intervenes. An example or two will make this extremely clear.

An act is always a voluntary muscle contraction, and nothing more. The series of physical actions that it triggers or leads to the plaintiff's injury is not part of it, and often a long chain of those actions comes into play. A couple of examples will clarify this completely.

When a man commits an assault and battery with a pistol, his only act is to contract the muscles of his arm and forefinger in a certain way, but it is the delight of elementary writers to point out what a vast series of physical changes must take place before the harm is done. Suppose that, instead of firing a pistol, he takes up a hose which is discharging water on the sidewalk, and directs it at the plaintiff, he does not even set in motion the physical causes which must co-operate with his act to make a battery. Not only natural causes, but a living being, may intervene between the act and its effect. Gibbons v. Pepper, /1/ which decided that there was no battery when a man's horse was frightened by accident or a third person and ran away with him, and ran over the plaintiff, takes the distinction that, if the rider by spurring is the cause of [92] the accident, then he is guilty. In Scott v. Shepherd, /1/ already mentioned, trespass was maintained against one who had thrown a squib into a crowd, where it was tossed from hand to hand in self-defence until it burst and injured the plaintiff. Here even human agencies were a part of the chain between the defendant's act and the result, although they were treated as more or less nearly automatic, in order to arrive at the decision.

When a man assaults someone with a gun, all he really does is flex the muscles in his arm and finger in a specific way. However, basic writers love to explain the numerous physical changes that need to happen before any harm occurs. For example, if instead of firing a gun, he uses a hose that's shooting water on the sidewalk and aims it at the plaintiff, he doesn't even start the physical processes that are required to make it a battery. Both natural causes and another person can intervene between the action and its effect. In Gibbons v. Pepper, /1/, it was determined that there was no battery when a man's horse was spooked by accident or by someone else, causing it to run away and collide with the plaintiff. The ruling noted that if the rider caused the accident by spurring the horse, then he would be guilty. In Scott v. Shepherd, /1/, which has already been mentioned, trespass was upheld against someone who threw a firework into a crowd. It was then passed from hand to hand in an attempt to protect against it until it exploded and hurt the plaintiff. In this case, even human actions were part of the sequence linking the defendant's act to the outcome, even though they were treated as largely automatic to reach the judgment.

Now I repeat, that, if principle requires us to charge a man in trespass when his act has brought force to bear on another through a comparatively short train of intervening causes, in spite of his having used all possible care, it requires the same liability, however numerous and unexpected the events between the act and the result. If running a man down is a trespass when the accident can be referred to the rider's act of spurring, why is it not a tort in every case, as was argued in Vincent v. Stinehour, /2/ seeing that it can always be referred more remotely to his act of mounting and taking the horse out?

Now I repeat that if the principle requires us to hold someone responsible for trespassing when their actions have caused harm to another through a relatively short chain of events, even if they took every possible precaution, then the same responsibility applies, no matter how many or how unexpected the events are between the action and the outcome. If hitting someone with a horse is considered a trespass when the accident can be traced back to the rider’s action of spurring, then why isn’t it a tort in every instance, as was argued in Vincent v. Stinehour, /2/, since it can always be traced back even further to the action of getting on the horse and taking it out?

Why is a man not responsible for the consequences of an act innocent in its direct and obvious effects, when those consequences would not have followed but for the intervention of a series of extraordinary, although natural, events? The reason is, that, if the intervening events are of such a kind that no foresight could have been expected to look out for them, the defendant is not to blame for having failed to do so. It seems to be admitted by the English judges that, even on the question whether the acts of leaving dry trimmings in hot weather by the side of a railroad, and then sending an engine over the track, are [93] negligent,—that is, are a ground of liability,—the consequences which might reasonably be anticipated are material. /1/ Yet these are acts which, under the circumstances, can hardly be called innocent in their natural and obvious effects. The same doctrine has been applied to acts in violation of statute which could not reasonably have been expected to lead to the result complained of. /2/

Why is a man not held accountable for the effects of an action that is innocent in its direct and obvious results when those effects wouldn't have happened without a series of extraordinary, yet natural, events? The reason is that if the intervening events are such that no one could have reasonably anticipated them, the defendant isn't at fault for not doing so. English judges seem to agree that even when considering whether leaving dry trimmings in hot weather by the side of a railroad, and then sending an engine over the track, are [93] negligent—that is, grounds for liability—the consequences that could reasonably be expected are significant. /1/ However, these actions can hardly be considered innocent in their natural and obvious outcomes. The same principle has been applied to actions that violate statutes which could not reasonably be expected to cause the complained-of result. /2/

But there is no difference in principle between the case where a natural cause or physical factor intervenes after the act in some way not to be foreseen, and turns what seemed innocent to harm, and the case where such a cause or factor intervenes, unknown, at the time; as, for the matter of that, it did in the English cases cited. If a man is excused in the one case because he is not to blame, he must be in the other. The difference taken in Gibbons v. Pepper, cited above, is not between results which are and those which are not the consequences of the defendant's acts: it is between consequences which he was bound as a reasonable man to contemplate, and those which he was not. Hard spurring is just so much more likely to lead to harm than merely riding a horse in the street, that the court thought that the defendant would be bound to look out for the consequences of the one, while it would not hold him liable for those resulting merely from the other; [94] because the possibility of being run away with when riding quietly, though familiar, is comparatively slight. If, however, the horse had been unruly, and had been taken into a frequented place for the purpose of being broken, the owner might have been liable, because "it was his fault to bring a wild horse into a place where mischief might probably be done."

But there's no fundamental difference between a situation where a natural cause or physical factor unexpectedly intervenes after an action and turns something that seemed harmless into something harmful, and a situation where such a cause or factor unknowingly intervenes at the time; as it did in the English cases mentioned. If someone is excused in the first case because they aren’t to blame, they should be in the second case too. The distinction made in Gibbons v. Pepper, referenced above, isn’t about whether the outcomes are or aren’t the results of the defendant’s actions: it’s about whether those outcomes were something a reasonable person would be expected to consider, versus those that they wouldn’t. Hard spurring is much more likely to cause harm than just riding a horse down the street, so the court determined that the defendant should have anticipated the consequences of the former, whereas they wouldn’t hold him responsible for those resulting from the latter; [94] because the chance of being thrown off while riding calmly, though familiar, is relatively small. However, if the horse had been wild and taken into a busy area for the purpose of being trained, the owner might have been held liable because "it was his fault to bring a wild horse into a place where mischief might probably be done."

To return to the example of the accidental blow with a stick lifted in self-defence, there is no difference between hitting a person standing in one's rear and hitting one who was pushed by a horse within range of the stick just as it was lifted, provided that it was not possible, under the circumstances, in the one case to have known, in the other to have anticipated, the proximity. In either case there is wanting the only element which distinguishes voluntary acts from spasmodic muscular contractions as a ground of liability. In neither of them, that is to say, has there been an opportunity of choice with reference to the consequence complained of,—a chance to guard against the result which has come to pass. A choice which entails a concealed consequence is as to that consequence no choice.

To go back to the example of accidentally hitting someone with a stick while trying to defend yourself, there’s no difference between striking a person behind you and hitting someone who got pushed by a horse just as you lifted the stick, as long as it wasn’t possible, in either case, to know or anticipate the person's closeness. In both situations, the key element that separates intentional actions from involuntary muscle movements, which would lead to liability, is missing. In neither case was there an opportunity to choose regarding the complained consequence—a chance to prevent the result that occurred. A choice that has an unexpected outcome isn’t really a choice regarding that outcome.

The general principle of our law is that loss from accident must lie where it falls, and this principle is not affected by the fact that a human being is the instrument of misfortune. But relatively to a given human being anything is accident which he could not fairly have been expected to contemplate as possible, and therefore to avoid. In the language of the late Chief Justice Nelson of New York: "No case or principle can be found, or if found can be maintained, subjecting an individual to liability for [95] an act done without fault on his part.... All the cases concede that an injury arising from inevitable accident, or, which in law or reason is the same thing, from an act that ordinary human care and foresight are unable to guard against, is but the misfortune of the sufferer, and lays no foundation for legal responsibility." /1/ If this were not so, any act would be sufficient, however remote, which set in motion or opened the door for a series of physical sequences ending in damage; such as riding the horse, in the case of the runaway, or even coming to a place where one is seized with a fit and strikes the plaintiff in an unconscious spasm. Nay, why need the defendant have acted at all, and why is it not enough that his existence has been at the expense of the plaintiff? The requirement of an act is the requirement that the defendant should have made a choice. But the only possible purpose of introducing this moral element is to make the power of avoiding the evil complained of a condition of liability. There is no such power where the evil cannot be foreseen. /2/ Here we reach the argument from policy, and I shall accordingly postpone for a moment the discussion of trespasses upon land, and of conversions, and will take up the liability for cattle separately at a later stage.

The general rule in our law is that losses from accidents should fall on the person who experiences them, and this rule remains true even when a person is the cause of the accident. However, for any given individual, anything is considered an accident if they could not reasonably have anticipated or avoided it. As the late Chief Justice Nelson of New York stated: "No case or principle can be found, or if found can be maintained, subjecting an individual to liability for an act done without fault on his part.... All cases agree that an injury from an unavoidable accident, or, which legally or reasonably is the same, from an act that ordinary care and foresight cannot prevent, is simply the misfortune of the victim and does not create legal responsibility." /1/ If this were not the case, any action, no matter how distant, could trigger a series of events leading to damage; for example, riding a horse in a runaway situation, or even being in a place where someone suddenly has a seizure and accidentally injures another person. In fact, why would the defendant even need to act at all? Why isn’t it sufficient that their mere existence has caused the plaintiff harm? The requirement for an action suggests that the defendant made a choice. But the only reason to include this moral aspect is to make the ability to prevent the harm a condition for liability. Such ability doesn’t exist where the harm cannot be foreseen. /2/ Now we arrive at the policy argument, and I will temporarily set aside the discussion of land trespasses and conversions, and will address liability for livestock at a later point.

A man need not, it is true, do this or that act, the term act implies a choice,—but he must act somehow. Furthermore, the public generally profits by individual activity. As action cannot be avoided, and tends to the public good, there is obviously no policy in throwing the hazard of what is at once desirable and inevitable upon the actor. [96] The state might conceivably make itself a mutual insurance company against accidents, and distribute the burden of its citizens' mishaps among all its members. There might be a pension for paralytics, and state aid for those who suffered in person or estate from tempest or wild beasts. As between individuals it might adopt the mutual insurance principle pro tanto, and divide damages when both were in fault, as in the rusticum judicium of the admiralty, or it might throw all loss upon the actor irrespective of fault. The state does none of these things, however, and the prevailing view is that its cumbrous and expensive machinery ought not to be set in motion unless some clear benefit is to be derived from disturbing the status quo. State interference is an evil, where it cannot be shown to be a good. Universal insurance, if desired, can be better and more cheaply accomplished by private enterprise. The undertaking to redistribute losses simply on the ground that they resulted from the defendant's act would not only be open to these objections, but, as it is hoped the preceding discussion has shown, to the still graver one of offending the sense of justice. Unless my act is of a nature to threaten others, unless under the circumstances a prudent man would have foreseen the possibility of harm, it is no more justifiable to make me indemnify my neighbor against the consequences, than to make me do the same thing if I had fallen upon him in a fit, or to compel me to insure him against lightning.

A person doesn’t have to perform this or that action; the term action implies a choice, but they must take some kind of action. Moreover, society generally benefits from individual efforts. Since action is unavoidable and tends to promote the common good, it makes no sense to place the risks of something that is both desirable and inevitable solely on the individual. The government could potentially act as a mutual insurance provider against accidents, spreading the costs of its citizens' misfortunes among everyone. There could be pensions for those who are paralyzed and government assistance for people suffering losses due to storms or wild animals. Between individuals, the government could adopt a mutual insurance approach to some extent, sharing the damages when both parties are at fault, similar to the rusticum judicium of the admiralty, or it could place all the burden on the one who acted, regardless of fault. However, the government does none of these things, and the prevailing view is that its cumbersome and costly machinery shouldn't be activated unless it can clearly benefit the situation. Government intervention is considered a negative unless it can be shown to provide a clear advantage. Universal insurance, if needed, can be better and more affordably handled by private businesses. The idea of redistributing losses simply because they were a result of someone’s actions faces these criticisms and, as hopefully discussed earlier, an even more significant concern of violating the sense of justice. Unless my actions pose a threat to others, or unless a reasonable person would have seen the potential for harm, it's just as unreasonable to require me to compensate my neighbor for the consequences as it is to make me do the same if I accidentally harmed him during a seizure or to force me to insure him against lightning strikes.

I must now recur to the conclusions drawn from innocent trespasses upon land, and conversions, and the supposed analogy of those cases to trespasses against the person, lest the law concerning the latter should be supposed to lie between two antinomies, each necessitating with equal cogency an opposite conclusion to the other.

I need to go back to the conclusions made from minor infringements on land, and conversions, and the supposed similarities of those cases to personal trespasses, so that the law regarding the latter doesn't seem to be caught between two conflicting principles, each strongly supporting an opposite conclusion.

[97] Take first the case of trespass upon land attended by actual damage. When a man goes upon his neighbor's land, thinking it is his own, he intends the very act or consequence complained of. He means to intermeddle with a certain thing in a certain way, and it is just that intended intermeddling for which he is sued. /1/ Whereas, if he accidentally hits a stranger as he lifts his staff in self defence, the fact, which is the gist of the action,—namely, the contact between the staff and his neighbor's head,—was not intended, and could not have been foreseen. It might be answered, to be sure, that it is not for intermeddling with property, but for intermeddling with the plaintiff's property, that a man is sued; and that in the supposed cases, just as much as in that of the accidental blow, the defendant is ignorant of one of the facts making up the total environment, and which must be present to make his action wrong. He is ignorant, that is to say, that the true owner either has or claims any interest in the property in question, and therefore he does not intend a wrongful act, because he does not mean to deal with his neighbor's property. But the answer to this is, that he does intend to do the damage complained of. One who diminishes the value of property by intentional damage knows it belongs to somebody. If he thinks it belongs to himself, he expects whatever harm he may do to come out of his own pocket. It would be odd if he were to get rid of the burden by discovering that it belonged to his neighbor. It is a very different thing to say that he who intentionally does harm must bear the loss, from saying that one from whose acts harm follows accidentally, as [98] a consequence which could not have been foreseen, must bear it.

[97] Let's first consider the situation of trespassing on land that results in actual damage. When someone steps onto their neighbor's property, believing it's theirs, they are deliberately carrying out the very action or resulting consequence that is being complained about. They intend to interfere with something in a specific way, and it is exactly that intended interference for which they are being sued. /1/ In contrast, if someone accidentally hits a stranger while lifting their stick in self-defense, the key fact—the contact between the stick and the neighbor's head—was unintentional and could not have been predicted. One might argue that it's not about interfering with property in general, but specifically with the plaintiff's property that a person is being sued; and that, in both scenarios, just like the accidental blow, the defendant is unaware of an important fact in the overall context that is necessary for their action to be considered wrong. They don't realize that the true owner has or claims any interest in the property in question, so they don't intend to commit a wrongful act since they aren't trying to deal with their neighbor's property. However, the counterargument is that they do intend to cause the damage that's being complained about. Someone who intentionally reduces the value of property through damage knows it belongs to someone else. If they believe it belongs to them, they expect any harm they cause to impact them directly. It would be strange if they were to escape that responsibility simply by finding out it belongs to their neighbor. It's one thing to say that someone who intentionally causes harm should bear the loss, and quite another to say that someone who causes harm accidentally, as [98] a result that couldn't have been anticipated, should bear it.

Next, suppose the act complained of is an exercise of dominion over the plaintiff's property, such as a merely technical trespass or a conversion. If the defendant thought that the property belonged to himself, there seems to be no abstract injustice in requiring him to know the limits of his own titles, or, if he thought that it belonged to another, in holding him bound to get proof of title before acting. Consider, too, what the defendant's liability amounts to, if the act, whether an entry upon land or a conversion of chattels, has been unattended by damage to the property, and the thing has come back to the hands of the true owner. The sum recovered is merely nominal, and the payment is nothing more than a formal acknowledgment of the owner's title; which, considering the effect of prescription and statutes of limitation upon repeated acts of dominion, is no more than right. /1/ All semblance of injustice disappears when the defendant is allowed to avoid the costs of an action by tender or otherwise.

Next, let’s say the action in question involves taking control of the plaintiff's property, like a technical trespass or conversion. If the defendant believed the property belonged to him, there's no real injustice in expecting him to understand the boundaries of his own ownership, or, if he thought it belonged to someone else, in requiring him to prove ownership before taking action. Also, consider what the defendant's liability actually is if the action, whether it’s entering someone’s land or converting personal property, hasn’t caused any damage and the property has returned to its rightful owner. The amount recovered is really just nominal, and the payment is simply a formal acknowledgment of the owner's title; given how prescription and statutes of limitation affect repeated actions of control, this seems fair. Any hint of injustice goes away when the defendant can avoid the costs of a lawsuit by offering to resolve the matter in some way.

But suppose the property has not come back to the hands of the true owner. If the thing remains in the hands of the defendant, it is clearly right that he should surrender it. And if instead of the thing itself he holds the proceeds of a sale, it is as reasonable to make him pay over its value in trover or assumpsit as it would have been to compel a surrender of the thing. But the question whether the defendant has subsequently paid over the proceeds of the sale of a chattel to a third person, cannot affect the rights of the true owner of the [99] chattel. In the supposed case of an auctioneer, for instance, if he had paid the true owner, it would have been an answer to his bailor's claim. If he has paid his bailor instead, he has paid one whom he was not bound to pay, and no general principle requires that this should be held to divest the plaintiff's right.

But let's say the property hasn't returned to the true owner. If the defendant still has it, it's only fair that they should give it back. And if instead of the actual item they have the money from a sale, it's just as reasonable to require them to pay its value in a trover or assumpsit claim as it would have been to force a return of the item. However, whether the defendant has later given the sale proceeds to someone else doesn't impact the rights of the true owner of the [99] item. For example, in the case of an auctioneer, if he had paid the true owner, that would address his bailor's claim. If he paid his bailor instead, he's given money to someone he wasn't obligated to pay, and no general rule says this should strip the plaintiff of their rights.

Another consideration affecting the argument that the law as to trespasses upon property establishes a general principle, is that the defendant's knowledge or ignorance of the plaintiff's title is likely to lie wholly in his own breast, and therefore hardly admits of satisfactory proof. Indeed, in many cases it cannot have been open to evidence at all at the time when the law was settled, before parties were permitted to testify. Accordingly, in Basely v. Clarkson, /1/ where the defence set up to an action of trespass quare clausum was that the defendant in mowing his own land involuntarily and by mistake mowed down some of the plaintiff's grass, the plaintiff had judgment on demurrer. "For it appears the fact was voluntary, and his intention and knowledge are not traversable; they can't be known."

Another consideration that impacts the argument about the law on trespasses to property establishing a general principle is that the defendant's knowledge or ignorance regarding the plaintiff's ownership is likely to be completely internal and therefore difficult to prove satisfactorily. In fact, in many instances, it may not have even been admissible as evidence at the time the law was established, before parties were allowed to testify. Therefore, in Basely v. Clarkson, /1/ where the defense in a trespass case claimed that the defendant accidentally and unknowingly mowed down some of the plaintiff's grass while cutting his own land, the plaintiff won the case on demurrer. "Because it seems the act was voluntary, and his intention and knowledge are not open to challenge; they can't be known."

This language suggests that it would be sufficient to explain the law of trespass upon property historically, without attempting to justify it. For it seems to be admitted that if the defendant's mistake could be proved it might be material. /2/ It will be noticed, further, that any general argument from the law of trespass upon laud to that governing trespass against the person is shown to be misleading by the law as to cattle. The owner is bound at his peril [100] to keep them off his neighbor's premises, but he is not bound at his peril in all cases to keep them from his neighbor's person.

This language suggests that it would be enough to explain the law of trespassing on property from a historical perspective without trying to justify it. It seems accepted that if the defendant's mistake could be proven, it could be significant. /2/ Additionally, it's worth noting that any general argument from the law of trespass on land to that governing trespass against a person is proven to be misleading by the law regarding cattle. The owner is responsible at his own risk [100] for keeping them off his neighbor's property, but he isn't always responsible for keeping them away from his neighbor personally.

The objections to such a decision as supposed in the case of an auctioneer do not rest on the general theory of liability, but spring altogether from the special exigencies of commerce. It does not become unjust to hold a person liable for unauthorized intermeddling with another's property, until there arises the practical necessity for rapid dealing. But where this practical necessity exists, it is not surprising to find, and we do find, a different tendency in the law. The absolute protection of property, however natural to a primitive community more occupied in production than in exchange, is hardly consistent with the requirements of modern business. Even when the rules which we have been considering were established, the traffic of the public markets was governed by more liberal principles. On the continent of Europe it was long ago decided that the policy of protecting titles must yield to the policy of protecting trade. Casaregis held that the general principle nemo plus juris in alium transferre potest quam ipse habet must give way in mercantile transactions to possession vaut titre. /1/ In later times, as markets overt have lost their importance, the Factors' Acts and their successive amendments have tended more and more in the direction of adopting the Continental doctrine.

The objections to a decision like the one involving an auctioneer aren't based on the general theory of liability, but are entirely related to the specific needs of commerce. It’s not unfair to hold someone accountable for improperly messing with another person's property until there's a real need for quick transactions. But when that need is present, it's understandable, and we do see, a shift in the law. The strict protection of property, which makes sense in a simple society focused more on production than on trade, doesn't really fit with the needs of modern business. Even when the rules we’ve been discussing were established, public market trading was governed by more flexible principles. In Europe, it was decided long ago that protecting ownership must take a backseat to protecting trade. Casaregis stated that the general principle nemo plus juris in alium transferre potest quam ipse habet should give way in commercial dealings to possession vaut titre. In more recent times, as traditional markets have lost their significance, the Factors' Acts and their subsequent updates have increasingly leaned toward adopting this Continental concept.

I must preface the argument from precedent with a reference to what has been said already in the first Lecture about early forms of liability, and especially about [101] the appeals. It was there shown that the appeals de pace et plagis and of mayhem became the action of trespass, and that those appeals and the early actions of trespass were always, so far as appears, for intentional wrongs. /1/

I need to start the discussion on precedent by referring to what was mentioned earlier in the first Lecture about early forms of liability, particularly regarding [101] the appeals. It was demonstrated that the appeals de pace et plagis and of mayhem evolved into the action of trespass, and that these appeals, along with the early actions of trespass, were consistently, as far as we can tell, for intentional wrongs. /1/

The contra pacem in the writ of trespass was no doubt inserted to lay a foundation for the king's writ; but there seems to be no reason to attribute a similar purpose to vi et armis, or cum vi sua, as it was often put. Glanvill says that wounds are within the sheriff's jurisdiction, unless the appellor adds a charge of breach of the king's peace. /2/ Yet the wounds are given vi et armis as much in the one case as in the other. Bracton says that the lesser wrongs described by him belong to the king's jurisdiction, "because they are sometimes against the peace of our lord the king," /3/ while, as has been observed, they were supposed to be always committed intentionally. It might even perhaps be inferred that the allegation contra pacem was originally material, and it will be remembered that trespasses formerly involved the liability to pay a fine to the king. /4/

The "contra pacem" in the writ of trespass was definitely included to provide a basis for the king's writ; however, there doesn’t seem to be a reason to assign the same purpose to "vi et armis," or "cum vi sua," as it was often stated. Glanvill mentions that wounds fall under the sheriff's jurisdiction, unless the person bringing the claim adds a charge of breaching the king's peace. Yet, the wounds are inflicted "vi et armis" in both cases. Bracton states that the lesser wrongs he talks about are under the king's jurisdiction, "because they are sometimes against the peace of our lord the king," while, as noted, they were believed to be intentionally committed at all times. It might also be suggested that the allegation of "contra pacem" was initially significant, and it's worth recalling that trespasses used to carry the obligation to pay a fine to the king.

If it be true that trespass was originally confined to intentional wrongs, it is hardly necessary to consider the argument drawn from the scope of the general issue. In form it was a mitigation of the strict denial de verbo in verbum of the ancient procedure, to which the inquest given by the king's writ was unknown. /5/ The strict form seems to have lasted in England some time after the trial of the issue by recognition was introduced. /6/ When [102] a recognition was granted, the inquest was, of course, only competent to speak to the facts, as has been said above. /1/ When the general issue was introduced, trespass was still confined to intentional wrongs.

If it's true that trespass was originally limited to intentional wrongs, it’s not really necessary to think about the argument based on the general issue. Formally, it was a relaxation of the strict denial word-for-word from the old procedure, which the inquest given by the king's writ didn't know about. The strict form seemed to persist in England for a while after the trial of the issue by recognition was introduced. When [102] a recognition was granted, the inquest could only speak to the facts, as mentioned above. When the general issue was introduced, trespass was still limited to intentional wrongs.

We may now take up the authorities. It will be remembered that the earlier precedents are of a date when the assize and jurata had not given place to the modern jury. These bodies spoke from their own knowledge to an issue defined by the writ, or to certain familiar questions of fact arising in the trial of a cause, but did not hear the whole case upon evidence adduced. Their function was more limited than that which has been gained by the jury, and it naturally happened that, when they had declared what the defendant had done, the judges laid down the standard by which those acts were to be measured without their assistance. Hence the question in the Year Books is not a loose or general inquiry of the jury whether they think the alleged trespasser was negligent on such facts as they may find, but a well-defined issue of law, to be determined by the court, whether certain acts set forth upon the record are a ground of liability. It is possible that the judges may have dealt pretty strictly with defendants, and it is quite easy to pass from the premise that defendants have been held trespassers for a variety of acts, without mention of neglect, to the conclusion that any act by which another was damaged will make the actor chargeable. But a more exact scrutiny of the early books will show that liability in general, then as later, was [103] founded on the opinion of the tribunal that the defendant ought to have acted otherwise, or, in other words, that he was to blame.

We can now discuss the authorities. It’s important to remember that the earlier precedents come from a time when the assize and jurata hadn’t yet been replaced by the modern jury. These groups relied on their own knowledge regarding an issue defined by the writ, or on certain familiar factual questions that arose during the trial, but they didn’t hear the entire case based on the evidence presented. Their role was more limited than that of today’s jury, and it naturally happened that after they declared what the defendant had done, the judges established the standard by which those actions would be evaluated, without their input. Therefore, the question in the Year Books isn’t a vague or general inquiry of the jury about whether they think the alleged trespasser was negligent based on the facts they might find, but a clearly defined legal issue to be resolved by the court, determining whether certain actions listed in the record constitute a valid reason for liability. It’s possible that the judges may have been quite strict with defendants, and it’s easy to go from the idea that defendants were considered trespassers for various actions, without mentioning negligence, to the conclusion that any action leading to harm for another will make the actor accountable. However, a closer examination of the early texts reveals that liability, both then and now, was [103] based on the tribunal’s belief that the defendant should have acted differently, or in other words, that they were at fault.

Returning first to the case of the thorns in the Year Book, /1/ it will be seen that the falling of the thorns into the plaintiff's close, although a result not wished by the defendant, was in no other sense against his will. When he cut the thorns, he did an act which obviously and necessarily would have that consequence, and he must be taken to have foreseen and not to have prevented it. Choke, C. J. says, "As to what was said about their falling in, ipso invito, that is no plea, but he ought to show that he could not do it in any other way, or that he did all in his power to keep them out"; and both the judges put the unlawfulness of the entry upon the plaintiff's land as a consequence of the unlawfulness of dropping the thorns there. Choke admits that, if the thorns or a tree had been blown over upon the plaintiff's land, the defendant might have entered to get them. Chief Justice Crew says of this case, in Millen v. Fawdry, /2/ that the opinion was that "trespass lies, because he did not plead that he did his best endeavor to hinder their falling there; yet this was a hard case." The statements of law by counsel in argument may be left on one side, although Brian is quoted and mistaken for one of the judges by Sir William Blackstone, in Scott v. Shepherd.

Returning to the case regarding the thorns in the Year Book, /1/ it becomes clear that the thorns falling into the plaintiff's property, while not intended by the defendant, was not against his will in any other way. When he cut the thorns, he took an action that clearly and inevitably led to that result, and he should have foreseen it and done something to prevent it. Choke, C. J. states, "Regarding their falling in against his will, that is not a valid argument; he needs to show that he couldn't have done it any other way or that he did everything he could to keep them out." Both judges identified the illegality of the thorns entering the plaintiff's land as a result of their unlawful dropping there. Choke acknowledges that if the thorns or a tree had been blown onto the plaintiff's land, the defendant would have been allowed to go in and retrieve them. Chief Justice Crew mentions this case in Millen v. Fawdry, /2/ stating that the opinion was "trespass lies, because he did not plead that he did his best to prevent their falling there; yet this was a tough case." The legal arguments presented by counsel can be set aside, although Brian is referenced and incorrectly identified as one of the judges by Sir William Blackstone in Scott v. Shepherd.

The principal authorities are the shooting cases, and, as shooting is an extra-hazardous act, it would not be surprising if it should be held that men do it at their peril in public places. The liability has been put on the general ground of fault, however, wherever the line of necessary [104] precaution may be drawn. In Weaver v. Ward, /1/ the defendant set up that the plaintiff and he were skirmishing in a trainband, and that when discharging his piece he wounded the plaintiff by accident and misfortune, and against his own will. On demurrer, the court says that "no man shall be excused of a trespass,... except it may be judged utterly without his fault. As if a man by force take my hand and strike you, or if here the defendant had said, that the plaintiff ran cross his piece when it was discharging, or had set forth the case with the circumstances so as it had appeared to the court that it had been inevitable, and that the defendant had committed no negligence to give occasion to the hurt." The later cases simply follow Weaver v. Ward.

The main focus is on shooting incidents, and since shooting is an extremely dangerous act, it wouldn’t be surprising if it were determined that people do it at their own risk in public spaces. Liability has generally been based on the idea of fault, no matter where the necessary line of precaution might be drawn. In Weaver v. Ward, /1/, the defendant claimed that he and the plaintiff were play fighting in a militia, and that while he was firing his weapon, he accidentally injured the plaintiff against his will. On appeal, the court stated that "no one should be excused from a trespass... unless it can be shown to be entirely without fault on their part. For example, if someone forcibly takes my hand and strikes you, or if the defendant had claimed that the plaintiff suddenly ran in front of his weapon while it was being fired, or had presented the situation with enough details to show the court that it was unavoidable and that the defendant had not been negligent in causing the injury." Subsequent cases simply follow the precedent set by Weaver v. Ward.

The quotations which were made above in favor of the strict doctrine from Sir T. Raymond, in Bessey v. Olliot, and from Sir William Blackstone, in Scott v. Shepherd, are both taken from dissenting opinions. In the latter case it is pretty clear that the majority of the court considered that to repel personal danger by instantaneously tossing away a squib thrown by another upon one's stall was not a trespass, although a new motion was thereby imparted to the squib, and the plaintiff's eye was put out in consequence. The last case cited above, in stating the arguments for absolute responsibility, was Leame v. Bray. /2/ The question under discussion was whether the action (for running down the plaintiff) should not have been case rather than trespass, the defendant founding his objection to trespass on the ground that the injury happened through his neglect, but was not done wilfully. There was therefore no question of absolute responsibility for one's acts [105] before the court, as negligence was admitted; and the language used is all directed simply to the proposition that the damage need not have been done intentionally.

The quotes mentioned earlier in support of the strict doctrine from Sir T. Raymond in Bessey v. Olliot and from Sir William Blackstone in Scott v. Shepherd are both from dissenting opinions. In the latter case, it’s pretty clear that the majority of the court believed that throwing away a squib tossed by someone else to avoid personal harm wasn’t considered a trespass, even though it caused a new motion to the squib and resulted in the plaintiff losing an eye. The last case mentioned, which argues for absolute responsibility, is Leame v. Bray. The discussion was about whether the case (for running down the plaintiff) should have been categorized as case instead of trespass, with the defendant arguing that the injury was due to neglect rather than intentional harm. Therefore, there was no issue of absolute responsibility for one’s actions before the court, since negligence was acknowledged; and the language used is solely focused on the idea that the damage didn’t have to be intentional.

In Wakeman v. Robinson, /1/another runaway case, there was evidence that the defendant pulled the wrong rein, and that he ought to have kept a straight course. The jury were instructed that, if the injury was occasioned by an immediate act of the defendant, it was immaterial whether the act was wilful or accidental. On motion for a new trial, Dallas, C. J. said, "If the accident happened entirely without default on the part of the defendant, or blame imputable to him, the action does not lie ....The accident was clearly occasioned by the default of the defendant. The weight of evidence was all that way. I am now called upon to grant a new trial, contrary to the justice of the case, upon the ground, that the jury were not called on to consider whether the accident was unavoidable, or occasioned by the fault of the defendant. There can be no doubt that the learned judge who presided would have taken the opinion of the jury on that ground, if he had been requested so to do." This language may have been inapposite under the defendant's plea (the general issue), but the pleadings were not adverted to, and the doctrine is believed to be sound.

In Wakeman v. Robinson, /1/ another runaway case, there was evidence that the defendant pulled the wrong rein and should have kept a straight course. The jury was told that if the injury was caused by the defendant's direct actions, it didn’t matter whether those actions were intentional or accidental. During a motion for a new trial, Chief Justice Dallas said, "If the accident occurred completely without any fault on the part of the defendant, or any blame on him, the case doesn’t hold .... The accident was clearly caused by the defendant’s fault. All the evidence pointed that way. Now, I am being asked to grant a new trial, which goes against the justice of the case, based on the argument that the jury was not required to consider whether the accident was unavoidable or caused by the defendant's fault. There’s no doubt that the learned judge who presided would have taken the jury's opinion on that point if he had been asked." This wording may not have been appropriate under the defendant's plea (the general issue), but the pleadings weren’t mentioned, and the doctrine is considered to be valid.

In America there have been several decisions to the point. In Brown v. Kendall, /2/ Chief Justice Shaw settled the question for Massachusetts. That was trespass for assault and battery, and it appeared that the defendant, while trying to separate two fighting dogs, had raised his stick over his shoulder in the act of striking, and had accidentally hit the plaintiff in the eye, inflicting upon him a [106] severe injury. The case was stronger for the plaintiff than if the defendant had been acting in self-defence; but the court held that, although the defendant was bound by no duty to separate the dogs, yet, if he was doing a lawful act, he was not liable unless he was wanting in the care which men of ordinary prudence would use under the circumstances, and that the burden was on the plaintiff to prove the want of such care.

In America, there have been several notable decisions on this matter. In Brown v. Kendall, /2/ Chief Justice Shaw addressed the issue for Massachusetts. This case involved trespass for assault and battery, where the defendant, while trying to break up two fighting dogs, had raised his stick over his shoulder to strike but accidentally hit the plaintiff in the eye, causing him a [106] severe injury. The case was stronger for the plaintiff than if the defendant had been acting in self-defense; however, the court found that although the defendant wasn’t required to separate the dogs, he wasn’t liable unless he lacked the care that a reasonably prudent person would use in similar circumstances, and it was the plaintiff's responsibility to prove that such care was lacking.

In such a matter no authority is more deserving of respect than that of Chief Justice Shaw, for the strength of that great judge lay in an accurate appreciation of the requirements of the community whose officer he was. Some, indeed many, English judges could be named who have surpassed him in accurate technical knowledge, but few have lived who were his equals in their understanding of the grounds of public policy to which all laws must ultimately be referred. It was this which made him, in the language of the late Judge Curtis, the greatest magistrate which this country has produced.

In this matter, no authority is more deserving of respect than Chief Justice Shaw, because his strength came from a deep understanding of the needs of the community he served. While many English judges may have had better technical expertise, few have matched his insight into the principles of public policy that all laws must ultimately align with. This understanding is what led the late Judge Curtis to call him the greatest magistrate this country has ever produced.

Brown v. Kendall has been followed in Connecticut, /1/ in a case where a man fired a pistol, in lawful self-defence as he alleged, and hit a bystander. The court was strongly of opinion that the defendant was not answerable on the general principles of trespass, unless there was a failure to use such care as was practicable under the circumstances. The foundation of liability in trespass as well as case was said to be negligence. The Supreme Court of the United States has given the sanction of its approval to the same doctrine. /2/ The language of Harvey v. Dunlop /3/ has been [107] quoted, and there is a case in Vermont which tends in the same direction. /1/

Brown v. Kendall has been referenced in Connecticut, /1/ in a case where a man fired a gun, claiming it was in lawful self-defense, and hit an innocent bystander. The court strongly believed that the defendant shouldn’t be held responsible under general trespass principles unless he failed to exercise reasonable care given the situation. The basis of liability in both trespass and negligence cases was stated to be negligence. The Supreme Court of the United States has endorsed the same principle. /2/ The language from Harvey v. Dunlop /3/ has been [107] quoted, and there’s a case in Vermont that supports this viewpoint. /1/

Supposing it now to be conceded that the general notion upon which liability to an action is founded is fault or blameworthiness in some sense, the question arises, whether it is so in the sense of personal moral shortcoming, as would practically result from Austin's teaching. The language of Rede, J., which has been quoted from the Year Book, gives a sufficient answer. "In trespass the intent" (we may say more broadly, the defendant's state of mind) "cannot be construed." Suppose that a defendant were allowed to testify that, before acting, he considered carefully what would be the conduct of a prudent man under the circumstances, and, having formed the best judgment he could, acted accordingly. If the story was believed, it would be conclusive against the defendant's negligence judged by a moral standard which would take his personal characteristics into account. But supposing any such evidence to have got before the jury, it is very clear that the court would say, Gentlemen, the question is not whether the defendant thought his conduct was that of a prudent man, but whether you think it was. /2/

Assuming it's agreed that liability in a lawsuit is based on fault or blame in some way, the question arises whether this means personal moral failure, as Austin suggested. The words of Rede, J., quoted from the Year Book, provide a clear answer. "In trespass, the intent" (or more generally, the defendant's mindset) "cannot be interpreted." Imagine if a defendant could testify that, before taking action, he carefully considered what a reasonable person would do in the same situation and acted accordingly based on his best judgment. If that story was believed, it would absolve the defendant of negligence according to a moral standard that considered his personal traits. However, if such evidence were presented to the jury, it's evident that the court would state, "Gentlemen, the question is not whether the defendant believed his actions were prudent, but whether you believe they were." /2/

Some middle point must be found between the horns of this dilemma.

A middle ground has to be found between the two extremes of this dilemma.

[108 The standards of the law are standards of general application. The law takes no account of the infinite varieties of temperament, intellect, and education which make the internal character of a given act so different in different men. It does not attempt to see men as God sees them, for more than one sufficient reason. In the first place, the impossibility of nicely measuring a man's powers and limitations is far clearer than that of ascertaining his knowledge of law, which has been thought to account for what is called the presumption that every man knows the law. But a more satisfactory explanation is, that, when men live in society, a certain average of conduct, a sacrifice of individual peculiarities going beyond a certain point, is necessary to the general welfare. If, for instance, a man is born hasty and awkward, is always having accidents and hurting himself or his neighbors, no doubt his congenital defects will be allowed for in the courts of Heaven, but his slips are no less troublesome to his neighbors than if they sprang from guilty neglect. His neighbors accordingly require him, at his proper peril, to come up to their standard, and the courts which they establish decline to take his personal equation into account.

[108 The standards of the law apply to everyone. The law doesn't consider the endless variety of personalities, intelligence, and education that make each person's character different when they perform the same act. It doesn't try to see people as God sees them, for several valid reasons. First, it's much harder to accurately measure a person's abilities and limitations than to determine their understanding of the law, which is why there's a common belief that everyone knows the law. But a better explanation is that when people live in society, a certain average level of behavior is necessary for the common good, which requires some sacrifice of individual quirks. For example, if someone is naturally impulsive and clumsy and frequently causes accidents or injuries, the courts of Heaven might take into account his inherent flaws, but his actions are still just as problematic for his neighbors as if they were the result of willful negligence. His neighbors thus expect him, at his own risk, to meet their standards, and the courts they create choose not to consider his personal circumstances.

The rule that the law does, in general, determine liability by blameworthiness, is subject to the limitation that minute differences of character are not allowed for. The law considers, in other words, what would be blameworthy in the average man, the man of ordinary intelligence and prudence, and determines liability by that. If we fall below the level in those gifts, it is our misfortune; so much as that we must have at our peril, for the reasons just given. But he who is intelligent and prudent does not act at his peril, in theory of law. On the contrary, it is [109] only when he fails to exercise the foresight of which he is capable, or exercises it with evil intent, that he is answerable for the consequences.

The general principle is that the law determines liability based on blameworthiness, but this is limited in that it doesn't account for small differences in character. In other words, the law considers what would be considered blameworthy in an average person—someone of ordinary intelligence and caution—and assesses liability accordingly. If we fall short of these qualities, it is our misfortune; we must bear the consequences for that reason. However, someone who is intelligent and prudent doesn't act recklessly, according to legal theory. Instead, he is only held accountable when he fails to exercise the foresight he is capable of or when he acts with malicious intent.

There are exceptions to the principle that every man is presumed to possess ordinary capacity to avoid harm to his neighbors, which illustrate the rule, and also the moral basis of liability in general. When a man has a distinct defect of such a nature that all can recognize it as making certain precautions impossible, he will not be held answerable for not taking them. A blind man is not required to see at his peril; and although he is, no doubt, bound to consider his infirmity in regulating his actions, yet if he properly finds himself in a certain situation, the neglect of precautions requiring eyesight would not prevent his recovering for an injury to himself, and, it may be presumed, would not make him liable for injuring another. So it is held that, in cases where he is the plaintiff, an infant of very tender years is only bound to take the precautions of which an infant is capable; the same principle may be cautiously applied where he is defendant. /1/ Insanity is a more difficult matter to deal with, and no general rule can be laid down about it. There is no doubt that in many cases a man may be insane, and yet perfectly capable of taking the precautions, and of being influenced by the motives, which the circumstances demand. But if insanity of a pronounced type exists, manifestly incapacitating the sufferer from complying with the rule which he has broken, good sense would require it to be admitted as an excuse.

There are exceptions to the idea that everyone is expected to have the common sense to avoid harming others, which both highlight the standard and the moral reasoning behind liability in general. When someone has a clear disability that everyone can see makes certain precautions impossible, they won't be held responsible for not taking those precautions. A blind person isn't required to see at their own risk; while they do need to consider their disability when making decisions, if they find themselves in a particular situation, not taking precautions that require sight won’t stop them from claiming damages for an injury and likely won't make them liable for injuring someone else. Similarly, it’s understood that when very young children are plaintiffs, they’re only expected to take precautions that are reasonable for a child their age; this concept can also be cautiously applied when they are defendants. Insanity is trickier to handle, and no clear rules can be established for it. It's clear that in many cases, a person may be insane and still be capable of taking the precautions that the situation calls for. However, if someone has a severe mental disorder that clearly prevents them from acting according to the rule they broke, it would make sense to accept that as an excuse.

Taking the qualification last established in connection with the general proposition previously laid down, it will [110] now be assumed that, on the one hand, the law presumes or requires a man to possess ordinary capacity to avoid harming his neighbors, unless a clear and manifest incapacity be shown; but that, on the other, it does not in general hold him liable for unintentional injury, unless, possessing such capacity, he might and ought to have foreseen the danger, or, in other words, unless a man of ordinary intelligence and forethought would have been to blame for acting as he did. The next question is, whether this vague test is all that the law has to say upon the matter, and the same question in another form, by whom this test is to be applied.

Taking the qualification just established in connection with the general principle previously discussed, it will now be assumed that, on one hand, the law expects a person to have the basic ability to avoid harming others, unless a clear and obvious inability is demonstrated; but, on the other hand, it generally does not hold him responsible for unintentional harm, unless he could and should have foreseen the danger, or, in other words, unless a person of average intelligence and foresight would have been at fault for acting as he did. The next question is whether this vague standard is all the law has to say on the matter, and the same question in another form: by whom this standard is to be applied.

Notwithstanding the fact that the grounds of legal liability are moral to the extent above explained, it must be borne in mind that law only works within the sphere of the senses. If the external phenomena, the manifest acts and omissions, are such as it requires, it is wholly indifferent to the internal phenomena of conscience. A man may have as bad a heart as he chooses, if his conduct is within the rules. In other words, the standards of the law are external standards, and, however much it may take moral considerations into account, it does so only for the purpose of drawing a line between such bodily motions and rests as it permits, and such as it does not. What the law really forbids, and the only thing it forbids, is the act on the wrong side of the line, be that act blameworthy or otherwise.

Even though the basis of legal liability is moral to the extent explained above, it’s important to remember that the law operates only within the realm of observable actions. If the external behaviors, the obvious acts and omissions, meet its requirements, it doesn’t concern itself with the internal workings of one's conscience. A person may have a terrible character, but as long as their behavior follows the rules, it doesn’t matter. In other words, the law sets external standards, and although it may consider moral issues, it does so solely to distinguish between actions it allows and those it doesn’t. What the law actually prohibits, and the only thing it prohibits, is the action that crosses the line, regardless of whether that action is morally wrong or not.

Again, any legal standard must, in theory, be one which would apply to all men, not specially excepted, under the same circumstances. It is not intended that the public force should fall upon an individual accidentally, or at the whim of any body of men. The standard, that is, [111] must be fixed. In practice, no doubt, one man may have to pay and another may escape, according to the different feelings of different juries. But this merely shows that the law does not perfectly accomplish its ends. The theory or intention of the law is not that the feeling of approbation or blame which a particular twelve may entertain should be the criterion. They are supposed to leave their idiosyncrasies on one side, and to represent the feeling of the community. The ideal average prudent man, whose equivalent the jury is taken to be in many cases, and whose culpability or innocence is the supposed test, is a constant, and his conduct under given circumstances is theoretically always the same.

Again, any legal standard should, in theory, be one that applies to everyone, without exception, under the same circumstances. The public force shouldn't target an individual randomly or based on the discretion of any group. The standard needs to be consistent. In reality, one person might be penalized while another might escape based on the differing perspectives of various juries. But this just highlights that the law doesn’t always achieve its goals. The theory or intention of the law is not for the opinions of a specific set of twelve individuals to be the deciding factor. They are expected to set aside their personal biases and reflect the views of the community. The ideal average reasonable person, which the jury is often considered to represent, and whose guilt or innocence serves as the standard, is a constant, and their behavior in specific situations is theoretically always the same.

Finally, any legal standard must, in theory, be capable of being known. When a man has to pay damages, he is supposed to have broken the law, and he is further supposed to have known what the law was.

Finally, any legal standard should, in theory, be understandable. When someone has to pay damages, they're expected to have violated the law, and they're also expected to have known what the law was.

If, now, the ordinary liabilities in tort arise from failure to comply with fixed and uniform standards of external conduct, which every man is presumed and required to know, it is obvious that it ought to be possible, sooner or later, to formulate these standards at least to some extent, and that to do so must at last be the business of the court. It is equally clear that the featureless generality, that the defendant was bound to use such care as a prudent man would do under the circumstances, ought to be continually giving place to the specific one, that he was bound to use this or that precaution under these or those circumstances. The standard which the defendant was bound to come up to was a standard of specific acts or omissions, with reference to the specific circumstances in which he found himself. If in the whole department of [112] unintentional wrongs the courts arrived at no further utterance than the question of negligence, and left every case, without rudder or compass, to the jury, they would simply confess their inability to state a very large part of the law which they required the defendant to know, and would assert, by implication, that nothing could be learned by experience. But neither courts nor legislatures have ever stopped at that point.

If the typical liabilities in tort come from not following consistent and established standards of behavior that everyone is expected to know, it's clear that we should eventually be able to define these standards to some degree, and that it should ultimately be the court's job to do so. It's also obvious that the vague general idea that the defendant was required to act as a reasonable person would in those situations should be replaced by the more specific notion that they were obligated to take certain precautions depending on the circumstances. The standard the defendant needed to meet was based on specific actions or inactions related to the particular situation they were in. If the courts handling cases of [112] unintentional wrongs only focused on the issue of negligence and left every case without clear guidance for the jury, they would simply admit they couldn't articulate a significant part of the law the defendant should be aware of and would imply that no lessons could be learned from experience. However, neither courts nor legislatures have ever settled for that.

From the time of Alfred to the present day, statutes and decisions have busied themselves with defining the precautions to be taken in certain familiar cases; that is, with substituting for the vague test of the care exercised by a prudent man, a precise one of specific acts or omissions. The fundamental thought is still the same, that the way prescribed is that in which prudent men are in the habit of acting, or else is one laid down for cases where prudent men might otherwise be in doubt.

From the time of Alfred to today, laws and rulings have been focused on defining the precautions to take in certain familiar situations; that is, replacing the unclear standard of care used by a reasonable person with a clear set of specific actions or inactions. The core idea remains the same: the prescribed method is what reasonable people typically do, or it’s something established for situations where reasonable people might otherwise be uncertain.

It will be observed that the existence of the external tests of liability which will be mentioned, while it illustrates the tendency of the law of tort to become more and more concrete by judicial decision and by statute, does not interfere with the general doctrine maintained as to the grounds of liability. The argument of this Lecture, although opposed to the doctrine that a man acts or exerts force at his peril, is by no means opposed to the doctrine that he does certain particular acts at his peril. It is the coarseness, not the nature, of the standard which is objected to. If, when the question of the defendant's negligence is left to a jury, negligence does not mean the actual state of the defendant's mind, but a failure to act as a prudent man of average intelligence would have done, he is required to conform to an objective standard at his [113] peril, even in that case. When a more exact and specific rule has been arrived at, he must obey that rule at his peril to the same extent. But, further, if the law is wholly a standard of external conduct, a man must always comply with that standard at his peril.

It can be observed that the existence of the external tests for liability, which will be discussed, shows the trend of tort law becoming more concrete through court decisions and laws, but it doesn't disrupt the overall principles regarding liability. The argument of this lecture, despite being contrary to the idea that a person acts or takes action at their own risk, doesn't contradict the idea that a person does specific actions at their own risk. The issue lies with the roughness of the standard, not its essence. When determining the defendant's negligence is left to a jury, negligence does not refer to the actual mindset of the defendant, but rather to a failure to act like a reasonable person of average intelligence would. The defendant must meet an objective standard at their own risk, even in that situation. When a more precise and detailed rule is established, they must follow that rule at their risk to the same degree. Moreover, if the law is entirely about external behavior, a person must always adhere to that standard at their own risk.

Some examples of the process of specification will be useful. In LL. Alfred, 36, /1/ providing for the case of a man's staking himself on a spear carried by another, we read, "Let this (liability) be if the point be three fingers higher than the hindmost part of the shaft; if they be both on a level,... be that without danger."

Some examples of the process of specification will be helpful. In LL. Alfred, 36, /1/ addressing the situation where a man is betting his life on a spear held by someone else, it says, "This (liability) applies if the point is three fingers higher than the back part of the shaft; if they are both level,... it should be without danger."

The rule of the road and the sailing rules adopted by Congress from England are modern examples of such statutes. By the former rule, the question has been narrowed from the vague one, Was the party negligent? to the precise one, Was he on the right or left of the road? To avoid a possible misconception, it may be observed that, of course, this question does not necessarily and under all circumstances decide that of liability; a plaintiff may have been on the wrong side of the road, as he may have been negligent, and yet the conduct of the defendant may have been unjustifiable, and a ground of liability. /2/ So, no doubt, a defendant could justify or excuse being on the wrong side, under some circumstances. The difference between alleging that a defendant was on the wrong side of the road, and that he was negligent, is the difference between an allegation of facts requiring to be excused by a counter allegation of further facts to prevent their being a ground of liability, and an allegation which involves a conclusion of law, and denies in advance the existence of an [114] excuse. Whether the former allegation ought not to be enough, and whether the establishment of the fact ought not to shift the burden of proof, are questions which belong to the theory of pleading and evidence, and could be answered either way consistently with analogy. I should have no difficulty in saying that the allegation of facts which are ordinarily a ground of liability, and which would be so unless excused, ought to be sufficient. But the forms of the law, especially the forms of pleading, do not change with every change of its substance, and a prudent lawyer would use the broader and safer phrase.

The rules of the road and the sailing regulations adopted by Congress from England are current examples of such laws. With the former rule, the question has shifted from the vague one, "Was the person negligent?" to the specific one, "Were they on the right or left side of the road?" To avoid any misunderstanding, it’s important to note that this question doesn’t automatically determine liability; a plaintiff could be on the wrong side of the road or negligent, yet the defendant’s actions might still be unjustifiable and a reason for liability. So, surely, a defendant could justify or excuse being on the wrong side in certain situations. The difference between claiming that a defendant was on the wrong side of the road and that they were negligent is the difference between stating facts that need to be justified with further facts to avoid being liable and a claim that includes a legal conclusion, which preemptively denies any excuse. Whether the first claim should be enough and whether proving that fact should shift the burden of proof are questions related to legal theory and evidence that could be answered either way consistently. I’d have no trouble saying that the assertion of facts that typically lead to liability, which would apply unless justified, should be adequate. However, the legal forms, particularly the forms of pleadings, don’t change with every shift in substance, and a wise lawyer would choose the broader, safer term.

The same course of specification which has been illustrated from the statute-book ought also to be taking place in the growth of judicial decisions. That this should happen is in accordance with the past history of the law. It has been suggested already that in the days of the assize and jurata the court decided whether the facts constituted a ground of liability in all ordinary cases. A question of negligence might, no doubt, have gone to the jury. Common sense and common knowledge are as often sufficient to determine whether proper care has been taken of an animal, as they are to say whether A or B owns it. The cases which first arose were not of a kind to suggest analysis, and negligence was used as a proximately simple element for a long time before the need or possibility of analysis was felt. Still, when an issue of this sort is found, the dispute is rather what the acts or omissions of the defendant were than on the standard of conduct. /1/ The [115] distinction between the functions of court and jury does not come in question until the parties differ as to the standard of conduct. Negligence, like ownership, is a complex conception. Just as the latter imports the existence of certain facts, and also the consequence (protection against all the world) which the law attaches to those facts; the former imports the existence of certain facts (conduct) and also the consequence (liability) which the law attaches to those facts. In most cases the question is upon the facts, and it is only occasionally that one arises on the consequence.

The same process of specification illustrated from the law books should also be happening in the development of judicial decisions. This aligns with the historical evolution of the law. It has already been pointed out that during the days of the assize and juries, the court determined whether the facts established a basis for liability in most cases. A question of negligence could have indeed gone to the jury. Common sense and common knowledge are often enough to decide whether proper care has been taken of an animal, just as they can determine whether A or B owns it. The initial cases that emerged weren't suited for detailed analysis, and negligence served as a relatively simple concept for a long time before the need or possibility for deeper analysis was recognized. Still, when such an issue arises, the dispute tends to be more about the actions or inactions of the defendant rather than the standard of conduct. The [115] distinction between the roles of the court and jury only becomes relevant when the parties disagree on the standard of conduct. Negligence, like ownership, is a complex idea. Just as ownership involves certain facts and the legal consequence (protection against everyone) tied to those facts, negligence involves specific facts (behavior) and the legal consequence (liability) associated with those facts. In most cases, the question revolves around the facts, and only occasionally does it focus on the consequence.

It will have been noticed how the judges pass on the defendant's acts (on grounds of fault and public policy) in the case of the thorns, and that in Weaver v. Ward /1/it is said that the facts constituting an excuse, and showing that the defendant was free from negligence, should have been spread upon the record, in order that the court might judge. A similar requirement was laid down with regard to the defence of probable cause in an action for malicious prosecution. /2/ And to this day the question of probable cause is always passed on by the court. Later evidence will be found in what follows.

It will have been noticed how the judges assess the defendant's actions (based on fault and public policy) in the thorns case, and that in Weaver v. Ward /1/ it is stated that the facts that constitute a valid excuse and show that the defendant was not negligent should have been included in the record so that the court could make a judgment. A similar requirement was established regarding the defense of probable cause in a malicious prosecution case. /2/ Even today, the issue of probable cause is always evaluated by the court. Further evidence will be presented in what follows.

There is, however, an important consideration, which has not yet been adverted to. It is undoubtedly possible that those who have the making of the law should deem it wise to put the mark higher in some cases than the point established by common practice at which blameworthiness begins. For instance, in Morris v. Platt, /2/ the court, while declaring in the strongest terms that, in general, [116] negligence is the foundation of liability for accidental trespasses, nevertheless hints that, if a decision of the point were necessary, it might hold a defendant to a stricter rule where the damage was caused by a pistol, in view of the danger to the public of the growing habit of carrying deadly weapons. Again, it might well seem that to enter a man's house for the purpose of carrying a present, or inquiring after his health when he was ill, was a harmless and rather praiseworthy act, although crossing the owner's boundary was intentional. It is not supposed that an action would lie at the present day for such a cause, unless the defendant had been forbidden the house. Yet in the time of Henry VIII. it was said to be actionable if without license, "for then under that color my enemy might be in my house and kill me." /1/ There is a clear case where public policy establishes a standard of overt acts without regard to fault in any sense. In like manner, policy established exceptions to the general prohibition against entering another's premises, as in the instance put by Chief Justice Choke in the Year Book, of a tree being blown over upon them, or when the highway became impassable, or for the purpose of keeping the peace. /2/

There is an important consideration that hasn't been mentioned yet. It is certainly possible that lawmakers might decide it's wise to set the bar higher in some cases than the point established by common practice where blameworthiness starts. For example, in Morris v. Platt, /2/ the court, while strongly asserting that, in general, [116] negligence is the basis for liability in accidental trespasses, still suggests that if a decision were required, it might hold a defendant to a stricter standard if the damage was caused by a gun, considering the public danger posed by the increasing prevalence of carrying deadly weapons. Additionally, it might seem that entering someone's home to deliver a gift or check on their health when they were sick is a harmless and even commendable act, even though crossing the owner's boundary was intentional. It is not expected that a lawsuit could be filed today for such a reason unless the defendant had been specifically banned from entering the house. However, during the time of Henry VIII, it was said to be actionable if done without permission, "because then under that pretext my enemy might be in my house and kill me." /1/ This clearly illustrates a case where public policy sets a standard of overt acts without considering fault in any way. Similarly, policy established exceptions to the general rule against entering someone else's property, such as the example given by Chief Justice Choke in the Year Book about a tree falling on the property, or when the road became impassable, or for the purpose of maintaining peace. /2/

Another example may perhaps be found in the shape which has been given in modern times to the liability for animals, and in the derivative principle of Rylands v. Fletcher, /3/ that when a person brings on his lands, and collects and keeps there, anything likely to do mischief if it escapes, he must keep it in at his peril; and, if he does not do so, is prima facie answerable for all the [117] damage which is the natural consequence of its escape. Cases of this sort do not stand on the notion that it is wrong to keep cattle, or to have a reservoir of water, as might have been thought with more plausibility when fierce and useless animals only were in question. /1/ It may even be very much for the public good that the dangerous accumulation should be made (a consideration which might influence the decision in some instances, and differently in different jurisdictions); but as there is a limit to the nicety of inquiry which is possible in a trial, it may be considered that the safest way to secure care is to throw the risk upon the person who decides what precautions shall be taken. The liability for trespasses of cattle seems to lie on the boundary line between rules based on policy irrespective of fault, and requirements intended to formulate the conduct of a prudent man.

Another example can be seen in how liability for animals has evolved in modern times, as established by the principle from Rylands v. Fletcher, /3/ which states that when someone brings onto their property something that could cause harm if it escapes, they must keep it secured; if they fail to do so, they’re generally responsible for all the [117] damage that results from its escape. Cases like these don’t rely on the idea that it’s wrong to own livestock or have a water reservoir, which might have seemed more reasonable when only aggressive and useless animals were considered. /1/ In fact, it could be beneficial for the public good to have such potentially dangerous things in place (a point that could impact decisions in some cases and vary across jurisdictions); however, since there is a limit to how detailed inquiries can be during a trial, it may be viewed as safer to place the responsibility on the individual who chooses what safety measures to implement. The liability for livestock trespassing seems to sit at the intersection of rules driven by policy, regardless of fault, and guidelines meant to outline the behavior of a sensible person.

It has been shown in the first Lecture how this liability for cattle arose in the early law, and how far the influence of early notions might be traced in the law of today, Subject to what is there said, it is evident that the early discussions turn on the general consideration whether the owner is or is not to blame. /2/ But they do not stop there: they go on to take practical distinctions, based on common experience. Thus, when the defendant chased sheep out of his land with a dog, and as soon as the sheep were out called in his dog, but the dog pursued them into adjoining land, the chasing of the sheep beyond the defendant's line was held no trespass, because "the nature of a dog is such that he cannot be ruled suddenly." /3/

It was demonstrated in the first Lecture how the liability for cattle originated in early law and how the influence of those early ideas can still be traced in today's law. Based on what was discussed there, it’s clear that the early debates focus on whether the owner is at fault or not. However, they go further: they make practical distinctions grounded in common experience. For example, when the defendant drove sheep off his property with a dog and then called the dog back as soon as the sheep were out, but the dog chased them into neighboring land, it was ruled that chasing the sheep beyond the defendant's property was not a trespass because "the nature of a dog is such that he cannot be controlled suddenly."

[118] It was lawful in ploughing to turn the horses on adjoining land, and if while so turning the beasts took a mouthful of grass, or subverted the soil with the plough, against the will of the driver, he had a good justification, because the law will recognize that a man cannot at every instant govern his cattle as he will. /1/ So it was said that, if a man be driving cattle through a town, and one of them goes into another man's house, and he follows him, trespass does not lie for this. /2/ So it was said by Doderidge, J., in the same case, that if deer come into my land out of the forest, and I chase them with dogs, it is excuse enough for me to wind my horn to recall the dogs, because by this the warden of the forest has notice that a deer is being chased. /3/

[118] It was legal to turn the horses onto nearby land while plowing, and if, during the turn, the animals took a bite of grass or disturbed the soil with the plow against the driver's wishes, he had a valid reason, because the law understands that a person cannot control their livestock at all times. /1/ Similarly, it was stated that if someone is herding cattle through a town and one of them wanders into another person's house, following it does not count as trespassing. /2/ Doderidge, J., mentioned in the same case that if deer come onto my property from the forest and I chase them with dogs, it's reason enough for me to blow my horn to call the dogs back, as this informs the forest warden that a deer is being chased. /3/

The very case of Mason v. Keeling, /4/ which is referred to in the first Lecture for its echo of primitive notions, shows that the working rules of the law had long been founded on good sense. With regard to animals not then treated as property, which in the main were the wilder animals, the law was settled that, "if they are of a tame nature, there must be notice of the ill quality; and the law takes notice, that a dog is not of a fierce nature, but rather the contrary." /5/ If the animals "are such as are naturally [119] mischievous in their kind, he shall answer for hurt done by them, without any notice." /1/ The latter principle has been applied to the case of a bear, /2/ and amply accounts for the liability of the owner of such animals as horses and oxen in respect of trespasses upon land, although, as has been seen, it was at one time thought to stand upon his ownership. It is said to be the universal nature of cattle to stray, and, when straying in cultivated land, to do damage by trampling down and eating the crops, whereas a dog does no harm. It is also said to be usual and easy to restrain them. /3/ If, as has been suggested, the historical origin of the rule was different, it does not matter.

The case of Mason v. Keeling, /4/ mentioned in the first Lecture for its connection to basic ideas, illustrates that the fundamental principles of the law had long been based on common sense. Regarding animals that weren't considered property at that time, primarily wild ones, the law established that "if they are of a tame nature, there must be notice of their bad qualities; and the law recognizes that a dog is generally not fierce but rather the opposite." /5/ If the animals "are typically [119] mischievous by nature, the owner is responsible for any harm they cause, without any prior notice." /1/ This principle has been applied in cases involving bears, /2/ and it clearly explains the liability of owners of animals like horses and oxen for damages when they trespass on land, even though at one time it was believed that liability depended on ownership. It is said that cattle naturally wander, and when they stray into cultivated land, they can damage crops by trampling and eating them, whereas dogs typically do not cause harm. It is also said to be common and straightforward to keep them restrained. /3/ Even if, as suggested, the historical roots of the rule were different, it doesn’t change anything.

Following the same line of thought, the owner of cattle is not held absolutely answerable for all damage which they may do the person. According to Lord Holt in the alcove opinion, these animals, "which are not so familiar to mankind" as dogs, "the owner ought to confine, and take all reasonable caution that they do no mischief.... But... if the owner puts a horse or an ox to grass in his field, which is adjoining to the highway, and the horse or the ox breaks the hedge and runs into the highway, and kicks or gores some passenger, an action will not lie against the owner; otherwise, if he had notice that they had done such a thing before."

Following the same line of thought, the owner of cattle is not completely responsible for all the damage they may cause to a person. According to Lord Holt in the alcove opinion, these animals, "which are not as familiar to people" as dogs, "the owner should keep contained and take all reasonable precautions to ensure they don't cause harm.... But... if the owner lets a horse or an ox graze in his field next to the highway, and the horse or ox breaks through the fence and runs into the highway, causing injury to a passerby, the owner won't be liable; unless, of course, he had been warned that they had done something like this before."

[120] Perhaps the most striking authority for the position that the judge's duties are not at an end when the question of negligence is reached, is shown by the discussions concerning the law of bailment. Consider the judgment in Coggs v. Bernard, /1/ the treatises of Sir William Jones and Story, and the chapter of Kent upon the subject. They are so many attempts to state the duty of the bailee specifically, according to the nature of the bailment and of the object bailed. Those attempts, to be sure, were not successful, partly because they were attempts to engraft upon the native stock a branch of the Roman law which was too large to survive the process, but more especially because the distinctions attempted were purely qualitative, and were therefore useless when dealing with a jury. /2/ To instruct a jury that they must find the defendant guilty of gross negligence before he can be charged, is open to the reproach that for such a body the word "gross" is only a vituperative epithet. But it would not be so with a judge sitting in admiralty without a jury. The Roman law and the Supreme Court of the United States agree that the word means something. /3/ Successful or not, it is enough for the present argument that the attempt has been made.

[120] One of the most compelling arguments for the idea that a judge's responsibilities don’t end when negligence is decided is found in the discussions about bailment law. Take a look at the ruling in Coggs v. Bernard, /1/ along with the writings of Sir William Jones and Story, and the chapter by Kent on the topic. These are all efforts to clearly define the bailee's duty based on the type of bailment and the item involved. These efforts, of course, didn't fully succeed, partly because they tried to graft a significant branch of Roman law onto American law that was too complex to integrate, but especially because the distinctions they tried to make were solely qualitative, making them ineffective when dealing with a jury. /2/ Telling a jury that they must find the defendant guilty of gross negligence to hold them accountable is problematic, as the term "gross" can seem like just an insulting adjective to them. However, this wouldn’t apply to a judge in admiralty without a jury. Both Roman law and the Supreme Court of the United States agree that the term has an actual meaning. /3/ Whether they succeeded or not, the important thing for this argument is that this attempt was made.

The principles of substantive law which have been established by the courts are believed to have been somewhat obscured by having presented themselves oftenest in the form of rulings upon the sufficiency of evidence. When a judge rules that there is no evidence of negligence, he does something more than is embraced in an ordinary ruling that there is no evidence of a fact. He rules that [121] acts or omissions proved or in question do not constitute a ground of legal liability, and in this way the law is gradually enriching itself from daily life, as it should. Thus, in Crafton v. Metropolitan Railway Co., /1/ the plaintiff slipped on the defendant's stairs and was severely hurt. The cause of his slipping was that the brass nosing of the stairs had been worn smooth by travel over it, and a builder testified that in his opinion the staircase was unsafe by reason of this circumstance and the absence of a hand-rail. There was nothing to contradict this except that great numbers of persons had passed over the stairs and that no accident had happened there, and the plaintiff had a verdict. The court set the verdict aside, and ordered a nonsuit. The ruling was in form that there was no evidence of negligence to go to the jury; but this was obviously equivalent to saying, and did in fact mean, that the railroad company had done all that it was bound to do in maintaining such a staircase as was proved by the plaintiff. A hundred other equally concrete instances will be found in the text-books.

The principles of substantive law established by the courts seem to have been somewhat hidden because they are often presented mainly as rulings on the adequacy of evidence. When a judge declares that there is no evidence of negligence, he is doing more than simply stating that there is no evidence of a fact. He rules that the acts or omissions in question do not amount to legal liability, and through this process, the law is gradually evolving based on real-life situations, as it should. For example, in Crafton v. Metropolitan Railway Co., /1/ the plaintiff slipped on the defendant's stairs and was seriously injured. The reason for his slip was that the brass edging of the stairs had been worn smooth from use, and a builder testified that, in his opinion, the staircase was unsafe due to this condition and the lack of a handrail. The only evidence to counter this was that many people had used the stairs without incident, and the plaintiff won the case. However, the court overturned the verdict and ordered a nonsuit. The ruling was essentially that there was no evidence of negligence for the jury to consider; but this effectively meant that the railroad company had fulfilled its obligation to maintain a staircase as demonstrated by the plaintiff. Many other similarly specific examples can be found in the law books.

On the other hand, if the court should rule that certain acts or omissions coupled with damage were conclusive evidence of negligence unless explained, it would, in substance and in truth, rule that such acts or omissions were a ground of liability, /2/ or prevented a recovery, as the case might be. Thus it is said to be actionable negligence to let a house for a dwelling knowing it to be so infected with small-pox as to be dangerous to health, and concealing the knowledge. /3/ To explain the acts or omissions in such a [122] case would be to prove different conduct from that ruled upon, or to show that they were not, juridically speaking, the cause of the damage complained of. The ruling assumes, for the purposes of the ruling, that the facts in evidence are all the facts.

On the other hand, if the court decides that certain actions or failures to act, along with resulting damage, are clear evidence of negligence unless explained, it would effectively determine that these actions or failures are a basis for liability, or that they prevent recovery, depending on the situation. For example, it is considered actionable negligence to rent out a house for living purposes while knowing it is infected with smallpox to the point of being hazardous to health and hiding that information. To explain the actions or failures in such a case would mean proving different behavior than what was ruled on, or showing that they were not, legally speaking, the cause of the damage being complained about. The ruling assumes that, for the purposes of the decision, all the facts in evidence are the complete set of facts.

The cases which have raised difficulties needing explanation are those in which the court has ruled that there was prima facie evidence of negligence, or some evidence of negligence to go to the jury.

The cases that have created challenges requiring clarification are those where the court has determined that there was initial evidence of negligence, or some evidence of negligence that should be presented to the jury.

Many have noticed the confusion of thought implied in speaking of such cases as presenting mixed questions of law and fact. No doubt, as has been said above, the averment that the defendant has been guilty of negligence is a complex one: first, that he has done or omitted certain things; second, that his alleged conduct does not come up to the legal standard. And so long as the controversy is simply on the first half, the whole complex averment is plain matter for the jury without special instructions, just as a question of ownership would be where the only dispute was as to the fact upon which the legal conclusion was founded. /1/ But when a controversy arises on the second half, the question whether the court or the jury ought to judge of the defendant's conduct is wholly unaffected by the accident, whether there is or is not also a dispute as to what that conduct was. If there is such a dispute, it is entirely possible to give a series of hypothetical instructions adapted to every state of facts which it is open to the jury to find. If there is no such dispute, the court may still take their opinion as to the standard. The problem is [123] to explain the relative functions of court and jury with regard to the latter.

Many have noticed the confusion in discussing cases that involve mixed questions of law and fact. As mentioned earlier, claiming that the defendant was negligent is a complex issue: first, it involves whether he did or didn’t do certain things; second, it considers whether his actions meet the legal standard. As long as the dispute is focused only on the first part, the entire claim is straightforward for the jury to decide without needing special instructions, just like determining ownership would be if the only disagreement was about the facts that led to the legal conclusion. /1/ However, when a disagreement arises about the second part, whether the court or the jury should judge the defendant's conduct is completely independent of whether there’s also a dispute about what that conduct was. If there is such a dispute, it's entirely possible to give a series of hypothetical instructions that fit every possible scenario the jury could find. If there isn’t a dispute, the court can still seek their opinion on the standard. The challenge is [123] to clarify the respective roles of the court and the jury regarding the latter.

When a case arises in which the standard of conduct, pure and simple, is submitted to the jury, the explanation is plain. It is that the court, not entertaining any clear views of public policy applicable to the matter, derives the rule to be applied from daily experience, as it has been agreed that the great body of the law of tort has been derived. But the court further feels that it is not itself possessed of sufficient practical experience to lay down the rule intelligently. It conceives that twelve men taken from the practical part of the community can aid its judgment. /1/ Therefore it aids its conscience by taking the opinion of the jury.

When a case comes up where the standard of conduct is clearly presented to the jury, the reasoning is straightforward. The court, without any strong beliefs about the relevant public policy, bases the rule on everyday experiences, just like how most of tort law has developed. However, the court also feels that it doesn't have enough practical experience to set the rule effectively. It believes that twelve individuals from the practical side of the community can help guide its judgment. /1/ So, it seeks guidance for its decision by consulting the jury.

But supposing a state of facts often repeated in practice, is it to be imagined that the court is to go on leaving the standard to the jury forever? Is it not manifest, on the contrary, that if the jury is, on the whole, as fair a tribunal as it is represented to be, the lesson which can be got from that source will be learned? Either the court will find that the fair teaching of experience is that the conduct complained of usually is or is not blameworthy, and therefore, unless explained, is or is not a ground of liability; or it will find the jury oscillating to and fro, and will see the necessity of making up its mind for itself. There is no reason why any other such question should not be settled, as well as that of liability for stairs with smooth strips of brass upon their edges. The exceptions would mainly be found where the standard was rapidly changing, as, for instance, in some questions of medical treatment. /2/

But if we consider a situation that's often repeated in practice, can we really think that the court will keep leaving the standard up to the jury indefinitely? Isn't it clear that if the jury is generally as fair as it's said to be, the lessons learned from that source will eventually be understood? Either the court will determine that the fair insights gained from experience show whether the behavior in question is usually blameworthy or not, and therefore, unless clarified, whether it’s a basis for liability, or it will notice the jury fluctuating in their decisions and realize it needs to make a judgment on its own. There’s no reason why any other similar issue can’t be resolved as well as the question of liability for stairs with smooth brass strips on their edges. The exceptions would mostly be found where the standard is changing quickly, such as in some matters of medical treatment. /2/

[124] If this be the proper conclusion in plain cases, further consequences ensue. Facts do not often exactly repeat themselves in practice; but cases with comparatively small variations from each other do. A judge who has long sat at nisi prius ought gradually to acquire a fund of experience which enables him to represent the common sense of the community in ordinary instances far better than an average jury. He should be able to lead and to instruct them in detail, even where he thinks it desirable, on the whole, to take their opinion. Furthermore, the sphere in which he is able to rule without taking their opinion at all should be continually growing.

[124] If this is the right conclusion in straightforward cases, further implications follow. Facts rarely repeat themselves exactly in real life; however, cases with relatively minor differences do occur. A judge who has spent a lot of time in preliminary hearings should gradually build up a wealth of experience that allows him to reflect the common sense of the community in typical situations much better than a regular jury. He should be capable of guiding and educating them in detail, even when he believes it’s generally best to get their input. Additionally, the area where he can make decisions without seeking their opinions should keep expanding.

It has often been said, that negligence is pure matter of fact, or that, after the court has declared the evidence to be such that negligence may be inferred from it, the jury are always to decide whether the inference shall be drawn. /1/ But it is believed that the courts, when they lay down this broad proposition, are thinking of cases where the conduct to be passed upon is not proved directly, and the main or only question is what that conduct was, not what standard shall be applied to it after it is established.

It’s often said that negligence is simply a matter of fact, or that once the court has determined the evidence is sufficient to imply negligence, the jury decides if that implication should be made. /1/ However, it’s thought that when courts state this general principle, they are referring to cases where the behavior in question isn’t directly proven, and the primary or sole issue is what that behavior was, not what standard should be applied once it’s established.

Most cases which go to the jury on a ruling that there is evidence from which they may find negligence, do not go to them principally on account of a doubt as to the standard, but of a doubt as to the conduct. Take the case where the fact in proof is an event such as the dropping of a brick from a railway bridge over a highway upon the plaintiff, the fact must be inferred that the dropping was [125] due, not to a sudden operation of weather, but to a gradual falling out of repair which it was physically possible for the defendant to have prevented, before there can be any question as to the standard of conduct. /1/

Most cases that go to the jury based on a ruling that there is evidence for negligence typically don't go to them mainly because of a doubt about the standard but because of uncertainty regarding the behavior. For instance, consider a situation where a brick falls from a railway bridge onto the plaintiff. It's necessary to conclude that the brick's drop was not just due to sudden weather changes but rather because of a gradual decline in maintenance that the defendant could have physically prevented before any questions about the standard of conduct arise. /1/

So, in the case of a barrel falling from a warehouse window, it must be found that the defendant or his servants were in charge of it, before any question of standard can arise. /2/ It will be seen that in each of these well-known cases the court assumed a rule which would make the defendant liable if his conduct was such as the evidence tended to prove. When there is no question as to the conduct established by the evidence, as in the case of a collision between two trains belonging to the same company, the jury have, sometimes at least, been told in effect that, if they believed the evidence, the defendant was liable. /3/

So, in the case of a barrel falling from a warehouse window, it must be established that the defendant or their employees were responsible for it before any question of liability can come up. /2/ It's clear that in each of these well-known cases, the court assumed a rule that would hold the defendant accountable if their actions matched what the evidence suggested. When there's no dispute about the actions confirmed by the evidence, like in the case of a collision between two trains owned by the same company, the jury has sometimes been instructed that, if they believed the evidence, the defendant was liable. /3/

The principal argument that is urged in favor of the view that a more extended function belongs to the jury as matter of right, is the necessity of continually conforming our standards to experience. No doubt the general foundation of legal liability in blameworthiness, as determined by the existing average standards of the community, should always be kept in mind, for the purpose of keeping such concrete rules as from time to time may be laid down conformable to daily life. No doubt this conformity is the practical justification for requiring a man to know the civil law, as the fact that crimes are also generally sins is one of the practical justifications for requiring a man to know the criminal law. But these considerations only lead to [126] the conclusion that precedents should be overruled when they become inconsistent with present conditions; and this has generally happened, except with regard to the construction of deeds and wills. On the other hand, it is very desirable to know as nearly as we can the standard by which we shall be judged at a given moment, and, moreover, the standards for a very large part of human conduct do not vary from century to century.

The main argument supporting the idea that the jury should have a broader role by right is the need to continuously adjust our standards to keep pace with real-life experiences. It's important to remember that the basic foundation of legal responsibility is based on blameworthiness, as defined by the current average standards of the community, to ensure that any concrete rules we establish align with everyday life. This alignment is a practical reason for expecting people to be aware of civil law, just as the fact that crimes usually are also considered sins justifies the need to understand criminal law. However, these points ultimately lead to the conclusion that legal precedents should be changed when they no longer match current realities; this has generally been the case, except for how deeds and wills are interpreted. On the other hand, it's very important to understand as closely as possible the standard by which we will be judged at any given moment, and many standards regarding human behavior remain consistent over the centuries.

The considerations urged in this Lecture are of peculiar importance in this country, or at least in States where the law is as it stands in Massachusetts. In England, the judges at nisi prius express their opinions freely on the value and weight of the evidence, and the judges in banc, by consent of parties, constantly draw inferences of fact. Hence nice distinctions as to the province of court and jury are not of the first necessity. But when judges are forbidden by statute to charge the jury with respect to matters of fact, and when the court in banc will never hear a case calling for inferences of fact, it becomes of vital importance to understand that, when standards of conduct are left to the jury, it is a temporary surrender of a judicial function which may be resumed at any moment in any case when the court feels competent to do so. Were this not so, the almost universal acceptance of the first proposition in this Lecture, that the general foundation of liability for unintentional wrongs is conduct different from that of a prudent man under the circumstances, would leave all our rights and duties throughout a great part of the law to the necessarily more or less accidental feelings of a jury.

The points made in this Lecture are especially important in this country, or at least in states where the law is similar to that of Massachusetts. In England, judges at the preliminary hearings openly share their views on the importance and credibility of the evidence, and judges in court often draw conclusions of fact with the agreement of the parties involved. Therefore, subtle distinctions regarding the roles of the court and jury aren't as critical. However, when judges are legally prohibited from instructing the jury on matters of fact, and when the court won’t hear cases requiring factual inferences, it's crucial to understand that when the jury is left to decide on standards of conduct, it temporarily hands over a judicial responsibility that can be reclaimed at any time when the court feels capable of doing so. If this weren't the case, the almost universal acceptance of the first point in this Lecture—that the general basis for liability in unintentional wrongs is conduct that differs from that of a reasonable person under the circumstances—would leave our rights and responsibilities largely up to the potentially random sentiments of a jury.

It is perfectly consistent with the views maintained in this Lecture that the courts have been very slow to withdraw questions of negligence from the jury, without distinguishing [127] nicely whether the doubt concerned the facts or the standard to be applied. Legal, like natural divisions, however clear in their general outline, will be found on exact scrutiny to end in a penumbra or debatable land. This is the region of the jury, and only cases falling on this doubtful border are likely to be carried far in court. Still, the tendency of the law must always be to narrow the field of uncertainty. That is what analogy, as well as the decisions on this very subject, would lead us to expect.

It aligns perfectly with the ideas presented in this Lecture that the courts have been quite hesitant to remove negligence cases from the jury, without clearly distinguishing whether the uncertainty related to the facts or the applicable standard. Legal divisions, like natural ones, may seem distinct at a glance, but upon closer inspection, they often blur into a gray area or territory of debate. This is where the jury operates, and only cases that fall within this unclear zone are likely to progress significantly in court. Nonetheless, the trend in law should always aim to reduce the scope of uncertainty. That’s what both analogy and the rulings on this specific issue would suggest.

The growth of the law is very apt to take place in this way. Two widely different cases suggest a general distinction, which is a clear one when stated broadly. But as new eases cluster around the opposite poles, and begin to approach each other, the distinction becomes more difficult to trace; the determinations are made one way or the other on a very slight preponderance of feeling, rather than of articulate reason; and at last a mathematical line is arrived at by the contact of contrary decisions, which is so far arbitrary that it might equally well have been drawn a little farther to the one side or to the other, but which must have been drawn somewhere in the neighborhood of where it falls. /1/

The development of the law often happens like this. Two very different cases point to a clear general distinction when looked at broadly. However, as new cases gather around these opposite ends and start to converge, it becomes harder to see that distinction. Decisions are often made based on a slight inclination of feeling rather than clear reasoning. Eventually, a precise boundary is created by conflicting rulings, which is fairly arbitrary and could have easily been set a bit further one way or the other, but had to be established somewhere near where it is now. /1/

In this way exact distinctions have been worked out upon questions in which the elements to be considered are few. For instance, what is a reasonable time for presenting negotiable paper, or what is a difference in kind and what a difference only in quality, or the rule against perpetuities.

In this way, clear distinctions have been developed regarding questions where the elements involved are limited. For example, what constitutes a reasonable time for presenting negotiable instruments, or what defines a difference in kind compared to a difference in quality, or the rule against perpetuities.

An example of the approach of decisions towards each other from the opposite poles, and of the function of the jury midway, is to be found in the Massachusetts adjudications, [128] that, if a child of two years and four months is unnecessarily sent unattended across and down a street in a large city, he cannot recover for a negligent injury; /1/ that to allow a boy of eight to be abroad alone is not necessarily negligent; /2/ and that the effect of permitting a boy of ten to be abroad after dark is for the jury; /3/ a coupled with the statement, which may be ventured on without authority, that such a permission to a young man of twenty possessed of common intelligence has no effect whatever.

An example of how decisions approach each other from opposite ends, with the jury positioned in between, can be seen in Massachusetts rulings. For instance, if a child who is two years and four months old is sent unattended across a busy street, they cannot claim damages for a negligent injury; /1/ allowing an eight-year-old to be out alone isn’t automatically considered negligent; /2/ and whether it’s acceptable for a ten-year-old to be out after dark is up to the jury to decide; /3/ furthermore, it can be said, without needing to reference any authority, that allowing a twenty-year-old with average intelligence to go out at night has no consequences at all.

Take again the law of ancient lights in England. An obstruction to be actionable must be substantial. Under ordinary circumstances the erection of a structure a hundred yards off, and one foot above the ground, would not be actionable. One within a foot of the window, and covering it, would be, without any finding of a jury beyond these facts. In doubtful cases midway, the question whether the interference was substantial has been left to the jury. /4/ But as the elements are few and permanent, an inclination has been shown to lay down a definite rule, that, in ordinary cases, the building complained of must not be higher than the distance of its base from the dominant windows. And although this attempt to work out an exact line requires much caution, it is entirely philosophical in spirit. /5/

Consider the ancient lights law in England. For an obstruction to be considered actionable, it must be significant. Generally, if a structure is built a hundred yards away and one foot above the ground, it wouldn't be actionable. However, if it's within a foot of the window and blocks it completely, it would be actionable without any further jury deliberation beyond these facts. In uncertain situations, the decision on whether the interference is substantial has been left to the jury. But since the key factors are few and constant, there has been a tendency to establish a clear rule that, in general, the height of the disputed building should not exceed the distance from its base to the dominant windows. Although trying to determine an exact threshold requires careful consideration, the approach is fundamentally sound in principle.

The same principle applies to negligence. If the whole evidence in the case was that a party, in full command of [129] senses and intellect, stood on a railway track, looking at an approaching engine until it ran him down, no judge would leave it to the jury to say whether the conduct was prudent. If the whole evidence was that he attempted to cross a level track, which was visible for half a mile each way, and on which no engine was in sight, no court would allow a jury to find negligence. Between these extremes are cases which would go to the jury. But it is obvious that the limit of safety in such cases, supposing no further elements present, could be determined to a foot by mathematical calculation.

The same principle applies to negligence. If the entire evidence in the case showed that a person, fully aware of their surroundings and with sound judgment, stood on a railway track and watched an approaching train until it hit them, no judge would let the jury decide if that behavior was sensible. If the evidence indicated that they tried to cross a level track, which was clear for half a mile in either direction, and no train was visible, no court would permit a jury to find negligence. Between these two extremes are cases that would go to the jury. But it's clear that the safety limit in these cases, assuming no other factors are involved, could be determined precisely by mathematical calculation.

The trouble with many cases of negligence is, that they are of a kind not frequently recurring, so as to enable any given judge to profit by long experience with juries to lay down rules, and that the elements are so complex that courts are glad to leave the whole matter in a lump for the jury's determination.

The issue with many negligence cases is that they are not commonly seen, which prevents any specific judge from gaining enough experience with juries to establish rules. Additionally, the factors involved are so complicated that courts prefer to let the jury decide the entire matter.

I reserve the relation between negligent and other torts for the next Lecture.

I will discuss the relationship between negligent acts and other torts in the next lecture.





LECTURE IV. — FRAUD, MALICE, AND INTENT.—THE THEORY OF TORTS.

[130] The next subjects to be considered are fraud, malice, and intent. In the discussion of unintentional wrongs, the greatest difficulty to be overcome was found to be the doctrine that a man acts always at his peril. In what follows, on the other hand, the difficulty will be to prove that actual wickedness of the kind described by the several words just mentioned is not an element in the civil wrongs to which those words are applied.

[130] The next topics to discuss are fraud, malice, and intent. In talking about unintentional wrongs, the biggest challenge was the idea that a person is always responsible for their actions. However, in what follows, the challenge will be to show that actual wrongdoing, like the kinds described by the terms just mentioned, is not a factor in the civil wrongs to which those terms apply.

It has been shown, in dealing with the criminal law, that, when we call an act malicious in common speech, we mean that harm to another person was intended to come of it, and that such harm was desired for its own sake as an end in itself. For the purposes of the criminal law, however, intent alone was found to be important, and to have the same consequences as intent with malevolence superadded. Pursuing the analysis, intent was found to be made up of foresight of the harm as a consequence, coupled with a desire to bring it about, the latter being conceived as the motive for the act in question. Of these, again, foresight only seemed material. As a last step, foresight was reduced to its lowest term, and it was concluded that, subject to exceptions which were explained, the general basis of criminal liability was knowledge, at the time of action, [131] of facts from which common experience showed that certain harmful results were likely to follow.

It has been demonstrated that when we refer to an act as malicious in everyday language, we mean that it was intended to cause harm to another person, and that such harm was desired for its own sake. However, in the context of criminal law, intent alone has been recognized as significant and carries the same consequences as intent with added malice. Further analysis revealed that intent consists of the awareness of the harm as a likely outcome, combined with the desire to cause it, the latter being viewed as the motivation for the act in question. Among these, awareness appeared to be the most relevant factor. Ultimately, awareness was simplified to its most basic form, leading to the conclusion that, with some exceptions that were explained, the general foundation of criminal liability was knowledge, at the time of the action, of facts from which common experience indicated that certain harmful outcomes were likely to occur.

It remains to be seen whether a similar reduction is possible on the civil side of the law, and whether thus fraudulent, malicious, intentional, and negligent wrongs can be brought into a philosophically continuous series.

It’s still unclear if a similar reduction can happen in civil law, and whether fraudulent, malicious, intentional, and negligent wrongs can be grouped together in a coherent philosophical way.

A word of preliminary explanation will be useful. It has been shown in the Lecture just referred to that an act, although always importing intent, is per se indifferent to the law. It is a willed, and therefore an intended coordination of muscular contractions. But the intent necessarily imported by the act ends there. And all muscular motions or co-ordinations of them are harmless apart from concomitant circumstances, the presence of which is not necessarily implied by the act itself. To strike out with the fist is the same act, whether done in a desert or in a crowd.

A quick preliminary explanation is important. It's been shown in the lecture just mentioned that an act, while always involving intent, is neutral under the law. It’s a deliberate, and therefore intended, coordination of muscle movements. However, the intent associated with the act stops there. All muscle movements or their coordination are harmless, unless specific circumstances are present, which are not necessarily suggested by the act itself. Throwing a punch is the same action, whether it happens in a desert or in a crowd.

The same considerations which have been urged to show that an act alone, by itself, does not and ought not to impose either civil or criminal liability, apply, at least frequently, to a series of acts, or to conduct, although the series shows a further co-ordination and a further intent. For instance, it is the same series of acts to utter a sentence falsely stating that a certain barrel contains No. 1 Mackerel, whether the sentence is uttered in the secrecy of the closet, or to another man in the course of a bargain. There is, to be sure, in either case, the further intent, beyond the co-ordination of muscles for a single sound, to allege that a certain barrel has certain contents,—an intent necessarily shown by the ordering of the words. But both the series of acts and the intent are per se indifferent. They are innocent when spoken in solitude, and [132] are only a ground of liability when certain concomitant circumstances are shown.

The same reasons that have been put forward to argue that a single act doesn’t and shouldn’t create either civil or criminal liability also apply, often, to a series of acts or conduct, even if the series shows more coordination and intention. For example, it’s the same series of acts to falsely say that a certain barrel contains No. 1 Mackerel, whether the statement is made privately or to someone else during a negotiation. There is, of course, in both instances, an additional intent, beyond just coordinating muscles to produce a single sound, to claim that a specific barrel has certain contents—an intent clearly indicated by the arrangement of the words. However, both the series of acts and the intent are inherently neutral. They are innocent when said in private, and only become a basis for liability when certain related circumstances are present.

The intent which is meant when spoken of as an element of legal liability is an intent directed toward the harm complained of, or at least toward harm. It is not necessary in every case to carry the analysis back to the simple muscular contractions out of which a course of conduct is made up. On the same principle that requires something more than an act followed by damage to make a man liable, we constantly find ourselves at liberty to assume a co-ordinated series of acts as a proximately simple element, per se indifferent, in considering what further circumstances or facts must be present before the conduct in question is at the actor's peril. It will save confusion and the need of repetition if this is borne in mind in the following discussion.

The intent referred to as part of legal liability is an intention aimed at the harm being complained about, or at least toward causing harm. It isn't necessary to trace every case back to the simple muscle movements that make up a course of action. Following the principle that requires more than just an act followed by damage to hold someone liable, we can often assume a coordinated series of actions as a straightforward element, neutral in itself, when considering what additional circumstances or facts need to be present before the conduct in question puts the actor at risk. Keeping this in mind will help avoid confusion and unnecessary repetition in the following discussion.

The chief forms of liability in which fraud, malice, and intent are said to be necessary elements, are deceit, slander and libel, malicious prosecution, and conspiracy, to which, perhaps, may be added trover.

The main types of liability that require fraud, malice, and intent are deceit, slander and libel, malicious prosecution, and conspiracy, with possibly trover also included.

Deceit is a notion drawn from the moral world, and in its popular sense distinctly imports wickedness. The doctrine of the common law with regard to it is generally stated in terms which are only consistent with actual guilt, and all actual guilty intent. It is said that a man is liable to an action for deceit if he makes a false representation to another, knowing it to be false, but intending that the other should believe and act upon it, if the person addressed believes it, and is thereby persuaded to act to his own harm. This is no doubt the typical case, and it is a case of intentional moral wrong. Now, what is the party's conduct here. It consists in uttering certain words, [133] so ordered that the utterance of them imports a knowledge of the meaning which they would convey if heard. But that conduct with only that knowledge is neither moral nor immoral. Go one step further, and add the knowledge of another's presence within hearing, still the act has no determinate character. The elements which make it immoral are the knowledge that the statement is false, and the intent that it shall be acted on.

Deceit is an idea from the moral realm, and in its common use, it clearly implies wickedness. The common law's view on deceit is usually expressed in terms that only align with actual wrongdoing and guilty intent. A person can be held liable for deceit if they make a false statement to someone else, knowing it’s false and intending for the other person to believe it and act on it, especially if that person believes it and is then led to their own detriment. This is certainly the classic example and represents intentional moral wrongdoing. Now, what are we looking at in terms of the party's behavior here? It involves saying certain words, arranged in a way that suggests an understanding of the meaning they would have if heard. However, just having that knowledge does not make the behavior moral or immoral. If we go a step further and acknowledge that someone else is present to hear it, the act still lacks a clear moral nature. The factors that make it immoral are knowing that the statement is false and having the intent for it to be acted on.

The principal question then is, whether this intent can be reduced to the same terms as it has been in other cases. There is no difficulty in the answer. It is perfectly clear that the intent that a false representation should be acted on would be conclusively established by proof that the defendant knew that the other party intended to act upon it. If the defendant foresaw the consequence of his acts, he is chargeable, whether his motive was a desire to induce the other party to act, or simply an unwillingness for private reasons to state the truth. If the defendant knew a present fact (the other party's intent), which, according to common experience, made it likely that his act would have the harmful consequence, he is chargeable, whether he in fact foresaw the consequence or not.

The main question is whether this intention can be expressed in the same way as it has been in other cases. The answer is straightforward. It's clear that the intent for someone to act on a false representation would be definitively shown by evidence that the defendant knew the other party intended to rely on it. If the defendant anticipated the outcome of their actions, they are responsible, whether their goal was to persuade the other party to act or simply to avoid stating the truth for personal reasons. If the defendant was aware of a current fact (the other party's intent) that, based on common experience, made it likely that their action would lead to a negative outcome, they are accountable, regardless of whether they actually anticipated the result or not.

In this matter the general conclusion follows from a single instance. For the moment it is admitted that in one case knowledge of a present fact, such as the other party's intent to act on the false statement, dispenses with proof of an intent to induce him to act upon it, it is admitted that the lesser element is all that is necessary in the larger compound. For intent embraces knowledge sufficing for foresight, as has been shown. Hence, when you prove intent you prove knowledge, and intent may often [134] be the easier to prove of the two. But when you prove knowledge you do not prove intent.

In this situation, the overall conclusion comes from just one example. For now, if we accept that in one case, knowing a current fact—like the other party's intention to act on the false statement—removes the need to prove an intention to get them to act on it, then we agree that knowing less is all that’s needed for the bigger picture. Intent includes knowledge that is enough for foresight, as has been demonstrated. Therefore, when you prove intent, you also prove knowledge, and often it’s easier to prove intent than knowledge. However, proving knowledge doesn’t automatically prove intent.

It may be said, however, that intent is implied or presumed in such a case as has been supposed. But this is only helping out a false theory by a fiction. It is very much like saying that a consideration is presumed for an instrument under seal; which is merely a way of reconciling the formal theory that all contracts must have a consideration with the manifest fact that sealed instruments do not require one. Whenever it is said that a certain thing is essential to liability, but that it is conclusively presumed from something else, there is always ground for suspicion that the essential clement is to be found in that something else, and not in what is said to be presumed from it.

It can be argued that intent is suggested or assumed in cases like the one discussed. However, this only supports a false theory through a fiction. It's similar to claiming that a consideration is assumed for an instrument under seal, which is just a way of aligning the formal idea that all contracts need a consideration with the clear reality that sealed instruments don't require one. Whenever it is stated that something is crucial for liability, but it is supposedly assumed from something else, there's always reason to be skeptical that the crucial element is actually found in that something else, not in what is claimed to be inferred from it.

With regard to the intent necessary to deceit, we need not stop with the single instance which has been given. The law goes no farther than to require proof either of the intent, or that the other party was justified in inferring such intention. So that the whole meaning of the requirement is, that the natural and manifest tendency of the representation, under the known circumstances, must have been to induce the opinion that it was made with a view to action, and so to induce action on the faith of it. The standard of what is called intent is thus really an external standard of conduct under the known circumstances, and the analysis of the criminal law holds good here.

Regarding the intent necessary for deceit, we don't need to focus on just one example. The law simply requires evidence of intent or proof that the other party was justified in inferring such intent. Essentially, this means that the natural and obvious tendency of the statement, given the known circumstances, must have been aimed at leading someone to believe it was made with the intention of prompting action, and therefore to encourage action based on that belief. The standard for what is considered intent is actually an external measure of behavior under the known circumstances, and the principles of criminal law apply here.

Nor is this all. The law pursuing its course of specification, as explained in the last Lecture, decides what is the tendency of representations in certain cases,—as, for instance, that a horse is sound at the time of making a [135] sale; or, in general, of any statement of fact which it is known the other party intends to rely on. Beyond these scientific rules lies the vague realm of the jury.

Nor is this all. The law, as discussed in the last lecture, specifies what the implications of certain representations are—like, for example, stating that a horse is healthy at the time of making a [135] sale; or more generally, any factual statement that the other party is known to depend on. Beyond these established rules, there's the uncertain territory of the jury.

The other moral element in deceit is knowledge that the statement was false. With this I am not strictly concerned, because all that is necessary is accomplished when the elements of risk are reduced to action and knowledge. But it will aid in the general object of showing that the tendency of the law everywhere is to transcend moral and reach external standards, if this knowledge of falsehood can be transmuted into a formula not necessarily importing guilt, although, of course, generally accompanied by it in fact. The moment we look critically at it, we find the moral side shade away.

The other moral aspect of deceit is knowing that the statement was false. I'm not really focused on that because all that matters is when the risks are turned into actions and knowledge. However, it will help support the overall goal of demonstrating that the law tends to go beyond just moral considerations and aim for external standards. If this awareness of falsehood can be transformed into a concept that doesn't always mean guilt—though it usually does in reality—it shows that when we examine it closely, the moral aspect starts to fade away.

The question is, what known circumstances are enough throw the risk of a statement upon him who makes it, if it induces another man to act, and it turns out untrue. Now, it is evident that a man may take the risk of his statement by express agreement, or by an implied one which the law reads into his bargain. He may in legal language warrant the truth of it, and if it is not true, the law treats it as a fraud, just as much when he makes it fully believing it, as when he knows that it is untrue, and means to deceive. If, in selling a horse, the seller warranted him to be only five years old, and in fact he was thirteen, the seller could be sued for a deceit at common law, although he thought the horse was only five. /1/ The common-law liability for the truth of statements is, therefore, more extensive than the sphere of actual moral fraud. But, again, it is enough in general if a representation [136] is made recklessly, without knowing whether it is true or false. Now what does "recklessly" mean. It does not mean actual personal indifference to the truth of the statement. It means only that the data for the statement were so far insufficient that a prudent man could not have made it without leading to the inference that he was indifferent. That is to say, repeating an analysis which has been gone through with before, it means that the law, applying a general objective standard, determines that, if a man makes his statement on those data, he is liable, whatever was the state of his mind, and although he individually may have been perfectly free from wickedness in making it.

The question is, what circumstances are enough to hold someone responsible for a statement if it encourages another person to act and turns out to be false? It's clear that a person can take on the responsibility for their statement either through an explicit agreement or an implied one that the law recognizes in their arrangement. They may legally guarantee its truth, and if it isn't true, the law treats it as fraud, whether they genuinely believe it to be true or know it's false and intend to deceive. For instance, if someone sells a horse and says it's only five years old when it’s actually thirteen, that seller could be sued for deceit, even if they believed the horse was just five. Therefore, the common-law responsibility for the truth of statements is broader than what would typically be considered moral fraud. Additionally, in general, it suffices if a representation [136] is made recklessly, without knowing if it's true or false. So what does "recklessly" mean? It doesn’t mean being indifferent to the truth of the statement. It simply means that the information used for the statement was so inadequate that a reasonable person wouldn't have made it without implying indifference. In other words, repeating a previously discussed analysis, the law uses a general objective standard to determine that if someone makes a statement based on such data, they are liable, regardless of their state of mind, even if they personally hold no malicious intent in making it.

Hence similar reasoning to that which has been applied already to intent may be applied to knowledge of falsity. Actual knowledge may often be easier to prove than that the evidence was insufficient to warrant the statement, and when proved it contains the lesser element. But as soon as the lesser element is shown to be enough, it is shown that the law is ready to apply an external or objective standard here also.

Hence, similar reasoning to what has already been applied to intent can also be applied to knowledge of falsehood. Actual knowledge is often easier to prove than to show that the evidence was not enough to support the statement, and when proven, it includes the lesser element. But as soon as the lesser element is demonstrated to be sufficient, it becomes clear that the law is prepared to apply an external or objective standard here as well.

Courts of equity have laid down the doctrine in terms which are so wholly irrespective of the actual moral condition of the defendant as to go to an opposite extreme. It is said that "when a representation in a matter of business is made by one man to another calculated to induce him to adapt his conduct to it, it is perfectly immaterial whether the representation is made knowing it to be untrue, or whether it is made believing it to be true, if, in fact, it was untrue." /1/

Courts of equity have established a principle that completely ignores the actual moral situation of the defendant, reaching the opposite extreme. It is stated that "when one person makes a business representation to another that is meant to encourage him to change his behavior accordingly, it doesn't matter at all whether the representation is made knowing it's false or believing it to be true if, in reality, it was false." /1/

Perhaps the actual decisions could be reconciled on a [137] narrower principle, but the rule just stated goes the length of saying that in business matters a man makes every statement (of a kind likely to be acted on) at his peril. This seems hardly justifiable in policy. The moral starting point of liability in general should never be forgotten, and the law cannot without disregarding it hold a man answerable for statements based on facts which would have convinced a wise and prudent man of their truth. The public advantage and necessity of freedom in imparting information, which privileges even the slander of a third person, ought a fortiori, it seems to me, to privilege statements made at the request of the party who complains of them.

Maybe the actual decisions could be reconciled on a [137] narrower principle, but the stated rule implies that in business matters, a person makes every statement (of a kind likely to be acted on) at his own risk. This seems hardly justifiable in policy. The moral foundation of liability in general should always be remembered, and the law cannot, without ignoring it, hold a person accountable for statements based on facts that would have convinced a reasonable and prudent person of their truth. The public benefit and necessity of freedom in sharing information, which even protects third-party slander, should even more so protect statements made at the request of the person who is complaining about them.

The common law, at any rate, preserves the reference to morality by making fraud the ground on which it goes. It does not hold that a man always speaks at his peril. But starting from the moral ground, it works out an external standard of what would be fraudulent in the average prudent member of the community, and requires every member at his peril to avoid that. As in other cases, it is gradually accumulating precedents which decide that certain statements under certain circumstances are at the peril of the party who makes them.

The common law, in any case, maintains a connection to morality by using fraud as its basis. It doesn’t claim that a person always speaks at their own risk. Rather, starting from a moral foundation, it establishes an external standard of what would be considered fraudulent by the average reasonable person in the community and requires everyone to avoid that at their own risk. Like in other situations, it is gradually building a body of precedents that determine that certain statements in specific circumstances put the person making them at risk.

The elements of deceit which throw the risk of his conduct upon a party are these. First, making a statement of facts purporting to be serious. Second, the known presence of another within hearing. Third, known facts sufficient to warrant the expectation or suggest the probability that the other party will act on the statement. (What facts are sufficient has been specifically determined by the courts in some instances; in others, no doubt, the question would go to the jury on the principles heretofore explained.) Fourth, the [138] falsehood of the statement. This must be known, or else the known evidence concerning the matter of the statement must be such as would not warrant belief according to the ordinary course of human experience. (On this point also the court may be found to lay down specific rules in some cases. /1/)

The elements of deceit that shift the risk of his actions onto another party are as follows. First, making a serious-sounding statement of facts. Second, the known presence of someone else within earshot. Third, known facts that are enough to lead to the expectation or suggest the likelihood that the other party will rely on the statement. (What facts are enough has been specifically determined by the courts in some cases; in other cases, the jury would likely decide based on the principles mentioned earlier.) Fourth, the [138] falsehood of the statement. This must either be known, or the known evidence about the statement must be such that it wouldn’t be believed according to common human experience. (Regarding this, the court may set specific rules in some instances. /1/)

I next take up the law of slander. It has often been said that malice is one of the elements of liability, and the doctrine is commonly stated in this way: that malice must exist, but that it is presumed by law from the mere speaking of the words; that again you may rebut this presumption of malice by showing that the words were spoken under circumstances which made the communication privileged,—as, for instance, by a lawyer in the necessary course of his argument, or by a person answering in good faith to inquiries as to the character of a former servant,— and then, it is said, the plaintiff may meet this defence in some cases by showing that the words were spoken with actual malice.

I’ll now discuss the law of slander. It’s often said that malice is one of the key components of liability, and this principle is usually expressed like this: malice must be present, but it’s assumed by law simply from the act of speaking the words. You can counter this assumption of malice by demonstrating that the words were spoken in a context that made the communication privileged—like when a lawyer speaks during necessary arguments or someone responds in good faith to questions about a former employee’s character—and then, it’s said, the plaintiff might challenge this defense in some cases by proving that the words were spoken with actual malice.

All this sounds as if at least actual intent to cause the damage complained of, if not malevolence, were at the bottom of this class of wrongs. Yet it is not so. For although the use of the phrase "malice" points as usual to an original moral standard, the rule that it is presumed upon proof of speaking certain words is equivalent to saying that the overt conduct of speaking those words may be actionable whether the consequence of damage to the plaintiff was intended or not. And this fails in with the general theory, because the manifest tendency of slanderous words is to harm the person of whom they are spoken. Again, the real substance of the defence is not that the damage [139] was not intended,—that would be no defence at all; but that, whether it was intended or not,—that is, even if the defendant foresaw it and foresaw it with pleasure,—the manifest facts and circumstances under which he said it were such that the law considered the damage to the plaintiff of less importance than the benefit of free speaking.

All of this suggests that there was at least some real intention to cause the damage being complained about, if not outright malice, at the heart of these kinds of wrongs. However, that's not the case. While the term "malice" usually points to a moral standard, the rule that it’s assumed when certain words are spoken means that simply saying those words could lead to legal action, regardless of whether or not damaging the plaintiff was intended. This doesn't align with the overall theory since slanderous words typically have the clear effect of harming the person they're directed at. Furthermore, the core of the defense isn’t about whether the damage was intended—because that wouldn't be a valid defense at all—but rather that, whether it was intended or not—even if the defendant anticipated it and even took pleasure in that anticipation—the clear facts and circumstances of how he expressed those words were such that the law prioritized the importance of free speech over the potential harm to the plaintiff.

It is more difficult to apply the same analysis to the last stage of the process, but perhaps it is not impossible. It is said that the plaintiff may meet a case of privilege thus made out on the part of the defendant, by proving actual malice, that is, actual intent to cause the damage complained of. But how is this actual malice made out? It is by showing that the defendant knew the statement which he made was false, or that his untrue statements were grossly in excess of what the occasion required. Now is it not very evident that the law is looking to a wholly different matter from the defendant's intent? The fact that the defendant foresaw and foresaw with pleasure the damage to the plaintiff, is of no more importance in this case than it would be where the communication was privileged. The question again is wholly a question of knowledge, or other external standard. And what makes even knowledge important? It is that the reason for which a man is allowed in the other instances to make false charges against his neighbors is wanting. It is for the public interest that people should be free to give the best information they can under certain circumstances without fear, but there is no public benefit in having lies told at any time; and when a charge is known to be false, or is in excess of what is required by the occasion, it is not necessary to make that charge in order to speak freely, and [140] therefore it falls under the ordinary rule, that certain charges are made at the party's peril in case they turn out to be false, whether evil consequences were intended or not. The defendant is liable, not because his intent was evil, but because he made false charges without excuse.

It’s harder to apply the same analysis to the final stage of the process, but maybe it’s not impossible. It’s said that the plaintiff can counter a privilege defense by proving actual malice, which means actual intent to cause the harm that’s being complained about. But how is this actual malice established? It’s by demonstrating that the defendant knew the statement he made was false, or that his untrue statements were far beyond what was necessary for the situation. Isn’t it clear that the law is focused on something completely different from the defendant's intent? The fact that the defendant saw the damage to the plaintiff coming and even took pleasure in it is no more relevant in this case than it would be if the communication were privileged. The question, once again, is entirely about knowledge or another external standard. And why is knowledge important? It’s because the justification that allows people in other situations to make false accusations against their neighbors is absent here. It’s in the public interest for people to share their best information in certain situations without fear, but there’s no public benefit in spreading lies at any time; when a claim is known to be false or goes beyond what the situation warrants, it’s not necessary to make that claim in order to speak freely. Therefore, it falls under the usual rule that certain accusations are made at the party's risk if they turn out to be false, regardless of whether bad intentions were involved. The defendant is held liable not because his intentions were malicious, but because he made false claims without justification.

It will be seen that the peril of conduct here begins farther back than with deceit, as the tendency of slander is more universally harmful. There must be some concomitant circumstances. There must at least be a human being in existence whom the statement designates. There must be another human being within hearing who understands the statement, and the statement must be false. But it is arguable that the latter of these facts need not be known, as certainly the falsity of the charge need not be, and that a man must take the risk of even an idle statement being heard, unless he made it under known circumstances of privilege. It would be no great curtailment of freedom to deny a man immunity in attaching a charge of crime to the name of his neighbor, even when he supposes himself alone. But it does not seem clear that the law would go quite so far as that.

The danger of behavior here starts earlier than just deceit, as slander is more broadly damaging. There must be specific conditions present. At least one person must exist who the statement is about. There must be another person nearby who understands the statement, and the statement has to be false. However, it's debatable whether the falsehood needs to be known, just as the person making the accusation doesn't need to know it's false. Essentially, someone has to risk having even a casual statement overheard, unless it was made under established circumstances of privilege. It wouldn’t significantly limit freedom to deny a person protection when accusing their neighbor of a crime, even when they think they are alone. But it’s not entirely clear that the law would take that stance.

The next form of liability is comparatively insignificant. I mean the action for malicious prosecution. A man may recover damages against another for maliciously and without probable cause instituting a criminal, or, in some cases, a civil prosecution against him upon a false charge. The want of probable cause refers, of course, only to the state of the defendant's knowledge, not to his intent. It means the absence of probable cause in the facts known to the defendant when he instituted the suit. But the standard applied to the defendant's consciousness is external to it. The question is not whether he thought the [141] facts to constitute probable cause, but whether the court thinks they did.

The next type of liability is relatively minor. I'm talking about the action for malicious prosecution. Someone can claim damages against another person for maliciously starting a criminal or, in some cases, a civil prosecution against them based on a false accusation, and without any reasonable justification. The lack of reasonable justification refers, of course, only to what the defendant knew, not their intent. It indicates that there was no reasonable justification in the facts known to the defendant when they filed the lawsuit. However, the standard used regarding the defendant's awareness is external to them. The issue isn't whether they believed the [141] facts amounted to reasonable justification, but whether the court believes they did.

Then as to malice. The conduct of the defendant consists in instituting proceedings on a charge which is in fact false, and which has not prevailed. That is the root of the whole matter. If the charge was true, or if the plaintiff has been convicted, even though he may be able now to prove that he was wrongly convicted, the defendant is safe, however great his malice, and however little ground he had for his charge.

Then regarding malice. The defendant's actions involve filing a case based on a false accusation that hasn’t succeeded. That's the core of the issue. If the accusation were true, or if the plaintiff had been convicted, even if he can now prove that the conviction was unjust, the defendant is in the clear, no matter how much malice he had or how flimsy his accusation was.

Suppose, however, that the charge is false, and does not prevail. It may readily be admitted that malice did originally mean a malevolent motive, an actual intent to harm the plaintiff by making a false charge. The legal remedy here, again, started from the moral basis, the occasion for it, no doubt, being similar to that which gave rise to the old law of conspiracy, that a man's enemies would sometimes seek his destruction by setting the criminal law in motion against him. As it was punishable to combine for such a purpose, it was concluded, with some hesitation, that, when a single individual wickedly attempted the same thing, he should be liable on similar grounds. /1/ I must fully admit that there is weighty authority to the effect that malice in its ordinary sense is to this day a distinct fact to be proved and to be found by the jury.

Suppose, however, that the accusation is false and does not hold up. It's easy to agree that malice originally meant having a harmful intention—an actual desire to hurt the plaintiff by making a false accusation. The legal response here also came from a moral foundation, likely because it was similar to what led to the old laws around conspiracy: that enemies might try to ruin a person by using criminal law against them. Since it was punishable to conspire for that purpose, it was reluctantly concluded that when a single individual maliciously tried to do the same, they should be held liable for similar reasons. /1/ I must acknowledge that there is significant authority indicating that malice, in its usual sense, is still a distinct fact that needs to be proven and determined by the jury.

But this view cannot be accepted without hesitation. It is admitted that, on the one side, the existence of probable cause, believed in, is a justification notwithstanding malice; /2/ that, on the other, "it is not enough to show [142] that the case appeared sufficient to this particular party, but it must be sufficient to induce a sober, sensible and discreet person to act upon it, or it must fail as a justification for the proceeding upon general grounds." /1/ On the one side, malice alone will not make a man liable for instituting a groundless prosecution; on the other, his justification will depend, not on his opinion of the facts, but on that of the court. When his actual moral condition is disregarded to this extent, it is a little hard to believe that the existence of an improper motive should be material. Yet that is what malice must mean in this case, if it means anything. /2/ For the evil effects of a successful indictment are of course intended by one who procures all other to be indicted. I cannot but think that a jury would be told that knowledge or belief that the charge was false at the time of making it was conclusive evidence of malice. And if so, on grounds which need not be repeated, malice is not the important thing, but the facts known to the defendant.

But this perspective can’t be accepted without some hesitation. It’s acknowledged that, on one hand, the existence of probable cause, if genuinely believed in, justifies actions even in the presence of malice; /2/ on the other hand, “it’s not enough to show [142] that the case seemed sufficient to this particular person, but it must be convincing enough to lead a sober, sensible, and reasonable person to act on it, or it fails as a justification for the proceeding on general grounds.” /1/ On one hand, malice alone won’t make someone liable for starting a baseless prosecution; on the other, their justification depends not on their view of the facts, but on the court's. When their actual moral state is disregarded to this degree, it’s hard to believe that a wrongful motive should matter. Yet that’s what malice must imply in this situation, if it means anything at all. /2/ The harmful consequences of a successful indictment are clearly intended by anyone who causes others to be indicted. I can’t help but think that a jury would be informed that knowing or believing the charge was false at the time it was made is conclusive evidence of malice. And if that’s the case, for reasons that need not be repeated, malice isn’t the main concern, but rather the facts known to the defendant.

Nevertheless, as it is obviously treading on delicate ground to make it actionable to set the regular processes of the law in motion, it is, of course, entirely possible to say that the action shall be limited to those cases where the charge was preferred from improper motives, at least if the defendant thought that there was probable cause. Such a limitation would stand almost alone in the law of civil liability. But the nature of the wrong is peculiar, and, moreover, it is quite consistent with the theory of liability here advanced that it should be confined in any given instance to actual wrong-doing in a moral sense.

However, since it's clearly sensitive territory to make it possible to set the usual legal processes in motion, it's entirely feasible to state that the action will be limited to situations where the charge was made out of improper motives, at least if the defendant believed there was a valid reason for it. Such a restriction would be quite unique in civil liability law. But the nature of the wrongdoing is distinctive, and it aligns with the theory of liability presented here that it should be restricted in any specific case to actual wrongdoing in a moral sense.

The only other cause of action in which the moral condition [143] of the defendant's consciousness might seem to be important is conspiracy. The old action going by that name was much like malicious prosecution, and no doubt was originally confined to cases where several persons had conspired to indict another from malevolent motives. But in the modern action on the case, where conspiracy is charged, the allegation as a rule only means that two or more persons were so far co-operating in their acts that the act of any one was the act of all. Generally speaking, the liability depends not on the co-operation or conspiring, but on the character of the acts done, supposing them all to be done by one man, or irrespective of the question whether they were done by one or several. There may be cases, to be sure, in which the result could not be accomplished, or the offence could not ordinarily be proved, without a combination of several; as, for instance, the removal of a teacher by a school board. The conspiracy would not affect the case except in a practical way, but the question would be raised whether, notwithstanding the right of the board to remove, proof that they were actuated by malevolence would not make a removal actionable. Policy, it might be said, forbids going behind their judgment, but actual evil motives coupled with the absence of grounds withdraw this protection, because policy, although it does not require them to take the risk of being right, does require that they should judge honestly on the merits. /1/

The only other reason for legal action where the moral state of the defendant's mind might be relevant is conspiracy. The old legal action known as conspiracy was similar to malicious prosecution and was likely initially limited to situations where multiple people conspired to falsely charge another out of spite. However, in modern cases where conspiracy is alleged, it usually just means that two or more people were acting together so closely that the actions of one were considered the actions of all. Generally, liability isn't based on the collaboration or conspiracy itself, but rather on the nature of the actions taken, assuming they were all done by a single person, regardless of whether they were performed by one or more individuals. There may be instances where the outcome couldn’t be achieved, or the crime couldn’t normally be proven, without a partnership among several people, like when a school board removes a teacher. The conspiracy wouldn’t affect the case except practically, but the issue would arise whether, despite the board's right to remove someone, evidence that they acted out of malice could make the removal legally actionable. It could be argued that policy prevents questioning their judgment, but genuine harmful motives, coupled with a lack of justifiable reasons, would revoke that protection, since policy doesn’t require them to guarantee they are right, but does demand they make honest judgments based on the facts. /1/

Other isolated instances like the last might, perhaps, be found in different parts of the law, in which actual malevolence would affect a man's liability for his conduct. Again, in trover for the conversion of another's chattel, where the dominion exercised over it was of a slight and ambiguous [144] nature, it has been said that the taking must be "with the intent of exercising an ownership over the chattel inconsistent with the real owner's right of possession." /1/ But this seems to be no more than a faint shadow of the doctrine explained with regard to larceny, and does not require any further or special discussion. Trover is commonly understood to go, like larceny, on the plaintiff's being deprived of his property, although in practice every possessor has the action, and, generally speaking, the shortest wrongful withholding of possession is a conversion.

Other isolated cases like the last one might be found in different areas of the law where actual malice would influence a person's liability for their actions. In cases of trover for the wrongful taking of someone else's property, where the control over it was minimal and unclear, it has been stated that the taking must be "with the intent of exercising ownership over the property that conflicts with the true owner's right to possess it." /1/ However, this seems to be just a faint echo of the principle related to larceny, and it doesn't need more detailed discussion. Trover is generally understood to operate, like larceny, on the basis that the plaintiff has been deprived of their property, although in practice, any possessor can initiate the action, and, generally speaking, even the briefest wrongful withholding of possession qualifies as conversion.

Be the exceptions more or less numerous, the general purpose of the law of torts is to secure a man indemnity against certain forms of harm to person, reputation, or estate, at the hands of his neighbors, not because they are wrong, but because they are harms. The true explanation of the reference of liability to a moral standard, in the sense which has been explained, is not that it is for the purpose of improving men's hearts, but that it is to give a man a fair chance to avoid doing the harm before he is held responsible for it. It is intended to reconcile the policy of letting accidents lie where they fall, and the reasonable freedom of others with the protection of the individual from injury.

Whether there are many exceptions or just a few, the main goal of tort law is to provide compensation to someone who suffers certain types of harm to their person, reputation, or property, caused by others in the community, not because those others are in the wrong, but because the harm itself is what matters. The real reason for linking liability to a moral standard, as explained earlier, isn’t to improve people’s character, but to give someone a fair chance to prevent the harm before being held accountable for it. The aim is to balance the approach of allowing accidents to happen without intervention and the reasonable freedom of others while also protecting individuals from injury.

But the law does not even seek to indemnify a man from all harms. An unrestricted enjoyment of all his possibilities would interfere with other equally important enjoyments on the part of his neighbors. There are certain things which the law allows a man to do, notwithstanding the fact that he foresees that harm to another will follow from them. He may charge a man with crime if the charge is true. He may establish himself in business where he foresees that [145] of his competition will be to diminish the custom of another shopkeeper, perhaps to ruin him. He may a building which cuts another off from a beautiful prospect, or he may drain subterranean waters and thereby drain another's well; and many other cases might be put.

But the law doesn't aim to protect a person from all harm. Enjoying all his options without limits would hinder other equally important interests of his neighbors. There are certain actions that the law permits, even if he knows that they will harm someone else. He can accuse someone of a crime if the accusation is valid. He can start a business knowing that some of his competition will likely reduce another shopkeeper's customers, maybe even ruin him. He can build a structure that blocks another person's beautiful view, or he can drain underground water, which could deplete someone else's well; and there are many other examples that could be mentioned.

As any of these things may be done with foresight of their evil consequences, it would seem that they might be done with intent, and even with malevolent intent, to produce them. The whole argument of this Lecture and the preceding tends to this conclusion. If the aim of liability is simply to prevent or indemnify from harm so far as is consistent with avoiding the extreme of making a man answer for accident, when the law permits the harm to be knowingly inflicted it would be a strong thing if the presence of malice made any difference in its decisions. That might happen, to be sure, without affecting the general views maintained here, but it is not to be expected, and the weight of authority is against it.

As any of these actions can be taken with an awareness of their negative consequences, it seems like they could be done with intent, and even with the intention to cause harm. The overall argument of this Lecture and the previous one leads to this conclusion. If the goal of liability is simply to prevent or compensate for harm while avoiding the extreme of holding someone responsible for an accident, when the law allows harm to be intentionally inflicted, it would be notable if the presence of malice made any difference in its rulings. That might happen, of course, without changing the general principles stated here, but it's not expected, and most of the authoritative opinions are against it.

As the law, on the one hand, allows certain harms to be inflicted irrespective of the moral condition of him who inflicts them, so, at the other extreme, it may on grounds of policy throw the absolute risk of certain transactions on the person engaging in them, irrespective of blameworthiness in any sense. Instances of this sort have been mentioned in the last Lecture, /1/ and will be referred to again.

As the law, on one hand, permits certain harms to be imposed regardless of the moral character of the one causing them, so, on the other hand, it may for policy reasons place the full risk of certain transactions on the person involved in them, regardless of any blameworthiness. Examples of this have been discussed in the last lecture, /1/ and will be mentioned again.

Most liabilities in tort lie between these two extremes, and are founded on the infliction of harm which the defendant had a reasonable opportunity to avoid at the time of the acts or omissions which were its proximate cause. Rut as fast as specific rules are worked out in place of the [146] vague reference to the conduct of the average man, they range themselves alongside of other specific rules based on public policy, and the grounds from which they spring cease to be manifest. So that, as will be seen directly, rules which seem to lie outside of culpability in any sense have sometimes been referred to remote fault, while others which started from the general notion of negligence may with equal ease be referred to some extrinsic ground of policy.

Most liabilities in tort fall somewhere between these two extremes and are based on the harm that the defendant could reasonably have avoided at the time of the actions or omissions that directly caused it. However, as specific rules are developed to replace the vague reference to the behavior of the average person, they align with other specific rules grounded in public policy, and the underlying reasons for them become less clear. Therefore, as will be shown shortly, rules that might appear unrelated to blame in any way have sometimes been categorized as remote fault, while others that originated from the general idea of negligence can just as easily be linked to some external policy reason.

Apart from the extremes just mentioned, it is now easy to see how the point at which a man's conduct begins to be at his own peril is generally fixed. When the principle is understood on which that point is determined by the law of torts, we possess a common ground of classification, and a key to the whole subject, so far as tradition has not swerved the law from a consistent theory. It has been made pretty clear from what precedes, that I find that ground in knowledge of circumstances accompanying an act or conduct indifferent but for those circumstances.

Besides the extremes already mentioned, it’s now easy to see where a person’s behavior starts to be at their own risk. Once we understand the principle that determines this point according to tort law, we gain a common framework for classification and insight into the entire topic, as long as tradition hasn’t led the law away from a consistent theory. It has been made fairly clear from what has been discussed that I find this foundation in the awareness of the circumstances surrounding an act or behavior that are otherwise neutral but for those circumstances.

But it is worth remarking, before that criterion is discussed, that a possible common ground is reached at the preceding step in the descent from malice through intent and foresight. Foresight is a possible common denominator of wrongs at the two extremes of malice and negligence. The purpose of the law is to prevent or secure a man indemnity from harm at the hands of his neighbors, so far as consistent with other considerations which have been mentioned, and excepting, of course, such harm as it permits to be intentionally inflicted. When a man foresees that harm will result from his conduct, the principle which exonerates him from accident no longer applies, and he is liable. But, as has been shown, he is bound to foresee [147] whatever a prudent and intelligent man would have foreseen, and therefore he is liable for conduct from which such a man would have foreseen that harm was liable to follow.

But it's important to note, before we discuss that criterion, that a possible common ground is established at the earlier stage in the descent from malice through intent and foresight. Foresight serves as a possible common factor in wrongs at both ends of malice and negligence. The law aims to prevent harm or ensure compensation for a person harmed by others, as long as it aligns with other mentioned considerations, and obviously excluding harm that it allows to be intentionally caused. When someone anticipates that their actions will cause harm, the principle that protects them from being liable for accidents no longer applies, and they become responsible. However, as previously indicated, they are expected to foresee [147] anything that a reasonable and smart person would have anticipated, and therefore they are liable for actions that such a person would have recognized could lead to harm.

Accordingly, it would be possible to state all cases of negligence in terms of imputed or presumed foresight. It would be possible even to press the presumption further, applying the very inaccurate maxim, that every man is presumed to intend the natural consequences of his own acts; and this mode of expression will, in fact, be found to have been occasionally used, /1/ more especially in the criminal law, where the notion of intent has a stronger foothold. /2/ The latter fiction is more remote and less philosophical than the former; but, after all, both are equally fictions. Negligence is not foresight, but precisely the want of it; and if foresight were presumed, the ground of the presumption, and therefore the essential element, would be the knowledge of facts which made foresight possible.

Accordingly, it’s possible to describe all cases of negligence in terms of assumed or presumed foresight. It could even be argued further, using the very inaccurate saying that everyone is assumed to intend the natural outcomes of their own actions; and this way of expressing it will, in fact, be found to have been used occasionally, /1/ especially in criminal law, where the idea of intent has a stronger presence. /2/ This latter assumption is more distant and less philosophical than the former; however, in the end, both are equally assumptions. Negligence is not foresight, but rather the lack of it; and if foresight were assumed, the basis of that assumption, and thus the essential factor, would be the awareness of facts that made foresight possible.

Taking knowledge, then, as the true starting-point, the next question is how to determine the circumstances necessary to be known in any given case in order to make a man liable for the consequences of his act. They must be such as would have led a prudent man to perceive danger, although not necessarily to foresee the specific harm. But this is a vague test. How is it decided what those circumstances are? The answer must be, by experience.

Taking knowledge as the true starting point, the next question is how to determine the necessary circumstances to be known in any given situation to hold someone accountable for the consequences of their actions. These circumstances should be ones that would have made a reasonable person recognize the danger, even if they couldn't specifically predict the harm. However, this is a vague standard. How do we decide what those circumstances are? The answer has to be through experience.

But there is one point which has been left ambiguous in the preceding Lecture and here, and which must be touched upon. It has been assumed that conduct which [148] the man of ordinary intelligence would perceive to be dangerous under the circumstances, would be blameworthy if pursued by him. It might not be so, however. Suppose that, acting under the threats of twelve armed men, which put him in fear of his life, a man enters another's close and takes a horse. In such a case, he actually contemplates and chooses harm to another as the consequence of his act. Yet the act is neither blameworthy nor punishable. But it might be actionable, and Rolle, C. J. ruled that it was so in Gilbert v. Stone. /1/ If this be law, it goes the full length of deciding that it is enough if the defendant has had a chance to avoid inflicting the harm complained of. And it may well be argued that, although he does wisely to ransom his life as he best may, there is no reason why he should be allowed to intentionally and permanently transfer his misfortunes to the shoulders of his neighbors.

But there’s one point that’s been left unclear in the previous Lecture and here, and it needs to be addressed. It has been assumed that actions which a person of average intelligence would recognize as dangerous in a given situation would be blameworthy if that person proceeded with them. However, this might not be the case. Imagine that, under the threats of twelve armed men that put his life in jeopardy, a person goes into someone else’s property and takes a horse. In this situation, he is actually considering and choosing to harm another as a result of his action. Yet, that act is neither blameworthy nor punishable. Nonetheless, it might be actionable, and Rolle, C. J. ruled that it was in Gilbert v. Stone. /1/ If this is indeed the law, it clearly establishes that it is sufficient if the defendant had an opportunity to avoid causing the harm in question. It could also be argued that while it’s wise for him to save his life as best he can, there’s no justification for him to intentionally and permanently offload his troubles onto his neighbors.

It cannot be inferred, from the mere circumstance that certain conduct is made actionable, that therefore the law regards it as wrong, or seeks to prevent it. Under our mill acts a man has to pay for flowing his neighbor's lands, in the same way that he has to pay in trover for converting his neighbor's goods. Yet the law approves and encourages the flowing of lands for the erection of mills.

It can't be assumed, just because certain actions can lead to legal consequences, that the law sees them as wrong or aims to stop them. Under our mill laws, a person has to compensate for flooding their neighbor's land, just like they have to pay in trover for taking their neighbor's property. Still, the law supports and promotes the flooding of land for building mills.

Moral predilections must not be allowed to influence our minds in settling legal distinctions. If we accept the test of the liability alone, how do we distinguish between trover and the mill acts? Or between conduct which is prohibited, and that which is merely taxed? The only distinction which I can see is in the difference of the collateral consequences attached to the two classes of conduct. In the one, the maxim in pari delicto potior est [149] conditio defendentis, and the invalidity of contracts contemplating it, show that the conduct is outside the protection of the law. In the other, it is otherwise. /1/ This opinion is confirmed by the fact, that almost the only cases in which the distinction between prohibition and taxation comes up concern the application of these maxims.

Moral preferences shouldn't influence our thinking when it comes to defining legal differences. If we look only at liability, how do we tell apart trover and the mill acts? Or differentiate between actions that are banned and those that are simply taxed? The only difference I see lies in the collateral consequences linked to the two types of actions. In one case, the principle in pari delicto potior est [149] conditio defendentis, along with the invalidity of contracts based on it, indicates that the conduct falls outside legal protection. In the other case, it's different. /1/ This viewpoint is supported by the fact that almost the only situations where we see the distinction between prohibition and taxation involve these principles.

But if this be true, liability to an action does not necessarily import wrong-doing. And this may be admitted without at all impairing the force of the argument in the foregoing Lecture, which only requires that people should not be made to pay for accidents which they could not have avoided.

But if this is true, being liable to a lawsuit doesn’t automatically mean someone did something wrong. This can be accepted without weakening the argument made in the previous Lecture, which only requires that people shouldn’t have to pay for accidents they couldn’t have prevented.

It is doubtful, however, whether the ruling of Chief Justice Rolle would now be followed. The squib case, Scott v. Shepherd, and the language of some text-books, are more or less opposed to it. /2/ If the latter view is law, then an act must in general not only be dangerous, but one which would be blameworthy on the part of the average man, in order to make the actor liable. But, aside from such exceptional cases as Gilbert v. Stone, the two tests agree, and the difference need not be considered in what follows.

It's uncertain now whether Chief Justice Rolle's ruling would still be followed. The squib case, Scott v. Shepherd, and the wording in some textbooks largely contradict it. /2/ If the latter interpretation is the law, then an act must generally not only be dangerous but also something that would be considered wrong by the average person for the actor to be held liable. However, aside from exceptional cases like Gilbert v. Stone, the two tests align, and the difference doesn't need to be addressed in what comes next.

I therefore repeat, that experience is the test by which it is decided whether the degree of danger attending given conduct under certain known circumstances is sufficient to throw the risk upon the party pursuing it.

I’ll say it again: experience is the measurement used to determine if the level of danger associated with specific actions in certain known situations is enough to shift the risk onto the person taking those actions.

For instance, experience shows that a good many guns supposed to be unloaded go off and hurt people. The ordinarily intelligent and prudent member of the community [150] would foresee the possibility of danger from pointing a gun which he had not inspected into a crowd, and pulling the trigger, although it was said to be unloaded. Hence, it may very properly be held that a man who does such a thing does it at his peril, and that, if damage ensues, he is answerable for it. The co-ordinated acts necessary to point a gun and pull a trigger, and the intent and knowledge shown by the co-ordination of those acts, are all consistent with entire blamelessness. They threaten harm to no one without further facts. But the one additional circumstance of a man in the line and within range of the piece makes the conduct manifestly dangerous to any one who knows the fact. There is no longer any need to refer to the prudent man, or general experience. The facts have taught their lesson, and have generated a concrete and external rule of liability. He who snaps a cap upon a gun pointed in the direction of another person, known by him to be present, is answerable for the consequences.

For example, experience shows that many guns thought to be unloaded can go off and injure people. A normally smart and careful person in the community would recognize the potential danger of pointing a gun that he hasn't checked at a crowd and pulling the trigger, even if it was claimed to be unloaded. Therefore, it's fair to say that someone who does this takes a risk, and if it causes harm, they are responsible for it. The combined actions needed to aim a gun and pull the trigger, along with the intent and awareness shown by those actions, could all be innocent. They don't pose a threat to anyone without additional information. However, the mere fact that a person is in the line of fire and within range of the gun makes the behavior clearly dangerous to anyone who is aware of it. There's no longer a need to reference the cautious person or general experience. The facts have provided their lesson and established a clear and external rule of liability. Anyone who fires a gun aimed at another person, knowing that person is there, is responsible for the results.

The question what a prudent man would do under given circumstances is then equivalent to the question what are the teachings of experience as to the dangerous character of this or that conduct under these or those circumstances; and as the teachings of experience are matters of fact, it is easy to see why the jury should be consulted with regard to them. They are, however, facts of a special and peculiar function. Their only bearing is on the question, what ought to have been done or omitted under the circumstances of the case, not on what was done. Their function is to suggest a rule of conduct.

The question of what a sensible person would do in a particular situation is basically asking what experience teaches us about the risky nature of certain behaviors in those situations. Since these lessons from experience are factual, it’s clear why the jury should be involved in this matter. However, these facts serve a specific purpose. They only relate to what should have been done or avoided in the circumstances of the case, not what actually happened. Their role is to propose a guideline for behavior.

Sometimes courts are induced to lay down rules by facts of a more specific nature; as that the legislature passed a certain statute, and that the case at bar is within [151] the fair meaning of its words; or that the practice of a specially interested class, or of the public at large, has generated a rule of conduct outside the law which it is desirable that the courts should recognize and enforce. These are matters of fact, and have sometimes been pleaded as such. But as their only importance is, that, if believed, they will induce the judges to lay down a rule of conduct, or in other words a rule of law, suggested by them, their tendency in most instances is to disappear as fast as the rules suggested by them become settled. /1/ While the facts are uncertain, as they are still only motives for decision upon the law,—grounds for legislation, so to speak,—the judges may ascertain them in any way which satisfies their conscience. Thus, courts recognize the statutes of the jurisdiction judicially, although the laws of other jurisdictions, with doubtful wisdom, are left to the jury. /2/ They may take judicial cognizance of a custom of merchants. /3/ In former days, at least, they might inquire about it in pais after a demurrer. /4/ They may act on the statement of a special jury, as in the time of Lord Mansfield and his successors, or upon the finding of a common jury based on the testimony of witnesses, as is the practice to-day in this country. But many instances will be found the text-books which show that, when the facts are ascertained, they soon cease to be referred to, and give place to a rule of law.

Sometimes courts are prompted to establish rules based on more specific facts, such as when the legislature passes a certain statute, and the case at hand falls within [151] the clear meaning of its words; or when the practices of a particular interest group or the general public have created a behavioral rule outside the law that the courts should acknowledge and enforce. These are factual matters and have sometimes been argued as such. However, their only significance is that if they are believed, they will lead judges to establish a rule of conduct, or in other words, a legal rule suggested by them. Most of the time, they tend to fade away as the suggested rules become established. While the facts remain uncertain, as they are still just motives for legal decisions—essentially grounds for legislation—the judges can determine them in any way that aligns with their conscience. Thus, courts recognize the statutes of their jurisdiction judicially, while admittedly leaving the laws of other jurisdictions, with questionable wisdom, up to the jury. They can acknowledge customary practices among merchants. In the past, at least, they could inquire about these customs after a demurrer. They can rely on the statements from a special jury, as was done in the era of Lord Mansfield and his successors, or on the findings of a common jury based on witness testimony, like the practice today in this country. However, many examples in the textbooks show that once the facts are determined, they quickly stop being referenced and give way to a rule of law.

[152] The same transition is noticeable with regard to the teachings of experience. There are many cases, no doubt, in which the court would lean for aid upon a jury; but there are also many in which the teaching has been formulated in specific rules. These rules will be found to vary considerably with regard to the number of concomitant circumstances necessary to throw the peril of conduct otherwise indifferent on the actor. As the circumstances become more numerous and complex, the tendency to cut the knot with the jury becomes greater. It will be useful to follow a line of cases up from the simple to the more complicated, by way of illustration. The difficulty of distinguishing rules based on other grounds of policy from those which have been worked out in the field of negligence, will be particularly noticed.

[152] The same shift can be seen in the lessons learned from experience. There are definitely many instances where the court would rely on a jury for guidance; however, there are also many where these lessons have been developed into specific rules. These rules vary significantly in terms of how many accompanying circumstances are needed to shift the responsibility of otherwise neutral actions onto the actor. As the circumstances become more numerous and complicated, the tendency to resolve the situation with the jury increases. It will be helpful to examine a series of cases from the simple to the more complex for illustration. The challenge of distinguishing rules based on other policy considerations from those that have been developed in the area of negligence will be particularly noted.

In all these cases it will be found that there has been a voluntary act on the part of the person to be charged. The reason for this requirement was shown in the foregoing Lecture. Unnecessary though it is for the defendant to have intended or foreseen the evil which he has caused, it is necessary that he should have chosen the conduct which led to it. But it has also been shown that a voluntary act is not enough, and that even a co-ordinated series of acts or conduct is often not enough by itself. But the co-ordination of a series of acts shows a further intent than is necessarily manifested by any single act, and sometimes proves with almost equal certainty the knowledge of one or more concomitant circumstances. And there are cases where conduct with only the intent and knowledge thus necessarily implied is sufficient to throw the risk of it on the actor.

In all these cases, it will be found that the person being charged acted voluntarily. The reason for this requirement was explained in the previous Lecture. While it’s unnecessary for the defendant to have intended or foreseen the harm they caused, it is essential that they chose the actions that led to it. However, it has also been demonstrated that a voluntary act alone isn’t enough, and even a coordinated series of actions may often fall short on its own. Yet, the coordination of a series of actions indicates a greater intent than is typically shown by any single action and can sometimes clearly demonstrate the knowledge of one or more related circumstances. There are situations where conduct, with only the intent and knowledge that are necessarily implied, is enough to shift the risk onto the actor.

For instance, when a man does the series of acts called [153] walking, it is assumed for all purposes of responsibility that he knows the earth is under his feet. The conduct per se is indifferent, to be sure. A man may go through the motions of walking without legal peril, if he chooses to practise on a private treadmill; but if he goes through the same motions on the surface of the earth, it cannot be doubted that he knows that the earth is there. With that knowledge, he acts at his peril in certain respects. If he crosses his neighbor's boundary, he is a trespasser. The reasons for this strict rule have been partially discussed in the last Lecture. Possibly there is more of history or of past or present notions of policy its explanation than is there suggested, and at any rate I do not care to justify the rule. But it is intelligible. A man who walks knows that he is moving over the surface of the earth, he knows that he is surrounded by private estates which he has no right to enter, and he knows that his motion, unless properly guided, will carry him into those estates. He is thus warned, and the burden of his conduct is thrown upon himself.

For example, when someone engages in the activity known as [153] walking, it is assumed for all responsibility that they are aware the ground is beneath them. The action itself is neutral, of course. A person can walk on a private treadmill without any legal consequences, but if they perform the same action on the actual ground, it’s clear they know the ground is there. With that knowledge, they are responsible for their actions in certain ways. If they cross into their neighbor’s property, they are trespassing. The reasons for this strict rule have been partially covered in the last Lecture. There may be more historical or current policy-related explanations for it than have been mentioned, and I’m not particularly interested in justifying the rule. However, it makes sense. A person who walks understands they are moving across the surface of the earth, realizes they are surrounded by private properties that they can’t enter, and knows that if they aren’t careful, they might end up on those properties. They are therefore forewarned, and the responsibility for their actions falls on them.

But the act of walking does not throw the peril of all possible consequences upon him. He may run a man down in the street, but he is not liable for that unless he does it negligently. Confused as the law is with cross-lights of tradition, and hard as we may find it to arrive at perfectly satisfactory general theory, it does distinguish in a pretty sensible way, according to the nature and degree of the different perils incident to a given situation.

But walking doesn't automatically put all potential consequences on him. He might accidentally hit someone in the street, but he isn't responsible for that unless he's negligent. Although the law is complicated by various traditions, and it may be difficult to develop a completely satisfying general theory, it does differentiate quite reasonably based on the nature and level of different dangers present in a specific situation.

From the simple case of walking we may proceed to the more complex cases of dealings with tangible objects of property. It may be said that, generally speaking, a man meddles with such things at his own risk. It does not [154] matter how honestly he may believe that they belong to himself, or are free to the public, or that he has a license from the owner, or that the case is one in which the law has limited the rights of ownership; he takes the chance of how the fact may turn out, and if the fact is otherwise than as he supposes, he must answer for his conduct. As has been already suggested, he knows that he is exercising more or less dominion over property, or that he is injuring it; he must make good his right if it is challenged.

From the straightforward act of walking, we can move on to more complicated situations involving tangible property. Generally speaking, a person engages with such items at their own risk. It doesn’t matter how honestly they believe that the items belong to them, are publicly available, or that they have permission from the owner, or even if the law has restricted ownership rights in some way; they take the risk of how things might actually turn out, and if the reality is different from what they assumed, they have to be accountable for their actions. As mentioned earlier, they know they are exerting some level of control over the property or possibly damaging it; they must prove their right to the item if it's contested.

Whether this strict rule is based on the common grounds of liability, or upon some special consideration of past or present policy, policy has set some limits to it, as was mentioned in the foregoing Lecture.

Whether this strict rule is based on the common grounds of liability or on some special aspect of past or present policy, there are limits to it as policy has established, as mentioned in the previous lecture.

Another case of conduct which is at the risk of the party without further knowledge than it necessarily imports, is the keeping of a tiger or bear, or other animal of a species commonly known to be ferocious. If such an animal escapes and does damage, the owner is liable simply on proof that he kept it. In this instance the comparative remoteness of the moment of choice in the line of causation from the effect complained of, will be particularly noticed. Ordinary cases of liability arise out of a choice which was the proximate cause of the harm upon which the action is founded. But here there is usually no question of negligence in guarding the beast. It is enough in most, if not in all cases, that the owner has chosen to keep it. Experience has shown that tigers and bears are alert to find means of escape, and that, if they escape, they are very certain to do harm of a serious nature. The possibility of a great danger has the same effect as the probability of a less one, and the law throws the risk of [155] the venture on the person who introduces the peril into the community.

Another case where a party is at risk without any further knowledge than what is inherently understood is the keeping of a tiger or bear, or any other known ferocious animal. If such an animal escapes and causes damage, the owner is liable simply by proving that they kept it. In this situation, the relative distance between the moment of choosing to keep the animal and the resulting harm will be especially noted. Ordinary liability usually stems from a choice that is closely linked to the harm that is the basis for the action. However, in this case, there’s typically no issue of negligence regarding how the animal was guarded. In most, if not all, cases, it’s sufficient that the owner decided to keep it. Experience has shown that tigers and bears are quick to find ways to escape, and when they do escape, they are highly likely to cause serious harm. The potential for significant danger has the same effect as the likelihood of a lesser one, and the law places the risk of [155] the venture on the individual who brings the danger into the community.

This remoteness of the opportunity of choice goes far to show that this risk is thrown upon the owner for other reasons than the ordinary one of imprudent conduct. It has been suggested that the liability stood upon remote inadvertence. /1/ But the law does not forbid a man to keep a menagerie, or deem it in any way blameworthy. It has applied nearly as strict a rule to dealings which are even more clearly beneficial to the community than a show of wild beasts.

This distance from the opportunity to make a choice clearly indicates that this risk falls on the owner for reasons beyond just careless behavior. Some have argued that the liability is based on remote oversight. /1/ However, the law doesn’t prevent someone from owning a zoo, nor does it consider it wrong in any way. It has enforced nearly as strict a standard on transactions that are even more obviously beneficial to the community than a display of wild animals.

This seems to be one of those cases where the ground of liability is to be sought in policy coupled with tradition, rather than in any form of blameworthiness, or the existence of such a chance to avoid doing the harm as a man is usually allowed. But the fact that remote inadvertence has been suggested for an explanation illustrates what has been said about the difficulty of deciding whether a given rule is founded on special grounds, or has been worked out within the sphere of negligence, when once a special rule has been laid down.

This appears to be one of those situations where the basis for liability comes from policy and tradition, rather than from any kind of wrongdoing or the chance to avoid causing harm that a person typically has. However, the suggestion that distant neglect could explain this highlights the challenge of determining whether a particular rule is based on specific reasons or has been developed within the realm of negligence, once a special rule has been established.

It is further to be noticed that there is no question of the defendant's knowledge of the nature of tigers, although without that knowledge he cannot be said to have intelligently chosen to subject the community to danger. Here again even in the domain of knowledge the law applies its principle of averages. The fact that tigers and bears are dangerous is so generally known, that a man who keeps them is presumed to know their peculiarities. In other words, he does actually know that he has an animal with certain teeth, claws, and so forth, and he must find out the [156] rest of what an average member of the community would know, at his peril.

It’s also important to note that there’s no doubt about the defendant's understanding of tigers, but without that understanding, he can’t be seen as having made an informed choice to put the community at risk. Again, even in terms of knowledge, the law applies its principle of averages. The fact that tigers and bears are dangerous is so widely known that anyone who keeps them is assumed to understand their characteristics. In other words, he actually knows he has an animal with certain teeth, claws, and so on, and he needs to figure out the [156] rest of what an average person would know, at his own risk.

What is true as to damages in general done by ferocious wild beasts is true as to a particular class of damages done by domestic cattle, namely, trespasses upon another's land. This has been dealt with in former Lectures, and it is therefore needless to do more than to recall it here, and to call attention to the distinction based on experience and policy between damage which is and that which is not of a kind to be expected. Cattle generally stray and damage cultivated land when they get upon it. They only exceptionally hurt human beings.

What is true about the damages caused by wild animals is also true for a specific type of damage caused by domestic cattle, specifically when they trespass on someone else's land. This has been covered in earlier lectures, so it’s sufficient to just mention it here and highlight the difference, based on experience and policy, between damage that is expected and damage that is not. Cattle tend to wander onto cultivated land and cause damage when they do. They rarely injure people.

I need not recur to the possible historical connection of either of these last forms of liability with the noxoe deditio, because, whether that origin is made out or not, the policy of the rule has been accepted as sound, and carried further in England within the last few years by the doctrine that a man who brings upon his land and keeps there anything likely to do mischief if it escape, must keep it in at his peril. /1/ The strictness of this principle will vary in different jurisdictions, as the balance varies between the advantages to the public and the dangers to individuals from the conduct in question. Danger of harm to others is not the only thing to be considered, as has been said already. The law allows some harms to be intentionally inflicted, and a fortiori some risks to be intentionally run. In some Western States a man is not required to keep his cattle fenced in. Some courts have refused to follow Rylands v. Fletcher. /2/ On the other hand, the principle has been applied to artificial [157] reservoirs of water, to cesspools, to accumulations of snow and ice upon a building by reason of the form of its roof, and to party walls. /1/

I don’t need to go over the potential historical link between these recent forms of liability and the noxoe deditio, because whether that connection is proven or not, the reasoning behind the rule has been accepted as valid. This has been further explored in England in recent years with the idea that anyone who brings something onto their property that could cause harm if it escapes must keep it there at their own risk. /1/ The strictness of this principle will differ across various areas, depending on the trade-off between the benefits to the public and the risks to individuals from such actions. The potential harm to others isn’t the only factor to consider, as already mentioned. The law permits certain harms to be intentionally inflicted, and even more so, allows some risks to be intentionally taken. In some Western states, people aren’t required to keep their livestock enclosed. Some courts have chosen not to follow the ruling in Rylands v. Fletcher. /2/ On the flip side, this principle has been applied to artificial [157] reservoirs, cesspools, snow and ice buildup on buildings due to the shape of their roofs, and shared walls. /1/

In these cases, as in that of ferocious animals, it is no excuse that the defendant did not know, and could not have found out, the weak point from which the dangerous object escaped. The period of choice was further back, and, although he was not to blame, he was bound at his peril to know that the object was a continual threat to his neighbors, and that is enough to throw the risk of the business on him.

In these situations, just like with dangerous animals, it's not a valid excuse that the defendant didn't know, and couldn't have figured out, the weak point from which the dangerous object got away. The time to make a choice was earlier, and even though he wasn't at fault, he had to understand that the object was a constant threat to those around him, and that's enough to place the risk of the situation on him.

I now pass to cases one degree more complex than those so far considered. In these there must be another concomitant circumstance known to the party in addition to those of which the knowledge is necessarily or practically proved by his conduct. The cases which naturally suggest themselves again concern animals. Experience as interpreted by the English law has shown that dogs, rams, and bulls are in general of a tame and mild nature, and that, if any one of them does by chance exhibit a tendency to bite, butt, or gore, it is an exceptional phenomenon. Hence it is not the law that a man keeps dogs, rams, bulls, and other like tame animals at his peril as to the personal damages which they may inflict, unless he knows or has notice that the particular animal kept by him has the abnormal tendency which they do sometimes show. The law has, however, been brought a little nearer to actual experience by statute in many jurisdictions.

I will now discuss cases that are slightly more complex than those we've looked at so far. In these cases, there must be an additional factor that the person is aware of, in addition to what is obvious from their behavior. The examples that come to mind again involve animals. Experience, as interpreted by English law, has shown that dogs, rams, and bulls are generally tame and mild. If one of these animals happens to show a tendency to bite, butt, or gore, it's considered an unusual occurrence. Therefore, the law doesn’t hold a person liable for the actions of dogs, rams, bulls, and other similar tame animals unless they know or have been informed that their specific animal has the abnormal behavior that can sometimes occur. However, in many places, the law has been updated to better reflect actual experiences through legislation.

Now let us go one step farther still. A man keeps an unbroken and unruly horse, knowing it to be so. That is not enough to throw the risk of its behavior on him. The [158] tendency of the known wildness is not dangerous generally, but only under particular circumstances. Add to keeping, the attempt to break the horse; still no danger to the public is disclosed. But if the place where the owner tries to break it is a crowded thoroughfare, the owner knows an additional circumstance which, according to common experience, makes this conduct dangerous, and therefore must take the risk of what harm may be done. /1/ On the other hand, if a man who was a good rider bought a horse with no appearance of vice and mounted it to ride home, there would be no such apparent danger as to make him answerable if the horse became unruly and did damage. /2/ Experience has measured the probabilities and draws the line between the two cases.

Now let’s take it a step further. A person owns a wild and uncontrollable horse, fully aware of its nature. That alone isn’t enough to shift the risk of its behavior onto him. The [158] tendency of the known wildness isn’t generally dangerous, but only in specific situations. If, in addition to owning it, he tries to tame the horse, there’s still no risk to the public. However, if he chooses to try taming it in a busy street, he is aware of an extra factor that, based on common experience, makes his actions risky, and he must accept the responsibility for any harm that could result. On the other hand, if a competent rider buys a horse that shows no signs of being problematic and gets on it to ride home, there would be no clear danger that would make him liable if the horse suddenly acted up and caused damage. Experience has assessed the probabilities and defines the boundary between these two scenarios.

Whatever may be the true explanation of the rule applied to keeping tigers, or the principle of Rylands v. Fletcher, in the last cases we have entered the sphere of negligence, and, if we take a case lying somewhere between the two just stated, and add somewhat to the complexity of the circumstances, we shall find that both conduct and standard would probably be left without much discrimination to the jury, on the broad issue whether the defendant had acted as a prudent man would have done under the circumstances.

No matter what the real explanation is for the rule about keeping tigers or the principle from Rylands v. Fletcher, in the last cases, we have entered the area of negligence. If we take a case that falls somewhere between the two mentioned and add a bit more complexity to the situation, we’ll likely find that both behavior and standards would be hard for the jury to distinguish, focusing instead on the general question of whether the defendant acted like a reasonable person would have in that situation.

As to wrongs called malicious or intentional it is not necessary to mention the different classes a second time, and to find them a place in this series. As has been seen, they vary in the number of circumstances which must be known. Slander is conduct which is very generally at the risk of [159] the speaker, because, as charges of the kind with which it deals are manifestly detrimental, the questions which practically arise for the most part concern the defence of truth or privilege. Deceit requires more, but still simple facts. Statements do not threaten the harm in question unless they are made under such circumstances as to naturally lead to action, and are made on insufficient grounds.

When it comes to wrongs that are called malicious or intentional, it's not necessary to mention the different categories again or slot them into this discussion. As we've seen, they differ in terms of the number of circumstances that need to be known. Slander is a behavior that usually puts the speaker at risk because accusations of this nature are clearly harmful. The main issues that arise often revolve around defending the truth or claiming privilege. Deceit requires more, but still involves straightforward facts. Statements don’t pose a threat of harm unless they’re made in circumstances that naturally lead to action and are based on insufficient evidence.

It is not, however, without significance, that certain wrongs are described in language importing intent. The harm in such cases is most frequently done intentionally, if intent to cause a certain harm is shown, there need to prove knowledge of facts which made it that harm would follow. Moreover, it is often much easier to prove intent directly, than to prove the knowledge which would make it unnecessary.

It is important to note that some wrongs are described in a way that indicates intent. The damage in these situations is usually done on purpose; if there is proof of intent to cause a specific harm, it isn't necessary to demonstrate knowledge of the facts that would lead to that harm. Furthermore, it is often much easier to prove intent directly than to prove the knowledge that would make it unnecessary.

The cases in which a man is treated as the responsible cause of a given harm, on the one hand, extend beyond those in which his conduct was chosen in actual contemplation of that result, and in which, therefore, he may be to have chosen to cause that harm; and, on the other hand, they do not extend to all instances where the damages would not have happened but for some remote election his part. Generally speaking, the choice will be found to have extended further than a simple act, and to co-ordinated acts into conduct. Very commonly it will have extended further still, to some external consequence. But generally, also, it will be found to have stopped short of the consequence complained of.

The situations in which a person is held accountable for causing harm go beyond just those where they intentionally chose to cause that specific result. However, it doesn't cover every case where the damage wouldn't have occurred without some distant decision they made. Usually, the person's choice involves more than just a single action; it often includes a series of coordinated actions. Often, it may even relate to some external outcome. However, in most cases, it tends to stop short of the specific consequence that's being complained about.

The question in each case is whether the actual choice, or, in other words, the actually contemplated result, was near enough to the remoter result complained of to throw the peril of it upon the actor.

The question in each case is whether the actual choice, or, in other words, the result that was really considered, was close enough to the more distant result being complained about to shift the risk of it onto the person acting.

[160] Many of the cases which have been put thus far are cases where the proximate cause of the loss was intended to be produced by the defendant. But it will be seen that the same result may be caused by a choice at different points. For instance, a man is sued for having caused his neighbor's house to burn down. The simplest case is, that he actually intended to burn it down. If so, the length of the chain of physical causes intervening is of no importance, and has no bearing on the case.

[160] Many of the cases discussed so far involve situations where the defendant intended to cause the loss. However, it's clear that the same outcome can result from decisions made at different points. For example, a person is sued for causing their neighbor's house to catch fire. The simplest scenario is that they actually planned to set it on fire. If that's the case, the number of physical causes in between doesn't matter and has no impact on the case.

But the choice may have stopped one step farther back. The defendant may have intended to light a fire on his own land, and may not have intended to burn the house. Then the nature of the intervening and concomitant physical causes becomes of the highest importance. The question will be the degree of danger attending the contemplated (and therefore chosen) effect of the defendant's conduct under the circumstances known to him. If this was very plain and very great, as, for instance, if his conduct consisted in lighting stubble near a haystack close to the house, and if the manifest circumstances were that the house was of wood, the stubble very dry, and the wind in a dangerous quarter, the court would probably rule that he was liable. If the defendant lighted an ordinary fire in a fireplace in an adjoining house, having no knowledge that the fireplace was unsafely constructed, the court would probably rule that he was not liable. Midway, complicated and doubtful cases would go to the jury.

But the choice might have actually gone one step further back. The defendant might have meant to start a fire on his own property and might not have intended to burn down the house. Then, the nature of the intervening and simultaneous physical causes becomes crucial. The question will be how dangerous the intended (and therefore chosen) outcome of the defendant's actions was, given what he knew at the time. If this danger was very clear and significant—like if he lit stubble near a haystack close to the house, and the obvious circumstances were that the house was made of wood, the stubble was very dry, and the wind was blowing dangerously—the court would likely decide that he was liable. If the defendant lit a regular fire in a fireplace in a nearby house, without knowing that the fireplace was poorly constructed, the court would probably decide that he was not liable. Cases that are complicated and uncertain would go to the jury.

But the defendant may not even have intended to set the fire, and his conduct and intent may have been simply to fire a gun, or, remoter still, to walk across a room, in doing which he involuntarily upset a bottle of acid. So that cases may go to the jury by reason of the remoteness [161] of the choice in the series of events, as well as because of the complexity of the circumstances attending the act or conduct. The difference is, perhaps, rather dramatic than substantial.

But the defendant might not have even meant to start the fire; his actions and intentions could have simply been to fire a gun, or even more distantly, just to walk across a room, during which he accidentally knocked over a bottle of acid. This means that cases can be presented to the jury due to the remoteness of the choices made during the series of events, as well as because of the complicated circumstances surrounding the act or behavior. The difference is likely more dramatic than it is significant.

But the philosophical analysis of every wrong begins by determining what the defendant has actually chosen, that is to say, what his voluntary act or conduct has been, and what consequences he has actually contemplated as flowing from them, and then goes on to determine what dangers attended either the conduct under the known circumstances, or its contemplated consequence under the contemplated circumstances.

But analyzing every wrongdoing starts by figuring out what the defendant has really chosen, meaning what their voluntary actions or behavior have been, and what outcomes they actually expected from them. Then, it looks at the potential risks involved either in that behavior given the known circumstances, or in the expected consequences based on those anticipated circumstances.

Take a case like the glancing of Sir Walter Tyrrel's arrow. If an expert marksman contemplated that the arrow would hit a certain person, cadit qucoestio. If he contemplated that it would glance in the direction of another person, but contemplated no more than that, in order to judge of his liability we must go to the end of his fore-sight, and, assuming the foreseen event to happen, consider what the manifest danger was then. But if no such event was foreseen, the marksman must be judged by the circumstances known to him at the time of shooting.

Consider the example of Sir Walter Tyrrel's arrow. If an expert marksman believed that the arrow would hit a specific person, that's the end of the question. If he thought it would merely glance toward someone else, but didn't think any further than that, to determine his liability, we need to look at the extent of what he foresaw. Assuming that the anticipated event occurs, we then need to assess what the obvious danger was at that moment. However, if he didn't foresee any such event, the marksman should be evaluated based on what he knew at the time of the shot.

The theory of torts may be summed up very simply. At the two extremes of the law are rules determined by policy without reference of any kind to morality. Certain harms a man may inflict even wickedly; for certain others he must answer, although his conduct has been prudent and beneficial to the community.

The theory of torts can be summed up quite simply. At the two ends of the law are rules shaped by policy without any consideration for morality. A person may cause some harms even intentionally; for other harms, he must be held accountable, even if his actions were careful and beneficial to the community.

But in the main the law started from those intentional wrongs which are the simplest and most pronounced cases, as well as the nearest to the feeling of revenge which leads to self-redress. It thus naturally adopted the vocabulary, [162] and in some degree the tests, of morals. But as the law has grown, even when its standards have continued to model themselves upon those of morality, they have necessarily become external, because they have considered, not the actual condition of the particular defendant, but whether his conduct would have been wrong in the fair average member of the community, whom he is expected to equal at his peril.

But generally, the law started with intentional wrongs, which are the simplest and most obvious cases, as well as the closest to the feelings of revenge that lead to taking matters into one's own hands. It naturally adopted the vocabulary, [162] and to some extent the criteria, of morality. However, as the law has evolved, even as its standards continued to align with those of morality, they have inevitably become external, because they consider not the actual situation of the individual defendant, but whether his behavior would have been considered wrong by the average person in the community, whom he is expected to match at his own risk.

In general, this question will be determined by considering the degree of danger attending the act or conduct under the known circumstances. If there is danger that harm to another will follow, the act is generally wrong in the sense of the law.

In general, this question will be decided by looking at how dangerous the act or behavior is based on what is known about the situation. If there’s a risk that someone else could get hurt, the act is usually considered wrong by the law.

But in some cases the defendant's conduct may not have been morally wrong, and yet he may have chosen to inflict the harm, as where he has acted in fear of his life. In such cases he will be liable, or not, according as the law makes moral blameworthiness, within the limits explained above, the ground of liability, or deems it sufficient if the defendant has had reasonable warning of danger before acting. This distinction, however, is generally unimportant, and the known tendency of the act under the known circumstances to do harm may be accepted as the general test of conduct.

But in some cases, the defendant's behavior might not have been morally wrong, yet he may have chosen to cause harm, such as when he acted out of fear for his life. In these instances, he will be held responsible or not, depending on whether the law considers moral blameworthiness, within the limits explained above, as the basis for liability, or if it sees that reasonable warning of danger before acting is enough. However, this distinction is usually not significant, and the recognized tendency of the act under known circumstances to cause harm can generally be accepted as the main test of behavior.

The tendency of a given act to cause harm under given circumstances must be determined by experience. And experience either at first hand or through the voice of the jury is continually working out concrete rules, which in form are still more external and still more remote from a reference to the moral condition of the defendant, than even the test of the prudent man which makes the first stage of the division between law and morals. It does this in the domain [163] of wrongs described as intentional, as systematically as in those styled unintentional or negligent.

The likelihood of an action causing harm in specific situations must be assessed through experience. This experience, whether obtained directly or through the jury's perspective, constantly develops concrete rules that are increasingly external and detached from the defendant's moral state, even more so than the standard of the reasonable person, which forms the initial distinction between law and ethics. This occurs in both areas of wrongdoing labeled as intentional and those categorized as unintentional or negligent.

But while the law is thus continually adding to its specific rules, it does not adopt the coarse and impolitic principle that a man acts always at his peril. On the contrary, its concrete rules, as well as the general questions addressed to the jury, show that the defendant must have had at least a fair chance of avoiding the infliction of harm before he becomes answerable for such a consequence of his conduct. And it is certainly arguable that even a fair chance to avoid bringing harm to pass is not sufficient to throw upon a person the peril of his conduct, unless, judged by average standards, he is also to blame for what he does.

But while the law is constantly adding to its specific rules, it doesn’t follow the blunt and unwise idea that a person always acts at their own risk. Instead, its detailed rules, along with the general questions posed to the jury, indicate that the defendant must have had at least a fair opportunity to prevent causing harm before they are held responsible for the results of their actions. It can also be argued that having a fair chance to avoid causing harm isn’t enough to place the risk of their actions on someone, unless, based on average standards, they can also be considered at fault for what they did.

[164]

[164]





LECTURE V. — THE BAILEE AT COMMON LAW.

So far the discussion has been confined to the general principles of liability, and to the mode of ascertaining the point at which a man begins to act at his own peril. But it does not matter to a man whether he acts at his own peril or not, unless harm comes of it, and there must always be some one within reach of the consequences of the act before any harm can be done. Furthermore, and more to the point, there are certain forms of harm which are not likely to be suffered, and which can never be complained of by any one except a person who stands in a particular relation to the actor or to some other person or thing. Thus it is neither a harm nor a wrong to take fish from a pond unless the pond is possessed or owned by some one, and then only to the possessor or owner. It is neither a harm nor a wrong to abstain from delivering a bale of wool at a certain time and place, unless a binding promise has been made so to deliver it, and then it is a wrong only to the promisee.

Up to now, the discussion has focused on the general principles of liability and how to determine when someone starts acting at their own risk. However, it doesn’t really matter to someone whether they are acting at their own risk unless something harmful results from it, and there always has to be someone affected by the consequences of their actions before any harm can occur. Moreover, there are certain types of harm that are unlikely to happen and can only be complained about by someone who has a specific relationship to the actor or to another person or thing. For example, it’s neither harmful nor wrong to take fish from a pond unless the pond is owned by someone, and then it only matters to the owner. Similarly, it’s neither harmful nor wrong to fail to deliver a bale of wool at a specific time and place, unless there’s a binding promise to do so, in which case it’s a wrong only to the person who was promised the delivery.

The next thing to be done is to analyze those special relations out of which special rights and duties arise. The chief of them—and I mean by the word "relations" relations of fact simply—are possession and contract, and I shall take up those subjects successively.

The next step is to analyze the specific relationships that give rise to particular rights and responsibilities. The most important ones—by "relationships," I mean factual relationships—are possession and contract, and I will address these topics one after the other.

The test of the theory of possession which prevails in any system of law is to be found in its mode of dealing [165] who have a thing within their power, but not own it, or assert the position of an owner for with regard to it, bailees, in a word. It is therefore, as a preliminary to understanding the common-law theory of possession, to study the common law with regard to bailees.

The way a legal system tests the theory of possession is by examining how it handles those who have something in their control but do not own it, or who claim to act as if they are the owner—specifically, bailees. Therefore, to grasp the common-law theory of possession, it's essential to explore the common law related to bailees.

The state of things which prevailed on the border between England and Scotland within recent times, and which is brought back in the flesh by the ballad of the Fray O'Suport, is very like that which in an earlier century left its skeleton in the folk-laws of Germany and England. Cattle were the principal property known, and cattle-stealing the principal form of wrongful taking of property. Of law there was very little, and what there was depended almost wholly upon the party himself to enforce. The Salic Law of the fifth century and the Anglo-Saxon laws of Alfred are very full in their directions about following the trail. If the cattle were come up with before three days were gone, the pursuer had the fight to take and keep them, subject only to swearing that he lost them against his will. If more than three days went by before the cattle were found, the defendant might swear, if he could, to facts which would disprove the claimant's loss.

The situation on the border between England and Scotland recently, which is vividly depicted in the ballad of the Fray O'Suport, resembles what existed in earlier centuries, leaving behind a legacy in the folk laws of Germany and England. Cattle were the main form of wealth, and stealing cattle was the most common type of property crime. There was very little law, and what existed relied largely on the individuals to enforce it. The Salic Law from the fifth century and the Anglo-Saxon laws of Alfred provide detailed instructions about tracking stolen cattle. If the cattle were recovered within three days, the pursuer had the right to take and keep them, as long as they swore they lost them unwillingly. If more than three days passed before the cattle were found, the defendant could swear to evidence that would challenge the claimant's claim of loss.

This procedure was in truth a legal procedure; but it depended for its beginning and for its execution on the party making the claim. From its "executive" nature, it could hardly have been started by any other than the person on the spot, in whose keeping the cattle were. The oath was to the effect that the party had lost possession against his will. But if all that a man had to swear was that he had lost possession against his will, it is a natural conclusion that the right to take the oath and make use of [166] the procedure depended on possession, and not on ownership. Possession was not merely sufficient, but it was essential. Only he who was in possession could say that he had lost the property against his will, just as only he who was on the spot could follow the cattle. /1/

This process was actually a legal procedure; however, it relied on the party making the claim to start and carry it out. Given its "executive" nature, it could only have been initiated by the person present who had the cattle in their care. The oath was that the person had lost possession against their will. But if all that someone needed to swear was that they lost possession against their will, it's reasonable to conclude that the right to take the oath and use [166] the procedure was based on possession, not ownership. Possession was not just sufficient; it was crucial. Only someone who was in possession could claim they lost the property against their will, just as only the person present could track the cattle. /1/

This, so far as known, was the one means afforded by the early law of our race for the recovery of property lost against one's will. So that, in a word, this procedure, modelled on the self-redress natural to the case which gave rise to it, was the only remedy, was confined to the man in possession, and was not open to the owner unless he was that man.

This, as far as is known, was the only way provided by the early laws of our people to recover property lost against one's will. In short, this process, modeled after the self-defense typical of the situation that led to it, was the sole remedy, limited to the person in possession, and was not available to the owner unless he was that person.

To this primitive condition of society has been traced a rule which maintained itself to later times and a more civilized procedure, that, if chattels were intrusted by their owner to another person, the bailee, and not the bailor, was the proper party to sue for their wrongful appropriation by a third. It followed that if the bailee, or person [167] so intrusted, sold or gave the goods in his charge to another, the owner could only look to the bailee, and could not sue the stranger; not from any principle in favor of trade, intended to protect those who bought in good faith from parties in possession, but because there was no form of action known which was open to him. But as the remedies were all in the bailee's hands, it also followed that he was bound to hold his bailor harmless. If the goods were lost, it was no excuse that they were stolen without his fault. He alone could recover the lost property, and therefore he was bound to do so.

To this basic state of society, a rule has been linked that continued into later times and more civilized practices. This rule states that if someone hands over their belongings to another person (the bailee), it's the bailee, not the original owner (the bailor), who is the right person to sue if those belongings are wrongfully taken by someone else. So, if the bailee sold or gave away the goods they were in charge of, the owner could only go after the bailee and couldn't sue the third party. This wasn't meant to protect buyers acting in good faith from those in possession, but simply because there wasn't a legal way for the owner to take action. However, since all the remedies were in the bailee's control, it also meant that the bailee had to keep the bailor safe from any losses. If the goods were lost, it didn't matter if they were stolen through no fault of the bailee; they were still responsible for recovering the lost property.

In the course of time this reason ceased to exist. An owner out of possession could sue the wrongful taker of his property, as well as one who had possession. But the strict liability of the bailee remained, as such rules do remain in the law, long after the causes which gave rise to it had disappeared, and at length we find cause and effect inverted. We read in Beaumanoir (A.D. 1283) that, if a hired thing is stolen, the suit belongs to the bailee, because he is answerable to the person from whom he hired. /1/ At first the bailee was answerable to the owner, because he was the only person who could sue. Now it was said he could sue because he was answerable to the owner.

Over time, this reason disappeared. An owner who doesn't have their property can sue the person who wrongfully took it, just like someone who does have possession can. However, the strict liability of the bailee still applied, as such rules often do in the law, long after the reasons that created them have faded away, leading to a reversal in cause and effect. In Beaumanoir (A.D. 1283), we read that if a borrowed item is stolen, the lawsuit belongs to the bailee, because they are accountable to the person from whom they borrowed it. At first, the bailee was accountable to the owner, since they were the only one who could sue. Now, it was claimed they could sue because they were accountable to the owner.

All the above peculiarities reappear in the Anglo-Norman law, and from that day to this all kinds of bailees have been treated as having possession in a legal sense, as I shall presently show.

All the above peculiarities are present in Anglo-Norman law, and from that day to this, all kinds of bailees have been regarded as having possession in a legal sense, as I will show shortly.

It is desirable to prove the native origin of our law of bailment, in order that, when theory comes to be considered, modern German opinion may not be valued at more than its true worth. The only existing theories on [168] the subject come from Germany. The German philosophers who have written upon law have known no other system than the Roman, and the German lawyers who have philosophized have been professors of Roman law. Some rules which we think clear are against what the German civilians would regard as first principles. To test the value of those principles, or at least to prevent the hasty assumption that they are universal, toward which there is a slight tendency among English writers, it is well to realize that we are dealing with a new system, of which philosophy has not yet taken account.

It’s important to establish that our law of bailment has native roots so that when we look at theory, modern German perspectives aren’t overrated. The only theories on [168] that exist come from Germany. The German philosophers who have explored law have only known the Roman system, and the German lawyers who have contemplated these matters have been teachers of Roman law. Some rules that seem clear to us contradict what German legal experts would consider basic principles. To assess the validity of those principles, or at least to avoid quickly assuming they are universal—which is a slight tendency among English writers—it’s useful to recognize that we are engaging with a new system that philosophy has yet to fully address.

In the first place, we find an action to recover stolen property, which, like the Salic procedure, was based on possession, not on title. Bracton says that one may sue for his chattel as stolen, by the testimony of good men, and that it does not matter whether the thing thus taken was his own property or another's, provided it was in his custody. /1/

In the first place, we have a lawsuit to recover stolen property, which, similar to the Salic procedure, was based on possession rather than ownership. Bracton states that one can sue for their personal property as stolen, using the testimony of reliable witnesses, and it doesn't matter if the item taken was theirs or someone else's, as long as it was in their custody. /1/

The point of especial importance, it will be remembered, was the oath. The oath of the probi homines would seem from the letter of Bracton to have been that the thing was lost (adirata), and this we are expressly told was the fact in a report of the year 1294. "Note that where a man's chattel is lost (ou la chosse de un home est endire), he may count that he [the finder] tortiously detains it, &c., and tortiously for this that whereas he lost the said thing on such a day, &c., he [the loser] came on such a day, &c. [169] (la vynt yl e en jour), and found it in the house of such an one, and told him, &c., and prayed him to restore the Sing, but that he would not restore it, &c., to his damage, &c.; and if he, &c. In this case, the demandant must prove (his own hand the twelfth) that he lost the thing." /1/

The key point to remember is the oath. The oath of the worthy men seems to indicate, according to Bracton’s letter, that the item was lost, and we are explicitly told this was the case in a report from 1294. "Note that when someone's property is lost, they can claim that the finder is wrongfully keeping it, and for this reason, since they lost the item on a certain day, they came on another day and found it in someone's house, and told that person about it, and asked them to return it, but the other person refused, causing them harm; and if that person, etc. In this situation, the person making the claim must prove (by their own hand the twelfth) that they lost the item." /1/

Assuming that as the first step we find a procedure kindred to that of the early German folk-laws, the more important question is whether we find any principles similar to those which have just been explained. One of these, it will be remembered, concerned wrongful transfer by the bailee. We find it laid down in the Year Books that, if I deliver goods to a bailee to keep for me, and he sells or gives them to a stranger, the property is vested in the stranger by the gift, and I cannot maintain trespass against him; but that I have a good remedy against the bailee by writ of detinue (for his failure to return the goods). /2/ These cases have been understood, and it would seem on the whole rightly, not merely to deny trespass to the bailor, but any action whatever. Modern writers have added, however, the characteristically modern qualification, that the purchase must be bona fide, and without notice. /3/ It may be answered, that the proposition extends to gifts as well as to sales by the bailee, that there is no such condition in the old books, and that it is contrary to the spirit of the strict doctrines of the common law to read it in. No lawyer needs to be told that, even so qualified, this is no [170] longer the law. /1/ The doctrine of the Year Books must be regarded as a survival from the primitive times when we have seen the same rule in force, unless we are prepared to believe that in the fifteenth century they had a nicer feeling for the rights of bona fide purchasers than at present.

Assuming we start by finding a procedure similar to those of the early German folk laws, the more important question is whether we can identify any principles that are comparable to the ones just discussed. One of these principles, as we recall, dealt with wrongful transfer by the bailee. It's stated in the Year Books that if I hand over goods to a bailee to keep for me, and he sells or gives them to someone else, the ownership is transferred to that person by the gift, and I cannot sue him for trespass; however, I do have a valid remedy against the bailee through a writ of detinue (for not returning the goods). These cases have been understood, and it seems correctly, not only to deny trespass to the bailor but any action at all. Modern writers have added, though, a typically modern qualification, that the purchase must be made in good faith and without notice. It could be argued that this principle applies to gifts as well as sales by the bailee, that such a condition is absent from the old texts, and that it contradicts the spirit of the strict common law doctrines to insert it. No lawyer needs to be informed that, even with that qualification, this is no [170] longer the law. The doctrine from the Year Books must be seen as a remnant from earlier times when we have observed the same rule being applied, unless we are willing to believe that in the fifteenth century they had a better appreciation for the rights of good faith purchasers than we do today.

The next point in logical order would be the degree of responsibility to which the bailee was held as towards his bailor who intrusted him. But for convenience I will consider first the explanation which was given of the bailee's right of action against third persons wrongfully taking the goods from his possession. The inverted explanation of Beaumanoir will be remembered, that the bailee could sue because he was answerable over, in place of the original rule, that he was answerable over so strictly because only he could sue. We find the same reasoning often repeated in the Year Books, and, indeed, from that day to this it has always been one of the commonplaces of the law. Thus Hankford, then a judge of the Common Bench, says (circa A.D. 1410), /2/ "If a stranger takes beasts in my custody, I shall have a writ of trespass against him, and shall recover the value of the beasts, because I am chargeable for the beasts to my bailor, who has the property." There are cases in which this reasoning was pushed to the conclusion, that if, by the terms of the trust, the bailee was not answerable for the goods if stolen, he would not have an action against the thief. /3/ The same explanation is repeated to this day. Thus we read in a well- known textbook, [171] "For the bailee being responsible to the bailor, if the goods be lost or damaged by negligence, or if he do not deliver them up on lawful demand, it is therefore reasonable that he should have a right of action," &c. /1/ In general, nowadays, a borrower or hirer of property is not answerable if it is taken from him against his will, and if the reason offered were a true one, it would follow that, as he was not answerable over, he could not sue the wrong-doer. It would only be necessary for the wrong-doer to commit a wrong so gross as to free the bailee from responsibility, in order to deprive him of his right of action. The truth is, that any person in possession, whether intrusted and answerable over or not, a finder of property as well as a bailee, can sue any one except the true owner for interfering with his possession, as will be shown more particularly at the end of the next Lecture.

The next logical point to discuss is the level of responsibility the bailee had towards the bailor who entrusted him. However, for convenience, I’ll first cover the explanation given about the bailee's right to take legal action against third parties who wrongfully take the goods from his possession. You'll remember Beaumanoir's reversed explanation, which stated that the bailee could sue because he was liable, rather than the original rule, which held he was liable strictly because only he could sue. We often see the same reasoning in the Year Books, and it has been a legal commonplace from then until now. For example, Hankford, who was a judge of the Common Bench around A.D. 1410, stated, "If a stranger takes beasts in my custody, I can file a writ of trespass against him and recover the value of the beasts because I am accountable for them to my bailor, who owns the property." There are instances where this reasoning extended to the conclusion that if the bailee was not liable for the goods if stolen, he wouldn't have a case against the thief. The same explanation is still relevant today. For example, in a well-known textbook, it states, "For the bailee being responsible to the bailor, if the goods are lost or damaged due to negligence, or if he fails to return them upon lawful demand, it is reasonable that he should have a right of action." In general, nowadays, a borrower or renter of property isn't liable if it's taken from him against his will, and if that reasoning were valid, it would mean that since he wasn't liable, he couldn't sue the wrongdoer. The wrongdoer would only need to commit an offense severe enough to free the bailee from liability to deprive him of his right to take action. In reality, anyone in possession, whether they are entrusted and liable or not, including finders of property as well as bailees, can sue anyone except the true owner for interfering with their possession, as will be discussed further at the end of the next lecture.

The bailor also obtained a right of action against the wrong-doer at a pretty early date. It is laid down by counsel in 48 Edward III., /2/ in an action of trespass by an agister of cattle, that, "in this case, he who has the property may have a writ of trespass, and he who has the custody another writ of trespass. Persay: Sir, it is true. But [172] he who recovers first shall oust the other of the action, and so it shall be in many cases, as if tenant by elegit is ousted, each shall have the assize, and, if the one recover first, the writ of the other is abated, and so here."

The bailor also gained the right to take action against the wrongdoer quite early on. Counsel explains in 48 Edward III., /2/ in a trespass action by a cattle agister, that "in this case, the person with ownership can file a writ of trespass, and the person with custody can file a different writ of trespass. Indeed, it is true. But [172] whoever wins first will prevent the other from pursuing their case, and this applies in many situations, such as if a tenant by elegit is removed; both can pursue the assize, and if one succeeds first, the other's writ is dismissed, and the same applies here."

It would seem from other books that this was spoken of bailments generally, and was not limited to those which are terminable at the pleasure of the bailor. Thus in 22 Edward IV., counsel say, "If I bail to you my goods, and another takes them out of your possession, I shall have good action of trespass quare vi et armis." /1/ And this seems to have been Rolle's understanding in the passage usually relied on by modern courts. /2/

It appears from other writings that this was about bailments in general and wasn't restricted to those that can be ended at the bailor's will. For example, in 22 Edward IV, lawyers state, "If I give you my goods to hold, and someone else takes them from your possession, I will have a valid case for trespass with force." /1/ And this seems to have been Rolle's interpretation in the section commonly referenced by today's courts. /2/

It was to be expected that some action should be given to the bailor as soon as the law had got machinery which could be worked without help from the fresh pursuit and armed hands of the possessor and his friends. To allow the bailor to sue, and to give him trespass, were pretty nearly the same thing before the action on the case was heard of. Many early writs will be found which show that trespass had not always the clear outline which it developed later. The point which seems to be insisted on in the Year Books is, as Brooke sums it up in the margin of his Abridgment, that two shall have an action for a single act,—not that both shall have trespass rather than case. /3/ It should be added that the Year Books quoted do not go beyond the case of a wrongful taking out of the custody of the bailee, the old case of the folk-laws. /4/ Even thus [173] the right to maintain trespass is now denied where bailee has the exclusive right to the goods by lease or lien; /1/ although the doctrine has been repeated with reference to bailments terminable at the pleasure of the bailor. /2/ But the modified rule does not concern the present discussion, any more than the earlier form, because it still leaves open the possessory remedies to all bailees without exception. This appears from the relation of the modified rule to the ancient law; from the fact that Baron Parke, in the just cited case of Manders v. Williams, hints that he would have been prepared to apply the old rule to its full extent but for Gordon v. Harper, and still more obviously from the fact, that the bailee's right to trespass and trover is asserted in the same breath with that of the bailor, as well as proved by express decisions to be cited.

It was expected that some action should be taken by the bailor as soon as the law had a system that could function without relying on the fresh pursuit and force of the possessor and their associates. Allowing the bailor to sue and giving them a claim for trespass were almost the same before the action on the case was introduced. Many early writs illustrate that trespass did not always have the clear definition that it developed later. The main point emphasized in the Year Books is, as Brooke summarizes in the margin of his Abridgment, that two people should have a right to action for a single act—not that both should have trespass rather than case. It should be noted that the Year Books mentioned do not go beyond the case of a wrongful taking from the custody of the bailee, the old case from folk-laws. Even then, the right to maintain a claim for trespass is now denied where the bailee has the exclusive right to the goods through lease or lien; although this doctrine has been reiterated concerning bailments that can be ended at the bailor's discretion. But this modified rule isn’t relevant to the current discussion, just like the earlier version, because it still leaves open the possessory remedies to all bailees without exception. This is evident from the relationship of the modified rule to the ancient law; from the fact that Baron Parke, in the previously cited case of Manders v. Williams, suggested he would have been ready to apply the old rule fully if it weren't for Gordon v. Harper, and even more obviously from the fact that the bailee's right to trespass and trover is stated alongside that of the bailor, as well as confirmed by explicit decisions that will be referenced.

It is true that in Lotan v. Cross, /3/ Lord Ellenborough ruled at nisi prius that a lender could maintain trespass for damage done to a chattel in the hands of a borrower, and that the case is often cited as authority without remark. Indeed, it is sometimes laid down generally, in reputable text-books, that a gratuitous bailment does not change the possession, but leaves it in the bailor; /4/ that a gratuitous bailee is quasi a servant of the bailor, and the possession of one is the possession of the other; and that it is for this reason that, although the bailee may sue on [174] his possession, the bailor has the same actions. /1/ A part of this confusion has already been explained, and the rest will be when I come to speak of servants, between whom and all bailees there is a broad and well-known distinction. But on whatever ground Lotan v. Cross may stand, if on any, it cannot for a moment be admitted that borrowers in general have not trespass and trover. A gratuitous deposit for the sole benefit of the depositor is a much stronger case for the denial of these remedies to the depositary; yet we have a decision by the full court, in which Lord Ellenborough also took part, that a depositary has case, the reasoning implying that a fortiori a borrower would have trespass. And this has always been the law. /2/ It has been seen that a similar doctrine necessarily resulted from the nature of the early German procedure; and the cases cited in the note show that, in this as in other respects, the English followed the traditions of their race.

It is true that in Lotan v. Cross, /3/ Lord Ellenborough decided at nisi prius that a lender could sue for trespass due to damage done to a chattel in the hands of a borrower, and this case is often cited as precedent without comment. In fact, it's sometimes generally stated in reputable textbooks that a gratuitous bailment does not alter possession but keeps it with the bailor; /4/ that a gratuitous bailee is basically a servant of the bailor, and the possession of one is seen as the possession of the other; and that for this reason, although the bailee may sue based on [174] his possession, the bailor has the same rights. /1/ Some of this confusion has already been clarified, and more will be explained when I discuss servants, as there is a clear and well-known distinction between them and all bailees. However, regardless of how Lotan v. Cross may be interpreted, it cannot be denied that borrowers in general do have rights to trespass and trover. A gratuitous deposit solely for the benefit of the depositor is a much stronger case for denying these remedies to the depositary; yet we have a ruling from the full court, which included Lord Ellenborough, that a depositary has a case, suggesting that a borrower would by stronger reasoning have the right to trespass. This has always been the law. /2/ It has been observed that a similar doctrine necessarily arose from the nature of early German procedure; and the cases mentioned in the note demonstrate that, in this and other respects, the English followed the traditions of their ancestry.

The meaning of the rule that all bailees have the possessory remedies is, that in the theory of the common law every bailee has a true possession, and that a bailee recovers on the strength of his possession, just as a finder does, and as even a wrongful possessor may have full damages or a return of the specific thing from a stranger to the title. On the other hand, so far as the possessory actions are still allowed to bailors, it is not on the ground that they also have possession, but is probably by a survival, which [175] explained, and which in the modern form of the an anomaly. /1/ The reason usually given is, that a right of immediate possession is sufficient,—a reason which the notion that the bailor is actually possessed.

The meaning of the rule that all bailees have the possessory remedies is that, according to common law, every bailee has true possession, and a bailee can recover based on that possession, similar to how a finder can and even how a wrongful possessor might receive full damages or the return of the specific item from someone without title. On the other hand, even though possessory actions are still available to bailors, it's not because they have possession too; it's likely due to a survival, which [175] explained, and which in modern terms is an anomaly. The typical reason given is that the right to immediate possession is enough—a reasoning that suggests the bailor is actually in possession.

The point which is essential to understanding the common-law theory of possession is now established: that all bailees from time immemorial have been regarded by the English law as possessors, and entitled to the possessory remedies. It is not strictly necessary to go on and complete the proof that our law of bailment is of pure German descent. But, apart from curiosity, the doctrine remaining to be discussed has had such important influence upon the law of the present day, that I shall follow it out with some care. That doctrine was the absolute responsibility of the bailee to the bailor, if the goods were wrongfully taken from him. /2/

The key point needed to understand the common-law theory of possession is now clear: all bailees have been seen as possessors under English law for a long time, and they are entitled to possessory remedies. It’s not strictly necessary to prove that our law of bailment comes from pure German origins. However, aside from curiosity, the principle we are about to discuss has significantly influenced modern law, so I will explore it in detail. This principle is that the bailee is absolutely responsible to the bailor if the goods are wrongfully taken from him. /2/

The early text-writers are not as instructive as might be hoped, owing to the influence of the Roman law. Glanvil, however, says in terms that, if a borrowed thing be destroyed or lost in any way while in the borrower's custody, he is absolutely bound to return a reasonable price. /3/ So does Bracton, who partially repeats but modifies the language of Justinian as to commodatum, depositum, and pignus; /4/ and as to the duty of the hirer to use the care of a diligentissimus paterfamilias. /5/

The early legal writers aren't as helpful as one might hope because of the influence of Roman law. However, Glanvil states clearly that if something borrowed gets damaged or lost while in the borrower's possession, they are fully responsible for returning a fair price. /3/ Bracton echoes this, partially repeating but adjusting Justinian's terms regarding commodatum, depositum, and pignus; /4/ and he also addresses the obligation of the borrower to exercise the care of a very diligent household head. /5/

[176] The language and decisions of the courts are perfectly clear; and there we find the German tradition kept alive for several centuries. I begin with the time of Edward II., about 1315. In detinue the plea was that the plaintiff delivered the defendant a chest locked with his key, that the chattels were in the chest, and that they were taken from the defendant together with his own goods by robbery. The replication was that the goods were delivered to the defendant out of enclosure, and Fitzherbert says the party was driven to that issue; /1/ which implies that, if not in the chest, but in the defendant's custody, he was liable. Lord Holt, in Coggs v. Bernard, /2/ denies that the chest would make any difference; but the old books agree that there is no delivery if the goods are under lock and key; and this is the origin of the distinction as to carriers breaking bulk in modern criminal law. /3/ In the reign of Edward III., /4/ the case of a pledge came up, which seems always to have been regarded as a special bailment to keep as one's own goods. The defence was, that the goods were stolen with the defendant's own. The plaintiff was driven to reply a tender before the theft, which would have put an end to the pledge, and left the defendant a general bailee. /5/ Issue was taken thereon, which confirms the other cases, by implying that in that event the defendant would be liable.

[176] The language and rulings of the courts are very clear; here we see the German tradition maintained for several centuries. I start with the time of Edward II, around 1315. In a detinue case, the claim was that the plaintiff gave the defendant a chest locked with his key, containing chattels that were taken from the defendant along with his own belongings by theft. The response was that the goods were handed over to the defendant outside an enclosed area, and Fitzherbert notes that the party was pushed to that issue; /1/ which suggests that, if the goods were not in the chest but in the defendant's possession, he would be responsible. Lord Holt, in Coggs v. Bernard, /2/ argues that the chest wouldn’t make any difference; however, the old texts agree that there is no delivery if the goods are locked away; this is where the distinction in modern criminal law regarding carriers breaking bulk comes from. /3/ During the reign of Edward III, /4/ a case involving a pledge arose, which has always been seen as a special type of bailment to keep as one's own property. The defense claimed that the goods were stolen along with the defendant's belongings. The plaintiff had to reply with a tender before the theft, which would have terminated the pledge and left the defendant as a general bailee. /5/ An issue was raised on this, which supports the other cases, suggesting that in that situation the defendant would indeed be liable.

Next I take a case of the time of Henry VI., A.D. 1455. /6/ [177] was an action of debt against the Marshal of the Marshalsea, or jailer of the King's Bench prison, for an escape of a prisoner. Jailers in charge of prisoners were governed by the same law as bailees in charge of cattle. The body of the prisoner was delivered to the jailer to keep under the same liabilities that cows or goods might have been. /1/ He set up in defence that enemies of the king broke into the prison and carried off the prisoner, against the will of the defendant. The question was whether this was a good defence. The court said that, if alien enemies of the king, for instance the French, released the prisoner, or perhaps if the burning of the prison gave him a chance to escape, the excuse would be good, "because then [the defendant] has remedy against no one." But if subjects of the king broke the prison, the defendant would be liable, for they are not enemies, but traitors, and then, it is implied, the defendant would have a right of action against them, and therefore would himself be answerable. In this case the court got very near to the original ground of liability, and distinguished accordingly. The person intrusted was liable in those cases where he had a remedy over against the wrong-doer (and in which, originally, he was the only person who had such a remedy); and, on the other hand, his liability, being founded on that circumstance, ceased where the remedy ceased. The jailer could not sue the soldiers of an invading army of Frenchmen; but in theory he could sue any British subject who carried off the prisoner, however little it was likely that he would get much satisfaction in that way.

Next, I take a case from the time of Henry VI, A.D. 1455. /6/ [177] It was a debt action against the Marshal of the Marshalsea, or the jailer of the King's Bench prison, for letting a prisoner escape. Jailers responsible for prisoners were subject to the same laws as bailees handling livestock. The prisoner’s body was handed over to the jailer to be kept under the same liabilities that might apply to cattle or goods. /1/ The jailer defended himself by claiming that enemies of the king broke into the prison and took the prisoner against his will. The question was whether this was a valid defense. The court stated that if foreign enemies of the king, like the French, freed the prisoner, or if the prison caught fire and he escaped, then the excuse would be valid, "because then [the defendant] has remedy against no one." However, if subjects of the king broke into the prison, the jailer would be liable, as they are not enemies but traitors, implying that the defendant would have a right to take action against them, making him accountable. In this case, the court closely examined the original basis of liability and made the distinction accordingly. The person entrusted was liable in situations where he could seek remedy against the wrongdoer (and originally, he was the only one who could do so); on the other hand, his liability, based on that circumstance, ended where the remedy ended. The jailer could not sue the soldiers of a foreign invading army; but theoretically, he could sue any British subject who took the prisoner, though it was unlikely he would get much satisfaction that way.

A few years later the law is stated the same way by the famous Littleton. He says that, if goods are delivered to [178] a man, he shall have an action of trespass if they are carried off, for he is chargeable over. /1/ That is, he is bound to make the loss good to the party who intrusted him.

A few years later, the law is expressed the same way by the famous Littleton. He states that if goods are delivered to [178] a man, he can take legal action for trespass if they are taken away, because he is responsible for them. /1/ In other words, he must compensate the party who entrusted him with the goods.

In 9 Edward IV., /2/ Danby says if a bailee received goods to keep as his proper goods, then robbery shall excuse him, otherwise not. Again, in a later case /3/ robbery is said not to be an excuse. There may have been some hesitation as to robbery when the robber was unknown, and so the bailee had no remedy over, /4/ or even as to robbery generally, on the ground that by reason of the felony the bailee could not go against either the robber's body or his estate; for the one was hanged and the other forfeited. /5/ But there is not a shadow of doubt that the bailee was not excused by an ordinary wrongful taking. "If the goods are taken by a trespasser, of whom the bailee has conusance, he shall be chargeable to his bailor, and shall have his action over against his trespasser." /6/ The same point was touched in other passages of the Year Books, /7/ and the rule of law is clearly implied by the reason which was given for the bailee's right to sue in the cases cited above.

In 9 Edward IV., /2/ Danby states that if a bailee receives goods to keep as his own, then robbery can excuse him; otherwise, it cannot. In a later case /3/, it's stated that robbery is not an excuse. There may have been some uncertainty regarding robbery when the robber was unknown, leaving the bailee without any remedy, /4/ or even regarding robbery in general, because due to the felony, the bailee couldn't go after either the robber or their property; one was hanged and the other forfeited. /5/ However, there's no doubt that the bailee was not excused by a typical wrongful taking. "If the goods are taken by a trespasser, whom the bailee knows, he will be held accountable to his bailor and will have the right to take action against the trespasser." /6/ This point was also mentioned in other parts of the Year Books, /7/ and the law clearly supports the bailee's right to sue in the cases mentioned above.

The principle was directly decided in accordance with the ancient law in the famous case of Southcote v. Bennet. /8/ This was detinue of goods delivered to the defendant to [179] keep safely. The defendant confessed the delivery, and set up he was robbed of the goods by J.S. "And, after argument at the bar, Gawdy and Clench, ceteris absentibus, held that the plaintiff ought to recover, because it was not a special bailment; that the defendant accepted them to keep as his proper goods, and not otherwise; but it is a delivery, which chargeth him to keep them at his peril. And it is not any plea in a detinue to say that he was robbed by one such; for he hath his remedy over by trespass, or appeal, to have them again." The above from Croke's report implies, what Lord Coke expressly says, that "to be kept, and to be kept safe, is all one," and both reports agree that the obligation was founded on the delivery alone. Croke's report confirms the caution which Lord Coke adds to his report: "Note, reader, it is good policy for him who takes any goods to keep, to take them in special manner, scil. to keep them as he keeps his own goods,... or if they happen to be stolen or purloined, that he shall not be answerable for them; for he who accepted them ought to take them in such or the like manner, or otherwise he may be charged by his general acceptance."

The principle was directly determined according to ancient law in the well-known case of Southcote v. Bennet. /8/ This involved the detention of goods that were given to the defendant for safekeeping. The defendant admitted to receiving the goods and claimed he was robbed of them by J.S. "After discussion at the bar, Gawdy and Clench, with others absent, ruled that the plaintiff should win, because it wasn't a special bailment; the defendant accepted the goods as if they were his own, and not in any other way; rather, it was a delivery that required him to keep them at his own risk. It is not a valid defense in a detinue case to say he was robbed by someone; he has a remedy through trespass or appeal to reclaim them." The above from Croke's report indicates, as Lord Coke explicitly states, that "to be kept, and to be kept safe, is the same thing," and both reports confirm that the obligation arose solely from the delivery. Croke's report reinforces the caution that Lord Coke adds to his report: "Note, reader, it is wise for anyone who takes possession of goods to do so in a specific manner, namely, to keep them as they would their own goods,... or if they happen to be stolen or taken, they shall not be held liable for them; for anyone who accepts them should take them in such a manner, or else they may be liable due to their general acceptance."

Down to this time, at least, it was clear law that, if a person accepted the possession of goods to keep for another even as a favor, and lost them by wrongful taking, wholly without his fault, he was bound to make good the loss, unless when he took possession he expressly stipulated against such a responsibility. The attempts of Lord Holt in Coggs v. Bernard, and of Sir William Jones in his book on Bailments, to show that Southcote v. Bennet was not sustained by authority, were futile, as any one who will Study the Year Books for himself may see. The same principle was laid down seven years before by Peryam, [180] C. B., in Drake v. Royman, /1/ and Southcote's Case was followed as a leading precedent without question for a hundred years.

Up to this point, it was established law that if someone took possession of goods to hold for another as a favor and lost them due to someone else's wrongful actions, completely without their fault, they were obligated to cover the loss, unless they specifically stated otherwise when accepting possession. Lord Holt’s efforts in Coggs v. Bernard and Sir William Jones in his book on Bailments to argue that Southcote v. Bennet lacked legal backing were pointless, as anyone who studies the Year Books on their own can see. The same principle was established seven years earlier by Peryam, [180] C. B., in Drake v. Royman, /1/, and Southcote's Case was cited as a leading precedent without dispute for a hundred years.

Thus the circle of analogies between the English and the early German law is complete. There is the same procedure for lost property, turning on the single question whether the plaintiff had lost possession against his will; the same principle that, if the person intrusted with the property parted with it to another, the owner could not recover it, but must get his indemnity from his bailee; the same inverted explanation, that the bailee could sue because he was answerable over, but the substance of the true doctrine in the rule that when he had no remedy he was not answerable; and, finally, the same absolute responsibility for loss, even when happening without fault on the part of the person intrusted. The last and most important of these principles is seen in force as late as the reign of Queen Elizabeth. We have now to follow its later fortunes.

So, the parallels between English and early German law are clear. Both systems address lost property in the same way, focusing on whether the plaintiff lost possession against their will. They also share the principle that if someone entrusted with the property gives it to another person, the original owner can't recover it directly and instead must seek compensation from the person they entrusted it to. There's also a similar explanation where the person entrusted could sue because they were accountable, but the core truth is that when they had no way to remedy the situation, they weren't accountable. Finally, there’s the same total responsibility for loss, even if it occurred without fault on the part of the person entrusted. This last and most significant principle was still in effect during Queen Elizabeth's reign. Now, we need to look at what happened to it afterward.

A common carrier is liable for goods which are stolen from him, or otherwise lost from his charge except by the act of God or the public enemy. Two notions have been entertained with regard to the source of this rule: one, that it was borrowed from the Roman law; /2/ the other, that it was introduced by custom, as an exception to the general law of bailment, in the reigns of Elizabeth and James I. /3/

A common carrier is responsible for goods that are stolen or lost while in their possession, except in cases of acts of God or enemy actions. There are two main ideas about where this rule comes from: one suggests it was taken from Roman law; the other proposes it was established by custom as an exception to the general law of bailment during the reigns of Elizabeth and James I.

I shall try to show that both these notions are wrong, that this strict responsibility is a fragmentary survival from the general law of bailment which I have just explained; [181] the modifications which the old law has undergone were due in part to a confusion of ideas which came the displacement of detinue by the action on the case, in part to conceptions of public policy which were read into the precedents by Lord Holt, and in part to still later conceptions of policy which have been read into the reasonings of Lord Holt by later judges.

I will attempt to show that both of these ideas are incorrect, and that this strict responsibility is just a leftover from the general law of bailment that I have just explained; [181] the changes that the old law has gone through were partly due to a mix-up of ideas that occurred when detinue was replaced by the action on the case, partly due to public policy ideas that Lord Holt interpreted into the precedents, and partly due to later interpretations of policy that later judges have read into Lord Holt's reasoning.

Southcote's Case was decided in the forty-third year of Queen Elizabeth (A.D. 1601). I think the first mention of a carrier, pertinent to the question, occurs in Woodlife's Case, /1/ decided four or five years earlier (38 or 39 Eliz., A.D. 1596 or 1597). It was an action of account for merchandise delivered to the defendant, it would seem as a factor ("pur merchandizer")—clearly not as a carrier. Plea, robbery at sea with defendant's own goods. Gawdy, one of the judges who decided Southcote's Case, thought the plea bad; but Popham, C. J. said that, though it would not be a good plea for a carrier because he is paid for his carriage, there was a difference in this respect between carriers and other servants and factors.

Southcote's Case was decided in the forty-third year of Queen Elizabeth (A.D. 1601). I think the first mention of a carrier, relevant to the question, appears in Woodlife's Case, /1/ decided four or five years earlier (38 or 39 Eliz., A.D. 1596 or 1597). It was an action for an account regarding merchandise delivered to the defendant, seemingly as a factor ("pur merchandizer")—clearly not as a carrier. The plea was for robbery at sea involving the defendant's own goods. Gawdy, one of the judges who decided Southcote's Case, thought the plea was weak; however, Popham, C. J. stated that, although it wouldn’t be a valid plea for a carrier since he is compensated for his carriage, there is a difference in this regard between carriers and other servants and factors.

This is repeated in Southcote's Case, and appears to involve a double distinction,—first between paid and unpaid bailees, next between bailees and servants. If the defendant was a servant not having control over the goods, he might not fall within the law of bailment, and factors are treated on the footing of servants in the early law.

This is repeated in Southcote's Case and seems to involve a dual distinction—first between paid and unpaid bailees, and second between bailees and servants. If the defendant was a servant without control over the goods, they might not be covered by the law of bailment, and factors are considered on the same level as servants in early law.

The other diversity marked the entrance of the doctrine of consideration into the law of bailment. Consideration originally meant quid pro quo, as will be explained hereafter. It was thus dealt with in Doctor and Student /2/ when the principle was still young. Chief Justice [182] Popham probably borrowed his distinction between paid and unpaid bailees from that work, where common carriers are mentioned as an example of the former class. A little earlier, reward made no difference. /1/

The other diversity highlighted the introduction of the doctrine of consideration into bailment law. Originally, consideration meant something in return, as will be explained later. This was discussed in Doctor and Student /2/ when the principle was still new. Chief Justice [182] Popham likely took his distinction between paid and unpaid bailees from that work, which mentions common carriers as an example of the paid category. A little earlier, having a reward didn't make a difference. /1/

But in Woodlife's Case, in reply to what the Chief Justice had said, Gawdy cited the case of the Marshal of the King's Bench, /2/ stated above, whereupon Popham fell back on the old distinction that the jailer had a remedy over against the rebels, but that there was no remedy over in the case at bar.

But in Woodlife's Case, in response to what the Chief Justice mentioned, Gawdy referred to the case of the Marshal of the King's Bench, /2/ mentioned earlier, at which point Popham relied on the traditional distinction that the jailer had a remedy against the rebels, but that there was no remedy available in the current case.

The other cases relied on were some of those on general bailment collected above; the same authorities, in short, on which Southcote's Case was founded. The principle adopted was the same as in Southcote's Case, subject only to the question whether the defendant fell within it. Nothing was said of any custom of the realm, or ever had been in any reported case before this time; and I believe this to be the first instance in which carriers are in any way distinguished from any other class of persons intrusted with goods. There is no hint of any special obligation peculiar to them in the old books; and it certainly is not true, that this case introduced one. It will be noticed, with reference to what follows, that Popham does not speak of common carriers, but of carriers.

The other cases referenced were some of the general bailment cases mentioned earlier; essentially, the same authorities that Southcote's Case was based on. The principle used was the same as in Southcote's Case, only differentiated by whether the defendant was included under it. There was no mention of any customary law at the time, nor had there been any in previously reported cases; I believe this is the first instance where carriers are somehow treated differently from any other group of people entrusted with goods. There’s no indication of any specific obligation unique to them in the old texts; and it’s certainly not accurate to say that this case introduced one. It’s important to note, regarding what follows, that Popham refers to carriers, not specifically common carriers.

Next came Southcote's Case /3/ (43 Eliz., A.D. 1601), which presented the old law pure and simple, irrespective of reward or any modern innovation. In this and the earlier instances of loss by theft, the action was detinue, counting, we may presume, simply on a delivery and wrongful detainer.

Next came Southcote's Case /3/ (43 Eliz., A.D. 1601), which presented the old law as it was, without any reward or modern changes. In this case, just like in earlier cases of loss due to theft, the action was detinue, presumably based solely on a delivery and wrongful holding.

[183] But about this time important changes took place in the procedure usually adopted, which must be explained. If the chattel could be returned in specie, detinue afforded no satisfaction for damage which it might have suffered through the bailee's neglect. /1/ The natural remedy for such damage was the action on the case. But before this could be made entirely satisfactory, there were certain difficulties to be overcome. The neglect which occasioned the damage might be a mere omission, and what was there akin to trespass in a nonfeasance to sustain the analogy upon which trespass on the case was founded? Moreover, to charge a man for not acting, you must show that it was his duty to act. As pleadings were formerly construed, it would not have been enough to allege that the plaintiff's goods were damaged by the defendant's negligence. /2/ These troubles had been got over by the well-known words, super se assumpsit, which will be explained later. Assumpsit did not for a long time become an independent action of contract, and the allegation was simply the inducement to an action of tort. The ground of liability was that the defendant had started upon the undertaking, so that his negligent omission, which let in the damage, could be connected with his acts as a part of his dealing with the thing. /3/ We shall find Lord Holt recognizing this original purport of assumpsit when we come to Coggs v. Bernard. Of course it was not confined to cases of bailment.

[183] But around this time, significant changes occurred in the usual procedures that need to be explained. If the property could be returned in its original form, detinue didn’t really compensate for any damage that might have happened due to the bailee's neglect. /1/ The natural solution for such damage was to take legal action based on the circumstances. However, before that could be fully satisfying, there were certain challenges that needed to be addressed. The neglect causing the damage might simply be a failure to act, and how could that be similar to a trespass in a situation where there's a lack of action to support the analogy upon which the trespass on the case was based? Furthermore, to hold someone responsible for not taking action, you must show that it was their duty to act. As pleadings were interpreted in the past, it wasn’t enough to claim that the plaintiff’s property was damaged due to the defendant's negligence. /2/ These issues were overcome by the familiar phrase, super se assumpsit, which will be explained later. For a long time, assumpsit didn’t become a separate legal action for contracts, and the claim was merely a reason for a tort action. The basis for liability was that the defendant had engaged in the undertaking, so their negligent failure to act, which caused the damage, could be linked to their actions as part of their management of the item. /3/ We will see Lord Holt recognizing this original intent of assumpsit when we discuss Coggs v. Bernard. Of course, it wasn't limited to cases of bailment.

But there was another way besides this by which the defendant could be charged with a duty and made liable [184] in case, and which, although less familiar to lawyers, has a special bearing on the law of carriers in later times. If damage had been done or occasioned by the act or omission of the defendant in the pursuit of some of the more common callings, such as that of a farrier, it seems that the action could be maintained, without laying an assumpsit, on the allegation that he was a "common" farrier. /1/ The latter principle was also wholly independent of bailment. It expressed the general obligation of those exercising a public or "common" business to practise their art on demand, and show skill in it. "For," as Fitzherbert says, "it is the duty of every artificer to exercise his art rightly and truly as he ought." /2/

But there was another way for the defendant to be charged with a duty and held liable [184] in this case, which, although not as well-known to lawyers, has a specific relevance to the law of carriers in later years. If damage was caused by the actions or inactions of the defendant in carrying out some of the more common trades, like that of a farrier, it appears that a lawsuit could proceed without needing to establish a contract, based on the claim that he was a "common" farrier. /1/ This principle was also completely separate from bailment. It reflected the general obligation of those in public or "common" trades to perform their craft when needed and to demonstrate skill in it. "For," as Fitzherbert states, "it is the duty of every craftsman to exercise his craft properly and truthfully as he should." /2/

When it had thus been established that case would lie for damage when occasioned by the omission, as well as when caused by the act, of the defendant, there was no reason for denying it, even if the negligent custody had resulted in the destruction of the property. /3/ From this it was but a step to extend the same form of action to all cases of loss by a bailee, and so avoid the defendant's right to wage his law. Detinue, the primitive remedy, retained that mark of primitive procedure. The last extension was made about the time of Southcote's Case. /4/ But when the [185] same form of action thus came to be used alike for damage or destruction by the bailee's neglect and for loss by a wrong-doer against whom the bailee had a remedy over, a source was opened for confusion with regard to the foundation and nature of the defendant's duty.

When it was established that a case could be made for damages when they were caused by the defendant's omission, just as it could be for damages caused by their actions, there was no reason to deny it, even if the negligent handling led to the destruction of the property. /3/ From this, it was just a small step to apply the same legal action to all cases of loss by a bailee, thus preventing the defendant from claiming a legal defense. Detinue, the original remedy, still reflected its primitive roots. The last extension occurred around the time of Southcote's Case. /4/ However, when the same legal action started to be used for damages or destruction due to the bailee's neglect and for losses caused by a wrongdoer against whom the bailee had a recovery option, it opened the door to confusion about the basis and nature of the defendant's responsibility.

In truth, there were two sets of duties,—one not peculiar to bailees, arising from the assumpsit or public calling of the defendant, as just explained; the other, the ancient obligation, peculiar to them as such, of which Southcote's Case was an example. But any obligation of a bailee might be conceived of as part of a contract of bailment, after assumpsit had become appropriated to contract, the doctrine of consideration had been developed, (both of which had happened in Lord Coke's time,) it seemed unnecessary to distinguish nicely between the two sets of duties just mentioned, provided a consideration and special promise could be alleged. Furthermore, as formerly the defendant's public calling had the same effect as an assumpsit for the purpose of charging him in tort, it seems now to have been thought an equally good substitute for a special promise, in order to charge him in assumpsit. In Rogers v. Head, /1/ the argument was, that to charge one in assumpsit you must show either his public calling at the time of the delivery, or a special promise on sufficient consideration. This argument assumes that a bailee who received goods in the course of a public employment, [186] for instance as a common carrier, could be charged in this form of action for a breach of either of the above sets of duties, by alleging either his public calling or his reward and a special promise. It seems to have been admitted, as was repeatedly decided before and since that case, that one who was not a common carrier could have been charged for non-delivery in a special action; that is, in case as distinguished from assumpsit.

In reality, there were two types of responsibilities—one that wasn't specific to bailees, stemming from the defendant's promise or public role, as previously described; and the other, an ancient duty unique to bailees, exemplified by Southcote's Case. However, any responsibility of a bailee could be viewed as part of a bailment contract, especially after promises became associated with contracts and the concept of consideration was established (both of which occurred during Lord Coke's time). Therefore, it seemed unnecessary to meticulously differentiate between the two types of responsibilities, as long as there was a consideration and a specific promise involved. Additionally, just as the defendant's public role previously served as the basis for holding him liable in tort, it now appeared to be a valid alternative for a specific promise in order to hold him liable in a contractual sense. In Rogers v. Head, /1/ the argument was that to hold someone liable for a contract, you needed to demonstrate either their public role at the time of delivery or a specific promise backed by enough consideration. This argument suggests that a bailee receiving goods in the course of a public role, such as a common carrier, could be held liable in this type of action for breaching either of the mentioned responsibilities by asserting either their public role or their compensation along with a specific promise. It seems to have been accepted, as was repeatedly ruled before and after that case, that someone who was not a common carrier could be held liable for failing to deliver in a specific action; that is, in a case distinct from a contract claim.

Suppose, next, that the plaintiff sued in case for a tort. As before, the breach of duty complained of might be such damage to property as had always been sued for in that form of action, or it might be a loss by theft for which detinue would formerly have been brought, and which fell on the bailee only by reason of the bailment. If the goods had been stolen, the bailee's liability rested neither on his common calling nor on his assumpsit and his neglect, but arose from the naked facts that he had accepted a delivery and that the goods were gone, and in such cases it ought to have been enough to allege those facts in the declaration. /1/ But it was very natural that the time-honored foundations for the action on the case in its more limited application should still be laid in the pleadings, even after the scope of the action had been enlarged. We shall have to inquire, later, whether the principles of Southcote's Case were not also extended in the opposite direction to cases not falling within it. The reasons for the rule which it laid down had lost their meaning centuries before Gawdy and Clench were born, when owners had acquired the right to sue for the wrongful taking of property in the hands [187] and the rule itself was a dry precedent likely to be followed according to the letter because the spirit had departed. It had begun to totter when the reporter cautioned bailees to accept in such terms as to get rid of it. /1/

Suppose the plaintiff next sued for a tort. As before, the breach of duty could involve damage to property that has always been claimed in that type of action, or it might involve a loss due to theft, which in the past would have led to a detinue action, and which affected the bailee only because of the bailment. If the goods were stolen, the bailee's liability didn't come from his usual job or his promise and negligence but stemmed from the simple fact that he accepted the delivery and that the goods were missing. In such cases, it should have been enough to state those facts in the claim. /1/ However, it was completely normal for the long-standing foundations of action on the case in its narrower application to still be included in the pleadings, even after the action's scope had widened. We will need to explore later whether the principles from Southcote's Case were also applied in a broader sense to cases that did not fit within it. The reasons behind the rule it established had lost their significance centuries before Gawdy and Clench were born when owners had obtained the right to sue for the wrongful taking of property in the hands [187] and the rule itself had become a stale precedent likely to be followed just according to the letter because its spirit was gone. It started to waver when the reporter warned bailees to accept in ways that would avoid it. /1/

Accordingly, although that decision was the main authority relied on for the hundred years between it and Coggs v. Bernard whenever a peculiar responsibility was imposed upon bailees, we find that sometimes an assumpsit was laid as in the early precedents, /2/ or more frequently that the bailee was alleged to be a common bargeman, or common carrier, or the like, without much reference to the special nature of the tort in question; and that the true bearing of the allegation was sometimes lost sight of. At first, however, there were only some slight signs of confusion in the language of one or two cases, and if the duty was conceived to fall within the principle of Southcote's Case, pleaders did not always allege the common or public calling which was held unnecessary. /3/ But they also adopted other devices from the precedents in case, or to strengthen an obligation which they did not well understand. Chief Justice Popham had sanctioned a distinction between paid and unpaid bailees, hence it was deemed prudent to lay a reward. Negligence was of course averred; and finally it became frequent to allege an obligation by the law and custom of the realm. This last deserves a little further attention.

So, even though that decision was the main authority referenced for a hundred years between it and Coggs v. Bernard whenever a specific responsibility was placed on bailees, we see that sometimes an assumpsit was made as in the early cases, or more often that the bailee was said to be a common bargeman or a common carrier, or something similar, without much consideration of the unique nature of the tort involved; and the real significance of the allegation was occasionally overlooked. Initially, though, there were only minor signs of confusion in the language of a couple of cases, and if the duty was thought to fall within the principle of Southcote's Case, lawyers didn't always claim the common or public calling, which was deemed unnecessary. But they also used other strategies from the precedents in case, or to reinforce an obligation they didn’t fully understand. Chief Justice Popham had approved a distinction between paid and unpaid bailees, so it was considered wise to state a reward. Negligence was certainly mentioned; and eventually, it became common to assert an obligation by the law and custom of the realm. This last point deserves a bit more attention.

There is no writ in the Register alleging any special obligation of common carriers by the custom of the realm. But the writ against innkeepers did lay a duly "by the [188] law and custom of England," and it was easy to adopt the phrase. The allegation did not so much imply the existence of a special principle, as state a proposition of law in the form which was then usual. There are other writs of trespass which allege a common-law duty in the same way, and others again setting forth a statutory obligation. /1/ So "the judges were sworn to execute justice according to law and the custom of England." /2/

There isn't any legal document in the Register claiming a special obligation for common carriers based on the customs of the realm. However, the legal document against innkeepers did refer to the "law and custom of England," making it easy to use that phrase. This statement didn’t necessarily imply there was a special principle but rather expressed a legal proposition in the common format of the time. There are other trespass writs that describe a common-law duty similarly and others that specify a statutory obligation. /1/ So "the judges were sworn to execute justice according to law and the custom of England." /2/

The duties of a common carrier, so far as the earlier evidence goes, were simply those of bailees in general, coupled with the liabilities generally attached to the exercise of a public calling. The word "common" addressed itself only to the latter point, as has been shown above. This is further illustrated by the fact that, when the duty was thus set forth, it was not alleged as an obligation peculiar to common carriers as such, but was laid as the custom of law of common hoymen, or lightermen, &c., according to the business of the party concerned. It will be noticed that Chief Justice Holt in Coggs v. Bernard states the liability as applicable to all bailees for reward, exercising a public employment, and mentions common hoymen and masters of ships alongside of, not as embraced under, common carriers. It will also be noticed in the cases before that time, that there is no settled formula for the obligation in question, but that it is set forth in each case that the defendant was answerable for what he was said to have done or omitted in the particular instance. /3/

The responsibilities of a common carrier, according to the earlier evidence, were basically the same as those of bailees in general, along with the liabilities usually associated with a public service. The term "common" referred only to this last point, as previously mentioned. This is further illustrated by the fact that when the duty was laid out, it wasn't claimed as a specific obligation for common carriers, but rather as the legal custom of common workers like hoymen or lightermen, depending on the business of the person involved. It's important to note that Chief Justice Holt in Coggs v. Bernard describes the liability as relevant to all bailees for hire engaging in a public occupation, and he mentions common hoymen and shipmasters together with common carriers, not as part of them. Additionally, in earlier cases, there wasn't a standard definition for the obligation, but it was stated in each instance that the defendant was responsible for what they were alleged to have done or failed to do in that particular case. /3/

[189] Returning now to the succession of the cases, Rich v. Kneeland is the next in order (11 Jac. I., A.D. 1613). It was an action on the case (tort), against a common hoyman. In Croke's report nothing is said of custom; but the declaration avers that the defendant was a common bargeman, that the plaintiff delivered him a portmanteau, &c. to carry, and paid him for it, and that the defendant tam negligenter custodivit, that it was taken from him by persons unknown,—like the second count in Morse v. Slue, below. The plea was demurred to, and adjudged for the plaintiff. A writ of error being brought, it was assigned that "this action lies not against a common bargeman without special promise. But all the Justices and Barons held, that it well lies as against a common carrier upon the land." If we follow this report, it seems at the first glance that importance was attributed to the common calling. But as the loss was clearly within the principle of Southcote's Case, which required neither special promise nor common calling for its application, and which remained unquestioned law for three quarters of a century later, the court must have referred to the form of action employed (case), and not to the liability of the defendant in some form of action (detinue). The objection was that "this action lies not," not that the defendant not liable, "without special promise." Even thus narrowed, it rather countenances the notion that allegations which were necessary to charge a man for damage happening through his neglect, in the more ancient and use of this action, were also necessary in this new [190] extension of it to a different class of wrongs. As it was now pretty clear that case would lie for a nonfeasance, the notion was mistaken, and we shall see that it was denied in subsequent decisions. /1/

[189] Now, returning to the series of cases, Rich v. Kneeland is next on the list (11 Jac. I., A.D. 1613). It was a case based on tort against a common hoyman. Croke's report doesn’t mention any custom; however, the declaration states that the defendant was a common bargeman, that the plaintiff handed him a suitcase, etc., to transport, and paid him for it, and that the defendant negligently took care of it, leading to it being taken by unknown individuals—similar to the second count in Morse v. Slue, below. The plea was challenged, and the court ruled in favor of the plaintiff. After a writ of error was filed, it was claimed that "this action does not apply against a common bargeman without a special promise." But all the Justices and Barons agreed that it does apply to a common carrier on land. If we look closely at this report, it seems at first glance that there was significance given to the common profession. However, since the loss fit clearly within the principle from Southcote's Case, which didn't require a special promise or common profession for it to be applicable, and which remained undisputed law for another seventy-five years, the court must have been referencing the type of action used (case) and not the liability of the defendant in another type of action (detinue). The concern was that "this action does not apply," not that the defendant wasn't liable "without a special promise." Even with this limitation, it somewhat supports the idea that the allegations needed to hold a person accountable for damages caused by their negligence, in the older and more traditional use of this action, were still necessary in this new [190] extension to a different category of wrongs. As it became increasingly clear that a case could be made for nonfeasance, this notion was mistaken, and we will see that it was rejected in later rulings. /1/

According to Hobart's report, it was alleged that the defendant was a common hoyman, to carry goods by water, for hire, &c., that by the custom of England such carriers ought to keep the goods, &c., so as they should not be lost by the default of them or their servants, &c. "And it was resolved that, though it was laid as a custom of the realm, yet indeed it is common law." This last resolution may only mean that the custom of the realm and the common law are the same thing, as had been said concerning innkeepers long before. /2/ But the law as to innkeepers, which was called the custom of the realm in the writ, had somewhat the air of a special principle extending beyond the law of bailment, inasmuch as their liability extended to goods within the inn, of which they had not the custody, and the court may have meant to make an antithesis between such a special principle and the common law or general law of bailment governing the present case.

According to Hobart's report, it was claimed that the defendant was a typical hoyman, someone who transports goods by water for hire, etc., and that, according to English custom, such carriers are supposed to keep the goods safe so they aren't lost due to their or their employees' negligence, etc. "And it was concluded that, although it was stated as a custom of the realm, it is actually common law." This last statement might just mean that the realm's custom and the common law are essentially the same, similar to what had been said about innkeepers long before. But the law regarding innkeepers, which was referred to as a custom of the realm in the writ, had somewhat of a unique principle that went beyond the law of bailment, since their responsibility included goods inside the inn, even if they didn't have custody of them. The court may have intended to draw a contrast between that unique principle and the common law or general law of bailment applicable to the current case.

Whatever doubts some of Croke's language might raise, standing alone, the fact remains indisputable, that for nearly a century from Woodlife's Case the liability of carriers for loss of goods, whether the custom of the realm or the defendant's common calling was alleged or not, was placed upon the authority and was intended to be decided on the principle of Southcote's Case.

Whatever doubts some of Croke's language might cause, it’s undeniable that for almost a century since Woodlife's Case, the responsibility of carriers for lost goods, regardless of whether the customs of the realm or the defendant's common profession were mentioned, was based on established authority and was meant to be resolved according to the principle of Southcote's Case.

[191] Symons v. Darknell 1 (4 Car. I., A.D. 1628) is precisely in point. The declaration was, that, by the common law, every lighterman ought so to manage his lighter that the goods carried therein should not perish. "And although no promise laid, it seemed to the court that the plaintiff should recover; and not alleging that defendant was common lighterman was no harm. Hyde, C. J., delivery makes the contract." This did not mean that delivery was a good consideration for a promise; but, as was laid down in Southcote's Case, that delivery, without a special acceptance to keep only as one's own goods, bound the bailee to keep safely, and therefore made it unnecessary to allege either an assumpsit or the defendant's common calling. Whitlock, J. called attention to the fact that the action was tort, not contract. "Et en cest case... Southcote's Case fuit cite."

[191] Symons v. Darknell 1 (4 Car. I., A.D. 1628) is directly relevant. The claim stated that, under common law, every lighterman must handle their lighter in such a way that the goods being transported do not get damaged. "And even though there was no promise made, the court believed the plaintiff should win; and not stating that the defendant was a regular lighterman was not an issue. Hyde, C. J., said delivery constitutes the contract." This did not imply that delivery was a valid reason for a promise; rather, as established in Southcote's Case, delivery, without a specific agreement to keep the goods as one's own, obligated the bailee to take care of them, making it unnecessary to mention either an assumption or the defendant's usual profession. Whitlock, J. noted that the case was a tort, not a contract. "Et en cest case... Southcote's Case fuit cite."

The same rule is stated as to bailments in general, the same year, by Sergeant Maynard arguendo in Williams v. Hide, /2/ again citing Southcote's Case.

The same rule applies to bailments in general, as stated the same year by Sergeant Maynard in Williams v. Hide, /2/, again referencing Southcote's Case.

In Kenrig v. Eggleston /3/ (24 Car. I., A.D. 1648), "case against a country carrier for not delivering a box," &c., of which he was robbed, nothing was said about custom, nor being a common carrier, unless the above words imply that he was; but it was laid down, as in Southcote's Case, that "it must come on the carrier's part acceptance" if he would lessen his liability as bailee.

In Kenrig v. Eggleston /3/ (24 Car. I., A.D. 1648), "case against a country carrier for not delivering a box," &c., of which he was robbed, there was no mention of custom or being a common carrier, unless the above wording suggests that he was; however, it was established, as in Southcote's Case, that "it must come from the carrier's side acceptance" if he wanted to reduce his responsibility as a bailee.

Nichols v. Moore /4/ (13 Car. II., A.D. 1661) was case against a "water carrier," between Hull and London, laying a delivery to him at York. It was moved in arrest of [192] judgment, that the defendant did not undertake to carry the goods from York to Hull. "But notwithstanding this per totam curiam, the defendant shall be charged on his general receipt at York, according to Southcote's Case."

Nichols v. Moore /4/ (13 Car. II., A.D. 1661) was a case against a "water carrier," operating between Hull and London, with a delivery made to him at York. It was argued to halt the [192] judgment, claiming that the defendant did not agree to transport the goods from York to Hull. "However, despite this, by the whole court, the defendant will be held accountable based on his general receipt at York, following Southcote's Case."

It is fair to mention that in Matthews v. Hopkins /1/ (17 Car. II.)the declaration was on the custom of the realm against a common carrier, and there was a motion in arrest of judgment, because there was a misrecital of the custom of the realm, and the defendant was not alleged to have been a carrier at the time of the receipt, and also because counts in trover, and in case on the custom, were joined. Judgment was arrested, it would seem on the latter ground, but the court continued: "And, although the declaration may be good without recital of the custom of the realm, as Hobart says, still it is the better way to recite it."

It’s important to note that in Matthews v. Hopkins /1/ (17 Car. II.), the declaration was based on the custom of the realm against a common carrier. There was a motion to halt the judgment because the custom of the realm was misrecited, and the defendant wasn't claimed to be a carrier at the time of the receipt. Additionally, there were counts in trover and in case regarding the custom that were combined. The judgment was stopped, likely for the latter reason, but the court added: "And, even though the declaration might be valid without reciting the custom of the realm, as Hobart mentions, it’s still better to include it."

We now come to the great case of Morse v. Slue /2/ (23 & 24 Car. II., A.D. 1671, 1672). This was an action against the master of a ship lying in the river Thames, for the loss of goods intrusted to him. The goods in question were taken away by robbers, and it was found that the ship had the usual guard at the time. There seem to have been two counts, one on the law and custom of England (1 Vent. 190), for masters of ships "carefully to govern, preserve, and defend goods shipped, so long as said ship should remain in the river Thames" (2 Keb. 866); "to keep safely [goods shipped to be carried from London beyond sea] without loss or subtraction, ita quodpro defectu of them they may not come to any damage" (1 Vent. 190); "to keep safely goods delivered to them to carry, dangers [193] of the sea excepted" (2 Levinz, 69; the exception last was perhaps drawn by the reporter from the usual bills of lading referred to in argument). The second count, which is usually overlooked, was a special count "on delivery and being stolen by his neglect." /1/

We now arrive at the significant case of Morse v. Slue /2/ (23 & 24 Car. II., A.D. 1671, 1672). This was a lawsuit against the captain of a ship docked in the river Thames for the loss of goods that were entrusted to him. The goods in question were stolen by robbers, and it was determined that the ship had the usual security measures in place at the time. There appear to be two claims: one based on the law and customs of England (1 Vent. 190), stating that captains of ships must "carefully manage, preserve, and defend goods shipped, as long as the ship remains in the river Thames" (2 Keb. 866); "to securely keep [goods shipped to be transported from London overseas] without loss or theft, so that due to their negligence, no harm comes to them" (1 Vent. 190); "to keep safely the goods entrusted to them for transport, with the dangers of the sea excepted" (2 Levinz, 69; this last exception was possibly noted by the reporter from the standard bills of lading mentioned in argument). The second claim, which is often overlooked, was a special claim "for delivery and being stolen due to his neglect." /1/

The case was twice argued, and all the reports agree, as far as they go, in their statements of the points insisted on.

The case was argued twice, and all the reports agree, as far as they go, in their statements of the points raised.

Holt, for the plaintiff, maintained: /2/ 1. That the master receives goods generally, citing Southcote's Case, and that in "only guardian in socage who hath the custody by law, who factor who is servant at the master's dispose, and so cannot take care, are exempt." 2. That the master has a reward for his keeping, and is therefore a proper person to be sued. 3. That the master has a remedy over, citing the case of the Marshal of the King's Bench. /3/ That the mischief would be great if the master were not liable, as merchants put their trust in him, and no particular default be shown, as appears by the bill of lading, and, finally, that neglect appeared.

Holt, representing the plaintiff, argued: /2/ 1. That the master generally accepts goods, referencing Southcote's Case, and that the only guardian in socage who has custody by law, along with any factor who is an employee at the master's direction, cannot be held responsible. 2. That the master receives payment for his storage, making him the right person to sue. 3. That the master has recourse, referencing the case of the Marshal of the King's Bench. /3/ He pointed out that the consequences would be severe if the master wasn't held liable, as merchants rely on him, and no specific fault can be demonstrated, as indicated by the bill of lading, and ultimately, that negligence was evident.

On the other side, it was urged that no neglect was found, and that the master was only a servant; so that, if any one was liable, the owners were. /4/ It was also suggested that, as there would have been no liability if the goods had been taken at sea, when the case would have within the admiralty law, it was absurd that a different rule should govern the beginning of the voyage from would have governed the rest of it. /5/

On the flip side, it was argued that there was no negligence, and the captain was just doing his job; therefore, if anyone was responsible, it was the owners. /4/ It was also pointed out that since there wouldn't have been any liability if the goods had been lost at sea, which would fall under admiralty law, it was unreasonable for a different rule to apply at the start of the voyage than what would apply for the rest of it. /5/

[194] On the second argument, it was again maintained for the plaintiff that the defendant was liable "at the common law on the general bailment," citing Southcote's Case, and also that, by the Roman and maritime law, he was liable as a public carrier and master of a ship.

[194] In the second argument, the plaintiff reiterated that the defendant was responsible "according to common law on the general bailment," referencing Southcote's Case. Additionally, it was argued that under Roman and maritime law, the defendant was liable as a public carrier and the captain of a ship.

The opinion of the court was delivered by Chief Justice Hale. It was held that, the ship being within the body of the county, the admiralty law did not apply; or, according to 1 Mod. 85, note a, "the master could not avail himself of the rules of the civil law, by which masters are not chargeable pro damno fatali"; that the master was liable to an action because he took a reward; that "he might have made a caution for himself, which he omitting and taking in the goods generally, he shall answer for what happens." /1/ The case of Kenrig v. Eggleston /2/ seems also to have been referred to. It was further said that the master was rather an officer than a servant, and in effect received his wages from the merchant who paid freight. Finally, on the question of negligence, that it was not sufficient to have the usual number of men to guard the ship, but that it was neglect not to have enough to guard the goods, unless in case of the common enemies, citing the case of the Marshal, which it will be remembered was merely the principle of Southcote's Case and the common law of bailment in another form. /3/

The court's decision was presented by Chief Justice Hale. It was determined that, since the ship was within the county, admiralty law did not apply; or, as stated in 1 Mod. 85, note a, "the master couldn't use the rules of civil law, which state that masters aren't liable for unavoidable damages"; that the master was liable for action because he accepted a reward; that "he could have taken precautions for himself, but by neglecting that and taking the goods in general, he must be responsible for what occurs." /1/ The case of Kenrig v. Eggleston /2/ also appears to have been mentioned. It was additionally noted that the master was more of an officer than a servant and essentially received his pay from the merchant who covered the freight. Finally, regarding the issue of negligence, it wasn’t enough to have the usual number of men to protect the ship; it was considered neglect not to have enough to safeguard the goods, unless facing common enemies, referencing the case of the Marshal, which, it should be remembered, was just a reiteration of the principle from Southcote's Case and the common law of bailment in another form. /3/

It will be observed that this case did not go on any special custom, either as to common carriers or shipmasters, but that all the arguments and the opinion of the court assumed that, if the case was to be governed by the common law, and not by the milder provisions of the civil [195] law relied on for the defence, and if the defendant could be regarded as a bailee, and not merely a servant of the owners, then the general law of bailment would apply, and the defendant would be charged, as in Southcote's Case, "by his general acceptance."

It will be noted that this case didn’t follow any specific customs, whether for common carriers or shipmasters, but all the arguments and the court’s opinion assumed that, if the case was to be governed by common law, rather than the more lenient provisions of the civil [195] law used for the defense, and if the defendant could be seen as a bailer and not just as an employee of the owners, then the general law of bailment would apply, and the defendant would be held responsible, as in Southcote's Case, "by his general acceptance."

It can hardly be supposed, however, that so enlightened a judge as Sir Matthew Hale would not have broken away the Year Books, if a case had arisen before him where property had been received as a pure favor to the plaintiff, without consideration or reward, and was taken from the defendant by robbery. Such a case was tried before Chief Justice Pemberton, and he very sensibly ruled that no action lay, declining to follow the law of Lord Coke's time to such extreme results /1/ (33 Car. II., A.D. 1681).

It's hard to believe that a knowledgeable judge like Sir Matthew Hale wouldn't have discarded the Year Books if a case arose in front of him where property was given purely as a favor to the plaintiff, without anything in return, and was then stolen from the defendant. A similar case was tried before Chief Justice Pemberton, who wisely ruled that no action could be taken, choosing not to follow the law from Lord Coke's era to such an unreasonable extent /1/ (33 Car. II., A.D. 1681).

About the same time, the defendant's common calling began to assume a new importance. The more important alternative allegation, the assumpsit, had the effect in the end of introducing the not intrinsically objectionable doctrine that all duties arising from a bailment are founded on contract. /2/ But this allegation, having now a special action to which it had given rise, was not much used where the action was tort, while the other averment occurs with increasing frequency. The notion was evidently gaining ground that the liability of common carriers for loss of [196] goods, whatever the cause of the loss might be, arose from a special principle peculiar to them, and not applicable to bailees in general. The confusion of independent duties which has been explained, and of which the first trace was seen in Rich v. Kneeland, was soon to become complete. /1/ Holt became Chief Justice. Three of the cases in the last note were rulings of his. In Lane v. Cotton /2/ (13 Will. III., A.D. 1701), he showed his disapproval of Southcote's Case, and his impression that the common law of bailment was borrowed from Rome. The overthrow of Southcote's Case and the old common law may be said to date from Coggs v. Bernard /3/ (2 Anne, A.D. 1703). Lord Holt's famous opinion in the latter case quotes largely from the Roman law as it filtered to him through Bracton; but, whatever influence that may have had upon his general views, the point decided and the distinctions touching common carriers were of English growth.

Around the same time, the defendant's usual role began to take on new significance. The more crucial alternative claim, the assumpsit, ultimately led to the acceptance of the idea that all obligations stemming from a bailment are based on contract. /2/ However, since this claim now had a specific action associated with it, it wasn’t as frequently used in tort actions, while the other claim was appearing more often. It was becoming clear that the liability of common carriers for the loss of [196] goods, regardless of the cause, arose from a unique principle specific to them, and not applicable to bailees in general. The confusion surrounding independent duties, which was first noted in Rich v. Kneeland, was soon to become complete. /1/ Holt became Chief Justice. Three of the cases mentioned in the last note were rulings by him. In Lane v. Cotton /2/ (13 Will. III., A.D. 1701), he expressed his disapproval of Southcote's Case and indicated that the common law of bailment was derived from Roman law. The discrediting of Southcote's Case and the old common law is often considered to have begun with Coggs v. Bernard /3/ (2 Anne, A.D. 1703). Lord Holt's well-known opinion in that case heavily references Roman law as it was presented to him through Bracton; yet, regardless of how that may have shaped his overall perspective, the ruling and distinctions regarding common carriers were developed in England.

The action did not sound in contract. The cause was for damage to the goods, and the plaintiff sued for a tort, laying an assumpsit by way of inducement to a charge of negligence, as in the days of Henry VI. The plea was not guilty. But after verdict for the plaintiff, there was a motion in arrest of judgment, "for that it was not alleged in the declaration that the defendant was a common porter, nor averred that he had anything for his pains." Consideration was never alleged or thought of in the primitive assumpsit, but in the modern action of contract in that form [197] it was required. Hence, it was inferred that, wherever an assumpsit was laid, even in all action of tort for damage to property, it was the allegation of a contract, and that a consideration must be shown for the undertaking, although the contrary had been decided in the reign of Queen Elizabeth. /1/ But the motion did not prevail, and judgment was given for the plaintiff. Lord Holt was well aware that the use of an assumpsit was not confined to contract. It is true that he said, "The owner's trusting [the defendant] with the goods is a sufficient consideration to oblige him to a careful management," or to return them; but this means as distinguished from a consideration sufficient to oblige him to carry them, which he thought the defendant would not have been bound to do. He then expressly says, "This is a different case, for assumpsit does not only signify a future agreement, but, in such cases as this, it signifies an actual entry upon the thing and taking the trust upon himself"; following the earlier cases in the Year Books. /2/ This was enough for the decision, and the rule in Southcote's Case had nothing to do with the matter. But as the duty of common carriers by reason of their calling was now supposed to extend to all kinds of losses, and the doctrine of Southcote's Case was probably supposed to extend to many kinds of damage, it became necessary, in a general discussion, to reconcile or elect between the two principles.

The case wasn't based on a contract. The reason was for damage to the goods, and the plaintiff filed a lawsuit for a tort, claiming an assumpsit as a way to support a negligence charge, just like in the times of Henry VI. The response was not guilty. However, after the verdict favored the plaintiff, there was a motion to halt the judgment, "because it wasn’t stated in the complaint that the defendant was a common porter, nor claimed that he received anything for his efforts." Consideration was never mentioned or considered in the early assumpsit, but in the modern contract action in that form [197] it was necessary. Therefore, it was concluded that wherever an assumpsit was presented, even in any tort action for property damage, it indicated the claim of a contract and that a consideration must be demonstrated for the obligation, although the opposite had been determined during Queen Elizabeth’s reign. /1/ Yet, the motion was unsuccessful, and judgment was ruled in favor of the plaintiff. Lord Holt understood that the use of assumpsit wasn’t limited to contracts. He indeed stated, "The owner's trust in [the defendant] with the goods is a sufficient consideration to require him to take care of them," or to return them; but this implies a distinction from a consideration strong enough to compel him to transport them, which he believed the defendant wouldn’t have been obligated to do. He then clearly stated, "This is a different situation, because assumpsit does not only mean a future agreement, but, in cases like this, it means an actual taking of responsibility and management of the goods"; drawing from earlier cases in the Year Books. /2/ This was enough for the ruling, and the principle in Southcote's Case was irrelevant to the issue. However, since the responsibilities of common carriers due to their profession were now assumed to cover all types of losses, and the doctrine of Southcote's Case likely appeared to apply to various forms of damage, it became essential in a broader discussion to reconcile or choose between the two principles.

The Chief Justice therefore proceeded to distinguish between [198] bailees for reward exercising a public employment, such as common carriers, common hoymen, masters of ships, &c., and other bailees; denied the rule in Southcote's Case as to the latter; said that the principle of strict responsibility was confined to the former class, and was applied to them on grounds of public policy, and that factors were exonerated, not because they were mere servants, as had always been laid down (among others, by himself in arguing Morse v. Slue), but because they were not within the reason of the rule.

The Chief Justice then went on to differentiate between bailees for a fee performing a public role, like common carriers, common hoymen, ship masters, etc., and other bailees. He rejected the rule from Southcote's Case concerning the latter group, stating that the principle of strict responsibility only applied to the former group based on public policy. He noted that factors were not exempt because they were simply employees, as had always been argued (including by him in Morse v. Slue), but because they did not fall under the rationale of the rule.

The reader who has followed the argument so far, will hardly need to be convinced that this did not mean the adoption of the Praetor's Edict. There is further evidence at hand if required.

The reader who has kept up with the argument so far will hardly need convincing that this didn't mean adopting the Praetor's Edict. There's more evidence available if needed.

In the first place, as we have seen, there was a century of precedents ending with Morse v. Slue, argued by Holt himself, in which the liability of masters of ships, hoymen, carriers, &c. had been adjudicated. Morse v. Slue is cited and relied on, and there is no hint of dissatisfaction with the other cases. On the contrary, they furnished the examples of bailees for reward exercising a public calling. The distinction between bailees for reward and others is Chief Justice Popham's; the latter qualification (exercising a public calling) was also English, as has partly appeared already, and as will be explained further on.

First of all, as we’ve seen, there was a century of precedents ending with Morse v. Slue, argued by Holt himself, in which the liability of ship masters, hoymen, carriers, etc., was decided. Morse v. Slue is cited and relied upon, and there’s no hint of dissatisfaction with the other cases. On the contrary, they provided examples of bailees for reward engaging in a public calling. The distinction between bailees for reward and others is Chief Justice Popham's; the latter qualification (engaging in a public calling) was also recognized in England, as has already been partially noted and will be further explained later on.

In the next place, the strict rule is not confined to nautae, caupones, and stabularii, nor even to common carriers; but is applied to all bailees for reward, exercising a public calling.

In addition, the strict rule isn't limited to sailors, innkeepers, and stable keepers, nor just to common carriers; it applies to all bailees for hire who are engaged in a public profession.

In the next place, the degree of responsibility is precisely that of bailees in general, as worked out by the previous decisions; but quite unlike and much more severe [199] than that imposed by the Roman law, as others have observed. /1/

In the next place, the level of responsibility is exactly what it is for bailees in general, based on earlier rulings; however, it is very different and much harsher [199] than what was required by Roman law, as others have noted. /1/

And, finally, the exemption from liability for acts of God or the public enemy is characteristically English, as will be proved further on.

And, finally, exemption from liability for acts of God or the public enemy is typically English, as will be shown later.

But it has been partially shown in this Lecture that the law of to-day has made the carrier's burden heavier than it was in the time of the Year Books. Southcote's Case, and the earlier authorities which have been cited, all refer to a loss by robbery, theft, or trespass, and hold the bailee liable, where, in theory at least, he has a remedy over. It was with reference to such cases, as has been seen, that the rule arose, although it is not improbable that it would have been applied to an unexplained loss; the writ against innkeepers reads absque subtractionie seu amissione custodire. In later times, the principle may have been extended from loss by theft to loss by destruction. In Symons v. Darknoll /2/ (4 Car. I.), already cited as decided on the authority of Southcote's Case, the goods were spoiled, not stolen, and probably had not even perished in specie. Before this time, the old rule had become an arbitrary precedent, followed according to its form with little thought of its true intent.

But this lecture has partially shown that today's law has made the carrier's burden heavier than it was during the time of the Year Books. Southcote's Case and the earlier cases mentioned all deal with loss due to robbery, theft, or trespass, holding the bailee accountable, at least theoretically, where he has a remedy available. The rule emerged with regard to such cases, as noted, although it is likely it would have also been applied to unexplained losses; the writ against innkeepers states absque subtractione seu amissione custodire. In more recent times, the principle may have expanded from loss due to theft to losses caused by destruction. In Symons v. Darknoll /2/ (4 Car. I.), already cited as relying on Southcote's Case, the goods were damaged, not stolen, and probably hadn’t even been completely destroyed. By this time, the old rule had become an arbitrary precedent, followed strictly with little consideration for its original purpose.

The language of Coggs v. Bernard is, that "the law charges the person thus intrusted to carry goods as against all events but acts of God and the enemies of the king." This was adopted by solemn decision in Lord Mansfield's time, and it is now settled that the common carrier "is liable for all losses which do not fall within the excepted [200] cases." /1/ That is to say, he has become an insurer to that extent, not only against the disappearance or destruction, but against all forms of damage to the goods except as excepted above.

The language of Coggs v. Bernard states that "the law holds the person entrusted with carrying goods responsible for everything except acts of God and the enemies of the king." This principle was established in a notable decision during Lord Mansfield's era, and it is now well understood that a common carrier "is liable for all losses that don't fall under the excluded [200] cases." In other words, they have essentially become an insurer to that extent, not just for loss or destruction, but for all types of damage to the goods, except for those situations mentioned above.

The process by which this came to pass has been traced above, but a few words may be added here. The Year Books, even in dealing with the destruction (as distinguished from the conversion) of chattels in the hands of a bailee, always state his liability as based upon his fault, although it must be admitted that the language is used alio intuitu. /2/ A jettison, in tempest, seems to have been a good plea for a factor in the time of Edward III.; /3/ but that cannot be relied on for an analogy. The argument from the Marshal's case /4/ is stronger. There it appears to have been thought that burning of the prison was as good an excuse for an escape as a release by alien enemies. This must refer to an accidental fire, and would seem to imply that he was not liable in that event, if not in fault. The writs in the Register against bailees to keep or carry goods, all have the general allegation of negligence, and so do the older precedents of declarations, so far as I have observed, whether stating the custom of the realm or not. /5/ But a bailee was answerable for goods wrongfully taken from him, as an innkeeper was for goods stolen from his inn, irrespective of negligence. /6/

The process by which this happened has been outlined above, but a few more points can be added here. The Year Books, even when discussing the destruction (as opposed to the conversion) of property in a bailee's possession, always state that his liability is based on his fault, although it's clear the language is used with a different intention. A jettison during a storm seems to have been a valid defense for a factor in the time of Edward III; however, that can't be used as a reliable analogy. The argument from the Marshal's case is stronger. It seems to have been believed that the burning of the prison was just as valid an excuse for an escape as a release by hostile enemies. This must refer to an accidental fire and would suggest that he wasn't liable in that situation unless he was at fault. The writs in the Register against bailees to keep or transport goods all generally allege negligence, and the same goes for the older declarations I've observed, whether they state the custom of the realm or not. However, a bailee was responsible for goods wrongfully taken from him, just as an innkeeper was for goods stolen from his inn, regardless of negligence.

It is true that the Marshal's case speaks of his negligent [201] keeping when the prisoners were released by rebels, (although that was far less likely to result from negligence, one would think, than a fire in the prison,) and that after Lord Coke's time negligence was alleged, although the goods had been lost by wrongful taking. So the writ against innkeepers is pro defectu hujusmodi hospitatorum. In these instances, neglect only means a failure de facto to keep safely. As was said at a much later date, "everything is a negligence in a carrier or hoyman that the law does not excuse." /1/ The allegation is simply the usual allegation of actions on the case, and seems to have extended itself from the earlier declarations for damage, when case supplanted detinue and the use of the former action became universal. It can hardly have been immaterial to the case for which it was first introduced. But the short reason for disbelieving that there was any warrant in the old law for making the carrier an insurer against damage is, that there seem to be no early cases in which bailees were held to such a responsibility, and that it was not within the principle on which they were made answerable for a loss by theft.

It’s true that the Marshal’s situation refers to his careless [201] management when the rebels released the prisoners, (even though that seems much less likely to be due to negligence than a fire in the prison), and that after Lord Coke's time, negligence was claimed, despite the fact that the goods were taken wrongfully. So, the writ against innkeepers is for the defect of such hosts. In these cases, neglect simply means a failure to keep things secure in practice. As was stated much later, “everything is negligence for a carrier or hoyman that the law doesn’t excuse.” /1/ The claim is just the typical allegation of actions on the case and seems to have expanded from earlier claims for damages, when case replaced detinue and the use of the former action became standard. It can hardly have been irrelevant to the case for which it was initially introduced. But the simple reason to doubt that there was any basis in old law for making the carrier an insurer against damages is that there don’t seem to be any early cases where bailees were held to such a responsibility, and it wasn’t part of the principle that made them accountable for losses due to theft.

Having traced the process by which a common carrier has been made an insurer, it only remains to say a word upon the origin of the admitted exceptions from the risk assumed. It has been seen already how loss by the public enemy came to be mentioned by Chief Justice Holt. It is the old distinction taken in the Marshal's case that there the bailee has no remedy over.

Having examined how a common carrier has become an insurer, we now need to discuss the origin of the recognized exceptions to the risk assumed. We've already seen how loss caused by a public enemy was noted by Chief Justice Holt. This relates to the old distinction made in the Marshal's case, where the bailee has no recourse.

With regard to the act of God, it was a general principle, not peculiar to carriers nor to bailees, that a duty was [202] discharged if an act of God made it impossible of performance. Lord Coke mentions the case of jettison from a Gravesend barge, /1/ and another of a party bound to keep and maintain sea-walls from overflowing, as subject to the same limitation, /2/ and a similar statement as to contracts in general will be found in the Year Books. /3/ It is another form of the principle which has been laboriously reargued in our own day, that parties are excused from the performance of a contract which has become impossible before breach from the perishing of the thing, or from change of circumstances the continued existence of which was the foundation of the contract, provided there was no warranty and no fault on the part of the contractor. Whether the act of God has now acquired a special meaning with regard to common carriers may be left for others to consider.

In terms of acts of God, there’s a general principle—not specific to carriers or bailees—that a duty is considered [202] fulfilled if an act of God makes it impossible to perform. Lord Coke refers to the case of a cargo thrown overboard from a Gravesend barge, /1/ and another case involving someone responsible for maintaining sea-walls to prevent flooding, as subject to the same limitation, /2/ and a similar idea regarding contracts in general can be found in the Year Books. /3/ This is another expression of the principle that’s been heavily debated in recent times, which states that parties are excused from fulfilling a contract that has become impossible to perform before a breach occurs, either due to the loss of the subject matter or changes in circumstances that were the basis of the contract, as long as there was no warranty or fault on the contractor’s part. Whether "act of God" now has a unique meaning for common carriers is something to be examined by others.

It appears, from the foregoing evidence, that we cannot determine what classes of bailees are subject to the strict responsibility imposed on common carriers by referring to the Praetor's Edict and then consulting the lexicons under Nautoe, Caupones, or Stabularii. The question of precedent is simply to what extent the old common law of bailment still survives. We can only answer it by enumerating the decisions in which the old law is applied; and we shall find it hard to bring them together under a general principle. The rule in Southcote's Case has been done away with for bailees in general: that is clear. But it is equally clear that it has not maintained itself, even within the limits of the public policy invented by Chief Justice [203] Holt. It is not true to-day that all bailees for reward exercising a public calling are insurers. No such doctrine is applied to grain-elevators or deposit-vaults. /1/

It seems, based on the evidence presented, that we cannot figure out which types of bailees are held to the strict responsibility placed on common carriers by looking at the Praetor's Edict and then checking the definitions for Nautoe, Caupones, or Stabularii. The key question is how much of the old common law of bailment still exists. We can only answer this by listing the cases where the old law is applied, and we will find it challenging to group them under a general rule. The rule from Southcote's Case has been abolished for bailees in general: that is clear. However, it is also clear that it has not persisted, even within the public policy framework established by Chief Justice [203] Holt. It's not accurate today to say that all bailees for reward engaged in a public calling are insurers. No such principle is applied to grain elevators or deposit vaults. /1/

How Lord Holt came to distinguish between bailees for reward and others has been shown above. It is more pertinent here to notice that his further qualification, exercising a public calling, was part of a protective system which has passed away. One adversely inclined might say that it was one of many signs that the law was administered in the interest of the upper classes. It has been shown above that if a man was a common farrier he could be charged for negligence without an assumpsit. The same judge who threw out that intimation established in another case that he could be sued if he refused to shoe a horse on reasonable request. /2/ Common carriers and common innkeepers were liable in like case, and Lord Holt stated the principle: "If a man takes upon him a public employment, he is bound to serve the public as far as the employment extends, and for refusal an action lies." /3/ An attempt to apply this doctrine generally at the present day would be thought monstrous. But it formed part of a consistent scheme for holding those who followed useful callings up to the mark. Another part was the liability of persons exercising a public employment for loss or damage, enhanced in cases of bailment by what remained of the rule in Southcote's Case. The scheme has given way to more liberal notions; but the disjecta membra still move.

How Lord Holt came to differentiate between bailees for reward and others has been explained above. It’s more relevant here to note that his additional requirement of having a public occupation was part of a protective system that has since disappeared. Some might argue that it was one of many indications that the law was applied in favor of the upper classes. As mentioned earlier, if a man was a common farrier, he could be held liable for negligence without needing a contract. The same judge who dismissed that suggestion clarified in another case that he could be sued if he refused to shoe a horse when reasonably requested. Common carriers and common innkeepers faced similar liabilities, and Lord Holt stated the principle: "If a man takes on a public job, he is obligated to serve the public to the extent of that job, and refusal can lead to legal action." An attempt to apply this principle broadly today would be considered outrageous. However, it was part of a consistent approach to ensure that those in useful professions were held accountable. Another aspect was the liability of people in public roles for loss or damage, which was heightened in bailment cases by what was left of the rule in Southcote's Case. This approach has been replaced by more generous ideas, but the remnants still persist.

Lord Mansfield stated his views of public policy in terms [204] not unlike those used by Chief Justice Holt in Coggs v. Bernard, but distinctly confines their application to common carriers. "But there is a further degree of responsibility by the custom of the realm, that is, by the common law; a carrier is in the nature of an insurer.... To prevent litigation, collusion, and the necessity of going into circumstances impossible to be unravelled, the law presumes against the carrier, unless," &c. /1/

Lord Mansfield expressed his views on public policy in terms [204] not much different from those used by Chief Justice Holt in Coggs v. Bernard, but specifically limits their application to common carriers. "However, there is an additional level of responsibility established by the customs of the realm, that is, by the common law; a carrier acts essentially as an insurer.... To avoid lawsuits, collusion, and the need to investigate situations that are impossible to untangle, the law assumes against the carrier, unless," &c. /1/

At the present day it is assumed that the principle is thus confined, and the discussion is transferred to the question who are common carriers. It is thus conceded, by implication, that Lord Holt's rule has been abandoned. But the trouble is, that with it disappear not only the general system which we have seen that Lord Holt entertained, but the special reasons repeated by Lord Mansfield. Those reasons apply to other bailees as well as to common carriers. Besides, hoymen and masters of ships were not originally held because they were common carriers, and they were all three treated as co-ordinate species, even in Coggs v. Bernard, where they were mentioned only as so many instances of bailees exercising a public calling. We do not get a new and single principle by simply giving a single name to all the cases to be accounted for. If there is a sound rule of public policy which ought to impose a special responsibility upon common carriers, as those words are now understood, and upon no others, it has never yet been stated. If, on the other hand, there are considerations which apply to a particular class among those so designated,—for instance, to railroads, who may have a private individual at their mercy, or exercise a power too vast for the common welfare,—we do not prove that the [205] reasoning extends to a general ship or a public cab by calling all three common carriers.

At present, it's understood that the principle is limited, and the discussion shifts to the question of who qualifies as common carriers. This implies that Lord Holt's rule has been set aside. However, the problem is that with this abandonment, not only does the general system Lord Holt proposed vanish, but also the specific reasons reiterated by Lord Mansfield. These reasons apply to other bailees besides common carriers. Additionally, hoymen and ship masters were not originally recognized just because they were common carriers; all three were treated as equivalent categories, even in Coggs v. Bernard, where they were mentioned merely as examples of bailees engaged in a public calling. We don’t arrive at a new, singular principle merely by assigning a single name to all the situations to be explained. If there is a valid public policy rule that should impose a special responsibility specifically on common carriers, as the term is currently understood, and not on others, it has yet to be articulated. On the flip side, if there are factors that apply to a particular group among those labeled as such—like railroads, which could have a private individual at their mercy or wield excessive power for the common good—we don’t establish that the [205] reasoning applies to a general ship or a public cab simply by grouping all three as common carriers.

If there is no common rule of policy, and common carriers remain a merely empirical exception from general doctrine, courts may well hesitate to extend the significance of those words. Furthermore, notions of public policy which would not leave parties free to make their own bargains are somewhat discredited in most departments of the law. /1/ Hence it may perhaps be concluded that, if any new case should arise, the degree of responsibility, and the validity and interpretation of any contract of bailment that there may be, should stand open to argument on general principles, and that the matter has been set at large so far as early precedent is concerned.

If there isn't a standard policy and common carriers are just an exception to the general rules, courts might be reluctant to broaden the meaning of those terms. Additionally, ideas about public policy that restrict parties from making their own agreements are generally viewed as outdated in many areas of law. /1/ Therefore, it can be suggested that if any new case comes up, the level of responsibility and the validity and interpretation of any bailment contract should be open to discussion based on general principles, and that the issue has been left vague in terms of earlier precedents.

I have treated of the law of carriers at greater length than is proportionate, because it seems to me an interesting example of the way in which the common law has grown up, and, especially, because it is an excellent illustration of the principles laid down at the end of the first Lecture. I now proceed to the discussion for the sake of which an account of the law of bailment was introduced, and to which an understanding of that part of the law is a necessary preliminary.

I have discussed the law of carriers in more detail than is usual because I find it to be an interesting example of how common law has developed. Additionally, it serves as a great illustration of the principles outlined at the end of the first lecture. Now, I will move on to the discussion that led to the introduction of the law of bailment, which is essential to understanding that area of law.

[206]

[206]





LECTURE VI. — POSSESSION.

POSSESSION is a conception which is only less important than contract. But the interest attaching to the theory of possession does not stop with its practical importance in the body of English law. The theory has fallen into the hands of the philosophers, and with them has become a corner-stone of more than one elaborate structure. It will be a service to sound thinking to show that a far more civilized system than the Roman is framed upon a plan which is irreconcilable with the a priori doctrines of Kant and Hegel. Those doctrines are worked out in careful correspondence with German views of Roman law. And most of the speculative jurists of Germany, from Savigny to Ihering, have been at once professors of Roman law, and profoundly influenced if not controlled by some form of Kantian or post-Kantian philosophy. Thus everything has combined to give a special bent to German speculation, which deprives it of its claim to universal authority.

POSSESSION is a concept that’s almost as important as contract. However, the interest in the theory of possession goes beyond its practical significance in English law. Philosophers have taken up this theory, and it has become a foundational element in more than one complex system. It would benefit clear thinking to demonstrate that a much more advanced system than the Roman one is based on a framework that fundamentally conflicts with the a priori theories of Kant and Hegel. Those theories align closely with German interpretations of Roman law. Most speculative legal scholars in Germany, from Savigny to Ihering, have been both Roman law professors and heavily influenced, if not entirely shaped, by some form of Kantian or post-Kantian philosophy. As a result, various factors have combined to give a unique direction to German thought, undermining its claim to universal authority.

Why is possession protected by the law, when the possessor is not also an owner? That is the general problem which has much exercised the German mind. Kant, it is well known, was deeply influenced in his opinions upon ethics and law by the speculations of Rousseau. Kant, Rousseau, and the Massachusetts Bill of Rights agree that all men are born free and equal, and one or the other branch of that declaration has afforded the answer to the [207] question why possession should be protected from that day to this. Kant and Hegel start from freedom. The freedom of the will, Kant said, is the essence of man. It is an end in itself; it is that which needs no further explanation, which is absolutely to be respected, and which it is the very end and object of all government to realize and affirm. Possession is to be protected because a man by taking possession of an object has brought it within the sphere of his will. He has extended his personality into or over that object. As Hegel would have said, possession is the objective realization of free will. And by Kant's postulate, the will of any individual thus manifested is entitled to absolute respect from every other individual, and can only be overcome or set aside by the universal will, that is, by the state, acting through its organs, the courts.

Why is possession protected by the law when the possessor isn't also an owner? That's the main issue that has preoccupied German thinkers. Kant, as we know, was heavily influenced by Rousseau's ideas on ethics and law. Kant, Rousseau, and the Massachusetts Bill of Rights all agree that all people are born free and equal, and one aspect of that statement has provided the answer to the [207] question of why possession should be protected from that time onward. Kant and Hegel start with the concept of freedom. According to Kant, the freedom of the will is the essence of being human. It is an end in itself; it requires no further justification, is to be fully respected, and is the ultimate goal of all government to achieve and uphold. Possession is protected because when a person takes possession of an object, they have brought it into the realm of their will. They have extended their identity into or over that object. As Hegel would put it, possession is the tangible expression of free will. And based on Kant's principle, the will of any individual thus expressed deserves complete respect from every other individual and can only be overridden or disregarded by the universal will, meaning the state, acting through its institutions, the courts.

Savigny did not follow Kant on this point. He said that every act of violence is unlawful, and seemed to consider protection of possession a branch of protection to the person. /1/ But to this it was answered that possession was protected against disturbance by fraud as well as by force, and his view is discredited. Those who have been contented with humble grounds of expediency seem to have been few in number, and have recanted or are out of favor.

Savigny disagreed with Kant on this issue. He stated that every act of violence is illegal and appeared to believe that protecting possession is a part of protecting individuals. /1/ However, it was countered that possession is protected against interference not only by force but also by fraud, which undermined his perspective. Those who were satisfied with simple, practical reasons for their beliefs seem to be few and have either changed their minds or fallen out of favor.

The majority have followed in the direction pointed out by Kant. Bruns, an admirable writer, expresses a characteristic yearning of the German mind, when he demands an internal juristic necessity drawn from the nature of possession itself, and therefore rejects empirical reasons. /2/ He finds the necessity he seeks in the freedom of the human will, which the whole legal system does but recognize [208] and carry out. Constraint of it is a wrong, which must be righted without regard to conformity of the will to law, and so on in a Kantian vein. /1/ So Gans, a favorite disciple of Hegel, "The will is of itself a substantial thing to be protected, and this individual will has only to yield to the higher common will." /2/ So Puchta, a great master, "The will which wills itself, that is, the recognition of its own personality, is to be protected." /3/

The majority have followed the path pointed out by Kant. Bruns, an excellent writer, expresses a typical longing of the German mind when he calls for an internal legal necessity based on the nature of possession itself, thus rejecting empirical reasons. /2/ He finds the necessity he seeks in the freedom of the human will, which the entire legal system merely acknowledges [208] and implements. Restricting this freedom is a wrong that must be corrected regardless of how well it aligns with the law, echoing a Kantian perspective. /1/ Likewise, Gans, a notable follower of Hegel, states, "The will is inherently a substantial entity that needs protection, and this individual will must only submit to the higher common will." /2/ Similarly, Puchta, a great master, asserts, "The will that affirms itself, meaning the recognition of its own identity, deserves protection." /3/

The chief variation from this view is that of Windscheid, a writer now in vogue. He prefers the other branch of the declaration in the Bill of Rights. He thinks that the protection to possession stands on the same grounds as protection against injuria, that every one is the equal of every other in the state, and that no one shall raise himself over the other. /4/ Ihering, to be sure, a man of genius, took an independent start, and said that possession is ownership on the defensive; and that, in favor of the owner, he who is exercising ownership in fact (i. e. the possessor) is freed from the necessity of proving title against one who is in an unlawful position. But to this it was well answered by Bruns, in his later work, that it assumes the title of disseisors to be generally worse than that of disseisees, which cannot be taken for granted, and which probably is not true in fact. /5/

The main difference from this perspective is Windscheid’s, a currently popular writer. He favors the other part of the declaration in the Bill of Rights. He believes that the protection of possession is based on the same principles as protection against injury, that everyone is equal in the state, and that no one should elevate themselves above another. /4/ Ihering, of course, a brilliant thinker, took a different approach and argued that possession is a form of ownership in defense; and that, in support of the owner, whoever is actually exercising ownership (i.e., the possessor) does not need to prove their title against someone who is unlawfully in possession. However, Bruns effectively countered this in his later work, pointing out that it assumes the title of those who have taken possession is generally worse than that of those who have been dispossessed, which cannot be taken for granted and likely isn’t true in reality. /5/

It follows from the Kantian doctrine, that a man in possession is to be confirmed and maintained in it until he is put out by an action brought for the purpose. Perhaps [209] another fact besides those which have been mentioned has influenced this reasoning, and that is the accurate division between possessory and petitory actions or defences in Continental procedure. /1/ When a defendant in a possessory action is not allowed to set up title in himself, a theorist readily finds a mystical importance in possession.

It follows from the Kantian doctrine that a person in possession should be recognized and upheld in that possession until they are removed through a legal action specifically aimed at that purpose. Perhaps [209] another fact beyond those already mentioned has shaped this reasoning, which is the clear distinction between possessory and petitory actions or defenses in Continental procedure. /1/ When a defendant in a possessory action is not permitted to claim title for themselves, a theorist easily discovers a significant meaning in possession.

But when does a man become entitled to this absolute protection? On the principle of Kant, it is not enough that he has the custody of a thing. A protection based on the sacredness of man's personality requires that the object should have been brought within the sphere of that personality, that the free will should have unrestrainedly set itself into that object. There must be then an intent to appropriate it, that is, to make it part of one's self, or one's own.

But when does a person gain the right to this complete protection? According to Kant's principle, it’s not enough just to have possession of something. Protection rooted in the inviolability of a person's identity requires that the object must be integrated into that identity, meaning the individual’s free will has fully engaged with that object. There must be a clear intention to claim it, to make it a part of oneself or one's own.

Here the prevailing view of the Roman law comes in to fortify principle with precedent. We are told that, of the many who might have the actual charge or custody of a thing, the Roman law recognized as possessor only the owner, or one holding as owner and on his way to become one by lapse of time. In later days it made a few exceptions on practical grounds. But beyond the pledgee and the sequester (a receiver appointed by the court) these exceptions are unimportant and disputed. /2/ Some of the Roman jurists state in terms that depositaries and borrowers have not possession of the things intrusted to them. /3/ Whether the German interpretation of the sources goes too far or not, it must be taken account of in the examination of German theories.

Here, the prevailing understanding of Roman law helps reinforce principles with examples. It tells us that, among many who might have actual control over an item, Roman law only recognized the true owner or someone acting as the owner, on their way to becoming one over time. In later times, it made a few practical exceptions. However, apart from the pledgee and the sequester (a court-appointed receiver), these exceptions are minor and debated. Some Roman jurists clearly state that depositaries and borrowers do not possess the items entrusted to them. Whether the German interpretation of these sources is overly broad or not, it must be considered when examining German theories.

[210] Philosophy by denying possession to bailees in general cunningly adjusted itself to the Roman law, and thus put itself in a position to claim the authority of that law for the theory of which the mode of dealing with bailees was merely a corollary. Hence I say that it is important to show that a far more developed, more rational, and mightier body of law than the Roman, gives no sanction to either premise or conclusion as held by Kant and his successors.

[210] Philosophy, by denying possession to bailees in general, cleverly aligned itself with Roman law, allowing it to claim that law's authority for its theory, where the treatment of bailees was simply a supporting idea. Therefore, I argue that it’s crucial to demonstrate that a much more advanced, rational, and powerful legal framework than Roman law offers no support for either the premise or conclusion as asserted by Kant and his followers.

In the first place, the English law has always had the good sense /1/ to allow title to be set up in defence to a possessory action. In the assize of novel disseisin, which which was a true possessory action, the defendant could always rely on his title. /2/ Even when possession is taken or kept in a way which is punished by the criminal law, as in case of forcible entry and detainer, proof of title allows the defendant to retain it, and in many cases has been held an answer to an action of trespass. So in trespass for taking goods the defendant may set up title in himself. There might seem to be a trace of the distinction in the general rule, that the title cannot be tried in trespass quare clausum. But this is an exception commonly put on the ground that the judgment cannot change the property, as trespass for chattels or trover can. /3/ The rule that you cannot go into title in a possessory action presupposes great difficulty in the proof, the probatio diabolica of the Canon law, delays in the process, and importance of possession [211] ad interim,—all of which mark a stage of society which has long been passed. In ninety-nine cases out of a hundred, it is about as easy and cheap to prove at least a prima facie title as it is to prove possession.

In the first place, English law has always been smart enough to allow a title to be used as a defense in a possessory action. In the assize of novel disseisin, which was a true possessory action, the defendant could always rely on their title. Even when possession is taken or maintained in a way that is punished by criminal law, as in cases of forcible entry and detainer, proving title lets the defendant keep it, and in many situations, it has been accepted as a defense in a trespass action. So, in a trespass claim for taking goods, the defendant can assert their own title. There might seem to be a hint of a distinction in the general rule that title cannot be disputed in trespass quare clausum. But this is an exception often justified by the fact that the judgment cannot change ownership, unlike trespass for chattels or trover can. The rule that you can't bring up title in a possessory action assumes great difficulty in proving it, the probatio diabolica of Canon law, delays in the legal process, and the significance of possession, all of which reflect a stage of society that has long passed. In ninety-nine cases out of a hundred, it is about as easy and inexpensive to prove at least a preliminary title as it is to prove possession.

In the next place, and this was the importance of the last Lecture to this subject, the common law has always given the possessory remedies to all bailees without exception. The right to these remedies extends not only to pledgees, lessees, and those having a lien, who exclude their bailor, but to simple bailees, as they have been called, who have no interest in the chattels, no right of detention as against the owner, and neither give nor receive a reward. /1/

In addition, and this was the significance of the last lecture on this topic, common law has always provided possessory remedies to all bailees without exception. The right to these remedies applies not just to pledgees, lessees, and those with a lien who keep their bailor out, but also to simple bailees, as they are referred to, who have no interest in the goods, no right to hold onto them against the owner, and neither give nor receive any compensation. /1/

Modern German statutes have followed in the same path so far as to give the possessory remedies to tenants and some others. Bruns says, as the spirit of the Kantian theory required him to say, that this is a sacrifice of principle to convenience. /2/ But I cannot see what is left of a principle which avows itself inconsistent with convenience and the actual course of legislation. The first call of a theory of law is that it should fit the facts. It must explain the observed course of legislation. And as it is pretty certain that men will make laws which seem to them convenient without troubling themselves very much what principles are encountered by their legislation, a principle which defies convenience is likely to wait some time before it finds itself permanently realized.

Modern German laws have taken a similar approach by providing possessory remedies to tenants and others. Bruns argues, as the Kantian theory would suggest, that this is a compromise of principle for the sake of convenience. /2/ However, I don't see what remains of a principle that claims to be at odds with convenience and the actual path of legislation. The primary requirement of a legal theory is that it should align with the facts. It must account for the observable trends in legislation. Since it’s quite likely that people will create laws based on what seems convenient to them without much regard for the principles that might be challenged by their legislation, a principle that contradicts convenience may take a long time to be fully accepted.

It remains, then, to seek for some ground for the protection of possession outside the Bill of Rights or the Declaration of Independence, which shall be consistent with the larger scope given to the conception in modern law.

It’s necessary to look for some basis for protecting possession outside of the Bill of Rights or the Declaration of Independence that aligns with the broader understanding in modern law.

[212] The courts have said but little on the subject. It was laid down in one case that it was an extension of the protection which the law throws around the person, and on that ground held that trespass quare clausum did not pass to an assignee in bankruptcy. /1/ So it has been said, that to deny a bankrupt trover against strangers for goods coming to his possession after his bankruptcy would be "an invitation to all the world to scramble for the possession of them"; and reference was made to "grounds of policy and convenience." /2/ I may also refer to the cases of capture, some of which will be cited again. In the Greenland whale-fishery, by the English custom, if the first striker lost his hold on the fish, and it was then killed by another, the first had no claim; but he had the whole if he kept fast to the whale until it was struck by the other, although it then broke from the first harpoon. By the custom in the Gallipagos, on the other hand, the first striker had half the whale, although control of the line was lost. /3/ Each of these customs has been sustained and acted on by the English courts, and Judge Lowell has decided in accordance with still a third, which gives the whale to the vessel whose iron first remains in it, provided claim be made before cutting in. /4/ The ground as put by Lord Mansfield is simply that, were it not for such customs, there must be a sort of warfare perpetually subsisting between the adventurers. /5/ If courts adopt different rules on similar facts, according to the point at which men will fight in the [213] several cases, it tends, so far as it goes, to shake an a priori theory of the matter.

[212] The courts haven't said much on this topic. In one case, it was established that it was an extension of the protection the law provides for individuals, and based on that, it was determined that trespass quare clausum didn’t transfer to an assignee in bankruptcy. /1/ It has also been stated that denying a bankrupt person's right to recover goods that came into their possession after bankruptcy would be "an invitation to everyone to fight over them"; with mention of "policy and convenience." /2/ I can also refer to the cases of capture, some of which I will mention again. In the Greenland whale fishery, according to English custom, if the first striker lost their grip on the fish, and another person subsequently killed it, the first striker had no claim; however, if they maintained their hold on the whale until it was struck by the other, they kept the whole thing even if it broke free from the first harpoon. In the Galapagos, on the other hand, the first striker received half the whale even if they lost control of the line. /3/ Each of these customs has been upheld and recognized by English courts, and Judge Lowell has ruled in line with a different custom, which grants the whale to the vessel whose iron stays in it first, as long as a claim is made before it is cut up. /4/ Lord Mansfield explained that, without such customs, there would be constant conflict between the adventurers. /5/ If courts apply different rules to similar scenarios based on the points at which people will contest in the [213] various cases, it tends, to some extent, to undermine a priori theories on the subject.

Those who see in the history of law the formal expression of the development of society will be apt to think that the proximate ground of law must be empirical, even when that ground is the fact that a certain ideal or theory of government is generally entertained. Law, being a practical thing, must found itself on actual forces. It is quite enough, therefore, for the law, that man, by an instinct which he shares with the domestic dog, and of which the seal gives a most striking example, will not allow himself to be dispossessed, either by force or fraud, of what he holds, without trying to get it back again. /1/ Philosophy may find a hundred reasons to justify the instinct, but it would be totally immaterial if it should condemn it and bid us surrender without a murmur. As long as the instinct remains, it will be more comfortable for the law to satisfy it in an orderly manner, than to leave people to themselves. If it should do otherwise, it would become a matter for pedagogues, wholly devoid of reality.

Those who view the history of law as a formal reflection of society's development are likely to believe that the foundation of law must be based on empirical evidence, even when that foundation is the general acceptance of a particular ideal or theory of government. Since law is a practical matter, it must be based on real forces. Therefore, it is sufficient for the law that humans, driven by an instinct they share with domestic dogs—of which seals provide a striking example—will not allow themselves to be dispossessed of what they own, whether by force or deceit, without attempting to reclaim it. Philosophy might provide countless justifications for this instinct, but it wouldn't really matter if it condemned it and urged us to surrender without complaint. As long as this instinct exists, it will be easier for the law to address it in an orderly way than to leave people to fend for themselves. If it did otherwise, it would reduce itself to the realm of educators, completely detached from reality.

I think we are now in a position to begin the analysis of possession. It will be instructive to say a word in the first place upon a preliminary question which has been debated with much zeal in Germany. Is possession a fact or a right? This question must be taken to mean, by possession and right, what the law means by those words, and not something else which philosophers or moralists may mean by them; for as lawyers we have nothing to do with either, except in a legal sense. If this had always been borne steadily in mind, the question would hardly have been asked.

I believe we’re now ready to start analyzing possession. First, it’s helpful to touch on a preliminary question that has been hotly debated in Germany: Is possession a fact or a right? This question should be understood in the legal sense of possession and right, not in terms of how philosophers or moralists might interpret them; as lawyers, we only deal with these concepts in a legal context. If this distinction had always been kept in mind, the question probably wouldn’t have been raised at all.

[214] A legal right is nothing but a permission to exercise certain natural powers, and upon certain conditions to obtain protection, restitution, or compensation by the aid of the public force. Just so far as the aid of the public force is given a man, he has a legal right, and this right is the same whether his claim is founded in righteousness or iniquity. Just so far as possession is protected, it is as much a source of legal rights as ownership is when it secures the same protection.

[214] A legal right is simply a permission to use certain natural powers and, under certain conditions, to receive protection, restitution, or compensation with the help of public authority. To the extent that public authority supports a person, they hold a legal right, and this right remains the same whether their claim is based on fairness or unfairness. Similarly, as long as possession is protected, it serves as a source of legal rights just as much as ownership does when it guarantees the same protection.

Every right is a consequence attached by the law to one or more facts which the law defines, and wherever the law gives any one special rights not shared by the body of the people, it does so on the ground that certain special facts, not true of the rest of the world, are true of him. When a group of facts thus singled out by the law exists in the case of a given person, he is said to be entitled to the corresponding rights; meaning, thereby, that the law helps him to constrain his neighbors, or some of them, in a way in which it would not, if all the facts in question were not true of him. Hence, any word which denotes such a group of facts connotes the rights attached to it by way of legal consequences, and any word which denotes the rights attached to a group of facts connotes the group of facts in like manner.

Every right is a consequence that the law links to one or more defined facts, and whenever the law grants someone specific rights that aren’t shared by everyone else, it does so because certain unique facts, which aren’t true for the rest of the population, are true for that person. When a specific group of facts identified by the law applies to a person, that person is considered entitled to the corresponding rights; this means that the law helps them to limit their neighbors, or some of them, in a way it wouldn’t if all the relevant facts didn’t apply to them. Therefore, any term that signifies such a group of facts implies the rights associated with it through legal consequences, and any term that indicates the rights associated with a group of facts likewise implies that group of facts.

The word "possession" denotes such a group of facts. Hence, when we say of a man that he has possession, we affirm directly that all the facts of a certain group are true of him, and we convey indirectly or by implication that the law will give him the advantage of the situation. Contract, or property, or any other substantive notion of the law, may be analyzed in the same way, and should be treated in the same order. The only difference is, that, [215] while possession denotes the facts and connotes the consequence, property always, and contract with more uncertainty and oscillation, denote the consequence and connote the facts. When we say that a man owns a thing, we affirm directly that he has the benefit of the consequences attached to a certain group of facts, and, by implication, that the facts are true of him. The important thing to grasp is, that each of these legal compounds, possession, property, and contract, is to be analyzed into fact and right, antecedent and consequent, in like manner as every other. It is wholly immaterial that one element is accented by one word, and the other by the other two. We are not studying etymology, but law. There are always two things to be asked: first, what are the facts which make up the group in question; and then, what are the consequences attached by the law to that group. The former generally offers the only difficulties.

The term "possession" refers to a specific set of facts. So, when we say a person has possession, we are asserting that all the facts of that particular group apply to him, and we also imply that the law will recognize his advantage in that situation. Concepts like contract, property, or any other significant legal notion can be analyzed similarly and should be treated in the same order. The only difference is that, [215] while possession identifies the facts and suggests the consequences, property consistently—and contracts, with more variability—identify the consequences while implying the facts. When we state that someone owns something, we are directly affirming that they benefit from the consequences related to a specific set of facts and, by implication, affirming that those facts apply to them. The key point to understand is that each of these legal concepts—possession, property, and contract—should be broken down into fact and right, antecedent and consequent, just like any other concept. It doesn’t matter that one aspect is highlighted by one term, while the others are emphasized by the other two. We are not focused on etymology but rather on the law. There are always two key questions to consider: first, what are the facts that make up the relevant group; and second, what are the legal consequences linked to that group? The first aspect usually presents the main challenges.

Hence, it is almost tautologous to say that the protection which the law attaches by way of consequence to possession, is as truly a right in a legal sense as those consequences which are attached to adverse holding for the period of prescription, or to a promise for value or under seal. If the statement is aided by dramatic reinforcement, I may add that possessory rights pass by descent or devise, as well as by conveyance, /1/ and that they are taxed as property in some of the States. /2/

Therefore, it’s almost redundant to point out that the legal protection associated with possession is just as much a right in a legal sense as the rights linked to adverse possession over the period required for prescription, or to a promise made for value or under seal. For added emphasis, I should mention that possessory rights can be inherited or transferred through a will, as well as through a conveyance, /1/ and that they are taxed as property in some states. /2/

We are now ready to analyze possession as understood by the common law. In order to discover the facts which constitute it, it will be found best to study them at the moment when possession is first gained. For then they must [216] all be present in the same way that both consideration and promise must be present at the moment of making a contract. But when we turn to the continuance of possessory rights, or, as is commonly said, the continuance of possession, it will be agreed by all schools that less than all the facts required to call those rights into being need continue presently true in order to keep them alive.

We are now ready to look at possession as it's defined by common law. To figure out the facts that make up possession, it's best to examine them at the moment when possession is first taken. At that point, all necessary elements must be present, just like both consideration and promise must be there when a contract is made. However, when we consider the ongoing possessory rights, or what is often referred to as the continuance of possession, everyone agrees that not all the facts needed to establish those rights need to remain true in order for them to stay valid.

To gain possession, then, a man must stand in a certain physical relation to the object and to the rest of the world, and must have a certain intent. These relations and this intent are the facts of which we are in search.

To take possession, a person must have a specific physical connection to the object and the surrounding world, and must also have a particular intent. These connections and this intent are the facts we are looking for.

The physical relation to others is simply a relation of manifested power coextensive with the intent, and will need to have but little said about it when the nature of the intent is settled. When I come to the latter, I shall not attempt a similar analysis to that which has been pursued with regard to intent as an element of liability. For the principles developed as to intent in that connection have no relation to the present subject, and any such analysis so far as it did not fail would be little more than a discussion of evidence. The intent inquired into here must be overtly manifested, perhaps, but all theories of the grounds on which possession is protected would seem to agree in leading to the requirement that it should be actual, subject, of course, to the necessary limits of legal investigation.

The physical relationship with others is basically a display of power that matches the intent, and not much needs to be said about it once we define the intent. When I address that, I won’t be doing a similar analysis to what was done regarding intent as a factor in liability. The principles established about intent in that context don’t relate to the current topic, and any analysis that didn’t fail would just be a discussion of evidence. The intent we're looking at here should be obviously shown, but it seems like all theories on how possession is protected agree that it should be actual, while still respecting the necessary limits of legal investigation.

But, besides our power and intent as towards our fellow-men, there must be a certain degree of power over the object. If there were only one other man in the world, and he was safe under lock and key in jail, the person having the key would not possess the swallows that flew over the prison. This element is illustrated by cases of capture, [217] although no doubt the point at which the line is drawn is affected by consideration of the degree of power obtained as against other people, as well as by that which has been gained over the object. The Roman and the common law agree that, in general, fresh pursuit of wild animals does not give the pursuer the rights of possession. Until escape has been made impossible by some means, another may step in and kill or catch and carry off the game if he can. Thus it has been held that an action does not lie against a person for killing and taking a fox which had been pursued by another, and was then actually in the view of the person who had originally found, started, and chased it. /1/ The Court of Queen's Bench even went so far as to decide, notwithstanding a verdict the other way, that when fish were nearly surrounded by a seine, with an opening of seven fathoms between the ends, at which point boats were stationed to frighten them from escaping, they were not reduced to possession as against a stranger who rowed in through the opening and helped himself. /2/ But the difference between the power over the object which is sufficient for possession, and that which is not, is clearly one of degree only, and the line may be drawn at different places at different times on grounds just referred to. Thus we are told that the legislature of New York enacted, in 1844, that any one who started and pursued deer in certain counties of that State should be deemed in possession of the game so long as he continued in fresh pursuit of it, /3/ and to that extent modified the New York decisions just cited. So, while Justinian decided that a wild beast so [218] badly wounded that it might easily be taken must be actually taken before it belongs to the captors, /1/ Judge Lowell, with equal reason, has upheld the contrary custom of the American whalemen in the Arctic Ocean, mentioned above, which gives a whale to the vessel whose iron first remains in it, provided claim be made before cutting in. /2/

But besides our power and intention towards others, there must be some level of control over the object itself. If there were only one other person in the world, and he was securely locked away in jail, the person with the key wouldn't own the swallows that flew above the prison. This idea is shown in cases of capture, [217], although the exact point at which we draw the line is influenced by how much control is gained over other people, as well as how much is gained over the object. Both Roman law and common law agree that, generally, pursuing wild animals doesn't grant the pursuer possession rights. Until the escape is completely blocked by some means, anyone else can step in and kill or capture the animal if they can. Therefore, it's been ruled that a person can’t be sued for killing and taking a fox that was being chased by someone else, especially when that fox was visible to the person who originally spotted, started, and pursued it. /1/ The Court of Queen's Bench even decided, despite a different verdict, that when fish were nearly surrounded by a net with a seven-fathom gap between the ends and boats were positioned to scare them from escaping, they hadn’t been possessed by someone who rowed in through the gap and helped themselves. /2/ However, the difference between having control over an object that's enough for possession and that which isn’t, is clearly just a matter of degree, and the line can be drawn at different points at different times due to the reasons mentioned earlier. For instance, the New York legislature enacted in 1844 that anyone who started and pursued deer in certain counties of the state should be considered in possession of the game as long as they continued to pursue it actively, /3/ thus modifying the earlier New York decisions noted. So, while Justinian ruled that a wild animal that was [218] badly wounded must be actually captured before it belongs to the captors, /1/ Judge Lowell reasonably upheld the contrary custom of American whalemen in the Arctic Ocean, as previously mentioned, where the whale belongs to the vessel whose iron first remains in it, provided a claim is made before cutting it up. /2/

We may pass from the physical relation to the object with these few examples, because it cannot often come into consideration except in the case of living and wild things. And so we come to the intent, which is the really troublesome matter. It is just here that we find the German jurists unsatisfactory, for reasons which I have already explained. The best known theories have been framed as theories of the German interpretation of the Roman law, under the influence of some form of Kantian or post-Kantian philosophy. The type of Roman possession, according to German opinion, was that of an owner, or of one on his way to become owner. Following this out, it was said by Savigny, the only writer on the subject with whom English readers are generally acquainted, that the animus domini, or intent to deal with the thing as owner, is in general necessary to turn a mere physical detention into juridical possession. /3/ We need not stop to inquire whether this modern form or the [Greek characters] (animus dominantis, animus dominandi) of Theophilus /4/ and the Greek sources is more exact; for either excludes, as the civilians and canonists do, and as the [219] German theories must, most bailees and termors from the list of possessors. /1/

We can move from the physical relationship to the object with these few examples, since it usually only applies to living and wild things. This brings us to intent, which is the really tricky part. It’s here that the German jurists fall short, for reasons I've already mentioned. The most well-known theories have been shaped as theories of the German interpretation of Roman law, influenced by some form of Kantian or post-Kantian philosophy. According to German thought, the type of Roman possession was that of an owner or someone on the path to becoming an owner. Following this, Savigny, the only writer on this topic that English readers are generally familiar with, stated that the animus domini, or intent to treat the thing as an owner, is usually necessary to change a simple physical detention into legal possession. /3/ We don't need to determine whether this modern version or the [Greek characters] (animus dominantis, animus dominandi) of Theophilus /4/ and the Greek sources is more accurate; either way, it excludes, just as the civilians and canonists do, and as the [219] German theories must, most bailees and termors from the list of possessors. /1/

The effect of this exclusion as interpreted by the Kantian philosophy of law, has been to lead the German lawyers to consider the intent necessary to possession as primarily self-regarding. Their philosophy teaches them that a man's physical power over an object is protected because he has the will to make it his, and it has thus become a part of his very self, the external manifestation of his freedom. /2/ The will of the possessor being thus conceived as self-regarding, the intent with which he must hold is pretty clear: he must hold for his own benefit. Furthermore, the self-regarding intent must go to the height of an intent to appropriate; for otherwise, it seems to be implied, the object would not truly be brought under the personality of the possessor.

The impact of this exclusion, as understood through Kantian legal philosophy, has led German lawyers to view the intention required for possession as mainly self-centered. Their philosophy suggests that a person's physical control over an object is safeguarded because they intend to claim it as their own, making it a part of their identity and an expression of their freedom. Since the possessor's will is seen as self-focused, it's clear what intent they must have: they should possess for their own advantage. Moreover, this self-focused intent must reach the level of an intent to claim; otherwise, it implicitly suggests that the object wouldn't genuinely be under the possessor's identity.

The grounds for rejecting the criteria of the Roman law have been shown above. Let us begin afresh. Legal duties are logically antecedent to legal rights. What may be their relation to moral rights if there are any, and whether moral rights are not in like manner logically the offspring of moral duties, are questions which do not concern us here. These are for the philosopher, who approaches the law from without as part of a larger series of human manifestations. The business of the jurist is to make known the content of the law; that is, to work upon it from within, or logically, arranging and distributing it, in order, from its stemmum genus to its infima species, so far as practicable. Legal duties then come before legal [220] rights. To put it more broadly, and avoid the word duty, which is open to objection, the direct working of the law is to limit freedom of action or choice on the part of a greater or less number of persons in certain specified ways; while the power of removing or enforcing this limitation which is generally confided to certain other private persons, or, in other words, a right corresponding to the burden, is not a necessary or universal correlative. Again, a large part of the advantages enjoyed by one who has a right are not created by the law. The law does not enable me to use or abuse this book which lies before me. That is a physical power which I have without the aid of the law. What the law does is simply to prevent other men to a greater or less extent from interfering with my use or abuse. And this analysis and example apply to the case of possession, as well as to ownership.

The reasons for rejecting the criteria of Roman law have been discussed above. Let’s start over. Legal duties logically come before legal rights. What their relationship is to moral rights, if they exist, and whether moral rights are similarly the result of moral duties are questions we won’t explore here. Those are for philosophers, who look at the law as part of a bigger picture of human behavior. The role of the legal expert is to clarify what the law entails; that is, to work from within it, logically organizing and categorizing it, from its broadest categories down to its most specific instances, as much as possible. Legal duties precede legal rights. To broaden this and avoid the potentially problematic term "duty," we can say that the main function of the law is to restrict the freedom of action or choice for a greater or lesser number of people in certain defined ways. The ability to lift or enforce this restriction, which is generally given to certain other private individuals—or in other words, a right that corresponds to the obligation—is not necessarily or universally required. Additionally, many benefits enjoyed by someone with a right are not granted by the law. The law doesn’t give me the ability to use or misuse this book in front of me. That’s a physical ability I possess without the law’s assistance. What the law does is simply limit other people’s ability to interfere with my use or misuse of it. This analysis and example apply to possession as well as ownership.

Such being the direct working of the law in the case of possession, one would think that the animus or intent most nearly parallel to its movement would be the intent of which we are in search. If what the law does is to exclude others from interfering with the object, it would seem that the intent which the law should require is an intent to exclude others. I believe that such an intent is all that the common law deems needful, and that on principle no more should be required.

Given how the law operates regarding possession, one might assume that the intent closely linked to this action is the intent we are looking for. If the law is designed to prevent others from interfering with the object, it seems logical that the intent required by the law is simply the intent to keep others out. I believe that's all the common law considers necessary, and that, in principle, nothing more should be needed.

It may be asked whether this is not simply the animus domini looked at from the other side. If it were, it would nevertheless be better to look at the front of the shield than at the reverse. But it is not the same if we give to the animus domini the meaning which the Germans give it, and which denies possession to bailees in general. The intent to appropriate or deal with a thing as owner can [221] hardly exist without an intent to exclude others, and something more; but the latter may very well be where there is no intent to hold as owner. A tenant for years intends to exclude all persons, including the owner, until the end of his term; yet he has not the animus domini in the sense explained. Still less has a bailee with a lien, who does not even mean to use, but only to detain the thing for payment. But, further, the common law protects a bailee against strangers, when it would not protect him against the owner, as in the case of a deposit or other bailment terminable at pleasure; and we may therefore say that the intent even to exclude need not be so extensive as would be implied in the animus domini. If a bailee intends to exclude strangers to the title, it is enough for possession under our law, although he is perfectly ready to give the thing up to its owner at any moment; while it is of the essence of the German view that the intent must not be relative, but an absolute, self-regarding intent to take the benefit of the thing. Again, if the motives or wishes, and even the intentions, most present to the mind of a possessor, were all self-regarding, it would not follow that the intent toward others was not the important thing in the analysis of the law. But, as we have seen, a depositary is a true possessor under the common-law theory, although his intent is not self-regarding, and he holds solely for the benefit of the owner.

It might be asked whether this is just the mindset of the owner viewed from the other side. If it were, it would be better to look at the front of the shield than the back. However, it’s different if we interpret the mindset of the owner the way the Germans do, which denies possession to bailees in general. The intent to treat something as if you owned it can hardly exist without wanting to exclude others, and something more; but that "more" can definitely be present even if there’s no intent to hold as an owner. A tenant for years intends to exclude everyone, including the owner, until the end of their lease; yet they don’t have the owner’s mindset as explained. Even less does a bailee with a lien, who doesn’t mean to use the item but only to keep it until payment. Moreover, common law protects a bailee against outsiders, even when it wouldn’t protect them against the owner, like in cases of a deposit or other bailments that can be ended at any time; so we can say that the intent to exclude doesn’t have to be as broad as implied in the mindset of the owner. If a bailee wants to exclude those without a title, that’s enough for possession under our law, even though they’re fully prepared to return the item to its owner at any point; while the essence of the German perspective is that the intent must be absolute and focused solely on benefiting from the item. Again, even if the motives or desires, and even the intentions, most prominent in a possessor's mind are all self-centered, that doesn’t mean that their intent toward others isn’t the crucial factor in analyzing the law. But, as we've seen, a depositary is truly a possessor under common law theory, even though their intent is not self-serving, and they hold solely for the owner's benefit.

There is a class of cases besides those of bailees and tenants, which will probably, although not necessarily, be decided one way or the other, as we adopt the test of an intent to exclude, or of the animus domini. Bridges v. Hawkesworth /1/ will serve as a starting-point. There, [222] a pocket-book was dropped on the floor of a shop by a customer, and picked up by another customer before the shopkeeper knew of it. Common-law judges and civilians would agree that the finder got possession first, and so could keep it as against the shopkeeper. For the shopkeeper, not knowing of the thing, could not have the intent to appropriate it, and, having invited the public to his shop, he could not have the intent to exclude them from it. But suppose the pocket-book had been dropped in a private room, how should the case be decided? There can be no animus domini unless the thing is known of; but an intent to exclude others from it may be contained in the larger intent to exclude others from the place where it is, without any knowledge of the object's existence.

There is a type of case beyond those involving bailees and tenants that will likely, though not necessarily, be resolved in one direction or the other, as we apply the test of intent to exclude, or animus domini. Bridges v. Hawkesworth /1/ will be a good starting point. In that case, a pocketbook was dropped on the floor of a shop by a customer and was picked up by another customer before the shopkeeper was aware of it. Common law judges and legal scholars would agree that the finder took possession first, allowing them to keep it against the shopkeeper. The shopkeeper, being unaware of the item, could not have intended to claim it, and having invited the public into his shop, he could not have intended to exclude them from it. But what if the pocketbook had been dropped in a private room? How would that case be resolved? There can be no animus domini unless the object is known; however, the intention to exclude others from it may exist within a broader intent to exclude others from the location it's in, even without any awareness of the item itself.

In McAvoy v. Medina, /1/ a pocket-book had been left upon a barber's table, and it was held that the barber had a better right than the finder. The opinion is rather obscure. It takes a distinction between things voluntarily placed on a table and things dropped on the floor, and may possibly go on the ground that, when the owner leaves a thing in that way, there is an implied request to the shopkeeper to guard it, which will give him a better right than one who actually finds it before him. This is rather strained, however, and the court perhaps thought that the barber had possession as soon as the customer left the shop. A little later, in a suit for a reward offered to the finder of a pocket-book, brought by one who discovered it where the owner had left it, on a desk for the use of customers in a bank outside the teller's counter, the same court said that this was not the finding of a lost article, and that "the occupants of the banking house, and not [223] the plaintiff, were the proper depositaries of an article so left." /1/ This language might seem to imply that the plaintiff was not the person who got possession first after the defendant, and that, although the floor of a shop may be likened to a street, the public are to be deemed excluded from the shop's desks, counters, and tables except for the specific use permitted. Perhaps, however, the case only decides that the pocket-book was not lost within the condition of the offer.

In McAvoy v. Medina, /1/ a wallet was left on a barber's table, and the court ruled that the barber had a superior right to it than the person who found it. The reasoning is somewhat unclear. It differentiates between items voluntarily placed on a table and those dropped on the floor. It may be based on the idea that when an owner leaves an item in that manner, it implies a request for the shopkeeper to keep it safe, giving him a better right than someone who finds it later. This interpretation seems a bit forced, though, and the court might have believed that the barber took possession as soon as the customer left the shop. Shortly after, in a case regarding a reward offered for the finder of a wallet, which was discovered in a bank on a customer desk outside the teller's counter, the same court stated that this wasn't considered the finding of a lost item and asserted that "the occupants of the banking house, and not [223] the plaintiff, were the appropriate custodians of an item left there." /1/ This statement might suggest that the plaintiff wasn't the first to take possession after the defendant, and even though the shop's floor could be compared to a street, the public is regarded as being excluded from the shop's desks, counters, and tables unless specifically allowed. However, the case might simply clarify that the wallet was not lost under the terms of the reward offer.

I should not have thought it safe to draw any conclusion from wreck cases in England, which are mixed up with questions of prescription and other rights. But the precise point seems to have been adjudicated here. For it has been held that, if a stick of timber comes ashore on a man's land, he thereby acquires a "right of possession" as against an actual finder who enters for the purpose of removing it. /2/ A right of possession is said to be enough for trespass; but the court seems to have meant possession by the phrase, inasmuch as Chief Justice Shaw states the question to be which of the parties had "the preferable claim, by mere naked possession, without other title," and as there does not seem to have been any right of possession in the case unless there was actual possession.

I shouldn't have thought it was safe to draw any conclusions from shipwreck cases in England, which involve issues of ownership and other rights. However, the exact point seems to have been decided here. It's been determined that if a piece of timber washes up on someone's property, that person gains a "right of possession" against anyone who tries to take it. A right of possession is said to be sufficient for a trespass claim; however, the court appears to have intended possession by this phrase, since Chief Justice Shaw framed the question as which party had "the preferable claim, by mere naked possession, without other title," and it seems there wasn't any right of possession in this case unless there was actual possession.

In a criminal case, the property in iron taken from the bottom of a canal by a stranger was held well laid in the canal company, although it does not appear that the company knew of it, or had any lien upon it. /3/

In a criminal case, the iron taken from the bottom of a canal by a stranger was determined to belong to the canal company, even though it doesn't seem like the company was aware of it or had any claim on it. /3/

[224] The only intent concerning the thing discoverable in such instances is the general intent which the occupant of land has to exclude the public from the land, and thus, as a consequence, to exclude them from what is upon it.

[224] The only intention regarding what can be found in these situations is the general intent that the landowner has to keep the public out of the land, and as a result, to keep them away from what’s on it.

The Roman lawyers would probably have decided all these cases differently, although they cannot be supposed to have worked out the refined theories which have been built upon their remains. /1/

The Roman lawyers would likely have ruled on all these cases differently, even though they probably didn't develop the sophisticated theories that have been constructed from their remains. /1/

I may here return to the case of goods in a chest delivered under lock and key, or in a bale, and the like. It is a rule of the criminal law, that, if a bailee of such a chest or bale wrongfully sells the entire chest or bale, he does not commit larceny, but if he breaks bulk he does, because in the former case he does not, and in the latter he does, commit a trespass. /2/ The reason sometimes offered is, that, by breaking bulk, the bailee determines the bailment, and that the goods at once revest in the possession of the bailor. This is, perhaps, an unnecessary, as well as inadequate fiction. /3/ The rule comes from the Year Books, and the theory of the Year Books was, that, although the chest was delivered to the bailee, the goods inside of it were not, and this theory was applied to civil as well as criminal cases. The bailor has the power and intent to exclude the bailee from the goods, and therefore may be said to be in possession of them as against the bailee. /4/

I can now go back to the situation involving goods in a locked chest or in a bale, and similar cases. According to criminal law, if someone who has been given a chest or bale wrongly sells the entire item, it’s not considered theft. However, if they take out some of the items, it is theft, because in the first scenario, they don’t commit a trespass and in the second, they do. One explanation often given is that by taking out items, the bailee ends the bailment, and the goods immediately return to the possession of the bailor. This idea might be unnecessary and insufficient as a legal fiction. The rule comes from historical legal texts known as the Year Books, which argued that even though the bailee received the chest, they did not receive the goods inside. This concept applied to both civil and criminal matters. The bailor has the right and intention to keep the bailee from the goods and can thus be considered to still possess them in relation to the bailee.

[225] On the other hand, a case in Rhode Island /1/ is against the view here taken. A man bought a safe, and then, wishing to sell it again, sent it to the defendant, and gave him leave to keep his books in it until sold. The defendant found some bank-notes stuck in a crevice of the safe, which coming to the plaintiff's ears he demanded the safe and the money. The defendant sent back the safe, but refused to give up the money, and the court sustained him in his refusal. I venture to think this decision wrong. Nor would my opinion be changed by assuming, what the report does not make perfectly clear, that the defendant received the safe as bailee, and not as servant or agent, and that his permission to use the safe was general. The argument of the court goes on the plaintiff's not being a finder. The question is whether he need be. It is hard to believe that, if the defendant had stolen the bills from the safe while it was in the owner's hands, the property could not have been laid in the safe-owner, /2/ or that the latter could not have maintained trover for them if converted under those circumstances. Sir James Stephen seems to have drawn a similar conclusion from Cartwright v. Green and Merry v. Green; /3/ but I believe that no warrant for it can be found in the cases, and still less for the reason suggested.

[225] On the other hand, there's a case in Rhode Island /1/ that goes against the view presented here. A man bought a safe and then, wanting to sell it again, sent it to the defendant, allowing him to store his books in it until it was sold. The defendant discovered some banknotes stuck in a crevice of the safe, and when the plaintiff found out, he demanded both the safe and the money. The defendant returned the safe but refused to hand over the money, and the court supported him in his refusal. I believe this decision is wrong. My opinion wouldn't change even if we assume, though the report doesn't make this clear, that the defendant received the safe as a bailee and not as a servant or agent, and that his permission to use the safe was broad. The court's argument hinges on the plaintiff not being a finder. The question is whether he needs to be. It's hard to believe that if the defendant had stolen the bills from the safe while it was still in the owner's possession, the property couldn't have been attributed to the safe-owner /2/ or that the owner couldn't have pursued a trover claim for them if they were converted under those circumstances. Sir James Stephen seems to reach a similar conclusion in Cartwright v. Green and Merry v. Green; /3/ but I believe there's no support for it in those cases, and even less for the suggested reasoning.

It will be understood, however, that Durfee v. Jones is perfectly consistent with the view here maintained of the [226] general nature of the necessary intent, and that it only touches the subordinate question, whether the intent to exclude must be directed to the specific thing, or may be even unconsciously included in a larger intent, as I am inclined to believe.

It’s important to note that Durfee v. Jones aligns perfectly with the perspective presented here regarding the [226] general nature of the necessary intent. It only addresses the secondary issue of whether the intent to exclude needs to focus on a specific item or can be unconsciously included as part of a broader intention, which I tend to believe.

Thus far, nothing has been said with regard to the custody of servants. It is a well-known doctrine of the criminal law, that a servant who criminally converts property of his master intrusted to him and in his custody as servant, is guilty of theft, because he is deemed to have taken the property from his master's possession. This is equivalent to saying that a servant, having the custody of his master's property as servant, has not possession of that property, and it is so stated in the Year Books. /1/

So far, nothing has been mentioned about the custody of employees. It's a well-known principle of criminal law that if an employee illegally takes their employer's property that has been entrusted to them, they are guilty of theft because it's considered that they have taken the property from their employer’s possession. Essentially, this means that an employee, who has custody of their employer's property in their role, does not actually possess that property, as stated in the Year Books. /1/

The anomalous distinction according to which, if the servant receives the thing from another person for his master, the servant has the possession, and so cannot commit theft, /2/ is made more rational by the old cases. For the distinction taken in them is, that, while the servant is in the house or with his master, the latter retains possession, but if he delivers his horse to his servant to ride to market, or gives him a bag to carry to London, then the thing is out of the master's possession and in the servant's. /3/ In this more intelligible form, the rule would not now prevail. But one half of it, that a guest at a tavern has not possession of the plate with which he is served, is no doubt still law, [227] for guests in general are likened to servants in their legal position. /1/

The unusual difference that states if a servant receives something from someone else for their master, the servant has possession and therefore can't steal, is made clearer by old cases. The distinction in those cases is that while the servant is in the house or with their master, the master keeps possession. However, if the master hands over their horse for the servant to ride to market or gives them a bag to carry to London, then the item is no longer in the master's possession and is with the servant. In this clearer form, the rule wouldn't hold up today. However, one part of it, that a guest in a tavern doesn’t have possession of the dish they were served, is still considered law, since guests are generally treated like servants in their legal standing. [227]

There are few English decisions, outside the criminal on the question whether a servant has possession. But the Year Books do not suggest any difference between civil and criminal cases, and there is an almost tradition of courts and approved writers that he has not, in any case. A master has maintained trespass against a servant for converting cloth which he was employed to sell, /2/ and the American cases go the full length of the old doctrine. It has often been remarked that a servant must be distinguished from a bailee.

There are few English decisions, outside of criminal cases, about whether a servant has possession. However, the Year Books don't indicate any difference between civil and criminal cases, and there's an almost established understanding among courts and respected writers that there isn't any distinction in any case. A master has successfully brought a trespass action against a servant for converting cloth that he was hired to sell, and the American cases fully support the old doctrine. It has often been noted that a servant should be differentiated from a bailee.

But it may be asked how the denial of possession to servants can be made to agree with the test proposed, and it will be said with truth that the servant has as much the intent to exclude the world at large as a borrower. The law of servants is unquestionably at variance with that test; and there can be no doubt that those who have built their theories upon the Roman law have been led by this fact, coupled with the Roman doctrine as to bailees in general, to seek the formula of reconciliation where they have. But, in truth, the exception with regard to servants stands on purely historical grounds. A servant is denied possession, not from any peculiarity of intent with regard to the things in his custody, either towards his master or other people, by which he is distinguished [228] from a depositary, but simply as one of the incidents of his status. It is familiar that the status of a servant maintains many marks of the time when he was a slave. The liability of the master for his torts is one instance. The present is another. A slave's possession was his owner's possession on the practical ground of the owner's power over him, /1/ and from the fact that the slave had no standing before the law. The notion that his personality was merged in that of his family head survived the era of emancipation.

But it can be asked how denying possession to servants aligns with the proposed test, and it can truthfully be said that a servant intends to exclude the world just as much as a borrower does. The law regarding servants is clearly at odds with that test; and it is undeniable that those who have based their theories on Roman law have been led by this reality, along with the Roman doctrine involving bailees in general, to search for a way to reconcile these differences. However, in reality, the exception concerning servants is based purely on historical reasons. A servant is denied possession not because of any unique intent regarding the items in their care, whether towards their master or others, which would set them apart from a depositary, but simply as a consequence of their status. It is well known that a servant’s status carries many reminders of the time when they were a slave. The master’s liability for their wrongs is one example. This situation is another. A slave's possession was considered the owner's possession because of the owner's control over them, and due to the fact that the slave had no legal standing. The idea that a slave's identity was intertwined with that of their family head persisted even after emancipation.

I have shown in the first Lecture /2/ that agency arose out of the earlier relation in the Roman law, through the extension pro hac vice to a freeman of conceptions derived from that source. The same is true, I think, of our own law, the later development of which seems to have been largely under Roman influence. As late as Blackstone, agents appear under the general head of servants, and the first precedents cited for the peculiar law of agents were cases of master and servant. Blackstone's language is worth quoting: "There is yet a fourth species of servants, if they may be so called, being rather in a superior, a ministerial capacity; such as stewards, factors, and bailiffs: whom, however, the law considers as servants pro tempore, with regard to such of their acts as affect their master's or employer's property." /3/

I showed in the first Lecture /2/ that agency developed from earlier relationships in Roman law by extending certain concepts to a free person. I believe this is also true for our own legal system, which seems to have evolved significantly under Roman influence. Even as late as Blackstone's time, agents were categorized under the general label of servants, and the initial examples provided for the specific law of agents were cases involving master and servant. Blackstone's wording is noteworthy: "There is yet a fourth type of servants, if they may be called that, acting in a superior, ministerial role; such as stewards, factors, and bailiffs: who the law, however, regards as servants pro tempore, concerning those acts of theirs that impact their master's or employer's property." /3/

[229] It is very true that in modern times many of the effects of either relation—master and servant or principal and agent—may be accounted for as the result of acts done by the master himself. If a man tells another to make a contract in his name, or commands him to commit a tort, no special conception is needed to explain why he is held; although even in such cases, where the intermediate party was a freeman, the conclusion was not reached until the law had become somewhat mature. But, if the title Agency deserves to stand in the law at all, it must be because some peculiar consequences are attached to the fact of the relation. If the mere power to bind a principal to an authorized contract were all, we might as well have a chapter on ink and paper as on agents. But it is not all. Even in the domain of contract, we find the striking doctrine that an undisclosed principal has the rights as well as the obligations of a known contractor,—that he can be sued, and, more remarkable, can sue on his agent's contract. The first precedent cited for the proposition that a promise to an agent may be laid as a promise to the principal, is a case of master and servant. /1/

[229] It is very true that in modern times, many of the effects of either relationship—master and servant or principal and agent—can be explained as actions taken by the master himself. If a person tells someone else to make a contract in his name, or instructs him to commit a wrongful act, no special understanding is needed to explain why he is held responsible; although, even in these cases, when the middle person was a free individual, the conclusion wasn't reached until the law had evolved somewhat. However, if the term Agency has any place in the law, it must be because some specific consequences are linked to this relationship. If the only aspect was the power to bind a principal to an authorized contract, we might as well have a chapter on ink and paper instead of agents. But it’s not just that. Even in the area of contracts, we find the notable principle that an undisclosed principal has both rights and obligations just like a known contractor—that he can be sued, and, even more surprisingly, can sue based on his agent's contract. The first precedent cited for the idea that a promise made to an agent can also be seen as a promise to the principal comes from a case involving master and servant. /1/

As my present object is only to show the meaning of the doctrine of identification in its bearing upon the theory of possession, it would be out of place to consider at any length how far that doctrine must be invoked to explain the liability of principals for their agents' torts, or whether a more reasonable rule governs other cases than that applied where the actor has a tolerably defined status as a [230] servant. I allow myself a few words, because I shall not be able to return to the subject.

As my current goal is simply to explain the meaning of the doctrine of identification in relation to the theory of possession, it wouldn’t be appropriate to discuss at length how this doctrine applies to the liability of principals for their agents' torts, or whether a more reasonable rule applies in other situations than the one used when the actor has a clearly defined status as a [230] servant. I’ll allow myself a few comments here because I won’t have the chance to revisit this topic.

If the liability of a master for the torts of his servant had hitherto been recognized by the courts as the decaying remnant of an obsolete institution, it would not be surprising to find it confined to the cases settled by ancient precedent. But such has not been the fact. It has been extended to new relations by analogy, /1/ It exists where the principal does not stand in the relation of paterfamilias to the actual wrong-doer. /2/ A man may be held for another where the relation was of such a transitory nature as to exclude the conception of status, as for the negligence of another person's servant momentarily acting for the defendant, or of a neighbor helping him as a volunteer; /3/ and, so far as known, no principal has ever escaped on the ground of the dignity of his agent's employment. /4/ The courts habitually speak as if the same rules applied to brokers and other agents, as to servants properly so called. /5/ Indeed, it [231] has been laid down in terms, that the liability of employers is not confined to the case of servants, /1/ although the usual cases are, of course, those of menial servants, and the like, who could not pay a large verdict.

If a master’s liability for the wrongdoings of his servant had previously been seen by the courts as a leftover from an outdated institution, it wouldn’t be surprising to find it limited to cases established by old precedents. However, that hasn’t been the case. It has been expanded to new relationships by analogy. It exists even when the principal isn’t in a paternal role to the actual wrong-doer. A person can be held responsible for another when the relationship is so temporary that it doesn’t imply a status, such as when someone’s servant is acting on behalf of the defendant for a brief moment, or when a neighbor is helping out voluntarily. Moreover, to the best of our knowledge, no principal has ever avoided liability based on the dignity of their agent’s job. The courts commonly imply that the same rules apply to brokers and other agents as they do to traditional servants. In fact, it has been clearly stated that employer liability isn’t limited to cases involving servants, although the most typical cases involve domestic servants and similar roles, who are unlikely to pay a significant verdict.

On the other hand, if the peculiar doctrines of agency are anomalous, and form, as I believe, the vanishing point of the servile status, it may well happen that common sense will refuse to carry them out to their furthest applications. Such conflicts between tradition and the instinct of justice we may see upon the question of identifying a principal who knows the truth with an agent who makes a false representation, in order to make out a fraud, as in Cornfoot v. Fowke, /2/ or upon that as to the liability of a principal for the frauds of his agent discussed in many English cases. /3/ But, so long as the fiction which makes the root of a master's liability is left alive, it is as hopeless to reconcile the differences by logic as to square the circle.

On the other hand, if the strange principles of agency seem out of place, and I believe they signify the end of the servile status, it's possible that common sense will resist extending them to their fullest implications. We can see these clashes between tradition and the sense of justice in discussions about identifying a principal who knows the truth versus an agent who makes a false claim to prove fraud, like in Cornfoot v. Fowke, /2/ or in debates about a principal's liability for their agent's frauds discussed in many English cases. /3/ However, as long as the fiction that underpins a master's liability remains, trying to reconcile these differences through logic is as impossible as squaring the circle.

In an article in the American Law Review /4/ I referred [232] to an expression of Godefroi with regard to agents; eadem est persona domini et procuratoris. /1/ This notion of a fictitious unity of person has been pronounced a darkening of counsel in a recent useful work. /2/ But it receives the sanction of Sir Henry Maine, /3/ and I believe that it must stand as expressing an important aspect of the law, if, as I have tried to show, there is no adequate and complete explanation of the modern law, except by the survival in practice of rules which lost their true meaning when the objects of them ceased to be slaves. There is no trouble in understanding what is meant by saying that a slave has no legal standing, but is absorbed in the family which his master represents before the law. The meaning seems equally clear when we say that a free servant, in his relations as such, is in many respects likened by the law to a slave (not, of course, to his own detriment as a freeman). The next step is simply that others not servants in a general sense may be treated as if servants in a particular connection. This is the progress of ideas as shown us by history; and this is what is meant by saying that the characteristic feature which justifies agency as a title of the law is the absorption pro hac vice of the agent's legal individuality in that of his principal.

In an article in the American Law Review /4/ I referred [232] to a statement by Godefroi regarding agents; the identity of the principal and the agent is the same. /1/ This idea of a fictional unity of person has been criticized as confusing in a recent helpful work. /2/ However, it has the approval of Sir Henry Maine, /3/ and I believe it remains significant in understanding an important aspect of the law, especially if, as I've tried to demonstrate, there isn't a sufficient and complete explanation of modern law without recognizing the persistence in practice of rules that lost their true meaning when the subjects ceased to be slaves. It's easy to grasp what it means when we say a slave has no legal standing and is instead included in the family represented by his master before the law. The meaning seems just as clear when we say that a free servant, in his role, is in many ways treated by the law like a slave (not, of course, to his own disadvantage as a free person). The next step is simply that others who aren’t servants in a general sense may be treated as if they are in a specific context. This progression of ideas is illustrated by history; and this is what is meant by saying that the defining feature that legitimizes agency within the law is the temporary absorption of the agent's legal individuality into that of his principal.

If this were carried out logically, it would follow that an agent constituted to hold possession in his principal's name would not be regarded as having the legal possession, or as entitled to trespass. But, after what has been said, no opinion can be expressed whether the law would go so far, unless it is shown by precedent. /4/ The nature of the case [233] will be observed. It is that of an agent constituted for the very point and purpose of possession. A bailee may be an agent for some other purpose. A free servant may be made a bailee. But the bailee holds in his own as we say, following the Roman idiom, and the servant or agent holding as such does not.

If this were done logically, it would mean that an agent designated to hold possession in their principal's name wouldn't actually have legal possession or the right to trespass. However, based on what’s been discussed, no firm opinion can be made about how far the law will go unless there is supporting precedent. /4/ The nature of the case [233] will be noted. It involves an agent appointed specifically for the purpose of possession. A bailee can also act as an agent for other reasons. A regular employee can be made a bailee. But the bailee holds possession in their own right, as we say, following the Roman phrase, while the employee or agent holding as such does not.

It would hardly be worth while, if space allowed, to search the books on this subject, because of the great confusion of language to be found in them. It has been said, for instance, in this connection, that a carrier is a servant; /1/ while nothing can be clearer than that, while goods are in custody, they are in his possession. /2/ So where goods remain in the custody of a vendor, appropriation to the contract and acceptance have been confounded with delivery. /3/ Our law has adopted the Roman doctrine, /4/ that there may be a delivery, that is, a change of possession, by a change in the character in which the vendor holds, but has not always imitated the caution of the civilians with regard to what amounts to such a change. /5/ Bailees are constantly spoken of as if they were agents to possess,—a confusion made [234] easier by the fact that they generally are agents for other purposes. Those cases which attribute possession to a transferee of goods in the hands of a middleman, /1/ without distinguishing whether the middleman holds in his own name or the buyer's, are generally right in the result, no doubt, but have added to the confusion of thought upon the subject.

It wouldn't really be worth it, if there was enough space, to search the books on this topic because of the huge confusion in the language used. For example, it has been said that a carrier is a servant; while it's clear that when goods are in custody, they are in his possession. Similarly, when goods remain with a vendor, appropriation to the contract and acceptance have been mixed up with delivery. Our law has adopted the Roman idea that there can be a delivery, meaning a change of possession, by a shift in how the vendor holds the goods, but it hasn't always followed the caution of the legal experts regarding what counts as such a change. Bailees are often referred to as if they were agents to possess—this confusion is made easier by the fact that they are usually agents for other things. Those cases that attribute possession to a transferee of goods in the hands of a middleman, without clarifying whether the middleman holds in his own name or the buyer's, are often correct in the outcome but have contributed to the confusion surrounding the topic.

German writers are a little apt to value a theory of possession somewhat in proportion to the breadth of the distinction which it draws between juridical possession and actual detention; but, from the point of view taken here, it will be seen that the grounds for denying possession and the possessory remedies to servants and agents holding as such—if, indeed, the latter have not those remedies—are merely historical, and that the general theory can only take account of the denial as an anomaly. It will also be perceived that the ground on which servants and depositaries have been often likened to each other, namely, that they both hold for the benefit of another and not for themselves, is wholly without influence on our law, which has always treated depositaries as having possession; and is not the true explanation of the Roman doctrine, which did not decide either case upon that ground, and which decided each for reasons different from those on which it decided the other.

German writers tend to value a theory of possession based on how sharply it distinguishes between legal possession and actual control; however, from the perspective presented here, it will become clear that the reasons for denying possession and the possessory rights of servants and agents—if, indeed, they lack those rights—are simply historical. The general theory can only view the denial as an exception. It will also be noted that the basis on which servants and depositaries have often been compared, that they both hold for someone else's benefit rather than their own, is completely irrelevant to our law, which has consistently regarded depositaries as having possession. This is not the true reasoning behind the Roman doctrine, which did not base its decisions in either case on that point and approached each situation for different reasons than the other.

It will now be easy to deal with the question of power as to third persons. This is naturally a power coextensive with the intent. But we must bear in mind that the law deals only or mainly with manifested facts; and hence, when we speak of a power to exclude others, we mean no more than a power which so appears in its manifestation. [235] A ruffian may be within equal reach and sight when a child picks up a pocket-book; but if he does nothing, the child has manifested the needful power as well as if it had been backed by a hundred policemen. Thus narrowed, it might be suggested that the manifestation of is only important as a manifestation of intent. But the two things are distinct, and the former becomes decisive when there are two contemporaneous and conflicting intents. Thus, where two parties, neither having title, claimed a crop of corn adversely to each other, and cultivated it alternately, and the plaintiff gathered and threw it in small piles in the same field, where it lay for a week, and then each party simultaneously began to carry it away, it was held the plaintiff had not gained possession. /1/ But the first interference of the defendant had been after the gathering into piles, the plaintiff would probably have recovered. /2/ So where trustees possessed of a schoolroom put in a schoolmaster, and he was afterwards dismissed, but the next day (June 30) re-entered by force; on the fourth of July he was required by notice to depart, and was not ejected until the eleventh; it was considered that the schoolmaster never got possession as against the trustees. /3/

It’s now straightforward to address the issue of power concerning third parties. This power naturally aligns with intent. However, we need to remember that the law primarily deals with what is expressed or demonstrated; so when we talk about the power to exclude others, we mean a power that is evident in its expression. [235] A thug may be just as close and visible when a child picks up a wallet; but if he does nothing, the child has shown the necessary power just as effectively as if it had been supported by a hundred police officers. With this in mind, it could be argued that the manifestation is only significant as an indication of intent. But the two aspects are different, and the former becomes critical when there are two conflicting intents at the same time. For example, when two parties, neither having ownership, laid claim to a field of corn against each other and took turns cultivating it, and the plaintiff gathered it into small piles in the same field where it remained for a week, then both parties started to take it away simultaneously, it was ruled that the plaintiff did not gain possession. /1/ However, if the defendant had interfered after the corn was gathered into piles, the plaintiff would likely have won. /2/ Likewise, when trustees in charge of a classroom hired a schoolmaster who was later dismissed, but the next day (June 30) forcibly re-entered; on July 4, he was ordered to leave and was not removed until the 11th; it was determined that the schoolmaster never established possession over the trustees. /3/

We are led, in this connection, to the subject of the continuance of the rights acquired by gaining possession. To gain possession, it has been seen, there must be certain physical relations, as explained, and a certain intent. It remains to be inquired, how far these facts must continue [236] to be presently true of a person in order that he may keep the rights which follow from their presence. The prevailing view is that of Savigny. He thinks that there must be always the same animus as at the moment of acquisition, and a constant power to reproduce at will the original physical relations to the object. Every one agrees that it is not necessary to have always a present power over the thing, otherwise one could only possess what was under his hand. But it is a question whether we cannot dispense with even more. The facts which constitute possession are in their nature capable of continuing presently true for a lifetime. Hence there has arisen an ambiguity of language which has led to much confusion of thought. We use the word "possession," indifferently, to signify the presence of all the facts needful to gain it, and also the condition of him who, although some of them no longer exist, is still protected as if they did. Consequently it has been only too easy to treat the cessation of the facts as the loss of the right, as some German writers very nearly do. /1/

We are led to the topic of maintaining the rights gained through possession. To gain possession, as discussed, certain physical relationships and intentions must exist. The question remains: how long must these facts remain true for a person to retain the rights that come with them? The common view is that of Savigny, who believes that the same mindset at the time of acquisition must always be maintained, along with the ability to recreate the original physical relationship with the object. Everyone agrees that it's not necessary to have direct control over the item at all times; otherwise, one could only possess what is within immediate reach. However, the question arises whether we can do without even more. The elements that define possession can naturally remain true for a lifetime. This has led to a confusion of language that complicates understanding. We use the term "possession" interchangeably to refer to both the presence of all necessary elements for acquiring it and the situation of someone who, despite the loss of some elements, is still protected as if they were intact. As a result, it has become too easy to treat the end of these elements as the loss of the right, as some German authors almost do. /1/

But it no more follows, from the single circumstance that certain facts must concur in order to create the rights incident to possession, that they must continue in order to keep those rights alive, than it does, from the necessity of a consideration and a promise to create a right ex contractu, that the consideration and promise must continue moving between the parties until the moment of performance. When certain facts have once been made manifest which confer a right, there is no general ground on which the law need hold the right at an end except the manifestation of some fact inconsistent with its continuance, [237] the reasons for conferring the particular right have great weight in determining what facts shall be to be so. Cessation of the original physical relations to the object might be treated as such a fact; but it never has been, unless in times of more ungoverned violence than the present. On the same principle, it is only a question of tradition or policy whether a cessation of the power to reproduce the original physical relations shall affect the continuance of the rights. It does not stand on the same ground as a new possession adversely taken by another. We have adopted the Roman law as to animals ferae naturae, but the general tendency of our law is to favor appropriation. It abhors the absence of proprietary or possessory rights as a kind of vacuum. Accordingly, it has been expressly decided, where a man found logs afloat and moored them, but they again broke loose and floated away, and were found by another, that the first finder retained the rights which sprung from his having taken possession, and that he could maintain trover against the second finder, who refused to give them up. /1/

But just because certain facts need to come together to create the rights associated with possession, it doesn’t mean those facts have to stay the same to keep those rights valid. Similarly, the requirement of consideration and a promise to create a right from a contract doesn’t mean that those elements have to keep changing between the parties until the performance happens. Once certain facts are established that grant a right, there is no general principle in law that ends that right unless there is some evidence showing that it shouldn't continue. The reasons for granting that particular right heavily influence what facts would qualify as such evidence. The end of the original physical relationship with the object could be seen as evidence, but it hasn’t been treated that way except in times of greater unchecked violence than we see today. Based on the same principle, whether the loss of power to recreate the original physical relationship impacts the continuation of rights is more a matter of tradition or policy. It’s not viewed the same way as a new possession taken over by another person. We have embraced Roman law regarding wild animals, but our general legal inclination is to support appropriation. The law dislikes the idea of absent property or possession, viewing it as a void. Therefore, it has been clearly established that if someone finds logs floating and secures them, but they break free and are found by someone else, the first finder keeps the rights that come from having taken possession and can sue the second finder for refusing to return them. /1/

Suppose that a finder of a purse of gold has left it in his country-house, which is lonely and slightly barred, and he is a hundred miles away, in prison. The only person within twenty miles is a thoroughly equipped burglar at his front door, who has seen the purse through a window, and who intends forthwith to enter and take it. The finder's power to reproduce his former physical relation to the gold is rather limited, yet I believe that no one would say that his possession was at an end until the burglar, by an overt [238] act, had manifested his power and intent to exclude others from the purse. The reason for this is the same which has been put with regard to the power to exclude at the moment of gaining possession. The law deals, for the most part, with overt acts and facts which can be known by the senses. So long as the burglar has not taken the purse, he has not manifested his intent; and until he breaks through the barrier which measures the present possessor's power of excluding him, he has not manifested his power. It may be observed further, that, according to the tests adopted in this Lecture, the owner of the house has a present possession in the strictest sense, because, although he has not the power which Savigny says is necessary, he has the present intent and power to exclude others.

Imagine a person who found a purse full of gold but left it at their country house, which is isolated and somewhat secured, while they are a hundred miles away in prison. The only person nearby is a well-prepared burglar right at the front door, who has spotted the purse through a window and plans to break in and take it. The finder’s ability to reclaim their physical connection to the gold is pretty limited, but I think it's fair to say that their possession isn't lost until the burglar makes a clear [238] move to show he intends to take it. The reasoning behind this is similar to the idea of having the ability to exclude someone right when possession is obtained. The law mainly focuses on clear actions and facts that can be perceived through our senses. As long as the burglar hasn’t grabbed the purse, he hasn’t shown his intent; and until he breaks through the barrier that defines the current possessor’s ability to keep him out, he hasn’t demonstrated his power. Additionally, according to the criteria discussed in this Lecture, the house owner maintains a true possession since, even though they lack the power that Savigny argues is needed, they still have the current intent and ability to exclude others.

It is conceivable that the common law should go so far as to deal with possession in the same way as a title, and should hold that, when it has once been acquired, rights are acquired which continue to prevail against all the world but one, until something has happened sufficient to divest ownership.

It’s possible that the common law could address possession just like a title, asserting that once possession is acquired, rights are established that remain effective against everyone except one person, until something occurs that is enough to strip away ownership.

The possession of rights, as it is called, has been a fighting-ground for centuries on the Continent. It is not uncommon for German writers to go so far as to maintain that there may be a true possession of obligations; this seeming to accord with a general view that possession and right are in theory coextensive terms; that the mastery of the will over an external object in general (be that object a thing or another will), when in accord with the general will, and consequently lawful, is called right, when merely de facto is possession. /1/ Bearing in mind what was [239] said on the question whether possession was a fact or right, it will be seen that such an antithesis between possession and right cannot be admitted as a legal distinction. The facts constituting possession generate rights as truly as do the facts which constitute ownership, although the rights a mere possessor are less extensive than those of an owner.

The concept of rights has been a contentious issue for centuries on the Continent. It’s not unusual for German writers to argue that there can also be a genuine possession of obligations; this aligns with the broader idea that possession and rights are theoretically the same. When someone's will exercises control over an external object (whether that object is a thing or another person’s will), and it’s in accordance with the general will, it’s considered a right. If it merely exists in fact, it’s deemed possession. /1/ Considering what was [239] said about whether possession is a fact or a right, it becomes clear that we can’t accept a strict distinction between possession and rights as a legal difference. The elements that make up possession create rights just as much as the elements that define ownership do, although the rights of a mere possessor are more limited than those of an owner.

Conversely, rights spring from certain facts supposed to be true of the person entitled to such rights. Where these facts are of such a nature that they can be made successively true of different persons, as in the case of the occupation of land, the corresponding rights may be successively enjoyed. But when the facts are past and gone, such as the giving of a consideration and the receiving of a promise, there can be no claim to the resulting rights set up by any one except the party of whom the facts were originally true—in the case supposed, the original contractee,—because no one but the original contractee can fill the situation from which they spring.

On the other hand, rights come from certain facts that are assumed to be true about the person entitled to those rights. When these facts can be true for different people over time, like in the case of land ownership, the corresponding rights can be enjoyed by different individuals. However, when the facts are in the past, like when a payment is made and a promise is received, no one can claim the resulting rights except the original party involved— in this case, the original person who entered the contract—because no one else can take the place of the original party from which those rights originated.

It will probably be granted by English readers, that one of the essential constituent facts consists in a certain relation to a material object. But this object may be a slave, as well as a horse; /1/ and conceptions originated in this way may be extended by a survival to free services. It is noticeable that even Bruns, in the application of his theory, does not seem to go beyond cases of status and those where, in common language, land is bound for the services in question, as it is for rent. Free services being [240] so far treated like servile, even by our law, that the master has a right of property in them against all the world, it is only a question of degree where the line shall be drawn. It would be possible to hold that, as one might be in possession of a slave without title, so one might have all the rights of an owner in free services rendered without contract. Perhaps there is something of that sort to be seen when a parent recovers for the seduction of a daughter over twenty-one, although there is no actual contract of service. /1/ So, throughout the whole course of the canon law and in the early law of England, rents were regarded as so far a part of the realty as to be capable of possession and disseisin, and they could be recovered like land by all assize. /2/

It’s likely that English readers would agree that one of the fundamental facts involves a certain relationship to a physical object. However, this object could be a slave just as easily as a horse; /1/ and ideas that come from this relationship can be extended to free services. It's interesting to note that even Bruns, in applying his theory, doesn’t seem to go beyond cases of status and those situations where, in everyday language, land is tied to the services in question, similar to how it is with rent. Free services have been [240] treated like servile ones, even by our law, to the extent that the master has property rights over them against everyone. It’s just a matter of degree where the line should be drawn. One could argue that, just as someone might possess a slave without a title, they could have all the rights of an owner regarding free services provided without a contract. Perhaps we can see a glimpse of this when a parent sues for the seduction of a daughter over twenty-one, even though there’s no formal service contract. /1/ Thus, throughout the entire history of canon law and in early English law, rents were viewed as part of the real estate, capable of possession and disseisin, and they could be recovered like land in any assize. /2/

But the most important case of the so-called possession of rights in our law, as in the Roman, occurs with regard to easements. An easement is capable of possession in a certain sense. A man may use land in a certain way, with the intent to exclude all others from using it in any way inconsistent with his own use, but no further. If this be true possession, however, it is a limited possession of land, not of a right, as others have shown. But where an easement has been actually created, whether by deed or prescription, although it is undoubtedly true that any possessor of the dominant estate would be protected in its enjoyment, it has not been so protected in the past on the ground that the easement was in itself an object of possession, but by the survival of precedents explained in a later [241] Lecture. Hence, to test the existence of a mere possession of this sort which the law will protect, we will take the case of a way used de facto for four years, but in which no easement has yet been acquired, and ask whether the possessor of the quasi dominant tenement would be protected in his use as against third persons. It is conceivable that he should be, but I believe that he would not. /2/

But the most important example of what's called possession of rights in our law, similar to the Roman system, relates to easements. An easement can be possessed in a certain sense. A person can use land in a specific way, intending to keep others from using it in any way that conflicts with their own use, but no more than that. If this counts as true possession, it is a limited possession of land, not a right, as others have pointed out. However, when an easement has actually been created, whether by deed or prescription, it is undoubtedly true that any possessor of the dominant estate would be protected in enjoying it. But it hasn't been protected in the past simply because the easement itself was an object of possession; it was protected due to the continued existence of precedents explained in a later [241] Lecture. Therefore, to test the existence of a mere possession of this sort that the law will protect, we will consider a situation where a way has been used de facto for four years, but no easement has yet been established, and ask whether the possessor of the quasi dominant tenement would be protected in their use against third parties. It's possible that they could be, but I think they would not. /2/

The chief objection to the doctrine seems to be, that there is almost a contradiction between the assertions that one man has a general power and intent to exclude the world from dealing with the land, and that another has the power to use it in a particular way, and to exclude the from interfering with that. The reconciliation of the two needs somewhat artificial reasoning. However, it should be borne in mind that the question in every case is not what was the actual power of the parties concerned, but what was their manifested power. If the latter stood thus balanced, the law might recognize a kind of split possession. But if it does not recognize it until a right is acquired, then the protection of a disseisor in the use of an easement must still be explained by a reference to the facts mentioned in the Lecture referred to.

The main issue with the doctrine seems to be that there's almost a contradiction between the claims that one person has a general power and intent to keep everyone else from using the land, and that another person has the power to use it in a specific way and to prevent others from interfering. Combining these two ideas requires somewhat forced reasoning. However, it's important to remember that in every case, the question isn't about what the actual power of the parties was, but what their demonstrated power was. If this demonstrated power is roughly equal, the law might recognize a kind of divided possession. But if it doesn't acknowledge this until a right is established, then the protection of someone wrongfully occupying the land in their use of an easement must still be explained by referring to the facts discussed in the previously mentioned lecture.

The consequences attached to possession are substantially those attached to ownership, subject to the question the continuance of possessory rights which I have touched upon above. Even a wrongful possessor of a [242] chattel may have full damages for its conversion by a stranger to the title, or a return of the specific thing. /1/

The consequences of possession are essentially the same as those of ownership, considering the ongoing discussion about possessory rights that I mentioned earlier. Even someone who wrongfully possesses a [242] piece of property can claim full damages for its conversion by someone who doesn't hold the title, or ask for the return of the specific item. /1/

It has been supposed, to be sure, that a "special property" was necessary in order to maintain replevin /2/ or trover. /3/ But modern cases establish that possession is sufficient, and an examination of the sources of our law proves that special property did not mean anything more. It has been shown that the procedure for the recovery of chattels lost against one's will, described by Bracton, like its predecessor on the Continent, was based upon possession. Yet Bracton, in the very passage in which he expressly makes that statement, uses a phrase which, but for the explanation, would seem to import ownership,—"Poterit rem suam petere." /4/ The writs of later days used the same language, and when it was objected, as it frequently was, to a suit by a bailee for a taking of bona et catalla sua, that it should have been for bona in custodia sua existentia, it was always answered that those in the Chancery would not frame a writ in that form. /5/

It has been assumed, of course, that a "special property" was necessary to pursue replevin /2/ or trover /3/. However, modern cases show that possession alone is enough, and a look at the origins of our law reveals that special property didn't mean anything more than that. It's been demonstrated that the process for recovering goods lost against one's will, as described by Bracton, much like its predecessor on the Continent, was based on possession. Yet, in the very section where he makes this statement, Bracton uses a phrase that, without clarification, would seem to imply ownership—"Poterit rem suam petere." /4/ The writs from later periods used similar language, and when it was often argued, as it was, that a bailee's suit for a taking of bona et catalla sua should instead have been for bona in custodia sua existentia, the common response was that those in the Chancery wouldn't draft a writ that way. /5/

The substance of the matter was, that goods in a man's possession were his (sua), within the meaning of the writ. But it was very natural to attempt a formal reconciliation between that formal word and the fact by saying that, although the plaintiff had not the general property in the [243] chattels, yet he had a property as against strangers, /1/ or a special property. This took place, and, curiously enough, two of the earliest instances in which I have found the latter phrase used are cases of a depositary, /2/ and a borrower. /3/ Brooke says that a wrongful taker "has title against all but the true owner." /4/ In this sense the special property was better described as a "possessory property," as it was, in deciding that, in an indictment for larceny, the property could be laid in the bailee who suffered the trespass. /5/

The main point was that goods someone has are theirs (sua), according to the meaning of the writ. However, it made sense to try to find a formal connection between that legal term and reality by saying that, even though the plaintiff didn't have full ownership of the [243] goods, he had a claim against others, or a specific claim. This idea emerged, and interestingly, two of the earliest cases where I’ve seen this phrase are about a depositary and a borrower. Brooke states that a wrongful taker "has title against all but the true owner." In this way, the specific claim was better referred to as "possessory property," as it was established that, in a larceny indictment, the property could be attributed to the bailee who experienced the trespass.

I have explained the inversion by which a bailee's right of action against third persons was supposed to stand on his responsibility over, although in truth it was the foundation of that responsibility, and arose simply from his possession. The step was short, from saying that bailees could sue because they were answerable over, /6/ to saying that they had the property as against strangers, or a special property, because they were answerable over, /7/ and that they could sue because they had a special property and were answerable over. /8/ And thus the notion that special property meant something more than possession, and was a requisite to maintaining an action, got into the law.

I’ve explained the reversal where a bailee’s right to take action against third parties was thought to depend on their liability, even though it actually stemmed from their possession. The transition was small, going from saying that bailees could sue because they were liable to saying they had property against outsiders, or a special property, because they were liable, and that they could take action because they had a special property and were liable. This is how the idea that special property meant something beyond mere possession, and was necessary for pursuing a legal action, became established in the law.

The error was made easier by a different use of the phrase in a different connection. A bailee was in general liable for goods stolen from his custody, whether he had a lien or not. But the law was otherwise as to a [244] pledgee, if he had kept the pledge with his own goods, and the two were stolen together. /1/ This distinction was accounted for, at least in Lord Coke's time, by saying that the pledge was, in a sense, the pledgee's own, that he had a special property in it, and thus that the ordinary relation of bailment did not exist, or that the undertaking was only to keep as his own goods. /2/ The same expression was used in discussing the pledgee's right to assign the pledge, /3/ In this sense the term applied only to pledges, but its significance in a particular connection was easily carried over into the others in which it was used, with the result that the special property which was requisite to maintain the possessory actions was supposed to mean a qualified interest in the goods.

The mistake was made easier by a different use of the phrase in another context. A bailee was generally responsible for goods stolen from his possession, whether he had a lien or not. However, the law treated a [244] pledgee differently if he had kept the pledge alongside his own goods, and both were stolen together. /1/ This distinction, at least in Lord Coke's time, was explained by saying that the pledge was, in a way, the pledgee's own, meaning he had a special property right in it, and therefore the usual bailment relationship did not apply, or that the agreement was only to keep it as his own property. /2/ The same term was used when discussing the pledgee's right to transfer the pledge, /3/ In this context, the term only referred to pledges, but its meaning in a specific situation easily translated to other contexts, leading to the assumption that the special property required to uphold possessory actions implied a qualified interest in the goods.

With regard to the legal consequences of possession, it only remains to mention that the rules which have been laid down with regard to chattels also prevail with regard to land. For although the plaintiff in ejectment must recover on the strength of his own title as against a defendant in possession, it is now settled that prior possession is enough if the defendant stands on his possession alone Possession is of course sufficient for trespass.5 And although the early remedy by assize was restricted to those who had a technical seisin, this was for reasons which do not affect the general theory.

In terms of the legal consequences of possession, it's important to note that the rules established for personal property also apply to land. Although the plaintiff in a lawsuit to reclaim property must prove their title against a defendant who is in possession, it's now clear that simply having prior possession is enough if the defendant relies solely on their possession. Of course, possession is sufficient for cases of trespass. While the earlier remedy by assize was limited to those who had a formal seisin, this restriction does not impact the overall theory.

Before closing I must say a word concerning ownership and kindred conceptions. Following the order of analysis [245] which has been pursued with regard to possession, the first question must be, What are the facts to which the rights called ownership are attached as a legal consequence? The most familiar mode of gaining ownership is by conveyance from the previous owner. But that presupposes ownership already existing, and the problem is to discover what calls it into being.

Before I wrap things up, I need to touch on ownership and related ideas. Following the analysis order [245] used for possession, the initial question should be: What are the facts that give rise to the rights known as ownership as a legal outcome? The most common way to acquire ownership is through a transfer from the current owner. However, that assumes ownership already exists, and the challenge is to figure out what brings it into existence.

One fact which has this effect is first possession. The captor of wild animals, or the taker of fish from the ocean, has not merely possession, but a title good against all the world. But the most common mode of getting an original and independent title is by certain proceedings, in court or out of it, adverse to all the world. At one extreme of these is the proceeding in rem of the admiralty, which conclusively disposes of the property in its power, and, when it sells or condemns it, does not deal with this or that man's title, but gives a new title paramount to all previous interests, whatsoever they may be. The other and more familiar case is prescription, where a public adverse holding for a certain time has a similar effect. A title by prescription is not a presumed conveyance from this or owner alone, it extinguishes all previous and inconsistent claims. The two coalesce in the ancient fine with proclamations where the combined effect of the judgment and the lapse of a year and a day was to bar claims. /1/

One fact that plays a role in this is first possession. The person who captures wild animals or takes fish from the ocean doesn’t just have possession; they hold a title that is valid against everyone. However, the most common way to establish an original and independent title is through certain actions, whether in court or outside of it, that challenge everyone’s claims. At one end of this spectrum is the admiralty's proceeding in rem, which definitively determines the property in its control, and when it sells or seizes it, it doesn’t concern itself with anyone's specific title but instead grants a new title that supersedes all previous interests, no matter what they are. The other, more familiar scenario is prescription, where a public adverse holding over a set period has a similar effect. A title by prescription doesn't just imply a transfer from one owner; it nullifies all previous conflicting claims. The two concepts come together in the ancient fine with proclamations, where the combined effect of the judgment and a year and a day’s passage served to block claims. /1/

So rights analogous to those of ownership may be given by the legislature to persons of whom some other set of facts is true. For instance, a patentee, or one to whom the government has issued a certain instrument, and who in fact has made a patentable invention.

So rights similar to ownership can be granted by the legislature to individuals who meet different criteria. For example, a patent holder, or someone who has received a specific document from the government, and who has actually created a patentable invention.

[246] But what are the rights of ownership? They are substantially the same as those incident to possession. Within the limits prescribed by policy, the owner is allowed to exercise his natural powers over the subject-matter uninterfered with, and is more or less protected in excluding other people from such interference. The owner is allowed to exclude all, and is accountable to no one. The possessor is allowed to exclude all but one, and is accountable to no one but him. The great body of questions which have made the subject of property so large and important are questions of conveyancing, not necessarily or generally dependent on ownership as distinguished from possession. They are questions of the effect of not having an independent and original title, but of coming in under a title already in existence, or of the modes in which an original title can be cut up among those who come in under it. These questions will be dealt with and explained where they belong, in the Lectures on Successions.

[246] But what are the rights of ownership? They're basically the same as those that come with possession. Within the limits set by policy, the owner is allowed to exercise their natural rights over the property without interference and is generally protected from others interfering. The owner can exclude everyone and isn't accountable to anyone. The possessor can exclude everyone except one person and is accountable only to that person. The majority of issues that make property law so extensive and important are related to conveyancing, not necessarily or usually about ownership as separate from possession. These issues concern the consequences of not having an independent and original title, but rather entering under a title that already exists, or the ways in which an original title can be divided among those who come under it. These issues will be addressed and explained where they fit, in the Lectures on Successions.

[247]

[247]





LECTURE VII. — CONTRACT.—I. HISTORY.

The doctrine of contract has been so thoroughly remodelled to meet the needs of modern times, that there is less here than elsewhere for historical research. It has been so ably discussed that there is less room here elsewhere for essentially new analysis. But a short of the growth of modern doctrines, whether necessary or not, will at least be interesting, while an analysis of their main characteristics cannot be omitted, and may present some new features.

The concept of contracts has been so completely revamped to fit today's needs that there's less historical research needed here than in other areas. It's been discussed so well that there's little space for totally new analysis. However, a brief overview of the development of modern theories, whether necessary or not, will still be interesting, while analyzing their main features is essential and may reveal some new aspects.

It is popularly supposed that the oldest forms of contract known to our law are covenant and debt, and they are of early date, no doubt. But there are other contracts still in use which, although they have in some degree put on modern forms, at least suggest the question whether they were not of equally early appearance.

It’s widely believed that the oldest types of contracts recognized by our law are covenant and debt, and they are indeed quite old. However, there are other contracts still in use that, even though they have taken on more modern forms, raise the question of whether they also originated around the same time.

One of these, the promissory oath, is no longer the foundation of any rights in private law. It is used, but as mainly as a solemnity connected with entering upon a public office. The judge swears that he will execute justice according to law, the juryman that he will find his verdict according to law and the evidence, the newly adopted citizen that he will bear true faith and allegiance to the government of his choice.

One of these, the promissory oath, no longer serves as a basis for any rights in private law. It's still used, but mainly as a formal act related to taking on a public office. The judge swears he will deliver justice according to the law, the juror pledges to reach his verdict based on the law and the evidence, and the new citizen vows to be loyal and faithful to the government of his choice.

But there is another contract which plays a more important part. It may, perhaps, sound paradoxical to mention [248] the contract of suretyship. Suretyship, nowadays, is only an accessory obligation, which presupposes a principal undertaking, and which, so far as the nature of the contract goes, is just like any other. But, as has been pointed out by Laferriere, /1/ and very likely by earlier writers, the surety of ancient law was the hostage, and the giving of hostages was by no means confined to international dealings.

But there’s another contract that plays a more significant role. It might sound contradictory to mention [248] the contract of suretyship. Today, suretyship is just an accessory obligation that relies on a main commitment and, in terms of the contract's nature, is similar to any other. However, as Laferriere has noted, /1/ and likely earlier writers as well, the surety in ancient law was essentially a hostage, and the practice of giving hostages was not limited to international relations.

In the old metrical romance of Huon of Bordeaux, Huon, having killed the son of Charlemagne, is required by the Emperor to perform various seeming impossibilities as the price of forgiveness. Huon starts upon the task, leaving twelve of his knights as hostages. /2/ He returns successful, but at first the Emperor is made to believe that his orders have been disobeyed. Thereupon Charlemagne cries out, "I summon hither the pledges for Huon. I will hang them, and they shall have no ransom." /3/ So, when Huon is to fight a duel, by way of establishing the truth or falsehood of a charge against him, each party begins by producing some of his friends as hostages.

In the old story of Huon of Bordeaux, Huon, after killing Charlemagne's son, is ordered by the Emperor to complete a number of seemingly impossible tasks as a condition for forgiveness. Huon takes on the challenge, leaving twelve of his knights as hostages. He returns victorious, but initially, the Emperor is led to believe his commands have been ignored. Charlemagne then exclaims, "I call forth the hostages for Huon. I will hang them, and there will be no ransom." So, when Huon is set to duel to prove whether the charges against him are true or false, both sides start by presenting some of their friends as hostages.

When hostages are given for a duel which is to determine the truth or falsehood of an accusation, the transaction is very near to the giving of similar security in the trial of a cause in court. This was in fact the usual course of the Germanic procedure. It will be remembered that the earliest appearance of law was as a substitute for the private feuds between families or clans. But while a defendant who did not peaceably submit to the jurisdiction of the court might be put outside the protection of the law, so that any man might kill him at sight, there was at first [249] no way of securing the indemnity to which the plaintiff was entitled unless the defendant chose to give such security. /1/

When hostages are provided for a duel intended to decide the truth or falsehood of an accusation, the situation is quite similar to offering security in a legal trial. This was actually the standard practice in Germanic legal procedures. It's important to note that the earliest form of law emerged as a replacement for private feuds between families or clans. However, if a defendant refused to peacefully accept the court's authority, they could be stripped of legal protection, meaning anyone could kill them on sight. Initially, there was [249] no way to ensure the indemnity the plaintiff deserved unless the defendant chose to provide that security. /1/

English customs which have been preserved to us are somewhat more advanced, but one of the noticeable features in their procedure is the giving of security at every step. All lawyers will remember a trace of this in the fiction of John Doe and Richard Roe, the plaintiff's pledges to prosecute his action. But a more significant example is found in the rule repeated in many of the early laws, that a defendant accused of a wrong must either find security or go to prison. /2/ This security was the hostage of earlier days, and later, when the actions for punishment and for redress were separated from each other, became the bail of the criminal law. The liability was still conceived in the same way as when the bail actually put his own body into the power of the party secured.

English customs that have been passed down to us are somewhat more advanced, but one of the notable aspects of their process is the requirement of security at every step. All lawyers will recognize a trace of this in the fiction of John Doe and Richard Roe, which represents the plaintiff's promise to pursue his case. However, a more significant example is found in the rule repeated in many of the early laws, which states that a defendant accused of wrongdoing must either provide security or go to jail. This security was the equivalent of a hostage in earlier times, and later, when the processes for punishment and redress were separated, it became known as bail in criminal law. The responsibility was still viewed in the same way as when the person providing bail actually put his own body in the control of the secured party.

One of Charlemagne's additions to the Lex Salica speaks of a freeman who has committed himself to the power of another by way of surety. /3/ The very phrase is copied in the English laws of Henry I. /4/ We have seen what this meant in the story of Huon of Bordeaux. The Mirror of Justices /5/ says that King Canute used to judge the mainprisors according as the principals when their principals not in judgment, but that King Henry I. confined Canute's rule to mainprisors who were consenting to the fact.

One of Charlemagne's additions to the Lex Salica talks about a freeman who has committed himself to the control of another as a form of surety. /3/ This exact phrase appears in the English laws of Henry I. /4/ We’ve seen the implications of this in the story of Huon of Bordeaux. The Mirror of Justices /5/ states that King Canute would judge the mainprisors based on the principals, even when the principals were not present in court, but King Henry I. limited Canute's rule to mainprisors who agreed to the matter.

As late as the reign of Edward III., Shard, an English judge, after stating the law as it still is, that bail are a prisoner's [250] keepers, and shall be charged if he escapes, observes, that some say that the bail shall be hanged in his place. /1/ This was the law in the analogous case of a jailer. /2/ The old notion is to be traced in the form still given by modern writers for the undertaking of bail for felony. They are bound "body for body," /3/ and modern law-books find it necessary to state that this does not make them liable to the punishment of the principal offender if he does not appear, but only to a fine. /4/ The contract also differed from our modern ideas in the mode of execution. It was simply a solemn admission of liability in the presence of the officer authorized to take it. The signature of the bail was not necessary, /5/ and it was not requisite that the person bailed should bind himself as a party. /6/

As late as the reign of Edward III, Shard, an English judge, after explaining the law as it still is—that bail are a prisoner's [250] keepers and will be held responsible if he escapes—notes that some argue the bail should be hanged in his place. /1/ This was the law in similar situations involving a jailer. /2/ The old belief can be seen in the way modern writers still phrase the bail's undertaking for felony. They are bound "body for body," /3/ and current law books clarify that this does not make them subject to the same punishment as the principal offender if he fails to appear, but only to a fine. /4/ The contract also differs from our modern understanding in how it was executed. It was simply a solemn acknowledgment of liability in front of the authorized officer. The bail's signature was not required, /5/ and it wasn't necessary for the person being bailed to bind himself as a party. /6/

But these peculiarities have been modified or done away with by statute, and I have dwelt upon the case, not so much as a special form of contract differing from all others as because the history of its origin shows one of the first appearances of contract in our law. It is to be traced to the gradual increase of faith in the honor of a hostage if the case calling for his surrender should arrive, and to the consequent relaxation of actual imprisonment. An illustration may be found in the parallel mode of dealing with the prisoner himself. His bail, to whom his body is supposed to be delivered, have a right to seize him at any time and anywhere, but he is allowed to go at large until [251] surrendered. It will be noticed that this form of contract, like debt as dealt with by the Roman law of the Twelve Tables, and for the same motive, although by a different process, looked to the body of the contracting party as the satisfaction.

But these peculiarities have been changed or eliminated by law, and I’ve focused on this case not so much as a unique type of contract different from others, but because its history shows one of the first instances of contracts in our legal system. It can be traced back to the growing trust in the honor of a hostage if the situation arose requiring his surrender, which led to a loosening of actual imprisonment. An example can be seen in the way prisoners are treated. Their bail, to whom they are supposed to be delivered, has the right to capture them at any time and anywhere, but they are allowed to remain free until [251] they are surrendered. It’s important to note that this form of contract, similar to debt as handled by the Roman law of the Twelve Tables and for the same reason, although through a different method, focused on the physical presence of the contracting party as the means of fulfillment.

Debt is another and more popular candidate for the honors of priority. Since the time of Savigny, the first appearance of contract both in Roman and German law has often been attributed to the case of a sale by some accident remaining incomplete. The question does not seem to be of great philosophical significance. For to explain how mankind first learned to promise, we must go to metaphysics, and find out how it ever came to frame a future tense. The nature of the particular promise which was first enforced in a given system can hardly lead to any truth of general importance. But the history of the action of debt is instructive, although in a humbler way. It is necessary to know something about it in order to understand the enlightened rules which make up the law of contract at the present time.

Debt is another more popular candidate for priority. Since Saviny's time, the first emergence of contracts in both Roman and German law has often been linked to cases where a sale was somehow left incomplete. This question doesn’t seem to carry much philosophical weight. To understand how people first began to make promises, we would have to dive into metaphysics and explore how we developed a concept of the future. The specific promise that was first enforced in any legal system likely doesn’t reveal any broadly significant truth. However, the history of debt actions is informative, even if in a simpler way. It’s important to know a bit about it to grasp the enlightened rules that currently shape contract law.

In Glanvill's treatise the action of debt is found already to be one of the well-known remedies. But the law of those days was still in a somewhat primitive state, and it will easily be imagined that a form of action which goes back as far as that was not founded on any very delicate discriminations. It was, as I shall try to show directly, simply the general form in which any money claim was collected, except unliquidated claims for damages by force, for which there was established the equally general remedy of trespass.

In Glanvill's treatise, the action of debt is already recognized as one of the established remedies. However, the law of that time was still fairly basic, and it's easy to see that a form of action dating back that far wasn't based on very nuanced distinctions. As I will demonstrate shortly, it was simply the standard way to collect any claim for money, except for unliquidated claims for damages due to force, which had the more general remedy of trespass.

It has been thought that the action was adopted from the then more civilized procedure of the Roman law. A [252] natural opinion, seeing that all the early English law-writers adopt their phraseology and classification from Rome. Still it seems much more probable that the action is of pure German descent. It has the features of the primitive procedure which is found upon the Continent, as described by Laband. /1/

It has been suggested that this action was taken from the more civilized practices of Roman law at the time. This is a reasonable perspective, considering that all the early English legal writers used the language and classification from Rome. However, it seems much more likely that the action has purely German origins. It exhibits characteristics of the primitive procedures found on the Continent, as described by Laband. /1/

The substance of the plaintiff's claim as set forth in the writ of debt is that the defendant owes him so much and wrongfully withholds it. It does not matter, for a claim framed like that, how the defendant's duty arises. It is not confined to contract. It is satisfied if there is a duty to pay on any ground. It states a mere conclusion of law, not the facts upon which that conclusion is based, and from which the liability arises. The old German complaint was, in like manner, "A owes me so much."

The essence of the plaintiff's claim as stated in the writ of debt is that the defendant owes him a certain amount and is wrongfully withholding it. For a claim like this, it doesn't matter how the defendant's obligation came about. It's not limited to contracts; it holds if there's a duty to pay for any reason. It simply presents a legal conclusion, not the details that support that conclusion and lead to the liability. The old German complaint was similarly straightforward: "A owes me this amount."

It was characteristic of the German procedure that the defendant could meet that complaint by answering, in an equally general form, that he did not owe the plaintiff. The plaintiff had to do more than simply allege a debt, if he would prevent the defendant from escaping in that way. In England, if the plaintiff had not something to show for his debt, the defendant's denial turned him out of court; and even if he had, he was liable to be defeated by the defendant's swearing with some of his friends to back him that he owed nothing. The chief reason why debt was supplanted for centuries by a later remedy, assumpsit, was the survival of this relic of early days.

In the German legal system, defendants could respond to a claim by simply stating that they didn't owe the plaintiff anything. To keep the defendant from getting away with that response, the plaintiff needed to do more than just claim a debt. In England, if the plaintiff didn’t have proof of the debt, the defendant's denial would send the plaintiff out of court. Even if the plaintiff had some evidence, he could still lose if the defendant brought in friends to testify that he owed nothing. The main reason debt claims were replaced by the later remedy of assumpsit for centuries was due to this outdated practice.

Finally, in England as in Germany, debt for the detention of money was the twin brother of the action brought for wrongfully withholding any other kind of chattel. The gist of the complaint in either case was the same.

Finally, in England as in Germany, borrowing money came with the same legal repercussions as taking someone else's property without permission. The essence of the grievance in both situations was identical.

It seems strange that this crude product of the infancy of law should have any importance for us at the present time. Yet whenever we trace a leading doctrine of substantive law far enough back, we are very likely to find some forgotten circumstance of procedure at its source. Illustrations of this truth have been given already. The action of debt and the other actions of contract will furnish others. Debt throws most light upon the doctrine of consideration.

It seems odd that this rough product from the early days of law should hold any significance for us today. However, whenever we trace a key principle of substantive law back far enough, we often discover a forgotten procedural detail at its origin. We've already seen examples of this truth. Actions like debt and other contract actions will provide more. Debt offers the clearest insight into the doctrine of consideration.

[253] Our law does not enforce every promise which a man may make. Promises made as ninety-nine promises out of a hundred are, by word of mouth or simple writing, are not binding unless there is a consideration for them. That is, as it is commonly explained, unless the promisee has either conferred a benefit on the promisor, or incurred a detriment, as the inducement to the promise.

[253] Our law doesn't enforce every promise a person makes. Most promises—like ninety-nine out of a hundred—made verbally or in simple writing aren't binding unless there's something in return for them. In other words, as it's commonly put, the person receiving the promise has to have either given something of value to the person making the promise or suffered a loss as the reason for the promise.

It has been thought that this rule was borrowed from Roman law by the Chancery, and, after undergoing some modification there, passed into the common law.

It is believed that this rule was taken from Roman law by the Chancery, and after being slightly modified there, it entered common law.

But this account of the matter is at least questionable. So far as the use of words goes, I am not aware that consideration is distinctly called cause before the reign of Elizabeth; in the earlier reports it always appears as quid pro quo. Its first appearance, so far as I know, is in Fleta's account of the action of debt, /1/ and although I am inclined to believe that Fleta's statement is not to be trusted, a careful consideration of the chronological order of the cases in the Year Books will show, I think, that the doctrine was fully developed in debt before any mention of it in equity can be found. One of the earliest [254] references to what a promisor was to have for his undertaking was in the action of assumpsit. /1/ But the doctrine certainly did not originate there. The first mention of consideration in connection with equity which I have seen is in the form of quid pro quo, /2/ and occurs after the requirement had been thoroughly established in debt. /3/

But this account of the situation is at least questionable. As far as language goes, I’m not aware that "consideration" is distinctly referred to as "cause" before the reign of Elizabeth; in earlier reports, it always appears as "quid pro quo." Its first mention, as far as I know, is in Fleta's description of the action of debt, /1/ and although I’m inclined to think that Fleta’s statement isn’t reliable, a close look at the chronological order of cases in the Year Books will likely show that the doctrine was fully developed in debt before any reference to it in equity can be found. One of the earliest [254] mentions of what a promisor was to receive for his commitment was in the action of assumpsit. /1/ But the doctrine definitely didn’t originate there. The first mention of consideration related to equity that I’ve come across is in the form of quid pro quo, /2/ and it appears after the requirement had been thoroughly established in debt. /3/

The single fact that a consideration was never required for contracts under seal, unless Fleta is to be trusted against the great weight of nearly contemporaneous evidence, goes far to show that the rule cannot have originated on grounds of policy as a rule of substantive law. And conversely, the coincidence of the doctrine with a peculiar mode of procedure points very strongly to the probability that the peculiar requirement and the peculiar procedure were connected. It will throw light on the question to put together a few undisputed facts, and to consider what consequences naturally followed. It will therefore be desirable to examine the action of debt a little further. But it is only fair to admit, at the outset, that I offer the explanation which follows with great hesitation, and, I think, with a full appreciation of the objections which might be urged.

The fact that no consideration was ever needed for contracts under seal, unless we trust Fleta against the strong evidence from that time, indicates that this rule likely didn’t arise from policy as a substantive law rule. Similarly, the alignment of this doctrine with a specific type of procedure strongly suggests that the unique requirement and the procedure were related. To better understand this issue, it helps to compile a few clear facts and consider the natural outcomes. It would therefore be useful to take a closer look at the action of debt. However, it’s important to acknowledge from the start that I present the following explanation with significant hesitation and, I believe, a deep understanding of any objections that might be raised.

It was observed a moment ago, that, in order to recover against a defendant who denied his debt, the plaintiff had to show something for it; otherwise he was turned over to the limited jurisdiction of the spiritual tribunals. /4/ This requirement did not mean evidence in the modern sense. It meant simply that he must maintain his cause in one of the ways then recognized by law. These were three, the [255] duel, a writing, and witnesses. The duel need not be discussed, as it soon ceased to be used in debt, and has no bearing on what I have to say. Trial by writing and by witnesses, on the other hand, must both be carefully studied. It will be convenient to consider the latter first and to find out what these witnesses were.

It was noted a moment ago that in order for a plaintiff to win against a defendant who disputed his debt, he had to provide some proof; otherwise, he would be sent to the limited jurisdiction of the spiritual courts. /4/ This requirement didn't mean evidence in the way we understand it today. It simply meant that he had to support his claim in one of the ways recognized by law at that time. There were three methods: the [255] duel, a written document, and witnesses. The duel doesn’t need to be discussed, as it quickly fell out of use for debt cases and isn’t relevant to what I want to explain. On the other hand, both trial by writing and by witnesses need to be examined carefully. It will be helpful to look at the latter first and figure out who these witnesses were.

One thing we know at the start; they were not witnesses as we understand the term. They were not produced before a jury for examination and cross-examination, nor did their testimony depend for its effect on being believed by the court that heard it. Nowadays, a case is not decided by the evidence, but by a verdict, or a finding of facts, followed by a judgment. The oath of a witness has no effect unless it is believed. But in the time of Henry II. our trial by jury did not exist. When an oath was allowed to be sworn it had the same effect, whether it was believed or not. There was no provision for sifting it by a second body. In those cases where a trial by witnesses was possible, if the party called on to go forward could find a certain number of men who were willing to swear in a certain form, there was an end of the matter.

One thing is clear from the start; they weren't witnesses in the way we think of the term today. They weren't brought before a jury for questioning and cross-examination, nor did their testimony rely on being accepted by the court that heard it. These days, a case isn't determined by the evidence alone, but by a verdict or a finding of facts, followed by a judgment. A witness's oath means nothing unless it's believed. But in the time of Henry II, we didn't have trial by jury. When someone was allowed to take an oath, it carried the same weight whether it was believed or not. There was no way to verify it through another group. In cases where witness trials were possible, if the party required to proceed could find enough men willing to swear in a specific way, that settled the issue.

Now this seems like a more primitive way of establishing a debt than the production of the defendant's written acknowledgement, and it is material to discover its origin.

Now, this seems like a more basic way of establishing a debt than getting a written acknowledgment from the defendant, and it's important to find out where it came from.

The cases in which this mode of trial was used appear from the early books and reports to have been almost wholly confined to claims arising out of a sale or loan. And the question at once occurs, whether we are not upon traces of an institution which was already ancient when Glanvill wrote. For centuries before the Conquest Anglo-Saxon law /1/ had required the election of a certain [256] number of official witnesses, two or three of whom were to be called in to every bargain of sale. The object for which these witnesses were established is not commonly supposed to have been the proof of debts. They go back to a time when theft and similar offences were the chief ground of litigation, and the purpose for which they were appointed was to afford a means of deciding whether a person charged with having stolen property had come by it rightfully or not. A defendant could clear himself of the felony by their oath that he had bought or received the thing openly in the way appointed by law.

The cases where this trial method was used seem, from the early books and reports, to have been mostly limited to claims from a sale or loan. And the question immediately arises: are we not looking at an institution that was already old when Glanvill wrote? For centuries before the Conquest, Anglo-Saxon law /1/ required the selection of a certain [256] number of official witnesses, two or three of whom had to be called for every sale agreement. The purpose for which these witnesses were established is not commonly thought to be for proving debts. They date back to a time when theft and similar offenses were the main reasons for litigation, and the aim of appointing them was to provide a way to determine whether a person accused of having stolen property had acquired it lawfully. A defendant could clear himself of the crime by having these witnesses swear that he had bought or received the item openly as required by law.

Having been present at the bargain, the witnesses were able to swear to what they had seen and heard, if any question arose between the parties. Accordingly, their use was not confined to disposing of a charge of felony. But that particular service identifies the transaction witnesses of the Saxon period. Now we know that the use of these witnesses did not at once disappear under Norman influence. They are found with their old function in the laws of William the Conqueror. /1/ The language of Glanvill seems to prove that they were still known under Henry II. He says that, if a purchaser cannot summon in the man from whom he bought, to warrant the property to him and defend the suit, (for if he does, the peril is shifted to the seller,) then if the purchaser has sufficient proof of his having lawfully bought the thing, de legittimo marcatu suo, it will clear him of felony. But if he have not sufficient suit, he will be in danger. /2/ This is the law of William over again. It follows that purchasers still used the transaction witnesses.

Since they were present during the deal, the witnesses could testify to what they saw and heard if any disagreements arose between the parties. Their role wasn't limited to resolving a felony charge. However, that specific function identifies the transaction witnesses of the Saxon period. We now see that these witnesses didn't completely fade away under Norman influence. They still had their original role in the laws of William the Conqueror. /1/ The language of Glanvill seems to show that they were still recognized under Henry II. He states that if a buyer cannot call on the person from whom they purchased to guarantee the property and defend against the lawsuit (because if they can, the risk shifts to the seller), then if the buyer has enough proof of having lawfully bought the item, de legittimo marcatu suo, it will absolve them of any felony. But if they don’t have enough evidence, they will be at risk. /2/ This is essentially the law of William again. This indicates that buyers still relied on transaction witnesses.

[257] But Glanvill also seems to admit the use of witness to establish debts. /1/ As the transaction witnesses were formerly available for this purpose, I see no reason to doubt that they still were, and that he is speaking of them here also. /2/ Moreover, for a long time after Henry II., whenever an action was brought for a debt of which there was no written evidence, the plaintiff, when asked what he had to show for it, always answered "good suit," and tendered his witnesses, who were sometimes examined by the court. /3/ I think it is not straining the evidence to infer that the "good suit" of the later reports was the descendant of the Saxon transaction witnesses, as it has been shown that Glanvill's secta was. /4/

[257] But Glanvill also seems to acknowledge the use of witnesses to prove debts. /1/ Since witnesses from transactions were previously available for this purpose, I see no reason to believe that they weren’t still used, and that he is referring to them here as well. /2/ Furthermore, for a long time after Henry II., whenever a case was brought for a debt without written evidence, the plaintiff, when asked what proof he had, always responded with "good suit," and presented his witnesses, who were sometimes questioned by the court. /3/ I don’t think it’s a stretch to suggest that the "good suit" in later reports was derived from the Saxon transaction witnesses, just as it has been shown that Glanvill's secta was. /4/

Assuming this step in the argument to have been taken, it will be well to recall again for a moment the original nature of the witness oath. It was confined to facts within the witnesses' knowledge by sight and hearing. But as the purposes for which witnesses were provided only required their presence when property changed hands, the principal case in which they could be of service between the parties [258] to a bargain was when a debt was claimed by reason of the delivery of property. The purpose did not extend to agreements which were executory on both sides, because there no question of theft could arise. And Glanvill shows that in his time the King's Court did not enforce such agreements. /1/ Now, if the oath of the secta could only be used to establish a debt where the transaction witnesses could have sworn, it will be seen, readily enough, how an accident of procedure may have led to a most important rule of substantive law.

Assuming this step in the argument has been taken, it’s helpful to remember the original purpose of the witness oath. It was limited to facts that the witnesses knew by sight and hearing. However, since the roles of witnesses only required their presence when property changed hands, the main situation where they could assist the parties in a deal was when a debt arose from the delivery of property. The purpose didn’t apply to agreements that were still pending on both sides, because there was no issue of theft in that case. And Glanvill illustrates that during his time, the King's Court didn’t enforce such agreements. /1/ Now, if the oath of the secta could only be used to prove a debt when the transaction witnesses could have testified, it becomes clear how a procedural accident may have led to a significant rule of substantive law.

The rule that witnesses could only swear to facts within their knowledge, coupled with the accident that these witnesses were not used in transactions which might create a debt, except for a particular fact, namely, the delivery of property, together with the further accident that this delivery was quid pro quo, was equivalent to the rule that, when a debt was proved by witnesses there must be quid pro quo. But these debts proved by witnesses, instead of by deed are what we call simple contract debts, and thus beginning with debt, and subsequently extending itself to other contracts, is established our peculiar and most important doctrine that every simple contract must have a consideration. This was never the law as to debts or contracts proved in the usual way by the defendant's seal, and the fact that it applied only to obligations which were formerly established by a procedure of limited use, [259] goes far to show that the connection with procedure was not accidental.

The rule that witnesses could only testify about facts they personally knew, along with the fact that these witnesses weren't involved in transactions that could create a debt, except for a specific situation—the delivery of property—combined with the further fact that this delivery was quid pro quo, was effectively the same as the rule stating that when a debt is proven by witnesses, there must be a quid pro quo. However, the debts proven by witnesses, rather than by a legal document, are what we call simple contract debts. Thus, starting with debts and later applying to other contracts, our unique and crucial principle that every simple contract must have a consideration is established. This was never the law for debts or contracts proven in the typical way by the defendant's seal, and the fact that it only applied to obligations previously established by a limited-use process, [259] indicates that the link to that procedure was not coincidental.

The mode of proof soon changed, but as late as the reign of Queen Elizabeth we find a trace of this original connection. It is said, "But the common law requires that there should be a new cause (i. e. consideration), whereof the country may have intelligence or knowledge for the trial of it, if need be, so that it is necessary for the Public-weal." /1/ Lord Mansfield showed his intuition of the historical grounds of our law when he said, "I take it that the ancient notion about the want of consideration was for the sake of evidence only; for when it is reduced into writing, as in covenants, specialties, bonds, etc., there was no objection to the want of consideration." /2/

The way proof was handled soon changed, but even during Queen Elizabeth's reign, we can still see signs of this original connection. It is said, "However, the common law requires that there should be a new cause (i.e., consideration), which the country should be aware of or informed about for the trial, if necessary, so that it serves the Public-good." /1/ Lord Mansfield demonstrated his understanding of the historical roots of our law when he remarked, "I believe that the old idea regarding the lack of consideration was mainly about evidence; because when it's put in writing, as in contracts, specialties, bonds, etc., there was no issue with the lack of consideration." /2/

If it should be objected that the preceding argument is necessarily confined to debt, whereas the requirement of consideration applies equally to all simple contracts, the answer is, that in all probability the rule originated with debt, and spread from debt to other contracts.

If someone argues that the previous point only applies to debt and that consideration is needed for all simple contracts, the response is that the rule likely started with debt and then extended to other contracts.

But, again, it may be asked whether there were no other contracts proved by witness except those which have been mentioned. Were there no contracts proved in that way to which the accidental consideration was wanting? To this also there is an easy answer. The contracts enforced by the civil courts, even as late as Henry II., were few and simple. The witness procedure was no doubt broad enough for all the contracts which were made in early times. Besides those of sale, loan, and the like, which have been mentioned, I find but two contractual [260] obligations. These were the warranties accompanying a sale and suretyship which was referred to at the beginning of the Lecture. Of the former, warranty of title was rather regarded as an obligation raised by the law out of the relation of buyer and seller than as a contract. Other express warranties were matters within the knowledge of the transaction witnesses, and were sworn to by them in Saxon times. /1/

But again, one might wonder if there were any other contracts proven by witnesses aside from those mentioned. Were there no contracts shown that lacked the accidental consideration? The answer to this is straightforward. The contracts enforced by civil courts, even as late as Henry II’s time, were few and simple. The witness procedure was indeed broad enough to cover all contracts made in early times. Apart from those of sale, loan, and similar types already mentioned, I find only two contractual obligations. These were the warranties linked to a sale and suretyship, which were referenced at the beginning of the lecture. For the former, warranty of title was more seen as an obligation established by law from the relationship of buyer and seller rather than as a contract. Other express warranties were matters known to the witnesses of the transaction and were sworn to by them in Saxon times. /1/

But in the Norman period warranty is very little heard of, except with regard to land, and then it was decided by the duel. It so wholly disappeared, except where it was embodied in a deed, that it can have had no influence upon the law of consideration. I shall therefore assume, without more detail, that it does not bear upon the case.

But during the Norman period, warranty was rarely mentioned, except in relation to land, and even then, it was settled by combat. It almost completely vanished, except when included in a deed, so it couldn't have impacted the law of consideration. I'll therefore assume, without going into further detail, that it doesn't apply to the case.

Then as to the pledge or surety. He no longer paid with his body, unless in very exceptional cases, but his liability was translated into money, and enforced in an action of debt. This time-honored contract, like the other debts of Glanvill's time, could be established by witness without a writing, /2/ and in this case there was not such a consideration, such a benefit to the promisor, as the law required when the doctrine was first enunciated. But this also is unimportant, because his liability on the oath of witness came to an end, as well as that of the warrantor, before the foundations were laid for the rule which I am seeking to explain. A writing soon came to be required, as will be seen in a moment.

Then regarding the pledge or guarantee. He no longer paid with his physical presence, except in very rare cases, but his liability was converted into money and enforced through a debt action. This long-standing contract, like other debts from Glanvill's time, could be proven by testimony without a written document, /2/ and in this case, there wasn't such a consideration, such a benefit to the promisor, as the law initially required when this principle was first articulated. However, this detail is less significant, because his liability based on witness testimony ended, along with that of the guarantor, before the foundations were established for the rule I intend to explain. A written document soon became necessary, as will be revealed shortly.

The result so far is, that the only action of contract in Glanvill's time was debt, that the only debts recovered [261] without writing were those which have been described, and that the only one of these for which there was not quid pro quo ceased to be recoverable in that way by the reign of Edward III.

The result so far is that the only contract action in Glanvill's time was debt, that the only debts that could be recovered [261] without writing were those previously described, and that the only one of these for which there wasn’t a quid pro quo stopped being recoverable that way by the reign of Edward III.

But great changes were beginning in the reign of Henry II. More various and complex contracts soon came to be enforced. It may be asked, Why was not the scope of the witness oath enlarged, or, if any better proof were forthcoming, why was not the secta done away with, and other oral testimony admitted? In any event, what can the law of Henry II.'s time have to do with consideration, which not heard of until centuries later?

But significant changes were starting during the reign of Henry II. More diverse and complicated contracts began to be enforced. One might wonder, why wasn't the scope of the witness oath expanded, or if better evidence was available, why wasn’t the secta eliminated and other oral testimony allowed? In any case, what connection can the law from Henry II's time have with consideration, which wasn't recognized until centuries later?

It is manifest that a witness oath, which disposes of a case by the simple fact that it is sworn, is not a satisfactory mode of proof. A written admission of debt produced in court, and sufficiently identified as issuing from the defendant, is obviously much better. The only weak point about a writing is the means of identifying it as the defendant's, and this difficulty disappeared as soon as the use of seals became common. This had more or less taken place in Glanvill's time, and then all that a party had to do was to produce the writing and satisfy the court by inspection that the impression on the wax fitted his opponent's seal. /1/ The oath of the secta could always be successfully met by wager of law, /2/ that is, by a counter oath the part of the defendant, with the same or double the number of fellow-swearers produced by the plaintiff. But a writing proved to be the defendant's could not be contradicted. [262] /1/ For if a man said he was bound, he was bound. There was no question of consideration, because there was as yet no such doctrine. He was equally bound if he acknowledged all obligation in any place having a record, such as the superior courts, by which his acknowledgment could be proved. Indeed, to this day some securities are taken simply by an oral admission before the clerk of a court noted by him in his papers. The advantage of the writing was not only that it furnished better proof in the old cases, but also that it made it possible to enforce obligations for which there would otherwise have been no proof at all.

It's clear that a witness's oath, which settles a case just by being sworn, isn’t a reliable way to prove something. A written acknowledgment of debt brought to court and clearly identified as coming from the defendant is obviously much stronger. The only issue with a written document is proving it belongs to the defendant, but this problem faded as the use of seals became common. This was already happening in Glanvill's time; then any party just had to present the document and convince the court through inspection that the wax impression matched the opponent's seal. /1/ The oath from the secta could always be countered by wager of law, /2/ meaning the defendant could take a counter-oath with the same or more fellow swearers than the plaintiff had. But a written document identified as belonging to the defendant couldn’t be disputed. [262] /1/ Because if a person claimed they were bound, they were. There was no question of consideration back then, as that concept didn’t exist yet. They were still bound if they acknowledged any obligation in a place with a record, like the higher courts, where their acknowledgment could be verified. In fact, to this day, some securities are accepted simply based on an oral admission before a court clerk, which is noted in his documents. The benefit of having a written document was not just that it provided better proof in past cases, but also that it allowed for the enforcement of obligations that otherwise wouldn’t have any proof at all.

What has been said sufficiently explains the preference of proof by writing to proof by the old-fashioned witness oath. But there were other equally good reasons why the latter should not be extended beyond its ancient limits. The transaction witnesses were losing their statutory and official character. Already in Glanvill's time the usual modes of proving a debt were by the duel or by writing. /2/ A hundred years later Bracton shows that the secta had degenerated to the retainers and household of the party, and he says that their oath raises but a slight presumption. /3/

What has been said clearly explains why written proof is preferred over the traditional witness oath. However, there were also other valid reasons why the latter shouldn't be expanded beyond its historical boundaries. The witnesses to transactions were losing their legal and official status. Even back in Glanvill's time, the typical ways to prove a debt were through combat or written evidence. /2/ A hundred years later, Bracton noted that the secta had declined to become just the retainers and household members of the party, and he stated that their oath only creates a weak presumption. /3/

Moreover, a new mode of trial was growing up, which, although it was not made use of in these cases /4/ for a good while, must have tended to diminish the estimate set on the witness oath by contrast. This was the beginning of our trial by jury. It was at first an inquest of the neighbors [263] most likely to know about a disputed matter of fact. They spoke from their own knowledge, but they were selected by an officer of the court instead of by the interested party, and were intended to be impartial. /1/ Soon witnesses were summoned before them, not, as of old, to the case by their oath, but to aid the inquest to find a verdict by their testimony. With the advent of this enlightened procedure, the secta soon ceased to decide the case, and it may well be asked why it did not disappear and leave no traces.

Moreover, a new way of conducting trials was emerging, which, although it wasn’t used in these cases for a while, likely contributed to decreasing the value placed on the witness oath in comparison. This was the beginning of our trial by jury. At first, it was an inquiry conducted by the neighbors [263] most likely to have knowledge about a disputed fact. They spoke from their own understanding, but they were chosen by a court official instead of by the interested party, and they were meant to be impartial. Soon, witnesses were called to appear before them, not as before, bound to the case by their oath, but to assist the inquiry in reaching a verdict through their testimony. With the introduction of this improved procedure, the secta soon stopped deciding cases, and one might reasonably wonder why it didn’t just disappear entirely, leaving no traces.

Taking into account the conservatism of the English law, and the fact that, before deeds came in, the only debts for which there had been a remedy were debts proved by the transaction witnesses, it would not have been a surprise to find the tender of suit persisting in those cases. But there was another reason still more imperative. The defence in debt where there was no deed was by wager of law. /2/ A section of Magna Charta was interpreted to prohibit a man's being put to his law on the plaintiff's own statement without good witness. /3/ Hence, the statute required witness—that is, the secta—in every case of debt where the plaintiff did not rely upon a writing. Thus it happened that suit continued to be tendered in those cases where it had been of old, /4/ and as the defendant, if he did not admit the debt in such cases, always waged his law, it was long before the inquest got much foothold.

Considering the conservative nature of English law, and the fact that, before deeds existed, the only debts that had a remedy were those backed by transaction witnesses, it wouldn't be surprising to see the tender of suit continuing in those cases. However, there was an even more pressing reason. The defense in debt cases without a deed was by wager of law. A section of Magna Carta was interpreted to forbid a person from being put to their law based solely on the plaintiff’s statement without credible witnesses. Therefore, the statute mandated witnesses—that is, the secta—in every debt case where the plaintiff didn’t rely on written evidence. As a result, suit continued to be tendered in those cases as it had been in the past, and since the defendant, if he didn’t admit the debt in such situations, always waged his law, it took a long time before the inquest gained much traction.

To establish a debt which arose merely by way of promise or acknowledgment, and for which there had formerly [264] been no mode of trial provided, you must have a writing, the new form of proof which introduced it into the law. The rule was laid down, "by parol the party is not obliged." /1/ But the old debts were not conceived of as raised by a promise. /2/ They were a "duty" springing from the plaintiff's receipt of property, a fact which could be seen and sworn to. In these cases the old law maintained and even extended itself a little by strict analogy.

To establish a debt that came about simply through a promise or acknowledgment, and for which there was previously no way to try in court, you need to have it in writing, as this new form of evidence made it part of the law. The rule was set: "by oral agreement, the party is not obliged." /1/ However, old debts were not viewed as created by a promise. /2/ They were a "duty" arising from the plaintiff receiving property, which was a fact that could be seen and sworn to. In these situations, the old law upheld and even slightly expanded itself by strict analogy.

But the undertaking of a surety, in whatever form it was clothed, did not really arise out of any such fact. It had become of the same nature as other promises, and it was soon doubted whether it should not be proved by the same evidence. /3/ By the reign of Edward III., it was settled that a deed was necessary, /4/ except where the customs of particular cities had kept the old law in force. /5/

But the commitment of a guarantor, regardless of how it was presented, didn't actually stem from any such fact. It had taken on the same character as other promises, and it soon became uncertain whether it should be validated by the same evidence. By the reign of Edward III., it was established that a deed was required, except where the customs of specific cities had maintained the old law in effect.

This reign may be taken as representing the time when the divisions and rules of procedure were established which have lasted until the present day. It is therefore worth while to repeat and sum up the condition of the law at that time.

This reign can be seen as the period when the divisions and rules of procedure were created that still exist today. It's therefore important to restate and summarize the state of the law at that time.

It was still necessary that the secta should be tendered in every action of debt for which no writing was produced. For this, as well as for the other reasons which have been mentioned, the sphere of such actions was not materially enlarged beyond those cases which had formerly been established by the witness-oath. As suretyship was no [265] longer one of these, they became strictly limited to cases in which the debt arose from the receipt of a quid pro quo. Moreover there was no other action of contract which could be maintained without a writing. New species of contracts were now enforced by an action of covenant, but there a deed was always necessary. At the same time the secta had shrunk to a form, although it was still argued that its function was more important in contract than elsewhere. It could no longer be examined before the court. /1/ It was a mere survival, and the transaction witness had ceased to be an institution. Hence, the necessity of tendering the witness oath did not fix the limit of debt upon simple contract except by tradition, and it is not surprising to find that the action was slightly extended by analogy from its scope in Glanvill's time.

It was still necessary for the secta to be presented in every debt action where no written document was provided. Because of this, as well as for other reasons previously mentioned, the range of such actions didn’t significantly expand beyond those cases established by the witness oath. Since suretyship was no longer one of these, these cases were strictly limited to situations where the debt stemmed from receiving something in return. Additionally, there was no other type of contract action that could be pursued without a written agreement. New types of contracts were now enforced through an action of covenant, but a deed was always required there. At the same time, the secta had diminished to a formal token, although it was still argued that its role was more significant in contracts than in other areas. It could no longer be examined in court. /1/ It had become just a remnant, and the transaction witness was no longer a formal institution. Therefore, the requirement to provide the witness oath did not set a limit on debts from simple contracts except by tradition, and it’s not surprising that the action was slightly broadened by analogy from its scope in Glanvill's time.

But debt remained substantially at the point which I have indicated, and no new action available for simple contracts was introduced for a century. In the mean time the inversion which I have explained took place, and what was an accident of procedure had become a doctrine of substantive law. The change was easy when the debts which could be enforced without deed all sprung from a benefit to the debtor.

But debt stayed pretty much where I mentioned, and no new actions for simple contracts were introduced for a hundred years. Meanwhile, the shift I talked about happened, and what was originally just a procedural issue turned into a rule of substantive law. The change was straightforward since the debts that could be enforced without a deed all came from a benefit to the debtor.

The influence of the Roman law, no doubt, aided in bringing about this result. It will be remembered that in the reign of Henry II. most simple contracts and debts for which there was not the evidence of deed or witness were left to be enforced by the ecclesiastical courts, so far as their jurisdiction extended. /2/ Perhaps it was this circumstance [266] which led Glanvill and his successors to apply the terminology of the civilians to common-law debts. But whether he borrowed it from the ecclesiastical courts, or went directly to the fountain-head, certain it is that Glanvill makes use of the classification and technical language of the Corpus Juris throughout his tenth book.

The influence of Roman law undoubtedly helped bring about this outcome. It's important to remember that during Henry II's reign, most simple contracts and debts without proof in the form of a deed or witness were enforced by the ecclesiastical courts, as far as their authority allowed. /2/ This situation [266] might have led Glanvill and his successors to use the terminology of civil law for common-law debts. Whether he took it from the ecclesiastical courts or went straight to the source, it's clear that Glanvill uses the classification and technical language from the Corpus Juris in his tenth book.

There were certain special contracts in the Roman system called real, which bound the contractor either to return a certain thing put into his hands by the contractee, as in a case of lease or loan, or to deliver other articles of the same kind, as when grain, oil, or money was lent. This class did not correspond, except in the most superficial way, with the common-law debts. But Glanvill adopted the nomenclature, and later writers began to draw conclusions from it. The author of Fleta, a writer by no means always intelligent in following and adopting his predecessors' use of the Roman law, /1/ says that to raise a debt there must be not only a certain thing promised, but a certain thing promised in return. /2/

There were certain special contracts in the Roman system called real contracts, which required the contractor to either return a specific item given to him by the contractee, like in a lease or loan, or to deliver other items of the same kind, such as when grain, oil, or money was lent. This category didn't really match up, except in the most superficial way, with common-law debts. However, Glanvill adopted the terminology, and later writers began to draw conclusions from it. The author of Fleta, who wasn't always clear in following and adopting his predecessors' use of Roman law, says that to create a debt, there must be not only a specific item promised but also a specific item promised in return.

If Fleta had confined his statement to debts by simple contract, it might well have been suggested by the existing state of the law. But as he also required a writing and a seal, in addition to the matter given or promised in return, the doctrine laid down by him can hardly have prevailed at any time. It was probably nothing more than a slight vagary of reasoning based upon the Roman elements which he borrowed from Bracton.

If Fleta had limited his statement to debts from simple contracts, it could have made sense based on the current state of the law. However, since he also demanded a written document and a seal, in addition to the item given or promised in exchange, his doctrine likely never gained real traction. It was probably just a minor quirk of reasoning influenced by the Roman concepts he took from Bracton.

[267] It only remains to trace the gradual appearance of consideration in the decisions. A case of the reign of Edward III. /1/ seems to distinguish between a parol obligation founded on voluntary payments by the obligee and one founded on a payment at the obligor's request. It also speaks of the debt or "duty" in that case as arising by cause of payments. Somewhat similar language is used in the next reign. /2/ So, in the twelfth year of Henry IV., /3/ there is an approach to the thought: "If money is promised to a man for making a release, and he makes the release, he will have a good action of debt in the matter." In the next reign /4/ it was decided that, in such a case, the plaintiff could not recover without having executed the release, which is explained by the editor on the ground that ex nudo pacto non oritur actio. But the most important fact is, that from Edward I. to Henry VI. we find no case where a debt was recovered, unless a consideration had in fact been received.

[267] It remains to outline the gradual emergence of consideration in the decisions. A case from the reign of Edward III. /1/ seems to differentiate between a verbal obligation based on voluntary payments by the obligee and one based on a payment requested by the obligor. It also describes the debt or "duty" in that instance as arising from these payments. Similar language appears in the following reign. /2/ Thus, in the twelfth year of Henry IV., /3/ there's a hint of the idea: "If money is promised to someone for making a release, and he makes that release, he will have a valid claim for the debt." In the next reign /4/, it was determined that in such a case, the plaintiff could not recover unless the release had been executed, which the editor explains based on the principle that a claim does not arise from a bare agreement. However, the key point is that from Edward I. to Henry VI., there is no case where a debt was recovered unless some consideration had actually been received.

Another fact to be noticed is, that since Edward III. debts arising from a transaction without writing are said to arise from contract, as distinguished from debts arising from an obligation. /5/ Hence, when consideration was required as such, it was required in contracts not under seal, whether debts or not. Under Henry VI. quid pro quo became a necessity in all such contracts. In the third year of that reign /6/ it was objected to au action upon an [268] assumpsit for not building a mill, that it was not shown what the defendant was to have for doing it. In the thirty-sixth year of the same reign (A.D. 1459), the doctrine appears full grown, and is assumed to be familiar. /1/

Another important point to note is that since Edward III, debts from transactions not documented in writing are considered to come from a contract, as opposed to debts from an obligation. /5/ Therefore, when consideration was needed, it applied to contracts not under seal, whether they involved debts or not. During Henry VI's reign, quid pro quo became essential in all such contracts. In the third year of his reign /6/, there was an objection to an action on an [268] assumpsit for failing to build a mill, stating that it wasn’t clear what the defendant would receive for completing the task. By the thirty-sixth year of that reign (A.D. 1459), this doctrine was well established and was assumed to be commonly understood. /1/

The case turned upon a question which was debated for centuries before it was settled, whether debt would lie for a sum of money promised by the defendant to the plaintiff if he would marry the defendant's daughter. But whereas formerly the debate had been whether the promise was not so far incident to the marriage that it belonged exclusively to the jurisdiction of the spiritual courts, it now touched the purely mundane doubt whether the defendant had had quid pro quo.

The case revolved around a question that had been argued for centuries before it was resolved: whether a debt could be claimed for a sum of money the defendant promised to the plaintiff in exchange for marrying the defendant's daughter. Previously, the debate was about whether the promise was so closely related to the marriage that it fell solely under the authority of spiritual courts. Now, however, it raised the straightforward concern of whether the defendant had received something of value in return.

It will be remembered that the fact formerly sworn to by the transaction witnesses was a benefit to the defendant, namely, a delivery of the things sold or the money lent to him. Such cases, also, offer the most obvious form of consideration. The natural question is, what the promisor was to have for his promise. /2/ It is only by analysis that the supposed policy of the law is seen to be equally satisfied by a detriment incurred by the promisee. It therefore not unnaturally happened that the judges, when they first laid down the law that there must be quid pro quo, were slow to recognize a detriment to the contractee as satisfying the requirement which had been laid down. In the case which I have mentioned some of the judges were inclined to hold that getting rid of his daughter was a sufficient benefit to the defendant to make him a debtor for the money which he promised; and there was even some hint of the opinion, that marrying the lady was a [269] consideration, because it was a detriment to the promisee. /1/ But the other opinion prevailed, at least for a time, because the defendant had had nothing from the plaintiff to raise a debt. /2/

It should be noted that what was previously sworn by the witnesses was advantageous to the defendant, specifically, the delivery of the items sold or the money lent to him. These situations also clearly show the most straightforward form of consideration. The natural question to ask is, what did the promisor get in return for his promise. /2/ It's only through analysis that the supposed intention of the law appears to be equally fulfilled by a detriment faced by the promisee. So, it’s not surprising that the judges, when they first established that there had to be quid pro quo, were slow to accept that a detriment to the contractee could fulfill that requirement. In the case I mentioned, some judges leaned towards the view that helping dispose of his daughter was enough of a benefit to the defendant to make him a debtor for the money he promised; there was even a suggestion that marrying the lady was a [269] consideration, as it was a detriment to the promisee. /1/ However, the other viewpoint won out, at least for a while, because the defendant hadn’t received anything from the plaintiff to establish a debt. /2/

So it was held that a service rendered to a third person upon the defendant's request and promise of a reward would not be enough, /3/ although not without strong opinions to the contrary, and for a time the precedents were settled. It became established law that an action of debt would only lie upon a consideration actually received by and enuring to the benefit of the debtor.

So it was determined that providing a service to a third party at the defendant's request and promise of a reward wouldn't be sufficient, /3/ even though there were significant opposing views, and for a while, the precedents were firm. It became established law that a debt action would only be valid if there was a consideration that was actually received by and benefited the debtor.

It was, however, no peculiarity of either the action or contract of debt which led to this view, but the imperfectly developed theory of consideration prevailing between the reigns of Henry VI. and Elizabeth. The theory the same in assumpsit, /4/ and in equity. /5/ Wherever consideration was mentioned, it was always as quid pro quo, as what the contractor was to have for his contract.

It wasn’t the specifics of the action or the debt contract that caused this viewpoint, but rather the underdeveloped theory of consideration that existed between the reigns of Henry VI and Elizabeth. The theory was the same in assumpsit, /4/ and in equity. /5/ Whenever consideration was discussed, it was always framed as quid pro quo, meaning what the contractor would receive in return for their contract.

Moreover, before consideration was ever heard of, debt was the time-honored remedy on every obligation to pay money enforced by law, except the liability to damages for a wrong. /6/ It has been shown already that a surety could be sued in debt until the time of Edward III. without a writing, yet a surety receives no benefit from the dealing with his principal. For instance, if a man sells corn to A, [270] and B says, "I will pay if A does not," the sale does B no good so far as appears by the terms of the bargain. For this reason, debt cannot now be maintained against a surety in such a case.

Moreover, before any consideration was ever acknowledged, debt was the traditional solution for every legal obligation to pay money, except for liability to damages caused by a wrongdoing. /6/ It has already been established that a guarantor could be sued for debt until the time of Edward III without any written agreement, yet a guarantor gains no advantage from the transaction with their principal. For example, if someone sells corn to A, [270] and B says, "I will pay if A doesn’t," the sale offers no benefit to B based on the terms of the agreement. For this reason, debt cannot be pursued against a guarantor in such a situation.

It was not always so. It is not so to this day if there is an obligation under seal. In that case, it does not matter how the obligation arose, or whether there was any consideration for it or not. But a writing was a more general way of establishing a debt in Glanvill's time than witness, and it is absurd to determine the scope of the action by considering only a single class of debts enforced by it. Moreover, a writing for a long time was only another, although more conclusive, mode of proof. The foundation of the action was the same, however it was proved. This was a duty or "duity" /1/ to the plaintiff, in other words, that money was due him, no matter how, as any one may see by reading the earlier Year Books. Hence it was, that debt lay equally upon a judgment, /2/ which established such a duty by matter of record, or upon the defendant's admission recorded in like manner. /3/

It hasn’t always been this way. It’s still true today if there’s an obligation that’s formalized. In that situation, it doesn’t matter how the obligation came about or if there was any consideration for it. Back in Glanvill's time, writing was a more common way to establish a debt than having witnesses, and it doesn’t make sense to define the action’s scope by looking at just one type of debt enforced by it. Also, for a long time, a writing was just another, though more decisive, way of proving a claim. The basis of the action was the same, regardless of how it was proven. This was a duty or “duity” /1/ owed to the plaintiff, meaning that money was due to him, no matter the circumstances, as anyone can see by reading the earlier Year Books. Thus, a debt could arise from a judgment /2/ that established such a duty in a formal record, or from the defendant’s admission recorded similarly. /3/

To sum up, the action of debt has passed through three stages. At first, it was the only remedy to recover money due, except when the liability was simply to pay damages for a wrongful act. It was closely akin to—indeed it was but a branch of—the action for any form of personal property which the defendant was bound by contract or otherwise to hand over to the plaintiff. /4/ If there was a contract to pay money, the only question was how you [271] could prove it. Any such contract, which could be proved by any of the means known to early law, constituted a debt. There was no theory of consideration, and therefore, of course, no limit to either the action or the contract based upon the nature of the consideration received.

To sum up, the action of debt has gone through three stages. Initially, it was the only way to recover money owed, except when the obligation was simply to pay damages for a wrongful act. It was closely related to—actually, it was just a branch of—the action for any type of personal property that the defendant was legally required to hand over to the plaintiff. If there was a contract to pay money, the only question was how you could prove it. Any such contract that could be proven by any of the methods recognized by early law constituted a debt. There was no concept of consideration, and therefore, no limits on either the action or the contract based on the type of consideration received.

The second stage was when the doctrine of consideration was introduced in its earlier form of a benefit to the promisor. This applied to all contracts not under seal while it prevailed, but it was established while debt was the only action for money payable by such contracts. The precedents are, for the most part, precedents in debt.

The second stage was when the idea of consideration was introduced in its earlier form as a benefit to the promisor. This applied to all contracts not under seal while it was in effect, but it was established when debt was the only action for money owed by such contracts. The precedents are mostly cases involving debt.

The third stage was reached when a larger view was taken of consideration, and it was expressed in terms of detriment to the promisee. This change was a change in substantive law, and logically it should have been applied throughout. But it arose in another and later form of action, under circumstances peculiarly connected with that action, as will be explained hereafter. The result was that the new doctrine prevailed in the new action, and the old in the old, and that what was really the anomaly of inconsistent theories carried out side by side disguised itself in the form of a limitation upon the action of debt. That action did not remain, as formerly, the remedy for all binding contracts to pay money, but, so far as parol contracts were concerned, could only be used where the consideration was a benefit actually received by the promisor. With regard to obligations arising in any other way, it has remained unchanged.

The third stage was reached when a broader perspective was taken into account, focused on the harm to the promisee. This shift was a change in substantive law, and logically, it should have been applied consistently. However, it emerged in a different and later form of action, under circumstances closely linked to that action, as will be explained later. The result was that the new doctrine took hold in the new action, while the old doctrine continued in the old one, leading to an inconsistency where different theories coexisted, which appeared as a limitation on the action of debt. That action no longer served, as it did before, as the remedy for all binding contracts to pay money; instead, concerning parol contracts, it could only be used when the consideration involved a benefit actually received by the promisor. For obligations arising in any other way, it has remained unchanged.

I must now devote a few words to the effect upon our law of the other mode of proof which I have mentioned. I mean charters. A charter was simply a writing. As few could write, most people had to authenticate a document [272] in some other way, for instance, by making their mark. This was, in fact, the universal practice in England until the introduction of Norman customs. /1/ With them seals came in. But as late as Henry II. they were said by the Chief Justice of England to belong properly only to kings and to very great men. /2/ I know no ground for thinking that an authentic charter had any less effect at that time when not under seal than when it was sealed. /3/ It was only evidence either way, and is called so in many of the early cases. /4/ It could be waived, and suit tendered in its place. /5/ Its conclusive effect was due to the satisfactory nature of the evidence, not to the seal. /6/

I need to say a few words about how the other method of proof I mentioned affects our law. I'm talking about charters. A charter was just a written document. Since few people could write, most had to confirm a document [272] in another way, like by making their mark. This was the standard practice in England until Norman customs were introduced. /1/ With them came the use of seals. However, as late as Henry II's time, the Chief Justice of England said that seals were meant only for kings and very important people. /2/ I have no reason to believe that an authentic charter had any less effect at that time when it wasn't sealed than when it was. /3/ It was just evidence either way, and many early cases refer to it as such. /4/ It could be waived, and a lawsuit could be initiated in its place. /5/ Its definitive effect came from the reliability of the evidence, not from the seal. /6/

But when seals came into use they obviously made the evidence of the charter better, in so far as the seal was more difficult to forge than a stroke of the pen. Seals acquired such importance, that, for a time, a man was bound by his seal, although it was affixed without his consent. /7/ At last a seal came to be required, in order that a charter should have its ancient effect. /8/

But when seals became used, they clearly improved the reliability of the charter because a seal was harder to fake than just a signature. Seals became so important that, for a while, a person was held to their seal even if it was placed there without their permission. Eventually, a seal was needed for a charter to retain its traditional validity.

A covenant or contract under seal was no longer a promise well proved; it was a promise of a distinct nature, for which a distinct form of action came to be provided. [273] /1/ I have shown how the requirement of consideration became a rule of substantive law, and also why it never had any foothold in the domain of covenants. The exception of covenants from the requirement became a rule of substantive law also. The man who had set his hand to a charter, from being bound because he had consented to be, and because there was a writing to prove it, /2/ was now held by force of the seal and by deed alone as distinguished from all other writings. And to maintain the integrity of an inadequate theory, a seal was said to a consideration.

A sealed agreement or contract wasn't just a reliable promise anymore; it became a promise of a different kind, which led to a specific legal action being established. [273] /1/ I've explained how the need for consideration became a fundamental rule of law and why it never really applied to covenants. The exception of covenants from the requirement also became a fundamental legal rule. A person who signed a charter was bound not just by their consent and the written evidence, /2/ but now also by the seal and the deed itself, setting it apart from all other forms of writing. To uphold a flawed theory, it was claimed that a seal served as consideration.

Nowadays, it is sometimes thought more philosophical to say that a covenant is a formal contract, which survives alongside of the ordinary consensual contract, just as happened in the Roman law. But this is not a very instructive way of putting it either. In one sense, everything is form which the law requires in order to make a promise binding over and above the mere expression of the promisor's will. Consideration is a form as much as a seal. The only difference is, that one form is of modern introduction, and has a foundation in good sense, or at least in with our common habits of thought, so that we do not notice it, whereas the other is a survival from an older condition of the law, and is less manifestly sensible, or less familiar. I may add, that, under the influence of the latter consideration, the law of covenants is breaking down. In many States it is held that a mere scroll or flourish of the pen is a sufficient seal. From this it is a short step to abolish the distinction between sealed and unsealed instruments altogether, and this has been done in some of the Western States.

Today, some people think it's more philosophical to describe a covenant as a formal contract that exists alongside regular consensual contracts, similar to what happened in Roman law. However, this isn't a particularly helpful way to explain it either. In a way, everything the law requires to make a promise binding goes beyond just the simple expression of the promisor's intention. Consideration is just as much a form as a seal. The difference is that one form is more modern and is based on common sense or our usual way of thinking, so we don't really notice it, while the other is an old remnant of the law and seems less sensible or familiar. I should also mention that because of this older consideration, the law around covenants is starting to break down. In many states, simply putting a scrawl or flourish of a pen is considered a sufficient seal. This makes it easy to eliminate the distinction between sealed and unsealed documents entirely, and that's already happened in some Western states.

[274] While covenants survive in a somewhat weak old age, and debt has disappeared, leaving a vaguely disturbing influence behind it, the whole modern law of contract has grown up through the medium of the action of Assumpsit, which must now be explained.

[274] While agreements linger in a somewhat diminished state, and debt has faded away, leaving behind a slightly unsettling impact, the entire modern law of contract has developed through the concept of Assumpsit, which needs further explanation.

After the Norman conquest all ordinary actions were begun by a writ issuing from the king, and ordering the defendant to be summoned before the court to answer the plaintiff. These writs were issued as a matter of course, in the various well-known actions from which they took their names. There were writs of debt and of covenant; there were writs of trespass for forcible injuries to the plaintiff's person, or to property in his possession, and so on. But these writs were only issued for the actions which were known to the law, and without a writ the court had no authority to try a case. In the time of Edward I. there were but few of such actions. The cases in which you could recover money of another fell into a small number of groups, for each of which there was a particular form of suing and stating your claim.

After the Norman conquest, all standard legal actions began with a writ issued by the king, summoning the defendant to appear before the court to respond to the plaintiff. These writs were issued automatically for the various well-known actions they represented. There were writs for debt and for breach of contract; there were writs for trespass involving physical harm to the plaintiff or damage to property in their possession, and so on. However, these writs were only issued for actions recognized by law, and without a writ, the court had no power to hear a case. During the time of Edward I, there were only a few such actions. The situations in which you could recover money from someone else were limited to a small number of categories, each with its own specific way of filing a claim and stating your case.

These forms had ceased to be adequate. Thus there were many cases which did not exactly fall within the definition of a trespass, but for which it was proper that a remedy should be furnished. In order to furnish a remedy, the first thing to be done was to furnish a writ. Accordingly, the famous statute of 13 Edward I., c. 24, authorized the office from which the old writs issued to frame new ones in cases similar in principle to those for which writs were found, and requiring like remedy, but not exactly falling within the scope of the writs already in use.

These forms were no longer sufficient. As a result, there were many situations that didn’t quite fit the definition of a trespass, but still needed a remedy. To provide a remedy, the first step was to create a writ. Therefore, the well-known statute of 13 Edward I., c. 24, allowed the office that issued the old writs to develop new ones for cases that were similar in principle to those that already had writs, requiring a similar remedy, but not strictly covered by the existing writs.

Thus writs of trespass on the case began to make their appearance; that is, writs stating a ground of complaint [275] to a trespass, but not quite amounting to a trespass as it had been sued for in the older precedents. To take an instance which is substantially one of the earliest cases, suppose that a man left a horse with a blacksmith to be shod, and he negligently drove a nail into the horse's foot. It might be that the owner of the horse could not have one of the old writs, because the horse was not in his possession when the damage was done. A strict trespass property could only be committed against the person in possession of it. It could not be committed by one who was in possession himself. /1/ But as laming the horse was equally a wrong, whether the owner held the horse by the bridle or left it with the smith, and as the wrong was closely analogous to a trespass, although not one, the law gave the owner a writ of trespass on the case. /2/

Thus, writs of trespass on the case started to emerge; that is, writs stating a reason for complaint related to a trespass, but not quite qualifying as a trespass as it had been claimed in older precedents. To illustrate with one of the earliest cases, suppose a man left a horse with a blacksmith to be shod, and the blacksmith carelessly drove a nail into the horse's foot. It might be that the horse’s owner couldn’t use one of the old writs because the horse wasn’t in his possession when the damage occurred. A strict trespass could only be committed against the person who had possession of it. It couldn’t be committed by one who was in possession themselves. But since injuring the horse was equally a wrong, whether the owner held the horse by the bridle or left it with the smith, and since the wrong was closely related to a trespass, although not exactly one, the law allowed the owner to receive a writ of trespass on the case.

An example like this raises no difficulty; it is as much an action of tort for a wrong as trespass itself. No contract was stated, and none was necessary on principle. But this does not belong to the class of cases to be considered, for the problem before us is to trace the origin of assumpsit, which is an action of contract. Assumpsit, however, began as an action of trespass on the case, and the thing to be discovered is how trespass on the case ever became available for a mere breach of agreement.

An example like this is straightforward; it's as much a wrongful act as trespass itself. No contract was mentioned, and one wasn’t needed in principle. However, this isn’t part of the cases we need to look at, because the issue we’re examining is the origin of assumpsit, which is a contract action. Assumpsit, though, started as a trespass on the case, and the key question is how trespass on the case became applicable to just a breach of agreement.

It will be well to examine some of the earliest cases in which an undertaking (assumpsit) was alleged. The first reported in the books is of the reign of Edward III. /3/ The plaintiff alleged that the defendant undertook to carry the plaintiff's horse safely across the Humber, but surcharged [276] the boat, by reason of which the horse perished. It was objected that the action should have been either covenant for breach of the agreement, or else trespass. But it was answered that the defendant committed a wrongful act when he surcharged the boat, and the objection was overruled. This case again, although an undertaking was stated, hardly introduced a new principle. The force did not proceed directly from the defendant, to be sure, but it was brought to bear by the combination of his overloading and then pushing into the stream.

It’s important to look at some of the earliest cases where a promise (assumpsit) was claimed. The first one recorded in the books is from the reign of Edward III. /3/ The plaintiff claimed that the defendant promised to safely transport the plaintiff's horse across the Humber but overloaded the boat, which caused the horse to die. It was argued that the action should have been either a breach of contract or a trespass. However, it was noted that the defendant committed a wrongful act when he overloaded the boat, and the objection was dismissed. This case, although it mentioned a promise, didn’t really introduce a new principle. While the force didn’t come directly from the defendant, it resulted from his overloading the boat and then pushing it into the water.

The next case is of the same reign, and goes further. /1/ The writ set forth that the defendant undertook to cure the plaintiff's horse of sickness (manucepit equum praedicti W. de infirmirate), and did his work so negligently that the horse died. This differs from the case of laming the horse with a nail in two respects. It does not charge any forcible act, nor indeed any act at all, but a mere omission. On the other hand, it states an undertaking, which the other did not. The defendant at once objected that this was an action for a breach of an undertaking, and that the plaintiff should have brought covenant. The plaintiff replied, that he could not do that without a deed, and that the action was for negligently causing the death of the horse; that is, for a tort, not for a breach of contract. Then, said the defendant, you might have had trespass. But the plaintiff answered that by saying that the horse was not killed by force, but died per def. de sa cure; and upon this argument the writ was adjudged good, Thorpe, J. saying that he had seen a man indicted for killing a patient by want of care (default in curing), whom he had undertaken to cure.

The next case is from the same time period and goes further. The writ stated that the defendant agreed to treat the plaintiff's sick horse and did so carelessly, causing the horse to die. This is different from the case where the horse was injured by a nail in two ways. First, it doesn't accuse anyone of a forceful action, or any action at all, but rather just a failure to act. Second, it mentions a specific promise, which the other case did not. The defendant immediately argued that this was a case about breaking a promise, and that the plaintiff should have filed a covenant instead. The plaintiff responded that he couldn't do that without a written deed, and that the case was about carelessly causing the horse's death; in other words, it was a tort, not a breach of contract. The defendant then suggested that the plaintiff could have pursued a trespass claim. But the plaintiff clarified that the horse wasn't killed by force, but died due to the defendant's failure to care for it; based on this reasoning, the writ was deemed valid, with Judge Thorpe saying he had seen someone charged with causing the death of a patient due to a lack of care when he had promised to treat them.

[277] Both these cases, it will be seen, were dealt with by the court as pure actions of tort, notwithstanding the allegation of an undertaking on the part of the defendant. But it will also be seen that they are successively more remote from an ordinary case of trespass. In the case last stated, especially, the destroying force did not proceed from the defendant in any sense. And thus we are confronted with the question, What possible analogy could have been found between a wrongful act producing harm, and a failure to act at all?

[277] In both of these cases, it’s clear that the court treated them as straightforward tort actions, despite the defendant's claim of responsibility. However, it’s also evident that they are increasingly distant from a typical case of trespass. In the last case mentioned, in particular, the destructive force didn’t actually come from the defendant in any way. This leads us to the question: What possible similarities could exist between a wrongful act causing harm and a complete failure to act?

I attempt to answer it, let me illustrate a little further by examples of somewhat later date. Suppose a man undertook to work upon another's house, and by his unskilfulness spoiled his employer's timbers; it would be like a trespass, although not one, and the employer would sue in trespass on the case. This was stated as clear law by one of the judges in the reign of Henry IV. /1/ But suppose that, instead of directly spoiling the materials, the carpenter had simply left a hole in the roof through which the rain had come in and done the damage. The analogy to the previous case is marked, but we are a step farther away from trespass, because the force does not come from the defendant. Yet in this instance also the judges thought that trespass on the case would lie. /2/ In the time of Henry IV. the action could not have been maintained for a simple refusal to build according to agreement; but it was suggested by the court, that, if the writ had mentioned "that the thing had been commenced and then by not done, it would have been otherwise." /3/

I try to answer it, so let me explain further with some more recent examples. Imagine a guy was hired to work on someone else's house, but due to his lack of skill, he ruined the materials. It would be similar to a trespass, even though it's not one, and the homeowner could sue for trespass on the case. This was clearly stated by one of the judges during the reign of Henry IV. But let’s say that instead of ruining the materials directly, the carpenter just left a hole in the roof, letting the rain in and causing damage. The comparison to the first case is clear, but we are further removed from trespass because the force isn’t coming directly from the carpenter. Still, in this case, the judges believed that a lawsuit for trespass on the case could still happen. Back in Henry IV's time, a lawsuit couldn’t simply be filed for not building according to the agreement; however, the court suggested that if the legal document had mentioned “that the work had started and then was not completed, it would have been different.”

[278] I now recur to the question, What likeness could there have been between an omission and a trespass sufficient to warrant a writ of trespass on the case? In order to find an answer it is essential to notice that in all the earlier cases the omission occurred in the course of dealing with the plaintiff's person or property, and occasioned damage to the one or the other. In view of this fact, Thorpe's reference to indictments for killing a patient by want of care, and the later distinction between neglect before and after the task is commenced, are most pregnant. The former becomes still more suggestive when it is remembered that this is the first argument or analogy to be found upon the subject.

[278] I now return to the question: What similarity could exist between an omission and a trespass that would justify a writ of trespass on the case? To find an answer, it's important to note that in all the earlier cases, the omission happened while dealing with the plaintiff's person or property and caused damage to one or the other. Given this fact, Thorpe's reference to indictments for causing a patient's death through negligence, as well as the later distinction made between neglect before and after the task begins, are particularly significant. The former becomes even more meaningful when we remember that this is the first argument or analogy on the subject.

The meaning of that analogy is plain. Although a man has a perfect right to stand by and see his neighbor's property destroyed, or, for the matter of that, to watch his neighbor perish for want of his help, yet if he once intermeddles he has no longer the same freedom. He cannot withdraw at will. To give a more specific example, if a surgeon from benevolence cuts the umbilical cord of a newly-born child, he cannot stop there and watch the patient bleed to death. It would be murder wilfully to allow death to come to pass in that way, as much as if the intention had been entertained at the time of cutting the cord. It would not matter whether the wickedness began with the act, or with the subsequent omission.

The meaning of that analogy is clear. Although a person has every right to stand by and watch their neighbor's property get destroyed, or even to see their neighbor suffer without helping, once they get involved, their freedom changes. They can't back out whenever they want. To illustrate this further, if a surgeon out of goodwill cuts the umbilical cord of a newborn, they can't just leave and watch the baby bleed to death. Allowing that to happen would be murder, just as much as if they had intended for the baby to die when they cut the cord. It doesn't matter if the wrongdoing started with the action or with the later neglect.

The same reasoning applies to civil liability. A carpenter need not go to work upon another man's house at all, but if he accepts the other's confidence and intermeddles, he cannot stop at will and leave the roof open to the weather. So in the case of the farrier, when he had taken charge of the horse, he could not stop at the critical moment [279] and leave the consequences to fortune. So, still more clearly, when the ferryman undertook to carry a horse across the Humber, although the water drowned the horse, his remote acts of overloading his boat and pushing it into the stream in that condition occasioned the loss, and he was answerable for it.

The same reasoning applies to civil liability. A carpenter doesn't have to work on someone else's house at all, but if he accepts the other person's trust and gets involved, he can't just walk away and leave the roof exposed to the elements. Similarly, in the case of the farrier, once he took responsibility for the horse, he couldn't just bail out at the critical moment and let fate decide the outcome. Even more clearly, when the ferryman agreed to transport a horse across the Humber, even though the water ended up drowning the horse, his earlier actions of overloading the boat and launching it under those conditions caused the loss, and he was responsible for it.

In the foregoing cases the duty was independent of contract, or at least was so regarded by the judges who decided them, and stood on the general rules applied to human conduct even by the criminal law. The immediate occasion of the damage complained of may have been a mere omission letting in the operation of natural forces. But if you connect it, as it was connected in fact, with the previous dealings, you have a course of action and conduct which, taken as a whole, has caused or occasioned the harm.

In the cases mentioned above, the responsibility was separate from any contract, or at least that’s how the judges saw it, and it was based on general principles governing human behavior, including those in criminal law. The direct cause of the damage claimed might have simply been a failure that allowed natural forces to take effect. However, if you link it, as it was in reality linked, to the prior interactions, you have a sequence of actions and behaviors that, when viewed as a whole, resulted in or contributed to the harm.

The objection may be urged, to be sure, that there is a considerable step from holding a man liable for the consequences of his acts which he might have prevented, to making him answerable for not having interfered with the course of nature when he neither set it in motion nor opened the door for it to do harm, and that there is just that difference between making a hole in a roof and leaving it open, or cutting the cord and letting it bleed, on the one side, and the case of a farrier who receives a sick horse and omits proper precautions, on the other. /1/

The argument can be made, of course, that there’s a significant difference between holding someone responsible for the results of their actions that they could have prevented, and making them accountable for not intervening in the natural order when they didn’t cause it to happen or allow it to cause harm. There’s a clear distinction between making a hole in a roof and leaving it open, or cutting a cord and letting it bleed, compared to a farrier who takes in a sick horse but fails to take appropriate precautions. /1/

There seem to be two answers to this. First, it is not clear that such a distinction was adverted to by the court which decided the case which I have mentioned. It was alleged that the defendant performed his cure so negligently that the horse died. It might not have occurred to [280] the judges that the defendant's conduct possibly went no further than the omission of a series of beneficial measures. It was probably assumed to have consisted of a combination of acts and neglects, which taken as a whole amounted to an improper dealing with the thing.

There seem to be two answers to this. First, it’s unclear whether the court that decided the case I mentioned recognized such a distinction. It was claimed that the defendant was so negligent in his treatment that the horse died. The judges might not have considered that the defendant's actions could have been limited to failing to take a series of beneficial steps. They likely assumed that his actions included a mix of both acts and neglect, which overall amounted to improper handling of the situation.

In the next place, it is doubtful whether the distinction is a sound one on practical grounds. It may well be that, so long as one allows a trust to be reposed in him, he is bound to use such precautions as are known to him, although he has made no contract, and is at liberty to renounce the trust in any reasonable manner. This view derives some support from the issue on which the parties went to trial, which was that the defendant performed the cure as well as he knew how, without this, that the horse died for default of his care (cure?). /1/

In the next place, it's uncertain whether this distinction is a practical one. It’s possible that as long as someone is trusted, they are required to take the precautions they are aware of, even if no contract exists, and they can choose to give up the trust in any reasonable way. This perspective is supported by the fact that the parties went to trial based on the issue that the defendant did his best to care for the horse, and without that, the horse died due to his lack of attention (care?). /1/

But it cannot be denied that the allegation of an undertaking conveyed the idea of a promise, as well as that of an entering upon the business in hand. Indeed, the latter element is sufficiently conveyed, perhaps, without it. It may be asked, therefore, whether the promise did not count for something in raising a duty to act. So far as this involves the consequence that the action was in fact for the breach of a contract, the answer has been given already, and is sustained by too great a weight of authority to be doubted. /2/ To bind the defendant by a contract, an instrument under seal was essential. As has been shown, already, even the ancient sphere of debt had been limited by this requirement, and in the time of Edward III. a deed was necessary even to bind a surety. It was so [281] a fortiori to introduce a liability upon promises not enforced by the ancient law. Nevertheless, the suggestion was made at an early date, that an action on the case for damage by negligence, that is, by an omission of proper precautions, alleging an undertaking by way of inducement, was in fact an action of contract.

But it can't be denied that the claim of an undertaking gave the impression of a promise, as well as suggesting that a business venture was being initiated. In fact, the latter point is generally clear, possibly even without needing this implication. One might wonder if the promise played a role in creating an obligation to act. To the extent that this implies that the action was actually for breaching a contract, this has already been addressed and is backed by enough authority to leave no room for doubt. To hold the defendant accountable under a contract, a sealed document was necessary. As previously demonstrated, even the historical area of debt was restricted by this requirement, and during the reign of Edward III, a deed was needed even to commit a guarantor. It was even more so necessary to create a liability for promises not enforced by the old laws. Nevertheless, it was suggested early on that a lawsuit for damages due to negligence, meaning the failure to take appropriate precautions, claiming an undertaking as a reason, was essentially a contract action.

Five years after the action for negligence in curing a horse, which has been stated, an action was brought /1/ in form against a surgeon, alleging that he undertook to cure the plaintiff's hand, and that by his negligence the hand was maimed. There was, however, this difference, that it was set forth that the plaintiff's hand had been wounded by one T.B. And hence it appeared that, however much the bad treatment may have aggravated matters, the maiming was properly attributable to T.B., and that the plaintiff had an action against him. This may have led the defendant to adopt the course he did, because he felt uncertain whether any action of tort would lie. He took issue on the undertaking, assuming that to be essential to the plaintiff's case, and then objected that the writ did not show the place of the undertaking, and hence was bad, because it did not show whence the inquest should be summoned to speak to that point. The writ was adjudged bad on that ground, which seems as if the court sanctioned the defendant's view. Indeed, one of the judges called it an action of covenant, and said that "of necessity it was maintainable without specialty, because for so small a matter a man cannot always have a clerk at hand to write a deed" (pur faire especially). At the same time the earlier cases which [282] have been mentioned were cited and relied on, and it is evident that the court was not prepared to go beyond them, or to hold that the action could be maintained on its merits apart from the technical objection. In another connection it seems to have considered the action from the point of view of trespass. /1/

Five years after the negligence lawsuit over a horse that was mentioned earlier, a case was filed against a surgeon, claiming that he agreed to treat the plaintiff's hand and that his negligence resulted in the hand being injured. However, there was an important difference: it was stated that the plaintiff's hand had been injured by someone named T.B. This indicated that, regardless of how much the poor treatment may have worsened the situation, the injury was primarily due to T.B., and the plaintiff had a case against him. This might have led the defendant to take the approach he did because he was unsure whether a tort case would be valid. He disputed the agreement, assuming it was crucial to the plaintiff's argument, and then argued that the writ did not specify where the agreement took place, making it invalid because it didn’t indicate where the jury should be summoned to address that issue. The writ was ruled invalid on that basis, which seemed to support the defendant's perspective. In fact, one of the judges referred to it as a covenant case and stated that "it necessarily needed to be maintainable without a formal contract because for such a minor issue, a person cannot always have a clerk available to draft a document" (pur faire especially). At the same time, the earlier cases that [282] had referenced were cited and relied upon, and it’s clear that the court was not willing to go beyond those precedents or to conclude that the case could be sustained on its merits without addressing the technical issue. In another context, it appeared to consider the case in terms of trespass.

Whatever questions this case may suggest, the class of actions which alleged an undertaking on the part of the defendant continued to be dealt with as actions of tort for a long time after Edward III. The liability was limited to damage to person or property arising after the defendant had entered upon the employment. And it was mainly through reasoning drawn from the law of tort that it was afterwards extended, as will be seen.

Whatever questions this case raises, the type of actions that claimed the defendant took on a responsibility continued to be treated as tort actions long after Edward III. The liability was restricted to harm to a person or property that occurred after the defendant started the employment. It was mainly through reasoning from tort law that it was later expanded, as will be shown.

At the beginning of the reign of Henry VI. it was probably still the law that the action would not lie for a simple failure to keep a promise. /2/ But it had been several times suggested, as has been shown, that it would be otherwise if the omission or neglect occurred in the course of performance, and the defendant's conduct had been followed by physical damage. /3/ This suggestion took its most striking form in the early years of Henry VI., when the case of the carpenter leaving a hole in the roof was put. /4/ When the courts had got as far as this, it was easy to go one step farther, and to allow the same effect to an omission at any stage, followed by similar damage.

At the start of Henry VI's reign, it was likely still the case that you couldn't sue for just breaking a promise. But, as we've seen, it had been suggested multiple times that things might be different if the failure or neglect happened during the process of fulfilling the promise, especially if it resulted in physical damage. This idea was most clearly illustrated in the early years of Henry VI, when a case was presented about a carpenter who left a hole in the roof. Once the courts moved this far, it was easy to extend the same reasoning to any omission at any stage that led to similar damage.

[283] What is the difference in principle, it was asked, a few years later, /1/ between the cases where it is admitted that the action will lie, and that of a smith who undertakes to shoe a horse and does not, by reason of which the horse goes lame,—or that of a lawyer, who undertakes to argue your case, and, after thus inducing you to rely upon him, neglects to be present, so that you lose it? It was said that in the earlier instances the duty was dependent on or accessory to the covenant, and that, if the action would lie on the accessory matter, it would lie on the principal. /2/ It was held on demurrer that an action would lie for not procuring certain releases which the defendant had undertaken to get.

[283] What’s the difference in principle, it was asked, a few years later, /1/ between the cases where it’s accepted that a lawsuit can proceed, and that of a blacksmith who agrees to shoe a horse and fails to do so, causing the horse to go lame—or that of a lawyer who promises to handle your case and, after making you depend on him, fails to show up, leading you to lose? It was stated that in the earlier cases, the duty was dependent on or related to the agreement, and that if you could sue for the related matter, you could also sue for the main issue. /2/ It was determined on appeal that you could take legal action for not obtaining certain releases that the defendant had promised to secure.

Five years later another case /3/ came up, which was very like that of the farrier in the reign of Edward III. It was alleged that the defendant undertook to cure the plaintiff's horse, and applied medicine so negligently that the horse died. In this, as in the earlier case, the issue was taken on the assumpsit. And now the difference between an omission and an act was clearly stated, the declaration was held not to mean necessarily anything more than an omission, and it was said that but for the undertaking the defendant would have owed no duty to act. Hence the allegation of the defendant's promise was material, and an issue could properly be taken on it.

Five years later, another case /3/ came up that was very similar to the case of the farrier in the reign of Edward III. It was claimed that the defendant agreed to treat the plaintiff's horse and applied medicine so carelessly that the horse died. In this case, as in the earlier one, the focus was on the assumpsit. Now, the distinction between an omission and an act was clearly outlined; the declaration was deemed to imply nothing more than an omission, and it was noted that without the agreement, the defendant wouldn't have had any duty to take action. Therefore, the defendant's promise was important, and a proper issue could be raised on it.

This decision distinctly separated from the mass of actions on the case a special class arising out of a promise as the source of the defendant's obligation, and it was only a matter of time for that class to become a new and distinct [284] action of contract. Had this change taken place at once, the doctrine of consideration, which was first definitely enunciated about the same time, would no doubt have been applied, and a quid pro quo would have been required for the undertaking. /1/ But the notion of tort was not at once abandoned. The law was laid down at the beginning of the reign of Henry VII., in accordance with the earlier decisions, and it was said that the action would not lie for a failure to keep a promise, but only for negligence after the defendant had entered upon his undertaking. /2/

This decision clearly set apart a special category from the many actions in the case, arising from a promise as the basis of the defendant's obligation, and it was just a matter of time before this category evolved into a new and distinct [284] action of contract. If this change had happened immediately, the doctrine of consideration, which was first clearly articulated around that time, would surely have been applied, and a quid pro quo would have been necessary for the commitment. /1/ However, the concept of tort wasn't immediately discarded. The law was established at the start of Henry VII's reign, following earlier decisions, stating that an action would not be valid for failing to fulfill a promise, only for negligence after the defendant had taken on his task. /2/

So far as the action did not exceed the true limits of tort, it was immaterial whether there was a consideration for the undertaking or not. But when the mistake was made of supposing that all cases, whether proper torts or not, in which an assumpsit was alleged, were equally founded on the promise, one of two erroneous conclusions was naturally thought to follow. Either no assumpsit needed any quid pro quo, /3/ as there was clearly none in the older precedents, (they being cases of pure tort,) or else those precedents were wrong, and a quid pro quo should be alleged in every case. It was long recognized with more or less understanding of the true limit, that, in cases where the gist of the action was negligent damage to property, a consideration was not necessary. /4/ And there are some traces of the notion that it was always superfluous, as late as Charles I.

As long as the action didn't go beyond the true boundaries of tort, it didn't matter whether there was a consideration for the undertaking. However, when one mistakenly believed that all cases, whether valid torts or not, that involved an assumpsit were equally based on a promise, two incorrect conclusions were typically thought to follow. Either no assumpsit required any quid pro quo, as clearly there was none in the older cases (which were pure tort cases), or those earlier cases were incorrect, and a quid pro quo should be specified in every instance. It was long acknowledged, to varying degrees of understanding about the true limits, that in situations where the core of the action was negligent damage to property, a consideration wasn't necessary. And there are some hints of the belief that it was always unnecessary, even into the time of Charles I.

[285] In a case of that reign, the defendant retained an attorney to act in a suit for a third person, and promised to pay him all his fees and expenses. The attorney rendered the service, and then brought debt. It was objected that debt did not lie, because there was no contract between the parties, and the defendant had not any quid pro quo. The court adopted the argument, and said that there was no contract or consideration to ground this action, but that the plaintiff might have sued in assumpsit. /1/

[285] During that reign, the defendant hired a lawyer to represent someone else and agreed to cover all his fees and expenses. The lawyer provided the service and then filed a lawsuit for payment. It was argued that a lawsuit for debt was not appropriate because there was no contract between the parties, and the defendant received nothing in return. The court agreed with this argument, stating that there was no contract or consideration to support this lawsuit, but that the plaintiff could have sued for breach of contract instead. /1/

It was, perhaps, the lingering of this idea, and the often repeated notion that an assumpsit was not a contract, /2/ to which was attributable a more enlarged theory of consideration than prevailed in debt. It was settled that assumpsit would lie for a mere omission or nonfeasance. The cases which have been mentioned of the reign of Henry VI. were followed by others in the latter years of Henry VII., /3/ and it was never again doubted. An action for such a cause was clearly for a breach of promise, as had been recognized from the time of Edward III. If so, a consideration was necessary. /4/ Notwithstanding occasional vagaries, that also had been settled or taken for granted in many cases of Queen Elizabeth's time. But the bastard origin of the action which gave rise to the doubt how far any consideration at all was necessary, made it possible to hold considerations sufficient which had been in debt.

It was likely the persistence of this idea, along with the frequently repeated belief that an assumpsit wasn’t a contract, that contributed to a broader understanding of consideration than what existed in debt cases. It was established that assumpsit could be applied for a simple omission or failure to act. The cases from the reign of Henry VI were followed by others in the later years of Henry VII, and this was never questioned again. An action based on such grounds was clearly a breach of promise, as had been acknowledged since the time of Edward III. If that’s the case, a consideration was necessary. Despite occasional inconsistencies, this too had been settled or assumed in many cases during Queen Elizabeth's reign. However, the questionable origin of the action raised doubts about how much consideration was actually needed, allowing for the acceptance of considerations that had sufficed in debt cases.

Another circumstance may not have been without its influence. It would seem that, in the period when assumpsit [286] was just growing into its full proportions, there was some little inclination to identify consideration with the Roman causa, taken in its broadest sense. The word "cause" was used for consideration in the early years of Elizabeth, with reference to a covenant to stand seized to uses. /1/ It was used in the same sense in the action of assumpsit. /2/ In the last cited report, although the principal case only laid down a doctrine that would be followed to-day, there was also stated an anonymous case which was interpreted to mean that an executed consideration furnished upon request, but without any promise of any kind, would support a subsequent promise to pay for it. /3/ Starting from this authority and the word "cause," the conclusion was soon reached that there was a great difference between a contract and an assumpsit; and that, whereas in contracts "everything which is requisite ought to concur and meet together, viz. the consideration of the one side, and the sale or the promise on the other side,... to maintain an action upon an assumpsit, the same is not requisite, for it is sufficient if there be a moving cause or consideration precedent; for which cause or consideration the promise was made." /4/

Another factor may have played a role. It seems that during the time when assumpsit [286] was developing, there was some inclination to equate consideration with the Roman causa, understood in its broadest sense. The term "cause" was used for consideration in the early years of Elizabeth, particularly relating to a covenant to stand seized to uses. /1/ It was also used in the same context in the action of assumpsit. /2/ In the last cited report, although the main case only established a principle that remains valid today, there was also an anonymous case mentioned which was interpreted to suggest that an executed consideration provided upon request, but without any promise, would support a later promise to pay for it. /3/ Building on this authority and the term "cause," it was soon concluded that there is a significant difference between a contract and an assumpsit; and that while in contracts "everything that is necessary should align and come together, namely the consideration on one side, and the sale or the promise on the other side,... to bring an action upon an assumpsit, this is not required, for it is enough if there is a moving cause or consideration provided beforehand; for which cause or consideration the promise was made." /4/

Thus, where the defendant retained the plaintiff to be [287] to his aunt at ten shillings a week, it was held that assumpsit would lie, because the service, though not beneficial to the defendant, was a charge or detriment to the plaintiff. /1/ The old questions were reargued, and views which were very near prevailing in debt under Henry VI., prevailed in assumpsit under Elizabeth and James.

Thus, where the defendant hired the plaintiff to be [287] to his aunt for ten shillings a week, it was decided that a claim for breach of promise could be made, because the service, even though not helpful to the defendant, was a cost or disadvantage to the plaintiff. /1/ The old questions were reargued, and views that were very close to winning in debt under Henry VI prevailed in breach of promise under Elizabeth and James.

A surety could be sued in assumpsit, although he had ceased to be liable in debt. /2/ There was the same remedy on a promise in consideration that the plaintiff would marry the defendant's daughter. /3/ The illusion that assumpsit thus extended did not mean contract, could not be kept up. In view of this admission and of the ancient precedents, the law oscillated for a time in the direction of reward as the true essence of consideration. /4/ But the other view prevailed, and thus, in fact, made a change in the substantive law. A simple contract, to be recognized as binding by the courts of Henry VI., must have been based upon a benefit to the debtor; now a promise might be enforced in consideration of a detriment to the promisee. But in the true archaic spirit the doctrine was not separated or distinguished from the remedy which introduced it, and thus debt in modern times has presented the altered appearance of a duty limited to cases where the consideration was of a special sort.

A guarantor could be sued for a promise, even if they were no longer liable for a debt. There was the same legal remedy for a promise made in exchange for the plaintiff marrying the defendant's daughter. The misconception that this type of promise could not mean an actual contract couldn’t be maintained. Given this acknowledgment and ancient precedents, the law wavered for a while in the direction of reward as the true essence of consideration. However, the alternate view ultimately won out, leading to a change in the substantive law. For a simple contract to be recognized as binding by the courts during Henry VI's reign, it had to be based on a benefit to the debtor; now, a promise could be enforced based on a detriment to the promisee. But in the true original spirit, the doctrine wasn’t separated from the remedy that introduced it. Consequently, in modern times, debt has come to appear as a duty limited to cases where the consideration was of a specific type.

The later fortunes of assumpsit can be briefly told. It introduced bilateral contracts, because a promise was a [288] detriment, and therefore a sufficient consideration for another promise. It supplanted debt, because the existence of the duty to pay was sufficient consideration for a promise to pay, or rather because, before a consideration was required, and as soon as assumpsit would lie for a nonfeasance, this action was used to avoid the defendant's wager of law. It vastly extended the number of actionable contracts, which had formerly been confined to debts and covenants, whereas nearly any promise could be sued in assumpsit; and it introduced a theory which has had great influence on modern law,—that all the liabilities of a bailee are founded on contract. /1/ Whether the prominence which was thus given to contract as the foundation of legal rights and duties had anything to do with the similar prominence which it soon acquired in political speculation, it is beyond my province to inquire.

The later developments of assumpsit can be summarized quickly. It introduced bilateral contracts, since a promise was a [288] detriment, making it a valid consideration for another promise. It replaced debt because the obligation to pay was enough consideration for a promise to pay, or rather because, before a consideration was needed, and as soon as assumpsit could be claimed for a failure to act, this action was used to bypass the defendant's wager of law. It greatly expanded the types of actionable contracts, which were previously limited to debts and covenants, so that nearly any promise could be enforced in assumpsit; and it brought in a theory that has greatly influenced modern law—that all the responsibilities of a bailee are based on contract. /1/ Whether the emphasis placed on contract as the basis of legal rights and duties influenced its similar significance in political thought is beyond my scope to explore.

[289]

[289]





LECTURE VIII. — CONTRACT. II. ELEMENTS.

THE general method to be pursued in the analysis of contract is the same as that already explained with regard to possession. Wherever the law gives special rights to one, or imposes special burdens on another, it does so on the ground that certain special facts are true of those individuals. In all such cases, therefore, there is a twofold task. First, to determine what are the facts to which the special consequences are attached; second, to ascertain the consequences. The first is the main field of legal argument. With regard to contracts the facts are not always the same. They may be that a certain person has signed, sealed, and delivered a writing of a certain purport. They may be that he has made an oral promise, and that the promisee has furnished him a consideration.

THE general method of analyzing contracts is the same as what has been explained regarding possession. Whenever the law grants specific rights to one person or places special responsibilities on another, it does so because certain specific facts apply to those individuals. Therefore, in all these cases, there are two main tasks. First, to identify the facts to which the special outcomes are tied; second, to understand those outcomes. The first task is the primary area of legal discussion. When it comes to contracts, the facts aren’t always identical. They could be that a person has signed, sealed, and delivered a document with a specific meaning. They might be that he has made an oral promise, and that the person receiving the promise has provided him with a consideration.

The common element of all contracts might be said to be a promise, although even a promise was not necessary to a liability in debt as formerly understood. But as it will not be possible to discuss covenants further, and as consideration formed the main topic of the last Lecture, I will take up that first. Furthermore, as there is an historical difference between consideration in debt and in assumpsit, I shall confine myself to the latter, which is the later and more philosophical form.

The common element in all contracts can be seen as a promise, even though a promise wasn't always necessary for liability in debt as it was previously understood. Since we can't discuss covenants in more detail and consideration was the main topic of the last lecture, I'll address that first. Additionally, since there's a historical difference between consideration in debt and in assumpsit, I will focus only on the latter, which is the more modern and philosophical form.

It is said that any benefit conferred by the promisee on the promisor, or any detriment incurred by the promisee, [290] may be a consideration. It is also thought that every consideration may be reduced to a case of the latter sort, using the word "detriment" in a somewhat broad sense.

It’s said that any benefit given by the promisee to the promisor, or any disadvantage faced by the promisee, [290] can be considered as consideration. It’s also believed that every type of consideration can be seen as a case of the latter, using the term "detriment" in a somewhat broad way.

To illustrate the general doctrine, suppose that a man is desirous of having a cask of brandy carried from Boston to Cambridge, and that a truckman, either out of kindness or from some other motive, says that he will carry it, and it is delivered to him accordingly. If he carelessly staves in the cask, there would perhaps be no need to allege that he undertook to carry it, and on principle, and according to the older cases, if an undertaking was alleged, no consideration for the assumpsit need be stated. /1/ The ground of complaint in that case would be a wrong, irrespective of contract. But if the complaint was that he did not carry it as agreed, the plaintiff's difficulty would be that the truckman was not bound to do so unless there was a consideration for his promise. Suppose, therefore, that it was alleged that he promised to do so in consideration of the delivery to him. Would this be a sufficient consideration? The oldest cases, going on the notion of benefit to the promisor, said that it could not be, for it was a trouble, not a benefit. /2/ Then take it from the side of detriment. The delivery is a necessary condition to the promisor's doing the kindness, and if he does it, the delivery, so far from being a detriment to the promisee, is a clear benefit to him.

To illustrate the general principle, imagine a man wants to have a cask of brandy transported from Boston to Cambridge. A truck driver, either out of kindness or for some other reason, agrees to carry it, and the cask is delivered to him. If he carelessly damages the cask, there might not be a need to claim that he agreed to carry it. Based on principle and older cases, if an agreement was stated, no consideration for the promise needs to be mentioned. The basis for complaint in that situation would be a wrongdoing, separate from any contract. However, if the complaint is that he didn’t carry it as promised, the challenge for the plaintiff would be that the truck driver wasn’t obligated to do so unless there was consideration for his promise. Now, suppose it was claimed that he promised to do it in exchange for the delivery. Would that be enough consideration? The oldest cases, based on the idea of benefit to the promisor, said it wouldn’t be, as it only created trouble, not a benefit. Now, let’s consider it from the perspective of detriment. The delivery is crucial for the promisor to perform the favor, and if he goes through with it, the delivery, rather than being a burden to the promisee, is actually a clear benefit.

But this argument is a fallacy. Clearly the delivery would be sufficient consideration to enable the owner to declare in assumpsit for the breach of those duties which [291] arose, irrespective of contract, from the defendant's having undertaken to deal with the thing. /1/ It would be a sufficient consideration for any promise not involving a dealing with the thing for its performance, for instance, to pay a thousand dollars. /2/ And the law has not pronounced the consideration good or bad according to the nature of the promise founded upon it. The delivery is a sufficient consideration for any promise. /3/

But this argument is flawed. Clearly, the delivery would be enough consideration to allow the owner to file a claim for the breach of those duties which [291] came from, regardless of any contract, due to the defendant's handling of the item. /1/ It would be adequate consideration for any promise that doesn’t involve dealing with the item for its fulfillment, like paying a thousand dollars. /2/ And the law has not judged the consideration as good or bad based on the nature of the promise built on it. The delivery is sufficient consideration for any promise. /3/

The argument on the other side leaves out of sight the point of time at which the sufficiency of the consideration is to be determined. This is the moment when the consideration is furnished. At that moment the delivery of the cask is a detriment in the strictest sense. The owner of the cask has given up a present control over it, which he has a right to keep, and he has got in return, not a performance for which a delivery was necessary, but a mere promise of performance. The performance is still future. /4/

The argument from the other side overlooks when we should evaluate whether the consideration is sufficient. This should be considered at the time the consideration is provided. At that time, delivering the cask is a true detriment. The cask's owner has surrendered immediate control over it, a right they have, and in return, they only received a promise of performance, not an actual performance that required the delivery. The actual performance is still yet to come. /4/

But it will be seen that, although the delivery may be a consideration, it will not necessarily be one. A promise to carry might be made and accepted on the understanding that it was mere matter of favor, without consideration, and not legally binding. In that case the detriment of delivery would be incurred by the promisee as before, but obviously it would be incurred for the sole purpose of enabling the promisor to carry as agreed.

But it will be evident that, while delivery might be a factor, it doesn’t have to be. A promise to deliver could be made and accepted with the understanding that it was simply a favor, without any consideration, and not legally enforceable. In that situation, the delivery expense would still fall on the promisee, as before, but clearly it would be solely to allow the promisor to deliver as agreed.

[292] It appears to me that it has not always been sufficiently borne in mind that the same thing may be a consideration or not, as it is dealt with by the parties. The popular explanation of Coggs v. Bernard is, that the delivery was a consideration for a promise to carry the casks safely. I have given what I believe to be the true explanation, and that which I think Lord Holt had in view, in the fifth Lecture. /1/ But whether that which I have offered be true or not, a serious objection to the one which is commonly accepted is that the declaration does not allege that the delivery was the consideration.

[292] It seems to me that it hasn't always been fully recognized that the same action can be considered significant or not, depending on how the parties approach it. The common understanding of Coggs v. Bernard is that the delivery was a consideration for a promise to transport the casks safely. I've provided what I believe to be the accurate explanation, which I think Lord Holt intended in the fifth Lecture. /1/ However, whether my explanation is correct or not, a major issue with the commonly accepted one is that the declaration does not state that the delivery was the consideration.

The same caution should be observed in construing the terms of an agreement. It is hard to see the propriety of erecting any detriment which an instrument may disclose or provide for, into a consideration, unless the parties have dealt with it on that footing. In many cases a promisee may incur a detriment without thereby furnishing a consideration. The detriment may be nothing but a condition precedent to performance of the promise, as where a man promises another to pay him five hundred dollars if he breaks his leg. /2/

The same caution should be taken when interpreting the terms of an agreement. It’s difficult to justify considering any disadvantages revealed by a document as part of the deal unless both parties have agreed to that approach. In many situations, a promisee can suffer a disadvantage without actually providing consideration. This disadvantage may simply be a condition that must be met before the promise is fulfilled, like when someone promises to pay another five hundred dollars if they break their leg. /2/

The courts, however, have gone far towards obliterating this distinction. Acts which by a fair interpretation of language would seem to have been contemplated as only the compliance with a condition, have been treated as the consideration of the promise. /3/ And so have counter promises in an agreement which expressly stated other matters as the consideration. /4/ So it should be mentioned, subject [293] to the question whether there may not be a special explanation for the doctrine, that it is said that an assignment of a leasehold cannot be voluntary under the statute of 27 Elizabeth, c. 4, because the assignee comes into the obligations of the tenant. /1/ Yet the assignee's incurring this detriment may not be contemplated as the inducement of the assignment, and in many cases only amounts to a deduction from the benefit conferred, as a right of way would be, especially if the only obligation is to pay rent, which issues out of the land in theory of law.

The courts, however, have made significant progress in eliminating this distinction. Actions that, by a reasonable interpretation of language, would appear to have been intended solely as compliance with a condition have been regarded as the consideration for the promise. /3/ The same applies to counter-promises in an agreement that explicitly identified other matters as the consideration. /4/ It's also worth noting, subject [293] to the question of whether there might be a specific reason for the doctrine, that it’s stated that an assignment of a leasehold cannot be voluntary under the statute of 27 Elizabeth, c. 4, because the assignee assumes the obligations of the tenant. /1/ However, the assignee taking on this burden may not be seen as the reason for the assignment, and in many cases, it only serves as a reduction of the benefit received, like a right of way might be, especially if the only obligation is to pay rent, which theoretically comes from the land in legal terms.

But although the courts may have sometimes gone a little far in their anxiety to sustain agreements, there can be no doubt of the Principle which I have laid down, that the same thing may be a consideration or not, as it is dealt with by the parties. This raises the question how a thing must be dealt with, in order to make it a consideration.

But even though the courts may have occasionally pushed too hard to uphold agreements, there's no doubt about the principle I've established: the same thing can be a consideration or not, depending on how the parties handle it. This brings up the question of how something must be handled to qualify as a consideration.

It is said that consideration must not be confounded with motive. It is true that it must not be confounded with what may be the prevailing or chief motive in actual fact. A man may promise to paint a picture for five hundred dollars, while his chief motive may be a desire for fame. A consideration may be given and accepted, in fact, solely for the purpose of making a promise binding. But, nevertheless, it is the essence of a consideration, that, by the terms of the agreement, it is given and accepted as the motive or inducement of the promise. Conversely, the promise must be made and accepted as the conventional motive or inducement for furnishing the consideration. The root of the whole matter is the relation of reciprocal [294] conventional inducement, each for the other, between consideration and promise.

It is said that consideration should not be confused with motive. It's true that it shouldn't be mixed up with what might be the main or primary motive in reality. A person might agree to paint a picture for five hundred dollars, while their main motive might be a desire for recognition. A consideration can be given and accepted specifically to make a promise legally binding. However, the core idea of consideration is that, according to the terms of the agreement, it is given and accepted as the motivation or reason for the promise. Likewise, the promise must be made and accepted as the usual motivation or reason for providing the consideration. The fundamental issue is the relationship of reciprocal [294] conventional motivation, each for the other, between consideration and promise.

A good example of the former branch of the proposition is to be found in a Massachusetts case. The plaintiff refused to let certain wood be removed from his land by one who had made an oral bargain and given his note for it, unless he received additional security. The purchaser and the plaintiff accordingly went to the defendant, and the defendant put his name upon the note. The plaintiff thereupon let the purchaser carry off the wood. But, according to the testimony, the defendant signed without knowing that the plaintiff was to alter his position in any way on the faith of the signature, and it was held that, if that story was believed, there was no consideration. /1/

A good example of the first part of the statement can be found in a Massachusetts case. The plaintiff refused to allow someone to take certain wood from his land after making an oral agreement and giving a note for it, unless he received extra security. The buyer and the plaintiff went to the defendant, and the defendant signed the note. After that, the plaintiff allowed the buyer to take the wood. However, according to the testimony, the defendant signed without knowing that the plaintiff would change his position based on the signature, and it was determined that if that story was believed, there was no consideration. /1/

An illustration of the other half of the rule is to be found in those cases where a reward is offered for doing something, which is afterwards done by a person acting in ignorance of the offer. In such a case the reward cannot be claimed, because the alleged consideration has not been furnished on the faith of the offer. The tendered promise has not induced the furnishing of the consideration. The promise cannot be set up as a conventional motive when it was not known until after the alleged consideration was performed. /2/

An example of the other side of the rule can be seen in situations where a reward is offered for completing a task, but a person does it without knowing about the offer. In this case, the reward can't be claimed because the supposed consideration wasn't provided based on the offer. The promise made didn't lead to the providing of the consideration. The promise can't be considered a motivating factor if it wasn't known until after the supposed consideration was completed. /2/

Both sides of the relation between consideration and promise, and the conventional nature of that relation, may be illustrated by the case of the cask. Suppose that the [295] truckman is willing to carry the cask, and the owner to let him carry it, without any bargain, and that each knows the other's state of mind; but that the truckman, seeing his own advantage in the matter, says to the owner, "In consideration of your delivering me the cask, and letting me carry it, I promise to carry it," and that the owner thereupon delivers it. I suppose that the promise would be binding. The promise is offered in terms as the inducement for the delivery, and the delivery is made in terms as the inducement for the promise. It may be very probable that the delivery would have been made without a promise, and that the promise would have been made in gratuitous form if it had not been accepted upon consideration; but this is only a guess after all. The delivery need not have been made unless the owner chose, and having been made as the term of a bargain, the promisor cannot set up what might have happened to destroy the effect of what did happen. It would seem therefore that the same transaction in substance and spirit might be voluntary or obligatory, according to the form of words which the parties chose to employ for the purpose of affecting the legal consequences.

Both sides of the relationship between consideration and promise, along with the conventional nature of that relationship, can be illustrated by the case of the cask. Imagine that the truck driver is willing to carry the cask, and the owner is okay with him doing so, without any agreement, and both know how the other feels; but then the truck driver, seeing the benefit for himself, says to the owner, "In exchange for you giving me the cask and letting me carry it, I promise to carry it," and the owner then hands it over. I believe that the promise would be binding. The promise is made as an incentive for the delivery, and the delivery is made as an incentive for the promise. It’s quite possible that the delivery would have happened without a promise, and that the promise would have been given for free if it hadn’t been accepted in exchange for something; but that’s just a guess after all. The delivery didn’t have to occur unless the owner decided it should, and since it was made as part of a bargain, the person who made the promise can’t argue about what might have happened to invalidate what actually did happen. Therefore, it seems that the same transaction, in essence and intent, could be voluntary or obligatory, depending on the wording that the parties chose to use to affect the legal consequences.

If the foregoing principles be accepted, they will be seen to explain a doctrine which has given the courts some trouble to establish. I mean the doctrine that an executed consideration will not sustain a subsequent promise. It has been said, to be sure, that such a consideration was sufficient if preceded by a request. But the objections to the view are plain. If the request was of such a nature, and so put, as reasonably to imply that the other person was to have a reward, there was an express promise, although not put in words, and that promise was made at [296] the same time the consideration was given, and not afterwards. If, on the other hand, the words did not warrant the understanding that the service was to be paid for, the service was a gift, and a past gift can no more be a consideration than any other act of the promisee not induced by the promise.

If you accept the principles outlined above, they clarify a doctrine that has caused some difficulties for the courts to establish. I'm referring to the doctrine that an executed consideration cannot support a subsequent promise. It has been claimed, of course, that such a consideration is sufficient if it follows a request. However, the objections to this perspective are clear. If the request was made in such a way that reasonably implied the other person would receive a reward, there was an implied promise, even if it wasn't explicitly stated, and that promise was made at [296] the same time the consideration was given, not afterward. Conversely, if the words did not support the understanding that the service was to be compensated, then the service was considered a gift, and a past gift cannot serve as consideration any more than any other action of the promisee that wasn’t induced by the promise.

The source of the error can be traced partially, at least, in history. Some suggestions touching the matter were made in the last Lecture. A few words should be added here. In the old cases of debt, where there was some question whether the plaintiff had showed enough to maintain his action, a "contract precedent" was spoken of several times as raising the duty. Thus, where a man had granted that he would be bound in one hundred shillings to pay his servant on a certain day for his services, and for payments made by the servant on his account, it was argued that there was no contract precedent, and that by parol the party is not obliged; and, further, that, so far as appeared, the payments were made by the servant out of his own head and at no request, from which no duty could commence. /1/

The source of the error can at least partially be traced back in history. Some suggestions regarding this issue were made in the last lecture. A few additional points should be noted here. In past debt cases, where there was some question about whether the plaintiff had provided enough evidence to support their claim, a "precedent contract" was often mentioned as establishing the obligation. For example, when a man agreed to be responsible for one hundred shillings to pay his servant on a specific day for the servant's work and for any payments the servant made on his behalf, it was argued that there was no precedent contract, and that without a formal agreement, the party was not bound; furthermore, it was suggested that, as far as anyone could tell, the payments were made by the servant independently and without a request, from which no obligation could arise.

So when debt was brought on a deed to pay the plaintiff ten marks, if he would take the defendant's daughter to wife, and it was objected that the action should have been covenant, it was answered that the plaintiff had a contract precedent which gave him debt. /2/

So when there was a debt on a deed to pay the plaintiff ten marks if he would marry the defendant's daughter, and it was argued that the action should have been a covenant, it was replied that the plaintiff had a prior contract that entitled him to the debt. /2/

The first case in assumpsit /3/ only meant to adopt this long familiar thought. A man went bail for his friend's servant, who had been arrested. Afterwards the master [297] promised to indemnify the bail, and on his failure to do so was sued by him in assumpsit. It was held that there was no consideration wherefore the defendant should be charged unless the master had first promised to indemnify the plaintiff before the servant was bailed; "for the master did never make request to the plaintiff for his servant to do so much, but he did it of his own head." This is perfectly plain sailing, and means no more than the case in the Year Books. The report, however, also states a case in which it was held that a subsequent promise, in consideration that the plaintiff at the special instance of the defendant had married the defendant's cousin, was binding, and that the marriage was "good cause... because [it] ensued the request of the defendant." Whether this was intended to establish a general principle, or was decided with reference to the peculiar consideration of marriage, /1/ it was soon interpreted in the broader sense, as was shown in the last Lecture. It was several times adjudged that a past and executed matter was a sufficient consideration for a promise at a later day, if only the matter relied on had been done or furnished at the request of the promisor. /2/

The first case in assumpsit /3/ was simply meant to adopt this long-known idea. A man became a guarantor for his friend’s servant, who had been arrested. Later, the master [297] promised to cover the guarantor’s costs, and when he failed to do so, the guarantor sued him in assumpsit. It was determined that there was no reason for the defendant to be held liable unless the master had first promised to indemnify the plaintiff before the servant was bailed; "for the master never requested the plaintiff to act on his servant's behalf; he did it on his own." This is straightforward and doesn’t mean anything different than the case in the Year Books. However, the report also mentions a case where it was ruled that a subsequent promise, in consideration of the plaintiff marrying the defendant’s cousin at the defendant’s request, was binding, and that the marriage was "valid grounds... because [it] followed the request of the defendant." Whether this was meant to set a general principle, or was decided based on the specific consideration of marriage, /1/ it was soon understood in a broader context, as shown in the last Lecture. It was ruled multiple times that a past and completed action was enough consideration for a promise made later, as long as the action relied upon had been done or provided at the request of the promisor. /2/

It is now time to analyze the nature of a promise, which is the
second and most conspicuous element in a simple contract. The
Indian Contract Act, 1872, Section 2,8 says:—

 "(a.) When one person signifies to another his willingness [298]
to do or to abstain from doing anything, with a view to obtaining
the assent of that other to such act or abstinence, he is said to
make a proposal:

 "(b.) When the person to whom the proposal is made signifies his
assent thereto, the proposal is said to be accepted. A proposal
when accepted becomes a promise."
It’s time to examine the nature of a promise, which is the second and most important element in a simple contract. The Indian Contract Act, 1872, Section 2,8 states:—

 "(a.) When one person communicates to another his willingness [298] to do something or to refrain from doing something, with the intent of getting that other person’s agreement to that action or inaction, he is said to make a proposal:

 "(b.) When the person receiving the proposal indicates his agreement to it, the proposal is considered accepted. A proposal, once accepted, becomes a promise."

According to this definition the scope of promises is confined to conduct on the part of the promisor. If this only meant that the promisor alone must bear the legal burden which his promise may create, it would be true. But this is not the meaning. For the definition is of a promise, not of a legally binding promise. We are not seeking for the legal effects of a contract, but for the possible contents of a promise which the law may or may not enforce. We must therefore only consider the question what can possibly be promised in a legal sense, not what will be the secondary consequence of a promise binding, but not performed.

According to this definition, the scope of promises is limited to the actions of the promisor. If this only meant that the promisor has to handle the legal responsibility that their promise may create, then that would be accurate. However, that’s not the case. The definition relates to a promise, not necessarily a legally binding one. We are not looking for the legal implications of a contract, but rather the potential content of a promise that the law might or might not uphold. Therefore, we need to consider what can be legally promised, not the potential outcomes of a promise being binding but unfulfilled.

An assurance that it shall rain to-morrow, /1/ or that a third person shall paint a picture, may as well be a promise as one that the promisee shall receive from some source one hundred bales of cotton, or that the promisor will pay the promisee one hundred dollars. What is the difference in the cases? It is only in the degree of power possessed by the promisor over the event. He has none in the first case. He has equally little legal authority to make a man paint a picture, although he may have larger means of persuasion. He probably will be able to make sure that the promisee has the cotton. Being a rich man, he is certain [299] to be able to pay the one hundred dollars, except in the event of some most improbable accident.

An assurance that it will rain tomorrow, /1/ or that someone else will paint a picture, can be just as much of a promise as one where the promisee is guaranteed to receive one hundred bales of cotton, or that the promisor will pay the promisee one hundred dollars. What’s the difference in these situations? It only comes down to how much control the promisor has over the outcome. In the first case, they have none. They have just as little legal power to make someone paint a picture, even if they might have more persuasive abilities. However, they will likely ensure the promisee gets the cotton. Since they are wealthy, they are almost guaranteed to be able to pay the one hundred dollars, unless something highly unlikely happens.

But the law does not inquire, as a general thing, how far the accomplishment of an assurance touching the future is within the power of the promisor. In the moral world it may be that the obligation of a promise is confined to what lies within reach of the will of the promisor (except so far as the limit is unknown on one side, and misrepresented on the other). But unless some consideration of public policy intervenes, I take it that a man may bind himself at law that any future event shall happen. He can therefore promise it in a legal sense. It may be said that when a man covenants that it shall rain to-morrow, or that A shall paint a picture, he only says, in a short form, I will pay if it does not rain, or if A does not paint a picture. But that is not necessarily so. A promise could easily be framed which would be broken by the happening of fair weather, or by A not painting. A promise, then, is simply an accepted assurance that a certain event or state of things shall come to pass.

But the law generally doesn’t investigate how much control the person making a promise has over whether a future event will happen. In the moral sphere, it's possible that a promise only binds someone to what they can actually do (unless there's some unknown limit on one side and a misrepresentation on the other). However, unless there's a public policy concern, I believe that a person can legally commit to ensuring that a future event occurs. So, he can legally promise it. One might say that when someone promises it will rain tomorrow, or that A will paint a picture, they’re just saying, in a nutshell, “I’ll pay if it doesn’t rain” or “if A doesn’t paint a picture.” But that's not necessarily true. A promise can easily be worded to be broken by nice weather or A not painting. Thus, a promise is simply an accepted guarantee that a particular event or situation will occur.

But if this be true, it has more important bearings than simply to enlarge the definition of the word promise. It concerns the theory of contract. The consequences of a binding promise at common law are not affected by the degree of power which the promisor possesses over the promised event. If the promised event does not come to pass, the plaintiff's property is sold to satisfy the damages, within certain limits, which the promisee has suffered by the failure. The consequences are the same in kind whether the promise is that it shall rain, or that another man shall paint a picture, or that the promisor will deliver a bale of cotton.

But if this is true, it has more significant implications than just expanding the definition of the word promise. It relates to contract theory. The consequences of a binding promise under common law aren't influenced by how much control the person making the promise has over the event in question. If the promised event doesn't happen, the plaintiff's property is sold to cover the damages, within certain limits, that the person who received the promise has suffered due to the failure. The consequences are the same, whether the promise is that it will rain, that another person will paint a picture, or that the promisor will deliver a bale of cotton.

[300] If the legal consequence is the same in all cases, it seems proper that all contracts should be considered from the same legal point of view. In the case of a binding promise that it shall rain to-morrow, the immediate legal effect of what the promisor does is, that he takes the risk of the event, within certain defined limits, as between himself and the promisee. He does no more when he promises to deliver a bale of cotton.

[300] If the legal outcome is the same in all situations, it makes sense for all contracts to be viewed from the same legal perspective. In the case of a binding promise that it will rain tomorrow, the immediate legal effect of what the person making the promise does is that they assume the risk of the event, within certain defined limits, between themselves and the person receiving the promise. They are not doing anything more when they promise to deliver a bale of cotton.

If it be proper to state the common-law meaning of promise and contract in this way, it has the advantage of freeing the subject from the superfluous theory that contract is a qualified subjection of one will to another, a kind of limited slavery. It might be so regarded if the law compelled men to perform their contracts, or if it allowed promisees to exercise such compulsion. If, when a man promised to labor for another, the law made him do it, his relation to his promisee might be called a servitude ad hoc with some truth. But that is what the law never does. It never interferes until a promise has been broken, and therefore cannot possibly be performed according to its tenor. It is true that in some instances equity does what is called compelling specific performance. But, in the first place, I am speaking of the common law, and, in the next, this only means that equity compels the performance of certain elements of the total promise which are still capable of performance. For instance, take a promise to convey land within a certain time, a court of equity is not in the habit of interfering until the time has gone by, so that the promise cannot be performed as made. But if the conveyance is more important than the time, and the promisee prefers to have it late rather than never, the law may compel the performance of [301] that. Not literally compel even in that case, however, but put the promisor in prison unless he will convey. This remedy is an exceptional one. The only universal consequence of a legally binding promise is, that the law makes the promisor pay damages if the promised event does not come to pass. In every case it leaves him free from interference until the time for fulfilment has gone by, and therefore free to break his contract if he chooses.

If it's appropriate to express the common-law meaning of promise and contract this way, it has the benefit of removing the unnecessary theory that a contract is a constrained subjugation of one will to another, a kind of limited slavery. It could be seen that way if the law required people to fulfill their contracts, or if it allowed those owed promises to force compliance. If, for instance, when someone promised to work for another, the law mandated that he must do it, his relationship to the promisee could be fairly described as a temporary servitude. However, that's not what the law does. It doesn’t get involved until a promise has been broken, meaning the promise cannot be executed as intended. It’s true that in some cases equity does what’s called compelling specific performance. But, first of all, I'm discussing common law, and secondly, that just means equity enforces the execution of certain parts of the overall promise that can still be carried out. For example, take a promise to transfer land within a specific timeframe; a court of equity typically won’t step in until the time has expired, making the promise impossible to fulfill as initially made. But if getting the conveyance is more important than the timing, and the promisee would rather have it late than not at all, the law may allow for the enforcement of [301] that. However, even in that case, it doesn't literally compel compliance but may imprison the promisor until he follows through. This remedy is an exception. The only consistent result of a legally binding promise is that the law requires the promisor to pay damages if the promised event doesn't occur. In every instance, it lets him remain free from interference until the deadline for fulfillment has passed, thus allowing him the option to break his contract if he wants.

A more practical advantage in looking at a contract as the taking of a risk is to be found in the light which it throws upon the measure of damages. If a breach of contract were regarded in the same light as a tort, it would seem that if, in the course of performance of the contract the promisor should be notified of any particular consequence which would result from its not being performed, he should be held liable for that consequence in the event of non-performance. Such a suggestion has been made. /1/ But it has not been accepted as the law. On the contrary, according to the opinion of a very able judge, which seems to be generally followed, notice, even at the time of making the contract, of special circumstances out of which special damages would arise in case of breach, is not sufficient unless the assumption of that risk is to be taken as having fairly entered into the contract. /2/ If a carrier should undertake to carry the machinery of a saw-mill from Liverpool to Vancouver's Island, and should fail [302] to do so, he probably would not be held liable for the rate of hire of such machinery during the necessary delay, although he might know that it could not be replaced without sending to England, unless he was fairly understood to accept "the contract with the special condition attached to it." /1/

A more practical advantage of viewing a contract as a risk assumption is how it clarifies the measure of damages. If a breach of contract were treated like a tort, it would seem that if the promisor is informed of any specific consequences that would result from failing to fulfill the contract, they should be responsible for those consequences if they don't perform. Some have suggested this. /1/ However, it hasn't been accepted as law. On the contrary, according to the view of a highly regarded judge, which appears to be widely followed, even if someone is informed of specific circumstances at the time of making the contract that could lead to special damages in the event of a breach, that alone isn't enough unless it's clear that accepting that risk was part of the contract. /2/ For example, if a carrier agrees to transport machinery from Liverpool to Vancouver Island and fails [302] to do so, they probably wouldn't be held liable for the rental rate of that machinery during the resulting delay, even if they knew it couldn't be replaced without ordering from England, unless it was clearly understood that they accepted "the contract with the special condition attached to it." /1/

It is true that, when people make contracts, they usually contemplate the performance rather than the breach. The express language used does not generally go further than to define what will happen if the contract is fulfilled. A statutory requirement of a memorandum in writing would be satisfied by a written statement of the promise as made, because to require more would be to run counter to the ordinary habits of mankind, as well as because the statement that the effect of a contract is the assumption of the risk of a future event does not mean that there is a second subsidiary promise to assume that risk, but that the assumption follows as a consequence directly enforced by the law, without the promisor's co-operation. So parol evidence would be admissible, no doubt, to enlarge or diminish the extent of the liability assumed for nonperformance, where it would be inadmissible to affect the scope of the promise.

It's true that when people make contracts, they usually think about the performance rather than the breach. The specific language used typically only explains what will happen if the contract is fulfilled. A legal requirement for a written memorandum would be met with a written statement of the promise as it was made, because asking for more would go against the normal habits of people. Additionally, the idea that a contract's effect is the assumption of risk for a future event doesn't imply there is a secondary promise to take on that risk; instead, the assumption is directly enforced by law, without needing the promisor's cooperation. Therefore, parol evidence would be allowed to expand or reduce the extent of liability for nonperformance, while it wouldn't be allowed to change the scope of the promise.

But these concessions do not affect the view here taken. As the relation of contractor and contractee is voluntary, the consequences attaching to the relation must be voluntary. What the event contemplated by the promise is, or in other words what will amount to a breach of contract, is a matter of interpretation and construction. What consequences of the breach are assumed is more remotely, in like manner, a matter of construction, having regard [303] to the circumstances under which the contract is made. Knowledge of what is dependent upon performance is one of those circumstances. It is not necessarily conclusive, but it may have the effect of enlarging the risk assumed.

But these concessions don’t change the view expressed here. Since the relationship between the contractor and the contractee is voluntary, the results that come from that relationship must also be voluntary. What the promise is meant to achieve, or in other words, what would count as a breach of contract, is a matter of interpretation and understanding. The consequences of the breach that are assumed are similarly a matter of interpretation, taking into account the circumstances under which the contract is made. Understanding what is dependent on performance is one of those circumstances. It’s not necessarily final, but it can increase the risk involved.

The very office of construction is to work out, from what is expressly said and done, what would have been said with regard to events not definitely before the minds of the parties, if those events had been considered. The price paid in mercantile contracts generally excludes the construction that exceptional risks were intended to be assumed. The foregoing analysis is believed to show that the result which has been reached by the courts on grounds of practical good sense, falls in with the true theory of contract under the common law.

The main role of interpretation is to determine, based on what is clearly stated and done, what would have been said about situations that the parties didn't explicitly consider if those situations had been addressed. The price agreed upon in business contracts typically rules out the interpretation that unusual risks were meant to be taken on. The analysis above suggests that the conclusions reached by the courts, based on practical common sense, align with the true theory of contracts under common law.

The discussion of the nature of a promise has led me to analyze contract and the consequences of contract somewhat in advance of their place. I must say a word more concerning the facts which constitute a promise. It is laid down, with theoretical truth, that, besides the assurance or offer on the one side, there must be an acceptance on the other. But I find it hard to think of a case where a simple contract fails to be made, which could not be accounted for on other grounds, generally by the want of relation between assurance or offer and consideration as reciprocal inducements each of the other. Acceptance of an offer usually follows by mere implication from the furnishing of the consideration; and inasmuch as by our law an accepted offer, or promise, until the consideration is furnished, stands on no different footing from an offer not yet accepted, each being subject to revocation until that time, and each continuing [304] until then unless it has expired or has been revoked, the question of acceptance is rarely of practical importance.

The discussion about the nature of a promise has led me to analyze contracts and their consequences a bit earlier than they might typically be addressed. I need to say a bit more about the facts that make up a promise. It's established, with theoretical accuracy, that in addition to the assurance or offer from one side, there must also be an acceptance from the other side. However, I find it difficult to think of a situation where a simple contract doesn’t come into existence without being able to explain it by other reasons, usually due to a lack of a connection between the assurance or offer and the consideration, which serve as reciprocal motivations for each other. Acceptance of an offer usually occurs just by implication from providing the consideration; and since our law states that an accepted offer, or promise, remains on the same level as an unaccepted offer until the consideration is provided, both are subject to withdrawal until that point and both remain valid until then unless they have expired or have been revoked. Therefore, the issue of acceptance is rarely of practical significance.

Assuming that the general nature of consideration and promise is understood, some questions peculiar to bilateral contracts remain to be considered. These concern the sufficiency of the consideration and the moment when the contract is made.

Assuming that the basic idea of consideration and promise is understood, a few specific questions about bilateral contracts still need to be addressed. These relate to the adequacy of the consideration and the exact time when the contract is formed.

A promise may be a consideration for a promise, although not every promise for every other. It may be doubted whether a promise to make a gift of one hundred dollars would be supported by a promise to accept it. But in a case of mutual promises respectively to transfer and to accept unpaid shares in a railway company, it has been held that a binding contract was made. Here one party agrees to part with something which may prove valuable, and the other to assume a liability which may prove onerous. /1/

A promise can serve as consideration for another promise, but not all promises work that way. For instance, it’s questionable whether a promise to give someone one hundred dollars would be valid if countered by a promise to accept it. However, in a situation where both parties promise to transfer and accept unpaid shares in a railway company, it has been decided that a binding contract exists. In this case, one party agrees to give up something that could be valuable, while the other takes on a potentially burdensome obligation. /1/

But now suppose that there is no element of uncertainty except in the minds of the parties. Take, for instance, a wager on a past horse-race. It has been thought that this would amount to an absolute promise on one side, and no promise at all on the other. /2/ But this does not seem to me sound. Contracts are dealings between men, by which they make arrangements for the future. In making such arrangements the important thing is, not what is objectively true, but what the parties know. Any present fact which is unknown to the parties is just as uncertain for the purposes of making an arrangement at this moment, as any future fact. It is therefore a detriment to undertake to be ready to pay if the event turns out not [305] to have been as expected. This seems to be the true explanation why forbearance to sue upon a claim believed the plaintiff to be good is a sufficient consideration, although the claim was bad in fact, and known by the defendant to be bad. /1/ Were this view unsound, it is hard to see how wagers on any future event, except a miracle, could be sustained. For if the happening or not happening of the event is subject to the law of causation, the only uncertainty about it is in our foresight, not in its happening.

But now imagine that there’s no uncertainty except in the minds of the people involved. Take, for example, a bet on a past horse race. It has been thought that this would result in a total promise from one side and no promise from the other. But this perspective doesn’t seem right to me. Contracts are agreements between people, where they plan for the future. When making these plans, what really matters is not what is objectively true, but what the parties actually know. Any current fact that is unknown to the parties is just as uncertain for the purpose of making an agreement at this moment as any future fact. Therefore, it’s a disadvantage to agree to be ready to pay if the outcome turns out not to have been as expected. This seems to be the real reason why choosing not to sue on a claim believed by the plaintiff to be valid counts as sufficient consideration, even though the claim was actually invalid and known by the defendant to be invalid. If this view were incorrect, it’s hard to see how bets on any future event, except for a miracle, could be justified. Because if the occurrence or non-occurrence of the event follows the law of causation, the only uncertainty about it lies in our ability to foresee it, not in whether it will actually happen.

The question when a contract is made arises for the most part with regard to bilateral contracts by letter, the doubt being whether the contract is complete at the moment when the return promise is put into the post, or at the moment when it is received. If convenience preponderates in favor of either view, that is a sufficient reason for its adoption. So far as merely logical grounds go, the most ingenious argument in favor of the later moment is Professor Langdell's. According to him the conclusion follows from the fact that the consideration which makes the offer binding is itself a promise. Every promise, he says, is an offer before it is a promise, and the essence of an offer is that it should be communicated. /2/ But this reasoning seems unsound. When, as in the case supposed, the consideration for the return promise has been put into the power of the offeree and the return promise has been accepted in advance, there is not an instant, either in time or logic, when the return promise is an offer. It is a promise and a term of a binding contract as soon as it is anything. An offer is a revocable and unaccepted communication of willingness to promise. [306] When an offer of a certain bilateral contract has been made, the same contract cannot be offered by the other side. The so-called offer would neither be revocable nor unaccepted. It would complete the contract as soon as made.

The question of when a contract is formed mostly comes up with bilateral contracts made by mail. The uncertainty is whether the contract is finalized when the return promise is mailed or when it is received. If convenience leans toward either option, that’s a valid reason to choose it. Logically speaking, the strongest argument for the later timing comes from Professor Langdell. He argues that the conclusion stems from the fact that the consideration making the offer binding is itself a promise. According to him, every promise is an offer before it becomes a promise, and the essence of an offer is that it should be communicated. /2/ However, this reasoning seems flawed. In the situation described, when the consideration for the return promise has been given to the offeree and the return promise has already been accepted, there’s no moment—in terms of time or logic—when the return promise is merely an offer. It is a promise and a part of a binding contract as soon as it exists. An offer is a revocable and unaccepted indication of willingness to promise. [306] Once an offer for a specific bilateral contract is made, the other party cannot offer the same contract. That so-called offer wouldn’t be revocable or unaccepted; it would complete the contract as soon as it’s made.

If it be said that it is of the essence of a promise to be communicated, whether it goes through the stage of offer or not, meaning by communicated brought to the actual knowledge of the promisee, the law is believed to be otherwise. A covenant is binding when it is delivered and accepted, whether it is read or not. On the same principle, it is believed that, whenever the obligation is to be entered into by a tangible sign, as, in the case supposed, by letter containing the return promise, and the consideration for and assent to the promise are already given, the only question is when the tangible sign is sufficiently put into the power of the promisee. I cannot believe that, if the letter had been delivered to the promisee and was then snatched from his hands before he had read it, there would be no contract. /1/ If I am right, it appears of little importance whether the post-office be regarded as agent or bailee for the offerer, or as a mere box to which he has access. The offeree, when he drops the letter containing the counter-promise into the letter-box, does an overt act, which by general understanding renounces control over the letter, and puts it into a third hand for the benefit of the offerer, with liberty to the latter at any moment thereafter to take it.

If it's said that a promise must be communicated, meaning it needs to be brought to the actual knowledge of the person receiving the promise, the law actually thinks otherwise. A covenant becomes binding when it’s delivered and accepted, regardless of whether it’s read or not. Similarly, whenever an obligation is to be established through a physical sign, like in this case with a letter containing the return promise, and the consideration for and agreement to the promise have already been exchanged, the only real question is when the physical sign is sufficiently placed into the hands of the promisee. I can’t believe that if the letter had been delivered to the promisee and then snatched away before he had a chance to read it, there would be no contract. If I’m correct, it seems to matter very little whether the post office is seen as an agent or a bailee for the offerer, or just as a simple box that he can access. When the offeree drops the letter with the counter-promise into the mailbox, he takes an action that, by common understanding, gives up control over the letter and hands it over to a third party for the benefit of the offerer, allowing the latter to retrieve it at any time afterward.

The principles governing revocation are wholly different. One to whom an offer is made has a right to assume that it remains open according to its terms until he has actual [307] notice to the contrary. The effect of the communication must be destroyed by a counter communication. But the making of a contract does not depend on the state of the parties' minds, it depends on their overt acts. When the sign of the counter promise is a tangible object, the contract is completed when the dominion over that object changes.

The rules around revocation are completely different. Someone who receives an offer has the right to assume that it stays open as stated until they get actual [307] notice that it isn’t. A counter-communication must negate the effect of the original communication. However, forming a contract doesn’t rely on how the parties feel; it relies on their visible actions. When the sign of the counter-promise is a physical item, the contract is completed when control over that item changes.

[308]

[308]





LECTURE IX. — CONTRACT.—III. VOID AND VOIDABLE.

THE elements of fact necessary to call a contract into existence, and the legal consequences of a contract when formed, have been discussed. It remains to consider successively the cases in which a contract is said to be void, and those in which it is said to be voidable,—in which, that is, a contract fails to be made when it seems to have been, or, having been made, can be rescinded by one side or the other, and treated as if it had never been. I take up the former class of cases first.

The key elements needed to create a contract and the legal implications of a contract once it's formed have been covered. Now, we need to look at the situations where a contract is considered void and those where it’s considered voidable—meaning a contract doesn’t actually exist even though it appears to, or if it has been created, it can be canceled by either party and treated as if it never existed. I’ll start with the first category of cases.

When a contract fails to be made, although the usual forms have been gone through with, the ground of failure is commonly said to be mistake, misrepresentation, or fraud. But I shall try to show that these are merely dramatic circumstances, and that the true ground is the absence of one or more of the primary elements, which have been shown, or are seen at once, to be necessary to the existence of a contract.

When a contract doesn’t go through, even though the standard procedures have been followed, the reason for the failure is often said to be a mistake, misrepresentation, or fraud. However, I will attempt to demonstrate that these are just dramatic scenarios, and that the real reason is the lack of one or more of the essential elements, which have been established as necessary for a contract to exist.

If a man goes through the form of making a contract with A through B as A's agent, and B is not in fact the agent of A, there is no contract, because there is only one party. The promise offered to A has not been accepted by him, and no consideration has moved from him. In such a case, although there is generally mistake on one side and fraud on the other, it is very clear that no special [309] doctrine need be resorted to, because the primary elements of a contract explained in the last Lecture are not yet present.

If a person goes through the motions of making a contract with A via B, but B isn't actually A's agent, then there's no contract because only one party is involved. A hasn't accepted the promise offered to them, and no consideration has come from A. In this situation, while there’s usually a mistake on one side and fraud on the other, it’s clear that no special [309] doctrine is needed, because the essential elements of a contract discussed in the last lecture aren’t present yet.

Take next a different case. The defendant agreed to buy, and the plaintiff agreed to sell, a cargo of cotton, "to arrive ex Peerless from Bombay." There were two such vessels sailing from Bombay, one in October, the other in December. The plaintiff meant the latter, the defendant the former. It was held that the defendant was not bound to accept the cotton. /1/ It is commonly said that such a contract is void, because of mutual mistake as to the subject-matter, and because therefore the parties did not consent to the same thing. But this way of putting it seems to me misleading. The law has nothing to do with the actual state of the parties' minds. In contract, as elsewhere, it must go by externals, and judge parties by their conduct. If there had been but one "Peerless," and the defendant had said "Peerless" by mistake, meaning "Peri," he would have been bound. The true ground of the decision was not that each party meant a different thing from the other, as is implied by the explanation which has been mentioned, but that each said a different thing. The plaintiff offered one thing, the defendant expressed his assent to another.

Consider a different situation. The defendant agreed to buy, and the plaintiff agreed to sell, a shipment of cotton, "to arrive ex Peerless from Bombay." There were two ships named Peerless departing from Bombay, one in October and the other in December. The plaintiff meant the one in December, while the defendant was thinking of the one in October. It was ruled that the defendant was not obligated to accept the cotton. It is often stated that the contract is void due to a mutual misunderstanding about the subject, which means the parties didn’t agree on the same thing. However, I think this description is misleading. The law doesn't concern itself with the actual thoughts of the parties involved. In contracts, as in other areas, it relies on external factors and judges parties based on their actions. If there had been only one "Peerless," and the defendant mistakenly referred to it as "Peerless," intending to mean "Peri," he would have been bound. The real reason for the decision was not that both parties meant something different, as is suggested by the prior explanation, but that they each referred to different things. The plaintiff offered one thing, while the defendant agreed to another.

A proper name, when used in business or in pleading, /2/ means one individual thing, and no other, as every one knows, and therefore one to whom such a name is used must find out at his peril what the object designated is. If there are no circumstances which make the use deceptive on either side, each is entitled to insist on the [310] meaning favorable to him for the word as used by him, and neither is entitled to insist on that meaning for the word as used by the other. So far from mistake having been the ground of decision, as mistake, its only bearing, as it seems to me, was to establish that neither party knew that he was understood by the other to use the word "Peerless "in the sense which the latter gave to it. In that event there would perhaps have been a binding contract, because, if a man uses a word to which he knows the other party attaches, and understands him to attach, a certain meaning, he may be held to that meaning, and not be allowed to give it any other. /1/

A proper name, when used in business or legal matters, means one specific thing and nothing else, as everyone knows. Therefore, whoever uses that name must figure out, at their own risk, what the object referred to is. If there are no circumstances that make the use misleading for either party, each one can insist on the [310] meaning that benefits them for the word as they are using it, and neither can demand that the other follow their interpretation. Mistake was not the basis for the decision; rather, it simply showed that neither party realized the other understood the word "Peerless" in the sense that the latter assigned to it. In that case, there might have been a binding contract because if someone uses a word that they know the other party associates with a specific meaning, they can be held to that meaning and cannot change it.

Next, suppose a case in which the offer and acceptance do not differ, and in which both parties have used the same words in the same sense. Suppose that A agreed to buy, and B agreed to sell, "these barrels of mackerel," and that the barrels in question turn out to contain salt. There is mutual mistake as to the contents of the barrels, and no fraud on either side. I suppose the contract would be void. /2/

Next, let's consider a situation where the offer and acceptance are the same and both parties have used the same words with the same meaning. Imagine that A agreed to buy, and B agreed to sell, "these barrels of mackerel," but it turns out that the barrels actually contain salt. There is a mutual mistake about the contents of the barrels, and neither side has committed fraud. In this case, I would assume that the contract would be void. /2/

It is commonly said that the failure of the contract in such a case is due to the fact of a difference in kind between the actual subject-matter and that to which the intention of the parties was directed. It is perhaps more instructive to say that the terms of the supposed contract, although seemingly consistent, were contradictory, in matters that went to the root of the bargain. For, by one of the essential terms, the subject-matter of the agreement was the contents of certain barrels, and nothing else, and, by another equally important, it was mackerel, and nothing else; [311] while, as a matter of fact, it could not be both, because the contents of the barrels were salt. As neither term could be left out without forcing on the parties a contract which they did not make, it follows that A cannot be required to accept, nor B to deliver either these barrels of salt, or other barrels of mackerel; and without omitting one term, the promise is meaningless.

It’s often said that the failure of the contract in this case is because there’s a fundamental difference between what the actual subject is and what the parties intended. It might be more helpful to point out that the supposed contract’s terms, while appearing consistent, were actually contradictory in ways that went to the heart of the agreement. One of the essential terms specified that the subject of the agreement was the contents of certain barrels and nothing else, while another equally important term stated it was mackerel and nothing else; [311] but, in reality, it couldn’t be both because the barrels contained salt. Since neither term could be removed without imposing a contract on the parties that they didn’t agree to, it follows that A can’t be required to accept, nor B to deliver either these barrels of salt or other barrels of mackerel; and without excluding one term, the promise is pointless.

If there had been fraud on the seller's part, or if he had known what the barrels really contained, the buyer might have had a right to insist on delivery of the inferior article. Fraud would perhaps have made the contract valid at his option. Because, when a man qualifies sensible words with others which he knows, on secret grounds, are insensible when so applied, he may fairly be taken to authorize his promisee to insist on the possible part of his promise being performed, if the promisee is willing to forego the rest.

If the seller had been dishonest or if he knew what the barrels actually contained, the buyer might have been justified in demanding delivery of the inferior product. Fraud might have made the contract valid at the buyer's discretion. When someone uses sensible words but combines them with others that he secretly knows don't make sense in that context, he can reasonably be understood to allow the person he's making the promise to insist on the feasible part of that promise being fulfilled, provided that the promisee is willing to give up the rest.

Take one more illustration like the last case. A policy of insurance is issued on a certain building described in the policy as a machine-shop. In fact the building is not a machine-shop, but an organ factory, which is a greater risk. The contract is void, not because of any misrepresentation, but, as before, because two of its essential terms are repugnant, and their union is insensible. /1/

Take one more example like the last case. An insurance policy is issued on a building described in the policy as a machine shop. In reality, the building is not a machine shop, but an organ factory, which is a greater risk. The contract is void, not due to any misrepresentation, but, as before, because two of its essential terms are contradictory, and their combination is unreasonable. /1/

Of course the principle of repugnancy last explained might be stretched to apply to any inconsistency between the different terms of a contract. It might be said, for instance, that if a piece of gold is sold as eighteen-carat gold, and it is in fact not so pure, or if a cow is sold as yielding an average of twelve quarts of milk a day, and in fact she yields only six quarts, there is no logical difference, [312] according to the explanation which has just been offered, between those cases and that of the barrel of salt sold for mackerel. Yet those bargains would not be void. At the most, they would only be voidable, if the buyer chose to throw them up.

Of course, the principle of repugnancy just explained could be applied to any inconsistency between different terms of a contract. For example, if a piece of gold is sold as eighteen-carat gold but isn’t really that pure, or if a cow is sold claiming she produces an average of twelve quarts of milk a day when she only gives six quarts, there’s no logical difference, according to the explanation given, between these cases and that of the barrel of salt sold as mackerel. However, those deals wouldn't be void. At most, they would only be voidable if the buyer decided to back out.

The distinctions of the law are founded on experience, not on logic. It therefore does not make the dealings of men dependent on a mathematical accuracy. Whatever is promised, a man has a right to be paid for, if it is not given; but it does not follow that the absence of some insignificant detail will authorize him to throw up the contract, still less that it will prevent the formation of a contract, which is the matter now under consideration. The repugnant terms must both be very important,—so important that the court thinks that, if either is omitted, the contract would be different in substance from that which the words of the parties seemed to express.

The differences in the law are based on real-life experiences, not on strict logic. This means that people's interactions aren't supposed to rely on mathematical precision. If someone makes a promise, they have the right to be compensated if it isn't fulfilled. However, it doesn't mean that the lack of a minor detail allows them to cancel the contract; even more so, it doesn't stop the contract from being formed, which is what we're discussing now. The conflicting terms must both be quite significant—so significant that the court believes if either is left out, the contract would be fundamentally different from what the parties intended to express.

A term which refers directly to an identification by the senses has always this degree of importance. If a promise is made to sell this cow, or this mackerel, to this man, whatever else may be stricken from the contract, it can never be enforced except touching this object and by this man. If this barrel of salt is fraudulently sold for a barrel of mackerel, the buyer may perhaps elect to take this barrel of salt if he chooses, but he cannot elect to take another barrel of mackerel. If the seller is introduced by the name B, and the buyer supposes him to be another person of the same name, and under that impression delivers his written promise to buy of B, the B to whom the writing is delivered is the contractee, if any one is, and, notwithstanding what has been said of the use of proper names, I should suppose [313] a contract would be made. /1/ For it is further to be said that, so far as by one of the terms of a contract the thing promised or the promisee is identified by sight and hearing, that term so far preponderates over all others that it is very rare for the failure of any other element of description to prevent the making of a contract. /2/ The most obvious of seeming exceptions is where the object not in fact so identified, but only its covering or wrapper.

A term that directly refers to something identifiable by the senses has always carried this level of importance. If someone promises to sell this cow, or this mackerel, to this person, no matter what else is removed from the contract, it can only be enforced regarding this specific item and this specific person. If this barrel of salt is fraudulently sold as a barrel of mackerel, the buyer might choose to take this barrel of salt if they want, but they can’t choose to take another barrel of mackerel. If the seller is introduced by the name B, and the buyer mistakenly thinks he is a different person with the same name, and based on that misunderstanding delivers a written promise to buy from B, then the B to whom the writing is delivered is the one in the contract, if anyone is, and despite what has been discussed about the use of proper names, I would think a contract would be established. /1/ Additionally, it should be noted that as far as one of the terms of a contract identifies the promised item or the person being promised to by sight and sound, that term takes precedence over all others so much so that it’s quite rare for the failure of any other describing element to stop a contract from being created. /2/ The clearest seeming exception is when the object is not actually identified, but only its packaging or covering.

Of course the performance of a promise may be made conditional on all the terms stipulated from the other side being complied with, but conditions attaching to performance can never come into consideration until a contract has been made, and so far the question has been touching the existence of a contract in the first instance.

Of course, fulfilling a promise can depend on all the terms agreed upon by the other party being met, but conditions related to fulfillment can't be considered until a contract has been established. Up to this point, the discussion has been about whether a contract exists in the first place.

A different case may be suggested from any yet considered. Instead of a repugnancy between offer and assent which prevents an agreement, or between the terms of an agreement which makes it insensible on its fact, there may be a like repugnancy between a term of the contract and a previous representation of fact which is not expressly made a part of the contract. The representation may have been the chief inducement and very foundation of the bargain. It may be more important than any of the expressed terms, and yet the contract may have [314] been reduced to writing in words which cannot fairly be construed to include it. A vendor may have stated that barrels filled with salt contain mackerel, but the contract may be only for the barrels and their contents. An applicant for insurance may have misstated facts essential to the risk, yet the policy may simply insure a certain building or a certain life. It may be asked whether these contracts are not void also.

A different situation might be proposed that hasn't been considered yet. Instead of a conflict between the offer and acceptance that prevents an agreement, or between the terms of an agreement that makes it nonsensical, there could be a similar conflict between a term of the contract and a previous statement of fact that isn’t explicitly included in the contract. This statement might have been the main reason for the deal and the very basis of the agreement. It could be more significant than any of the written terms, yet the contract might have been drafted in a way that doesn’t clearly include it. For example, a seller might have claimed that barrels filled with salt contain mackerel, but the contract could only cover the barrels and their contents. An insurance applicant might have provided incorrect information that is crucial to the risk, yet the policy could just cover a specific building or a specific life. One might wonder if these contracts are also void.

There might conceivably be cases in which, taking into account the nature of the contract, the words used could be said to embody the representation as a term by construction. For instance, it might be said that the true and well-understood purport of a contract of insurance is not, as the words seem to say, to take the risk of any loss by fire or perils of the sea, however great the risk may be, but to take a risk of a certain magnitude, and no other, which risk has been calculated mathematically from the statements of the party insured. The extent of the risk taken is not specified in the policy, because the old forms and established usage are otherwise, but the meaning is perfectly understood.

There could be situations where, considering the nature of the contract, the wording might be interpreted as including the representation as a term by construction. For example, it could be argued that the actual and commonly understood meaning of an insurance contract is not, as the words suggest, to cover the risk of any loss from fire or sea perils, no matter how significant the risk is, but to cover a specific level of risk that has been calculated mathematically based on the information provided by the insured party. The extent of the covered risk isn't detailed in the policy because of traditional formats and established practices, but the meaning is very clear.

If this reasoning were adopted, there would be an equal repugnancy in the terms of the contract, whether the nature of the risk were written in the policy or fixed by previous description. But, subject to possible exceptions of this kind, it would seem that a contract would be made, and that the most that could be claimed would be a right to rescind. Where parties having power to bind themselves do acts and use words which are fit to create an obligation, I take it that an obligation arises. If there is a mistake as to a fact not mentioned in the contract, it goes only to the motives for making the contract. But a [315] contract is not prevented from being made by the mere fact that one party would not have made it if he had known the truth. In what cases a mistake affecting motives is a ground for avoidance, does not concern this discussion, because the subject now under consideration is when a contract is made, and the question of avoiding or rescinding it presupposes that it has been made.

If this reasoning were accepted, there would be the same issue with the terms of the contract, whether the risk is outlined in the policy or described beforehand. However, aside from possible exceptions, it seems a contract would still be formed, and the most that could be requested would be the right to cancel it. When parties who have the authority to commit themselves act and use words that create an obligation, I believe an obligation is established. If there is a mistake about a fact not included in the contract, it only affects the reasons for making the contract. However, a contract isn't invalidated simply because one party wouldn’t have entered into it had they known the truth. The question of when a mistake regarding motives can be a reason to void the contract isn’t relevant to this discussion, because we are currently considering when a contract is formed, and the matter of canceling or voiding it assumes that a contract has already been created.

I think that it may now be assumed that, when fraud, misrepresentation, or mistake is said to make a contract void, there is no new principle which comes in to set aside an otherwise perfect obligation, but that in every such case there is wanting one or more of the first elements which were explained in the foregoing Lecture. Either there is no second party, or the two parties say different things, or essential terms seemingly consistent are really inconsistent as used.

I think we can now assume that when fraud, misrepresentation, or mistake is said to make a contract void, there's no new principle introduced to invalidate an otherwise valid obligation. Instead, in every case like this, one or more of the initial elements explained in the previous lecture is missing. Either there isn't a second party, or the two parties are saying different things, or essential terms that seem consistent are actually inconsistent in their usage.

When a contract is said to be voidable, it is assumed that a contract has been made, but that it is subject to being unmade at the election of one party. This must be because of the breach of some condition attached to its existence either expressly or by implication.

When a contract is called voidable, it means that a contract has been created, but one party has the option to cancel it. This is usually due to a violation of some condition tied to its existence, either stated directly or implied.

If a condition is attached to the contract's coming into being, there is as yet no contract. Either party may withdraw, at will, until the condition is determined. There is no obligation, although there may be an offer or a promise, and hence there is no relation between the parties which requires discussion here. But some conditions seemingly arising out of a contract already made are conditions of this sort. Such is always the case if the condition of a promise lies within the control of the promisor's own will. For instance, a promise to pay for clothes if made to the customer's satisfaction, has been held in Massachusetts to [316] make the promisor his own final judge. /1/ So interpreted, it appears to me to be no contract at all, until the promisor's satisfaction is expressed. His promise is only to pay if he sees fit, and such a promise cannot be made a contract because it cannot impose any obligation. /2/ If the promise were construed to mean that the clothes should be paid for provided they were such as ought to satisfy the promisor, /3/ and thus to make the jury the arbiter, there would be a contract, because the promisor gives up control over the event, but it would be subject to a condition in the sense of the present analysis.

If there’s a condition tied to the creation of the contract, then there isn’t a contract yet. Either party can back out at any time until the condition is settled. There’s no obligation, even though there might be an offer or a promise, so there’s no relationship between the parties that needs discussion here. However, some conditions that seem to come from an already established contract are of this type. This is always true if the condition of a promise is within the control of the promisor’s own will. For example, a promise to pay for clothes if they meet the customer's satisfaction has been interpreted in Massachusetts to [316] make the promisor the final judge. /1/ Under this interpretation, it seems to me that there’s no contract at all until the promisor expresses satisfaction. His promise is merely to pay if he chooses to, and such a promise can’t form a contract because it doesn’t impose any obligation. /2/ If the promise were understood to mean that the clothes should be paid for as long as they are satisfactory to the promisor, /3/ and thus make the jury the decision-maker, there would be a contract because the promisor gives up control over the outcome, but it would still be dependent on a condition in the sense of this analysis.

The conditions which a contract may contain have been divided by theorists into conditions precedent and conditions subsequent. The distinction has even been pronounced of great importance. It must be admitted that, if the course of pleading be taken as a test, it is so. In some cases, the plaintiff has to state that a condition has been performed in order to put the defendant to his answer; in others, it is left to the defendant to set up that a condition has been broken.

The conditions that a contract can include have been categorized by scholars into conditions precedent and conditions subsequent. This distinction has been considered very important. It's true that, if we use the way legal arguments are presented as a measure, it holds significance. In some situations, the plaintiff must assert that a condition has been met to require the defendant to respond; in other cases, it's up to the defendant to claim that a condition has been violated.

In one sense, all conditions are subsequent; in another, all are precedent. All are subsequent to the first stage of the obligation. /4/ Take, for instance, the case of a promise to pay for work if done to the satisfaction of an architect. The condition is a clear case of what is called a condition precedent. There can be no duty to pay until the architect is satisfied. But there can be a [317] contract before that moment, because the determination whether the promisor shall pay or not is no longer within his control. Hence the condition is subsequent to the existence of the obligation.

In one way, all conditions come after; in another, all come before. All come after the initial stage of the obligation. /4/ For example, consider a promise to pay for work if it meets the architect's satisfaction. This condition is a clear case of what's known as a condition precedent. There’s no obligation to pay until the architect is satisfied. However, a contract can exist before that point, because whether the promisor has to pay or not is no longer in their control. Therefore, the condition comes after the obligation exists.

On the other hand, every condition subsequent is precedent to the incidence of the burden of the law. If we look at the law as it would be regarded by one who had no scruples against doing anything which he could do without incurring legal consequences, it is obvious that the main consequence attached by the law to a contract is a greater or less possibility of having to pay money. The only question from the purely legal point of view is whether the promisor will be compelled to pay. And the important moment is that at which that point is settled. All conditions are precedent to that.

On the other hand, every condition that follows comes before the burden of the law takes effect. If we consider the law from the perspective of someone who has no qualms about doing anything they can without facing legal consequences, it's clear that the main impact of a contract under the law is the likelihood of having to pay money. The only question from a strictly legal standpoint is whether the person making the promise will be forced to pay. The crucial moment is when that decision is made. All conditions come before that.

But all conditions are precedent, not only in this extreme sense, but also to the existence of the plaintiff's cause of action. As strong a case as can be put is that of a policy of insurance conditioned to be void if not sued upon within one year from a failure to pay as agreed. The condition does not come into play until a loss has occurred, the duty to pay has been neglected, and a cause of action has arisen. Nevertheless, it is precedent to the plaintiff's cause of action. When a man sues, the question is not whether he has had a cause of action in the past, but whether he has one then. He has not one then, unless the year is still running. If it were left for the defendant to set up the lapse of the year, that would be due to the circumstance that the order of pleading does not require a plaintiff to meet all possible defences, and to set out a case unanswerable except by denial. The point at which the law calls on the defendant for an answer varies [318] in different cases. Sometimes it would seem to be governed simply by convenience of proof, requiring the party who has the affirmative to plead and prove it. Sometimes there seems to be a reference to the usual course of events, and matters belong to the defence because they are only exceptionally true.

But all conditions are necessary, not only in this extreme sense but also for the existence of the plaintiff's case. A strong example is an insurance policy that becomes void if not claimed within a year of a failure to pay as agreed. The condition doesn’t apply until a loss occurs, the obligation to pay is ignored, and a cause of action arises. However, it is necessary for the plaintiff’s case. When someone sues, the issue isn’t whether they had a cause of action in the past but whether they have one at that moment. They don’t have one unless the year is still ongoing. If it were up to the defendant to bring up the year’s lapse, it would be because the order of pleading doesn’t require a plaintiff to address every possible defense or to present a case that can only be countered with a denial. The moment the law expects the defendant to respond varies [318] in different situations. Sometimes it appears to be determined simply by the convenience of proof, asking the party with the affirmative to plead and prove it. Other times, it seems to refer to the usual course of events, where matters belong to the defense because they are only true in exceptional cases.

The most logical distinction would be between conditions which must be satisfied before a promise can be broken, and those which, like the last, discharge the liability after a breach has occurred. /1/ But this is of the slightest possible importance, and it may be doubted whether another case like the last could be found.

The most reasonable distinction would be between conditions that need to be met before a promise can be broken, and those that, like the last one, release the responsibility after a breach has happened. /1/ But this is of minimal importance, and it’s questionable whether another situation like the last one could be found.

It is much more important to mark the distinction between a stipulation which only has the effect of confining a promise to certain cases, and a condition properly so called. Every condition, it is true, has this effect upon the promise to which it is attached, so that, whatever the rule of pleading may be, /2/ a promise is as truly kept and performed by doing nothing where the condition of the stipulated act has been broken, as it would have been by doing the act if the condition had been fulfilled. But if this were all, every clause in a contract which showed what the promisor did not promise would be a condition, and the word would be worse than useless. The characteristic feature is quite different.

It's really important to distinguish between a stipulation that limits a promise to specific situations and a true condition. Every condition does indeed limit the promise it relates to, so regardless of the rules of pleading, a promise is just as effectively kept and fulfilled by doing nothing when the condition has been broken, as it would have been by taking action if the condition had been met. However, if that were the whole story, then every clause in a contract that indicates what the promisor did not promise would simply be a condition, making the term almost meaningless. The key difference is something else entirely.

A condition properly so called is an event, the happening of which authorizes the person in whose favor the condition is reserved to treat the contract as if it had not been made,—to avoid it, as is commonly said,—that is, to insist on both parties being restored to the position in [319] which they stood before the contract was made. When a condition operates as such, it lets in an outside force to destroy the existing state of things. For although its existence is due to consent of parties, its operation depends on the choice of one of them. When a condition is broken, the person entitled to insist on it may do so if he chooses; but he may, if he prefers, elect to keep the contract on foot. He gets his right to avoid it from the agreement, but the avoidance comes from him.

A condition, as it's properly defined, is an event that allows the person benefiting from the condition to treat the contract as if it never existed—to cancel it, as is often said—that is, to require both parties to be returned to the position in [319] where they were before the contract was made. When a condition functions this way, it introduces an external element that disrupts the current situation. Although the condition arises from the agreement of the parties, its effect relies on the choice of one party. When a condition is violated, the person entitled to enforce it can choose to do so, but they can also decide to uphold the contract if they prefer. Their right to cancel comes from the agreement, but the actual cancellation is up to them.

Hence it is important to distinguish those stipulations which have this extreme effect from those which only interpret the extent of a promise, or define the events to which it applies. And as it has just been shown that a condition need not be insisted on as such, we must further distinguish between its operation by way of avoidance, which is peculiar to it, and its incidental working by way of interpretation and definition, in common with other clauses not conditions.

Therefore, it's important to separate those stipulations that have this significant effect from those that merely clarify the scope of a promise or specify the events it involves. And since it has just been demonstrated that a condition doesn’t always have to be treated as one, we also need to differentiate between its function in avoiding obligations, which is unique to it, and its incidental effect of clarifying and defining, which is shared with other clauses that are not conditions.

This is best illustrated by taking a bilateral contract between A and B, where A's undertaking is conditional on B's doing what he promises to do, and where, after A has got a certain distance in his task, B breaks his half of the bargain. For instance, A is employed as a clerk by B, and is wrongfully dismissed in the middle of a quarter. In favor of A, the contract is conditional on B's keeping his agreement to employ him. Whether A insists on the condition or not, he is not bound to do any more. /1/ So far, the condition works simply by way of definition. It establishes that A has not promised to act in the case which has happened. But besides this, for which a condition [320] was not necessary, A may take his choice between two courses. In the first place, he may elect to avoid the contract. In that case the parties stand as if no contract had been made, and A, having done work for B which was understood not to be gratuitous, and for which no rate of compensation has been fixed, can recover what the jury think his services were reasonably worth. The contract no longer determines the quid pro quo. But as an alternative course A may stand by the contract if he prefers to do so, and sue B for breaking it. In that case he can recover as part of his damages pay at the contract rate for what he had done, as well as compensation for his loss of opportunity to finish it. But the points which are material for the present discussion are, that these two remedies are mutually exclusive, /1/ one supposing the contract to be relied on, the other that it is set aside, but that A's stopping work and doing no more after B's breach is equally consistent with either choice, and has in fact nothing to do with the matter.

This is best illustrated by considering a bilateral contract between A and B, where A's obligations depend on B doing what he promised. If A completes part of his task and then B breaks his side of the agreement, for example, if A is hired as a clerk by B and gets wrongfully dismissed in the middle of a quarter, the contract relies on B keeping his promise to employ A. Whether A insists on this condition or not, he is not required to continue working. So far, the condition serves simply as a definition. It clarifies that A hasn’t promised to act in the situation that has occurred. Additionally, A has two options. First, he can choose to void the contract. In this case, it's as if no contract existed, and A, having completed work for B that wasn't meant to be free, can recover what the jury believes his services were worth. The contract no longer dictates the exchange rate. Alternatively, A can choose to uphold the contract and sue B for the breach. In this case, he can recover damages based on the contract rate for the work he completed, along with compensation for his lost opportunity to finish it. However, the critical points for this discussion are that these two options are mutually exclusive—one assumes the contract is still in effect, while the other assumes it is canceled. A’s decision to stop working after B’s breach is consistent with either choice and isn't related to the matter at hand.

One word should be added to avoid misapprehension. When it is said that A has done all that he promised to do in the case which has happened, it is not meant that he is necessarily entitled to the same compensation as if he had done the larger amount of work. B's promise in the case supposed was to pay so much a quarter for services; and although the consideration of the promise was the promise by A to perform them, the scope of it was limited to the case of their being performed in fact. Hence A could not simply wait till the end of his term, and then recover the full amount which he would have had if the employment had continued. Nor is he any more entitled to do so from [321] the fact that it was B's fault that the services were not rendered. B's answer to any such claim is perfect. He is only liable upon a promise, and he in his turn only promised to pay in a case which has not happened. He did promise to employ, however, and for not doing that he is liable in damages.

One word should be added to avoid misunderstanding. When it says that A has done everything he promised to do in the situation that occurred, it doesn't mean that he's automatically entitled to the same payment as if he had completed a larger amount of work. B's promise in the hypothetical situation was to pay a certain amount per quarter for services; and while the basis of the promise was A's agreement to perform those services, the scope of it was limited to the actual performance. Therefore, A couldn't just wait until the end of his term and then claim the full amount he would have received if the employment had continued. Nor is he any more entitled to do so just because it was B's fault that the services weren't provided. B's response to any such claim is valid. He is only liable under the promise, and he, in turn, only promised to pay in a situation that didn’t occur. However, he did promise to employ, and for failing to do that, he is liable for damages.

One or two more illustrations will be useful. A promises to deliver, and B promises to accept and pay for, certain goods at a certain time and place. When the time comes, neither party is on hand. Neither would be liable to an action, and, according to what has been said, each has done all that he promised to do in the event which has happened, to wit, nothing. It might be objected that, if A has done all that he is bound to do, he ought to be able to sue B, since performance or readiness to perform was all that was necessary to give him that right, and conversely the same might be said of B. On the other hand, considering either B or A as defendant, the same facts would be a complete defence. The puzzle is largely one of words.

A couple more examples will help clarify. A promises to deliver, and B promises to accept and pay for, certain goods at a specific time and place. When the time arrives, neither party shows up. Neither would be liable for any legal action, and as has been discussed, each has fulfilled their obligations given the situation, which is to say, they did nothing. It could be argued that if A has done everything required of him, he should be able to sue B, since simply being prepared to perform was all he needed for that right, and the same could be said for B. However, if we consider either B or A as the defendant, the same facts would serve as a complete defense. The confusion mainly comes down to semantics.

A and B have, it is true, each performed all that they promised to do at the present stage, because they each only promised to act in the event of the other being ready and willing to act at the same time. But the readiness and willingness, although not necessary to the performance of either promise, and therefore not a duty, was necessary in order to present a case to which the promise of action on the other side would apply. Hence, although A and B have each performed their own promise, they have not performed the condition to their right of demanding more from the other side. The performance of that condition is purely optional until one side has brought it within the [322] scope of the other's undertaking by performing it himself. But it is performance in the latter sense, that is, the satisfying of all conditions, as well as the keeping of his own promises, which is necessary to give A or B a right of action.

A and B have each done what they agreed to do at this point, because they only promised to act if the other was also ready and willing to act at the same time. However, while being ready and willing isn't required to fulfill either promise, it is essential to create a situation where one person's promise can apply to the actions of the other. Therefore, although A and B have both kept their own promises, they haven't met the condition that would allow them to ask for more from each other. Fulfilling that condition is entirely optional until one side brings it into the other person's promise by performing it themselves. It's this kind of performance—fulfilling all conditions and keeping their own promises—that is needed for A or B to have the right to take action.

Conditions may be created by the very words of a contract. Of such cases there is nothing to be said, for parties may agree to what they choose. But they may also be held to arise by construction, where no provision is made in terms for rescinding or avoiding the contract in any case. The nature of the conditions which the law thus reads in needs explanation. It may be said, in a general way, that they are directed to the existence of the manifest grounds for making the bargain on the side of the rescinding party, or the accomplishment of its manifest objects. But that is not enough. Generally speaking, the disappointment must be caused by the wrong-doing of the person on the other side; and the most obvious cases of such wrong-doing are fraud and misrepresentation, or failure to perform his own part of the contract.

Conditions can be established through the specific language of a contract. In such instances, there's nothing more to discuss, as parties can agree to whatever they wish. However, conditions can also come about through interpretation, especially when there’s no specific clause for canceling or avoiding the contract. The nature of the conditions that the law infers requires some explanation. Generally, these conditions relate to the clear reasons behind making the agreement for the party seeking to cancel it, or to achieving their obvious goals. But that’s not sufficient. Typically, the disappointment must stem from wrongdoing by the other party; and the most common forms of such wrongdoing include fraud and misrepresentation, or failing to fulfill their own obligations under the contract.

Fraud and misrepresentation thus need to be considered once more in this connection. I take the latter first. In dealing with it the first question which arises is whether the representation is, or is not, part of the contract. If the contract is in writing and the representation is set out on the face of the paper, it may be material or immaterial, but the effect of its untruth will be determined on much the same principles as govern the failure to perform a promise on the same side. If the contract is made by word of mouth, there may be a large latitude in connecting words of representation with later words of promise; but when they are determined to be a part of the contract, [323] the same principles apply as if the whole were in writing.

Fraud and misrepresentation need to be reconsidered in this context. I’ll address misrepresentation first. When looking at it, the first question is whether the representation is part of the contract or not. If the contract is written and the representation is clearly stated on the document, it can be either significant or insignificant, but the impact of its falsehood will be assessed based on similar principles that apply to failing to fulfill a promise in the same context. If the contract is made verbally, there can be considerable flexibility in linking the words of representation with subsequent promises; however, once they're deemed part of the contract, the same principles apply as if everything were in writing.

The question now before us is the effect of a misrepresentation which leads to, but is not a part of, the contract. Suppose that the contract is in writing, but does not contain it, does such a previous misrepresentation authorize rescission in any case? and if so, does it in any case except where it goes to the height of fraud? The promisor might say, It does not matter to me whether you knew that your representation was false or not; the only thing I am concerned with is its truth. If it is untrue, I suffer equally whether you knew it to be so or not. But it has been shown, in an earlier Lecture, that the law does not go on the principle that a man is answerable for all the consequences of all his acts. An act is indifferent in itself. It receives its character from the concomitant facts known to the actor at the time. If a man states a thing reasonably believing that he is speaking from knowledge, it is contrary to the analogies of the law to throw the peril of the truth upon him unless he agrees to assume that peril, and he did not do so in the case supposed, as the representation was not made part of the contract.

The question we have to consider now is the impact of a misrepresentation that leads to, but isn’t included in, the contract. Let’s say the contract is written, but it doesn’t include the misrepresentation. Does that earlier misrepresentation justify canceling the contract in any situation? And if so, does it apply in any case except when it’s outright fraud? The person making the promise might argue, "I don’t care whether you knew your statement was false or not; what matters to me is whether it’s true. If it’s not true, I’m affected the same way regardless of your awareness." However, as was discussed in an earlier lecture, the law doesn’t operate on the idea that someone is accountable for all the outcomes of their actions. An action is neutral by itself. It gets its meaning from the accompanying facts known to the person taking the action at that time. If someone states something while reasonably believing they are speaking from knowledge, it goes against the legal principles to place the risk of the truth on them unless they agree to take that risk, and in this case, they didn’t, as the misrepresentation wasn’t included in the contract.

It is very different when there is fraud. Fraud may as well lead to the making of a contract by a statement outside the contract as by one contained in it. But the law would hold the contract not less conditional on good faith in one case than in the other.

It’s quite different when fraud is involved. Fraud can lead to a contract being formed by a statement outside of the contract just as easily as by one that’s included in it. However, the law would still regard the contract as no less dependent on good faith in either case.

To illustrate, we may take a somewhat extreme case. A says to B, I have not opened these barrels myself, but they contain No. 1 mackerel: I paid so much for them to so and so, naming a well-known dealer. Afterwards A writes B, I will sell the barrels which you saw, and their [324] contents, for so much; and B accepts. The barrels turn out to contain salt. I suppose the contract would be binding if the statements touching the contents were honest, and voidable if they were fraudulent.

To illustrate, let's consider a somewhat extreme case. A tells B, "I haven’t opened these barrels myself, but they contain No. 1 mackerel. I paid this amount to a well-known dealer." Later, A writes to B, "I will sell you the barrels you saw and their contents for this price," and B agrees. It turns out the barrels contain salt. I think the contract would be binding if A’s statements about the contents were honest, but it would be voidable if they were misleading.

Fraudulent representations outside a contract can never, it would seem, go to anything except the motives for making it. If outside the contract, they cannot often affect its interpretation. A promise in certain words has a definite meaning, which the promisor is presumed to understand. If A says to B, I promise you to buy this barrel and its contents, his words designate a person and thing identified by the senses, and they signify nothing more. There is no repugnancy, and if that person is ready to deliver that thing, the purchaser cannot say that any term in the contract itself is not complied with. He may have been fraudulently induced to believe that B was another B, and that the barrel contained mackerel; but however much his belief on those points may have affected his willingness to make the promise, it would be somewhat extravagant to give his words a different meaning on that account. "You" means the person before the speaker, whatever his name, and "contents" applies to salt, as well as to mackerel.

Fraudulent statements made outside of a contract seem to only relate to the reasons behind making the contract. If these statements are outside the contract, they usually don't affect how the contract is interpreted. A promise made with specific words has a clear meaning that the person making the promise is expected to understand. If A says to B, "I promise to buy this barrel and its contents," his words clearly identify a person and a thing that can be perceived by the senses, and they mean nothing more. There's no contradiction, and if that person is willing to deliver that item, the buyer can’t argue that any term in the contract hasn't been met. A might have been misled into believing that B was a different B and that the barrel contained mackerel; however, no matter how much those beliefs influenced his willingness to make the promise, it would be unreasonable to interpret his words differently based on that. "You" refers to the person in front of the speaker, regardless of their name, and "contents" can apply to both salt and mackerel.

It is no doubt only by reason of a condition construed into the contract that fraud is a ground of rescission. Parties could agree, if they chose, that a contract should be binding without regard to truth or falsehood outside of it on either part.

It’s definitely because of a condition included in the contract that fraud is a reason for cancellation. The parties could decide, if they wanted, that a contract should be binding regardless of any truth or lies from either side.

But, as has been said before in these Lectures, although the law starts from the distinctions and uses the language of morality, it necessarily ends in external standards not dependent on the actual consciousness of the individual. [325] So it has happened with fraud. If a man makes a representation, knowing facts which by the average standard of the community are sufficient to give him warning that it is probably untrue, and it is untrue, he is guilty of fraud in theory of law whether he believes his statement or not. The courts of Massachusetts, at least, go much further. They seem to hold that any material statement made by a man as of his own knowledge, or in such a way as fairly to be understood as made of his own knowledge, is fraudulent if untrue, irrespective of the reasons he may have had for believing it and for believing that he knew it. /1/ It is clear, therefore, that a representation may be morally innocent, and yet fraudulent in theory of law. Indeed, the Massachusetts rule seems to stop little short of the principle laid down by the English courts of equity, which has been criticised in an earlier Lecture, /2/ since most positive affirmations of facts would at least warrant a jury in finding that they were reasonably understood to be made as of the party's own knowledge, and might therefore warrant a rescission if they turned out to be untrue. The moral phraseology has ceased to be apposite, and an external standard of responsibility has been reached. But the starting-point is nevertheless fraud, and except on the ground of fraud, as defined by law, I do not think that misrepresentations before the contract affect its validity, although they lead directly to its making. But neither the contract nor the implied condition calls for the existence of the facts as to which the false representations were made. They call only for the absence of certain false representations. The condition is not that the promisee shall be a certain other B, or that the contents of the barrel shall be mackerel, [326] but that the promisee has not lied to him about material facts.

But, as mentioned earlier in these Lectures, while the law begins with moral distinctions and terminology, it ultimately relies on external standards that are not tied to an individual's actual awareness. [325] This is true for fraud. If someone makes a statement knowing facts that, according to the community's average standards, should raise alerts that the statement might be false, and the statement is indeed false, they are considered fraudulent under the law, regardless of whether they believe what they said. Courts in Massachusetts, at least, take this even further. They seem to assert that any significant statement made by a person as if they know it to be true, or in such a way that it can reasonably be seen as made from their own knowledge, is fraudulent if it turns out to be false, no matter what reasons they had for believing it was true. /1/ Thus, it’s clear that a statement can be morally innocent yet still be considered fraudulent under the law. In fact, the Massachusetts standard is quite close to the principle laid out by the English courts of equity, which was critiqued in an earlier Lecture, /2/ since most affirmative statements of fact would at least allow a jury to determine that they were reasonably interpreted as being made from the party's own knowledge, and could therefore justify canceling the contract if found untrue. The moral language is no longer relevant, and we’ve reached an external standard of responsibility. However, fraud remains the starting point, and except for the legal definition of fraud, I believe that misrepresentations made before a contract does not affect its validity, even if they directly contribute to its creation. Neither the contract nor the implied condition requires the existence of the facts related to the false statements. They only require that there are no significant false representations. The condition is not that the promisee must be a specific person, or that the contents of the barrel must be mackerel, [326] but that the promisee has not lied to them about important facts.

Then the question arises, How do you determine what facts are material? As the facts are not required by the contract, the only way in which they can be material is that a belief in their being true is likely to have led to the making of the contract.

Then the question comes up, how do you figure out which facts are important? Since the contract doesn’t require the facts, the only way they can be considered important is if believing they are true likely influenced the decision to create the contract.

It is not then true, as it is sometimes said, that the law does not concern itself with the motives for making contracts. On the contrary, the whole scope of fraud outside the contract is the creation of false motives and the removal of true ones. And this consideration will afford a reasonable test of the cases in which fraud will warrant rescission. It is said that a fraudulent representation must be material to have that effect. But how are we to decide whether it is material or not? If the above argument is correct, it must be by an appeal to ordinary experience to decide whether a belief that the fact was as represented would naturally have led to, or a contrary belief would naturally have prevented, the making of the contract.

It's not true, as some people say, that the law ignores the reasons behind making contracts. In fact, the entire concept of fraud outside of the contract revolves around creating false reasons and hiding the true ones. This idea provides a reasonable way to determine when fraud justifies canceling a contract. It's claimed that a fraudulent statement must be significant to have that effect. But how do we figure out if it's significant or not? If the argument above holds true, we should rely on common experience to assess whether believing the fact was as stated would have naturally led to making the contract, or if believing the opposite would have naturally prevented it.

If the belief would not naturally have had such an effect, either in general or under the known circumstances of the particular case, the fraud is immaterial. If a man is induced to contract with another by a fraudulent representation of the latter that he is a great-grandson of Thomas Jefferson, I do not suppose that the contract would be voidable unless the contractee knew that, for special reasons, his lie would tend to bring the contract about.

If the belief wouldn't normally have had such an effect, either in general or given the specific circumstances of the case, the fraud doesn't matter. If someone is persuaded to enter into a contract with another person based on a fraudulent claim that he is a great-grandson of Thomas Jefferson, I doubt the contract would be voidable unless the person making the contract knew that, for specific reasons, his lie would actually lead to the contract being made.

The conditions or grounds for avoiding a contract which have been dealt with thus far are conditions concerning the conduct of the parties outside of the itself. [327] Still confining myself to conditions arising by construction of law,—that is to say, not directly and in terms attached to a promise by the literal meaning of the words in which it is expressed,—I now come to those which concern facts to which the contract does in some way refer.

The reasons for voiding a contract that we've discussed so far involve the behavior of the parties outside of the contract itself. [327] Now, focusing on conditions that arise by legal interpretation—which means not directly related to the specific wording of the promise—I will now address those that pertain to facts that the contract references in some way.

Such conditions may be found in contracts where the promise is only on one side. It has been said that where the contract is unilateral, and its language therefore is all that of the promisor, clauses in his favor will be construed as conditions more readily than the same words in a bilateral contract; indeed, that they must be so construed, because, if they do not create a condition, they do him no good, since ex hypothesi they are not promises by the other party. /1/ How far this ingenious suggestion has had a practical effect on doctrine may perhaps be doubted.

Such conditions can be found in contracts where only one side makes a promise. It's been stated that in a unilateral contract, where all the language comes from the promisor, clauses that benefit him will be interpreted as conditions more easily than the same words in a bilateral contract; in fact, they must be interpreted that way because if they don't create a condition, they don’t help him at all, since hypothetically there are no promises from the other party. /1/ It may be questionable how much this clever idea has influenced actual legal doctrine.

But it will be enough for the purposes of this general survey to deal with bilateral contracts, where there are undertakings on both sides, and where the condition implied in favor of one party is that the other shall make good what he on his part has undertaken.

But for this general overview, it will be sufficient to focus on bilateral contracts, where both sides have commitments, and the condition implied for one party is that the other will fulfill what they have committed to.

The undertakings of a contract may be for the existence of a fact in the present or in the future. They can be promises only in the latter case; but in the former, they be equally essential terms in the bargain.

The obligations of a contract can involve a fact that exists now or will exist later. They can only be promises in the latter situation; however, in the former, they are just as crucial to the agreement.

Here again we come on the law of representations, but in a new phase. Being a part of the contract, it is always possible that their truth should make a condition of the contract wholly irrespective of any question of fraud. And it often is so in fact. It is not, however, every representation embodied in the words used on one side which will [328] make a condition in favor of the other party. Suppose A agrees to sell, and B agrees to buy, "A's seven-year-old sorrel horse Eclipse, now in the possession of B on trial," and in fact the horse is chestnut-colored, not sorrel. I do not suppose that B could refuse to pay for the horse on that ground. If the law were so foolish as to aim at merely formal consistency, it might indeed be said that there was as absolute a repugnancy between the different terms of this contract as in the ease of an agreement to sell certain barrels of mackerel, where the barrels turned out to contain salt. If this view were adopted, there would not be a contract subject to a condition, there would be no contract at all. But in truth there is a contract, and there is not even a condition. As has been said already, it is not every repugnancy that makes a contract void, and it is not every failure in the terms of the counter undertaking that makes it voidable. Here it plainly appears that the buyer knows exactly what he is going to get, and therefore that the mistake of color has no bearing on the bargain. /1/

Here again we encounter the law of representations, but in a new light. Being part of the contract, it’s possible that their truth could make a condition of the contract completely separate from any question of fraud. And often, that’s the case. However, not every representation made in the words used by one side will make a condition in favor of the other party. For example, if A agrees to sell, and B agrees to buy, "A's seven-year-old sorrel horse Eclipse, currently with B on trial," but the horse is actually chestnut-colored and not sorrel, I doubt that B could refuse to pay for the horse based on that. If the law were so misguided as to focus solely on formal consistency, it could be argued that there was as much contradiction between the different terms of this contract as in a situation where someone agreed to sell barrels of mackerel, only for the barrels to contain salt. If this interpretation were accepted, there would be no contract subject to a condition, there simply wouldn’t be a contract at all. But in reality, there is a contract, and there isn't even a condition. As already mentioned, not every contradiction makes a contract void, and not every failure in the terms of the counter agreement makes it voidable. Here it’s clear that the buyer knows exactly what he’s getting, which means that the color mistake has no impact on the deal. /1/

If, on the other hand, a contract contained a representation which was fraudulent, and which misled the party to whom it was made, the contract would be voidable on the same principles as if the representation had been made beforehand. But words of description in a contract are very frequently held to amount to what is sometimes called a warranty, irrespective of fraud. Whether they do so or not is a question to be determined by the court on grounds of common sense, looking to the meaning of the words, the importance in the transaction of the facts [329] which the words convey, and so forth. But when words of description are determined to be a warranty, the meaning of the decision is not merely that the party using them binds himself to answer for their truth, but that their truth is a condition of the contract.

If a contract includes a fraudulent representation that misleads the party it was directed at, the contract can be canceled based on the same principles as if the representation was made beforehand. However, descriptive language in a contract often qualifies as what’s sometimes called a warranty, regardless of fraud. Whether or not this applies is a matter for the court to decide based on common sense, considering the meaning of the words, the importance of the facts they represent, and so on. When descriptive words are deemed to be a warranty, this means that the party who used them not only commits to their accuracy but that their accuracy is a condition of the contract.

For instance, in a leading case /1/ the agreement was that the plaintiff's ship, then in the port of Amsterdam, should, with all possible despatch, proceed direct to Newport, England, and there load a cargo of coals for Hong Kong. At the date of the charter-party the vessel was not in Amsterdam, but she arrived there four days later. The plaintiff had notice that the defendant considered time important. It was held that the presence of the vessel in the port of Amsterdam at the date of the contract was a condition, the breach of which entitled the defendant to refuse to load, and to rescind the contract. If the view were adopted that a condition must be a future event, and that a promise purporting to be conditional on a past or present event is either absolute or no promise at all, it would follow that in this case the defendant had never made a promise. /2/ He had only promised if circumstances existed which did not exist. I have already stated my objections to this way of looking at such cases, /2/ and will only add that the courts, so far as I am aware, do not sanction it, and certainly did not in this instance.

For example, in a key case /1/, the agreement stated that the plaintiff's ship, which was in the port of Amsterdam at the time, should quickly go directly to Newport, England, to load a cargo of coal for Hong Kong. At the time the charter-party was signed, the vessel wasn't in Amsterdam, but it arrived there four days later. The plaintiff was aware that the defendant considered time to be important. It was determined that the ship's presence in the port of Amsterdam at the time of the contract was a condition, and breaching that condition allowed the defendant to refuse to load the cargo and cancel the contract. If one were to take the stance that a condition must be a future event, and that a promise which claims to be conditional on a past or present event is essentially absolute or not a promise at all, it would mean that in this case, the defendant never made a promise. /2/ He only promised if certain circumstances were in place, which they weren't. I have already expressed my objections to this perspective on such cases /2/, and I will only add that, as far as I know, the courts do not support it and certainly did not in this case.

There is another ground for holding the charter-party void and no contract, instead of regarding it as only voidable, which is equally against authority, which nevertheless I have never been able to answer wholly to my satisfaction. In the case put, the representation of the lessor of the vessel [330] concerned the vessel itself, and therefore entered into the description of the thing the lessee agreed to take. I do not quite see why there is not as fatal a repugnancy between the different terms of this contract as was found in that for the sale of the barrels of salt described as containing mackerel. Why is the repugnancy between the two terms,—first, that the thing sold is the contents of these barrels, and, second, that it is mackerel—fatal to the existence of a contract? It is because each of those terms goes to the very root and essence of the contract, /1/—because to compel the buyer to take something answering to one, but not to the other requirement, would be holding him to do a substantially different thing from what he promised, and because a promise to take one and the same thing answering to both requirements is therefore contradictory in a substantial matter. It has been seen that the law does not go on any merely logical ground, and does not hold that every slight repugnancy will make a contract even voidable. But, on the other hand, when the repugnancy is between terms which are both essential, it is fatal to the very existence of the contract. How then do we decide whether a given term is essential? Surely the best way of finding out is by seeing how the parties have dealt with it. For want of any expression on their part we may refer to the speech and dealings of every day, /2/ and say that, if its absence would make the subject-matter a different thing, its presence is essential to the existence of the agreement. But the parties may agree that anything, however trifling, shall be essential, as well [331] as that anything, however important, shall not be; and if that essential is part of the contract description of a specific thing which is also identified by reference to the senses, how can there be a contract in its absence any more than if the thing is in popular speech different in kind from its description? The qualities that make sameness or difference of kind for the purposes of a contract are not determined by Agassiz or Darwin, or by the public at large, but by the will of the parties, which decides that for their purposes the characteristics insisted on are such and such. /1/1 Now, if this be true, what evidence can there be that a certain requirement is essential, that without it the subject-matter will be different in kind from the description, better than that one party has required and the other given a warranty of its presence? Yet the contract description of the specific vessel as now in the port of Amsterdam, although held to be an implied warranty, does not seem to have been regarded as making the contract repugnant and void, but only as giving the defendant the option of avoiding it. /2/ Even an express warranty of quality in sales does not have this effect, and in England, indeed, it does not allow the purchaser to rescind in case of breach. On this last point the law of Massachusetts is different.

There’s another reason to consider the charter-party invalid and not just voidable, which goes against established authority, and I still haven’t been able to fully satisfy myself on it. In the case mentioned, the lessor’s representation about the vessel [330] referred to the vessel itself, and therefore it was part of the description of what the lessee agreed to take. I don't understand why there isn't a similarly fatal contradiction between the different terms of this contract as there was in the sale of barrels of salt described as containing mackerel. Why does the contradiction between the two terms—first, that what’s sold is the contents of these barrels, and second, that it is mackerel—negate the existence of the contract? It’s because each of those terms goes to the very core of the contract, /1/—because forcing the buyer to accept something that meets one term but not the other would mean holding him to do something quite different from what he promised, and because a promise to accept one thing that fulfills both requirements is fundamentally contradictory. It has been shown that the law doesn't simply operate on logical grounds and doesn’t consider every minor contradiction to make a contract voidable. However, when the contradiction is between terms that are both essential, it is detrimental to the very existence of the contract. So how do we determine if a term is essential? The best way to find out is by examining how the parties have treated it. In the absence of any indication from them, we can look at everyday speech and interactions and say that if its absence would change the subject matter significantly, its presence is essential for the agreement to exist. But the parties can agree that anything, no matter how trivial, shall be essential, just as they can agree that something important shall not be; and if that essential part is part of the contract description of a specific item identified through sensory reference, how can there be a contract in its absence just as if the thing is popularly understood to be different from its description? The qualities that determine sameness or difference for the purposes of a contract are not defined by Agassiz or Darwin or by the public, but by the parties' will, which establishes that for their purposes the insisted characteristics are specific. /1/1 Now, if this is true, what better evidence can there be that a certain requirement is essential—meaning that without it the subject matter would be fundamentally different from the description—than that one party explicitly requested it and the other provided a warranty for its presence? Yet, the contract description of the specific vessel currently in the port of Amsterdam, although considered an implied warranty, doesn’t appear to be seen as making the contract contradictory and void, but rather as giving the defendant the choice to avoid it. /2/ Even an express warranty of quality in sales doesn’t have this effect, and in England, it doesn’t even permit the buyer to withdraw in case of a breach. The law in Massachusetts differs on this last point.

The explanation has been offered of the English doctrine with regard to sales, that, when the title has passed, the purchaser has already had some benefit from the contract, and therefore cannot wholly replace the seller in statu quo, as must be done when a contract is rescinded. /3/ This reasoning [332] seems doubtful, even to show that the contract is not voidable, but has no bearing on the argument that it is void. For if the contract is void, the title does not pass.

The explanation of the English doctrine regarding sales states that once the title has transferred, the buyer has already gained some benefit from the contract and therefore cannot completely restore the seller to their original position, as would be required if a contract is canceled. This reasoning seems questionable, even if it indicates that the contract is not voidable, but it does not affect the argument that it is void. Because if the contract is void, the title does not transfer.

It might be said that there is no repugnancy in the charterer's promise, because he only promises to load a certain ship, and that the words "now in the port of Amsterdam" are merely matter of history when the time for loading comes, and no part of the description of the vessel which he promised to load. But the moment those words are decided to be essential they become part of the description, and the promise is to load a certain vessel which is named the Martaban, and which was in the port of Amsterdam at the date of the contract. So interpreted, it is repugnant.

It could be argued that there’s no conflict in the charterer's promise, because he’s only agreeing to load a specific ship, and the phrase "now in the port of Amsterdam" is just a historical detail when the loading time arrives, not part of the description of the vessel he promised to load. However, once those words are deemed essential, they become part of the description, making the promise to load a specific vessel known as the Martaban, which was in the port of Amsterdam at the time the contract was signed. Under that interpretation, it is indeed conflicting.

Probably the true solution is to be found in practical considerations. At any rate, the fact is that the law has established three degrees in the effect of repugnancy. If one of the repugnant terms is wholly insignificant, it is simply disregarded, or at most will only found a claim for damages. The law would be loath to hold a contract void for repugnancy in present terms, when if the same terms were only promised a failure of one of them would not warrant a refusal to perform on the other side. If, on the other hand, both are of the extremest importance, so that to enforce the rest of the promise or bargain without one of them would not merely deprive one party of a stipulated incident, but would force a substantially different bargain on him, the promise will be void. There is an intermediate class of cases where it is left to the disappointed party to decide. But as the lines between the three are of this vague kind, it is not surprising that they have been differently drawn in different jurisdictions.

The real answer probably lies in practical considerations. In any case, the law recognizes three levels of repugnancy. If one of the conflicting terms is completely meaningless, it's simply ignored, or at most, it might lead to a claim for damages. The law is reluctant to declare a contract void due to repugnancy in its current language, especially when, if the same terms were only promised, a failure to meet one wouldn't justify refusing to perform the other. On the flip side, if both terms are extremely important, enforcing the rest of the promise or agreement without one of them wouldn’t just deprive one party of a specified benefit, but would impose a significantly different deal on them, making the promise void. There's also a middle ground where it's up to the disappointed party to decide. However, since the distinctions between the three are rather vague, it's not surprising that different jurisdictions have interpreted them in various ways.

[333] The examples which have been given of undertakings for a present state of facts have been confined to those touching the present condition of the subject-matter of the contract. Of course there is no such limit to the scope of their employment. A contract may warrant the existence of other facts as well, and examples of this kind probably might be found or imagined where it would be clear that the only effect of the warranty was to attach a condition to the contract, in favor of the other side, and where the question would be avoided whether there was not something more than a condition,—a repugnancy which prevented the formation of any contract at all. But the preceding illustrations are enough for the present purpose.

[333] The examples provided of commitments related to a current state of facts have been limited to those concerning the existing condition of the contract's subject matter. However, there are no restrictions on how they can be used. A contract can also guarantee the existence of other facts, and we could likely find or imagine examples where it’s evident that the only purpose of the warranty is to impose a condition on the contract for the benefit of the other party, avoiding the question of whether there’s something beyond just a condition—such as a contradiction that would make the formation of any contract impossible. But the previous examples are sufficient for now.

We may now pass from undertakings that certain facts are true at the time of making the contract, to undertakings that certain facts shall be true at some later time,—that is, to promises properly so called. The question is when performance of the promise on one side is a condition to the obligation of the contract on the other. In practice, this question is apt to be treated as identical with another, which, as has been shown earlier, is a distinct point; namely, when performance on one side is a condition of the right to call for performance on the other. It is of course conceivable that a promise should be limited to the case of performance of the things promised on the other side, and yet that a failure of the latter should not warrant a rescission of the contract. Wherever one party has already received a substantial benefit under a contract of a kind which cannot be restored, it is too late to rescind, however important a breach may be committed later by the other side. Yet he may be [334] excused from going farther. Suppose a contract is made for a month's labor, ten dollars to be paid down, not to be recovered except in case of rescission for the laborer's fault, and thirty dollars at the end of the month. If the laborer should wrongfully stop work at the end of a fortnight, I do not suppose that the contract could be rescinded, and that the ten dollars could be recovered as money had and received; /1/ but, on the other hand, the employer would not be bound to pay the thirty dollars, and of course he could sue for damages on the contract. /2/

We can now move from commitments concerning the truth of certain facts at the time the contract is made to commitments that certain facts will be true at a later time—that is, to promises in the true sense. The question arises as to when one party's performance of the promise is a condition for the other party's obligation under the contract. In practice, this question is often treated as the same as another issue, which has been previously discussed and is actually a separate matter; specifically, when one party’s performance is a condition for the right to demand performance from the other. It’s entirely possible for a promise to be contingent upon the other party fulfilling their end, yet a failure on that part does not necessarily justify canceling the contract. Whenever one party has already received a significant benefit from a type of contract that cannot be undone, it's too late to cancel, even if the other party commits a serious breach later on. However, they may be [334] excused from taking further action. For instance, if a contract is established for a month of work, with ten dollars paid upfront that can only be recovered if the laborer is at fault for canceling, and thirty dollars due at the end of the month, if the laborer unjustifiably quits after two weeks, I don't think the contract could be canceled, and the ten dollars could not be reclaimed as money had and received; /1/ but conversely, the employer wouldn’t be required to pay the thirty dollars and could certainly sue for damages under the contract. /2/

But, for the most part, a breach of promise which discharges the promisee from further performance on his side will also warrant rescission, so that no great harm is done by the popular confusion of the two questions. Where the promise to perform on one side is limited to the case of performance on the other, the contract is generally conditioned on it also. In what follows, I shall take up the cases which I wish to notice without stopping to consider whether the contract was in a strict sense conditioned on performance of the promise on one side, or whether the true construction was merely that the promise on the other side was limited to that event.

But generally, a breach of promise that releases the promisee from further obligations will also justify canceling the contract, so the common mix-up of the two issues doesn't cause much trouble. When one party's promise to perform depends on the other party fulfilling their end, the contract is typically based on that condition as well. In what follows, I'll discuss the cases I want to highlight without pausing to determine if the contract was strictly conditional on one side's performance or if the correct interpretation was simply that the promise from the other side was restricted to that situation.

Now, how do we settle whether such a condition exists? It is easy to err by seeking too eagerly for simplicity, and by striving too hard to reduce all cases to artificial presumptions, which are less obvious than the decisions which they are supposed to explain. The foundation of the whole matter is, after all, good sense, as the courts have often said. The law means to carry out the intention of the parties, and, so far as they have not provided [335] for the event which has happened, it has to say what they naturally would have intended if their minds had been turned to the point. It will be found that decisions based on the direct implications of the language used, and others based upon a remoter inference of what the parties must have meant, or would have said if they had spoken, shade into each other by imperceptible degrees.

Now, how do we determine if such a condition exists? It's easy to make mistakes by looking too hard for simplicity and trying too much to reduce all cases to artificial assumptions, which are less clear than the decisions they are supposed to clarify. The core of the entire issue is, after all, common sense, as the courts have often stated. The law aims to fulfill the intentions of the parties, and as long as they haven't provided [335] for the event that has occurred, it has to interpret what they would naturally have intended if they had considered the matter. It will be observed that decisions based on the direct implications of the language used, and those based on a more distant inference of what the parties must have meant, or would have said if they had communicated, blur into each other by subtle degrees.

Mr. Langdell has called attention to a very important principle, and one which, no doubt, throws light on many decisions. /1/ This is, that, where you have a bilateral contract, while the consideration of each promise is the counter promise, yet prima facie the payment for performance of one is performance of the other. The performance of the other party is what each means to have in return for his own. If A promises a barrel of flour to B, and B promises him ten dollars for it, A means to have the ten dollars for his flour, and B means to have the flour for his ten dollars. If no time is set for either act, neither can call on the other to perform without being ready at the same time himself.

Mr. Langdell has highlighted a very important principle that certainly sheds light on many decisions. This principle states that, in a bilateral contract, although the consideration for each promise is the counter-promise, generally speaking, the payment for one performance is considered performance of the other. Each party expects to receive something in return for their own promise. For example, if A promises a barrel of flour to B and B promises A ten dollars for it, A expects to receive the ten dollars for his flour, while B expects to receive the flour for his ten dollars. If no time is specified for either action, neither party can demand performance from the other without being ready to perform their part at the same time.

But this principle of equivalency is not the only principle to be drawn even from the form of contracts, without considering their subject-matter, and of course it is not offered as such in Mr. Langdell's work.

But this equivalency principle isn’t the only one that can be inferred from the structure of contracts, regardless of their subject matter, and it's certainly not presented that way in Mr. Langdell's work.

Another very clear one is found in contracts for the sale or lease of a thing, and the like. Here the qualities or characteristics which the owner promises that the thing furnished shall possess, go to describe the thing which the buyer promises to accept. If any of the promised traits are wanting in the thing tendered, the buyer may refuse to accept, not merely on the ground that he has not [336] been offered the equivalent for keeping his promise, but also on the ground that he never promised to accept what is offered him. /1/ It has been seen that, where the contract contains a statement touching the condition of the thing at an earlier time than the moment for its acceptance, the past condition may not always be held to enter into the description of the thing to be accepted. But no such escape is possible here. Nevertheless there are limits to the right of refusal even in the present class of cases. If the thing promised is specific, the preponderance of that part of the description which identifies the object by reference to the senses is sometimes strikingly illustrated. One case has gone so far as to hold that performance of an executory contract to purchase a specific thing cannot be refused because it fails to come up to the warranted quality. /2/

Another very clear example is found in contracts for the sale or lease of an item and similar agreements. Here, the qualities or characteristics that the owner promises the item will have help define what the buyer agrees to accept. If any of the promised traits are missing from the item offered, the buyer can refuse to accept it, not only because they haven’t been given what was promised in return for their commitment but also because they never agreed to accept what was provided. /1/ It has been shown that when the contract includes a statement about the condition of the item at a time before it’s accepted, that past condition may not always be considered part of the description of the item being accepted. However, no such loophole exists in this case. Still, there are limits to the right of refusal even in these situations. If the promised item is specific, the way it’s described in terms of sensory experience can be quite clear. One case has even ruled that performance of a contract to buy a specific item cannot be refused just because it doesn’t meet the promised quality. /2/

Another principle of dependency to be drawn from the form of the contract itself is, that performance of the promise on one side may be manifestly intended to furnish the means for performing the promise on the other. If a tenant should promise to make repairs, and the landlord should promise to furnish him wood for the purpose, it is believed that at the present day, whatever may have been the old decisions, the tenant's duty to repair would be dependent upon the landlord's furnishing the material when required. /3/

Another principle of dependency that can be taken from the contract itself is that fulfilling one promise might clearly be intended to provide the means for fulfilling the other promise. If a tenant promises to make repairs and the landlord promises to supply the wood for that purpose, it is believed that today, regardless of past rulings, the tenant’s obligation to repair would depend on the landlord providing the materials when needed. /3/

[337] Another case of a somewhat exceptional kind is where a party to a bilateral contract agrees to do certain things and to give security for his performance. Here it is manifest good-sense to hold giving the security a condition of performance on the other side, if it be possible. For the requirement of security shows that the party requiring it was not content to rely on the simple promise of the other side, which he would be compelled to do if he had to perform before the security was given, and thus the very object of requiring it would be defeated. /1/

[337] Another example of a somewhat unique situation is when one party in a bilateral contract agrees to do certain things and provide security for their performance. It makes perfect sense to make the provision of security a condition for the other party's performance, if possible. This requirement for security demonstrates that the party asking for it doesn't want to depend solely on the other party's promise, which would force them to perform before the security is provided, thereby undermining the very reason for requesting it. /1/

This last case suggests what is very forcibly impressed on any one who studies the cases,—that, after all, the most important element of decision is not any technical, or even any general principle of contracts, but a consideration of the nature of the particular transaction as a practical matter. A promises B to do a day's work for two dollars, and B promises A to pay two dollars for a day's work. There the two promises cannot be performed at the same time. The work will take all day, the payment half a minute. How are you to decide which is to be done first, that is to say, which promise is dependent upon performance on the other side? It is only by reference to the habits of the community and to convenience. It is not enough to say that on the principle of equivalency a man is not presumed to intend to pay for a thing until he has it. The work is payment for the money, as much as the [338] money for the work, and one must be paid in advance. The question is, why, if one man is not presumed to intend to pay money until he has money's worth, the other is presumed to intend to give money's worth before he has money. An answer cannot be obtained from any general theory. The fact that employers, as a class, can be trusted for wages more safely than the employed for their labor, that the employers have had the power and have been the law-makers, or other considerations, it matters not what, have determined that the work is to be done first. But the grounds of decision are purely practical, and can never be elicited from grammar or from logic.

This last case highlights a key point for anyone studying these situations—that ultimately, the most important factor in decision-making isn't a technical rule or even a general principle of contracts, but rather an examination of the nature of the specific transaction in a practical sense. A promises B to do a day’s work for two dollars, and B promises A to pay two dollars for a day's work. In this scenario, the two promises can’t be fulfilled simultaneously. The work will take all day, while the payment takes just a moment. How do you determine which obligation should come first, meaning which promise depends on the other being fulfilled? It relies on the norms of the community and what's convenient. It's not enough to claim that, based on the principle of equivalence, a person isn't assumed to intend to pay for something until they've received it. The work acts as payment for the money, just as the money serves as payment for the work, and one must be settled in advance. The question is, if one person isn't presumed to intend to pay money until they have something of equal value, why is the other person presumed to provide value before having the money? No answer can come from any overarching theory. The reality that employers, as a group, can generally be trusted to pay wages more reliably than employees can be trusted to deliver their work, along with the fact that employers have had the power and set the laws, or other factors—whatever they may be—have guided the decision that the work is to be done first. But the reasons behind this decision are entirely practical and can never be derived from grammar or logic.

A reference to practical considerations will be found to run all through the subject. Take another instance. The plaintiff declared on a mutual agreement between himself and the defendant that he would sell, and the defendant would buy, certain Donskoy wool, to be shipped by the plaintiff at Odessa, and delivered in England. Among the stipulations of the contract was one, that the names of the vessels should be declared as soon as the wools were shipped. The defence was, that the wool was bought, with the knowledge of both parties, for the purpose of reselling it in the course of the defendant's business; that it was an article of fluctuating value, and not salable until the names of the vessels in which it was shipped should have been declared according to the contract, but that the plaintiff did not declare the names of the vessels as agreed. The decision of the court was given by one of the greatest technical lawyers that ever lived, Baron Parke; yet he did not dream of giving any technical or merely logical reason for the decision, but, after stating in the above words the facts which were deemed material to the question [339] whether declaring the names of the vessels was a condition to the duty to accept, stated the ground of decision thus: "Looking at the nature of the contract, and the great importance of it to the object with which the contract was entered into with the knowledge of both parties, we think it was a condition precedent." /1/

A reference to practical considerations can be seen running throughout the subject. Here’s another example. The plaintiff claimed there was a mutual agreement between him and the defendant that he would sell, and the defendant would buy, certain Donskoy wool, which would be shipped by the plaintiff from Odessa and delivered to England. One of the stipulations of the contract was that the names of the vessels should be declared as soon as the wool was shipped. The defense argued that the wool was bought, with both parties knowing, for the purpose of reselling it in the defendant's business; that it was a commodity with fluctuating value and not sellable until the names of the vessels it was shipped on were declared as per the contract, but that the plaintiff did not declare the vessel names as agreed. The court's decision was delivered by one of the greatest technical lawyers ever, Baron Parke; however, he didn’t attempt to provide any technical or merely logical rationale for the decision. Instead, after outlining the facts considered significant to the question [339] of whether declaring the names of the vessels was a condition for the obligation to accept, he stated the rationale for the decision like this: "Considering the nature of the contract and its great importance to the purpose for which it was made with the knowledge of both parties, we believe it was a condition precedent." /1/

[340]

[340]





LECTURE X. — SUCCESSIONS AFTER DEATH.

In the Lecture on Possession, I tried to show that the notion of possessing a right as such was intrinsically absurd. All rights are consequences attached to filling some situation of fact. A right which may be acquired by possession differs from others simply in being attached to a situation of such a nature that it may be filled successively by different persons, or by any one without regard to the lawfulness of his doing so, as is the case where the situation consists in having a tangible object within one's power.

In the Lecture on Possession, I aimed to explain that the idea of holding a right by itself is fundamentally ridiculous. All rights are tied to specific factual situations. A right that can be gained through possession is different from others only because it is linked to a situation that can be occupied one after another by different people or by anyone, regardless of whether what they are doing is lawful, like when the situation involves having a physical object in one's possession.

When a right of this sort is recognized by the law, there is no difficulty in transferring it; or, more accurately, there is no difficulty in different persons successively enjoying similar rights in respect of the subject-matter. If A, being the possessor of a horse or a field, gives up the possession to B, the rights which B acquires stand on the same ground as A's did before. The facts from which A's rights sprang have ceased to be true of A, and are now true of B. The consequences attached by the law to those facts now exist for B, as they did for A before. The situation of fact from which the rights spring is continuing one, and any one who occupies it, no matter how, has the rights attached to it. But there is no possession possible of a contract. The [341] fact that a consideration was given yesterday by A to B, and a promise received in return, cannot be laid hold of by X, and transferred from A to himself. The only thing can be transferred is the benefit or burden of the promise, and how can they be separated from the facts which gave rise to them? How, in short, can a man sue or be sued on a promise in which he had no part?

When a right like this is recognized by the law, transferring it isn’t an issue; or more accurately, it’s easy for different people to succeedively enjoy similar rights regarding the same subject. If A, who owns a horse or a field, hands over possession to B, the rights B gains are equal to A's rights before. The circumstances that created A's rights no longer apply to A and are now true for B. The legal consequences linked to those circumstances now apply to B, just as they did for A before. The situation from which the rights arise continues, and anyone who occupies that situation, regardless of how, holds the rights associated with it. However, you can't possess a contract. The fact that A gave B something in exchange yesterday, and received a promise in return, can’t be taken by X and transferred from A to himself. The only things that can be transferred are the benefits or burdens of the promise, and how can those be separated from the facts that created them? Ultimately, how can someone sue or be sued over a promise they weren’t involved in?

Hitherto it has been assumed, in dealing with any special right or obligation, that the facts from which it sprung were true of the individual entitled or bound. But it often happens, especially in modern law, that a person acquires and is allowed to enforce a special right, although that facts which give rise to it are not true of him, or are true of him only in part. One of the chief problems of the law is to explain the machinery by which this result has been brought to pass.

Until now, it has been assumed that when discussing any specific right or obligation, the facts that led to it were true for the individual who is entitled or bound. However, it often occurs, especially in modern law, that a person gains and is allowed to enforce a specific right, even if the facts that create it are not entirely true for them, or are true only in part. One of the main challenges in law is to clarify the mechanisms through which this outcome has been achieved.

It will be observed that the problem is not coextensive with the whole field of rights. Some rights cannot be transferred by any device or contrivance; for instance, a man's right a to bodily safety or reputation. Others again are incident to possession, and within the limits of that conception no other is necessary. As Savigny said, "Succession does not apply to possession by itself." /1/

It can be seen that the issue doesn't cover the entire area of rights. Some rights can't be transferred by any means; for example, a person's right to bodily safety or reputation. Others are tied to possession, and within that idea, no other right is needed. As Savigny stated, "Succession does not apply to possession by itself." /1/

But the notion of possession will carry us but a very little way in our understanding of the modern theory of transfer. That theory depends very largely upon the notion of succession, to use the word just quoted from Savigny, and accordingly successions will be the subject of this and the following Lecture. I shall begin by explaining the theory of succession to persons deceased, and after that is done shall pass to the theory of transfer between living [342] people, and shall consider whether any relation can be established between the two.

But the idea of possession will only take us a short distance in understanding the modern theory of transfer. That theory relies heavily on the concept of succession, as mentioned by Savigny, so successions will be the focus of this and the next lecture. I will start by explaining the theory of succession concerning deceased individuals, and once that is covered, I will move on to the theory of transfer between living [342] people, and I will explore whether any relationship can be established between the two.

The former is easily shown to be founded upon a fictitious identification between the deceased and his successor. And as a first step to the further discussion, as well as for its own sake, I shall briefly state the evidence touching the executor, the heir, and the devisee. In order to understand the theory of our law with regard to the first of these, at least, scholars are agreed that it is necessary to consider the structure and position of the Roman family as it was in the infancy of Roman society.

The former is clearly based on a made-up link between the deceased and their successor. As a starting point for the further discussion, and also for its own importance, I will briefly outline the evidence regarding the executor, the heir, and the devisee. To understand our legal theory about the first of these, scholars agree that it's essential to look at the structure and role of the Roman family during the early days of Roman society.

Continental jurists have long been collecting the evidence that, in the earlier periods of Roman and German law alike, the unit of society was the family. The Twelve Tables of Rome still recognize the interest of the inferior members of the family in the family property. Heirs are called sui heredes, that is, heirs of themselves or of their own property, as is explained by Gaius. /1/ Paulus says that they are regarded as owners in a certain sense, even in the lifetime of their father, and that after his death they do not so much receive an inheritance as obtain the full power of dealing with their property. /2/

Continental legal scholars have long been gathering evidence that, in the earlier days of both Roman and German law, the basic unit of society was the family. The Twelve Tables of Rome still acknowledge the rights of the lesser members of the family in relation to family property. Heirs are called sui heredes, meaning heirs of themselves or their own property, as explained by Gaius. /1/ Paulus states that they are seen as owners in a certain sense, even while their father is alive, and that after his death, they don't just receive an inheritance but gain full authority to manage their property. /2/

Starting from this point it is easy to understand the [343] succession of heirs to a deceased paterfamilias in the Roman system. If the family was the owner of the property administered by a paterfamilias, its rights remained unaffected by the death of its temporary head. The family continued, although the head died. And when, probably by a gradual change, /1/ the paterfamilias came to be regarded as owner, instead of a simple manager of the family rights, the nature and continuity of those rights did not change with the title to them. The familia continued to the heirs as it was left by the ancestor. The heir succeeded not to the ownership of this or that thing separately, but to the total hereditas or headship of the family with certain rights of property as incident, /2/ and of course he took this headship, or right of representing the family interests, subject to the modifications effected by the last manager.

Starting from this point, it’s easy to understand the [343] succession of heirs to a deceased head of the family in the Roman system. If the family owned the property managed by the head, its rights remained intact after the death of its temporary leader. The family continued on, despite the death of the head. And when, likely through a gradual change, /1/ the head came to be seen as the owner rather than just a manager of the family rights, the nature and continuity of those rights didn’t change with the title. The family passed on to the heirs as it was left by the ancestor. The heir didn’t inherit ownership of each specific item separately; instead, they inherited the total hereditas or leadership of the family along with certain property rights as part of it, /2/ and naturally, they took this leadership or right to represent the family interests, subject to the changes made by the last manager.

The aggregate of the ancestor's rights and duties, or, to use the technical phrase, the total persona sustained by him, was easily separated from his natural personality. For this persona was but the aggregate of what had formerly been family rights and duties, and was originally sustained by any individual only as the family head. Hence it was said to be continued by the inheritance, /3/ and when the heir assumed it he had his action in respect of injuries previously committed. /4/

The collection of an ancestor's rights and responsibilities, or in technical terms, the total persona held by them, could easily be separated from their natural personality. This persona was simply the sum of what had once been family rights and responsibilities and was initially held by an individual only as the family head. Therefore, it was said to be passed down through inheritance, and when the heir took it on, they could pursue actions for injuries that had occurred before.

Thus the Roman heir came to be treated as identified with his ancestor for the purposes of the law. And thus it is clear how the impossible transfers which I seek to explain were accomplished in that instance. Rights to which B [344] as B could show no title, he could readily maintain under the fiction that he was the same person as A, whose title was not denied.

Thus the Roman heir was treated as being the same as his ancestor for legal purposes. This makes it clear how the impossible transfers I’m trying to explain happened in that case. Rights that B [344] couldn't prove a title for could easily be maintained under the assumption that he was the same person as A, whose title was not questioned.

It is not necessary at this point to study family rights in the German tribes. For it is not disputed that the modern executor derives his characteristics from the Roman heir. Wills also were borrowed from Rome, and were unknown to the Germans of Tacitus. /1/ Administrators were a later imitation of executors, introduced by statute for cases where there was no will, or where, for any other reason, executors were wanting.

It’s not essential right now to look into family rights among the German tribes. It's generally accepted that the modern executor gets their traits from the Roman heir. Wills were also taken from Rome and weren’t known to the Germans described by Tacitus. /1/ Administrators were a later copy of executors, created by law for situations where there was no will, or where, for any other reason, executors were missing.

The executor has the legal title to the whole of the testator's personal estate, and, generally speaking, the power of alienation. Formerly he was entitled to the undistributed residue, not, it may fairly be conjectured, as legatee of those specific chattels, but because he represented the person of the testator, and therefore had all the rights which the testator would have had after distribution if alive. The residue is nowadays generally bequeathed by the will, but it is not even now regarded as a specific gift of the chattels remaining undisposed of, and I cannot help thinking that this doctrine echoes that under which the executor took in former times.

The executor has the legal right to the entire personal estate of the deceased and typically has the authority to transfer ownership. In the past, he was entitled to the undistributed remainder, not necessarily as a beneficiary of those specific items, but because he represented the deceased, and thus had all the rights the deceased would have had after distribution if they were still alive. Today, the remainder is usually specified in the will, but it is still not seen as a specific gift of the items that were not assigned, and I can't help but feel that this concept reflects the way executors operated in earlier times.

No such rule has governed residuary devises of real estate, which have always been held to be specific in England down to the present day. So that, if a devise of land should fail, that land would not be disposed of by the residuary clause, but would descend to the heir as if there had been no will.

No rule has governed leftover gifts of real estate, which have always been viewed as specific in England up to today. So, if a gift of land fails, that land won't be handled by the leftover clause; instead, it will go to the heir as if there was no will.

Again, the appointment of an executor relates back to the date of the testator's death. The continuity of person [345] is preserved by this fiction, as in Rome it was by personifying the inheritance ad interim.

Again, the appointment of an executor goes back to the date of the testator's death. The continuity of person [345] is maintained by this fiction, much like in Rome, where they personified the inheritance temporarily.

Enough has been said to show the likeness between our executor and the Roman heir. And bearing in mind what was said about the heres, it will easily be seen how it came to be said, as it often was in the old books, that the executor "represents the person of his testator." /1/ The meaning of this feigned identity has been found in history, but the aid which it furnished in overcoming a technical difficulty must also be appreciated. If the executor represents the person of the testator, there is no longer any trouble in allowing him to sue or be sued on his testator's contracts. In the time of Edward III., when an action of covenant was brought against executors, Persay objected: "I never heard that one should have a writ of covenant against executors, nor against other person but the very one who made the covenant, for a man cannot oblige another person to a covenant by his deed except him who was party to the covenant." /2/ But it is useless to object that the promise sued upon was made by A, the testator, not by B, the executor, when the law says that for this purpose B is A. Here then is one class of cases in which a transfer is accomplished by the help of a fiction, which shadows, as fictions so often do, the facts of an early stage of society, and which could hardly have been invented had these facts been otherwise.

Enough has been said to show the similarity between our executor and the Roman heir. Considering what was discussed about heirs, it's easy to see how it became said, as often noted in old texts, that the executor "represents the person of his testator." The significance of this fictional identity can be traced in history, but we also need to recognize how it helped overcome a legal challenge. If the executor represents the testator's person, then there's no issue allowing him to sue or be sued based on his testator's contracts. Back in the time of Edward III, when a covenant action was brought against executors, Persay argued: "I’ve never heard of someone being able to bring a writ of covenant against executors, nor anyone else but the actual person who made the covenant, because a person can't bind another to a covenant through his deed unless that person was part of the covenant." But it's pointless to argue that the promise being sued upon was made by A, the testator, not by B, the executor, when the law states that for this purpose B is A. Here is one type of case where a transfer occurs through the help of a fiction, which reflects, as fictions often do, the realities of an earlier stage of society, and which could hardly have been created if those realities had been different.

Executors and administrators afford the chief, if not the only, example of universal succession in the English [346] law. But although they succeed per universitatem, as has been explained, they do not succeed to all kinds of property. The personal estate goes to them, but land takes another course. All real estate not disposed of by will goes to the heir, and the rules of inheritance are quite distinct from those which govern the distribution of chattels. Accordingly, the question arises whether the English heir or successor to real estate presents the same analogies to the Roman heres as the executor.

Executors and administrators provide the main, if not the only, example of universal succession in English law. However, even though they succeed as a whole, as previously explained, they don’t inherit all types of property. They receive the personal estate, but land follows a different path. All real estate not allocated by a will goes to the heir, and the rules of inheritance are quite different from those that manage the distribution of personal property. Therefore, the question comes up whether the English heir or successor to real estate has the same similarities to the Roman heres as the executor does.

The English heir is not a universal successor. Each and every parcel of land descends as a separate and specific thing. Nevertheless, in his narrower sphere he unquestionably represents the person of his ancestor. Different opinions have been held as to whether the same thing was true in early German law. Dr. Laband says that it was; /1/ Sohm takes the opposite view. /2/ It is commonly supposed that family ownership, at least of land, came before that of individuals in the German tribes, and it has been shown how naturally representation followed from a similar state of things in Rome. But it is needless to consider whether our law on this subject is of German or Roman origin, as the principle of identification has clearly prevailed from the time of Glanvill to the present day. If it was not known to the Germans, it is plainly accounted for by the influence of the Roman law. If there was anything of the sort in the Salic law, it was no doubt due to natural causes similar to those which gave rise to the principle at Rome. But in either event I cannot doubt that the modern doctrine has taken a good deal of its form, and perhaps some of its substance, from the mature system [347] of the civilians, in whose language it was so long expressed. For the same reasons that have just been mentioned, it is also needless to weigh the evidence of the Anglo-Saxon sources, although it seems tolerably clear from several passages in the laws that there was some identification. /1/

The English heir isn't a universal successor. Every piece of land is inherited separately and specifically. However, within his limited scope, he definitely represents his ancestor. There have been different views on whether the same was true in early German law. Dr. Laband argues that it was; /1/ Sohm disagrees. It's generally believed that family ownership, especially of land, came before individual ownership among the German tribes, and it's been shown how naturally representation arose from a similar situation in Rome. But there's no need to determine whether our law on this topic has German or Roman roots, as the principle of identification has clearly been in place from the time of Glanvill to now. If it wasn't known to the Germans, it can be easily explained by the influence of Roman law. If there was anything like it in the Salic law, it was likely due to natural causes similar to those that created the principle in Rome. But in any case, I can't doubt that the modern doctrine has shaped much of its structure, and perhaps some of its essence, from the well-developed system [347] of the civilians, in whose language it was expressed for so long. For the same reasons already mentioned, it's also unnecessary to evaluate the evidence from Anglo-Saxon sources, although it appears fairly clear from several passages in the laws that some level of identification existed. /1/

As late as Bracton, two centuries after the Norman conquest, the heir was not the successor to lands alone, but represented his ancestor in a much more general sense, as will be seen directly. The office of executor, in the sense of heir, was unknown to the Anglo-Saxons, /2/ and even in Bracton's time does not seem to have been what it has since become. There is, therefore, no need to go back further than to the early Norman period, after the appointment of executors had become common, and the heir was more nearly what he is now.

As late as Bracton, two centuries after the Norman conquest, the heir wasn't just the successor to land; he also represented his ancestor in a broader sense, as will be discussed shortly. The role of executor, in the sense of heir, was not known to the Anglo-Saxons, and even in Bracton's time, it didn't seem to have developed into what it has become today. Therefore, we don't need to go back further than the early Norman period, when the appointment of executors had become common, and the role of the heir was closer to what it is now.

When Glanvill wrote, a little more than a century after the Conquest, the heir was bound to warrant the reasonable gifts of his ancestor to the grantees and their heirs; /3/ and if the effects of the ancestor were insufficient to pay his debts, the heir was bound to make up the deficiency from his own property. /4/ Neither Glanvill nor his Scotch imitator, the Regiam Majestatem, /5/ limits the liability to the amount of property inherited from the same source. This makes the identification of heir and ancestor as complete as that of the Roman law before such a limitation was introduced by Justinian. On the other hand, a century [348] later, it distinctly appears from Bracton, /1/ that the heir was only bound so far as property had descended to him, and in the early sources of the Continent, Norman as well as other, the same limitation appears. /2/ The liabilities of the heir were probably shrinking. Britton and Fleta, the imitators of Bracton, and perhaps Bracton himself, say that an heir is not bound to pay his ancestor's debt, unless he be thereto especially bound by the deed of his ancestor. /3/ The later law required that the heir should be mentioned if he was to be held.

When Glanvill wrote, a little over a hundred years after the Conquest, the heir was required to uphold the reasonable gifts of his ancestor to the grantees and their heirs; /3/ and if the ancestor's assets were not enough to cover his debts, the heir had to cover the shortfall from his own property. /4/ Neither Glanvill nor his Scottish imitator, the Regiam Majestatem, /5/ limited the heir's liability to the amount of property inherited from the same source. This means the connection between the heir and ancestor was as complete as in Roman law before such a limitation was introduced by Justinian. On the other hand, a century [348] later, it clearly shows from Bracton, /1/ that the heir was only responsible to the extent that property had descended to him, and in early sources from the Continent, both Norman and others, the same limitation appears. /2/ The liabilities of the heir were likely decreasing. Britton and Fleta, who followed Bracton, and possibly Bracton himself, state that an heir is not obligated to pay his ancestor's debt unless he is specifically bound by the deed of his ancestor. /3/ The later law required that the heir be mentioned if he was to be held accountable.

But at all events the identification of heir and ancestor still approached the nature of a universal succession in the time of Bracton, as is shown by another statement of his. He asks if the testator can bequeath his rights of action, and answers, No, so far as concerns debts not proved and recovered in the testator's life. But actions of that sort belong to the heirs, and must be sued in the secular court; for before they are so recovered in the proper court, the executor cannot proceed for them in the ecclesiastical tribunal. /4/

But in any case, the connection between heir and ancestor still resembled a universal succession during Bracton’s time, as indicated by another statement of his. He asks whether the testator can pass on his rights to take legal action and answers, No, regarding debts that were not proven and recovered during the testator's lifetime. However, those kinds of actions belong to the heirs and must be pursued in a secular court; because until they are properly recovered in that court, the executor cannot take action on them in the ecclesiastical court. /4/

This shows that the identification worked both ways. The heir was liable for the debts due from his ancestor, and he could recover those which were due to him, until [349] the executor took his place in the King's Courts, as well as in those of the Church. Within the limits just explained the heir was also bound to warrant property sold by his ancestor to the purchaser and his heirs. /1/ It is not necessary, after this evidence that the modern heir began by representing his ancestor generally, to seek for expressions in later books, since his position has been limited. But just as we have seen that the executor is still said to represent the person of his testator, the heir was said to represent the person of his ancestor in the time of Edward I. /2/ So, at a much later date, it was said that "the heir is in representation in point of taking by inheritance eadam persona cum antecessore," /3/ the same persona as his ancestor.

This shows that the identification worked both ways. The heir was responsible for the debts owed by his ancestor and could recover what was due to him until [349] the executor took over in the King's Courts and those of the Church. Within the limits just mentioned, the heir was also obligated to guarantee the property sold by his ancestor to the buyer and his heirs. /1/ After this evidence, it's clear that the modern heir started by representing his ancestor generally, so there's no need to look for phrases in later texts, as his role has been defined. However, just as we have seen that the executor is still said to represent the person of his testator, the heir was said to represent the person of his ancestor during the time of Edward I. /2/ Similarly, at a much later date, it was stated that "the heir is in representation in point of taking by inheritance eadam persona cum antecessore," /3/ the same person as his ancestor.

A great judge, who died but a few years ago, repeats language which would have been equally familiar to the lawyers of Edward or of James. Baron Parke, after laying down that in general a party is not required to make profert of an instrument to the possession of which he is not entitled, says that there is an exception "in the cases of heir and executor, who may plead a release to the ancestor or testator whom they respectively represent; so also with respect to several tortfeasors, for in all these cases there is a privity between the parties which constitutes an identity of person." /4/

A great judge, who passed away just a few years ago, uses language that would have been just as familiar to the lawyers of Edward or James. Baron Parke, after stating that generally a party does not have to present a document they don’t have the right to, mentions an exception "in the cases of heir and executor, who can plead a release to the ancestor or testator they represent; this also applies to several tortfeasors, because in all these cases there is a connection between the parties that creates an identity of person." /4/

But this is not all. The identity of person was carried [350] farther still. If a man died leaving male children, and owning land in fee, it went to the oldest son alone; but, if he left only daughters, it descended to them all equally. In this case several individuals together continued the persona of their ancestor. But it was always laid down that they were but one heir. /1/ For the purpose of working out this result, not only was one person identified with another, but several persons were reduced to one, that they might sustain a single persona.

But that's not all. The person's identity was taken [350] even further. If a man died leaving behind sons and owning land outright, it went to the eldest son only; however, if he left only daughters, it was divided equally among them. In this situation, several individuals together represented the persona of their ancestor. But it was always stated that they were considered one heir. /1/ To achieve this, not only was one person identified with another, but multiple people were combined into one so they could maintain a single persona.

What was the persona? It was not the sum of all the rights and duties of the ancestor. It has been seen that for many centuries his general status, the sum of all his rights and duties except those connected with real property, has been taken up by the executor or administrator. The persona continued by the heir was from an early day confined to real estate in its technical sense; that is, to property subject to feudal principles, as distinguished from chattels, which, as Blackstone tells us, /2/ include whatever was not a feud.

What was the persona? It wasn't just all the rights and responsibilities of the ancestor. For many centuries, it's been established that the executor or administrator took on his overall status, which included all his rights and duties except those related to real property. The persona carried on by the heir was, from an early point, limited to real estate in its specific legal sense; that is, to property governed by feudal principles, unlike chattels, which, as Blackstone explains, include everything that wasn't a feud.

But the heir's persona was not even the sum of all the ancestor's rights and duties in connection with real estate. It has been said already that every fee descends specifically, and not as incident to a larger universitas. This appears not so much from the fact that the rules of descent governing different parcels might be different, /3/ so that the same person would not be heir to both, as from the very nature of feudal property. Under the feudal system in its vigor, the holding of land was only one [351] incident of a complex personal relation. The land was forfeited for a failure to render the services for which it was granted; the service could be renounced for a breach of correlative duties on the part of the lord. /1/ It rather seems that, in the beginning of the feudal period under Charlemagne, a man could only hold land of one lord. /2/ Even when it had become common to hold of more than one, the strict personal relation was only modified so far as to save the tenant from having to perform inconsistent services. Glanvill and Bracton /3/ a tell us that a tenant holding of several lords was to do homage for each fee, but to reserve his allegiance for the lord of whom he held his chief estate; but that, if the different lords should make war upon each other, and the chief lord should command the tenant to obey him in person, the tenant ought to obey, saving the service due to the other lord for the fee held of him.

But the heir's identity wasn't just the total of all the ancestor's rights and responsibilities regarding real estate. It's already been mentioned that every property is passed down specifically, not as part of a larger estate. This stems not just from the fact that the rules for passing down different properties might vary, so the same person wouldn't inherit both, but from the very nature of feudal property. Under a strong feudal system, land ownership was merely one aspect of a complex personal relationship. The land could be taken away if the owner failed to provide the services for which it was given; those services could be rejected if the lord breached his own duties. It seems that, at the start of the feudal era under Charlemagne, a person could only hold land from one lord. Even when it became normal to hold land from multiple lords, the personal relationship was only adjusted enough to prevent the tenant from having to fulfill conflicting obligations. Glanvill and Bracton tell us that a tenant who held land from several lords was to show loyalty for each property but was to reserve his primary allegiance for the lord of the main estate; however, if the different lords went to war against each other and the main lord ordered the tenant to obey him personally, the tenant was expected to obey, while still honoring the service owed to the other lord for the land held from him.

We see, then, that the tenant had a distinct persona or status in respect of each of the fees which he held. The rights and duties incident to one of them had no relation to the rights and duties incident to another. A succession to one had no connection with the succession to another. Each succession was the assumption of a distinct personal relation, in which the successor was to be determined by the terms of the relation in question.

We can see that the tenant had a unique identity or role for each of the fees he held. The rights and responsibilities related to one fee didn’t connect to those of another. Taking over one fee had no link to taking over another. Each transition involved entering into a separate personal relationship, where the successor would be defined by the specifics of that relationship.

The persona which we are seeking to define is the estate. Every fee is a distinct persona, a distinct hereditas, or inheritance, as it has been called since the time of Bracton. We have already seen that it may be sustained by more [352] than one where there are several heirs, as well as by one, just as a corporation may have more or less members. But not only may it be divided lengthwise, so to speak, among persons interested in the same way at the same time: it may also be cut across into successive interests, to be enjoyed one after another. In technical language, it may be divided into a particular estate and remainders. But they are all parts of the same fee, and the same fiction still governs them. We read in an old case that "he in reversion and particular tenant are but one tenant." /1/ This is only a statement of counsel, to be sure; but it is made to account for a doctrine which seems to need the explanation, to the effect that, after the death of the tenant for life, he in reversion might have error or attaint on an erroneous judgment or false verdict given against the tenant for life. /2/

The concept we're trying to define is the estate. Every fee is a separate entity, a distinct inheritance, as it's been referred to since the time of Bracton. We've already noted that it can be held by more than one person when there are several heirs, just like a corporation can have multiple members. But it's not just that it can be divided among people who have a shared interest at the same time; it can also be split into successive interests that are enjoyed one after another. In legal terms, it can be divided into a particular estate and remainders. However, all of these are parts of the same fee, and the same principle still applies to them. We read in an old case that "he in reversion and particular tenant are but one tenant." This is merely a statement from legal counsel, but it aims to explain a doctrine that seems to require clarification: that after the death of the tenant for life, the person in reversion could challenge a wrong judgment or a false verdict given against the tenant for life.

To sum up the results so far, the heir of modern English law gets his characteristic features from the law as it stood soon after the Conquest. At that time he was a universal successor in a very broad sense. Many of his functions as such were soon transferred to the executor. The heir's rights became confined to real estate, and his liabilities to those connected with real estate, and to obligations of his ancestor expressly binding him. The succession to each fee or feudal inheritance is distinct, not part of the sum of all the ancestor's rights regarded as one whole. But to this day the executor in his sphere, and the heir in his, represent the person of the deceased, and are treated as if they were one with him, for the purpose of settling their rights and obligations.

To summarize the results so far, the heir of modern English law takes his key characteristics from the law as it existed shortly after the Conquest. At that time, he was a universal successor in a very broad sense. Many of his functions were soon passed on to the executor. The heir's rights became limited to real estate, and his responsibilities were tied to those associated with real estate and to obligations of his ancestor that explicitly bound him. The succession to each fee or feudal inheritance is separate, rather than part of the total sum of all the ancestor's rights considered as a whole. However, to this day, the executor in his role, and the heir in his, represent the deceased person and are treated as if they are one with him, for the purpose of settling their rights and responsibilities.

The bearing which this has upon the contracts of the [353] deceased has been pointed out. But its influence is not confined to contract; it runs through everything. The most striking instance, however, is the acquisition of prescriptive rights. Take the case of a right of way. A right of way over a neighbor's land can only be acquired by grant, or by using it adversely for twenty years. A man uses a way for ten years, and dies. Then his heir uses it ten years. Has any right been acquired? If common sense alone is consulted, the answer must be no. The ancestor did not get any right, because he did not use the way long enough. And just as little did the heir. How can it better the heir's title that another man had trespassed before him? Clearly, if four strangers to each other used the way for five years each, no right would be acquired by the last. But here comes in the fiction which has been so carefully explained. From the point of view of the law it is not two persons who have used the way for ten years each, but one who has used it for twenty. The heir has the advantage of sustaining his ancestor's and the right is acquired.

The impact this has on the contracts of the [353] deceased has been mentioned. But its effect isn't limited to contracts; it affects everything. The most notable example is the acquisition of prescriptive rights. Consider a right of way. A right of way over a neighbor's land can only be obtained either by a formal grant or by using it openly and negatively for twenty years. If a person uses a path for ten years and then dies, and their heir uses it for another ten years, has any right been obtained? If we rely solely on common sense, the answer must be no. The ancestor didn't acquire any right because they didn't use the path long enough. And the heir didn’t either. How does it improve the heir's claim that someone else trespassed before them? Clearly, if four strangers each used the path for five years, the last one wouldn't gain any right. However, this is where the legal fiction comes into play. Legally, it counts not as two individuals using the path for ten years each, but as one person using it for twenty years. The heir benefits from their ancestor’s usage, and thus the right is acquired.





LECTURE X. — SUCCESSIONS INTER VIVOS

I now reach the most difficult and obscure part of the subject. It remains to be discovered whether the fiction of identity was extended to others besides the heir and executor. And if we find, as we do, that it went but little farther in express terms, the question will still arise whether the mode of thought and the conceptions made possible by the doctrine of inheritance have not silently modified the law as to dealings between the living. It seems to me demonstrable that their influence has been profound, and that, without understanding the theory of inheritance, it is impossible to understand the theory of transfer inter vivos.

I’ve now arrived at the most challenging and unclear part of the topic. We still need to find out if the idea of identity was applied to anyone other than the heir and executor. Even if we see that it didn't extend much further in clear terms, the question will still come up whether the way of thinking and the ideas enabled by the doctrine of inheritance have quietly changed the law regarding transactions between the living. I believe it’s clear that their influence has been significant, and without grasping the theory of inheritance, it’s impossible to fully understand the theory of transfers during a person’s lifetime.

[354] The difficulty in dealing with the subject is to convince the sceptic that there is anything to explain. Nowadays, the notion that a right is valuable is almost identical with the notion that it may be turned into money by selling it. But it was not always so. Before you can sell a right, you must be able to make a sale thinkable in legal terms. I put the case of the transfer of a contract at the beginning of the Lecture. I have just mentioned the case of gaining a right by prescription, when neither party has complied with the requirement of twenty years' adverse use. In the latter instance, there is not even a right at the time of the transfer, but a mere fact of ten years' past trespassing. A way, until it becomes a right of way, is just as little susceptible of being held by a possessory title as a contract. If then a contract can be sold, if a buyer can add the time of his seller's adverse user to his own, what is the machinery by which the law works out the result?

[354] The challenge in addressing this topic is convincing skeptics that there's anything worth explaining. Today, the idea that a right has value is almost the same as saying it can be converted into money by selling it. But that hasn’t always been the case. Before you can sell a right, you need to make the sale legally feasible. I presented the example of transferring a contract at the start of the Lecture. I just mentioned the situation of acquiring a right through prescription when neither party has met the twenty years of adverse use requirement. In that case, there’s not even a right at the time of the transfer, just a simple fact of ten years of past trespassing. A path, until it becomes an established right of way, is just as unlikely to be held by a possessory title as a contract. So, if a contract can be sold and if a buyer can add the seller's time of adverse use to their own, what is the legal mechanism that brings about this result?

The most superficial acquaintance with any system of law in its earlier stages will show with what difficulty and by what slow degrees such machinery has been provided, and how the want of it has restricted the sphere of alienation. It is a great mistake to assume that it is a mere matter of common sense that the buyer steps into the shoes of the seller, according to our significant metaphor. Suppose that sales and other civil transfers had kept the form of warlike capture which it seems that they had in the infancy of Roman law, /1/ and which was at least [355] partially retained in one instance, the acquisition of wives, after the transaction had, in fact, taken the more civilized shape of purchase. The notion that the buyer came in adversely to the seller would probably have accompanied the fiction of adverse taking, and he would have stood on his own position as founding a new title. Without the aid of conceptions derived from some other source, it would have been hard to work out a legal transfer of objects which did not admit of possession.

The most basic understanding of any legal system in its early stages shows just how difficult and slow it has been to establish such processes, and how the lack of these processes has limited the ability to transfer property. It's a big mistake to think it's just common sense that the buyer takes over from the seller, as our popular saying goes. Imagine if sales and other property transfers had remained in the form of violent capture, which seems to have been the case in the early days of Roman law, and which was at least partially kept in one instance, specifically the acquisition of wives, even after the process evolved into something more civilized like purchase. The idea that the buyer came in opposition to the seller would likely have been linked to the notion of taking by force, and the buyer would have positioned himself as creating a new title. Without concepts drawn from other sources, it would have been challenging to figure out a legal transfer of items that couldn’t be physically possessed.

A possible source of such other conceptions was to be found in family law. The principles of inheritance furnished a fiction and a mode of thought which at least might have been extended into other spheres. In order to prove that they were in fact so extended, it will be necessary to examine once more the law of Rome, as well as the remains of German and Anglo-Saxon customs.

A possible source of these other ideas could be found in family law. The rules of inheritance provided a framework and a way of thinking that could have been applied to other areas. To demonstrate that this actually happened, we need to take another look at Roman law, along with the remnants of German and Anglo-Saxon customs.

I will take up first the German and Anglo-Saxon laws which are the ancestors of our own on one side of the house. For although what we get from those sources is not in the direct line of the argument, it lays a foundation for it by showing the course of development in different fields.

I will first discuss the German and Anglo-Saxon laws, which are the ancestors of our own legal system on one side of the house. Although the information we gather from these sources isn't directly related to the main argument, it provides a foundation by illustrating the development in various areas.

The obvious analogy between purchaser and heir seems to have been used in the folk-laws, but mainly for another purpose than those which will have to be considered in the English law. This was to enlarge the sphere of alienability. It will be remembered that there are many traces of family ownership in early German, as well as in early Roman law; and it would seem that the transfer [356] of property which originally could not be given outside the family, was worked out through the form of making the grantee an heir.

The clear connection between a buyer and an heir seems to have been used in traditional laws, but mostly for reasons different from those that need to be considered in English law. This was to broaden the possibilities for transferring ownership. It’s important to note that there are many signs of family ownership in both early German and early Roman law; and it appears that the transfer [356] of property that originally couldn’t be given outside the family was accomplished by making the recipient an heir.

The history of language points to this conclusion. Heres, as Beseler /1/ and others have remarked, from meaning a successor to the property of a person deceased, was extended to the donee mortis causa, and even more broadly to grantees in general. Hereditare was used in like manner for the transfer of land. Hevin is quoted by Laferriere /2/ as calling attention to the fact that the ancient usage was to say heriter for purchase, heritier for purchaser, and desheriter for sell.

The history of language leads to this conclusion. Here, as Beseler /1/ and others have noted, the term meaning a successor to the property of a deceased person was expanded to include the donee mortis causa, and even more broadly to grantees in general. Hereditare was similarly used for the transfer of land. Hevin is cited by Laferriere /2/ as highlighting that the ancient usage was to say heriter for purchase, heritier for purchaser, and desheriter for sell.

The texts of the Salic law give us incontrovertible evidence. A man might transfer the whole or any part of his property /3/ by delivering possession of it to a trustee who, within twelve months, handed it over to the beneficiaries. /4/ To those, the text reads, whom the donor has named heredes (quos heredes appellavit). Here then was a voluntary transfer of more or less property at pleasure to persons freely chosen, who were not necessarily universal successors, if they ever were, and who nevertheless took under the name heredes. The word, which must have meant at first persons taking by descent, was extended to persons taking by purchase. /5/ If the word became enlarged in meaning, it is probably because the thought which it conveyed was turned to new uses. The transaction seems [357] to have fallen half-way between the institution of an heir and a sale. The later law of the Ripuarian Franks treats it more distinctly from the former point of view. It permits a man who has no sons to give all his property to whomsoever he chooses, whether relatives or strangers, as inheritance, either by way of adfathamire, as the Salic form was called, or by writing or delivery. /1/

The texts of the Salic law provide clear evidence. A man could transfer all or part of his property by giving possession to a trustee, who would then hand it over to the beneficiaries within twelve months. The text states that these are the people the donor has named as heredes (quos heredes appellavit). This indicates a voluntary transfer of property to chosen individuals, who weren't necessarily universal heirs, but who still received the designation heredes. The term, which initially meant individuals inheriting by descent, was later broadened to include those acquiring by purchase. If the meaning of the word expanded, it was likely because the concept it represented evolved to serve new purposes. The transaction appears to occupy a middle ground between appointing an heir and conducting a sale. The later law of the Ripuarian Franks distinguishes it more clearly from the earlier perspective. It allows a man without sons to give all his property to anyone he chooses, whether they are relatives or strangers, as inheritance, either through a method called adfathamire, as the Salic form was named, or through writing or delivery.

The Lombards had a similar transfer, in which the donee was not only called heres, but was made liable like an heir for the debts of the donor on receiving the property after the donor's death. /2/2 By the Salic law a man who could not pay the wergeld was allowed to transfer formally his house-lot, and with it the liability. But the transfer was to the next of kin. /3/

The Lombards had a similar transfer, where the recipient was not only referred to as heres but was also held responsible like an heir for the donor's debts upon receiving the property after the donor's death. /2/2 According to Salic law, a man who couldn't pay the wergeld was permitted to formally transfer his property, along with the associated liability. However, the transfer had to be to the next of kin. /3/

The house-lot or family curtilage at first devolved strictly within the limits of the family. Here again, at least in England, freedom of alienation seems to have grown up by gradually increased latitude in the choice of successors. If we may trust the order of development to be noticed in the early charters, which it is hard to believe [358] accidental, although the charters are few, royal grants at first permitted an election of heirs among the kindred, and then extended it beyond them. In a deed of the year 679, the language is, "as it is granted so do you hold it and your posterity." One a century later reads, "which let him always possess, and after his death leave to which of his heirs he will." Another, "and after him with free power (of choice) leave to the man of his kin to whom he wishes to" (leave it). A somewhat earlier charter of 736 goes a step further: "So that as long as he lives he shall have the power of holding and possessing (and) of leaving it to whomsoever he choose, either in his lifetime, or certainly after his death." At the beginning of the ninth century the donee has power to leave the property to whomsoever he will, or, in still broader terms, to exchange or grant in his lifetime, and after his death to leave it to whom he chooses,—or to sell, exchange, and leave to whatsoever heir he chooses. /1/ This choice of heirs [359] recalls the quos heredes appellavit of the Salic law just mentioned, and may be compared with the language of a Norman charter of about the year 1190: "To W. and his heirs, to wit those whom he may constitute his heirs." /1/

The house lot or family property initially stayed strictly within the family. In England, it seems that the freedom to transfer ownership gradually developed through a broader choice of successors. If we look at the order of development noted in early charters—which is hard to believe is purely coincidental, even though there are few charters—royal grants initially allowed the selection of heirs among relatives and then extended it beyond them. In a deed from the year 679, it states, "as it is granted, so do you hold it and your descendants." One from a century later reads, "which let him always possess, and after his death leave to whichever of his heirs he chooses." Another says, "and after him, with full power (of choice), leave it to the person of his kin whom he wishes to." A somewhat earlier charter from 736 goes further: "So that as long as he lives, he shall have the power of holding and possessing (it), and of leaving it to whomever he chooses, either during his lifetime or certainly after his death." By the beginning of the ninth century, the recipient has the power to leave the property to anyone he wants, or, in even broader terms, to exchange or grant it during his lifetime, and after his death to leave it to whomever he wants—or to sell, exchange, and leave to any heir he chooses. This choice of heirs recalls the quos heredes appellavit of the Salic law just mentioned and can be compared to the language of a Norman charter from around the year 1190: "To W. and his heirs, specifically those whom he may designate as his heirs."

A perfect example of a singular succession worked out by the fiction of kinship is to be found in the story of Burnt Njal, an Icelandic saga, which gives us a living picture of a society hardly more advanced than the Salian Franks, as we see them in the Lex Salica. A lawsuit was to be transferred by the proper plaintiff to another more versed in the laws, and better able to carry it on,—in fact, to an attorney. But a lawsuit was at that time the alternative of a feud, and both were the peculiar affair of the family concerned. /2/ Accordingly, when a suit for killing a member of the family was to be handed over to a stranger, the innovation had to be reconciled with the theory that such suit belonged only to the next of kin. Mord is to take upon himself Thorgeir's suit against Flosi for killing Helgi, and the form of transfer is described as follows.

A great example of a unique succession created by the concept of kinship can be found in the story of Burnt Njal, an Icelandic saga that gives us a vivid picture of a society not much more advanced than the Salian Franks, as depicted in the Lex Salica. A lawsuit was to be transferred by the appropriate plaintiff to someone more knowledgeable about the laws and better equipped to handle it—in other words, to a lawyer. However, back then, a lawsuit was an alternative to a feud, and both were primarily the responsibility of the involved family. Therefore, when a case for the killing of a family member needed to be given to a stranger, the change had to align with the belief that such a case only belonged to the closest relatives. Mord is set to take on Thorgeir's case against Flosi for killing Helgi, and the process of transfer is described as follows.

"Then Mord took Thorgeir by the hand and named two witnesses to bear witness, 'that Thorgeir Thofir's son hands me over a suit for manslaughter against Flosi Thord's son, to plead it for the slaying of Helgi Njal's son, with all those proofs which have to follow the suit. Thou handest over to me this suit to plead and to settle, and to enjoy all rights in it, as though I were the rightful next of kin. Thou handest it over to me by law; and I [360] take it from thee by law.'" Afterwards, these witnesses come before the court, and bear witness to the transfer in like words: "He handed over to him then this suit, with all the proofs and proceedings which belonged to the suit, he handed it over to him to plead and to settle, and to make use of all rights, as though he were the rightful next of kin. Thorgeir handed it over lawfully, and Mord took it lawfully." The suit went on, notwithstanding the change of hands, as if the next of kin were plaintiff. This is shown by a further step in the proceedings. The defendant challenges two of the court, on the ground of their connection with Mord, the transferee, by blood and by baptism. But Mord replies that this is no good challenge; for "he challenged them not for their kinship to the true plaintiff, the next of kin, but for their kinship to him who pleaded the suit." And the other side had to admit that Mord was right in his law.

"Then Mord took Thorgeir by the hand and named two witnesses to testify, 'that Thorgeir Thofir's son hands me over a lawsuit for manslaughter against Flosi Thord's son, regarding the killing of Helgi Njal's son, along with all the evidence that follows the lawsuit. You are handing over this case to me to argue and resolve, and to enjoy all associated rights, as if I were the rightful next of kin. You are giving it to me legally; and I take it from you legally.'” Afterwards, these witnesses came before the court and testified to the handover in the same words: "He handed over to him this case, with all the evidence and proceedings that belonged to the case; he handed it over to him to argue and to resolve, and to make use of all rights, as if he were the rightful next of kin. Thorgeir handed it over lawfully, and Mord accepted it lawfully." The lawsuit continued as if the next of kin were the plaintiff, despite the change in parties. This was demonstrated by a further development in the proceedings. The defendant challenged two of the court members due to their relationship with Mord, the transferee, by blood and baptism. But Mord responded that this was not a valid challenge; for "he did not challenge them for their connection to the true plaintiff, the next of kin, but for their connection to the one who was arguing the case." The other side had to concede that Mord was correct in his legal argument.

I now turn from the German to the Roman sources. These have the closest connection with the argument, because much of the doctrine to be found there has been transplanted unchanged into modern law.

I now shift from the German to the Roman sources. These are most relevant to the argument because a lot of the principles found there have been transferred directly into modern law.

The early Roman law only recognized as relatives those who would have been members of the same patriarchal family, and under the same patriarchal authority, had the common ancestor survived. As wives passed into the families of their husbands, and lost all connection with that in which they were born, relationship through females was altogether excluded. The heir was one who traced his relationship to the deceased through males alone. With the advance of civilization this rule was changed. The praetor gave the benefits of the inheritance to the blood relations, although they were not heirs, and could [361] not be admitted to the succession according to the ancient law. /1/ But the change was not brought about by repealing the old law, which still subsisted under the name of the jus civile. The new principle was accommodated to the old forms by a fiction. The blood relation could sue on the fiction that he was an heir, although he was not one in fact. /2/

Early Roman law only recognized relatives as those who were part of the same patriarchal family and under the same patriarchal authority, assuming the common ancestor was still alive. Since wives moved into their husbands' families and lost all ties to their birth families, relationships through women were completely excluded. An heir was someone who traced their connection to the deceased strictly through males. However, as civilization progressed, this rule changed. The praetor granted inheritance rights to blood relatives, even if they were not considered heirs, and couldn't [361] be included in the succession according to the old law. /1/ This change didn’t come about by simply abolishing the old law, which continued to exist under the name of the jus civile. Instead, the new principle was creatively fitted into the old framework through a legal fiction. A blood relative could sue under the pretense that they were an heir, even though they were not one in reality. /2/

One the early forms of instituting an heir was a sale of the familia or headship of the family to the intended heir, with all its rights and duties. /3/ This sale of the universitas was afterwards extended beyond the case of inheritance to that of bankruptcy, when it was desired to put the bankrupt's property into the hands of a trustee for distribution. This trustee also could make use of the fiction, and sue as if he had been the bankrupt's heir. /4/ We are told by one of the great jurisconsults that in general universal successors stand in the place of heirs. /5/

One of the early ways to establish an heir was through the sale of the familia or headship of the family to the intended heir, along with all its rights and responsibilities. /3/ This sale of the universitas was later expanded beyond just inheritance to include bankruptcy, when it was necessary to place the bankrupt's property into the hands of a trustee for distribution. This trustee could also use the fiction and sue as if they were the bankrupt's heir. /4/ One of the leading legal experts tells us that generally, universal successors take the place of heirs. /5/

The Roman heir, with one or two exceptions, was always a universal successor; and the fiction of heirship, as such, could hardly be used with propriety except to enlarge the sphere of universal successions. So far as it extended, however, all the consequences attached to the original fiction of identity between heir and ancestor followed as of course.

The Roman heir, with a few exceptions, was always a universal successor; and the idea of heirship could hardly be used properly except to broaden the scope of universal successions. However far it extended, all the consequences connected to the original idea of identity between heir and ancestor naturally followed.

[362] To recur to the case of rights acquired by prescription, every universal successor could add the time of his predecessor's adverse use to his own in order to make out the right. There was no addition, legally speaking, but one continuous possession.

[362] When it comes to rights obtained through adverse possession, each universal successor could combine the time their predecessor’s adverse use with their own to establish the right. Legally, there wasn't an addition; it was one continuous possession.

The express fiction of inheritance perhaps stopped here. But when a similar joinder of times was allowed between a legatee or devisee (legatarius) and his testator, the same explanation was offered. It was said, that, when a specific thing was left to a person by will, so far as concerned having the benefit of the time during which the testator had been in possession for the purpose of acquiring a title, the legatee was in a certain sense quasi an heir. /1/ Yet a legatarius was not a universal successor, and for most purposes stood in marked contrast with such successors. /2/

The direct idea of inheritance probably ended here. However, when a similar connection of time was allowed between a beneficiary or heir and their testator, the same reasoning was provided. It was stated that when a specific item was left to someone in a will, regarding the benefit of the time during which the testator had been in possession to gain a title, the beneficiary was, in a way, almost like an heir. /1/ Still, a beneficiary was not a universal successor and, for most purposes, was quite different from those successors. /2/

Thus the strict law of inheritance had made the notion familiar that one man might have the advantage of a position filled by another, although it was not filled, or was only partially filled, by himself; and the second fiction, by which the privileges of a legal heir in this respect as well as others had been extended to other persons, broke down the walls which might otherwise have confined those privileges to a single case. A new conception was introduced into the law, and there was nothing to hinder its further application. As has been shown, it was applied in terms to a sale of the universitas for business purposes, and to at least one case where the succession was confined to a single specific thing. Why, then, might not every gift or sale be regarded as a succession, so far as to insure the same advantages?

The strict laws of inheritance had popularized the idea that one person could benefit from a position held by someone else, even if that position was unoccupied or only partially occupied by them. Additionally, the second concept, which extended the rights of a legal heir to others, broke down the barriers that might have limited those rights to just one scenario. A new idea was introduced into the law, and nothing stopped its further use. As previously mentioned, it was specifically applied to the sale of a business entity and at least one instance where inheritance was tied to a specific item. So, why shouldn’t every gift or sale be seen as a transfer of ownership, allowing for the same benefits?

[363] The joinder of times to make out a title was soon allowed between buyer and seller, and I have no doubt, from the language always used by the Roman lawyers, that it was arrived at in the way I have suggested. A passage from Scaevola (B. C. 30) will furnish sufficient proof. Joinder of possessions, he says, that is, the right to add the time of one's predecessor's holding to one's own, clearly belongs to those who succeed to the place of others, whether by contract or by will: for heirs and those who are treated as holding the place of successors are allowed to add their testator's possession to their own. Accordingly, if you sell me a slave I shall have the benefit of your holding. /1/

[363] The combining of time to establish a title was soon accepted between buyer and seller, and I believe, based on the language consistently used by Roman lawyers, that it came about in the way I suggested. A quote from Scaevola (B. C. 30) provides enough proof. He states that the joining of possessions, which means the right to add the time of one's predecessor's holding to one's own, clearly applies to those who take the place of others, whether through a contract or a will: heirs and those who are considered to be standing in for successors can add their testator's possession to their own. Therefore, if you sell me a slave, I will benefit from your previous ownership. /1/

The joinder of times is given to those who succeed to the place of another. Ulpian cites a like phrase from a jurisconsult of the time of the Antonines,—"to whose place I have succeeded by inheritance, or purchase, or any other right." /2/ Succedere in locum aliorum, like sustinere personam, is an expression of the Roman lawyers for those continuations of one man's legal position by another of which the type was the succession of heir to ancestor. Suecedere alone is used in the sense of inherit, /3/ and successio in that of "inheritance." /4/ The succession par excellence was the inheritance; and it is believed that scarcely any instance will be found in the Roman sources where "succession" does not convey that analogy, and indicate the partial [364] assumption, at least, of a persona formerly sustained by another. It clearly does so in the passage before us.

The combination of times applies to those who take the place of someone else. Ulpian cites a similar phrase from a legal expert during the time of the Antonines: "to whose place I have succeeded by inheritance, or purchase, or any other right." /2/ Succedere in locum aliorum, like sustinere personam, is a term used by Roman lawyers for the continuation of one person's legal position by another, exemplified by the heir succeeding the ancestor. Succedere is used to mean inherit /3/, and successio means "inheritance." /4/ The most prominent form of succession was inheritance; it's believed that there are few examples in Roman texts where "succession" doesn't convey this idea and at least suggests the partial [364] assumption of a persona previously held by another. This is clearly evident in the passage before us.

But the succession which admits a joinder of times is not hereditary succession alone. In the passage which has been cited Scaevola says that it may be by contract or purchase, as well as by inheritance or will. It may be singular, as well as universal. The jurists often mention antithetically universal successions and those confined to a single specific thing. Ulpian says that a man succeeds to another's place, whether his succession be universal or to the single object. /1/

But the succession that allows for a combination of times isn't just about hereditary succession. In the cited passage, Scaevola mentions that it can also come from a contract or purchase, in addition to inheritance or a will. It can be specific, as well as general. Legal experts often refer to universal successions versus those that are limited to a single item. Ulpian states that a person can take over another's position, whether their succession is universal or limited to one specific object. /1/

If further evidence were wanting for the present argument, it would be found in another expression of Ulpian's. He speaks of the benefit of joinder as derived from the persona of the grantor. "He to whom a thing is granted shall have the benefit of joinder from the persona of his grantor." /2/ A benefit cannot be derived from a persona except by sustaining it.

If more proof were needed for the current argument, it can be found in another statement by Ulpian. He talks about the benefit of joining as coming from the persona of the grantor. "The person to whom something is granted will receive the benefit of joining from the persona of their grantor." /2/ A benefit cannot come from a persona unless it is upheld.

It farther appears pretty plainly from Justinian's Institutes and the Digest, that the benefit was not extended to purchasers in all cases until a pretty late period. /3/

It seems pretty clear from Justinian's Institutes and the Digest that the benefit wasn't given to buyers in all cases until a relatively late time. /3/

Savigny very nearly expressed the truth when he said, somewhat broadly, that "every accessio, for whatever purpose, presupposes nothing else than a relation of juridical [365] succession between the previous and present possessor. For succession does not apply to possession by itself." /1/ And I may add, by way of further explanation, that every relation of juridical succession presupposes either an inheritance or a relation to which, so far as it extends, the analogies of the inheritance may be applied.

Savigny almost got it right when he said, somewhat broadly, that "every accessio, for whatever purpose, only implies a legal [365] relationship of succession between the previous and current possessor. Because succession doesn't just apply to possession on its own." /1/ Additionally, I'd like to explain further that every legal succession relationship assumes either an inheritance or a relationship where, to the extent that it applies, the principles of inheritance can be used.

The way of thinking which led to the accessio or joinder of times is equally visible in other cases. The time during which a former owner did not use an casement was imputed to the person who had succeeded to his place. /2/ The defence that the plaintiff had sold and delivered the thing in controversy was available not only to the purchaser, but to his heirs or to a second purchaser, even before delivery to him, against the successors of the seller, whether universal or only to the thing in question. /3/ If one used a way wrongfully as against the predecessor in title, it was wrongful as against the successor, whether by inheritance, purchase, or any other right. /4/ The formal oath of a party to an action was conclusive in favor of his successors, universal or singular. /5/ Successors by purchase or gift had the [366] benefit of agreements made with the vendor. /1/ A multitude of general expressions show that for most purposes, whether of action or defence, the buyer stood in the shoes of the seller, to use the metaphor of our own law. /2/ And what is more important than the result, which often might have been reached by other ways, the language and analogies are drawn throughout from the succession to the inheritance.

The way of thinking that led to the joining of times is also evident in other situations. The period during which a previous owner didn’t use an easement was assigned to the person who took over their position. The argument that the plaintiff had sold and delivered the item in question was valid not only for the buyer, but also for their heirs or a second buyer, even before it was delivered to them, against the seller’s successors, whether they were universal or only related to the specific item. If someone used a path unlawfully against the previous owner, it was also unlawful against the successor, whether by inheritance, purchase, or any other right. The formal oath of a party in a case was binding in favor of their successors, either universal or singular. Successors by purchase or gift had the [366] advantage of agreements made with the seller. A wide range of general terms indicates that for most purposes, whether for action or defense, the buyer took the place of the seller, to use a metaphor from our own law. And what’s even more significant than the result, which could often have been achieved through other means, is that the language and analogies are consistently drawn from succession to inheritance.

Thus understood, there could not have been a succession between a person dispossessed of a thing against his will and the wrongful possessor. Without the element of consent there is no room for the analogy just explained. Accordingly, it is laid down that there is no joinder of times when the possession is wrongful, /3/ and the only enumerated means of succeeding in rem are by will, sale, gift, or some other right.

Thus understood, there couldn't have been a transfer between someone who was deprived of something against their will and the person wrongfully possessing it. Without consent, there's no space for the analogy mentioned earlier. Therefore, it's established that there’s no connection of times when possession is wrongful, and the only recognized ways to succeed in rem are through will, sale, gift, or some other right.

The argument now returns to the English law, fortified with some general conclusions. It has been shown that in both the systems from whose union our law arose the rules governing conveyance, or the transfer of specific [367] objects between living persons, were deeply affected by notions drawn from inheritance. It had been shown previously that in England the principles of inheritance applied directly to the singular succession of the heir to a specific fee, as well as to the universal succession of the executor. It would be remarkable, considering their history, if the same principles had not affected other singular successions also. It will soon appear that they have. And not to be too careful about the order of proof, I will first take up the joinder of times in prescription, as that has just been so fully discussed. The English law of the subject is found on examination to be the same as the Roman in extent, reason, and expression. It is indeed largely copied from that source. For servitudes, such as rights of way, light, and the like, form the chief class of prescriptive rights, and our law of servitudes is mainly Roman. Prescriptions, it is said, "are properly personal, and therefore are always alleged in the person of him who prescribes, viz. that he and all those whose estate he hath, &c.; therefore, a bishop or a parson may prescribe,... for there is a perpetual estate, and a perpetual succession and the successor hath the very same estate which his predecessor had, for that continues, though the person alters, like the case of the ancestor and the heir." /1/ So in a modern case, where by statute twenty years' dispossession extinguished the owner's title, the Court of Queen's Bench said that probably the right would be transferred to the possessor "if the same person, or several persons, claiming one from the other by descent, will [368] or conveyance, had been in possession for the twenty years." "But.... such twenty years' possession must be either by the same person, or several persons claiming one from the other, which is not the case here." /1/

The discussion now shifts back to English law, supported by some general conclusions. It has been demonstrated that in both legal systems that contributed to our law, the rules governing conveyance, or the transfer of specific [367] objects between living individuals, were significantly influenced by ideas from inheritance. It was previously shown that in England, the principles of inheritance applied directly to the individual succession of an heir to a specific fee, as well as to the overall succession of an executor. It would be surprising, given their history, if the same principles didn’t impact other individual successions as well. It will soon be evident that they have. Without being overly cautious about the sequence of proof, I will first address the joining of times in prescription, as that has just been thoroughly discussed. An examination shows that English law on this issue aligns with Roman law in terms of scope, reasoning, and expression. In fact, it is largely derived from that source. For example, servitudes, such as rights of way, light, and similar rights, are the main category of prescriptive rights, and our law regarding servitudes is primarily Roman. It is stated that "prescriptions are properly personal, and therefore are always claimed in the name of the person who prescribes, namely that he and all those who hold his estate, etc.; thus, a bishop or a parson can prescribe,... because there is a perpetual estate and perpetual succession, and the successor has the exact same estate as his predecessor, as that continues even though the individual changes, similar to the case of the ancestor and the heir." /1/ In a more recent case, where a statute holds that twenty years of dispossession eliminates the owner’s title, the Court of Queen's Bench mentioned that likely the right would be transferred to the possessor "if the same person, or multiple persons, claiming one from the other by descent, will [368] or conveyance, had been in possession for those twenty years." "However.... such twenty years of possession must either be by the same individual or multiple individuals claiming one from the other, which is not the situation here." /1/

In a word, it is equally clear that the continuous possession of privies in title, or, in Roman phrase, successors, has all the effect of the continuous possession of one, and that such an effect is not attributed to the continuous possession of different persons who are not in the same chain of title. One who dispossesses another of land cannot add the time during which his disseisee has used a way to the period of his own use, while one who purchased can. /2/

In short, it’s clear that continuously owning property through title, or what the Romans called successors, has the same effect as continuously owning it alone. However, this doesn’t apply to different people who aren’t in the same ownership chain. If someone takes land from another person, they can’t count the time the dispossessed individual has used a path towards their own usage period, but someone who bought the land can. /2/

The authorities which have been quoted make it plain that the English law proceeds on the same theory as the Roman. One who buys land of another gets the very same estate which his seller had. He is in of the same fee, or hereditas, which means, as I have shown, that he sustains the same persona. On the other hand, one who wrongfully dispossesses another,—a disseisor,—gets a different estate, is in of a new fee, although the land is the same; and much technical reasoning is based upon this doctrine.

The authorities cited clearly indicate that English law operates on the same principle as Roman law. When someone buys land from another person, they receive the exact same rights that the seller had. They are part of the same ownership, or hereditas, which means, as I’ve explained, that they maintain the same persona. Conversely, someone who wrongfully takes land from another—known as a disseisor—acquires a different set of rights, entering into a new ownership, even though the land remains unchanged; and a lot of technical reasoning is built upon this principle.

In the matter of prescription, therefore, buyer and seller were identified, like heir and ancestor. But the question [369] remains whether this identification bore fruit in other parts of the law also, or whether it was confined to one particular branch, where the Roman law was grafted upon the English stock.

In the issue of prescription, buyer and seller were seen as equivalent to heir and ancestor. However, the question [369] remains whether this equivalence also applied to other areas of the law, or if it was limited to one specific area where Roman law was integrated into English law.

There can be no doubt which answer is most probable, but it cannot be proved without difficulty. As has been said, the heir ceased to be the general representative of his ancestor at an early date. And the extent to which even he was identified came to be a matter of discussion. Common sense kept control over fiction here as elsewhere in the common law. But there can be no doubt that in matters directly concerning the estate the identification of heir and ancestor has continued to the present day; and as an estate in fee simple has been shown to be a distinct persona, we should expect to find a similar identification of buyer and seller in this part of the law, if anywhere.

There’s no doubt which answer is most likely, but proving it isn’t easy. As mentioned, the heir stopped being the general representative of their ancestor a long time ago. The degree to which even the heir was identified became a topic of debate. Common sense has always kept fiction in check, both here and in other areas of common law. However, it’s clear that in matters directly related to the estate, the identification of heir and ancestor still exists today; and since an estate in fee simple has been shown to be its own entity, we would expect to see a similar identification of buyer and seller in this aspect of the law, if anywhere.

Where the land was devised by will, the analogy applied with peculiar ease. For although there is no difference in principle between a devise of a piece of land by will and a conveyance of it by deed, the dramatic resemblance of a devisee to an heir is stronger than that of a grantee. It will be remembered that one of the Roman jurists said that a legatarius (legatee or devisee) was in a certain sense quasi heres. The English courts have occasionally used similar expressions. In a case where a testator owned a rent, and divided it by will among his sons, and then one of the sons brought debt for his part, two of the judges, while admitting that the testator could not have divided the tenant's liability by a grant or deed in his lifetime, thought that it was otherwise with regard to a division by will. Their reasoning was that "the devise is quasi [370] an act of law, which shall inure without attornment, and shall make a sufficient privity, and so it may well be apportioned by this means." /1/ So it was said by Lord Ellenborough, in a case where a lessor and his heirs were entitled to terminate a lease on notice, that a devisee of the land as heres factus would be understood to have the same right. /2/

Where land was given through a will, the comparison was particularly straightforward. Although there's no fundamental difference between transferring a piece of land by will and doing so by deed, the similarity between a person who receives a gift through a will and an heir is stronger than that of a person who receives it through a deed. One of the Roman legal scholars noted that a legatarius (the person receiving the gift or devisee) is, in a certain sense, like an heir. English courts have occasionally used similar terms. In a case where a testator owned a rent and divided it among his sons in his will, one of the sons later sued for his share. Two judges, while recognizing that the testator couldn’t have similarly divided the tenant's obligation through a grant or deed during his lifetime, believed that the situation was different when it came to a division through a will. Their reasoning was that "the devise is quasi an act of law, which shall take effect without formal acceptance and shall create sufficient legal connection, and therefore can be apportioned in this way." So, Lord Ellenborough mentioned in a case where a lessor and his heirs had the right to end a lease with notice that a devisee of the land would also be understood to have the same right.

But wills of land were only exceptionally allowed by custom until the reign of Henry VIII., and as the main doctrines of conveyancing had been settled long before that time, we must look further back and to other sources for their explanation. We shall find it in the history of warranty. This, and the modern law of covenants running with the land, will be treated in the next Lecture.

But land wills were only occasionally accepted by custom until the reign of Henry VIII., and since the main principles of property transfer were established long before that, we need to look further back and to different sources for their explanation. We'll find it in the history of warranty. This, along with the modern law of covenants linked to the land, will be discussed in the next Lecture.





LECTURE XI. — SUCCESSIONS.—II. INTER VIVOS.

The principal contracts known to the common law and suable in the King's Courts, a century after the Conquest, were suretyship and debt. The heir, as the general representative of his ancestor's rights and obligations, was liable for his debts, and was the proper person to sue for those which were due the estate. By the time of Edward III. this had changed. Debts had ceased to concern the heir except secondarily. The executor took his place both for collection and payment. It is said that even when the heir was bound he could not be sued except in case the executor had no assets. /1/

The main contracts recognized by common law and actionable in the King’s Courts, a century after the Conquest, were suretyship and debt. The heir, as the general representative of their ancestor's rights and obligations, was responsible for their debts and was the right person to sue for those owed to the estate. By the time of Edward III, this had changed. Debts no longer primarily concerned the heir. The executor took over for both collecting and paying them. It’s said that even when the heir was obligated, they could only be sued if the executor had no assets. /1/

But there was another ancient obligation which had a different history. I refer to the warranty which arose upon the transfer of property. We should call it a contract, but it probably presented itself to the mind of Glanvill's predecessors simply as a duty or obligation attached by law to a transaction which was directed to a different point; just as the liability of a bailee, which is now treated as arising from his undertaking, was originally raised by the law out of the position in which he stood toward third persons.

But there was another old obligation that had a different background. I'm talking about the warranty that came with the transfer of property. We would call it a contract today, but it likely appeared to Glanvill's predecessors simply as a responsibility or obligation imposed by law on a transaction aimed at a different goal; just like the responsibility of a bailee, which is now seen as stemming from their agreement, was originally established by law based on their position relative to third parties.

After the Conquest we do not hear much of warranty, except in connection with land, and this fact will at once [372] account for its having had a different history from debt. The obligation of warranty was to defend the title, and, if the defence failed, to give to the evicted owner other land of equal value. If an ancestor had conveyed lands with warranty, this obligation could not be fulfilled by his executor, but only by his heir, to whom his other lands had descended. Conversely as to the benefit of warranties made to a deceased grantee, his heir was the only person interested to enforce such warranties, because the land descended to him. Thus the heir continued to represent his ancestor in the latter's rights and obligations by way of warranty, after the executor had relieved him of the debts, just as before that time he had represented his ancestor in all respects.

After the Conquest, we don't hear much about warranties except in relation to land, which explains why it had a different history compared to debt. The warranty obligation was to defend the title, and if that defense failed, to provide the evicted owner with other land of equal value. If an ancestor had transferred land with a warranty, this obligation couldn’t be fulfilled by his executor, but only by his heir, who inherited his other lands. On the other hand, for the warranties made to a deceased grantee, only his heir had the right to enforce those warranties because the land went to him. In this way, the heir continued to represent his ancestor in their rights and obligations through the warranty, after the executor had taken care of the debts, just as he had represented him in all other matters before.

If a man was sued for property which he had bought from another, the regular course of litigation was for the defendant to summon in his seller to take charge of the defence, and for him, in turn, to summon in his, if he had one, and so on until a party was reached in the chain of title who finally took the burden of the case upon himself. A contrast which was early stated between the Lombard and the Roman law existed equally between the Anglo-Saxon and the Roman. It was said that the Lombard presents his grantor, the Roman stands in his grantor's shoes,—Langobardus dat auctorem, Romanus stat loco auctoris. /1/

If a person was sued for property they had purchased from someone else, the usual legal process involved the defendant calling in their seller to handle the defense, and that seller would then call in their own seller, if there was one, and so on, until a party in the chain of ownership stepped up to take on the responsibility of the case. A difference that was noted early on between Lombard and Roman law was also present between Anglo-Saxon and Roman law. It was said that the Lombard presents their grantor, while the Roman stands in for their grantor—Langobardus dat auctorem, Romanus stat loco auctoris. /1/

Suppose, now, that A gave land to B, and B conveyed over to C. If C was sued by D, claiming a better title, C practically got the benefit of A's warranty, /2/ because, when he summoned B, B would summon A, and thus A [373] would defend the case in the end. But it might happen that between the time when B conveyed to C, and the time when the action was begun, B had died. If he left an heir, C might still be protected. But supposing B left no heir, C got no help from A, who in the other event would have defended his suit. This no doubt was the law in the Anglo-Saxon period, but it was manifestly unsatisfactory. We may conjecture, with a good deal of confidence, that a remedy would be found as soon as there was machinery to make it possible. This was furnished by the Roman law. According to that system, the buyer stood in the place of his seller, and a fusion of the Roman with the Anglo-Saxon rule was all that was needed.

Imagine that A gave land to B, and then B transferred it to C. If D sued C, claiming he had a better title, C essentially benefited from A's warranty because, when C brought B into the suit, B would bring A in, and A would defend the case in the end. However, it's possible that by the time B transferred the land to C and when the lawsuit started, B had died. If B left an heir, C might still be protected. But if B left no heir, C wouldn’t get help from A, who would have defended against the lawsuit otherwise. This was definitely the law during the Anglo-Saxon period, but it was obviously inadequate. We can reasonably guess that a solution would be created once there was a system to make it feasible. This was provided by Roman law. According to that system, the buyer took the place of the seller, and a combination of the Roman and Anglo-Saxon rules was all that was needed.

Bracton, who modelled his book upon the writings of the mediaeval civilians, shows how this thought was used. He first puts the case of a conveyance with the usual clause binding the grantor and his heirs to warrant and defend the grantee and his heirs. He then goes on: "Again one may make his gift greater and make other persons quasi heirs [of his grantee], although, in fact, they are not heirs, as when he says in the gift, to have and to hold to such a one and his heirs, or to whomsoever he shall choose to give or assign the said land, and I and my heirs will warrant to the said so and so, and his heirs, or to whomsoever he shall choose to give or assign the said land, and their heirs, against all persons. In which case if the grantee shall have given or assigned the land, and then have died without heirs, the [first] grantor and his heirs begin to hold the place of the first grantee and his heirs, and are in place of the first grantee's heir (pro herede) so far as concerns warranting to his assigns and their heirs [374] according to the clause contained in the first grantor's charter, which would not be but for the mention of assigns in the first gift. But so long as the first grantee survives, or his heirs, they are held to warranty, and not the first grantor." /1/

Bracton, who based his book on the writings of medieval lawyers, demonstrates how this idea was applied. He starts with a case involving a transfer that includes the usual clause binding the grantor and his heirs to protect and defend the grantee and his heirs. He continues: "Moreover, one can expand his gift and designate other people as quasi-heirs [of his grantee], even though they aren't actually heirs, as when he states in the gift that it is to be held by a certain individual and his heirs, or by anyone he chooses to give or assign the said land to, and I and my heirs will guarantee the said individual and his heirs, or anyone he decides to give or assign the said land to, and their heirs, against all others. In this situation, if the grantee has given or assigned the land and then dies without heirs, the [first] grantor and his heirs step into the shoes of the first grantee and his heirs and take the place of the first grantee's heir (pro herede) regarding the obligation to warrant to his assigns and their heirs [374] according to the clause in the first grantor's charter, which would not apply if assigns were not mentioned in the initial gift. However, as long as the first grantee or his heirs are alive, they are bound to warranty, not the first grantor." /1/

Here we see that, in order to entitle the assign to the benefit of the first grantor's warranty, assigns must be mentioned in the original grant and covenant. The scope of the ancient obligation was not extended without the warrantor's assent. But when it was extended, it was not by a contrivance like a modern letter of credit. Such a conception would have been impossible in that stage of the law. By mentioning assigns the first grantor did not offer a covenant to any person who would thereafter purchase the land. If that had been the notion, there would have been a contract directly binding the first grantor to the assign, as soon as the land was sold, and thus there would have been two warranties arising from the same clause,—one to the first grantee, a second to the assign. But in fact the assign recovered on the original warranty to the first grantee. /2/ He could only come on the first grantor after a failure of his immediate grantor's heirs. The first grantor by mentioning assigns simply enlarged the limits of his grantee's succession. The assign could vouch the first grantor only on the principles of succession. That is to say, he could only do so when, by the failure of the first grantee's blood, the first grantee's feudal relation to the first grantor, his persona, came to be sustained by the assign. /3/

Here we see that, to give the assignee the benefit of the first grantor's warranty, the assignees need to be mentioned in the original grant and agreement. The extent of the old obligation wasn't expanded without the warrantor's consent. But when it was expanded, it wasn't through something like a modern letter of credit. Such an idea would have been unthinkable back then. By mentioning assignees, the first grantor didn't create a guarantee to anyone who might later buy the land. If that had been the case, there would be a contract that directly bound the first grantor to the assignee as soon as the land was sold, leading to two warranties from the same clause—one to the first grantee and another to the assignee. In reality, the assignee relied on the original warranty to the first grantee. He could only pursue the first grantor after his immediate grantor's heirs failed. By mentioning assignees, the first grantor simply expanded the limits of his grantee's inheritance. The assignee could only call upon the first grantor based on the principles of inheritance. In other words, he could only do this when, through the failure of the first grantee's lineage, the first grantee's feudal relationship with the first grantor—that is, his status—was upheld by the assignee.

[375] This was not only carrying out the fiction with technical consistency, but was using it with good sense, as fictions generally have been used in the English law. Practically it made little difference whether the assign got the benefit of the first grantor's warranty mediately or immediately, if he got it. The trouble arose where he could not summon the mesne grantor, and the new right was given him for that case alone. Later, the assign did not have to wait for the failure of his immediate grantor's blood, but could take advantage of the first grantor's warranty from the beginning. /1/

[375] This was not just about applying the fiction consistently; it was also about using it wisely, as fictions have typically been applied in English law. In practice, it made little difference whether the assignee benefited from the first grantor's warranty directly or indirectly, as long as he received it. The issue arose when he couldn't bring the mesne grantor into the picture, and the new right was established just for that situation. Later on, the assignee didn’t need to wait for the death of his immediate grantor to benefit; he could rely on the first grantor's warranty from the outset. /1/

If it should be suggested that what has been said goes to show that the first grantor's duty to warrant arose from the assign's becoming his man and owing homage, the answer is that he was not bound unless he had mentioned assigns in his grant, homage or no homage. In this Bracton is confirmed by all the later authorities. /2/

If someone suggests that what has been said proves the first grantor's responsibility to guarantee came from the assignee becoming his follower and owing loyalty, the response is that he wasn't obligated unless he specifically included assignees in his grant, whether there was loyalty or not. This is backed up by all the later authorities according to Bracton. /2/

Another rule on which there are vast stores of forgotten learning will show how exactly the fiction fell in with the earlier law. Only those who were privy in estate with the person to whom the warranty was originally given, could vouch the original warrantor. Looking back to the early [376] procedure, it will be seen that of course only those in the same chain of title could even mediately get the benefit of a former owner's warranty. The ground on which a man was bound to warrant was that he had conveyed the property to the person who summoned him. Hence a man could summon no one but his grantor, and the successive vouchers came to an end when the last vouchee could not call on another from whom he had bought. Now when the process was abridged, no persons were made liable to summons who would not have been liable before. The present owner was allowed to vouch directly those who otherwise would have been indirectly bound to defend his title, but no others. Hence he could only summon those from whom his grantor derived his title. But this was equally well expressed in terms of the fiction employed. In order to vouch, the present owner must have the estate of the person to whom the warranty was made. As every lawyer knows, the estate does not mean the land. It means the status or persona in regard to that land formerly sustained by another. The same word was used in alleging a right by prescription, "that he and those whose estate he hath have for time whereof memory runneth not to the contrary," &c.; and it will be remembered that the word corresponds to the same requirement of succession there.

Another rule that holds a wealth of forgotten knowledge will show how closely the fiction matched the earlier law. Only those who shared a legal relationship with the person to whom the warranty was originally given could vouch for the original warrantor. Looking back at early procedures, it's clear that only those within the same chain of title could even indirectly benefit from a former owner's warranty. A person was obligated to warrant because they had transferred the property to the person who summoned them. Therefore, one could only summon their grantor, and the succession of vouchers ended when the last voucher could no longer call upon another from whom they had purchased. Now, with the simplified process, no one became liable to summons who wouldn't have been liable before. The current owner was allowed to vouch directly for those who otherwise would have been indirectly required to defend their title, but no one else. Thus, they could only summon those from whom their grantor obtained their title. However, this was just as well expressed in terms of the fiction used. To vouch, the current owner must have the estate of the person to whom the warranty was granted. As every lawyer knows, the estate doesn’t refer to the land itself. It refers to the status or legal standing regarding that land that was previously held by another. The same term was used in claiming a right by prescription, "that he and those whose estate he has have held for a time that cannot be disputed," etc.; and it's important to remember that this term corresponds to the same requirement of succession there.

To return to Bracton, it must be understood that the description of assigns as quasi heredes is not accidental. He describes them in that way whenever he has occasion to speak of them. He even pushes the reasoning drawn from the analogy of inheritance to extremes, and refers to it in countless passages. For instance: "It should be noted that of heirs some are true heirs and some quasi [377] heirs, in place of heirs, &c.; true heirs by way of succession quasi heirs, &c. by the form of the gift; such as assigns," &c. /1/

To revisit Bracton, it's important to recognize that his description of assigns as quasi heirs isn’t random. He uses this term consistently whenever he mentions them. He even takes the reasoning based on the analogy of inheritance to extremes, referencing it in numerous passages. For example: "It should be noted that some heirs are true heirs while others are quasi heirs, instead of heirs, etc.; true heirs through succession, quasi heirs, etc., by the nature of the gift; such as assigns," etc. /1/

If it should be suggested that Bracton's language is only a piece of mediaeval scholasticism, there are several answers. In the first place it is nearly contemporaneous with the first appearance of the right in question. This is shown by his citing authority for it as for something which might be disputed. He says, "And that warranty must be made to assigns according to the form of the gift is proved [by a case] in the circuit of W. de Ralegh, about the end of the roll,"&c. /2/ It is not justifiable to assume that a contemporary explanation of a new rule had nothing to do with its appearance. Again, the fact is clear that the assign got the benefit of the warranty to the first grantee, not of a new one to himself, as has been shown, and Bracton's explanation of how this was worked out falls in with what has been seen of the course of the German and Anglo-Saxon law, and with the pervading thought of the Roman law. Finally, and most important, the requirement that the assign should be in of the first grantee's estate has remained a requirement from that day to this. The fact that the same thing is required in the same words as in prescription goes far to show that the same technical thought has governed both.

If someone suggests that Bracton's language is just another case of medieval scholasticism, there are several responses. First, it is almost contemporary with the emergence of the right in question. This is evident as he cites authority for it as something that could be challenged. He states, "And that warranty must be made to assigns according to the form of the gift is proved [by a case] in the circuit of W. de Ralegh, about the end of the roll,"&c. /2/ It's not justified to assume that a contemporary explanation of a new rule had nothing to do with its introduction. Furthermore, it's clear that the assign benefited from the warranty to the first grantee, not from a new one for himself, as previously shown, and Bracton's explanation of how this was achieved aligns with what has been observed in the development of German and Anglo-Saxon law, as well as with the overarching principles of Roman law. Lastly, and most importantly, the requirement that the assign must be involved in the first grantee's estate has remained a constant requirement from that time to the present. The fact that the same stipulation is expressed in the same terms as in prescription strongly indicates that the same technical reasoning has influenced both.

I have said, Glanvill's predecessors probably regarded warranty as an obligation incident to a conveyance, rather than as a contract. But when it became usual to insert the undertaking to warrant in a deed or charter of feoffment, it lost something of its former isolation as a duty standing by itself, and admitted of being [378] generalized. It was a promise by deed, and a promise by deed was a covenant. /1/ This was a covenant having peculiar consequences attached to it, no doubt. It differed also in the scope of its obligation from some other covenants, as will be shown hereafter. But still it was a covenant, and could sometimes be sued on as such. It was spoken of in the Year Books of Edward III. as a covenant which "falls in the blood," /2/ as distinguished from those where the acquittance fell on the land, and not on the person. /3/

I have mentioned that Glanvill's predecessors likely saw warranty as an obligation related to a conveyance, rather than as a contract. However, when it became common to include the promise to warrant in a deed or charter of feoffment, it shifted away from being a standalone duty and could be [378] generalized. It was a promise made by deed, and a promise made by deed was considered a covenant. /1/ This was a covenant with specific consequences attached to it, of course. It also had a different scope of obligation compared to some other covenants, as will be explained later. But still, it was a covenant, and it could sometimes be enforced as such. In the Year Books of Edward III., it was referred to as a covenant that "falls in the blood," /2/ distinguishing it from those where the acquittance was tied to the land, rather than to the person. /3/

The importance of this circumstance lies in the working of the law of warranty upon other covenants which took its place. When the old actions for land gave way to more modern and speedier forms, warrantors were no longer vouched in to defend, and if a grantee was evicted, damages took the place of a grant of other land. The ancient warranty disappeared, and was replaced by the covenants which we still find in our deeds, including the covenants for seisin, for right to convey, against incumbrances, for quiet enjoyment, of warranty, and for further assurance. But the principles on which an assign could have the benefit of these covenants were derived from those which governed warranty, as any one may see by looking at the earlier decisions.

The significance of this situation lies in how the law of warranty impacted other agreements that replaced it. As the old property actions transitioned to more modern and efficient methods, warrantors were no longer called upon to defend, and if a grantee faced eviction, monetary damages became the substitute for a grant of alternative land. The traditional warranty faded away, replaced by the agreements we still see in our deeds, such as covenants for seisin, the right to convey, protection against encumbrances, quiet enjoyment, warranty, and further assurance. However, the principles allowing an assignee to benefit from these covenants originated from those governing warranty, which is apparent when examining earlier rulings.

For instance, the question, what was a sufficient assignment to give an assign the benefit of a covenant for quiet enjoyment, was argued and decided on the authority of the old cases of warranty. /4/

For example, the question of what constituted a sufficient assignment to transfer the benefit of a covenant for quiet enjoyment was debated and resolved based on the precedent of the older warranty cases. /4/

[379] The assign, as in warranty, came in under the old covenant with the first covenantee, not by any new right of his own. Thus, in an action by an assign on a covenant for further assurance, the defendant set up a release by the original covenantee after the commencement of the suit. The court held that the assignee should have the benefit of the covenant. "They held, that although the breach was in the time of the assignee, yet if the release had been by the covenantee (who is a party to the deed, and from whom the plaintiff derives) before any breach, or before the suit commenced, it had been a good bar to the assignee from bringing this writ of covenant. But the breach of the covenant being in the time of the assignee,... and the action brought by him, and so attached in his person, the covenantee cannot release this action wherein the assignee is interested." /1/ The covenantee even after assignment remains the legal party to the contract. The assign comes in under him, and does not put an end to his control over it, until by breach and action a new right attaches in the assign's person, distinct from the rights derived from the persona of his grantor. Later, the assign got a more independent standing, as the original foundation of his rights sunk gradually out of sight, and a release after assignment became ineffectual, at least in the case of a covenant to pay rent. /2/

[379] The assignment, similar to a warranty, was based on the old agreement with the first party involved, not because of any new right he had. So, in a case where an assignee took legal action on a covenant for further assurance, the defendant brought up a release made by the original party after the lawsuit had started. The court decided that the assignee should benefit from the covenant. "They decided that even though the breach occurred during the assignee's time, if the release had been made by the original party (who is part of the agreement, and from whom the plaintiff comes) before any breach or before the lawsuit began, it would have effectively prevented the assignee from pursuing this legal action. But since the breach happened during the assignee's time,... and the case was brought by him, and thus concerned him directly, the original party cannot release this action in which the assignee has a stake." /1/ The original party remains the legal party to the contract even after the assignment. The assignee comes in under him and does not end his control over the contract until a breach and a legal action create a new right in the assignee that is separate from the rights inherited from his grantor. Eventually, the assignee gained a more independent position as the basis of his rights faded away, and a release after the assignment became ineffective, especially in cases involving a covenant to pay rent. /2/

Only privies in estate with the original covenantee can have the benefit of covenants for title. It has been shown that a similar limitation of the benefits of the ancient [380] warranty was required by its earlier history before the assign was allowed to sue, and that the fiction by which he got that right could not extend it beyond that limit. This analogy also was followed. For instance, a tenant in tail male made a lease for years with covenants of right to let and for quiet enjoyment, and then died without issue male. The lessee assigned the lease to the plaintiff. The latter was soon turned out, and thereupon brought an action upon the covenant against the executor of the lessor. It was held that he could not recover, because he was not privy in estate with the original covenantee. For the lease, which was the original covenantee's estate, was ended by the death of the lessor and termination of the estate tail out of which the lease was granted, before the form of assignment to the plaintiff. /1/

Only those who have a direct connection to the original person who made the agreement can benefit from covenants related to the title. It has been established that a similar restriction on the benefits of the ancient [380] warranty was needed based on its earlier history before the assignee was allowed to sue, and that the fictional right by which they obtained that right could not extend beyond that limit. This analogy was also followed. For example, a tenant in tail male created a lease for years that included rights to sublet and for quiet enjoyment, and then died without male heirs. The lessee transferred the lease to the plaintiff. The plaintiff was soon evicted and subsequently filed a lawsuit on the covenant against the executor of the lessor. It was determined that he could not recover because he did not have a direct connection to the original covenantee. The lease, which was the original covenantee's estate, ended with the lessor's death and the termination of the estate tail from which the lease was granted, before the assignment to the plaintiff was made. /1/

The only point remaining to make the analogy between covenants for title and warranty complete was to require assigns to be mentioned in order to enable them to sue. In modern times, of course, such a requirement, if it should exist, would be purely formal, and would be of no importance except as an ear-mark by which to trace the history of a doctrine. It would aid our studies if we could say that wherever assigns are to get the benefit of a covenant as privies in estate with the covenantee, they must be mentioned in the covenant. Whether such a requirement does exist or not would be hard to tell from the decisions alone. It is commonly supposed not to. But the popular opinion on this trifling point springs from a failure to understand one of the great antinomies of the law, which must now be explained.

The only point left to make the comparison between title and warranty covenants complete is that assigns need to be mentioned so they can sue. Nowadays, if such a requirement existed, it would only be a formality and wouldn’t matter much except as a way to track the evolution of a legal principle. It would help our studies if we could assert that wherever assigns are entitled to the benefits of a covenant as those closely associated with the covenantee, they need to be named in the covenant. Whether or not such a requirement actually exists is difficult to determine just from the court rulings. It’s generally thought that it doesn’t. However, this common belief about this minor issue comes from a misunderstanding of one of the major contradictions in the law, which needs to be clarified now.

So far as we have gone, we have found that, wherever [381] one party steps into the rights or obligations of another, without in turn filling the situation of fact of which those rights or obligations are the legal consequences, the substitution is explained by a fictitious identification of the two individuals, which is derived from the analogy of the inheritance. This identification has been seen as it has been consciously worked out in the creation of the executor, whose entire status is governed by it. It has been seen still consciously applied in the narrower sphere of the heir. It has been found hidden at the root of the relation between buyer and seller in two cases at least, prescription and warranty, when the history of that relation is opened to a sufficient depth.

So far, we've discovered that whenever one party takes on the rights or responsibilities of another, without actually stepping into the factual situation that gave rise to those rights or responsibilities, this replacement is explained by a made-up identification of the two people, which is based on the concept of inheritance. This identification has been clearly illustrated in the role of the executor, whose entire position is defined by it. It's also seen in the more specific role of the heir. Additionally, it can be found at the core of the relationship between buyer and seller in at least two situations: prescription and warranty, when we look deeply enough into the history of that relationship.

But although it would be more symmetrical if this analysis exhausted the subject, there is another class of cases in which the transfer of rights takes place upon a wholly different plan. In explaining the succession which is worked out between buyer and seller for the purpose of creating a prescriptive right, such as a right of way over neighboring land to the land bought and sold, it was shown that one who, instead of purchasing the land, had wrongfully possessed himself of it by force, would not be treated as a successor, and would get no benefit from the previous use of the way by his disseisee. But when the former possessor has already gained a right of way before he is turned out, a new principle comes into operation. If the owner of the land over which the way ran stopped it up, and was sued by the wrongful possessor, a defence on the ground that the disseisor had not succeeded to the former owner's rights would not prevail. The disseisor would be protected in his possession of the land against all but the rightful owner, and he would equally be protected [382] in his use of the way. This rule of law does not stand on a succession between the wrongful possessor and the owner, which is out of the question. Neither can it be defended on the same ground as the protection to the occupation of the land itself. That ground is that the law defends possession against everything except a better title. But, as has been said before, the common law does not recognize possession of a way. A man who has used a way ten years without title cannot sue even a stranger for stopping it. He was a trespasser at the beginning, he is nothing but a trespasser still. There must exist a right against the servient owner before there is a right against anybody else. At the same time it is clear that a way is no more capable of possession because somebody else has a right to it, than if no one had.

But even though it would be more balanced if this analysis covered the entire topic, there’s another type of situation where the transfer of rights follows a completely different approach. When explaining the relationship between buyer and seller to create a prescriptive right, like a right of way over nearby land to the land that was bought and sold, it was noted that someone who wrongfully took possession of the land by force wouldn’t be considered a successor and wouldn’t benefit from the previous use of the path by the rightful owner. However, if the previous possessor had already established a right of way before being pushed out, a new principle applies. If the landowner who owned the land where the path existed blocked it and was sued by the wrongful possessor, a defense based on the idea that the wrongful possessor hadn't inherited the previous owner's rights wouldn't hold up. The wrongful possessor would be protected in their possession of the land against everyone except the rightful owner, and they would also be equally protected in their use of the path. This legal principle isn’t based on a transfer of rights between the wrongful possessor and the owner, which isn't relevant here. Nor can it be justified on the same basis as the protection of the land itself. That justification is that the law protects possession against all claims except those backed by a better title. But, as mentioned earlier, common law doesn’t recognize possession of a way. A person who uses a path for ten years without a title can’t even sue a stranger for blocking it. They were a trespasser from the start, and they remain just a trespasser. A right against the servient owner must exist before there’s any right against anyone else. At the same time, it's clear that a path can’t be possessed just because someone else has a right to it, any more than it could if no one did.

How comes it, then, that one who has neither title nor possession is so far favored? The answer is to be found, not in reasoning, but in a failure to reason. In the first Lecture of this course the thought with which we have to deal was shown in its theological stage, to borrow Comte's well-known phraseology, as where an axe was made the object of criminal process; and also in the metaphysical stage, where the language of personification alone survived, but survived to cause confusion of reasoning. The case put seems to be an illustration of the latter. The language of the law of easements was built up out of similes drawn from persons at a time when the noxoe deditio was still familiar; and then, as often happens, language reacted upon thought, so that conclusions were drawn as to the rights themselves from the terms in which they happened to be expressed. When one estate was said to be enslaved to another, or a right of way was said to be a quality or [383] incident of a neighboring piece of land, men's minds were not alert to see that these phrases were only so many personifying metaphors, which explained nothing unless the figure of speech was true.

How is it that someone without a title or ownership is so well-favored? The answer lies not in reasoning but in a lack of reason. In the first lecture of this course, we examined the idea in its theological context, as Comte famously described, like when an axe was put on trial; and also in the metaphysical context, where only the language of personification remained, causing confusion in reasoning. The situation described seems to illustrate the latter. The language of easements was created using metaphors from people at a time when noxae deditio was still understood; then, as often happens, language influenced thought, leading to conclusions about the rights themselves based on the way they were expressed. When one estate was said to be subordinate to another, or a right of way was called a quality or [383] incident of a nearby piece of land, people's minds were not sharp enough to recognize that these phrases were merely personifying metaphors, which clarified nothing unless the metaphor was accurate.

Rogron deduced the negative nature of servitudes from the rule that the land owes the services, not the person,—Proedium non persona servit. For, said Rogron, the land alone being bound, it can only be bound passively. Austin called this an "absurd remark." /1/ But the jurists from whom we have inherited our law of easements were contented with no better reasoning. Papinian himself wrote that servitudes cannot be partially extinguished, because they are due from lands, not persons. /2/ Celsus thus decides the case which I took for my illustration: Even if possession of a dominant estate is acquired by forcibly ejecting the owner, the way will be retained; since the estate is possessed in such quality and condition as it is when taken. /3/ The commentator Godefroi tersely adds that there are two such conditions, slavery and freedom; and his antithesis is as old as Cicero. /4/ So, in another passage, Celsus asks, What else are the rights attaching to land but qualities of that land? /5/ So Justinian's Institutes speak of servitudes which inhere in buildings. /6/ So Paulus [384] speaks of such rights as being accessory to bodies. "And thus," adds Godefroi, "rights may belong to inanimate things." /1/ It easily followed from all this that a sale of the dominant estate carried existing easements, not because the buyer succeeded to the place of the seller, but because land is bound to land. /2/

Rogron concluded that servitudes are inherently negative because the land is obligated to provide services, not the person—Proedium non persona servit. Rogron argued that since only the land is bound, it can only be bound in a passive way. Austin dismissed this as an "absurd remark." /1/ However, the jurists from whom we inherited our laws regarding easements were satisfied with no better reasoning. Papinian himself stated that servitudes cannot be partially extinguished because they are owed by land, not by individuals. /2/ Celsus thus resolved the case I used as an example: even if possession of a dominant estate is obtained by forcibly removing the owner, the easement will still remain since the estate is possessed in the state and condition it was in when taken. /3/ The commentator Godefroi succinctly adds that there are two such states: slavery and freedom; his opposition is as old as Cicero. /4/ Similarly, in another passage, Celsus asks, what else are the rights attached to land but characteristics of that land? /5/ Thus, Justinian's Institutes refer to servitudes that are inherent in buildings. /6/ Paulus [384] describes these rights as being attached to physical entities. "And so," adds Godefroi, "rights can belong to inanimate objects." /1/ All of this leads to the conclusion that a sale of the dominant estate includes existing easements, not because the buyer takes over the seller's position, but because land is obligated to land. /2/

All these figures import that land is capable of having rights, as Austin recognizes. Indeed, he even says that the land "is erected into a legal or fictitious person, and is styled 'praedium dominans.'" /3/ But if this means anything more than to explain what is implied by the Roman metaphors, it goes too far. The dominant estate was never "erected into a legal person," either by conscious fiction or as a result of primitive beliefs. /4/ It could not sue or be sued, like a ship in the admiralty. It is not supposed that its possessor could maintain an action for an interference with an easement before his time, as an heir could for an injury to property of the hereditas jacens. If land had even been systematically treated as capable of acquiring rights, the time of a disseisee might have been added to that Of the wrongful occupant, on the ground that the land, and not this or that individual, was gaining the easement, and that long association between the enjoyment of the privilege and the land was sufficient, which has never been the law.

All these figures suggest that land can have rights, as Austin points out. He even claims that the land "is treated as a legal or fictional person and is referred to as 'praedium dominans.'" /3/ But if this suggests anything beyond explaining the Roman metaphors, it goes too far. The dominant estate was never "treated as a legal person," whether through conscious fiction or primitive beliefs. /4/ It could not sue or be sued, like a ship in maritime law. It is not assumed that its owner could bring a lawsuit for interference with an easement before their time, the way an heir could for damage to the property of an inherited estate. If land had ever been systematically considered capable of acquiring rights, the time of a dispossessed owner might have been added to that of the unlawful occupant, on the basis that the land, and not a specific individual, was acquiring the easement, and that the long association between the use of the privilege and the land was sufficient, which has never been the law.

All that can be said is, that the metaphors and similes employed naturally led to the rule which has prevailed, [385] and that, as this rule was just as good as any other, or at least was unobjectionable, it was drawn from the figures of speech without attracting attention, and before any one had seen that they were only figures, which proved nothing and justified no conclusion.

All that can be said is that the metaphors and similes used naturally led to the rule that has taken hold, [385], and since this rule was just as good as any other, or at least not problematic, it was derived from the figures of speech without drawing attention, and before anyone realized that they were just figures, which proved nothing and supported no conclusion.

As easements were said to belong to the dominant estate, it followed that whoever possessed the land had a right of the same degree over what was incidental to it. If the true meaning had been that a way or other easement admits of possession, and is taken possession of with the land to which it runs, and that its enjoyment is protected on the same grounds as possession in other cases, the thought could have been understood. But that was not the meaning of the Roman law, and, as has been shown, it is not the doctrine of ours. We must take it that easements have become an incident of land by an unconscious and unreasoned assumption that a piece of land can have rights. It need not be said that this is absurd, although the rules of law which are based upon it are not so.

As easements were considered part of the dominant estate, it meant that whoever owned the land had a right to everything connected to it. If the real intention had been that a path or other easement can be possessed and is included with the land it serves, and that its use is protected like possession in other cases, that idea could have been understood. But that wasn't the interpretation in Roman law, and, as we've shown, it's not our doctrine either. We must accept that easements have become associated with land through an unthinking and unfounded belief that a piece of land can hold rights. It's unnecessary to say this is ridiculous, even though the legal rules based on it aren't.

Absurd or not, the similes as well as the principles of the Roman law reappear in Bracton. He says, "The servitude by which land is subjected to [other] land, is made on the likeness of that by which man is made the slave of man." /1/ "For rights belong to a free tenement, as well as tangible things.... They may be called rights or liberties with regard to the tenements to which they are owed, but servitudes with regard to the tenements by which they are owed.... One estate is free, the other subjected to slavery." /2/ "[A servitude] may be called an arrangement by which house is subjected to house, farm to [386] farm, holding to holding." /1/ No passage has met my eye in which Bracton expressly decides that an easement goes with the dominant estate upon a disseisin, but what he says leaves little doubt that he followed the Roman law in this as in other things.

Absurd or not, the comparisons and the principles of Roman law resurface in Bracton. He states, "The servitude by which land is bound to [other] land is similar to how a person becomes the slave of another." /1/ "Because rights are associated with a free property, just like physical objects.... They can be referred to as rights or liberties concerning the properties they belong to, but servitudes in relation to the properties they are owed to.... One property is free, while the other is subjected to servitude." /2/ "[A servitude] can be described as an arrangement where house is bound to house, farm to farm, holding to holding." /1/ No passage I’ve seen indicates that Bracton explicitly states that an easement transfers with the dominant estate upon a disseisin, but his comments leave little doubt that he adhered to Roman law in this as in other matters.

The writ against a disseisor was for "so much land and its appurtenances," /2/ which must mean that he who had the land even wrongfully had the appurtenances. So Bracton says an action is in rem "whether it is for the principal thing, or for a right which adheres to the thing,... as when one sues for a right of way, ... since rights of this sort are all incorporeal things, and are quasi possessed and reside in bodies, and cannot be got or kept without the bodies in which they inhere, nor in any way had without the bodies to which they belong." /3/ And again, "Since rights do not admit of delivery, but are transferred with the thing in which they are, that is, the bodily thing, he to whom they are transferred forthwith has a quasi possession of those rights as soon as he has the body in which they are." /4/

The writ against someone who took land unlawfully was for "so much land and its appurtenances," which means that whoever had the land, even if wrongfully, also had the appurtenances. Bracton states that an action is in rem "whether it is for the main thing, or for a right that is attached to the thing,... like when someone sues for a right of way,... since these types of rights are all intangible and are quasi-possessed, residing in physical entities, and cannot be acquired or maintained without the physical entities they belong to, nor can they be had in any way without the entities to which they belong." And again, "Since rights cannot be delivered, but are transferred along with the thing they are associated with, that is, the physical object, the person to whom they are transferred immediately has a quasi-possession of those rights as soon as they have the physical thing in which those rights reside."

There is no doubt about the later law, as has been said at the outset.

There’s no doubt about the later law, as mentioned at the beginning.

We have thus traced two competing and mutually inconsistent principles into our law. On the one hand is the conception of succession or privity; on the other, that of rights inhering in a thing. Bracton seems to have vacillated a little from a feeling of the possibility of conflict between the two. The benefit of a warranty was confined to those who, by the act and consent of the [387] grantee, succeeded to his place. It did not pass to assigns unless assigns were mentioned. Bracton supposes grants of easements with or without mention of assigns, which looks as if he thought the difference might be material with regard to easements also. He further says, that if an easement be granted to A, his heirs and assigns, all such by the form of the grant are allowed the use in succession, and all others are wholly excluded. /1/ But he is not speaking of what the rights of a disseisor would be as against one not having a better title, and he immediately adds that they are rights over a corporeal object belonging to a corporeal object.

We have identified two competing and contradictory principles in our law. On one side is the idea of succession or privity; on the other, the idea of rights that belong to a thing. Bracton seems to have wavered a bit due to the potential conflict between the two. The benefit of a warranty was limited to those who, through the act and consent of the [387] grantee, took over his position. It didn't extend to assigns unless they were specifically mentioned. Bracton considers grants of easements, with or without mentions of assigns, suggesting he believed the distinction might matter for easements as well. He also states that if an easement is granted to A, his heirs, and assigns, all of them are granted use in succession by the terms of the grant, and everyone else is completely excluded. /1/ However, he isn't addressing the rights of a disseisor against someone without a stronger title, and he quickly adds that these rights pertain to a physical object belonging to a physical object.

Although it may be doubted whether the mention of assigns was ever necessary to attach an easement to land, and although it is very certain that it did not remain so long, the difficulty referred to grew greater as time went on. It would have been easily disposed of if the only rights which could be annexed to land were easements, such as a right of way. It then might have been said that these were certain limited interests in land, less than ownership in extent, but like it in kind, and therefore properly transferred by the same means that ownership was. A right of way, it might have been argued, is not to be approached from the point of view of contract. It does not presuppose any promise on the part of the servient owner. His obligation, although more troublesome to him than to others, is the same as that of every one else. It is the purely negative duty not to obstruct or interfere with a right of property. /2/

Although it's questionable whether mentioning assigns was ever needed to attach an easement to land, and it's clear that this wasn't the case for long, the difficulty mentioned only increased over time. It could have been easily resolved if the only rights that could be attached to land were easements, like a right of way. In that case, it might have been said that these were specific limited interests in land, less than ownership in extent but similar in nature, and therefore could be transferred using the same methods as ownership. One could argue that a right of way shouldn't be viewed from a contractual perspective. It doesn't assume any promise from the servient owner. His obligation, while more of a hassle for him than for others, is the same as everyone else's. It's simply the negative duty not to block or interfere with a property right. /2/

[388] But although the test of rights going with the land may have been something of that nature, this will not help us to understand the cases without a good deal of explanation. For such rights might exist to active services which had to be performed by the person who held the servient estate. It strikes our ear strangely to hear a right to services from an individual called a right of property as distinguished from contract. Still this will be found to have been the way in which such rights were regarded. Bracton argues that it is no wrong to the lord for the tenant to alienate land held by free and perfect gift, on the ground that the land is bound and charged with the services into whose hands soever it may come. The lord is said to have a fee in the homage and services; and therefore no entry upon the land which does not disturb them injures him. /1/ It is the tenement which imposes the obligation of homage, /2/ and the same thing is true of villein and other feudal services. /3/

[388] While the test of rights associated with the land might have been somewhat like this, it doesn’t really help us understand the cases without a lot of explanation. These rights could involve active services that the person holding the servient estate had to perform. It sounds odd to refer to a right to someone's services as a right of property rather than a contract. Yet, this is how such rights were viewed historically. Bracton argues that it’s not wrong for the tenant to transfer land granted freely and fully, because the land is tied to the services regardless of who possesses it. The lord is said to have a fee based on the loyalty and services provided, so any entry onto the land that doesn’t interfere with those services doesn’t harm him. /1/ It is the tenement that creates the obligation of loyalty, /2/ and the same applies to villein and other feudal services. /3/

The law remained unchanged when feudal services took the form of rent. /4/ Even in our modern terms for years rent is still treated as something issuing out of the leased premises, so that to this day, although, if you hire a whole house and it burns down, you have to pay without abatement, because you have the land out of which the rent issues, yet if you only hire a suite of rooms and they are burned, you pay rent no longer, because you no longer have the tenement out of which it comes. /5/

The law stayed the same when feudal services turned into rent. /4/ Even today, rent is still considered something that comes from the leased property. So, even now, if you rent a whole house and it burns down, you still have to pay the full rent, because you still have the land the rent comes from. However, if you only rent a suite of rooms and they burn down, you don’t have to pay rent anymore, because you no longer have the unit from which it originates. /5/

[389] It is obvious that the foregoing reasoning leads to the conclusion that a disseisor of the tenant would be bound as much as the tenant himself, and this conclusion was adopted by the early law. The lord could require the services, /1/ or collect the rent /2/ of any one who had the land, because, as was said in language very like Bracton's, "the charge of the rent goes with the land." /3/

[389] It's clear that the reasoning above leads to the conclusion that a person who takes land from the tenant would be just as obligated as the tenant themselves, and this conclusion was accepted by early law. The landlord could demand services, /1/ or collect rent /2/ from anyone who had the land, because, as was stated in language very similar to Bracton's, "the obligation to pay rent goes with the land." /3/

Then as to the right to the rent. Rent was treated in early law as a real right, of which a disseisin was possible, and for which a possessory action could be brought. If, as was very frequently the case, the leased land lay within a manor, the rent was parcel of the manor, /4/ so that there was some ground for saying that one who was seised of the manor, that is, who possessed the lands occupied by the lord of the manor, and was recognized by the tenants as lord, had the rents as incident thereto. Thus Brian, Chief Justice of England under Henry VII., says, "If I am disseised of a manor, and the tenants pay their rent to the disseisor, and then I re-enter, I shall not have the back rent of my tenants which they have paid to my disseisor, but the disseisor shall pay for all in trespass or assize." /5/ This opinion was evidently founded on the notion that the rent was attached to the chief land like an easement. Sic fit ut debeantur rei a re. /6/

Then regarding the right to rent. Rent was considered in early law as a real right, which could be lost through disseisin, and for which a possessory action could be initiated. If, as was often the case, the leased land was part of a manor, the rent was considered part of the manor, /4/ meaning that one who was in possession of the manor, that is, who occupied the lands held by the lord of the manor and was recognized by the tenants as the lord, had the rents as a part of that possession. Thus, Brian, Chief Justice of England during Henry VII’s reign, states, "If I am dispossessed of a manor, and the tenants pay their rent to the dispossessor, and then I re-enter, I will not receive the back rent from my tenants that they paid to my dispossessor, but the dispossessor will owe for all in trespass or assize." /5/ This view was clearly based on the concept that rent was linked to the chief land like an easement. Sic fit ut debeantur rei a re. /6/

Different principles might have applied when the rent was not parcel of a manor, and was only part of the reversion; that is, part of the landlord's fee or estate out of [390] which the lease was carved. If the lease and rent were merely internal divisions of that estate, the rent could not be claimed except by one who was privy to that estate. A disseisor would get a new and different fee, and would not have the estate of which the rent was part. And therefore it would seem that in such a case the tenant could refuse to pay him rent, and that payment to him would be no defence against the true owner. /1/ Nevertheless, if the tenant recognized him, the disseisor would be protected as against persons who could not show a better title. /2/ Furthermore, the rent was so far annexed to the land that whoever came by the reversion lawfully could collect it, including the superior lord in case of escheat. /3/ Yet escheat meant the extinction of the fee of which the lease and rent were parts, and although Bracton regarded the lord as coming in under the tenant's title pro herede, in privity, it was soon correctly settled that he did not, but came in paramount. This instance, therefore, comes very near that of a disseisor.

Different principles might have applied when the rent wasn't part of a manor and was only part of the landlord's share or estate from which the lease was created. If the lease and rent were just internal divisions of that estate, the rent could only be claimed by someone who was connected to that estate. A disseisor would obtain a new and different fee and wouldn’t have the estate that included the rent. Therefore, it seems in such a case that the tenant could refuse to pay him rent, and payment to them wouldn’t protect the tenant against the actual owner. /1/ However, if the tenant acknowledged him, the disseisor would be protected against anyone who couldn’t prove a better title. /2/ Moreover, the rent was so closely tied to the land that anyone who acquired the reversion legally could collect it, including the superior lord in the case of escheat. /3/ Yet, escheat meant the termination of the fee from which the lease and rent originated, and although Bracton saw the lord as coming in under the tenant's title as an heir, in connection, it was soon clarified that he did not but came in as a superior claim. This situation, therefore, is very similar to that of a disseisor.

Services and rent, then, were, and to some extent are still, dealt with by the law from the point of view of property. They were things which could be owned and transferred like other property. They could be possessed even by wrong, and possessory remedies were given for them.

Services and rent were, and in some ways still are, handled by the law as property. They were items that could be owned and transferred like any other property. They could even be possessed wrongfully, and legal remedies were available for possession of them.

No such notion was applied to warranties, or to any right which was regarded wholly from the point of view of contract. And when we turn to the history of those remedies for rent which sounded in contract, we find that they were so regarded. The actions of debt and covenant [391] could not be maintained without privity. In the ninth year of Henry VI. /1/ it was doubted whether an heir having the reversion by descent could have debt, and it was held that a grantee of the reversion, although he had the rent, could not have that remedy for it. A few years later, it was decided that the heir could maintain debt, /2/ and in Henry VII.'s reign the remedy was extended to the devisee, /3/ who, as has been remarked above, seemed more akin to the heir than a grantee, and was more easily likened to him. It was then logically necessary to give assigns the same action, and this followed. /4/ The privity of contract followed the estate, so that the assignee of the reversion could sue the person then holding the term. /5/ On like grounds he was afterwards allowed to maintain covenant. /6/ But these actions have never lain for or against persons not privy in estate with the lessor and lessee respectively, because privity to the contract could never be worked out without succession to the title. /7/

No such idea was applied to warranties or any rights that were viewed purely from a contract perspective. When we look at the history of those remedies for rent that fell under contract law, we see they were treated that way. The actions of debt and covenant [391] couldn't be pursued without a connection between the parties involved. In the ninth year of Henry VI., it was questioned whether an heir who had inherited the reversion could pursue a debt claim, and it was determined that a grantee of the reversion, even if he had the rent, couldn't pursue that remedy. A few years later, it was ruled that the heir could seek a debt claim, /1/ and during Henry VII.'s reign, the remedy was expanded to cover the devisee, /2/ who, as noted earlier, seemed more similar to the heir than to a grantee, making the comparison easier. It then became logically necessary to allow assigns the same action, which happened subsequently. /3/ The connection in contract law followed the property, meaning that the assignee of the reversion could sue the individual then holding the lease. /4/ Similarly, he was later permitted to pursue a covenant. /5/ However, these actions have never been available for or against individuals who are not connected by property interests with the lessor and lessee, as a connection to the contract could never be established without succession to the title. /6/

However, all these niceties had no application to the old freehold rents of the feudal period, because the contractual remedies did not apply to them until the time of Queen Anne. /8/ The freehold rent was just as much real estate as an acre of land, and it was sued for by the similar remedy of an assize, asking to be put back into possession.

However, all these details were irrelevant to the old freehold rents from the feudal period, because the legal remedies didn’t apply to them until Queen Anne's reign. The freehold rent was just as much real estate as an acre of land, and it was pursued through the same legal remedy of an assize, seeking to regain possession.

[392] The allowance of contractual remedies shows that rent and feudal services of that nature, although dealt with as things capable of possession, and looked at generally from the point of view of property rather than of contract, yet approach much nearer to the nature of the latter than a mere duty not to interfere with a way. Other cases come nearer still. The sphere of prescription and custom in imposing active duties is large in early law. Sometimes the duty is incident to the ownership of certain land; sometimes the right is, and sometimes both are, as in the case of an easement. When the service was for the benefit of other land, the fact that the burden, in popular language, fell upon one parcel, was of itself a reason for the benefit attaching to the other.

[392] Allowing for contractual remedies indicates that rent and feudal services, while treated as items that can be owned and generally viewed more as property than as a contract, are actually much closer to the nature of a contract than simply a duty to not obstruct a path. Other examples come even closer. The role of prescription and custom in imposing active duties is quite extensive in early law. Sometimes the duty comes with owning specific land; sometimes the right does, and occasionally both apply, as seen in the case of an easement. When the service benefits another piece of land, the fact that the burden, in everyday terms, falls on one parcel is itself a reason for the benefit to apply to the other.

Instances of different kinds are these. A parson might be bound by custom to keep a bull and a boar for the use of his parish. /1/ A right could be attached to a manor by prescription to have a convent sing in the manor chapel. /2/ A right might be gained by like means to have certain land fenced by the owner of the neighboring lot. /3/ Now, it may readily be conceded that even rights like the last two, when attached to land, were looked at as property, and were spoken of as the subject of grant. /4/ It may be conceded that, in many cases where the statement sounds strange to modern ears, the obligation was regarded as failing on the land alone, and not on the person of the [393] tenant. And it may be conjectured that this view arose naturally and reasonably from there having been originally no remedy to compel performance of such services, except a distress executed on the servient land. /1/ But any conjectured distinction between obligations for which the primitive remedy was distress alone, and others, if it ever existed, must soon have faded from view; and the line between those rights which can be deemed rights of property, and those which are mere contracts, is hard to see, after the last examples. A covenant to repair is commonly supposed to be a pure matter of contract. What is the difference between a duty to repair, and a duty to fence? The difficulty remains almost as great as ever of finding the dividing line between the competing principles of transfer,—succession on the one side, and possession of dominant land on the other. If a right in the nature of an easement could be attached to land by prescription, it could equally be attached by grant. If it went with the land in one case, even into the hands of a disseisor, it must have gone with it in the other. No satisfactory distinction could be based on the mode of acquisition, /2/ nor was any attempted. As the right was not confined to assigns, there was no need of mentioning assigns. /3/ In modern times, at least, if not in early law, such rights can be created by covenant as well [394] as by grant. /1/ And, on the other hand, it is ancient law that an action of covenant may be maintained upon an instrument of grant. /2/ The result of all this was that not only a right created by covenant, but the action of covenant itself, might in such cases go to assigns, although not mentioned, at a time when such mention was essential to give them the benefit of a warranty. Logically, these premises led one step farther, and not only assigns not named, but disseisors, should have been allowed to maintain their action on the contract, as they had the right arising out of it. Indeed, if the plaintiff had a right which when obtained by grant would have entitled him to covenant, it was open to argument that he should be allowed the same action when he had the right by prescription, although, as has been seen in the case of rent, it did not follow in practice from a man's having a right that he had the contractual remedies for it. /3/ Covenant required a specialty, but prescription was said to be a sufficiently good specialty. /4/ Where, then, was the line to be drawn between covenants that devolved only to successors, and those that went with the land?

Instances of different kinds are these. A pastor might be required by tradition to keep a bull and a boar for the benefit of his parish. /1/ A right could be connected to a manor by long-standing practice to have a convent sing in the manor chapel. /2/ A right might also be established similarly to have certain land fenced by the neighbor who owns the adjacent lot. /3/ Now, it can be easily agreed that even rights like the last two, when attached to land, were viewed as property and were referred to as the subject of a grant. /4/ It might be accepted that, in many cases where the statement sounds unusual to modern ears, the obligation was seen as resting on the land itself, and not on the person of the [393] tenant. It is reasonable to suppose that this perspective naturally arose because there was originally no remedy to enforce such services, except for seizing the servient land. /1/ However, any assumed distinction between obligations that were only enforceable through distress and others, if it ever existed, must have soon become unclear; the line between those rights considered as property and those merely as contracts is difficult to discern after the last examples. A promise to repair is typically thought to be purely a matter of contract. What is the difference between a duty to repair and a duty to fence? The difficulty remains almost as significant as ever in determining the dividing line between the competing principles of transfer—succession on one side and possession of dominant land on the other. If a right similar to an easement could be attached to land by long-standing practice, it could also be attached by grant. If it carried with the land in one case, even into the hands of someone unlawfully in possession, it must have carried with it in the other scenario as well. No satisfactory distinction could be made based on how it was acquired, /2/ nor was any distinction attempted. Since the right was not limited to assignees, there was no need to mention them. /3/ In modern times, at least, if not in early law, such rights can be created by a covenant just as well [394] as by grant. /1/ Furthermore, it is an ancient principle that an action for covenant may be pursued based on a grant. /2/ The outcome of all this was that not only a right created by covenant, but the action of covenant itself, could in such cases pass to assignees, even if not mentioned, during a time when such mention was crucial for granting them the benefit of a warranty. Logically, these premises led one step further, and not only unnamed assignees, but unlawful possessors, should have been allowed to pursue their action on the contract, as they held the right arising from it. Indeed, if the plaintiff had a right that, when obtained by grant, would have allowed him to covenant, it could be argued that he should be allowed the same action when he acquired the right by long-standing practice, even though, as seen in the case of rent, it did not necessarily follow that having a right included the contractual remedies for it. /3/ Covenant required a specialty, but prescription was considered a sufficiently good specialty. /4/ Where, then, should the line be drawn between covenants that only pass to successors and those that go with the land?

The difficulty becomes more striking upon further examination of the early law. For side by side with the personal warranty which has been discussed hitherto, there was another warranty which has not yet been mentioned [395] by which particular land alone was bound. /1/ The personal warranty bound only the warrantor and his heirs. As was said in a case of the time of Edward I., "no one can bind assigns to warranty, since warranty always extends to heirs who claim by succession and not by assignment." /2/ But when particular land was bound, the warranty went with it, even into the hands of the King, because, as Bracton says, the thing goes with its burden to every one. /3/ Fleta writes that every possessor will be held. /4/ There cannot be a doubt that a disseisor would have been bound equally with one whose possession was lawful.

The difficulty becomes more obvious when you take a closer look at the early law. Alongside the personal warranty we've discussed so far, there was another warranty that hasn't been mentioned yet [395] which specifically bound particular land. /1/ The personal warranty only held the warrantor and his heirs accountable. As noted in a case from the time of Edward I, "no one can bind assigns to warranty, since warranty always extends to heirs who claim by succession and not by assignment." /2/ However, when specific land was bound, the warranty followed it, even to the King, because, as Bracton states, the thing goes with its burden to everyone. /3/ Fleta writes that every possessor will be held accountable. /4/ It's clear that a disseisor would have been equally bound as someone whose possession was lawful.

We are now ready for a case /5/ decided under Edward III., which has been discussed from the time of Fitzherbert and Coke down to Lord St. Leonards and Mr. Rawle, which is still law, and is said to remain still unexplained. /6/ It shows the judges hesitating between the two conceptions to which this Lecture has been devoted. If they are understood, I think the explanation will be clear.

We are now ready for a case decided under Edward III that has been discussed from the time of Fitzherbert and Coke to Lord St. Leonards and Mr. Rawle, which is still the law and is said to remain unexplained. It shows the judges struggling between the two ideas that this lecture has focused on. If they are understood, I believe the explanation will be clear.

Pakenham brought covenant as heir of the covenantee against a prior, for breach of a covenant made by the defendant's predecessor with the plaintiff's great-grandfather, that the prior and convent should sing every week in a chapel in his manor, for him and his servants. The defendant first pleaded that the plaintiff and his servants were not dwelling within the manor; but, not daring to [396] rest his case on that, he pleaded that the plaintiff was not heir, but that his elder brother was. The plaintiff replied that he was tenant of the manor, and that his great-grandfather enfeoffed a stranger, who enfeoffed the plaintiff and his wife; and that thus the plaintiff was tenant of the manor by purchase, and privy to the ancestor; and also that the services had been rendered for a time whereof the memory was not.

Pakenham brought a lawsuit as the heir of the person who made the covenant against a prior in relation to a breach of a covenant made by the defendant's predecessor with the plaintiff's great-grandfather. This covenant stated that the prior and convent should sing every week in a chapel on his manor for him and his servants. The defendant first argued that the plaintiff and his servants were not living within the manor. However, not wanting to rely solely on that, he claimed that the plaintiff was not the heir, but that his older brother was. The plaintiff countered that he was the tenant of the manor, and that his great-grandfather had granted land to a stranger, who subsequently granted it to the plaintiff and his wife. Therefore, the plaintiff was a tenant of the manor through purchase and was connected to the ancestor; he also stated that the services had been performed for a time beyond living memory.

It is evident from these pleadings that assigns were not mentioned in the covenant, and so it has always been taken. /1/ It also appears that the plaintiff was trying to stand on two grounds; first, privity, as descendant and assign of the covenantee; second, that the service was attached to the manor by covenant or by prescription, and that he could maintain covenant as tenant of the manor, from whichever source the duty arose.

It’s clear from these statements that assigns weren’t included in the agreement, and that’s been the accepted interpretation. /1/ It also seems that the plaintiff was attempting to base their case on two points; first, privity, as a descendant and assign of the covenantee; second, that the service was linked to the manor either by covenant or by long-standing usage, and that they could pursue a covenant as a tenant of the manor, regardless of where the obligation originated.

Finchden, J. puts the case of parceners making partition, and one covenanting with the other to acquit of suit. A purchaser has the advantage of the covenant. Belknap, for the defendants, agrees, but distinguishes. In that case the acquittance falls on the land, and not on the person. /2/ (That is to say, such obligations follow the analogy of easements, and, as the burden falls on the quasi servient estate, the benefit goes with the dominant land to assigns, whether mentioned or not, and they are not considered from the point of view of contract at all. Warranty, on the other hand, is a contract pure and simple, and lies in the blood,—falls on the person, not on the land. /3/)

Finchden, J. discusses the situation where co-owners are splitting property, and one of them agrees to release the other from any obligations. A buyer benefits from that agreement. Belknap, representing the defendants, agrees but makes a distinction. In that situation, the release applies to the property, not to the individual. /2/ (This means that such obligations resemble easements, where the burden is on the property that is being used, and the benefit goes with the primary property to future owners, whether or not they are specified, and they’re not viewed as a contract. In contrast, a warranty is just a simple contract that is personal—it affects the individual, not the property. /3/)

Finchden: a fortiori in this case; for there the action [397] was maintained because the plaintiff was tenant of the land from which the suit was due, and here he is tenant of the manor where the chapel is.

Finchden: a fortiori in this case; because there, the action [397] was upheld since the plaintiff was the tenant of the land that the lawsuit concerned, and here he is the tenant of the manor where the chapel is located.

Wichingham, J.: If the king grants warren to another who is tenant of the manor, he shall have warren, &c.; but the warren will not pass by the grant [of the manor], because the warren is not appendant to the manor. No more does it seem the services are here appendant to the manor.

Wichingham, J.: If the king gives the right to hunt (warren) to someone else who is a tenant of the manor, that person will have the right to hunt, etc.; but the right to hunt does not transfer with the grant of the manor, because the right to hunt is not attached to the manor. It also appears that the services are not attached to the manor either.

Thorpe, C. J., to Belknap: "There are some covenants on which no one shall have an action, but the party to the covenant, or his heir, and some covenants have inheritance in the land, so that whoever has the land by alienation, or in other manner, shall have action of covenant; [or, as it is stated in Fitzherbert's Abridgment, /1/ the inhabitants of the land as well as every one who has the land, shall have the covenant;] and when you say he is not heir, he is privy of blood, and may be heir: /2/ and also he is tenant of the land, and it is a thing which is annexed to the chapel, which is in the manor, and so annexed to the manor, and so he has said that the services have been rendered for all time whereof there is memory, whence it is right this action should be maintained." Belknap denied that the plaintiff counted on such a prescription; but Thorpe said he did, and we bear record of it, and the case was adjourned. /3/

Thorpe, C. J., to Belknap: "There are some agreements that no one can bring a lawsuit over, except for the party involved in the agreement, or their heir. Some agreements are tied to the land, so whoever has the land through transfer or in any other way has the right to sue for the agreement; [or, as stated in Fitzherbert's Abridgment, /1/ both the residents of the land and anyone who has the land can enforce the agreement;] and when you say he isn’t an heir, he has family ties and could be an heir: /2/ plus, he is a tenant of the land, and this is something that is connected to the chapel, which is part of the manor, and so connected to the manor. He has stated that the services have been provided for as long as anyone can remember, which is why this lawsuit should proceed." Belknap denied that the plaintiff relied on such a claim; but Thorpe insisted he did, and we have a record of it, and the case was postponed. /3/

It will be seen that the discussion followed the lines marked out by the pleading. One judge thought that [398] the plaintiff was entitled to recover as tenant of the manor. The other puisne doubted, but agreed that the case must be discussed on the analogy of easements. The Chief Justice, after suggesting the possibility of sufficient privity on the ground that the plaintiff was privy in blood and might be heir, turns to the other argument as more promising, and evidently founds his opinion upon it. /1/ It would almost seem that he considered a prescriptive right enough to support the action, and it is pretty clear that he thought that a disseisor would have had the same rights as the plaintiff.

It will be clear that the discussion followed the lines set out by the pleading. One judge believed that [398] the plaintiff was entitled to recover as the tenant of the manor. The other judge had doubts but agreed that the case must be discussed in relation to easements. The Chief Justice, after suggesting that there might be sufficient connection since the plaintiff was related by blood and could be an heir, shifted to another argument that seemed more promising, and clearly based his opinion on that. /1/ It almost seemed like he thought a prescriptive right was enough to support the action, and it’s fairly obvious that he believed a disseisor would have had the same rights as the plaintiff.

In the reign of Henry IV., another case /2/ arose upon a covenant very like the last. But this time the facts were reversed. The plaintiff counted as heir, but did not allege that he was tenant of the manor. The defendant, not denying the plaintiff's descent, pleaded in substance that he was not tenant of the manor in his own right. The question raised by the pleadings, therefore, was whether the heir of the covenantee could sue without being tenant of the manor. If the covenant was to be approached from the side of contract, the heir was party to it as representing the covenantee. If, on the other hand, it was treated as amounting to the grant of a service like an easement, it would naturally go with the manor if made to the lord of the manor. It seems to have been thought that such a covenant might go either way, according as it was made to the tenant of the manor or to a stranger. Markham, one of the judges, says: "In a writ of covenant one must be privy to the covenant if he would have a writ of covenant or aid by the covenant. But, peradventure, if the covenant [399] had been made with the lord of the manor, who had inheritance in the manor, ou issint come determination poit estre fait, it would be otherwise," which was admitted. /1/ It was assumed that the covenant was not so made as to attach to the manor, and the court, observing that the service was rather spiritual than temporal, were inclined to think that the heir could sue. /2/ The defendant accordingly over and set up a release. It will be seen how fully this agrees with the former case.

During the reign of Henry IV, another case /2/ came up regarding a covenant similar to the last one. But this time, the details were reversed. The plaintiff claimed to be the heir but did not state that he was the tenant of the manor. The defendant, not disputing the plaintiff's lineage, argued that he was not the tenant of the manor in his own right. Therefore, the issue raised by the pleadings was whether the heir of the covenantee could file a lawsuit without being the tenant of the manor. If the covenant was seen as a contract, the heir represented the covenantee. However, if it was viewed as a grant of service like an easement, it would naturally be associated with the manor if made to its lord. It was believed that such a covenant could go either way, depending on whether it was made to the tenant of the manor or to a stranger. Judge Markham stated: "In a writ of covenant, one must be privy to the covenant if they want a writ of covenant or to benefit from it. But perhaps, if the covenant [399] had been made with the lord of the manor, who had inheritance in the manor, it would be different," which was accepted. /1/ It was assumed that the covenant was not intended to attach to the manor, and the court, noting that the service was more spiritual than temporal, leaned towards the belief that the heir could sue. /2/ Consequently, the defendant argued against this and introduced a release. It will be evident how closely this aligns with the previous case.

The distinction taken by Markham is stated very clearly in a reported by Lord Coke. In the argument of Chudleigh's Case the line is drawn thus: "Always, the warranty as to voucher requires privity of estate to which it was annexed," (i.e. succession to the original covenantee,) "and the same law of a use.... But of things annexed to land, it is otherwise, as of commons, advowsons, and the like appendants or appurtenances.... So a disseisor, abator, intruder, or the lord by escheat, &c., shall have them as things annexed to the land. So note a diversity between a use or warranty, and the like things annexed to the estate of the land in privity, and commons, advowsons, and other hereditaments annexed to the possession of the land." /3/ And this, it seems to me, is the nearest approach which has ever been made to the truth.

The distinction made by Markham is stated very clearly in a report by Lord Coke. In the argument of Chudleigh's Case, the line is drawn like this: "Always, the warranty regarding voucher requires a direct connection to the estate to which it was attached," (i.e., succession to the original covenantee,) "and the same law applies to a use.... But for things attached to land, it is different, such as commons, advowsons, and similar appendages or appurtenances.... So a disseisor, abator, intruder, or the lord by escheat, etc., shall have them as things attached to the land. So, note the difference between a use or warranty, and similar things attached to the estate of the land in proximity, and commons, advowsons, and other hereditaments attached to the possession of the land." /3/ And this, it seems to me, is the closest we've ever come to the truth.

Coke, in his Commentary on Littleton (385 a), takes a distinction between a warranty, which binds the party to yield lands in recompense, and a covenant annexed to the land, which is to yield but damages. If Lord Coke had [400] meant to distinguish between warranties and all covenants which in our loose modern sense are said to run with the land, this statement would be less satisfactory than the preceding.

Coke, in his Commentary on Littleton (385 a), distinguishes between a warranty, which requires the party to provide land as compensation, and a covenant tied to the land, which only requires the payment of damages. If Lord Coke had [400] meant to differentiate between warranties and all covenants that, in our loose modern sense, are considered to run with the land, this statement would be less satisfactory than the one before it.

A warranty was a covenant which sometimes yielded but damages, and a covenant in the old law sometimes yielded land. In looking at the early cases we are reminded of the still earlier German procedure, in which it did not matter whether the plaintiff's claim was founded on a right of property in a thing, or simply on a contract for it. /1/ Covenant was brought for a freehold under Edward I., /2/ and under Edward III. it seems that a mill could be abated by the same action, when maintained contrary to an easement created by covenant. /3/ But Lord Coke did not mean to lay down any sweeping doctrine, for his conclusion is, that "a covenant is in many cases extended further than the warrantie." Furthermore, this statement, as Lord Coke meant it, is perfectly consistent with the other and more important distinction between warranties and rights in the nature of easements or covenants creating such rights. For Lord Coke's examples are confined to covenants of the latter sort, being in fact only the cases just stated from the Year Books.

A warranty was a promise that usually resulted in damages, while a covenant in old law sometimes resulted in land. When we look at early cases, we are reminded of even earlier German procedures, where it didn’t matter if the plaintiff's claim was based on a property right in a thing or simply on a contract for it. /1/ A covenant was used for a freehold under Edward I., /2/ and under Edward III., it seems that a mill could be removed using the same action if it was maintained against an easement created by covenant. /3/ But Lord Coke didn’t intend to establish a broad rule, as he concluded that “a covenant is in many cases extended further than the warranty.” Moreover, this statement, as Lord Coke intended it, is completely compatible with the more significant distinction between warranties and rights related to easements or covenants creating such rights. Lord Coke's examples are restricted to covenants of this latter type, essentially only the cases mentioned from the Year Books.

Later writers, however, have wholly forgotten the distinction in question, and accordingly it has failed to settle the disputed line between conflicting principles. Covenants which started from the analogy of warranties, and others to which was applied the language and reasoning of easements, have been confounded together under the title of [401] covenants running with the land. The phrase "running with the land" is only appropriate to covenants which pass like easements. But we can easily see how it came to be used more loosely.

Later writers, however, have completely overlooked the distinction in question, which has led to confusion about the disputed line between conflicting principles. Covenants that originated from the analogy of warranties and those that were described using the language and reasoning of easements have been mixed together under the label of [401] covenants running with the land. The term "running with the land" is only suitable for covenants that pass like easements. Yet, it’s clear how it became used more loosely.

It has already been shown that covenants for title, like warranties, went only to successors of the original covenantee. The technical expression for the rule was that they were annexed to the estate in privity. Nothing was easier than to overlook the technical use of the word "estate," and to say that such covenants went with the land. This was done, and forthwith all distinctions became doubtful. It probably had been necessary to mention assigns in covenants for title, as it certainly had been to give them the benefit of the ancient warranty; /1/ for this seems to have been the formal mark of those covenants which passed only to privies. But it was not necessary to mention assigns in order to attach easements and the like to land. Why should it be necessary for one covenant running with the land more than another? and if necessary for one, why not for all? /2/ The necessity of such mention in modern times has been supposed to be governed by a fanciful rule of Lord Coke's. /3/ On the other hand, the question is raised whether covenants which should pass irrespective of privity are not governed by the same rule which governs warranties.

It has already been shown that covenants for title, like warranties, apply only to successors of the original covenantee. The technical term for this rule was that they were tied to the estate in privity. It was easy to overlook the technical use of the word "estate" and suggest that such covenants went with the land. This misinterpretation led to a loss of clarity in all distinctions. It was probably necessary to mention assigns in covenants for title, just as it certainly was to allow them to benefit from the ancient warranty; for this seems to have been the formal indication of those covenants that only passed to privies. But it wasn't necessary to mention assigns to attach easements and similar rights to land. Why should it be required for one covenant running with the land more than another? And if it is necessary for one, why not for all? The need for such mention in modern times has been thought to be based on a whimsical rule from Lord Coke. On the other hand, the question arises whether covenants that should pass without regard to privity are governed by the same rule that applies to warranties.

These questions have not lost their importance. Covenants for title are in every deed, and other covenants are [402] only less common, which, it remains to show, belong to the other class.

These questions are still important. Title covenants are in every deed, and other covenants are [402] only slightly less common, which will be demonstrated as belonging to the other class.

Chief among these is the covenant to repair. It has already been observed that an easement of fencing may be annexed to land, and it was then asked what was the difference in kind between a right to have another person build such structures, and a right to have him repair structures already built. Evidence is not wanting to show that the likeness was perceived. Only, as such covenants are rarely, if ever, made, except in leases, there is always privity to the original parties. For the lease could not, and the reversion would not be likely to, go by disseisin.

Chief among these is the agreement to repair. It's already been pointed out that a fencing easement can be attached to land, and it was then questioned what the difference is between the right to have someone else build such structures and the right to have them repair structures that are already built. There is clear evidence that this similarity was recognized. However, since such agreements are rarely made, if ever, except in leases, there is always a direct relationship between the original parties. Because the lease couldn’t, and the reversion probably wouldn’t, be affected by unauthorized dispossession.

The Dean of Windsor's Case decides that such a covenant binds an assignee of the term, although not named. It is reported in two books of the highest authority, one of the reporters being Lord Coke, the other Croke, who was also a judge. Croke gives the reason thus: "For a covenant which runs and rests with the land lies for or against the assignee at the common law, quia transit terra cum onere, although the assignees be not named in the covenant." /1/ This is the reason which governed easements, and the very phrase which was used to account for all possessors being bound by a covenant binding a parcel of land to warranty. Coke says, "For such covenant which extends to the support of the thing demised is quodammodo appurtenant to it, and goes with it." Again the language of easements. And to make this plainer, if need be, it is added, "If a man grants to one estovers to repair his house, it is appurtenant to his house." Estovers for [403] repair went with the land, like other rights of common, /1/ which, as Lord Coke has told us, passed even to disseisors.

The Dean of Windsor's Case determines that a covenant is binding for anyone who takes over the term, even if they aren’t named. It’s documented in two highly respected sources, one being Lord Coke and the other Croke, who was also a judge. Croke explains, "Because a covenant that runs with the land applies to the assignee at common law, since the land transitions with the burden, even if the assignees aren’t named in the covenant." This principle governs easements and the concept that all possessors are obligated by a covenant associated with a parcel of land to warranty. Coke states, "For a covenant that extends to the support of the thing leased is in a sense attached to it and comes with it." This echoes the terminology of easements. To clarify this further, it adds, "If someone grants another the right to take estovers to repair his house, it is attached to his house." The right to take estovers for repair was included with the land, similar to other common rights, which, as Lord Coke pointed out, even passed to those who had been dispossessed.

In the next reign the converse proposition was decided, that an assignee of the reversion was entitled in like manner to the benefit of the covenant, because "it is a covenant which runs with the land." /2/ The same law was applied, with still clearer reason, to a covenant to leave fifteen acres unploughed for pasture, which was held to bind an assignee not named, /3/ and, it would seem, to a covenant to keep land properly manured. /4/

In the next reign, the opposite argument was determined, stating that someone who takes over the reversion can also benefit from the covenant because "it's a covenant that runs with the land." /2/ This same law was applied, with even more clarity, to a covenant requiring that fifteen acres be left unploughed for pasture, which was found to be binding on an unnamed assignee, /3/ and apparently, it also applied to a covenant to keep the land properly fertilized. /4/

If the analogy which led to this class of decisions were followed out, a disseisor could sue or be sued upon such covenants, if the other facts were of such a kind as to raise the question. There is nothing but the novelty of the proposition which need prevent its being accepted. It has been mentioned above, that words of covenant may annex an easement to land, and that words of grant may import a covenant. It would be rather narrow to give a disseisor one remedy, and deny him another, where the right was one, and the same words made both the grant and the covenant. /5/

If we follow the analogy that led to this type of decision, a disseisor could sue or be sued based on such covenants, provided that the other circumstances are significant enough to warrant the question. The only thing holding back its acceptance is the novelty of the idea. As mentioned earlier, covenant language can attach an easement to land, and grant language can imply a covenant. It would be quite limited to allow a disseisor one remedy while denying them another when the right is the same and the same language creates both the grant and the covenant. /5/

The language commonly used, however, throws doubt and darkness over this and every other question connected with the subject. It is a consequence, already referred to, of confounding covenants for title, and the class last discussed, [404] under the name of covenants running with the land. According to the general opinion there must be a privity of estate between the covenantor and covenantee in the latter class of cases in order to bind the assigns of the covenantor. Some have supposed this privity to be tenure; some, an interest of the covenantee in the land of the covenantor; and so on. /1/ The first notion is false, the second misleading, and the proposition to which they are applied is unfounded. Privity of estate, as used in connection with covenants at common law, does not mean tenure or easement; it means succession to a title. /2/ It is never necessary between covenantor and covenantee, or any other persons, except between the present owner and the original covenantee. And on principle it is only necessary between them in those cases—such as warranties, and probably covenants for title—where, the covenants being regarded wholly from the side of contract, the benefit goes by way of succession, and not with the land.

The language commonly used, however, casts doubt and confusion over this and every other question related to the topic. This is a result, as mentioned earlier, of mixing up covenants for title and the last class discussed, [404] known as covenants running with the land. Generally, people believe there must be a privity of estate between the covenantor and covenantee in these cases to bind the assigns of the covenantor. Some have thought this privity to be tenure; others see it as an interest of the covenantee in the covenantor's land, and so on. /1/ The first idea is incorrect, the second is misleading, and the argument they are based on is unfounded. Privity of estate, in relation to covenants at common law, does not refer to tenure or easement; it refers to succession to a title. /2/ It is never required between the covenantor and covenantee or any other parties, except between the current owner and the original covenantee. And fundamentally, it is only necessary between them in cases—like warranties and probably covenants for title—where, looking at the covenants purely as contracts, the benefit is inherited, rather than being tied to the land.

If now it should be again asked, at the end of this long discussion, where the line is to be drawn between these two classes of covenants, the answer is necessarily vague in view of the authorities. The following propositions may be of some service.

If it’s asked again, at the end of this long discussion, where the line should be drawn between these two types of covenants, the answer will be somewhat unclear given the sources. The following points may be helpful.

*A. With regard to covenants which go with the land:—

*A. Concerning covenants that are tied to the property:*

*(1.) Where either by tradition or good sense the burden of the obligation would be said, elliptically, to fall on the land of the covenantor, the creation of such a burden is in theory a grant or transfer of a partial interest in [405] that land to the covenantee. As the right of property so created can be asserted against every possessor of the land, it would not be extravagant or absurd to allow it to be asserted by the action of covenant.

*(1.) Where either by tradition or common sense the responsibility of the obligation is considered to fall, indirectly, on the land of the person making the covenant, establishing such a responsibility basically means granting or transferring a partial interest in [405] that land to the person receiving the covenant. Since the property right created can be claimed against anyone who possesses the land, it wouldn’t be unreasonable or ridiculous to allow it to be enforced through a lawsuit for breach of covenant.*

*(2.) Where such a right is granted to the owner of a neighboring piece of land for the benefit of that land, the right will be attached to the land, and go with it into all hands. The action of covenant would be allowed to assigns not named, and it would not be absurd to give it to disseisors.

*(2.) When a right is granted to the owner of a neighboring piece of land for the benefit of that land, the right will be attached to the land and will transfer with it to all future owners. The action of covenant would be permitted for assigns not specifically named, and it wouldn’t be unreasonable to extend it to those who have been wrongfully deprived of possession.*

*(3.) There is one case of a service, the burden of which does not fall upon land even in theory, but the benefit of which might go at common law with land which it benefited. This is the case of singing and the like by a convent. It will be observed that the service, although not falling on land, is to be performed by a corporation permanently seated in the neighborhood. Similar cases are not likely to arise now.

*(3.) There is one situation involving a service, where the responsibility doesn't technically fall on land, but the advantage might legally go with the land that it served. This situation is about singing and similar activities performed by a convent. It's important to note that the service, while not attached to land, is carried out by a group that is permanently established in the area. Similar situations are not likely to come up nowadays.*

*B. With regard to covenants which go only with the estate in the land:—

*B. Concerning agreements that are tied solely to the property itself:—

In general the benefit of covenants which cannot be likened to grants, and the burden of which does not fall on land, is confined to the covenantee and those who sustain his persona, namely, his executor or heir. In certain cases, of which the original and type was the ancient warranty, and of which the modern covenants for title are present examples, the sphere of succession was enlarged by the mention of assigns, and assigns are still allowed to represent the original covenantee for the purposes of that contract. But it is only by way of succession that any other person than the party to the contract can sue upon it. Hence the plaintiff must always be privy in estate with the covenantee.

In general, the benefits of covenants that aren’t similar to grants and don’t impose burdens on land are limited to the covenantee and those who inherit his position, such as his executor or heir. In certain situations—such as the original example of the ancient warranty and modern covenants for title—this scope of succession was expanded to include assigns. Assigns can still act on behalf of the original covenantee for the purposes of that contract. However, only through succession can anyone other than the original party to the contract bring a lawsuit based on it. Therefore, the plaintiff must always have a shared estate with the covenantee.

[406] C. It is impossible, however, to tell by general reasoning what rights will be held in English law to belong to the former class, or where the line will be drawn between the two. The authorities must be consulted as an arbitrary fact. Although it might sometimes seem that the test of the first was whether the service was of a nature capable of grant, so that if it rested purely in covenant it would not follow the land, /1/ yet if this test were accepted, it has already been shown that, apart from tradition, some services which do follow the land could only be matter of covenant. The grant of light and air, a well- established easement, is called a covenant not to build on the servient land to the injury of the light, by Baron Parke. /2/ And although this might be doubted, /3/ it has been seen that at least one well-established easement, that of fencing, cannot be considered as a right granted out of the servient land with any more propriety than a hundred other services which would be only matter of contract if the law allowed them to be annexed to land in like manner. The duty to repair exists only by way of covenant, yet the reasoning of the leading cases is drawn from the law of easement. On the other hand, a covenant by a lessee to build a wall upon the leased premises was held, in Spencer's Case, not to bind assigns unless mentioned; /4/ but Lord Coke says that it would have bound them if it had purported to. The analogy of warranty makes its appearance, and throws a doubt on the fundamental principle of the case. We can only say that the application [407] of the law is limited by custom, and by the rule that new and unusual burdens cannot be imposed on land.

[406] C. However, it's impossible to determine by general reasoning which rights in English law belong to the first class, or where the line will be drawn between the two. The authorities must be referenced as an arbitrary fact. Although it might sometimes seem that the first test was whether the service could be granted, so that if it was purely a covenant it wouldn't follow the land, /1/ it's already been shown that, apart from tradition, some services that do follow the land could only be a matter of covenant. The grant of light and air, a well-established easement, is referred to by Baron Parke as a covenant not to build on the servient land to the detriment of the light. /2/ And while this may be questioned, /3/ it's been noted that at least one well-established easement, that of fencing, cannot be viewed as a right granted out of the servient land with any more validity than a hundred other services that would only be contractual matters if the law allowed them to be attached to land in the same way. The obligation to repair exists only through a covenant, yet the reasoning in leading cases is derived from the law of easement. On the other hand, a lessee's covenant to build a wall on the leased premises was held in Spencer's Case not to bind successors unless mentioned; /4/ but Lord Coke states that it would have bound them if it had stated so. The analogy of warranty comes into play and raises doubt about the fundamental principle of the case. We can only say that the application [407] of the law is limited by custom and by the rule that new and unusual burdens cannot be placed on land.

The general object of this Lecture is to discover the theory on which a man is allowed to enjoy a special right when the facts out of which the right arises are not true of him. The transfer of easements presented itself as one case to be explained, and that has now been analyzed, and its influence on the law has been traced. But the principle of such transfers is clearly anomalous, and does not affect the general doctrine of the law. The general doctrine is that which has been seen exemplified in prescription, warranty, and such covenants as followed the analogy mentioned Another illustration which has not yet been is to be found in the law of uses.

The main goal of this Lecture is to explore the theory behind why someone can have a specific right even when the facts that give rise to that right aren't true for them. The transfer of easements has been one example we've looked at, and we've analyzed it and traced its effect on the law. However, the principle behind such transfers is clearly unusual and doesn't impact the overall legal doctrine. The general doctrine is exemplified in prescription, warranty, and similar covenants that follow the mentioned analogy. Another example that hasn't been discussed yet is found in the law of uses.

In old times a use was a chose in action,—that is, was considered very nearly from the point of view of contract, and it had a similar history to that which has been traced in other cases. At first it was doubted whether proof of such a secret trust ought to be allowed, even as against the heir. /1/ It was allowed, however, in the end, /2/ and then the principle of succession was extended to the assign. But it never went further. Only those who were privies in estate with the original feoffee to uses, were bound by the use. A disseisor was no more bound by the confidence reposed in his disseisee, than he was entitled to vouch his disseisee's warrantor. In the time of Henry VIII. it was said that "where a use shall be, it is requisite that there be two things, sc. confidence, and privity:... as I say, if there be not privity or confidence, [408] then there can be no use: and hence if the feoffees make a feoffment to one who has notice of the use, now the law will adjudge him seised to the first use, since there is sufficient privity between the first feoffor and him, for if he [i.e. the first feoflor] had warranted he [the last feoffee] should vouch as assign, which proves privity; and he is in in the per by the feoffees; but where one comes into the land in the post, as the lord by escheat or the disseisor, then the use is altered and changed, because privity is wanting." /1/

In the past, a use was considered a legal right to take action, meaning it was viewed similarly to a contract, and it had a history like other legal cases. Initially, there was doubt about whether proof of such a secret trust should be accepted, even against the heir. However, it was eventually permitted, and then the principle of succession was extended to the assignee. But it never went beyond that. Only those who had a close relationship with the original holder of the use were bound by it. A disseisor was not bound by the trust that the disseisee had in him, just as he could not invoke the disseisee’s third-party rights. During the reign of Henry VIII, it was stated that "for there to be a use, two things are necessary: confidence and a close relationship. If there is no close relationship or trust, then there can be no use. Therefore, if the feoffees convey property to someone who is aware of the use, the law will deem him to hold the property for the first use, since there is enough connection between the first feoffor and him. If the first feoffor had given a warranty, the last feoffee could rely on it as an assignee, proving the connection exists. He is in possession due to the feoffees; however, when someone comes into possession later, like the lord through escheat or the disseisor, the use gets altered and changed because the necessary connection is absent."

To this day it is said that a trust is annexed in privity to the person and to the estate /2/ (which means to the persona). It is not regarded as issuing out of the land like a rent, so that while a rent binds every one who has the land, no matter how, a disseisor is not bound by the trust. /3/ The case of the lord taking by escheat has been doubted, /4/ and it will be remembered that there is a difference between Bracton and later authors as to whether he comes in as quasi heres or as a stranger.

To this day, it's said that a trust is linked to the person and to the estate /2/ (which refers to the individual). It's not considered a product of the land like a rent, so while a rent affects everyone who has the land, regardless of how they acquired it, a disseisor is not obligated by the trust. /3/ The situation of the lord taking through escheat has raised questions, /4/ and it's important to note that there's a difference between Bracton and later writers regarding whether he comes in as a quasi heir or as a stranger.

Then as to the benefit of the use. We are told that the right to sue the subpoena descended indeed to the heir, on the ground of heres eadem persona cum antecessore, but that it was not assets. /5/ The cestui que use was given power to sell by an early statute. /6/ But with regard to trusts, Lord Coke tells us that in the reign of Queen Elizabeth [409] all the judges in England held that a trust could not be assigned, "because it was a matter in privity between them, and was in the nature of a chose in action." /1/ Uses and trusts were both devisable, however, from an early day, /2/ and now trusts are as alienable as any form of property.

Then regarding the benefits of use. We are told that the right to sue through the subpoena indeed passed down to the heir, based on the principle of heres eadem persona cum antecessore, but that it wasn't considered assets. /5/ The cestui que use was given the authority to sell by an early statute. /6/ However, concerning trusts, Lord Coke informs us that during the reign of Queen Elizabeth [409] all the judges in England agreed that a trust could not be assigned, "because it was a matter in privity between them, and was in the nature of a chose in action." /1/ Both uses and trusts were, however, transferable from an early time, /2/ and now trusts are as transferable as any type of property.

The history of early law everywhere shows that the difficulty of transferring a mere right was greatly felt when the situation of fact from which it sprung could not also be transferred. Analysis shows that the difficulty is real. The fiction which made such a transfer conceivable has now been explained, and its history has been followed until it has been seen to become a general mode of thought. It is now a matter of course that the buyer stands in the shoes of the seller, or, in the language of an old law-book, /3/ that "the assign is in a manner quasi successor to his assignor." Whatever peculiarities of our law rest on that assumption may now be understood.

The history of early law everywhere shows that the challenge of transferring just a right was keenly felt when the actual situation that created it couldn’t also be transferred. Analysis reveals that this challenge is real. The concept that made such a transfer possible has now been clarified, and its history has been traced until it has become a common way of thinking. It is now standard that the buyer takes on the responsibilities of the seller, or, in the words of an old legal text, /3/ that "the assignee is in a way a quasi successor to their assignor." Any unique aspects of our law based on that assumption can now be understood.






FOOTNOTES

3 (return)

3 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

3/1 E.g. Ine, c. 74; Alfred, c. 42; Ethelred, IV. 4, Section 1.

3/1 E.g. Ine, c. 74; Alfred, c. 42; Ethelred, IV. 4, Section 1.

3/2 Bract., fol. 144, 145; Fleta, I. c. 40, 41; Co. Lit. 126b; Hawkins, P.C., Bk. 2, ch. 23, Section 15.

3/2 Bract., fol. 144, 145; Fleta, I. c. 40, 41; Co. Lit. 126b; Hawkins, P.C., Bk. 2, ch. 23, Section 15.

3/3 Lib. I. c. 2, ad fin.

3/3 Lib. I. c. 2, ad fin.

3 /4 Bract., fol. 144a, "assulto praemeditato."

3 /4 Bract., fol. 144a, "premeditated assault."

4 (return)

4 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

4/1 Fol. 155; cf. 103b.

4/1 Fol. 155; see also 103b.

4/2 Y.B. 6 Ed. IV. 7, pl. 18.

4/2 Y.B. 6 Ed. IV. 7, pl. 18.

4/3 Ibid., and 21 H. VII. 27, pl. 5.

4/3 Ibid., and 21 H. VII. 27, pl. 5.

4/4 D. 47. 9. 9.

4/4 D. 47. 9. 9.

7 (return)

7 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

7/1 xxi. 28.

7/1 xxi. 28.

7/2 [theta], ix. Jowett's Tr., Bk. IX. p. 437; Bohn's Tr., pp. 378, 379.

7/2 [theta], ix. Jowett's Tr., Bk. IX. p. 437; Bohn's Tr., pp. 378, 379.

7/3 [theta], xv., Jowett, 449; Bohn, 397.

7/3 [theta], xv., Jowett, 449; Bohn, 397.

8 (return)

8 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

8/1 [iota alpha], xiv., Jowett, 509; Bohn, 495.

8/1 [iota alpha], xiv., Jowett, 509; Bohn, 495.

8/2 [theta], xii., Jowett, 443, 444; Bohn, 388.

8/2 [theta], xii., Jowett, 443, 444; Bohn, 388.

8/3 [Greek words]. 244, 245.

8/3 [Greek words]. 244, 245.

8/4 l. 28 (11).

8/4 l. 28 (11).

8/5 Solon.

8/5 Solon.

8/6 "Si quadrupes pauperiem fecisse dicetur actio ex lege duodecim tabularum descendit; quae lex voluit, aut dari [id] quod nocuit, id ist, id animal, quod noxiam commisit; aut estimationem noxiae offerre." D. 9. 1. 1, pr.; Just. Inst. 4. 9; XII Tab., VIII. 6.

8/6 "If a quadruped is said to have caused damage, the action arises from the Law of the Twelve Tables; this law dictates that either the owner must provide compensation for the harm done by the animal that committed the offense, or offer an assessment of the damage." D. 9. 1. 1, pr.; Just. Inst. 4. 9; XII Tab., VIII. 6.

8/7 Gaii Inst. IV. Sections 75, 76; D. 9. 4. 2, Section 1. "Si servus furtum faxit noxiam ve noxit." XII Tab., XII.2. Cf. Just. Inst. 4.8, Section 7.

8/7 Gaii Inst. IV. Sections 75, 76; D. 9. 4. 2, Section 1. "If a slave commits theft or harms." XII Tab., XII.2. Cf. Just. Inst. 4.8, Section 7.

9 (return)

9 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

9/1 D. 39. 2. 7, Sections 1, 2; Gaii Inst. IV. Section 75.

9/1 D. 39. 2. 7, Sections 1, 2; Gaii Inst. IV. Section 75.

9/2 "Noxa caput sequitur." D. 9. 1. 1, Section 12; Inst. 4.8, Section 5.

9/2 "The harm follows the head." D. 9. 1. 1, Section 12; Inst. 4.8, Section 5.

9/3 "Quia desinit dominus esse ubi fera evasit." D. 9. 1. 1, Section 10; Inst. 4. 9, pr. Compare May v. Burdett, 9 Q.B.101, 113.

9/3 "Because the master no longer exists where the wild animal has escaped." D. 9. 1. 1, Section 10; Inst. 4. 9, pr. Compare May v. Burdett, 9 Q.B.101, 113.

10 (return)

10 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

10/1 D. 19. 5. 14, Section 3; Plin. Nat. Hist., XVIII. 3.

10/1 D. 19. 5. 14, Section 3; Plin. Nat. Hist., XVIII. 3.

10/2 "In lege antiqua si servus sciente domino furtum fecit, vel aliam noxiam commisit, servi nomine actio est noxalis, nec dominus suo nomine tenetur." D. 9. 4. 2.

10/2 "In ancient law, if a slave committed theft with the owner’s knowledge, or committed another harmful act, the action for damages is against the slave's name, and the owner is not liable in his own name." D. 9. 4. 2.

10/3 Gaius, Inst. IV. Section 77, says that a noxal action may change to a direct, and conversely, a direct action to a noxal. If a paterfamilias commits a tort, and then is adopted or becomes a slave, a noxal action now lies against his master in place of the direct one against himself as the wrong-doer. Just. Inst. 4. 8, Section 5.

10/3 Gaius, Inst. IV. Section 77, states that a noxal action can turn into a direct action, and vice versa, a direct action can turn into a noxal action. If a paterfamilias commits a tort, and then is adopted or becomes a slave, a noxal action can now be brought against his master instead of a direct one against him as the wrong-doer. Just. Inst. 4. 8, Section 5.

11 (return)

11 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

11/1 LL. Alfred, c. 13; 1 Tylor, Primitive Culture, Am. ed., p. 285 et seq.; Bain, Mental and Moral Science, Bk. III. ch. 8, p. 261.

11/1 LL. Alfred, c. 13; 1 Tylor, Primitive Culture, Am. ed., p. 285 et seq.; Bain, Mental and Moral Science, Bk. III. ch. 8, p. 261.

11/2 Florus, Epitome, II. 18. Cf. Livy, IX 1, 8, VIII. 39; Zonaras, VII. 26, ed. Niebuhr, vol. 43, pp. 98, 99.

11/2 Florus, Epitome, II. 18. See Livy, IX 1, 8, VIII. 39; Zonaras, VII. 26, ed. Niebuhr, vol. 43, pp. 98, 99.

12 (return)

12 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

12/1 Gaii Inst. IV. Section 81. I give the reading of Huschke: "Licere enim etiam, si fato is fuerit mortuus, mortuum dare; nam quamquam diximus, non etiam permissum reis esse, et mortuos homines dedere, tamen et si quis eum dederit, qui fato suo vita excesserit, aeque liberatur." Ulpian's statement, in D. 9. 1. 1, Section 13, that the action is gone if the animal dies ante litem contestatam, is directed only to the point that liability is founded on possession of the thing.

12/1 Gaii Inst. IV. Section 81. I'm presenting Huschke's reading: "It's allowed to hand over a dead person if they have died by fate; for although we said that it's not allowed for those accused to give over dead people, if someone does give over someone who has passed away due to their fate, they are equally freed from responsibility." Ulpian's statement in D. 9. 1. 1, Section 13, that the claim is lost if the animal dies before the lawsuit has begun, is aimed solely at the fact that liability is based on possession of the item.

12/2 "Bello contra foedus suscepto."

12/2 "Beautiful against the chosen pact."

12/3 Livy, VIII. 39: "Vir...haud dubie proximarum induciarum ruptor. De eo coacti referre praetores decretum fecerunt 'Ut Brutulus Papius Romanis dederetur."...Fetiales Romam, ut censuerunt, missi, et corpus Brutuli exanime: ipse morte voluntaria ignominiae se ac supplicio subtraxit. Placuit cum corpore bona quoque ejus dedi." Cf. Zonaras, VII. 26, ed. Niebuhr, vol. 43, p. 97: [Greek characters]. See further Livy, V. 36, "postulatumque ut pro jure gentium violato Fabii dederentur," and Ib. I. 32.

12/3 Livy, VIII. 39: "The man...without a doubt, the violator of the recent truce. Consequently, the praetors decided to report that 'Brutulus Papius should be handed over to the Romans.'...Fetiales were sent to Rome as agreed, and the lifeless body of Brutulus was found: he himself removed the shame and punishment by choosing to die willingly. It was decided to give his possessions along with his body." Cf. Zonaras, VII. 26, ed. Niebuhr, vol. 43, p. 97: [Greek characters]. See further Livy, V. 36, "and they demanded that the Fabii be handed over for violating international law," and Ib. I. 32.

13 (return)

13 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

13/1 Livy, IX. 5, 8, 9, 10. "Nam quod deditione nostra negant exsolvi religione populum, id istos magis ne dedantur, quam quia ita se res habeat, dicere, quis adeo juris fetialium expers est, qui ignoret?" The formula of surrender was as follows: "Quandoque hisce homines injussu populi Romani Quiritium foedus ictum iri spoponderunt, atque ob eam rem noxam nocuerunt; ob eam rem, quo populus Romanus scelere impio sit solutus, hosce homines vobis dedo." Cf. Zonaras, VII. 26, ed. Niebuhr, vol. 43, pp. 98, 99.

13/1 Livy, IX. 5, 8, 9, 10. "The reason they claim that our surrender does not free the population from its religious obligations is more to ensure that they themselves do not surrender, rather than because it is actually the case. Who among those ignorant of the rules of the fetial law would not know this?" The surrender formula was as follows: "Whenever these men have promised, without the command of the Roman people, to enter into a treaty, and for this reason have harmed themselves; for this reason, in order for the Roman people to be freed from this wicked injury, I hand these men over to you." Cf. Zonaras, VII. 26, ed. Niebuhr, vol. 43, pp. 98, 99.

13/2 De Orator. I. 40, and elsewhere. It is to be noticed that Florus, in his account, says deditione Mancini expiavit. Epitome, II. 18. It has already been observed that the cases mentioned by Livy seem to suggest that the object of the surrender was expiation, as much as they do that it was satisfaction of a contract. Zonaras says, Postumius and Calvinus [Greek characters]. (VII. 26, ed. Niebuhr, Vol. 43, pp. 98, 99.) Cf. ib. p. 97. Compare Serv. ad Virg. Eclog. IV. 43: "In legibus Numae cautum est, ut si quis imprudens occidisset hominem pro capite occisi et natis [agnatis? Huschke] ejus in concione offerret arietem." Id. Geor. III. 387, and Festus, Subici, Subigere. But cf. Wordsworth's Fragments and Specimens of Early Latin, note to XII Tab., XII. 2, p. 538.

13/2 De Orator. I. 40, and elsewhere. It should be noted that Florus, in his account, states that Mancini's surrender was for atonement. Epitome, II. 18. It's already been pointed out that the examples mentioned by Livy seem to imply that the purpose of the surrender was for expiation just as much as it was for fulfilling a contract. Zonaras says, Postumius and Calvinus [Greek characters]. (VII. 26, ed. Niebuhr, Vol. 43, pp. 98, 99.) Cf. ib. p. 97. Compare Serv. ad Virg. Eclog. IV. 43: "In the laws of Numa, it is stipulated that if someone unintentionally killed a man, he should offer a ram for the life of the killed person and their descendants in the assembly." Id. Geor. III. 387, and Festus, Subici, Subigere. But cf. Wordsworth's Fragments and Specimens of Early Latin, note to XII Tab., XII. 2, p. 538.

14 (return)

14 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

14/1 D. 9. 4. 2

14/1 D. 9. 4. 2

14/2 2 Tissot, Droit Penal, 615; 1 Ihering, Geist d. Roem. R., Section 14; 4 id. Section 63.

14/2 2 Tissot, Criminal Law, 615; 1 Ihering, Spirit of Roman Law, Section 14; 4 id. Section 63.

14/3 Aul. Gell. Noctes Attici, 20. 1; Quintil. Inst. Orat. 3. 6. 84; Tertull. Apol., c. 4.

14/3 Aul. Gell. Noctes Attici, 20. 1; Quintil. Inst. Orat. 3. 6. 84; Tertull. Apol., c. 4.

14/4 Cf. Varro, De Lingua Latina, VI.: "Liber, qui suas operas in servitute pro pecunia, quam debeat, dum solveret Nexus vocatur."

14/4 Cf. Varro, De Lingua Latina, VI.: "A book is called a 'Liber' when it represents the work performed in servitude for money owed, while it is being paid off."

15 (return)

15 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

15/1 D. 9. 1. 1, Section 9 But cf. 1 Hale, P.C. 420.

15/1 D. 9. 1. 1, Section 9 But see 1 Hale, P.C. 420.

15/2 D. 9. 4. 2, Section 1.

15/2 D. 9. 4. 2, Section 1.

15/3 D. 9. 1. 1, Sections 4, 5.

15/3 D. 9. 1. 1, Sections 4, 5.

16 (return)

16 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

16/1 D. 4. 9. 1, Section 1; ib. 7, Section 4.

16/1 D. 4. 9. 1, Section 1; ib. 7, Section 4.

16/2 Gaius in D. 44. 7. 5, Section 6; Just. Inst. 4. 5, Section 3.

16/2 Gaius in D. 44. 7. 5, Section 6; Just. Inst. 4. 5, Section 3.

16/3 D. 4. 9. 7, pr.

16/3 D. 4. 9. 7, pr.

17 (return)

17 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

17/1 See Austin, Jurisp. (3d ed.) 513; Doctor and Student, Dial. 2, ch. 42.

17/1 See Austin, Jurisp. (3d ed.) 513; Doctor and Student, Dial. 2, ch. 42.

17/2 Cf. L. Burgund. XVIII.; L. Rip. XLVI. (al. 48).

17/2 Cf. L. Burgund. XVIII.; L. Rip. XLVI. (or 48).

17/3 See the word Lege, Merkel, Lex Salica, p. 103. Cf. Wilda, Strafrecht der Germanen, 660, n. 1. See further Lex Salica, XL.; Pactus pro tenore pacis Child. et Chloth., c. 5; Decretio Chlotharii, c. 5; Edictus Hilperichi, cc. 5, 7; and the observations of Sohm in his treatise on the Procedure of the Salic Law, Sections 20, 22, 27, French Tr. (Thevenin), pp. 83 n., 93, 94, 101-103, 130.

17/3 See the word Lege, Merkel, Lex Salica, p. 103. Cf. Wilda, Strafrecht der Germanen, 660, n. 1. See further Lex Salica, XL.; Pactus pro tenore pacis Child. et Chloth., c. 5; Decretio Chlotharii, c. 5; Edictus Hilperichi, cc. 5, 7; and the observations of Sohm in his treatise on the Procedure of the Salic Law, Sections 20, 22, 27, French Tr. (Thevenin), pp. 83 n., 93, 94, 101-103, 130.

17/4 Wilda, Strafrecht, 590.

17/4 Wilda, Criminal Law, 590.

18 (return)

18 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

18/1 Cf. Wilda, Strafrecht, 660, n. 1; Merkel, Lex Salica, Gloss. Lege, p. 103. Lex Saxon. XI. Section 3: "Si servus perpetrato facinore fugerit, ita ut adomino ulterius inveniri non possit, nihil solvat." Cf. id. II. Section 5. Capp. Rip. c. 5: "Nemini liceat servum suum, propter damnum ab illo cuibet inlatum, dimittere; sed justa qualitatem damni dominus pro illo respondeat vel eum in compositione aut ad poenam petitori offeret. Si autem servus perpetrato scelere fugerit, ita ut a domino paenitus inveniri non possit, sacramento se dominus ejus excusare studeat, quod nec suae voluntatis nec conscientia fuisset, quod servus ejus tale facinus commisit."

18/1 Cf. Wilda, Criminal Law, 660, n. 1; Merkel, Lex Salica, Gloss. Law, p. 103. Lex Saxon. XI. Section 3: "If a servant escapes after committing a crime, so that the master cannot find him any longer, he owes nothing." Cf. id. II. Section 5. Capp. Rip. c. 5: "No one is allowed to dismiss their servant because of damage caused by that servant to anyone; the master must respond for the rightful amount of the damage or offer the servant in compensation or as punishment to the claimant. However, if the servant escapes after committing a serious crime, so that the master cannot find him at all, the master should try to excuse himself with an oath, stating that it was neither his will nor his conscience that the servant committed such an act."

18/2 L. Saxon. XI. Section 1.

18/2 L. Saxon. XI. Section 1.

18/3 Lex Angl. et Wer. XVI.: "Omne damnum quod servus fecerit dominus emendet."

18/3 Lex Angl. et Wer. XVI.: "The master is responsible for any harm caused by the servant."

19 (return)

19 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

19/1 C. 3; 1 Thorpe, Anc. Laws, pp. 27, 29.

19/1 C. 3; 1 Thorpe, Anc. Laws, pp. 27, 29.

19/2 C. 74; 1 Thorpe, p. 149; cf. p. 118, n. a. See LL. Hen. I., LXX. Section 5.

19/2 C. 74; 1 Thorpe, p. 149; cf. p. 118, n. a. See LL. Hen. I., LXX. Section 5.

19/3 C. 24; 1 Thorpe, p. 79. Cf. Ine, c. 42; 1 Thorpe, p. 129.

19/3 C. 24; 1 Thorpe, p. 79. Cf. Ine, c. 42; 1 Thorpe, p. 129.

19/4 C. 13; 1 Thorpe, p. 71.

19/4 C. 13; 1 Thorpe, p. 71.

19/5 1 Tylor, Primitive Culture, Am. ed., p. 286.

19/5 1 Tylor, Primitive Culture, Am. ed., p. 286.

20 (return)

20 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

20/1 Cf. Record in Molloy, Book 2, ch. 3, Section 16, 24 Ed. III.: "Visum fuit curiae, quod unusquisque magister navis tenetur respondere de quacunque transgressione per servientes suos in navi sua facta." The Laws of Oleron were relied on in this case. Cf. Stat. of the Staple, Ed. III., Stat. 2, c. 19. Later, the influence of the Roman law is clear.

20/1 See Record in Molloy, Book 2, ch. 3, Section 16, 24 Ed. III.: "It has been seen by the court that every shipmaster is obligated to answer for any wrongdoing committed by their crew on their ship." The Laws of Oleron were relied upon in this case. See Stat. of the Staple, Ed. III., Stat. 2, c. 19. Later, the influence of Roman law is evident.

20/2 Quon. Attach., c. 48, pl. 10 et seq. Cf. The Forme and Maner of Baron Courts, c. 62 et seq.

20/2 Quon. Attach., c. 48, pl. 10 et seq. Cf. The Forme and Maner of Baron Courts, c. 62 et seq.

21 (return)

21 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

21/1 Forme and Maner of Baron Courts, c. 63.

21/1 Form and Manner of Baron Courts, c. 63.

21/2 C. 64. This substantially follows the Quoniam Attachiamenta, c. 48, pl. 13, but is a little clearer. Contra, Fitzh. Abr. Corone, Pl. 389, 8 Ed. II.

21/2 C. 64. This closely follows the Quoniam Attachiamenta, c. 48, pl. 13, but is somewhat clearer. In contrast, Fitzh. Abr. Corone, Pl. 389, 8 Ed. II.

22 (return)

22 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

22/1 Fitzh. Abr. Barre, pl. 290.

22/1 Fitzh. Abr. Barre, pl. 290.

22/2 Mitchil v. Alestree, 1 Vent. 295; S.C. 2 Lev. 172; S.C. 3 Keb. 650. Cf. May b. Burdett, 9 Q.B.101, 113.

22/2 Mitchil v. Alestree, 1 Vent. 295; S.C. 2 Lev. 172; S.C. 3 Keb. 650. Cf. May b. Burdett, 9 Q.B.101, 113.

22/3 May v. Burdett, 9 Q.B.101.

22/3 May v. Burdett, 9 Q.B.101.

22/4 Mason v. Keeling, 12 Mod. 332, 335; S.C. 1 Ld. Raym. 606, 608.

22/4 Mason v. Keeling, 12 Mod. 332, 335; S.C. 1 Ld. Raym. 606, 608.

23 (return)

23 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

23/1 Williams, J. in Cox v. Burbidge, 13 C.B. N.S. 430, 438. Cf. Willes, J. in Read v. Edwards, 17 C.B. N.S. 245, 261.

23/1 Williams, J. in Cox v. Burbidge, 13 C.B. N.S. 430, 438. Cf. Willes, J. in Read v. Edwards, 17 C.B. N.S. 245, 261.

23/2 Mason v. Keeling, 1 Ld. Raym. 606, 608.

23/2 Mason v. Keeling, 1 Ld. Raym. 606, 608.

23/3 In the laws of Ine, c. 42 (1 Thorpe, Anc. Laws, 129), personal liability seems to be imposed where there is a failure to fence. But if an animal breaks hedges the only remedy mentioned is to kill it, the owner to have the skin and flesh, and forfeit the rest. The defendant was held "because it was found that this was for default of guarding them,...for default of good guard," in 27 Ass., pl. 56, fol. 141, A.D. 1353 or 1354. It is much later that the reason is stated in the absolute form, "because I am bound by law to keep my beasts without doing wrong to any one." Mich. 12 Henry VII., Keilway, 3b, pl. 7. See, further, the distinctions as to a horse killing a man in Regiam Majestatem, IV, c. 24.

23/3 In the laws of Ine, c. 42 (1 Thorpe, Anc. Laws, 129), personal liability appears to apply when there's a failure to maintain a fence. However, if an animal breaks through the hedges, the only solution mentioned is to kill it, with the owner entitled to the skin and flesh while forfeiting the rest. The defendant was found liable "because it was determined that this was due to not guarding them,...for failure to provide proper protection," in 27 Ass., pl. 56, fol. 141, A.D. 1353 or 1354. It's much later that the justification is stated more clearly, "because I am legally obligated to keep my animals without causing harm to anyone." Mich. 12 Henry VII., Keilway, 3b, pl. 7. See also the distinctions regarding a horse killing a person in Regiam Majestatem, IV, c. 24.

24 (return)

24 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

24/1 Fol. 128.

24/1 Fol. 128.

24/2 Cf. 1 Britton (Nich.), 6a, b, 16 (top paging 15, 39); Bract., fol. 136b; LL. Alfred, c. 13 (1 Thorpe, Anc. Laws, p. 71); Lex Saxon., Tit. XIII.; Leg Alamann., Tit. CIII. 24.

24/2 Cf. 1 Britton (Nich.), 6a, b, 16 (top paging 15, 39); Bract., fol. 136b; LL. Alfred, c. 13 (1 Thorpe, Anc. Laws, p. 71); Lex Saxon., Tit. XIII.; Leg Alamann., Tit. CIII. 24.

25 (return)

25 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

25/1 Fleta, I. 26, Section 10; Fitzh. Abr. Corone, pl. 416. See generally Staundforde, P.C., I. c. 2, fol. 20 et seq.; 1 Hale, P.C. 410 et seq.

25/1 Fleta, I. 26, Section 10; Fitzh. Abr. Corone, pl. 416. See generally Staundforde, P.C., I. c. 2, fol. 20 et seq.; 1 Hale, P.C. 410 et seq.

25/2 Doctor and Student, Dial. 2, c. 51.

25/2 Doctor and Student, Dial. 2, c. 51.

25/3 Plowd. 260.

25/3 Plowd. 260.

25/4 Jacob, Law Dict. Deodand.

25/4 Jacob, Law Dict. Deodand.

25/5 Y.B. 30 & 31 Ed. I., pp. 524, 525; cf. Bract., fol. 136b.

25/5 Y.B. 30 & 31 Ed. I., pp. 524, 525; cf. Bract., fol. 136b.

26 (return)

26 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

26/1 Fitzh. Abr. Corone, pl. 403.

26/1 Fitzh. Abr. Corone, pl. 403.

26/2 Bract. 122; 1 Britton (Nich.), top p. 16; Fleta, Ic. 25, Section 9, fol. 37.

26/2 Bract. 122; 1 Britton (Nich.), top p. 16; Fleta, Ic. 25, Section 9, fol. 37.

26/3 1 Hale, P.C. 423.

26/3 1 Hale, P.C. 423.

26/4 1 Rot. Parl. 372; 2 Rot. Parl. 345, 372a, b; 3 Rot. Parl. 94a, 120a, 121; 4 Rot. Parl. 12a, b, 492b, 493. But see 1 Hale, P.C. 423.

26/4 1 Rot. Parl. 372; 2 Rot. Parl. 345, 372a, b; 3 Rot. Parl. 94a, 120a, 121; 4 Rot. Parl. 12a, b, 492b, 493. But see 1 Hale, P.C. 423.

26/5 1 Black Book of the Admiralty, 242.

26/5 1 Black Book of the Admiralty, 242.

27 (return)

27 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

27/1 Cf. Ticonderoga, Swabey, 215, 217.

27/1 Cf. Ticonderoga, Swabey, 215, 217.

27/2 China, 7 Wall. 53.

27/2 China, 7 Wall. 53.

28 (return)

28 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

28/1 Doctor and Student, Dial. 2, c. 51.

28/1 Doctor and Student, Dial. 2, c. 51.

28/2 1 Roll. Abr. 530 (C) 1.

28/2 1 Roll. Abr. 530 (C) 1.

29 (return)

29 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

29/1 3 Black Book of Adm. 103.

29/1 3 Black Book of Adm. 103.

29/2 Malek Adhel, 2 How. 210, 234.

29/2 Malek Adhel, 2 How. 210, 234.

30 (return)

30 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

30/1 3 Kent, 218; Customs of the Sea, cap. 27, 141, 182, in 3 Black Book of the Admiralty, 103, 243, 245.

30/1 3 Kent, 218; Customs of the Sea, cap. 27, 141, 182, in 3 Black Book of the Admiralty, 103, 243, 245.

31 (return)

31 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

31/1 3 Kent's Comm. 188.

31/1 3 Kent's Comm. 188.

31/2 Clay v. Snelgrave, 1 Ld. Raym. 576, 577; S.C. 1 Salk. 33. Cf. Molloy, p. 355, Book II. ch. 3, Section 8.

31/2 Clay v. Snelgrave, 1 Ld. Raym. 576, 577; S.C. 1 Salk. 33. Cf. Molloy, p. 355, Book II. ch. 3, Section 8.

31/3 "Ans perdront lurs loers quant la nef est perdue." 2 Black Book, 213. This is from the Judgments of the Sea, which, according to the editor (II., pp. xliv., xlvii.), is the most ancient extant source of modern maritime law except the decisions of Trani. So Molloy, Book II. ch. 3, Section 7, p. 354: "If the ship perishes at sea they lose their wages." So 1 Siderfin, 236, pl. 2.

31/3 "They will lose their wages when the ship is lost." 2 Black Book, 213. This is from the Judgments of the Sea, which, according to the editor (II., pp. xliv., xlvii.), is the oldest existing source of modern maritime law aside from the decisions of Trani. As Molloy states in Book II, ch. 3, Section 7, p. 354: "If the ship is lost at sea, they forfeit their wages." So 1 Siderfin, 236, pl. 2.

32 (return)

32 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

32/1 3 Black Book, pp. lix., lxxiv.

32/1 3 Black Book, pp. lix., lxxiv.

32/2 3 Black Book, 263. It should be added, however, that it is laid down in the same book that, if the vessel is detained in port by the local authorities, the master is not bound to give the mariners wages, "for he has earned no freight."

32/2 3 Black Book, 263. It should be noted, however, that the same book states that if the vessel is held in port by the local authorities, the captain is not required to pay the crew wages, "because he has earned no freight."

32/3 Lipson v. Harrison, 2 Weekly Rep. 10. Cf. Louisa Jane, 2 Lowell, 295.

32/3 Lipson v. Harrison, 2 Weekly Rep. 10. Cf. Louisa Jane, 2 Lowell, 295.

32/4 3 Kent's Comm. (12th ed.), 218; ib. 138, n. 1.

32/4 3 Kent's Comm. (12th ed.), 218; ib. 138, n. 1.

32/5 3 Kent, 218.

32/5 3 Kent, 218.

32/6 Justin v. Ballam, 1 Salk. 34; S.C. 2 Ld. Raym. 805.

32/6 Justin v. Ballam, 1 Salk. 34; S.C. 2 Ld. Raym. 805.

33 (return)

33 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

33/1 D. 20. 4. 5 & 6; cf. Livy, XXX. 38.

33/1 D. 20. 4. 5 & 6; cf. Livy, XXX. 38.

33/2 Pardessus, Droit. Comm., n. 961.

33/2 Pardessus, Droit. Comm., n. 961.

33/3 3 Keb. 112, 114, citing 1 Roll. Abr. 530.

33/3 3 Keb. 112, 114, citing 1 Roll. Abr. 530.

34 (return)

34 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

34/1 Godbolt, 260.

34/1 Godbolt, 260.

34/2 3 Colquhoun, Roman Civil Law, Section 2196.

34/2 3 Colquhoun, Roman Civil Law, Section 2196.

35 (return)

35 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

35/1 Lex Salica (Merkel), LXXVII.; Ed. Hilperich., Section 5.

35/1 Lex Salica (Merkel), LXXVII.; Ed. Hilperich., Section 5.

36 (return)

36 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

36/1 See Lecture III., ad fin.

36/1 See Lecture III., ad fin.

39 (return)

39 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

39/1 Cf. 2 Hawk. P.C. 303 et seq.; 27 Ass. 25.

39/1 Cf. 2 Hawk. P.C. 303 et seq.; 27 Ass. 25.

40 (return)

40 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

40/1 2 Palgrave, Commonwealth, cxxx., cxxxi.

40/1 2 Palgrave, Commonwealth, cxxx., cxxxi.

41 (return)

41 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

41/1 Butler, Sermons, VIII. Bentham, Theory of Legislation (Principles of Penal Code, Part 2, ch. 16), Hildreth's tr., p. 309.

41/1 Butler, Sermons, VIII. Bentham, Theory of Legislation (Principles of Penal Code, Part 2, ch. 16), Hildreth's tr., p. 309.

41/2 General View of the Criminal Law of England, p. 99.

41/2 General View of the Criminal Law of England, p. 99.

43 (return)

43 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

43/1 Wharton, Crim. Law, (8th ed.) Section 8, n. 1.

43/1 Wharton, Criminal Law, (8th ed.) Section 8, note 1.

43/2 Ibid., Section 7.

43/2 Ibid., Sec. 7.

43/3 Even the law recognizes that this is a sacrifice. Commonwealth v. Sawin, 2 Pick. (Mass.) 547, 549.

43/3 Even the law acknowledges that this is a sacrifice. Commonwealth v. Sawin, 2 Pick. (Mass.) 547, 549.

47 (return)

47 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

47/1 Cf. 1 East, P.C. 294; United States v. Holmes, 1 Wall. Jr. 1; 1 Bishop, Crim. Law, Sections 347-349, 845 (6th ed.); 4 Bl. Comm. 31.

47/1 Cf. 1 East, P.C. 294; United States v. Holmes, 1 Wall. Jr. 1; 1 Bishop, Crim. Law, Sections 347-349, 845 (6th ed.); 4 Bl. Comm. 31.

51 (return)

51 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

51/1 Art. 223.

51/1 Art. 223.

51/2 General View of the Criminal Law of England, p. 116.

51/2 General View of the Criminal Law of England, p. 116.

53 (return)

53 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

53/1 Harris, Criminal Law, p. 13.

53/1 Harris, Criminal Law, p. 13.

53/2 Steph. Dig. Crim. Law, Art. 223, Illustration (6), and n. 1.

53/2 Steph. Dig. Crim. Law, Art. 223, Illustration (6), and n. 1.

56 (return)

56 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

56/1 4 Bl. Comm. 192.

56/1 4 Bl. Comm. 192.

57 (return)

57 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

57/1 Cf. 4 Bl. Comm. 197.

57/1 Cf. 4 Bl. Comm. 197.

58 (return)

58 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

58/1 Reg. v. Hibbert, L.R. 1 C.C. 184.

58/1 Reg. v. Hibbert, L.R. 1 C.C. 184.

59 (return)

59 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

59/1 Reg. v. Prince, L.R. 2 C.C. 154.

59/1 Reg. v. Prince, L.R. 2 C.C. 154.

59/2 Commonwealth v. Hallett, 103 Mass. 452.

59/2 Commonwealth v. Hallett, 103 Mass. 452.

60 (return)

60 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

60/1 Stephen, Dig. Cr. Law, Art. 223, Illustr. (5); Foster, 294, 295.

60/1 Stephen, Dig. Cr. Law, Art. 223, Illustr. (5); Foster, 294, 295.

60/2 Cf. Gray's case, cited 2 Strange, 774.

60/2 Cf. Gray's case, cited 2 Strange, 774.

60/3 Steph. Dig., Art. 223, Illustr. (1).

60/3 Steph. Dig., Art. 223, Illustr. (1).

60/4 Steph. Dig., Art. 223, Illustr. (8).

60/4 Steph. Dig., Art. 223, Illustr. (8).

60/5 Rex v. Mastin, 6 C.&P. 396. Cf. Reg. v. Swindall, 2 C. & K. 230.

60/5 Rex v. Mastin, 6 C.&P. 396. Cf. Reg. v. Swindall, 2 C. & K. 230.

60/6 4 Bl. Comm. 192.

60/6 4 Bl. Comm. 192.

62 (return)

62 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

62/1 Steph. Dig. Cr. Law, Art. 225.

62/1 Steph. Dig. Cr. Law, Art. 225.

62/2 Rex v. Shaw, 6 C.&P. 372.

62/2 Rex v. Shaw, 6 C.&P. 372.

62/3 Rex v. Oneby, 2 Strange, 766, 773.

62/3 Rex v. Oneby, 2 Strange, 766, 773.

62/4 Rex v. Hayward, 6 C.&P. 157.

62/4 Rex v. Hayward, 6 C.&P. 157.

63 (return)

63 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

63/1 Commonwealth v. Walden, 3 Cush. (Mass.) 558. Cf. Steph. Gen. View of the Crim. Law, 84.

63/1 Commonwealth v. Walden, 3 Cush. (Mass.) 558. Cf. Steph. Gen. View of the Crim. Law, 84.

64 (return)

64 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

64/1 2 Bishop Crim. Law, Section 14 (6th ed.).

64/1 2 Bishop Crim. Law, Section 14 (6th ed.).

64/2 Glanv., Lib. XIV. c. 4.

64/2 Glanv., Lib. XIV. c. 4.

64/3 Bract., fol. 146b.

64/3 Bract., fol. 146b.

64/4 Ibid.

64/4 Same source.

64/5 2 East, P.C., c. 21, Sections 7, 8, pp. 1027, 1031.

64/5 2 East, P.C., c. 21, Sections 7, 8, pp. 1027, 1031.

66 (return)

66 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

66/1 1 Bishop, Crim. Law, Section 735 (6th ed.).

66/1 1 Bishop, Crim. Law, Section 735 (6th ed.).

66/2 Reg. v. Dilworth, 2 Moo. & Rob. 531; Reg. v. Jones, 9 C.&P. 258. The statement that a man is presumed to intend the natural consequences of his acts is a mere fiction disguising the true theory. See Lecture IV.

66/2 Reg. v. Dilworth, 2 Moo. & Rob. 531; Reg. v. Jones, 9 C.&P. 258. The idea that a person is assumed to intend the natural consequences of their actions is just a fiction that hides the real theory. See Lecture IV.

67 (return)

67 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

67/1 Reg. v. Taylor, 1 F. & F. 511.

67/1 Reg. v. Taylor, 1 F. & F. 511.

67/2 Reg. v. Roberts, 25 L. J. M. C. 17; S.C. Dearsly, C., C. 539.

67/2 Reg. v. Roberts, 25 L. J. M. C. 17; S.C. Dearsly, C., C. 539.

68 (return)

68 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

68/1 Lewis v. The State, 35 Ala. 380.

68/1 Lewis v. The State, 35 Ala. 380.

69 (return)

69 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

69/1 See M'Pherson's Case, Dearsly & Bell, 197, 201, Bramwell, B.

69/1 See M'Pherson's Case, Dearsly & Bell, 197, 201, Bramwell, B.

69/2 Cf. 1 Bishop, Crim. Law, Sections 741-745 (6th ed.).

69/2 Cf. 1 Bishop, Crim. Law, Sections 741-745 (6th ed.).

71 (return)

71 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

71/1 2 Bishop, Crim. Law, Section 758 (6th ed.).

71/1 2 Bishop, Crim. Law, Section 758 (6th ed.).

73 (return)

73 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

73/1 Cf. Stephen, General View of Criminal Law of England, 49 et seq.

73/1 Cf. Stephen, General View of Criminal Law of England, 49 et seq.

73/2 Cf. Stephen, General View, 49-52; 2 East, P.C. 553.

73/2 Cf. Stephen, General View, 49-52; 2 East, P.C. 553.

74 (return)

74 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

74/1 Rex v. Cabbage, Russ. & Ry. 292.

74/1 Rex v. Cabbage, Russ. & Ry. 292.

74/2 Cf. 4 Bl. Comm. 224; Steph. Dig. Crim. Law, Arts. 316, 319.

74/2 Cf. 4 Bl. Comm. 224; Steph. Dig. Crim. Law, Arts. 316, 319.

74/3 Cf. 4 Bl. Comm. 227, 228.

74/3 Cf. 4 Bl. Comm. 227, 228.

75 (return)

75 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

75/1 1 Starkie, Cr. Pl. 177. This doctrine goes further than my argument requires. For if burglary were dealt with only on the footing of an attempt, the whole crime would have to be complete at the moment of breaking into the house. Cf. Rex v. Furnival, Russ. & Ry. 445.

75/1 1 Starkie, Cr. Pl. 177. This principle goes beyond what my argument needs. If burglary were only considered as an attempt, the entire crime would have to be finished at the time of breaking into the house. Cf. Rex v. Furnival, Russ. & Ry. 445.

81 (return)

81 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

81/1 See Lecture VII.

See Lecture 7.

82 (return)

82 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

82/1 Austin, Jurisprudence (3d ed.), 440 et seq., 474, 484, Lect. XX., XXIV., XXV.

82/1 Austin, Jurisprudence (3d ed.), 440 et seq., 474, 484, Lect. XX., XXIV., XXV.

84 (return)

84 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

84/1 Lib. I. c. 2, ad fin.

84/1 Lib. I. c. 2, ad fin.

85 (return)

85 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

85/1 Hist. English Law, I. 113 (bis), n.a; Id., ed. Finlason, I. 178, n. 1. Fitzherbert (N.B. 85, F.) says that in the vicontiel writ of trespass, which is not returnable into the king's court, it shall not be said quare vi et armis. Cf. Ib. 86, H.

85/1 Hist. English Law, I. 113 (bis), n.a; Id., ed. Finlason, I. 178, n. 1. Fitzherbert (N.B. 85, F.) states that in the writ of trespass from the sheriff, which cannot be returned to the king's court, it shouldn't be stated "with force and arms." Cf. Ib. 86, H.

85/2 Milman v. Dolwell, 2 Camp. 378; Knapp v. Salsbury, 2 Camp. 500; Peafey v. Walter, 6 C.&P. 232; Hall v. Fearnley, 3 Q.B. 919.

85/2 Milman v. Dolwell, 2 Camp. 378; Knapp v. Salsbury, 2 Camp. 500; Peafey v. Walter, 6 C.&P. 232; Hall v. Fearnley, 3 Q.B. 919.

85/3 Y.B. 6 Ed. IV. 7, pl. 18, A.D. 1466; cf. Ames, Cases in Tort, 69, for a translation, which has been followed for the most part.

85/3 Y.B. 6 Ed. IV. 7, pl. 18, A.D. 1466; see Ames, Cases in Tort, 69, for a translation that has generally been used.

87 (return)

87 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

87/1 Y.B. 21 Hen. VII. 27, pl. 5, A.D. 1506.

87/1 Y.B. 21 Hen. VII. 27, pl. 5, A.D. 1506.

87/2 Cf. Bract., fol. 136 b. But cf. Stat. of Gloucester, 6 Ed. I. c. 9; Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 18, pl. 8, by Thirning; Essays in Ang. Sax. Law, 276.

87/2 Cf. Bract., fol. 136 b. But cf. Stat. of Gloucester, 6 Ed. I. c. 9; Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 18, pl. 8, by Thirning; Essays in Ang. Sax. Law, 276.

87/3 Hobart, 134, A.D. 1616.

87/3 Hobart, 134, AD 1616.

87/4 Sir T. Jones, 205, A.D. 1682.

87/4 Sir T. Jones, 205, A.D. 1682.

87/5 1 Strange, 596, A.D. 1723.

87/5 1 Strange, 596, A.D. 1723.

87/6 2 Keyes, 169, A.D. 1865.

87/6 2 Keyes, 169, A.D. 1865.

88 (return)

88 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

88/1 Anonymous, Cro. Eliz. 10, A.D. 1582.

88/1 Anonymous, Cro. Eliz. 10, A.D. 1582.

88/2 Sir T. Raym. 467, A.D. 1682.

88/2 Sir T. Raym. 467, A.D. 1682.

88/3 Scott v. Shepherd, 2 Wm. B1. 892, A.D. 1773.

88/3 Scott v. Shepherd, 2 Wm. B1. 892, A.D. 1773.

88/4 3 East, 593. See, further, Coleridge's note to 3 Bl. Comm. 123; Saunders, Negligence, ch. 1, Section I; argument in Fletcher v. Rylands, 3 H.&C. 774, 783; Lord Cranworth, in S.C., L.R. 3 H. L. 330, 341.

88/4 3 East, 593. See also Coleridge's note to 3 Bl. Comm. 123; Saunders, Negligence, ch. 1, Section I; argument in Fletcher v. Rylands, 3 H.&C. 774, 783; Lord Cranworth, in S.C., L.R. 3 H. L. 330, 341.

90 (return)

90 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

90/1 Ex. gr. Metropolitan Railway Co. v. Jackson, 3 App. Cas. 193. See M'Manus v. Crickett, 1 East, 106, 108.

90/1 Ex. gr. Metropolitan Railway Co. v. Jackson, 3 App. Cas. 193. See M'Manus v. Crickett, 1 East, 106, 108.

91 (return)

91 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

91/1 1 Ld. Raym. 38; S.C. Salk. 637; 4 Mod. 404; A.D. 1695.

91/1 1 Ld. Raym. 38; S.C. Salk. 637; 4 Mod. 404; A.D. 1695.

92 (return)

92 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

92/1 2 Wm. Bl. 892. Cf. Clark v. Chambers, 3 Q.B.D. 327, 330, 338.

92/1 2 Wm. Bl. 892. Cf. Clark v. Chambers, 3 Q.B.D. 327, 330, 338.

92/2 7 Vt, 62.

92/2 7 Vt, 62.

93 (return)

93 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

93/1 Smith v. London & South-Western Railway Co., L.R. 6 C.P. 14, 21. Cf. S.C., 5 id. 98, 103, 106.

93/1 Smith v. London & South-Western Railway Co., L.R. 6 C.P. 14, 21. Cf. S.C., 5 id. 98, 103, 106.

93/2 Sharp v. Powell, L.R. 7 C.P. 253. Cf. Clark v. Chambers, 3 Q.B.D. 327, 336-338. Many American cases could be cited which carry the doctrine further. But it is desired to lay down no proposition which admits of controversy, and it is enough for the present purposes that Si home fait un loyal act, que apres devint illoyal, ceo est damnum sine injuria. Latch, 13. I purposely omit any discussion of the true rule of damages where it is once settled that a wrong has been done. The text regards only the tests by which it is decided whether a wrong has been done.

93/2 Sharp v. Powell, L.R. 7 C.P. 253. Cf. Clark v. Chambers, 3 Q.B.D. 327, 336-338. Many American cases could be cited that take the doctrine even further. However, I want to avoid stating anything controversial, and it’s sufficient for now to say that if someone performs a legitimate act that later becomes illegitimate, it is considered damnum sine injuria. Latch, 13. I intentionally skip any discussion about the actual rule of damages once it’s established that a wrong has occurred. The text only focuses on the criteria used to determine whether a wrong has taken place.

94 (return)

94 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

94/1 Mitchil v. Alestree, 1 Ventris, 295; S.C., 3 Keb. 650; 2 Lev. 172. Compare Hammack v. White, 11 C.B. N.S. 588; infra, p. 158.

94/1 Mitchil v. Alestree, 1 Ventris, 295; S.C., 3 Keb. 650; 2 Lev. 172. Compare Hammack v. White, 11 C.B. N.S. 588; infra, p. 158.

95 (return)

95 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

95/1 Harvey v. Dunlop, Hill & Denio, (Lalor,) 193.

95/1 Harvey v. Dunlop, Hill & Denio, (Lalor,) 193.

95/2 See Lecture II. pp. 54, 55.

95/2 See Lecture II. pp. 54, 55.

97 (return)

97 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

97/1 cf. Hobart v. Hagget, 3 Fairf. (Me.) 67.

97/1 cf. Hobart v. Hagget, 3 Fairf. (Me.) 67.

98 (return)

98 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

98/1 See Bonomi v. Backhouse, El. Bl. & El. 622, Coleridge, J., at p. 640.

98/1 See Bonomi v. Backhouse, El. Bl. & El. 622, Coleridge, J., at p. 640.

99 (return)

99 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

99/1 3 Levirtz, 87, A.D. 1681.

99/1 3 Levirtz, 87, A.D. 1681.

99/2 Compare the rule as to cattle in Y.B. 22 Edw. IV. 8, pl. 24, stated below, p. 118.

99/2 Compare the rule regarding cattle in Y.B. 22 Edw. IV. 8, pl. 24, stated below, p. 118.

100 (return)

100 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

100/1 Disc. 123, pr.; 124, Sections 2, 3. As to the historical origin of the latter rule, compare Lecture V.

100/1 Disc. 123, pr.; 124, Sections 2, 3. For the historical origin of the latter rule, see Lecture V.

101 (return)

101 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

101/1 Lecture I, pp. 3, 4.

101/1 Lecture I, pp. 3, 4.

101/2 Lib. I. c. 2, ad. fin.

101/2 Lib. I. c. 2, ad. fin.

101/3 Fol. 155.

101/3 Fol. 155.

101/4 Bro. Trespass, pl. 119; Finch, 198; 3 Bl. Comm. 118, 119.

101/4 Bro. Trespass, pl. 119; Finch, 198; 3 Bl. Comm. 118, 119.

101/5 See Brunner, Schwurgerichte, p. 171.

101/5 See Brunner, Schwurgerichte, p. 171.

101/6 An example of the year 1195 will be found in Mr. Bigelow's very interesting and valuable Placita Anglo-Normanica, p. 285, citing Rot. Cur. Regis, 38; S.C. ? Abbr. Plac., fol. 2, Ebor. rot. 5. The suit was by way of appeal; the cause of action, a felonious trespass. Cf. Bract., fol. 144 a.

101/6 An example from the year 1195 can be found in Mr. Bigelow's very interesting and valuable "Placita Anglo-Normanica," p. 285, citing Rot. Cur. Regis, 38; S.C. ? Abbr. Plac., fol. 2, Ebor. rot. 5. The case was an appeal; the reason for the action was a criminal trespass. Cf. Bract., fol. 144 a.

102 (return)

102 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

102/1 An example may be seen in the Year Book, 30 & 31 Edward I. (Horwood), p. 106.

102/1 An example can be found in the Year Book, 30 & 31 Edward I. (Horwood), p. 106.

103 (return)

103 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

103/1 6 Ed. IV. 7, pl. 18.

103/1 6 Ed. IV. 7, pl. 18.

103/2 Popham, 151; Latch, 13, 119, A.D. 1605.

103/2 Popham, 151; Latch, 13, 119, A.D. 1605.

104 (return)

104 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

104/1 Hobart, 134, A.D. 1616.

104/1 Hobart, 134, AD 1616.

104/2 3 East, 593.

104/2 3 East, 593.

105 (return)

105 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

105/1 1 Bing. 213, A.D. 1823.

105/1 1 Bing. 213, A.D. 1823.

105/2 6 Cush. 292.

105/2 6 Cush. 292.

106 (return)

106 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

106/1 Morris v. Platt, 32 Conn. 75, 84 et seq., A.D. 1864.

106/1 Morris v. Platt, 32 Conn. 75, 84 et seq., A.D. 1864.

106/2 Nitro-glycerine Case (Parrot v. Wells), 15 Wall. 524, 538.

106/2 Nitro-glycerine Case (Parrot v. Wells), 15 Wall. 524, 538.

106/3 Hill & Denio, (Lalor,) 193; Losee v. Buchanan, 51 N.Y. 476, 489.

106/3 Hill & Denio, (Lalor,) 193; Losee v. Buchanan, 51 N.Y. 476, 489.

107 (return)

107 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

107/1 Vincent v. Stinehour, 7 Vt. 62. See, further, Clayton, 22, pl. 38; Holt, C.J., in Cole v. Turner, 6 Mod. 149; Lord Hardwicke, in Williams v. Jones, Cas. temp. Hardw. 298; Hall v. Fearnley, 8 Q.B. 919; Martin, B., in Coward v. Baddeley, 4 H.&N. 478; Holmes v. Mather, L.R. 10 Ex. 261; Bizzell v. Booker, 16 Ark. 308; Brown v. Collins, 53 N.H. 442.

107/1 Vincent v. Stinehour, 7 Vt. 62. See also, Clayton, 22, pl. 38; Holt, C.J., in Cole v. Turner, 6 Mod. 149; Lord Hardwicke, in Williams v. Jones, Cas. temp. Hardw. 298; Hall v. Fearnley, 8 Q.B. 919; Martin, B., in Coward v. Baddeley, 4 H.&N. 478; Holmes v. Mather, L.R. 10 Ex. 261; Bizzell v. Booker, 16 Ark. 308; Brown v. Collins, 53 N.H. 442.

107/2 Blyth v. Birmingham Waterworks Co., 11 Exch. 781, 784; Smith v. London & South-Western Ry. Co., L.R. 5 C.P. 98, 102. Compare Campbell, Negligence, Section 1 (2d ed.), for Austin's point of view.

107/2 Blyth v. Birmingham Waterworks Co., 11 Exch. 781, 784; Smith v. London & South-Western Ry. Co., L.R. 5 C.P. 98, 102. Compare Campbell, Negligence, Section 1 (2d ed.), for Austin's perspective.

109 (return)

109 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

109/1 cf. Bro. Corone, pl. 6; Neal v. Gillett, 23 Conn. 437, 442; D. 9. 2. 5, Section 2; D. 48. 8. 12.

109/1 cf. Bro. Corone, pl. 6; Neal v. Gillett, 23 Conn. 437, 442; D. 9. 2. 5, Section 2; D. 48. 8. 12.

113 (return)

113 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

113/1 I Thorpe, p. 85; cf. LL. Hen. I., c. 88, Section 3.

113/1 I Thorpe, p. 85; cf. LL. Hen. I., c. 88, Section 3.

113/2 Spofford v. Harlow, 3 Allen, 176.

113/2 Spofford v. Harlow, 3 Allen, 176.

114 (return)

114 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

114/1 See 27 Ass., pl. 56, fol. 141; Y.B. 43 Edw. III. 33, pl. 38. The plea in the latter case was that the defendant performed the cure as well as he knew how, without this that the horse died for default of his care. The inducement, at least, of this plea seems to deal with negligence as meaning the actual state of the party's mind.

114/1 See 27 Ass., pl. 56, fol. 141; Y.B. 43 Edw. III. 33, pl. 38. The plea in the latter case was that the defendant treated the horse as best as he could, without this meaning that the horse died due to his negligence. The basis of this plea seems to address negligence as referring to the actual mindset of the party involved.

115 (return)

115 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

115/1 Hobart, 134.

115/1 Hobart, 134.

115/2 See Knight v. Jermin, Cro. Eliz. 134; Chambers v. Taylor, Cro. Eliz. 900.

115/2 See Knight v. Jermin, Cro. Eliz. 134; Chambers v. Taylor, Cro. Eliz. 900.

115/3 32 Conn. 75, 89, 90.

115/3 32 Conn. 75, 89, 90.

116 (return)

116 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

116/1 Y.B. 12 Hen. VIII. 2 b, Pl. 2.

116/1 Y.B. 12 Hen. VIII. 2 b, Pl. 2.

116/2 Keilway, 46 b.

116/2 Keilway, 46 b.

116/3 L.R. 3 H.L. 330, 339; L.R. 1 Ex. 265, 279-282; 4 H.&C. 263; 3 id. 774.

116/3 L.R. 3 H.L. 330, 339; L.R. 1 Ex. 265, 279-282; 4 H.&C. 263; 3 id. 774.

117 (return)

117 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

117/1 See Card v. Case, 5 C.B. 622, 633, 634.

117/1 See Card v. Case, 5 C.B. 622, 633, 634.

117/2 See Lecture I. p. 23 and n. 3.

117/2 See Lecture I. p. 23 and n. 3.

117/3 Mitten v. Fandrye, Popham, 161; S.C., 1 Sir W. Jones, 136; S.C., nom. Millen v. Hawery, Latch, 13; id. 119. In the latter report, at p. 120, after reciting the opinion of the court in accordance with the text, it is said that judgment was given non obstant for the plaintiff; contrary to the earlier statement in the same book, and to Popham and Jones; but the principle was at all events admitted. For the limit, see Read v. Edwards, 17 C.B. N.S. 245.

117/3 Mitten v. Fandrye, Popham, 161; S.C., 1 Sir W. Jones, 136; S.C., nom. Millen v. Hawery, Latch, 13; id. 119. In the latter report, on page 120, after outlining the court's opinion in line with the text, it states that the judgment was given non obstant for the plaintiff; which contradicts the earlier statement in the same book, and to Popham and Jones; but the principle was acknowledged regardless. For the limit, see Read v. Edwards, 17 C.B. N.S. 245.

118 (return)

118 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

118/1 Y.B. 22 Edw. IV. 8, pl. 24.

118/1 Y.B. 22 Edw. IV. 8, pl. 24.

118/2 Popham, at p. 162; S.C., Latch, at p. 120; cf. Mason v. Keeling, 1 Ld. Raym. 606, 608. But cf. Y.B. 20 Edw. IV. 10, 11, pl. 10.

118/2 Popham, at p. 162; S.C., Latch, at p. 120; cf. Mason v. Keeling, 1 Ld. Raym. 606, 608. But cf. Y.B. 20 Edw. IV. 10, 11, pl. 10.

118/3 Latch, at p. 120. This is a further illustration of the very practical grounds on which the law of trespass was settled.

118/3 Latch, at p. 120. This is another example of the practical reasons behind the establishment of trespass law.

118/4 12 Mod. 332, 335; S.C., 1 Ld. Raym. 606, 608.

118/4 12 Mod. 332, 335; S.C., 1 Ld. Raym. 606, 608.

118/5 12 Mod. 335; Dyer, 25 b, pl. 162, and cas. in marg.; 4 Co. Rep. 18 b; Buxendin v. Sharp, 2 Salk. 662; S.C., 3 Salk. 169; S.C., nom. Bayntine v. Sharp, 1 Lutw. 90; Smith v. Pelah, 2 Strange, 264; May v. Burdett, 9 Q.B. 101; Card v. Case, 5 C.B. 622.

118/5 12 Mod. 335; Dyer, 25 b, pl. 162, and cases in margin; 4 Co. Rep. 18 b; Buxendin v. Sharp, 2 Salk. 662; S.C., 3 Salk. 169; S.C., also known as Bayntine v. Sharp, 1 Lutw. 90; Smith v. Pelah, 2 Strange, 264; May v. Burdett, 9 Q.B. 101; Card v. Case, 5 C.B. 622.

119 (return)

119 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

119/1 12 Mod. 335. See Andrew Baker's case, 1 Hale, P.C. 430.

119/1 12 Mod. 335. See Andrew Baker's case, 1 Hale, P.C. 430.

119/2 Besozzi v. Harris, 1 F.&F. 92.

119/2 Besozzi v. Harris, 1 F.&F. 92.

119/3 See Fletcher v. Rylands, L.R. I Ex. 265, 281, 282; Cox v. Burbridge, 13 C.B. N.S. 430, 441; Read v. Edwards, 17 C.B. N.S. 245, 260; Lee v. Riley, 18 C.B. N.S. 722; Ellis v. Loftus Iron Co., L.R. 10 C.P. 10; 27 Ass., pl. 56, fol. 141; Y.B. 20 Ed. IV. 11, pl. 10; 13 Hen. VII. 15, pl. 10; Keilway, 3 b, pl. 7. Cf. 4 Kent (12th ed.), 110, n. 1, ad fin.

119/3 See Fletcher v. Rylands, L.R. I Ex. 265, 281, 282; Cox v. Burbridge, 13 C.B. N.S. 430, 441; Read v. Edwards, 17 C.B. N.S. 245, 260; Lee v. Riley, 18 C.B. N.S. 722; Ellis v. Loftus Iron Co., L.R. 10 C.P. 10; 27 Ass., pl. 56, fol. 141; Y.B. 20 Ed. IV. 11, pl. 10; 13 Hen. VII. 15, pl. 10; Keilway, 3 b, pl. 7. Cf. 4 Kent (12th ed.), 110, n. 1, ad fin.

120 (return)

120 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

120/1 2 Ld. Raym. 909; 13 Am. L.R. 609.

120/1 2 Ld. Raym. 909; 13 Am. L.R. 609.

120/2 See Grill v. General Iron Screw Collier Co., L.R. 1 C.P. 600, 612, 614.

120/2 See Grill v. General Iron Screw Collier Co., L.R. 1 C.P. 600, 612, 614.

120/3 Railroad Co. v. Lockwood, 17 Wall. 357, 383.

120/3 Railroad Co. v. Lockwood, 17 Wall. 357, 383.

121 (return)

121 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

121/1 L.R. 1 C.P. 300.

121/1 L.R. 1 C.P. 300.

121/2 See Gorham v. Gross, 125 Mass. 232, 239, bottom.

121/2 See Gorham v. Gross, 125 Mass. 232, 239, bottom.

121/3 Minor v. Sharon, 112 Mass. 477, 487.

121/3 Minor v. Sharon, 112 Mass. 477, 487.

122 (return)

122 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

122/1 See Winsmore v. Greenbank, Willes, 577, 583; Rex v. Oneby, 2 Strange, 766, 773; Lampleigh v. Brathwait, Hobart, 105, 107; Wigram, Disc., pl. 249; Evans on Pleading, 49, 138, 139, 143 et seq.; Id., Miller's ed., pp. 147, 149.

122/1 See Winsmore v. Greenbank, Willes, 577, 583; Rex v. Oneby, 2 Strange, 766, 773; Lampleigh v. Brathwait, Hobart, 105, 107; Wigram, Disc., pl. 249; Evans on Pleading, 49, 138, 139, 143 et seq.; Id., Miller's ed., pp. 147, 149.

123 (return)

123 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

123/1 See Detroit & Milwaukee R. R. Co. v. Van Steinburg, 17 Mich. 99, 120.

123/1 See Detroit & Milwaukee R. R. Co. v. Van Steinburg, 17 Mich. 99, 120.

123/2 In the small-pox case, Minor v. Sharon, 112 Mass. 477, while the court ruled with regard to the defendant's conduct as has been mentioned, it held that whether the plaintiff was guilty of contributory negligence in not having vaccinated his children was "a question of fact, and was properly left to the jury." p. 488.

123/2 In the smallpox case, Minor v. Sharon, 112 Mass. 477, while the court ruled regarding the defendant's actions as previously mentioned, it determined that whether the plaintiff was partially at fault for not vaccinating his children was "a question of fact, and was properly left to the jury." p. 488.

124 (return)

124 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

124/1 Metropolitan Railway Co. v. Jackson, 3 App. Cas. 193, 197.

124/1 Metropolitan Railway Co. v. Jackson, 3 App. Cas. 193, 197.

125 (return)

125 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

125/1 See Kearney v. London, Brighton & S. Coast Ry. Co., L.R. 5 Q.B. 411, 414, 417; S.C., 6 id. 759.

125/1 See Kearney v. London, Brighton & S. Coast Ry. Co., L.R. 5 Q.B. 411, 414, 417; S.C., 6 id. 759.

125/2 Byrne v. Boadle, 2 H. & C. 722.

125/2 Byrne v. Boadle, 2 H. & C. 722.

125/3 See Skinnier v. Lodon, Brighton, & S. Coast Ry. Co., 5 Exch. 787. But cf. Hammack v. White, 11 C.B. N.S. 588, 594.

125/3 See Skinnier v. Lodon, Brighton, & S. Coast Ry. Co., 5 Exch. 787. But cf. Hammack v. White, 11 C.B. N.S. 588, 594.

127 (return)

127 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

127/1 7 American Law Review, 654 et seq., July, 1873.

127/1 7 American Law Review, 654 et seq., July, 1873.

128 (return)

128 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

128/1 Callahan v. Bean, 9 Allen, 401.

128/1 Callahan v. Bean, 9 Allen, 401.

128/2 Carter v. Towne, 98 Mass. 567.

128/2 Carter v. Towne, 98 Mass. 567.

128/3 Lovett v. Salem & South Danvers R. R. Co., 9 Allen, 557.

128/3 Lovett v. Salem & South Danvers R. R. Co., 9 Allen, 557.

128/4 Back v. Stacey, 2 C.&P. 465.

128/4 Back v. Stacey, 2 C.&P. 465.

128/5 Cf. Beadel v. Perry, L.R. 3 Eq. 465; City of London Brewery Co. v. Termant, L.R. 9 Ch. 212, 220; Hackett v. Baiss, L.R. 20 Eq. 494; Theed v. Debenham, 2 Ch. D. 165.

128/5 Cf. Beadel v. Perry, L.R. 3 Eq. 465; City of London Brewery Co. v. Termant, L.R. 9 Ch. 212, 220; Hackett v. Baiss, L.R. 20 Eq. 494; Theed v. Debenham, 2 Ch. D. 165.

135 (return)

135 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

135/1 Williamson v. Allison, 2 East, 446.

135/1 Williamson v. Allison, 2 East, 446.

136 (return)

136 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

136/1 Leather v. Simpson, L.R. 11 Eq. 398, 406. On the other hand, the extreme moral view is stated in Weir v. Bell, 3 Ex. D. 238, 243.

136/1 Leather v. Simpson, L.R. 11 Eq. 398, 406. Conversely, the strict moral perspective is outlined in Weir v. Bell, 3 Ex. D. 238, 243.

138 (return)

138 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

138/1 As to actual knowledge and intent, see Lecture II. p. 57.

138/1 For information on actual knowledge and intent, refer to Lecture II, page 57.

141 (return)

141 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

141/1 Cf. Knight v. German, Cro. Eliz. 70; S.C., ib. 134.

141/1 Cf. Knight v. German, Cro. Eliz. 70; S.C., ib. 134.

141/2 Mitchell v. Jenkins, 5 B.&Ad. 588, 594; Turner v. Ambler, 10 Q.B. 252, 257, 261.

141/2 Mitchell v. Jenkins, 5 B.&Ad. 588, 594; Turner v. Ambler, 10 Q.B. 252, 257, 261.

142 (return)

142 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

142/1 Redfield, C. J. in Barron v. Mason, 31 Vt. 189, 197.

142/1 Redfield, C. J. in Barron v. Mason, 31 Vt. 189, 197.

142/2 Mitchell v. Jenkins, 5 B.&Ad. 588, 595.

142/2 Mitchell v. Jenkins, 5 B.&Ad. 588, 595.

143 (return)

143 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

143/1 See Burton v. Fulton, 49 Penn. St. 151.

143/1 See Burton v. Fulton, 49 Penn. St. 151.

144 (return)

144 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

144/1 Rolfe, B. in Fouldes v. Willoughby, 8 Meeson & Welsby, 540.

144/1 Rolfe, B. in Fouldes v. Willoughby, 8 Meeson & Welsby, 540.

145 (return)

145 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

145/1 Supra, pp. 115 et seq.

145/1 Supra, pp. 115 and following.

147 (return)

147 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

147/1 See, e.g., Cooley, Torts, 164.

147/1 See, e.g., Cooley, Torts, 164.

147/2 Rex v. Dixon, 3 Maule & Selwyn, 11, 15; Reg. v. Hicklin, L.R. 3 Q.B. 360; 5 C.&P. 266, n.

147/2 Rex v. Dixon, 3 Maule & Selwyn, 11, 15; Reg. v. Hicklin, L.R. 3 Q.B. 360; 5 C.&P. 266, n.

148 (return)

148 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

148/1 Aleyn, 35; Style, 72; A.D. 1648.

148/1 Aleyn, 35; Style, 72; A.D. 1648.

149 (return)

149 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

149/1 1 Kent (12th ed.), 467, n. 1; 6 Am. Law Rev. 723-725; 7 id. 652.

149/1 1 Kent (12th ed.), 467, n. 1; 6 Am. Law Rev. 723-725; 7 id. 652.

149/2 2 Wm. Bl. 892, A.D. 1773; supra, p. 92; Addison on Torts (4th ed.), 264, citing Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 37, pl. 26, which hardly sustains the broad language of the text.

149/2 2 Wm. Bl. 892, A.D. 1773; above, p. 92; Addison on Torts (4th ed.), 264, citing Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 37, pl. 26, which barely supports the broad wording of the text.

151 (return)

151 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

151/1 Compare Crouch v. London & N. W. R. Co., 14 C.B. 255, 283; Calye's Case, 8 Co. Rep. 32; Co. Lit. 89 a, n. 7; 1 Ch. Pl. (lst ed,), 219, (6th ed.), 216, 217; 7 Am. Law Rev. 656 et seq.

151/1 Compare Crouch v. London & N. W. R. Co., 14 C.B. 255, 283; Calye's Case, 8 Co. Rep. 32; Co. Lit. 89 a, n. 7; 1 Ch. Pl. (1st ed.), 219, (6th ed.), 216, 217; 7 Am. Law Rev. 656 et seq.

151/2 But cf. The Pawashick, 2 Lowell, 142.

151/2 But cf. The Pawashick, 2 Lowell, 142.

151/3 Gibson v. Stevens, 8 How. 384, 398, 399; Barnett v. Brandao, 6 Man. & Gr. 630, 665; Hawkins v. Cardy, 1 Ld. Raym. 360.

151/3 Gibson v. Stevens, 8 How. 384, 398, 399; Barnett v. Brandao, 6 Man. & Gr. 630, 665; Hawkins v. Cardy, 1 Ld. Raym. 360.

151/4 Pickering v. Barkley, Style, 132; Wegerstoffe v. Keene, 1 Strange, 214, 216, 223; Smith v. Kendall, 6 T. R. 123, 124.

151/4 Pickering v. Barkley, Style, 132; Wegerstoffe v. Keene, 1 Strange, 214, 216, 223; Smith v. Kendall, 6 T. R. 123, 124.

155 (return)

155 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

155/1 Card v. Case, 5 C.B. 622, 634. Cf. Austin (3d ed.), 513.

155/1 Card v. Case, 5 C.B. 622, 634. Cf. Austin (3d ed.), 513.

156 (return)

156 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

156/1 Rylands v. Fletcher, L.R. 3 H.L. 330; supra, p. 116.

156/1 Rylands v. Fletcher, L.R. 3 H.L. 330; supra, p. 116.

156/2 See Marshall v. Welwood, 38 N.J. (9 Vroom), 339; 2 Thompson, Negligence, 1234, n. 3.

156/2 See Marshall v. Welwood, 38 N.J. (9 Vroom), 339; 2 Thompson, Negligence, 1234, n. 3.

157 (return)

157 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

157/1 Gorham v. Gross, 125 Mass. 232; supra, p. 117.

157/1 Gorham v. Gross, 125 Mass. 232; supra, p. 117.

158 (return)

158 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

158/1 Mitchil v. Alestree, 1 Vent. 295; S.C., 3 Keb. 650; 2 Lev. 172; supra, p. 94.

158/1 Mitchil v. Alestree, 1 Vent. 295; S.C., 3 Keb. 650; 2 Lev. 172; supra, p. 94.

158/2 Hammack v. White, 11 C.B. N.S. 588.

158/2 Hammack v. White, 11 C.B. N.S. 588.

166 (return)

166 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

166/1 Laband, Vermogensrechtlichen Klagen, Section 16, pp. 108 et seq.; Heusler, Gewere, 487, 492. These authors correct the earlier opinion of Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, Section 37, pp. 313 et seq., adopted by Sohm in his Proc. d. Lex Salica, Section 9. Cf. the discussion of sua in writs of trespass, &c. in the English law, at the end of Lecture VI. Those who wish short accounts in English may consult North Amer. Rev., CX. 210, and see Id., CXVIII. 416; Essays in Anglo-Saxon Law, pp. 212 et seq. Our knowledge as to the primitive form of action is somewhat meagre and dependent on inference. Some of the earliest texts are Ed. Liutpr. 131; Lex Baiw., XV. 4; L. Frision. Add. X.; L. Visig., V.5. I; L. Burg., XLIX. I, 2. The edict of Liutprand, dealing with housebreaking followed by theft of property left in charge of the householder, lays down that the owner shall look to the bailee alone, and the bailee shall hold the thief both for the housebreaking and for the stolen goods. Because, as it says, we cannot raise two claims out of one causa; somewhat as our law was unable to divide the severing a thing from the realty, and the conversion of it, into two different wrongs. Compare, further, Jones, Bailm. 112; Exodus xxii. 10-12; LL. Alfred, 28; I Thorpe, Anc. L., p. 51; Gaii Inst., III. Sections 202-207.

166/1 Laband, Vermogensrechtlichen Klagen, Section 16, pp. 108 et seq.; Heusler, Gewere, 487, 492. These authors correct the earlier opinion of Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, Section 37, pp. 313 et seq., which Sohm adopted in his Proc. d. Lex Salica, Section 9. See the discussion of sua in writs of trespass, etc., in English law at the end of Lecture VI. Those wanting brief summaries in English can check North Amer. Rev., CX. 210, and see Id., CXVIII. 416; Essays in Anglo-Saxon Law, pp. 212 et seq. Our understanding of the primitive form of action is somewhat limited and based on inference. Some of the earliest texts are Ed. Liutpr. 131; Lex Baiw., XV. 4; L. Frision. Add. X.; L. Visig., V.5. I; L. Burg., XLIX. I, 2. The edict of Liutprand, concerning housebreaking followed by theft of property left in the care of the homeowner, states that the owner should only hold the bailee responsible, and the bailee shall hold the thief accountable for both the housebreaking and the stolen goods. This is because, as it states, we cannot bring two claims from one cause; similar to how our law could not separate the act of severing something from the real property and the conversion of it into two different wrongs. Compare, further, Jones, Bailm. 112; Exodus xxii. 10-12; LL. Alfred, 28; I Thorpe, Anc. L., p. 51; Gaii Inst., III. Sections 202-207.

167 (return)

167 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

167/1 XXXI. 16.

167/1 XXXI. 16.

168 (return)

168 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

168/1 "Peterit enim rem suam petere [civiliter] ut adiratam per testimonium proborum hominum, et sic consequi rem suam quamvia furatam. . . Et non refert utrum res que ita subtracta fuit extiterit illius appellantis propria vel alterius, dum tamen de custodia sua." Bract., fol. 150 b, 151; Britton (Nich. ed.), I. 59, 60 [23 b], De Larcyns; cf. ib. 67 [26 b]; Fleta, fol. 5i, L. I. c. 38, Section 1.

168/1 "He may civilly seek to reclaim his property that has been taken through the testimony of credible witnesses, and thus recover what was stolen, regardless of whether the item belonged to him or someone else, as long as it was in his custody." Bract., fol. 150 b, 151; Britton (Nich. ed.), I. 59, 60 [23 b], De Larcyns; cf. ib. 67 [26 b]; Fleta, fol. 5i, L. I. c. 38, Section 1.

169 (return)

169 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

169/1 Y.B. 21 & 22 Ed. I. 466-468, noticed in North Amer. Rev., CXVIII. 421, n. (So Britton [26 b], "Si il puse averreer la perte.") This is not trover. The declaration in detinue per inventionem was called "un newfound Haliday" in Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 26, 27; cf. 7 Hen. VI. 22, pl. 3; Isack v. Clarke, I Rolle, R. 126, 128.

169/1 Y.B. 21 & 22 Ed. I. 466-468, mentioned in North Amer. Rev., CXVIII. 421, n. (So Britton [26 b], "If he could have the loss.") This is not trover. The declaration in detinue per inventionem was referred to as "a newfound Haliday" in Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 26, 27; cf. 7 Hen. VI. 22, pl. 3; Isack v. Clarke, I Rolle, R. 126, 128.

169/2 Y.B. 2 Ed. IV. 4, 5, pl. 9; 21 Hen. VII. 39, pl. 49; Bro. Trespass, pl. 216, 295.

169/2 Y.B. 2 Ed. IV. 4, 5, pl. 9; 21 Hen. VII. 39, pl. 49; Bro. Trespass, pl. 216, 295.

169/3 2 Wms. Saund. 47, n. 1. See above, p. 167.

169/3 2 Wms. Saund. 47, n. 1. See above, p. 167.

170 (return)

170 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

170/1 Notes to Saunders, Wilbraham v. Snow, note (h).

170/1 Notes to Saunders, Wilbraham v. Snow, note (h).

170/2 Y.B. 11 Hen. IV. 23, 24. See, further, Y.B. 8 Ed. IV. 6, pl. 5; 9 Ed. IV. 34, pl. 9; 3 Hen. VII. 4, pl. 16; 20 Hen. VII. 1, pl. 1; 21 Hen. VII. 14 b, pl. 23; 13 Co. Rep. 69; 1 Roll. Abr. 4(I), pl. I; F. N. B. 86, n. a; supra, p. 167.

170/2 Y.B. 11 Hen. IV. 23, 24. See also Y.B. 8 Ed. IV. 6, pl. 5; 9 Ed. IV. 34, pl. 9; 3 Hen. VII. 4, pl. 16; 20 Hen. VII. 1, pl. 1; 21 Hen. VII. 14 b, pl. 23; 13 Co. Rep. 69; 1 Roll. Abr. 4(I), pl. I; F. N. B. 86, n. a; supra, p. 167.

170/3 Fitz. Abr. Barre, pl. 130; Y.B. 9 Ed. IV. 34, pl. 9; 12 Am. Law Rev. 694.

170/3 Fitz. Abr. Barre, pl. 130; Y.B. 9 Ed. IV. 34, pl. 9; 12 Am. Law Rev. 694.

171 (return)

171 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

171/1 2 Steph. Comm. (6th ed.), 83, cited Dicey, Parties, 353; 2 Bl. Comm. 453; 2 Kent, 585. As the bailee recovered the whole value of the goods, the old reason, that he was answerable over, has in some cases become a new rule, (seemingly based on a misunderstanding,) that the bailee is a trustee for the bailor as to the excess over his own damage. Cf. Lyle v. Barker, 5 Binn. 457, 460; 7 Cowen, 68l, n.; White v. Webb, 15 Conn. 302, 305; in the order cited. (Thence the new rule has been extended to insurance recovered by a bailee. 1 Hall, N. Y. 84, 91; 3 Kent's Comm. (12th ed.), 371, 376, n. 1 (a).) In this form it ceases to be a reason for allowing the action.

171/1 2 Steph. Comm. (6th ed.), 83, cited Dicey, Parties, 353; 2 Bl. Comm. 453; 2 Kent, 585. Since the bailee received the full value of the goods, the original reasoning that he was accountable has, in some cases, turned into a new rule (seemingly based on a misunderstanding) that the bailee acts as a trustee for the bailor regarding any amount over his own loss. See Lyle v. Barker, 5 Binn. 457, 460; 7 Cowen, 681, n.; White v. Webb, 15 Conn. 302, 305, in the order cited. (From this, the new rule has also been applied to insurance claims processed by a bailee. 1 Hall, N. Y. 84, 91; 3 Kent's Comm. (12th ed.), 371, 376, n. 1 (a).) In this form, it no longer serves as a justification for allowing the action.

171/2 Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 20, pl. 8; Bro. Trespass, pl. 67. Cf. 1 Britton (Nich. ed.), 67 [26 b]; Y.B. 6 Hen. VI1. 12, pl. 9; 12 Ed. IV. 13, pl. 9; 12 Am. Law Rev. 694.

171/2 Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 20, pl. 8; Bro. Trespass, pl. 67. See also 1 Britton (Nich. ed.), 67 [26 b]; Y.B. 6 Hen. VI1. 12, pl. 9; 12 Ed. IV. 13, pl. 9; 12 Am. Law Rev. 694.

172 (return)

172 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

172/1 Y.B. 22 Ed. IV. 5, pl. 16.

172/1 Y.B. 22 Ed. IV. 5, pl. 16.

172/2 2 Rolle, Abr. 569, Trespass, 5. Cf. Y.B. 20 Hen. VII. 5, pl. 15; 21 Hen. VII. 39, pl. 49; Clayton, 135, pl. 243; 2 Wms. Saund. 47 e (3d ed.).

172/2 2 Rolle, Abr. 569, Trespass, 5. Cf. Y.B. 20 Hen. VII. 5, pl. 15; 21 Hen. VII. 39, pl. 49; Clayton, 135, pl. 243; 2 Wms. Saund. 47 e (3d ed.).

172/3 Bro. Trespass, pl, 67 in marg.; cf. Ed. Liutpr. 131, cited supra, p. 166, n.

172/3 Bro. Trespass, pl, 67 in marg.; cf. Ed. Liutpr. 131, cited above, p. 166, n.

172/4 In one instance, where, against the opinion of Brian, the bailor was allowed to sue for damage to the chattel by a stranger, the action seems to have been case. Y.B. 12 Ed. IV. 13, pl. 9; cf. the margin of the report.

172/4 In one case, where the bailor was allowed to sue for damage to the property caused by someone else, despite Brian's disagreement, it seems the action was a case. Y.B. 12 Ed. IV. 13, pl. 9; cf. the margin of the report.

173 (return)

173 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

173/1 Gordon v. Harper, 7 T. R. 9; Lord v. Price, L. IL 9 Ex. 54; Muggridge v. Eveleth, 9 Met. 233. Cf. Clayton, 135, pl. 243.

173/1 Gordon v. Harper, 7 T. R. 9; Lord v. Price, L. IL 9 Ex. 54; Muggridge v. Eveleth, 9 Met. 233. Cf. Clayton, 135, pl. 243.

173/2 Nicolls v. Bastard, 2 C. M. & R. 659, 660; Manders v. Williams, 4 Exch. 339, 343, 344; Morgan v. Ide, 8 Cush. 420; Strong v. Adams, 30 Vt. 221, 223; Little v. Fosseft, 34 Me. 545.

173/2 Nicolls v. Bastard, 2 C. M. & R. 659, 660; Manders v. Williams, 4 Exch. 339, 343, 344; Morgan v. Ide, 8 Cush. 420; Strong v. Adams, 30 Vt. 221, 223; Little v. Fosseft, 34 Me. 545.

173/3 2 Camp. 464; cf. Mears v. London & South-Western Railway Co., 11 C.B. N.S. 849, 854.

173/3 2 Camp. 464; cf. Mears v. London & South-Western Railway Co., 11 C.B. N.S. 849, 854.

173/4 Addison, Torts (4th ed.), 364.

173/4 Addison, Torts (4th ed.), 364.

174 (return)

174 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

174/1 Wms. Pers. Prop., 26 (5th ed.), 27 (7th ed.).

174/1 Wms. Pers. Prop., 26 (5th ed.), 27 (7th ed.).

174/2 Booth v. Wilson, I B. & Ald. 59; Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 20, pl. 8; 11 Hen. IV. 17, pl. 39; 11 Hen. IV. 23, 24, pl. 46 (Tre. "ou d'apprompter"); 21 Hen. VII. 14b, pl. 23; Godbolt, 173, pl. 239; Sutton v. Buck, 2 Taunt. 302, 309; Burton v. Hughes, 2 Bing. 173; Nicolls v. Bastard, 2 C. M. & R. 659, 660; Manders v. Williams, 4 Exch. 339, 343, 344; 2 Wms. Saund., note to Wilbraham v. Snow; 2 Kent, 585, 568, 574; Moran v. Portland S. P. Co., 35 Me. 55. See, further, Lecture VI. ad fin.

174/2 Booth v. Wilson, I B. & Ald. 59; Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 20, pl. 8; 11 Hen. IV. 17, pl. 39; 11 Hen. IV. 23, 24, pl. 46 (Tre. "or to arrange"); 21 Hen. VII. 14b, pl. 23; Godbolt, 173, pl. 239; Sutton v. Buck, 2 Taunt. 302, 309; Burton v. Hughes, 2 Bing. 173; Nicolls v. Bastard, 2 C. M. & R. 659, 660; Manders v. Williams, 4 Exch. 339, 343, 344; 2 Wms. Saund., note to Wilbraham v. Snow; 2 Kent, 585, 568, 574; Moran v. Portland S. P. Co., 35 Me. 55. See, further, Lecture VI. ad fin.

175 (return)

175 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

175/1 Cf. Lord v. Price, L.R. 9 Ex. 54, 56, supra, p. 172.

175/1 Cf. Lord v. Price, L.R. 9 Ex. 54, 56, supra, p. 172.

175/2 Supra, p. 167.

175/2 Supra, p. 167.

175/3 Lib. X. c. 13; cf. I., c. 8.

175/3 Lib. X. c. 13; cf. I., c. 8.

175/4 "Is qui rem commodatam accepit, ad ipsam restituendam tenetur, vel ejus precium, si forte incendio, ruins, naufragio, ant latronum, vel hostium incursu, consumpta fuerit vel deperdita, substracts, vel ablata." Fol. 99 a, b. This has been thought a corrupt text (Guterbock, Bracton, by Coxe, p. 175; 2 Twiss, Bract. Int. xxviii.), but agrees with Glanvill, supra, and with Fleta, L. II. c. 56, Section 5.

175/4 "The person who has received a loan is obligated to return the exact item or its value if it gets lost or destroyed due to fire, collapse, shipwreck, theft, or attacks by enemies." Fol. 99 a, b. This has been considered a corrupt text (Guterbock, Bracton, by Coxe, p. 175; 2 Twiss, Bract. Int. xxviii.), but aligns with Glanvill, supra, and with Fleta, L. II. c. 56, Section 5.

175/5 Bract., fol. 62 b, c. 28, Section 2; Fleta, L. II. e. 59, Section 4, fol. 128. Cf. Just. Inst. 3. 24, Section 5; ib. 15, Section 2.

175/5 Bract., fol. 62 b, c. 28, Section 2; Fleta, L. II. e. 59, Section 4, fol. 128. Cf. Just. Inst. 3. 24, Section 5; ib. 15, Section 2.

176 (return)

176 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

176/1 Y.B. 8 Ed. II. 275; Fitz. Detinue, pl. 59.

176/1 Y.B. 8 Ed. II. 275; Fitz. Detinue, pl. 59.

176/2 2 Ld. Raym. 909.

176/2 2 Ld. Raym. 909.

176/3 Y.B. 13 Ed. IV. 9, pl. 5. See Lecture VI.

176/3 Y.B. 13 Ed. IV. 9, pl. 5. See Lecture VI.

176/4 29 Ass. 163, pl. 28.

176/4 29 Ass. 163, pl. 28.

176/5 Cf. Ratcliff v. Davis, Yelv. 178; Cro. Jac. 244; Noy, 137; 1 Bulstr. 29.

176/5 Cf. Ratcliff v. Davis, Yelv. 178; Cro. Jac. 244; Noy, 137; 1 Bulstr. 29.

176/6 Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 1, pl. 3. This case is cited and largely relied on in Woodlife's Case, infra; Southcote v. Bennett, infra; Pickering v. Barkley, Style, 132 (24 Car. I., covenant on a charter-party); and Morse v. Slue, infra; in short, in all the leading cases on bailment.

176/6 Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 1, pl. 3. This case is referenced and heavily relied upon in Woodlife's Case, below; Southcote v. Bennett, below; Pickering v. Barkley, Style, 132 (24 Car. I., covenant on a charter-party); and Morse v. Slue, below; in short, in all the key cases on bailment.

177 (return)

177 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

177/1 Cf. Abbreviatio Plaeitorum, p. 343, col. 2, rot. 87, 17 Ed. II.

177/1 Cf. Abbreviatio Plaeitorum, p. 343, col. 2, rot. 87, 17 Ed. II.

178 (return)

178 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

178/1 Y.B. 9 Ed. IV. 34, pl. 9; 2 Ed. IV. 15, pl. 7. It is proper to add, that in the latter case Littleton does not seem to distinguish between servants and bailees.

178/1 Y.B. 9 Ed. IV. 34, pl. 9; 2 Ed. IV. 15, pl. 7. It’s worth noting that in the latter case, Littleton doesn’t appear to differentiate between servants and bailees.

178/2 Y.B. 9 Ed. IV, 40, pl. 22. So Brian, in 20 Ed. IV. 11, pl. 10, ad fin.

178/2 Y.B. 9 Ed. IV, 40, pl. 22. So Brian, in 20 Ed. IV. 11, pl. 10, at the end.

178/3 Y.B. 10 Hen. VII. 25, 26, pl. 3.

178/3 Y.B. 10 Hen. VII. 25, 26, pl. 3.

178/4 Cf. L. Baiw., XV. 5; Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 1, pl. 3.

178/4 Cf. L. Baiw., XV. 5; Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 1, pl. 3.

178/5 Y.B. 6 Hen. VII. 12, pl. 9; Bro. Detinue, pl. 37; 10 Hen. VI. 21, pl. 69.

178/5 Y.B. 6 Hen. VII. 12, pl. 9; Bro. Detinue, pl. 37; 10 Hen. VI. 21, pl. 69.

178/6 Y.B. 3 Hen. VII. 4, pl. 16. Cf. 10 Hen. VI. 21, pl. 69.

178/6 Y.B. 3 Hen. VII. 4, pl. 16. Cf. 10 Hen. VI. 21, pl. 69.

178/7 Y.B. 11 Hen. IV. 23, 24; 6 Hen. VII. 12, pl. 9.

178/7 Y.B. 11 Hen. IV. 23, 24; 6 Hen. VII. 12, pl. 9.

178/8 Cro. Eliz. 815; 4 Co. Rep. 83 b; Co. Lit. 89; 2 BI. Comm. 452.

178/8 Cro. Eliz. 815; 4 Co. Rep. 83 b; Co. Lit. 89; 2 BI. Comm. 452.

180 (return)

180 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

180/1 Savile, 133, 134. Cf. Bro. Accion sur le Case, pl. 103; Dyer, 161 a, b.

180/1 Savile, 133, 134. Cf. Bro. Accion sur le Case, pl. 103; Dyer, 161 a, b.

180/2 Nugent v. Smith, 1 C.P. D. 19, Brett, J., at p. 28.

180/2 Nugent v. Smith, 1 C.P. D. 19, Brett, J., at p. 28.

180/3 Nugent v. Smith, 1 C.P. D. 423, Cockburn, C. J., at p. 428.

180/3 Nugent v. Smith, 1 C.P. D. 423, Cockburn, C. J., at p. 428.

181 (return)

181 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

181/1 Moore, 462; Owen, 57.

181/1 Moore, 462; Owen, 57.

181/2 Dial. 2, ch. 38, A.D. 1530.

181/2 Dial. 2, ch. 38, A.D. 1530.

182 (return)

182 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

182/1 Keilway, 160, pl. 2 (2 Hen. VIII.); cf. ib. 77b (21 Hen. VII.).

182/1 Keilway, 160, pl. 2 (2 Hen. VIII.); cf. ib. 77b (21 Hen. VII.).

182/2 Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 1, pl. 3.

182/2 Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 1, pl. 3.

182/3 4 Co. Rep. 83 b; Cro. Eliz. 815.

182/3 4 Co. Rep. 83 b; Cro. Eliz. 815.

183 (return)

183 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

183/1 Keilway, 160, pl. 2.

183/1 Keilway, 160, page 2.

183/2 Y.B. 19 Hen. VI. 49, ad fin. Cf. Mulgrave v. Ogden, Cro. Eliz. 219; S.C., Owen, 141, 1 Leon. 224; with Isaack v. Clark, 2 Bulstr. 306, at p. 312, Coke, J.

183/2 Y.B. 19 Hen. VI. 49, at the end. See also Mulgrave v. Ogden, Cro. Eliz. 219; S.C., Owen, 141, 1 Leon. 224; with Isaack v. Clark, 2 Bulstr. 306, at p. 312, Coke, J.

183/3 See Lecture VII.

183/3 See Lecture 7.

184 (return)

184 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

184/1 Paston, J., in Y.B. 19 Hen. VI. 49. See, also, Rogers v. Head, Cro. Jac. 262; Rich v. Kneeland, Cro. Jac. 330, which will be mentioned again. An innkeeper must be a common innkeeper, Y.B. 11 Hen. IV. 45. See further, 3 Bl. Comm. 165, where "the transition from status to contract" will be found to have taken place.

184/1 Paston, J., in Y.B. 19 Hen. VI. 49. See, also, Rogers v. Head, Cro. Jac. 262; Rich v. Kneeland, Cro. Jac. 330, which will be mentioned again. An innkeeper must be a common innkeeper, Y.B. 11 Hen. IV. 45. See further, 3 Bl. Comm. 165, where "the transition from status to contract" will be found to have taken place.

184/2 F. N. B. 94 D; infra, p. 203.

184/2 F. N. B. 94 D; infra, p. 203.

184/3 Y.B. 7 Hen. IV. 14; 12 Ed. IV. 13, pl. 9, 10; Dyer, 22 b.

184/3 Y.B. 7 Hen. IV. 14; 12 Ed. IV. 13, pl. 9, 10; Dyer, 22 b.

184/4 The process may be traced by reading, in the following order, Y.B. 2 Hen. VII. 11; Keilway, 77 b, ad fin. (21 Hen. VII.); ib. 160, pl. 2 (2 Hen. VIII.); Drake v. Royman, Savile, 133, 134 (36 Eliz.); Mosley v. Fosset, Moore, 543 (40 Eliz.); 1 Roll. Abr. 4, F, pl. 5; Rich v. Kneeland, Cro. Jac. 330 (11 Jac. I.).

184/4 The process can be followed by reading in this order: Y.B. 2 Hen. VII. 11; Keilway, 77 b, ad fin. (21 Hen. VII.); ib. 160, pl. 2 (2 Hen. VIII.); Drake v. Royman, Savile, 133, 134 (36 Eliz.); Mosley v. Fosset, Moore, 543 (40 Eliz.); 1 Roll. Abr. 4, F, pl. 5; Rich v. Kneeland, Cro. Jac. 330 (11 Jac. I.).

185 (return)

185 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

185/1 Cro. Jac. 262 (8 Jac. I.). Compare Maynard's argument in Williams v. Hide, Palmer, 548; Symons v. Darknoll, ib. 523, and other cases below; 1 Roll. Abr. 4, F, pl. 3. Mosley v, Fosset, Moore, 543 (40 Eliz.); an obscurely reported case, seems to have been assumpsit against an agistor, for a horse stolen while in his charge, and asserts obiter that "without such special assumpsit the action does not lie." This must have reference to the form of the action, as the judges who decided Southcote's Case took part in the decision. See, further, Evans v. Yeoman, Clayton, 33.

185/1 Cro. Jac. 262 (8 Jac. I.). Compare Maynard's argument in Williams v. Hide, Palmer, 548; Symons v. Darknoll, ib. 523, and other cases below; 1 Roll. Abr. 4, F, pl. 3. Mosley v. Fosset, Moore, 543 (40 Eliz.); a poorly reported case, seems to have been a claim against an agistor for a horse stolen while in his care, and states obiter that "without such special assumpsit the action does not lie." This likely refers to the form of the action, as the judges who decided Southcote's Case were involved in the decision. See, further, Evans v. Yeoman, Clayton, 33.

186 (return)

186 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

186/1 See Symons v. Darknoll, and the second count in Morse v. Slue infra. (The latter case shows the averment of negligence to have been mere form.) Cf. I Salk. 18, top.

186/1 See Symons v. Darknoll, and the second count in Morse v. Slue infra. (The latter case shows that the claim of negligence was just a formality.) Cf. I Salk. 18, top.

187 (return)

187 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

187/1 Supra, p. 179.

187/1 Supra, p. 179.

187/2 Boson v. Sandford, Shower, 101; Coggs v. Bernard, infra.

187/2 Boson v. Sandford, Shower, 101; Coggs v. Bernard, below.

187/3 Symons v. Darknoll, infra.

187/3 Symons v. Darknoll, below.

188 (return)

188 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

188/1 Reg. Brev. 92b, 95a, 98a, 100b, 104a; cf. Y.B. 19 Ed. II. 624; 30 Ed. III. 25, 26; 2 Hen. IV. 18, pl. 6; 22 Hen. VI. 21, pl. 38; 32 & 33 Ed. I., Int., xxxiii.; Brunner, Schwurgerichte, 177; id. Franzosische, Inhaberpapier, 9, n. 1.

188/1 Reg. Brev. 92b, 95a, 98a, 100b, 104a; cf. Y.B. 19 Ed. II. 624; 30 Ed. III. 25, 26; 2 Hen. IV. 18, pl. 6; 22 Hen. VI. 21, pl. 38; 32 & 33 Ed. I., Int., xxxiii.; Brunner, Schwurgerichte, 177; id. Franzosische, Inhaberpapier, 9, n. 1.

188/2 12 Co. Rep. 64.

188/2 12 Co. Rep. 64.

188/3 See, besides the following cases, the declaration in Chamberlain v. Cooke, 2 Ventris, 75 (1 W. & M.), and note especially the variations of statement in Morse v. Slue, set forth below, in the text.

188/3 See, in addition to the following cases, the declaration in Chamberlain v. Cooke, 2 Ventris, 75 (1 W. & M.), and pay special attention to the differences in statements in Morse v. Slue, detailed below in the text.

189 (return)

189 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

189/1 Hobart, 17; Cro. Jac. 330. See also George v. Wiburn, 1 Roll. Abr. 6, pl. 4 (A.D. 1638).

189/1 Hobart, 17; Cro. Jac. 330. See also George v. Wiburn, 1 Roll. Abr. 6, pl. 4 (A.D. 1638).

190 (return)

190 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

190/1 The use which has been made of this case in later times shows the extreme difficulty in distinguishing between principles of substantive law and rules relating only to procedure, in the older books.

190/1 The way this case has been used in recent times highlights the significant challenge in differentiating between the principles of substantive law and rules that pertain solely to procedure in the older legal texts.

190/2 Y.B. 22 Hen. VI. 21, pl. 38; supra, p. 188, n. 1.

190/2 Y.B. 22 Hen. VI. 21, pl. 38; above, p. 188, n. 1.

191 (return)

191 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

191/1 Palmer, 523.

191/1 Palmer, 523.

191/2 Palmer, 548.

191/2 Palmer, 548.

191/3 Aleyn, 93.

191/3 Aleyn, 93.

191/4 1 Sid. 36.

191/4 1 Sid. 36.

192 (return)

192 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

192/1 1 Sid. 244. Cf. Dalston v. Janson, 1 Ld. Raym. 58.

192/1 1 Sid. 244. Cf. Dalston v. Janson, 1 Ld. Raym. 58.

192/2 2 Keb. 866; 3 id. 72, 112, 135; 2 Lev. 69; I Vent. 190, 238; 1 Mod. 85; Sir T. Raym. 220.

192/2 2 Keb. 866; 3 id. 72, 112, 135; 2 Lev. 69; I Vent. 190, 238; 1 Mod. 85; Sir T. Raym. 220.

193 (return)

193 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

193/1 2 Keb. 866. See 3 Keb. 74; 1 Mod. 85; Sir T. Raym. 220.

193/1 2 Keb. 866. See 3 Keb. 74; 1 Mod. 85; Sir T. Raym. 220.

193/2 2 Keb. 72.

193/2 2 Keb. 72.

193/3 Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 1; supra, p. 177.

193/3 Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 1; supra, p. 177.

193/4 3 Keble, 73. This is the main point mentioned by Sir T. Raymond and Levinz.

193/4 3 Keble, 73. This is the main point discussed by Sir T. Raymond and Levinz.

193/5 Cf. 1 Mod. 85.

193/5 See 1 Mod. 85.

194 (return)

194 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

194/1 1 Ventris, 238, citing Southcote's Case in the margin. Cf. 3 Keble, 135.

194/1 1 Ventris, 238, citing Southcote's Case in the margin. Cf. 3 Keble, 135.

194/2 Aleyn, 93; supra, p. 191.

194/2 Aleyn, 93; above, p. 191.

194/3 See also 1 Hale, P.C. 512, 513.

194/3 See also 1 Hale, P.C. 512, 513.

195 (return)

195 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

195/1 King v. Viscount Hertford, 2 Shower, 172, pl. 164; cf. Woodlife's Case, supra.

195/1 King v. Viscount Hertford, 2 Shower, 172, pl. 164; cf. Woodlife's Case, supra.

195/2 Boson v. Sandford, 1 Shower, 101 (2 W. & M.). See above, pp. 183,185; below, p. 197. Modern illustrations of the doctrine will be found in Fleming v. Manchester, Sheffield, & Lincolnshire Railway Co., 4 Q.B.D. 81, and cases cited. In Boorman v. Brown, 3 Q.B.511, 526, the reader the primitive assumpsit, which was the inducement to a declaration in tort, interpreted as meaning contract in the modern sense. It will be seen directly that Lord Holt took a different view. Note the mode of dealing with the Marshal's case, 33 Hen; VI. 1, in Aleyn, 27.

195/2 Boson v. Sandford, 1 Shower, 101 (2 W. & M.). See above, pp. 183, 185; below, p. 197. Modern examples of the doctrine can be found in Fleming v. Manchester, Sheffield, & Lincolnshire Railway Co., 4 Q.B.D. 81, and the cases cited. In Boorman v. Brown, 3 Q.B.511, 526, the reader sees the primitive assumpsit, which was the basis for a declaration in tort, understood as meaning contract in today's terms. It will soon be clear that Lord Holt had a different perspective. Note how the Marshal's case, 33 Hen; VI. 1, is handled in Aleyn, 27.

196 (return)

196 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

196/1 See Lovett v. Hobbs, 2 Shower, 127 (32 Car. II.); Chamberlain v. Cooke, 2 Ventris, 75 (1 W. & M.); Boson v. Sandford, 1 Shower, 101, citing Southcote's Case (2 W. & M.); Upshare v. Aidee, 1 Comyns, 25 (8 W. III.); Middleton v. Fowler, I Salk. 288 (10 W. III.).

196/1 See Lovett v. Hobbs, 2 Shower, 127 (32 Car. II.); Chamberlain v. Cooke, 2 Ventris, 75 (1 W. & M.); Boson v. Sandford, 1 Shower, 101, citing Southcote's Case (2 W. & M.); Upshare v. Aidee, 1 Comyns, 25 (8 W. III.); Middleton v. Fowler, I Salk. 288 (10 W. III.).

196/2 12 Mod. 472.

196/2 12 Mod. 472.

196/3 2 Ld. Raym. 909.

196/3 2 Ld. Raym. 909.

197 (return)

197 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

197/1 Powtuary v. Walton, 1 Roll. Abr. 10, pl. 5 (39 Eliz.). Cf. Keilway, 160.

197/1 Powtuary v. Walton, 1 Roll. Abr. 10, pl. 5 (39 Eliz.). Cf. Keilway, 160.

197/2 2 Ld. Raym. 919. See Lecture VII. How little Lord Holt meant to adopt the modern view, that delivery, being a detriment to the owner, was a consideration, may be further seen by examining the cases put and agreed to by him from the Year Books.

197/2 2 Ld. Raym. 919. See Lecture VII. How little Lord Holt intended to take on the modern perspective, that delivery, as a burden to the owner, was a consideration, can be further understood by looking at the cases he presented and agreed upon from the Year Books.

199 (return)

199 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

199/1 2 Kent, 598; 1 C.P. D. 429.

199/1 2 Kent, 598; 1 C.P. D. 429.

199/2 Palmer, 523. See too Keilway, 77 b, and 160, pl. 2, where the encroachment of case on detinue, and the corresponding confusion in principle, may be pretty clearly seen taking place. But see p. 175, supra.

199/2 Palmer, 523. Also check Keilway, 77 b, and 160, pl. 2, where the encroachment of case on detinue, and the resulting confusion in principle, can be seen quite clearly happening. But see p. 175, above.

200 (return)

200 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

200/1 2 Kent, 597; Forward v. Pittard, 1 T. R. 27.

200/1 2 Kent, 597; Forward v. Pittard, 1 T. R. 27.

200/2 Cf. Y.B. 7 Hen. IV. 14; 2 Hen. VII. 11; Keilway, 77 b, 160, pl. 2, and other cases already cited.

200/2 See Y.B. 7 Hen. IV. 14; 2 Hen. VII. 11; Keilway, 77 b, 160, pl. 2, and other cases already mentioned.

200/3 Y.B. 41 Ed. III. 3, pl. 8.

200/3 Y.B. 41 Ed. III. 3, pl. 8.

200/4 Y.B. 33 Hen. YI. 1, pl. 3.

200/4 Y.B. 33 Hen. YI. 1, pl. 3.

200/5 Reg. Brev. 107 a, 108 a, 110 a, b; entries cited 1 T. R. 29.

200/5 Reg. Brev. 107 a, 108 a, 110 a, b; entries cited 1 T. R. 29.

200/6 See above, pp. 167, 175 et seq.; 12 Am. Law Rev. 692, 693; Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 11, pl. 13; 42 Ass., pl. 17.

200/6 See above, pp. 167, 175 et seq.; 12 Am. Law Rev. 692, 693; Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 11, pl. 13; 42 Ass., pl. 17.

201 (return)

201 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

201/1 1 Wilson, 282; cf. 2 Kent (12th ed.), 596, n. 1, b.

201/1 1 Wilson, 282; cf. 2 Kent (12th ed.), 596, n. 1, b.

201/2 Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 1, pl. 3.

201/2 Y.B. 33 Hen. VI. 1, pl. 3.

202 (return)

202 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

202/1 Mouse's Case, 12 Co. Rep. 63.

202/1 Mouse's Case, 12 Co. Rep. 63.

202/2 Bird v. Astcock, 2 Bulstr. 280; cf. Dyer, 33 a, pl. 10; Keighley's Case, 10 Co. Rep. 139 b, 140.

202/2 Bird v. Astcock, 2 Bulstr. 280; cf. Dyer, 33 a, pl. 10; Keighley's Case, 10 Co. Rep. 139 b, 140.

202/3 Y.B. 40 Ed. III. 5, 6, pl. 11; see also Willams v. Hide, Palmer, 548; Shep. Touchst. 173.

202/3 Y.B. 40 Ed. III. 5, 6, pl. 11; see also Willams v. Hide, Palmer, 548; Shep. Touchst. 173.

203 (return)

203 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

203/1 See Safe Delcosit Company of Pittsburgh v. Pollock, 85 Penn. 391.

203/1 See Safe Delcosit Company of Pittsburgh v. Pollock, 85 Penn. 391.

203/2 Paston, J., in Y.B. 21 Hen. VI. 55; Keilway, 50 a, pl. 4; Hardres, 163.

203/2 Paston, J., in Y.B. 21 Hen. VI. 55; Keilway, 50 a, pl. 4; Hardres, 163.

203/3 Lane v. Cotton, 1 Ld. Raym. 646, 654; 1 Salk. 18; 12 Mod. 484.

203/3 Lane v. Cotton, 1 Ld. Raym. 646, 654; 1 Salk. 18; 12 Mod. 484.

204 (return)

204 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

204/1 Forward v. Pittard, 1 T. R. 27, 83.

204/1 Forward v. Pittard, 1 T. R. 27, 83.

205 (return)

205 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

205/1 Printing and Numerical Registering Co. v. Sampson, L.R. 19 Eq. 462, 465.

205/1 Printing and Numerical Registering Co. v. Sampson, L.R. 19 Eq. 462, 465.

207 (return)

207 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

207/1 Possession, Section 6, Eng. tr., pp. 27, 28.

207/1 Possession, Section 6, Eng. tr., pp. 27, 28.

207/2 R. d. Besitzes, 487.

207/2 R. d. Besitzes, 487.

208 (return)

208 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

208/1 R. d. Besitzes, 490, 491.

208/1 R. d. Besitzes, 490, 491.

208/2 Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, 415; Windscheid, Pand. Section 148, n. 6. Further Hegelian discourse may be found in Dr. J. Hutchison Sterling's Lectures on the Philosophy of Law.

208/2 Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, 415; Windscheid, Pand. Section 148, n. 6. More discussions on Hegel can be found in Dr. J. Hutchison Sterling's Lectures on the Philosophy of Law.

208/3 Institutionen, Sections 224, 226; Windscheid, Pand. Section 148, n. 6.

208/3 Institutions, Sections 224, 226; Windscheid, Pand. Section 148, n. 6.

208/4 Windscheid, Pand. Section 148, n. 6.

208/4 Windscheid, Pand. Section 148, n. 6.

208/5 Besitzklagen, 276, 279.

208/5 ownership claims, 276, 279.

209 (return)

209 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

209/1 Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, 499.

209/1 Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, 499.

209/2 Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, Section 2, pp. 5 et seq.; Puchta, Besitz, in Weiske, Rechtslex.; Windscheid, Pand. Section 154, pp. 461 et seq. (4th ed.).

209/2 Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, Section 2, pp. 5 et seq.; Puchta, Besitz, in Weiske, Rechtslex.; Windscheid, Pand. Section 154, pp. 461 et seq. (4th ed.).

209/3 D. 41.2.3, Section 20; 13.6.8 & 9. Cf. D. 41.1.9, Section 5.

209/3 D. 41.2.3, Section 20; 13.6.8 & 9. Cf. D. 41.1.9, Section 5.

210 (return)

210 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

210/1 But see Ihering, Geist d. Rom. R., Section 62, French tr., IV. p. 51.

210/1 But see Ihering, Spirit of Roman Law, Section 62, French translation, IV. p. 51.

210/2 Heusler thinks this merely a result of the English formalism and narrowness in their interpretation of the word suo in the writ (disseisivit de teuemento suo). Gewere, 429-432. But there was no such narrowness in dealing with catalla sua in trespass. See below, p. 242.

210/2 Heusler believes this is just a consequence of the English formalism and the limited way they interpret the word suo in the writ (disseisivit de teuemento suo). Gewere, 429-432. However, there was no such limitation when it came to catalla sua in trespass. See below, p. 242.

210/3 See, further, Bracton, fol. 413; Y.B. 6 Hen. VII. 9, pl. 4.

210/3 See, further, Bracton, fol. 413; Y.B. 6 Hen. VII. 9, pl. 4.

211 (return)

211 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

211/1 Infra, p. 243.

211/1 Infra, p. 243.

211/2 R. d. Besitzes, 494.

211/2 R. d. Besitzes, 494.

212 (return)

212 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

212/1 Rogers v. Spence, 13 M. & W. 579, 581.

212/1 Rogers v. Spence, 13 M. & W. 579, 581.

212/2 Webb v. Fox, 7 T. R. 391, 397.

212/2 Webb v. Fox, 7 T. R. 391, 397.

212/3 Fennings v. Lord Grenville, 1 Taunt. 241; Littledale v. Scaith, ib. 243, n. (a); cf. Hogarth v. Jackson, M. & M. 58; Skinner v. Chapman, ib. 59, n.

212/3 Fennings v. Lord Grenville, 1 Taunt. 241; Littledale v. Scaith, ib. 243, n. (a); cf. Hogarth v. Jackson, M. & M. 58; Skinner v. Chapman, ib. 59, n.

212/4 Swift v. Gifford, 2 Lowell, 110.

212/4 Swift v. Gifford, 2 Lowell, 110.

212/5 1 Taunt. 248.

212/5 1 Taunt. 248.

213 (return)

213 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

213/1 Cf. Wake, Evolution of Morality, Part I. ch. 4, pp. 296 et seq.

213/1 Cf. Wake, Evolution of Morality, Part I. ch. 4, pp. 296 and following.

215 (return)

215 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

215/1 Asher v. Whitlock, L.R. 1 Q.B.1.

215/1 Asher v. Whitlock, L.R. 1 Q.B.1.

215/2 People v. Shearer, 30 Cal. 645.

215/2 People v. Shearer, 30 Cal. 645.

217 (return)

217 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

217/1 2 Kent's Comm. 349, citing Pierson v. Post, 3 Caines, (N. Y.) 175; Buster v. Newkirk, 20 Johnson, (N. Y.) 75.

217/1 2 Kent's Comm. 349, referencing Pierson v. Post, 3 Caines, (N. Y.) 175; Buster v. Newkirk, 20 Johnson, (N. Y.) 75.

217/2 Young v. Hichens, 6 Q.B.606.

217/2 Young v. Hichens, 6 Q.B.606.

217/3 2 Kent's Comm. 349, n. (d).

217/3 2 Kent's Comm. 349, n. (d).

218 (return)

218 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

218/1 Inst. 2. 1, Section 13.

218/1 Inst. 2. 1, Section 13.

218/2 Swift v. Gifford, 2 Lowell, 110.

218/2 Swift v. Gifford, 2 Lowell, 110.

218/3 Savigny, R. d. Besitzes, Section 21.

218/3 Savigny, R. d. Besitzes, Section 21.

218/4 II. 9, Section 4; III. 29, Section 2. Animus domini will be used here as shortly indicating the general nature of the intent required even by those who deny the fitness of the expression, and especially because Savigny's opinion is that which has been adopted by English writers.

218/4 II. 9, Section 4; III. 29, Section 2. The term animus domini will be used here to briefly indicate the general nature of the intent needed, even by those who question the appropriateness of the term, especially since Savigny’s view is the one that English writers have accepted.

219 (return)

219 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

219/1 Cf. Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, 413, and ib. 469, 474, 493, 494, 505; Windscheid, Pand. Section 149, n. 5 (p. 447, 4th ed.); Puchta, Inst. Section 226.

219/1 Cf. Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, 413, and ib. 469, 474, 493, 494, 505; Windscheid, Pand. Section 149, n. 5 (p. 447, 4th ed.); Puchta, Inst. Section 226.

219/2 Supra, p. 207; 2 Puchta, Inst. Section 226 (5th ed.), pp. 545, 546.

219/2 Supra, p. 207; 2 Puchta, Inst. Section 226 (5th ed.), pp. 545, 546.

221 (return)

221 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

221/1 15 Jur. 1079; 21 L. J. Q.B.75; 7 Eng. L. & Eq. 424.

221/1 15 Jur. 1079; 21 L. J. Q.B.75; 7 Eng. L. & Eq. 424.

222 (return)

222 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

222/1 11 Allen, 548.

222/1 11 Allen, 548.

223 (return)

223 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

223/1 Kincaid v. Eaton, 98 Mass. 139.

223/1 Kincaid v. Eaton, 98 Mass. 139.

223/2 Barker v. Bates, 13 Pick. 255, 257, 261; Proctor v. Adams, 113 Mass. 376, 377; 1 Bl. Comm. 297, Sharsw. ed., n. 14. Cf. Blades v. Hiqgs, 13 C.B. N.S. 844, 847, 848, 850, 851; 11 H. L. C. 621; Smith v. Smith, Strange, 955.

223/2 Barker v. Bates, 13 Pick. 255, 257, 261; Proctor v. Adams, 113 Mass. 376, 377; 1 Bl. Comm. 297, Sharsw. ed., n. 14. Cf. Blades v. Higgs, 13 C.B. N.S. 844, 847, 848, 850, 851; 11 H. L. C. 621; Smith v. Smith, Strange, 955.

223/3 Reg. v. Rowe, Bell, C.C. 93.

223/3 Reg. v. Rowe, Bell, C.C. 93.

224 (return)

224 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

224/1 See, as to treasure hidden in another's land, D. 41. 2. 44, pr.; D. 10. 4. 15. Note the different opinions in D. 41.2. 3, Section 3.

224/1 See, regarding treasure buried on someone else's property, D. 41. 2. 44, pr.; D. 10. 4. 15. Take note of the varying opinions in D. 41.2. 3, Section 3.

224/2 3 Inst. 107; 1 Hale, P.C. 504, 505; 2 Bishop, Crim. Law, Sections 834, 860 (6th ed.).

224/2 3 Inst. 107; 1 Hale, P.C. 504, 505; 2 Bishop, Crim. Law, Sections 834, 860 (6th ed.).

224/3 Reg. v. Middleton, L.R. 2 C.C. 38, 55. Cf. Halliday v. Holgate, L.R. 3 Ex. 299, 302.

224/3 Reg. v. Middleton, L.R. 2 C.C. 38, 55. Cf. Halliday v. Holgate, L.R. 3 Ex. 299, 302.

224/4 Cf. Y.B. 8 Ed. II. 275; Fitzh. Abr. Detinue, ph 59; Y.B. 13 Ed. IV. 9, pl. 5; Keilway, 160, pl. 2; Merry v. Green, 7 M. & W. 623, 630. It may not be necessary to go quite so far, however, and these cases are not relied on as establishing the theory. For wrong explanations, see 2 East, P.C. 696.

224/4 Cf. Y.B. 8 Ed. II. 275; Fitzh. Abr. Detinue, p. 59; Y.B. 13 Ed. IV. 9, pl. 5; Keilway, 160, pl. 2; Merry v. Green, 7 M. & W. 623, 630. It may not be necessary to go that far, though, and these cases are not used as proof of the theory. For incorrect explanations, see 2 East, P.C. 696.

225 (return)

225 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

225/1 Durfee v. Jones, 11 R. I. 588.

225/1 Durfee v. Jones, 11 R. I. 588.

225/2 Reg. v. Rowe, Bell, C.C. 93, stated above.

225/2 Reg. v. Rowe, Bell, C.C. 93, stated above.

225/3 8 Ves. 405; 7 M. & W. 623; Stephen, Crim. Law, Art. 281, Ill. (4), p. 197. He says, "because [the owner of the safe] cannot be presumed to intend to act as the owner of it when he discovers it,"—a reason drawn from Savigny, but not fitted to the English law, as has been shown.

225/3 8 Ves. 405; 7 M. & W. 623; Stephen, Crim. Law, Art. 281, Ill. (4), p. 197. He says, "because [the owner of the safe] cannot be presumed to intend to act as the owner of it when he discovers it,"—a reason drawn from Savigny, but not suitable for English law, as has been demonstrated.

226 (return)

226 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

226/1 Y.B. 13 Ed. IV. 9, 10, pl. 5; 21 Hen. VII. 14, pl. 21. Cf. 3 Hen. VII. 12, pl. 9; Steph. Crim. Law, Art. 297, and App., note xvii.

226/1 Y.B. 13 Ed. IV. 9, 10, pl. 5; 21 Hen. VII. 14, pl. 21. Cf. 3 Hen. VII. 12, pl. 9; Steph. Crim. Law, Art. 297, and App., note xvii.

226/2 Steph. Crtre. Law, Art. 297, and App., note xvii. p. 882. It may be doubted whether the old law would have sanctioned the rule in this form. F. N. B. 91 E; Y.B. 2 Ed. IV. 15, pl. 7.

226/2 Steph. Crtre. Law, Art. 297, and App., note xvii. p. 882. It might be questioned whether the old law would have approved the rule in this way. F. N. B. 91 E; Y.B. 2 Ed. IV. 15, pl. 7.

226/3 Y.B. 21 Hen. VII. 14, pl. 21; 13 Co. Rep. 69.

226/3 Y.B. 21 Hen. VII. 14, pl. 21; 13 Co. Rep. 69.

227 (return)

227 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

227/1 They have been said to be a part of the family pro hac vice. Southcote v. Stanley, 1 H. & N. 247, 250. Cf. Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 18, pl. 6.

227/1 They are said to be part of the family for this specific case. Southcote v. Stanley, 1 H. & N. 247, 250. Cf. Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 18, pl. 6.

227/2 Moore, 248, pl. 392; S.C., Owen, 52; F. N. B. 91 E; 2 B1. Comm. 396; 1 H. Bl. 81, 84; 1 Chitty, Pl. 170 (1st ed.); Dicey, Parties, 358; 9 Mass. 104; 7 Cowen, 294; 3 S. & R. 20; 13 Iredell, 18; 6 Barb. 362, and cases cited. Some of the American cases have been denied, on the ground that the custodian was not a servant. Cf. Holiday v. Hicks, Cro. Eliz. 638, 661, 746; Drope v. Theyar, Popham, 178, 179.

227/2 Moore, 248, pl. 392; S.C., Owen, 52; F. N. B. 91 E; 2 B1. Comm. 396; 1 H. Bl. 81, 84; 1 Chitty, Pl. 170 (1st ed.); Dicey, Parties, 358; 9 Mass. 104; 7 Cowen, 294; 3 S. & R. 20; 13 Iredell, 18; 6 Barb. 362, and cases cited. Some of the American cases have been rejected, on the grounds that the custodian was not considered a servant. Cf. Holiday v. Hicks, Cro. Eliz. 638, 661, 746; Drope v. Theyar, Popham, 178, 179.

228 (return)

228 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

228/1 Bracton, fol. 6 a, Section 3, 12 a, 17 a, Cap. V. ad fin., 25 a, b, etc.; Pucbra, Inst. Section 228.

228/1 Bracton, fol. 6 a, Section 3, 12 a, 17 a, Cap. V. ad fin., 25 a, b, etc.; Pucbra, Inst. Section 228.

228/2 See also 7 Am. Law Rev. 62 et seq.; 10 Am. Law Rev. 431; 2 Kent, Comm. (12th ed.), 260, n. 1.

228/2 See also 7 Am. Law Rev. 62 et seq.; 10 Am. Law Rev. 431; 2 Kent, Comm. (12th ed.), 260, n. 1.

228/3 1 Comm. 427. Cf. Preface to Paley on Agency. Factors are always called servants in the old books, see, e. g., Woodlife's Case, Owen, 57; Holiday v. Hicks, Cro. Eliz. 638; Southcote's Case, 4 Co. Rep. 83 b, 84 a; Southern v. How, Cro. Jac. 468; St. 21 Jac. I., c. 16, Section 3; Morse v. Slue, 3 Keble, 72. As to bailiffs, see Bract. 26 b, "Reestituat domino, vel servienti," etc.; Y.B. 7 Hen. IV. 14, pl. 18.

228/3 1 Comm. 427. See Preface to Paley on Agency. In old texts, factors are often referred to as servants, as seen in cases like Woodlife's Case, Owen, 57; Holiday v. Hicks, Cro. Eliz. 638; Southcote's Case, 4 Co. Rep. 83 b, 84 a; Southern v. How, Cro. Jac. 468; St. 21 Jac. I., c. 16, Section 3; Morse v. Slue, 3 Keble, 72. Regarding bailiffs, refer to Bract. 26 b, "Reestituat domino, vel servienti," etc.; Y.B. 7 Hen. IV. 14, pl. 18.

229 (return)

229 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

229/1 Paley, Agency, c. 4, Section 1, citing Godbolt, 360. See, further, F. N. B. 120, G; Fitzh. Abr. Dette, pl. 3; Y.B. 8 Ed. IV. 11, pl. 9. These rules seem to be somewhat modern even as to servants. The liability of a master for debts contracted by his servant is very narrowly limited in the earlier Year Books.

229/1 Paley, Agency, c. 4, Section 1, citing Godbolt, 360. See, further, F. N. B. 120, G; Fitzh. Abr. Dette, pl. 3; Y.B. 8 Ed. IV. 11, pl. 9. These rules seem to be fairly modern even regarding servants. A master’s liability for debts incurred by his servant is very strictly limited in the earlier Year Books.

230 (return)

230 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

230/1 I am inclined to think that this extension has been largely due to the influence of the Roman law. See Lecture I. p. 20, n. 1, and observe the part which the precedents as to fire (e. g., Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 18, pl. 6) have played in shaping the modern doctrine of master and servant. Tuberville v. Stampe, I Ld. Raym. 264 (where Lord Holt's examples are from the Roman law); Brucker v. Fromont, 6 T. R. 659; M'Manus v. Crickett, 1 East, 106; Patten v. Rea, 2 C.B. N.S. 606. In Southern v. How, Popham, 143, Doctor and Student is referred to for the general principles of liability. Doctor and Student states Roman law. See, further, Boson v. Sandford, 1 Shower, 101, 102.

230/1 I think that this expansion has mostly been influenced by Roman law. See Lecture I, p. 20, n. 1, and notice the role that precedents related to fire (e.g., Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 18, pl. 6) have had in developing the modern understanding of master and servant. Tuberville v. Stampe, I Ld. Raym. 264 (where Lord Holt's examples are taken from Roman law); Brucker v. Fromont, 6 T. R. 659; M'Manus v. Crickett, 1 East, 106; Patten v. Rea, 2 C.B. N.S. 606. In Southern v. How, Popham, 143, Doctor and Student is cited for the general principles of liability. Doctor and Student outlines Roman law. See also, Boson v. Sandford, 1 Shower, 101, 102.

230/2 Bac. Ahr. Master and Servant, K; Smith, Master and Servant (3d ed.), 260, n. (t).

230/2 Bac. Ahr. Master and Servant, K; Smith, Master and Servant (3d ed.), 260, n. (t).

230/3 Clapp v. Kemp, 122 Mass. 481; Murray v. Currie, L.R. 6 C.P. 24, 28; Hill v. Morey, 26 Vt. 178.

230/3 Clapp v. Kemp, 122 Mass. 481; Murray v. Currie, L.R. 6 C.P. 24, 28; Hill v. Morey, 26 Vt. 178.

230/4 See, e.g., Patten v. Rea, 2 C.B. N.S. 606; Bolingbroke v. Swindon Local Board, L.R. 9 C.P. 575.

230/4 See, e.g., Patten v. Rea, 2 C.B. N.S. 606; Bolingbroke v. Swindon Local Board, L.R. 9 C.P. 575.

230/5 Freeman v. Rosher, 13 Q.B.780, 785; Gauntlett v. King, 3 C. B. N.S. 59; Haseler v. Lemoyne, 28 L. J. C.P. 103; Collett v. Foster, 2 H. & N. 356; Barwick v. English Joint Stock Bank, L.R. 2 Ex. 259, 265, 266; Lucas v. Mason, L.R. 10 Ex. 251, 253, last paragraph; Mackay v. Commercial Bank of New Brunswick, L.R. 5 P.C. 394, 411, 412. So as to partners, 3 Kent's Comm. (12th ed.), 46, notes (d) & 1.

230/5 Freeman v. Rosher, 13 Q.B.780, 785; Gauntlett v. King, 3 C. B. N.S. 59; Haseler v. Lemoyne, 28 L. J. C.P. 103; Collett v. Foster, 2 H. & N. 356; Barwick v. English Joint Stock Bank, L.R. 2 Ex. 259, 265, 266; Lucas v. Mason, L.R. 10 Ex. 251, 253, last paragraph; Mackay v. Commercial Bank of New Brunswick, L.R. 5 P.C. 394, 411, 412. So as to partners, 3 Kent's Comm. (12th ed.), 46, notes (d) & 1.

231 (return)

231 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

231/1 Bush v. Steinman, 1 B. & P. 404, 409.

231/1 Bush v. Steinman, 1 B. & P. 404, 409.

231/2 6 M. & W. 358. Cf. Udell v. Atherton, 7 H. & N. 172, 184, for a comment like that in the text. Other grounds for the decision are immaterial here.

231/2 6 M. & W. 358. See Udell v. Atherton, 7 H. & N. 172, 184, for a comment similar to the one in the text. Other reasons for the decision aren't relevant here.

231/3 Mackay v. Commercial Bank of New Brunswick, L.R. 5 P.C. 394; Barwick v. English Joint Stock Bank, L.R. 2 Ex. 259; Western Bank of Scotland v. Addie, L.R. 1 H. L. Sc. 145; 2 Kent (12th ed.), 616, n. 1; Swift v. Jewsbury, L.R. 9 Q.B.301, overruling S.C. sub nom. Swift v. Winterbotham, L.R. 8 Q.B.244; Weir v. Bell, 3 Ex. D. 238, 244. The objections which Baron Bramwell mentions (L.R. 9 Q.B.815) to holding one man liable for the frauds of another, are objections to the peculiar consequences attaching to the relation of master and servant in general, and have been urged in that more general form by the same learned judge. 12 Am. Law Rev. 197, 200; 2 H. & N. 856, 361. See 7 Am. Law Rev. 61, 62.

231/3 Mackay v. Commercial Bank of New Brunswick, L.R. 5 P.C. 394; Barwick v. English Joint Stock Bank, L.R. 2 Ex. 259; Western Bank of Scotland v. Addie, L.R. 1 H. L. Sc. 145; 2 Kent (12th ed.), 616, n. 1; Swift v. Jewsbury, L.R. 9 Q.B.301, overruling S.C. sub nom. Swift v. Winterbotham, L.R. 8 Q.B.244; Weir v. Bell, 3 Ex. D. 238, 244. The concerns that Baron Bramwell mentions (L.R. 9 Q.B.815) about making one person responsible for another's fraud are concerns about the unique consequences related to the master-servant relationship in general, and have been brought up in a more broad context by the same learned judge. 12 Am. Law Rev. 197, 200; 2 H. & N. 856, 361. See 7 Am. Law Rev. 61, 62.

231/3 7 Am. Law Rev. 63 (Oct. 1872).

231/3 7 Am. Law Rev. 63 (Oct. 1872).

232 (return)

232 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

232/1 D. 44. 2. 4, note 17, Elzevir ed.

232/1 D. 44. 2. 4, note 17, Elzevir ed.

232/2 Hunter's Roman Law, 431.

232/2 Hunter's Roman Law, 431.

232/3 Ancient Hist. of Inst. 235.

232/3 Ancient Hist. of Inst. 235.

232/4 Cf. Gillett v. Ball, 9 Penn. St. 13; Craig v. Gilbreth, 47 Me. 416; Nickolson v. Knowles, 5 Maddock, 47; Williams v. Port, L.R. 12 Eq. 149; Adams v. Jones, 12 Ad. & El. 455; Bracton, fol. 28 b, 42 b, 43. And compare with the passage cited above from Blackstone: "Possider, cujus riomine possidetur, procurator alienae possessioni praestat ministerium." D. 41. 2. 18, pr.

232/4 Cf. Gillett v. Ball, 9 Penn. St. 13; Craig v. Gilbreth, 47 Me. 416; Nickolson v. Knowles, 5 Maddock, 47; Williams v. Port, L.R. 12 Eq. 149; Adams v. Jones, 12 Ad. & El. 455; Bracton, fol. 28 b, 42 b, 43. And compare with the passage cited above from Blackstone: "The possessor, by whose name possession is held, serves the purpose of another's possession." D. 41. 2. 18, pr.

233 (return)

233 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

233/1 Ward v. Macaulay, 4 T. R. 489, 490. Cf. as to factors supra, p. 228.

233/1 Ward v. Macaulay, 4 T. R. 489, 490. Cf. as to factors supra, p. 228.

233/2 Berndtson v. Strang, L.R. 3 Ch. 588, 590.

233/2 Berndtson v. Strang, L.R. 3 Ch. 588, 590.

233/3 Blackburn, Sale, 33; Marvin v. Wallis, 6 El. & Bl. 726.

233/3 Blackburn, Sale, 33; Marvin v. Wallis, 6 El. & Bl. 726.

233/4 D. 41. 2. 18, pr. "Quod meo nomine possideo, possum alieno nomine possidere: nec enim muto mihi causam possessionis, sed desino possidere et alium possessorem ministerio meo facio. Nec idem est possidere et alieno nomine possidere: nam possidet, cujus nomine possidetur, procurator alienae possessioni praestat ministerium." Thus showing that the vendor changed possession by holding in the name of the purchaser, as his agent to possess. Cf. Bracton, fol. 28 b.

233/4 D. 41. 2. 18, pr. "If I possess something in my own name, I can also possess it in someone else's name: for I do not change the basis of my possession, but I stop possessing and make another the possessor through my service. To possess in someone else's name is not the same as simply possessing: for it is the person whose name it is possessed in who holds the position, with my service acting on behalf of another's possession." This demonstrates that the seller transferred possession by holding it in the name of the buyer, functioning as their agent to possess. Cf. Bracton, fol. 28 b.

233/4 Windscheid, Pand. Section 155, n. 8 a; 2 Kent (12th ed.), 492, n. 1 (a). It should be kept in mind also that the Roman law denied possession to bailees.

233/4 Windscheid, Pand. Section 155, n. 8 a; 2 Kent (12th ed.), 492, n. 1 (a). It should also be noted that Roman law did not recognize possession for bailees.

234 (return)

234 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

234/1 See, e. g., Farina v. Home, 16 M. & W. 119, 123.

234/1 See, e.g., Farina v. Home, 16 M. & W. 119, 123.

235 (return)

235 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

235/1 McGahey v. Moore, 3 Ired. (N. C.) 35.

235/1 McGahey v. Moore, 3 Ired. (N. C.) 35.

235/2 Reader v. Moody, 3 Jones, (N. C.) 372. Cf. Basset v. Maynard, Cro. Eliz. 819, 820.

235/2 Reader v. Moody, 3 Jones, (N. C.) 372. Cf. Basset v. Maynard, Cro. Eliz. 819, 820.

235/3 Browne v. Dawson, 12 A. & E. 624. Cf. D. 43. 16. 17; ib. 3, Section 9; D. 41. 2. 18, Section 3; Clayton, 147, pl. 268.

235/3 Browne v. Dawson, 12 A. & E. 624. Cf. D. 43. 16. 17; ib. 3, Section 9; D. 41. 2. 18, Section 3; Clayton, 147, pl. 268.

236 (return)

236 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

236/1 Cf. Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, 503.

236/1 Cf. Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, 503.

237 (return)

237 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

237/1 Clark v. Maloney, 3 Harrington (Del.), 68. Bruns (R. d. Besitzes, 503, 507) comes to the same conclusion on practical grounds of convenience, although he utterly repudiates it on theory. I must refer to what I said above touching these conflicts between theory and convenience.

237/1 Clark v. Maloney, 3 Harrington (Del.), 68. Bruns (R. d. Besitzes, 503, 507) reaches the same conclusion for practical reasons of convenience, even though he completely rejects it on theoretical grounds. I need to refer back to what I mentioned earlier about these conflicts between theory and convenience.

238 (return)

238 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

238/1 Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, Section 57, p. 486. A learned writer of more ancient date asks why a doctor has not a possessory action if you cease to employ him, and answers: "Sentio actionem non tenere, sed sentio tantum, nec si vel morte mineris, possum dicere quare. Tu lector, si sapis, rationes decidendi suggere." Hommel, Rhaps., qu. 489, cited, Bruns, 407.

238/1 Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, Section 57, p. 486. A knowledgeable writer from an earlier time questions why a doctor doesn’t have a claim to possessions if you stop using his services, and replies: "I feel that I have no claim, but I only feel, and even if the reason is as serious as death, I can't say why. You, reader, if you have wisdom, suggest the reasons for the decision." Hommel, Rhaps., qu. 489, cited, Bruns, 407.

239 (return)

239 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

239/1 Gardiner v. Thibodeau, 14 La. An. 732.

239/1 Gardiner v. Thibodeau, 14 La. An. 732.

239/2 Bruns, 483.

239/2 Bruns, 483.

240 (return)

240 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

240/1 2 Kent (12th ed.), 205, n. 1. Cf. Y.B. 21 Hen. VI. 8, 9, pl. 19; American note to Scott v. Shepherd, in 1 Sm. L. C. (Am. ed.).

240/1 2 Kent (12th ed.), 205, n. 1. Cf. Y.B. 21 Hen. VI. 8, 9, pl. 19; American note to Scott v. Shepherd, in 1 Sm. L. C. (Am. ed.).

240/2 Britton (Nich. ed.), I. 277 (cf. Bract., fol. 164 b; Fleta, fol. 214; Glanv., Lib. XIII. c. 37); Littleton, Sections 237-240, 588, 589; 3 Bl. Comm. 170; 3 Cruise, Dig., tit. xxviii., Rents, ch. 2, Section 34.

240/2 Britton (Nich. ed.), I. 277 (cf. Bract., fol. 164 b; Fleta, fol. 214; Glanv., Lib. XIII. c. 37); Littleton, Sections 237-240, 588, 589; 3 Bl. Comm. 170; 3 Cruise, Dig., tit. xxviii., Rents, ch. 2, Section 34.

241 (return)

241 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

241/1 See Lecture XI.

241/1 See Lecture 11.

241/2 Cf. Stockport Water Works v. Potter, 3 H. & C. 300, 318. The language in the seventh English edition of 1 Sm. L. C., 300, is rather too broad. If the law should protect a possessor of land in the enjoyment of water coming to it, it would do so because the use of the water was regarded as a part of the enjoyment of that land, and would by no means imply that it would do the same in the case just put of a way over land of another.

241/2 Cf. Stockport Water Works v. Potter, 3 H. & C. 300, 318. The language in the seventh English edition of 1 Sm. L. C., 300, is a bit too broad. If the law were to protect someone who owns land in their enjoyment of water that flows to it, it would be because using that water is seen as part of enjoying that land, and it certainly wouldn’t imply that the same protection would apply in the case of using a pathway over someone else's land.

242 (return)

242 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

242/1 Jefferies v. Great Western Railway Co., 5 El. & B1. 802. Cf. Armory v. Delamirie, 1 Strange, 505, 1 Sm. L. C.

242/1 Jefferies v. Great Western Railway Co., 5 El. & B1. 802. Cf. Armory v. Delamirie, 1 Strange, 505, 1 Sm. L. C.

242/2 Co. Lit. 145 b.

242/2 Co. Lit. 145 b.

242/3 2 Wms. Saund. 47 b, note 1, to Wilbraham v. Snow.

242/3 2 Wms. Saund. 47 b, note 1, to Wilbraham v. Snow.

242/4 Bract., fol. 150 b, 151; supra, p. 168; Y.B. 22 Ed. I. 466-468.

242/4 Bract., fol. 150 b, 151; above, p. 168; Y.B. 22 Ed. I. 466-468.

242/5 Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 20; 11 Hen. IV. 17; 11 Hen. IV. 23, 24; 21 Hen. VII. 14. The meaning of sua is discussed in Y.B. 10 Ed. IV. 1, B, by Catesby. Compare Laband, Vermogensrechtlichen Klagen, 111; Heusler, Gewere, 492 et seq., correcting Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, 300 et seq.; Sohm, Proc. d. L. Sal., Section 6.

242/5 Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 20; 11 Hen. IV. 17; 11 Hen. IV. 23, 24; 21 Hen. VII. 14. The meaning of sua is discussed in Y.B. 10 Ed. IV. 1, B, by Catesby. Compare Laband, Vermogensrechtlichen Klagen, 111; Heusler, Gewere, 492 et seq., correcting Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, 300 et seq.; Sohm, Proc. d. L. Sal., Section 6.

243 (return)

243 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

243/1 Y.B. 11 Hen. IV. 17, pl. 39.

243/1 Y.B. 11 Hen. IV. 17, pl. 39.

243/2 Y.B. 21 Hen. VII. 14 b, pl. 23.

243/2 Y.B. 21 Hen. VII. 14 b, pl. 23.

243/3 Godbolt, 173, pl. 239. Cf. 11 Hen. IV. 17, pl. 39.

243/3 Godbolt, 173, pl. 239. Cf. 11 Hen. IV. 17, pl. 39.

243/4 Bro. Abr. Trespass, pl. 433, cit. Y.B. 13 Hen. VII. 10.

243/4 Bro. Abr. Trespass, pl. 433, cit. Y.B. 13 Hen. VII. 10.

243/5 Kelyng, 89. See, further, Buller, N. P. 33.

243/5 Kelyng, 89. See also Buller, N. P. 33.

243/6 Lecture V.; Y.B. 20 Hen. VII. 1, pl. 11.

243/6 Lecture V.; Y.B. 20 Hen. VII. 1, pl. 11.

243/7 Y.B. 21 lien. VII. 14 b, pl. 23.

243/7 Y.B. 21 lien. VII. 14 b, pl. 23.

243/8 1 Roll. Abr. 4, 5 (I), pl. 1. Cf. Arnold v. Jefferson, 1 Ld. Raym. 275.

243/8 1 Roll. Abr. 4, 5 (I), pl. 1. Cf. Arnold v. Jefferson, 1 Ld. Raym. 275.

244 (return)

244 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

244/1 29 Ass., fol. 163, pl. 28.

244/1 29 Ass., fol. 163, pl. 28.

244/2 Southcote's Case, 4 Co. Rep. 83 b.

244/2 Southcote's Case, 4 Co. Rep. 83 b.

244/3 Mores v. Conham, Owen, 123. Cf. Ratcliff v. Davis, I Bulstr. 29.

244/3 Mores v. Conham, Owen, 123. Cf. Ratcliff v. Davis, I Bulstr. 29.

244/4 Doe v. Dyball, Mood. & M. 346 and note; 2 Wms. Saund. 111, and later notes; I Ad. & El. 119; Asher v. Whitlock, L.R. 1 Q.B.1.

244/4 Doe v. Dyball, Mood. & M. 346 and note; 2 Wms. Saund. 111, and later notes; I Ad. & El. 119; Asher v. Whitlock, L.R. 1 Q.B.1.

244/5 Graham v. Peat, 1 East, 244.

244/5 Graham v. Peat, 1 East, 244.

245 (return)

245 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

245/1 As to this period see Heusler, Gewere. Cf. Laveleye, Propriete, 166.

245/1 For this period, see Heusler, Gewere. Compare with Laveleye, Propriete, 166.

248 (return)

248 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

248/1 2 Hist. du Droit Franc., pp. 146 et seq, 152.

248/1 2 Hist. du Droit Franc., pp. 146 and following, 152.

248/2 Anciens Poetes de la France, (Guessard,) p. 71.

248/2 Anciens Poetes de la France, (Guessard,) p. 71.

248/3 Page 283; cf. 284, cxviii, et seq., 44, lxix.

248/3 Page 283; cf. 284, cxviii, et seq., 44, lxix.

249 (return)

249 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

249/1 Sohm, Proc. d. Lex. Sal., Sections 15, 23-25, tr. Thevenin, pp. 80, 105, 122.

249/1 Sohm, Proc. d. Lex. Sal., Sections 15, 23-25, tr. Thevenin, pp. 80, 105, 122.

249/2 Essays in A. S. Law, p. 292.

249/2 Essays in A. S. Law, p. 292.

249/3 Cap. VIII., Merkel, p. 48.

249/3 Cap. VIII., Merkel, p. 48.

249/4 Cap. LXXXIX. Section 3, Essays in A. S. Law, p. 291.

249/4 Cap. LXXXIX. Section 3, Essays in A. S. Law, p. 291.

249/5 Chap. IV. Section 16.

249/5 Chap. IV. Sec. 16.

250 (return)

250 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

250/1 Fitzh. Abr. Mainprise, pl. 12 (H. 33 Ed. III.); Staundforde, P.C. 65.

250/1 Fitzh. Abr. Mainprise, pl. 12 (H. 33 Ed. III.); Staundforde, P.C. 65.

250/2 Abbr. Plac., p. 343, col 2, rot. 37, 17 Ed. II.

250/2 Abbr. Plac., p. 343, col 2, rot. 37, 17 Ed. II.

250/3 Jacob, L. D., "Bail." Cf. I Bulstr. 45; .Hawkins, P.C., II. ch. 15, Section 83; Abbr. Plac., p. 343, col. 2, rot. 37, 17 Ed. II.

250/3 Jacob, L. D., "Bail." See I Bulstr. 45; Hawkins, P.C., II. ch. 15, Section 83; Abbr. Plac., p. 343, col. 2, rot. 37, 17 Ed. II.

250/4 Highmore, Bail, p. 199; Jacob, L. D., "Bail." Cf. 2 Laferriere, Hist. du Droit Franc., p. 148.

250/4 Highmore, Bail, p. 199; Jacob, L. D., "Bail." Cf. 2 Laferriere, Hist. du Droit Franc., p. 148.

250/5 Highmore, p. 195.

250/5 Highmore, p. 195.

250/6 Ibid., p. 200.

250/6 Ibid., p. 200.

252 (return)

252 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

252/1 Vermoegensrechtlichen Klagen.

252/1 Asset-related lawsuits.

253 (return)

253 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

253/1 II. c. 60, Section 25. Glanvill's "justa debendi causa" (Lib. X. c. 4) seems remote from consideration.

253/1 II. c. 60, Section 25. Glanvill's "justa debendi causa" (Lib. X. c. 4) seems unrelated to the discussion.

254 (return)

254 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

254/1 Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36.

254/1 Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36.

254/2 Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 13, pl. 3.

254/2 Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 13, pl. 3.

254/3 Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 8, pl. 33.

254/3 Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 8, pl. 33.

254/4 Glanv., Lib. X. c. 12; Bract, fol. 400b, Section 10; 22 Ass., pl. 70, fol. 101.

254/4 Glanv., Lib. X. c. 12; Bract, fol. 400b, Section 10; 22 Ass., pl. 70, fol. 101.

255 (return)

255 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

255/1 Essays in A. S. Law, 187.

255/1 Essays in A. S. Law, 187.

256 (return)

256 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

256/1 I. 45; III. 10.

256/1 I. 45; III. 10.

256/2 Lib. X. e. 17. Suit, secta, was the term applied to the persons whose oath the party tendered.

256/2 Lib. X. e. 17. Suit, secta, was the term used for the people whose oath the party presented.

257 (return)

257 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

257/1 Lib. X. c. 12 (Beames, p. 262); c. 8 & c. 5 (Beames, pp. 256, 251); cf. IV. c. 6, where witnesses are tendered de visu et auditu. Cf. Bract., 315 b, Section 6 Fleta, II. c. 63, Section10, p. 137. It was no doubt true, as Glanvill says, Lib. X. c. 17, that the usual mode of proof was by a writing or by duel, and that the King's Court did not generally give protection to private agreements made anywhere except in the Court of the King (Lib. X. c. 8). But it can hardly be that debts were never established by witness in his time, in view of the continuous evidence from Bracton onwards.

257/1 Lib. X. c. 12 (Beames, p. 262); c. 8 & c. 5 (Beames, pp. 256, 251); see IV. c. 6, where witnesses are presented de visu et auditu. See Bract., 315 b, Section 6 Fleta, II. c. 63, Section10, p. 137. It was certainly true, as Glanvill states, Lib. X. c. 17, that the usual way to prove things was through a written document or by duel, and that the King's Court generally did not protect private agreements made outside the King's Court (Lib. X. c. 8). But it’s hard to believe that debts were never confirmed by witness during his time, considering the consistent evidence from Bracton onward.

257/2 But cf. Brunner, Schwurgerichte, 399. I do not go so far as to say that they were still a living institution. However that may be, tradition must at least have modelled itself on what had been the function of the former official body.

257/2 But see Brunner, Schwurgerichte, 399. I won't claim that they were still an active institution. However, tradition must have at least been shaped by the role that the former official body played.

257/3 Bract., fol. 315 b, Section 6; Britt. (Nich.) I. p. 162; Magna Charta, c. 38; Y.B. 21 Ed. I. 456; 7 Ed. II. 242; 18 Ed. II. 582; 3 Bl. Comm. 295, 344. Cf. 17 Ed. III. 48 b.

257/3 Bract., fol. 315 b, Section 6; Britt. (Nich.) I. p. 162; Magna Charta, c. 38; Y.B. 21 Ed. I. 456; 7 Ed. II. 242; 18 Ed. II. 582; 3 Bl. Comm. 295, 344. Cf. 17 Ed. III. 48 b.

257/4 Cf. Glanv., Lib. IV. c. 6.

257/4 Cf. Glanv., Lib. IV. c. 6.

258 (return)

258 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

258/1 Lib. X. c. 18. It is possible that this means no more than Glanvill's often repeated statement, that the King's Court did not, generally speaking, take cognizance of private agreements. The substantive law was, perhaps, still limited by traditions from the infancy of contract. See pp. 248, 251, 259, 260. The proposition in its broadest form may have been based on the inability to try such agreements in any way but those which have been specified. Cf. the requirement of aliam diracionationem and aliis probationibus, in Lib. X. c. 12. But cf. Ibid. with Essays in A. S. Law, pp. 189, 190.

258/1 Lib. X. c. 18. This likely just reflects Glanvill's frequently repeated point that the King's Court generally didn’t handle private agreements. The foundational laws were probably still influenced by the early traditions of contract. See pp. 248, 251, 259, 260. The broad idea might have stemmed from the fact that such agreements could only be addressed in the specific ways that had been defined. Cf. the requirement of aliam diracionationem and aliis probationibus, in Lib. X. c. 12. But cf. Ibid. with Essays in A. S. Law, pp. 189, 190.

259 (return)

259 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

259/1 Sharington v. Strotton, Plowden, 298, at p. 302, M. 7 & 8 Eliz.

259/1 Sharington v. Strotton, Plowden, 298, at p. 302, M. 7 & 8 Eliz.

259/2 Pillans v. Van Mierop, 3 Burrow, 1663, 1669.

259/2 Pillans v. Van Mierop, 3 Burrow, 1663, 1669.

260 (return)

260 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

260/1 1 Thorpe, Anc. Laws, 181, Oaths, 7, 8.

260/1 1 Thorpe, Anc. Laws, 181, Oaths, 7, 8.

260/2 Glanv., Lib. X. c. 5 (Beames, p. 251); Y.B. 7 Ed. II. 242; Novae Narr. Dette-Vers plege, Rastell's Law Tracts, p. 253, D, 2 Finl. Reeves, 376.

260/2 Glanv., Lib. X. c. 5 (Beames, p. 251); Y.B. 7 Ed. II. 242; Novae Narr. Dette-Vers plege, Rastell's Law Tracts, p. 253, D, 2 Finl. Reeves, 376.

261 (return)

261 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

261/1 Glanv., Lib. X. c. 22 (Beames, p. 263); Bract., fol. 398 b, Section 1. The favorite proof by duel was also allowed, but this disappeared. When the inquest became general, the execution of the deed was tried, like any other fact, by that means.

261/1 Glanv., Lib. X. c. 22 (Beames, p. 263); Bract., fol. 398 b, Section 1. The popular practice of trial by combat was also permitted, but this gradually faded away. As the inquiry became more common, the execution of the deed was assessed like any other fact through that method.

261/2 Bract., fol. 315 b, Section 6, 400 b; Coke, 2d Inst., 44, 45.

261/2 Bract., fol. 315 b, Section 6, 400 b; Coke, 2d Inst., 44, 45.

262 (return)

262 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

262/1 Glanv., Lib. X. c. 12 (Beames, p. 263); Bract., fol. 100 b, Section 9.

262/1 Glanv., Lib. X. c. 12 (Beames, p. 263); Bract., fol. 100 b, Section 9.

262/2 Glanv., Lib. X. c. 17 (Beames, p. 272).

262/2 Glanv., Lib. X. c. 17 (Beames, p. 272).

262/3 Bract., fol. 400 b, Section 9.

262/3 Bract., fol. 400 b, Section 9.

262/4 Cf. Y.B. 20 Ed. I. 304, and 34 Ed. II., 150, 152; ib. 330, 332; 35 Ed. I. 546.

262/4 Cf. Y.B. 20 Ed. I. 304, and 34 Ed. II., 150, 152; ib. 330, 332; 35 Ed. I. 546.

263 (return)

263 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

263/1 Bract., fol. 400 b, Section 8.

263/1 Bract., fol. 400 b, Section 8.

263/2 Cf. Y.B. 20 Ed. I. 304.

263/2 Cf. Y.B. 20 Ed. I. 304.

263/3 Cap. 28; 32 & 33 Ed. I. 516; 18 Ed. II. 582; Fleta, II. c, 63, Section 9; Coke, 2d Inst., 44; 3 Bl. Comm. 344.

263/3 Cap. 28; 32 & 33 Ed. I. 516; 18 Ed. II. 582; Fleta, II. c, 63, Section 9; Coke, 2d Inst., 44; 3 Bl. Comm. 344.

263/4 Y.B. 18 Ed. II. 582; 17 Ed. III. 48 b, pl. 14.

263/4 Y.B. 18 Ed. II. 582; 17 Ed. III. 48 b, pl. 14.

264 (return)

264 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

264/1 Y.B. 29 Ed. III. 25, 26; cf. 48 Ed. III. 6, pl. 11; Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 25; Glanvill, Lib. X. c. 12.

264/1 Y.B. 29 Ed. III. 25, 26; cf. 48 Ed. III. 6, pl. 11; Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 25; Glanvill, Lib. X. c. 12.

264/2 Cf. Bro..Acc. sur le Case, pl. 5; S.C., 27 Hen. VIII. 24, 25, pl. 3.

264/2 Cf. Bro..Acc. on the Case, pl. 5; S.C., 27 Hen. VIII. 24, 25, pl. 3.

264/3 Y.B. 18 Ed. III. 13, pl. 7.

264/3 Y.B. 18 Ed. III. 13, pl. 7.

264/4 Y.B. 44 Ed. III. 21, pl. 23.

264/4 Y.B. 44 Ed. III. 21, pl. 23.

264/5 F. N. B. 122, I, in margin. Cf. F. N. B. 122 K; Y.B. 43 Ed. III. 11, pl. 1; S.C., Bro. Pledges, pl. 3; 9 Hen. V. 14, pl. 23.

264/5 F. N. B. 122, I, in margin. Cf. F. N. B. 122 K; Y.B. 43 Ed. III. 11, pl. 1; S.C., Bro. Pledges, pl. 3; 9 Hen. V. 14, pl. 23.

265 (return)

265 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

265/1 Y.B. 17 Ed. III. 48 b, pl. 14. Cf. Fortescue (Amos), 67, n.; 3 Bl. Comm. 295.

265/1 Y.B. 17 Ed. III. 48 b, pl. 14. Cf. Fortescue (Amos), 67, n.; 3 Bl. Comm. 295.

265/2 For limit, see Constit. of Clarendon, c. 15; Glanv., Lib. X. c. 8, 12; Y.B. 22 Ass., pl. 70, fol. 101; 45 Ed. III. 24, pl. 30; 19 R. II., Fitzh. Abr. Dett, pl. 166; 37 Hen. VI. 8, pl. 18; 14 Ed. IV. 6, pl. 3; 15 Ed. IV. 32, pl. 14; 19 Ed. IV. 10, pl. 18; 20 Ed. IV. 3, pl. 17.

265/2 For the limit, see the Constitution of Clarendon, chapter 15; Glanville, Book X, chapter 8, 12; Year Book 22 Assize, plea 70, folio 101; 45 Edward III, 24, plea 30; 19 Richard II, Fitzherbert Abstract, plea 166; 37 Henry VI, 8, plea 18; 14 Edward IV, 6, plea 3; 15 Edward IV, 32, plea 14; 19 Edward IV, 10, plea 18; 20 Edward IV, 3, plea 17.

266 (return)

266 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

266/1 See for an illustration 2 Kent's Comm. (12th ed.), 451, n. 1 (b).

266/1 See for an illustration 2 Kent's Comm. (12th ed.), 451, n. 1 (b).

266/2 Repromittatur, but cf. pro servitio tuo vel pro homagio, Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 25.

266/2 Repromittatur, but cf. for your service or for homage, Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 25.

267 (return)

267 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

267/1 Y.B. 29 Ed. III. 25, 26. But cf. 48 Ed. III. 3, pl. 6.

267/1 Y.B. 29 Ed. III. 25, 26. But cf. 48 Ed. III. 3, pl. 6.

267/2 19 R. II., Fitzh. Abr. Dett, pl. 166.

267/2 19 R. II., Fitzh. Abr. Dett, pl. 166.

267/3 Y.B. 12 Hen. IV. 17, pl. 13, ad fin.

267/3 Y.B. 12 Hen. IV. 17, pl. 13, ad fin.

267/4 Y.B. 9 Hen. V. 14, pl. 23.

267/4 Y.B. 9 Hen. V. 14, pl. 23.

267/5 (Cf. 13 Ed. II. 403; 17 Ed. IIL 48, pl. 14; 29 Ed. III. 25, 26.) 41 Ed. III. 7, pl. 15; 46 Ed. III. 6, pl. 16; Fitzh. Abr. Dett, pl. 166.

267/5 (Cf. 13 Ed. II. 403; 17 Ed. III. 48, pl. 14; 29 Ed. III. 25, 26.) 41 Ed. III. 7, pl. 15; 46 Ed. III. 6, pl. 16; Fitzh. Abr. Dett, pl. 166.

267/6 Y.B. 3 Hen, VI. 36, pl. 33.

267/6 Y.B. 3 Hen, VI. 36, pl. 33.

268 (return)

268 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

268/1 Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 8, pl. 18.

268/1 Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 8, pl. 18.

268/2 E. g., Rolfe in Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 23.

268/2 E. g., Rolfe in Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 23.

269 (return)

269 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

269/1 Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 8, pl. 18. Cf. Bro. Feoffements al Uses, pl. 54; Plowden, 301.

269/1 Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 8, pl. 18. Cf. Bro. Feoffements al Uses, pl. 54; Plowden, 301.

269/2 Y.B. 15 Ed. IV. 32, pl. 14; (S.C., 14 Ed. IV. 6, pl. 3;) 17 Ed. 4, pl. 4.

269/2 Y.B. 15 Ed. IV. 32, pl. 14; (S.C., 14 Ed. IV. 6, pl. 3;) 17 Ed. 4, pl. 4.

269/3 Cf. Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 8, pl. 18; 17 Ed. IV. 4, 5; Plowden, 305, 306.

269/3 Cf. Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 8, pl. 18; 17 Ed. IV. 4, 5; Plowden, 305, 306.

269/4 Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

269/4 Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

269/5 Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 13.

269/5 Y.B. 37 Hen. VI. 13.

269/6 As to requirement of certain sum, cf. Y.B. 12 Ed. II. 375; Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 24.

269/6 Regarding the requirement of a certain sum, see Y.B. 12 Ed. II. 375; Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 24.

270 (return)

270 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

270/1 Y.B. 29 Ed. III. 25, 26; 40 Ed. III. 24, pl. 27; 43 Ed. II1. 2, pl. 5.

270/1 Y.B. 29 Ed. III. 25, 26; 40 Ed. III. 24, pl. 27; 43 Ed. II1. 2, pl. 5.

270/2 Y.B. 43 Ed. III. 2, pl. 5; 46 Ed. III. 25, pl. 10; 50 Ed. III. 5, pl. 11.

270/2 Y.B. 43 Ed. III. 2, pl. 5; 46 Ed. III. 25, pl. 10; 50 Ed. III. 5, pl. 11.

270/3 Cf. Glanv., Lib. X. c. 8; Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 25.

270/3 Cf. Glanv., Lib. X. c. 8; Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 25.

270/4 Y.B. 35 Ed. I. 454; 12 Ed. II. 375.

270/4 Y.B. 35 Ed. I. 454; 12 Ed. II. 375.

272 (return)

272 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

272/1 Ducange, "Sigilium"; Ingulph. 901.

272/1 Ducange, "Sigilium"; Ingulph. 901.

272/2 Big. Pl. Ang. Norm. 177.

272/2 Big. Pl. Ang. Norm. 177.

272/3 Big. Pl. Ant. Norm. 177; Bract., fol. 100 b, Section 9, "scriptura." But cf. Y.B. 30 Ed. I. 158; Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 25.

272/3 Big. Pl. Ant. Norm. 177; Bract., fol. 100 b, Section 9, "scriptura." But cf. Y.B. 30 Ed. I. 158; Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 25.

272/4 Y.B. 33 Ed. I. 354, 356; 35 Ed. I. 455, top; 41 Ed. III. 7, pl. 15; 44 Ed. III. 21, pl. 23. Cf. 39 Hen. VI. 34, pl. 46.

272/4 Y.B. 33 Ed. I. 354, 356; 35 Ed. I. 455, top; 41 Ed. III. 7, pl. 15; 44 Ed. III. 21, pl. 23. Cf. 39 Hen. VI. 34, pl. 46.

272/5 Y.B. 7 Ed. I. 242. Cf. 35 Ed. I. 452.

272/5 Y.B. 7 Ed. I. 242. Cf. 35 Ed. I. 452.

272/6 Cf. Bract., fol. 100 b, Section 9.

272/6 Cf. Bract., fol. 100 b, Section 9.

272/7 Cf. Glanv., Lib. X. c. 12; Dugdale, Antiq. Warwic. 673, cited Ducange, "Sigillum"; Bract., fol. 396 b, Section 3; I Britt. (Nich.)163, Section 17; Abbrev. Plac. 8 Joh., Berk. rot. 4, pp. 55, 56; ib. 19 Ed. I., Norf. & Surf. rot. 7, p. 284; ib. Index "Sigillum."

272/7 Cf. Glanv., Lib. X. c. 12; Dugdale, Antiq. Warwic. 673, cited Ducange, "Sigillum"; Bract., fol. 396 b, Section 3; I Britt. (Nich.)163, Section 17; Abbrev. Plac. 8 Joh., Berk. rot. 4, pp. 55, 56; ib. 19 Ed. I., Norf. & Surf. rot. 7, p. 284; ib. Index "Sigillum."

272/8 Y.B. 30 Ed. I. 158; Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 25, p. 130.

272/8 Y.B. 30 Ed. I. 158; Fleta, II. c. 60, Section 25, p. 130.

273 (return)

273 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

273/1 45 Ed. III. 24, pl. 30.

273/1 45 Ed. III. 24, pl. 30.

273/2 Bract., fol. 100 b, Section 9.

273/2 Bract., fol. 100 b, Section 9.

275 (return)

275 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

275/1 Cf. 5 Co. Rep. 13 b, 14 a, with 1 Roll. Rep. 126, 128; Y.B. 43 Ed. III 30, pl. 15.

275/1 Cf. 5 Co. Rep. 13 b, 14 a, with 1 Roll. Rep. 126, 128; Y.B. 43 Ed. III 30, pl. 15.

275/2 Y.B. 46 Ed. III. 19, pl. 19; S.C. Bro. Acc. sur le Case, pl. 22.

275/2 Y.B. 46 Ed. III. 19, pl. 19; S.C. Bro. Acc. sur le Case, pl. 22.

275/3 Y.B. 22 Ass., pl. 4i, fol. 94.

275/3 Y.B. 22 Ass., pl. 4i, fol. 94.

276 (return)

276 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

276/1 Y.B. 43 Ed. III. 33, pl. 38.

276/1 Y.B. 43 Ed. III. 33, pl. 38.

277 (return)

277 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

277/1 Y.B. 11 Hen. IV. 33, pl. 60.

277/1 Y.B. 11 Hen. IV. 33, pl. 60.

277/2 Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

277/2 Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

277/3 Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 3, pl. 9; 11 Hen. IV. 33, pl. 60. Cf. 3 Hen. VI. 36, 83.

277/3 Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 3, pl. 9; 11 Hen. IV. 33, pl. 60. Cf. 3 Hen. VI. 36, 83.

279 (return)

279 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

279/1 Cf. 19 Hen. VI. 49, pl. 5 ad fin., Newton, C. J.

279/1 Cf. 19 Hen. VI. 49, pl. 5 at the end, Newton, C. J.

280 (return)

280 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

280/1 Cf. Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 6, pl. 11.

280/1 Cf. Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 6, pl. 11.

280/2 Cases supra; Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 3, pl. 9; 11 Hen. IV. 33. Cf. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33; 20 Hen. VI. 34, pl. 4; 2 Hen. VII. 11, pl. 9.

280/2 Cases above; Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 3, pl. 9; 11 Hen. IV. 33. See also 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33; 20 Hen. VI. 34, pl. 4; 2 Hen. VII. 11, pl. 9.

281 (return)

281 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

281/1 Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 6, pl. 11. Cf. Fitzh. Abr. Acc. sur le case, pl. 37, 11 R. II; 14 Hen. VI. 18. But cf. 43 Ed. III. 33, pl. 38.

281/1 Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 6, pl. 11. Cf. Fitzh. Abr. Acc. sur le case, pl. 37, 11 R. II; 14 Hen. VI. 18. But cf. 43 Ed. III. 33, pl. 38.

282 (return)

282 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

282/1 Cf. Candish's reasons for allowing wager of law with Y.B. 32 & 33 Ed. I., Preface, p. xxxvi., citing the old rules of pleading printed at the end of the tract entitled, Modus tenendi unum Hundredum sire Curiam de Recordo, in Rastell's Law Tracts, p. 410, E, F, G.

282/1 Cf. Candish's reasons for allowing wager of law with Y.B. 32 & 33 Ed. I., Preface, p. xxxvi., citing the old rules of pleading printed at the end of the tract titled, Modus tenendi unum Hundredum sire Curiam de Recordo, in Rastell's Law Tracts, p. 410, E, F, G.

282/2 Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

282/2 Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

282/3 Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 3, pl. 9; 11 Hen. IV. 33, pl. 60; 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

282/3 Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 3, pl. 9; 11 Hen. IV. 33, pl. 60; 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

282/4 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

282/4 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

283 (return)

283 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

283/1 Y.B. 14 Hen. VI. 18, pl. 58.

283/1 Y.B. 14 Hen. VI. 18, pl. 58.

283/2 Ibid. Cf. 48 Ed. III 6, pl. 11.

283/2 Ibid. Cf. 48 Ed. III 6, pl. 11.

283/3 Y.B. 19 Hen. VI. 49, pl. 5. See, further, Y.B. 20 Hen. VI. 25, pl. 11.

283/3 Y.B. 19 Hen. VI. 49, pl. 5. See, further, Y.B. 20 Hen. VI. 25, pl. 11.

284 (return)

284 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

284/1 Cf. Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

284/1 Cf. Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

284/2 Y.B. 2 Hen. VII. 11, pl. 9. Cf. 20 Hen. VI. 34, pl. 4.

284/2 Y.B. 2 Hen. VII. 11, pl. 9. Cf. 20 Hen. VI. 34, pl. 4.

284/3 Cf. Y.B. 14 Hen. VI. 18, pl. 58; 21 Hen. VII. 41, pl. 66, Fineux, C. J.

284/3 Cf. Y.B. 14 Hen. VI. 18, pl. 58; 21 Hen. VII. 41, pl. 66, Fineux, C. J.

284/4 Keilway, 160, pl. 2 (2 Hen. VIII.); Powtuary v. Walton, 1 Roll. Abr. 10, pl. 5 (39 Eliz.); Coggs v. Bernard, 2 Ld. Raym. 909 (2 Anne, A.D. 1703). Supra, p. 195.

284/4 Keilway, 160, pl. 2 (2 Hen. VIII.); Powtuary v. Walton, 1 Roll. Abr. 10, pl. 5 (39 Eliz.); Coggs v. Bernard, 2 Ld. Raym. 909 (2 Anne, A.D. 1703). Supra, p. 195.

285 (return)

285 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

285/1 Sands v. Trevilian, Cro. Car. 193, 194 (Mich. 4 Car. I., A.D. 1629).

285/1 Sands v. Trevilian, Cro. Car. 193, 194 (Mich. 4 Car. I., A.D. 1629).

285/2 Bro. Acc. sur le Case, pl. 5; S.C., Y.B. 27 Hen. VIII. 24, 25, pl. 3; Sidenham v. Worlington, 2 Leon. 224, A.D. 1585.

285/2 Bro. Acc. on the Case, pl. 5; S.C., Y.B. 27 Hen. VIII. 24, 25, pl. 3; Sidenham v. Worlington, 2 Leon. 224, A.D. 1585.

285/3 Y.B. 21 Hen. VII. 30, pl. 5; ib. 41, pl. 66.

285/3 Y.B. 21 Hen. VII. 30, pl. 5; ib. 41, pl. 66.

285/4 Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

285/4 Y.B. 3 Hen. VI. 36, pl. 33.

286 (return)

286 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

286/1 Sharington v. Strotton, Plowden, 298 (Mich. 7 & 8 Eliz.); ib. 309, note on "the civil law."

286/1 Sharington v. Strotton, Plowden, 298 (Mich. 7 & 8 Eliz.); ib. 309, note on "the civil law."

286/2 Hunt v. Bate, 3 Dyer, 272 a (10 Eliz., A.D. 1568).

286/2 Hunt v. Bate, 3 Dyer, 272 a (10 Eliz., A.D. 1568).

286/3 See Lecture VIII. Mr. Langdell, Contracts, Sections 92, 94, suggests the ingenious explanation for this doctrine, that it was then held that no promise could be implied in fact from the request. There may be evidence which I do not know, but the case cited (Bosden v. Thinne, Yelv. 40) for this statement was not decided until A.D. 1603, while the implication of Hunt v. Bate, supra, which was the authority followed by the cases to be explained, is all the other way.

286/3 See Lecture VIII. Mr. Langdell, Contracts, Sections 92, 94, offers an interesting explanation for this doctrine, suggesting that at the time, it was believed that no promise could be implied from the request. There might be evidence I'm unaware of, but the case cited (Bosden v. Thinne, Yelv. 40) for this statement wasn't decided until A.D. 1603, whereas the implication from Hunt v. Bate, supra, which was the basis followed by the cases to be clarified, points in a completely different direction.

286/4 Sidenham v. Worlington, 2 Leon. 224, A.D. 1585.

286/4 Sidenham v. Worlington, 2 Leon. 224, A.D. 1585.

287 (return)

287 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

287/1 Read v. Baxter, 3 Dyer, 272 b, n. (26 & 27 Eliz.). Cf. Richards and Bartlet's Case, 1 Leon. 19 (26 Eliz.).

287/1 Read v. Baxter, 3 Dyer, 272 b, n. (26 & 27 Eliz.). Cf. Richards and Bartlet's Case, 1 Leon. 19 (26 Eliz.).

287/2 Bro. Acc. sur le Case, pl. 5; S.C., Y.B. 27 Hen. VIII. 24, 25, pl. 3; 3 Dyer, 272, n.

287/2 Bro. Acc. on the Case, pl. 5; S.C., Y.B. 27 Hen. VIII. 24, 25, pl. 3; 3 Dyer, 272, n.

287/3 Marsh v. Rainsford, 3 Dyer, 272 b, n.; S.C., 2 Leon. 111, and Cro. Eliz. 59, sub. nom. Marsh v. Kavenford.

287/3 Marsh v. Rainsford, 3 Dyer, 272 b, n.; S.C., 2 Leon. 111, and Cro. Eliz. 59, sub. nom. Marsh v. Kavenford.

287/4 Smith and Smith's Case, 3 Leon. 88, A.D. 1583; Riches and Briggs, Yelv. 4, A.D. 1601; Pickas v. Guile, Yelv. 128, A.D. 1608.

287/4 Smith and Smith's Case, 3 Leon. 88, A.D. 1583; Riches and Briggs, Yelv. 4, A.D. 1601; Pickas v. Guile, Yelv. 128, A.D. 1608.

288 (return)

288 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

288/1 Supra, p. 195. Lord Coke's caution not to rely on the abridgments is very necessary to the proper study of the history of consideration. The abridgments apply the doctrine to cases which make no mention of it, and which were decided before it was ever heard of.

288/1 Supra, p. 195. Lord Coke's advice not to depend on the abridgments is crucial for understanding the history of consideration. The abridgments apply the doctrine to cases that don’t mention it and that were decided before it was even known.

290 (return)

290 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

290/1 Y.B. 46 Ed. III. 19, pl. 19; 19 Hen. VI. 49, pl. 5; Keilway, 160, pl. 2; Powtuary v. Walton, 1 Roll. Abr. 10, pl. 5; Coggs v. Bernaard, 2 Ld. Raym. 909.

290/1 Y.B. 46 Ed. III. 19, pl. 19; 19 Hen. VI. 49, pl. 5; Keilway, 160, pl. 2; Powtuary v. Walton, 1 Roll. Abr. 10, pl. 5; Coggs v. Bernaard, 2 Ld. Raym. 909.

290/2 Riches and Briggs, Yelv. 4, A.D. 1601; Pickas v. Guile, Yelv. 128.

290/2 Riches and Briggs, Yelv. 4, A.D. 1601; Pickas v. Guile, Yelv. 128.

291 (return)

291 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

291/1 Bainbridge v. Firmstone, 8 Ad. & El. 743, A.D. 1838.

291/1 Bainbridge v. Firmstone, 8 Ad. & El. 743, A.D. 1838.

291/2 Wilkinson v. Oliveira, 1 Bing. N. C. 490, A.D. 1835; Haigh v. Brooks, 10 Ad. & El. 309; lb. 323; Hart v. Miles, 4 C.B. N.S. 371, A.D. 1858.

291/2 Wilkinson v. Oliveira, 1 Bing. N. C. 490, A.D. 1835; Haigh v. Brooks, 10 Ad. & El. 309; lb. 323; Hart v. Miles, 4 C.B. N.S. 371, A.D. 1858.

291/3 Wheatley v. Low, Cro. Jac. 668, A.D. 1623. Cf. Byne and Playne's Case, 1 Leon. 220, 221 (32 & 33 Eliz.).

291/3 Wheatley v. Low, Cro. Jac. 668, A.D. 1623. Cf. Byne and Playne's Case, 1 Leon. 220, 221 (32 & 33 Eliz.).

291/4 Wilkinson v. Oliveira, 1 Bing. N. C. 490; Haigh v. Brooks, 10 Ad. & El. 309; Hart v. Miles, 4 C.B. N.S. 371; 6 Am. Law Rev. 47, Oct. 1871.

291/4 Wilkinson v. Oliveira, 1 Bing. N. C. 490; Haigh v. Brooks, 10 Ad. & El. 309; Hart v. Miles, 4 C.B. N.S. 371; 6 Am. Law Rev. 47, Oct. 1871.

292 (return)

292 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

292/1 Supra, pp. 196, 197. See also Lecture VII.

292/1 Supra, pp. 196, 197. See also Lecture VII.

292/2 Byles, J., in Shadwell v. Shadwell, 30 L. J. C.P. 145, 149.

292/2 Byles, J., in Shadwell v. Shadwell, 30 L. J. C.P. 145, 149.

292/3 Shadwell v. Shadwell, ubi supra; Burr v. Wilcox, 13 Allen, 269, 272, 273.

292/3 Shadwell v. Shadwell, cited earlier; Burr v. Wilcox, 13 Allen, 269, 272, 273.

292/4 Thomas v. Thomas, 2 Q.B.851.

292/4 Thomas v. Thomas, 2 Q.B.851.

293 (return)

293 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

293/1 Price v. Jenkins, 5 Ch. D. 619. Cf. Grabbe v. Moxey, 1 W. R. 226; Thomas v. Thomas, 2 Q.B.851; Monahan, Method of Law, 141 et seq.

293/1 Price v. Jenkins, 5 Ch. D. 619. Cf. Grabbe v. Moxey, 1 W. R. 226; Thomas v. Thomas, 2 Q.B.851; Monahan, Method of Law, 141 et seq.

294 (return)

294 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

294/1 Ellis v. Clark, 110 Mass. 389.

294/1 Ellis v. Clark, 110 Mass. 389.

294/2 Fitch v. Snedaker, 38 N. Y. 248, criticising Williaws v. Carwardine, 4 Barn. & Ad. 621, where, however, it does not appear that the plaintiff did not know of the offer of a reward, but merely that the jury found that she was in fact actuated by other motives, a finding wholly beside the mark.

294/2 Fitch v. Snedaker, 38 N. Y. 248, criticizing Williaws v. Carwardine, 4 Barn. & Ad. 621, where, however, it does not appear that the plaintiff was unaware of the reward offer, but rather that the jury found she was actually motivated by other reasons, a finding completely irrelevant.

296 (return)

296 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

296/1 Y.B. 29 Ed. III. 25, 26.

296/1 Y.B. 29 Ed. III. 25, 26.

296/2 19 R. II., Fitzh. Abr. Dett, pl. 166.

296/2 19 R. II., Fitzh. Abr. Dett, pl. 166.

296/3 Hunt v. Bate, Dyer, 272, A.D. 1568.

296/3 Hunt v. Bate, Dyer, 272, A.D. 1568.

297 (return)

297 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

297/1 See Barker v. Halifax, Cro. Eliz. 741; S.C. 3 Dyer, 272 a, n. 32.

297/1 See Barker v. Halifax, Cro. Eliz. 741; S.C. 3 Dyer, 272 a, n. 32.

297/2 Sidenham v. Worlington, 2 Leonard, 224; Bosden v. Thinne, Yelv. 40; Lampleigh v. Brathwait, Hobart, 105; Langdell, Cas. on Contr. (2d ed.), ch. 2, Section 11, Summary, Sections 90 et seq. See above, Lecture VII. p. 286.

297/2 Sidenham v. Worlington, 2 Leonard, 224; Bosden v. Thinne, Yelv. 40; Lampleigh v. Brathwait, Hobart, 105; Langdell, Cas. on Contr. (2d ed.), ch. 2, Section 11, Summary, Sections 90 et seq. See above, Lecture VII. p. 286.

297/3 Pollock, Contr. (lst ed.), p. 6.

297/3 Pollock, Contr. (1st ed.), p. 6.

298 (return)

298 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

298/1 Canham v. Barry, 15 C.B. 597, 619; Jones v. How, 9 C.B. 1, 9; Com. Dig. Condition, D. 2; I Roll. Abr. 420 (D), pl. 1; Y.B. 22 Ed. IV. 26, pl. 6.

298/1 Canham v. Barry, 15 C.B. 597, 619; Jones v. How, 9 C.B. 1, 9; Com. Dig. Condition, D. 2; I Roll. Abr. 420 (D), pl. 1; Y.B. 22 Ed. IV. 26, pl. 6.

301 (return)

301 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

301/1 Gee v. Lancashire & Yorkshire Railway Co., 6 H. & N. 211, 218, Bramwell, B. Cf. Hydraulic Engineering Co. v. McHaffie, 4 Q.B.D. 670, 674, 676.

301/1 Gee v. Lancashire & Yorkshire Railway Co., 6 H. & N. 211, 218, Bramwell, B. Cf. Hydraulic Engineering Co. v. McHaffie, 4 Q.B.D. 670, 674, 676.

301/2 British Columbia Saw-Mill Co. v. Nettleship, L.R. 3 C.P. 499, 509, Willes, J.; Horne v. Midland Railway Co., L.R. 7 C.P. 583, 591; S.C., L.R. 8 C.P. 131.

301/2 British Columbia Saw-Mill Co. v. Nettleship, L.R. 3 C.P. 499, 509, Willes, J.; Horne v. Midland Railway Co., L.R. 7 C.P. 583, 591; S.C., L.R. 8 C.P. 131.

302 (return)

302 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

302/1 British Columbia Saw-Mill Co. v. Nettleship, L.R. 3 C.P. 499, 509.

302/1 British Columbia Saw-Mill Co. v. Nettleship, L.R. 3 C.P. 499, 509.

304 (return)

304 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

304/1 Cheale v. Kenward, 3 DeG. & J. 27.

304/1 Cheale v. Kenward, 3 DeG. & J. 27.

304/2 Langdell, Contr., Sections 89, 28.

304/2 Langdell, Contr., Sections 89, 28.

305 (return)

305 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

305/1 Langdell, Contr., Section 57.

305/1 Langdell, Cont., Section 57.

305/2 Ibid., Sections 14, 15.

305/2 Ibid., Sections 14, 15.

306 (return)

306 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

306/1 But see Langdell, Contr., Sections 14, 15.

306/1 But see Langdell, Contr., Sections 14, 15.

309 (return)

309 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

309/1 Raffles v. Wichelhaus, 2 H. & C. 906. Cf. Kyle v. Kavanagh, 103 Mass. 356, 357.

309/1 Raffles v. Wichelhaus, 2 H. & C. 906. Cf. Kyle v. Kavanagh, 103 Mass. 356, 357.

309/2 Cf. Cocker v. Crompton, 1 B. & C. 489.

309/2 Cf. Cocker v. Crompton, 1 B. & C. 489.

310 (return)

310 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

310/1 Smith v. Hughes, L.R. 6 Q.B.597.

310/1 Smith v. Hughes, L.R. 6 Q.B.597.

310/2 See Gardner v. Lane, 12 Allen, 39; S.C. 9 Allen, 492, 98 Mass. 517.

310/2 See Gardner v. Lane, 12 Allen, 39; S.C. 9 Allen, 492, 98 Mass. 517.

311 (return)

311 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

311/1 Goddard v. Monitor Ins. Co., 108 Mass. 56.

311/1 Goddard v. Monitor Ins. Co., 108 Mass. 56.

313 (return)

313 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

313/1 See Cundy v. Lindsay, 3 App. Cas. 459, 469. Cf. Reg. v. Middleton, L.R. 2 C.C. 38, 55 et seq., 62 et seq.; Reg. v. Davies, Dearsly, C.C. 640; Rex v. Mucklow, 1 Moody, O.C. 160; Reg. v. Jacobs, 12 Cox, 151.

313/1 See Cundy v. Lindsay, 3 App. Cas. 459, 469. Cf. Reg. v. Middleton, L.R. 2 C.C. 38, 55 et seq., 62 et seq.; Reg. v. Davies, Dearsly, C.C. 640; Rex v. Mucklow, 1 Moody, O.C. 160; Reg. v. Jacobs, 12 Cox, 151.

313/2 "Praesentia corporis tollit errorem nominis." Cf. Byles, J., in Way v. Hearne, 32 L. J. N.S.C.P. 34, 40. But cf. the conflicting opinions in Reg. v. Middleton, L.R. 2 C.C. 38, 45, 57. It would seem that a proper name or other identification of an object or person as specific may have the same effect as an actual identification by the senses, because it refers to such an identification, although in a less direct way.

313/2 "The presence of the body eliminates the mistake of the name." Cf. Byles, J., in Way v. Hearne, 32 L. J. N.S.C.P. 34, 40. But cf. the conflicting opinions in Reg. v. Middleton, L.R. 2 C.C. 38, 45, 57. It appears that a proper name or another form of identifying an object or person specifically can have the same impact as a direct sensory identification, as it relates to such an identification, albeit in a less straightforward manner.

316 (return)

316 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

316/1 Brown v. Foster, 113 Mass. 136.

316/1 Brown v. Foster, 113 Mass. 136.

316/2 Leake, Dig. Contr. 13, 14, 637; Hunt v. Livermore, 5 Pick. 395, 397; Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 36.

316/2 Leake, Dig. Contr. 13, 14, 637; Hunt v. Livermore, 5 Pick. 395, 397; Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 36.

316/3 Leake, Dig. Contr. 638; Braunstein v. Accidental Death Ins. Co., 1 B. & S. 782.

316/3 Leake, Dig. Contr. 638; Braunstein v. Accidental Death Ins. Co., 1 B. & S. 782.

316/4 But cf. Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 29.

316/4 But cf. Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 29.

318 (return)

318 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

318/1 Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 29.

318/1 Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 29.

318/2 Bullen & Leake, Prec. of Plead. (3d ed.), 147, "Conditions Precedent."

318/2 Bullen & Leake, Prec. of Plead. (3d ed.), 147, "Conditions Precedent."

319 (return)

319 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

319/1 Cf. Cort v. Ambergate, Nottingham & Boston & Eastern Junction Railway Co., 17 Q.B.127.

319/1 Cf. Cort v. Ambergate, Nottingham & Boston & Eastern Junction Railway Co., 17 Q.B.127.

320 (return)

320 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

320/1 Goodman v. Pocock, 15 Q.B.576 (1850).

320/1 Goodman v. Pocock, 15 Q.B.576 (1850).

325 (return)

325 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

325/1 Fisher v. Mellen, 103 Mass. 503.

325/1 Fisher v. Mellen, 103 Mass. 503.

325/2 Supra, p. 136.

325/2 Supra, p. 136.

327 (return)

327 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

327/1 Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 33.

327/1 Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 33.

328 (return)

328 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

328/1 See the explanation of Dimech v. Corlett, 12 Moo. P.C. 199, in Behn v. Burness, 3 B. & S. 751, 760.

328/1 See the explanation of Dimech v. Corlett, 12 Moo. P.C. 199, in Behn v. Burness, 3 B. & S. 751, 760.

329 (return)

329 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

329/1 Behn v. Burness, 3 B. & S. 751.

329/1 Behn v. Burness, 3 B. & S. 751.

329/2 Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 28, p. 1000.

329/2 Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 28, p. 1000.

329/3 See Lecture VIII.

329/3 See Lecture 8.

330 (return)

330 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

330/1 Kennedy v. Panama, &c. Mail Co., L.R. 2 Q.B.580, 588; Lyon v. Bertram, 20 How. 149, 153. Cf. Windscheid, Pand., Section 76, nn. 6, 9.

330/1 Kennedy v. Panama, &c. Mail Co., L.R. 2 Q.B.580, 588; Lyon v. Bertram, 20 How. 149, 153. Cf. Windscheid, Pand., Section 76, nn. 6, 9.

330/2 Windscheid, Pand., Section 76(4). See, generally, Ibid., nn. 6, 7; Section 78, pp. 206, 207; Section 82, pp. 216 et seq.

330/2 Windscheid, Pand., Section 76(4). See, generally, Ibid., nn. 6, 7; Section 78, pp. 206, 207; Section 82, pp. 216 et seq.

331 (return)

331 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

331/1 Cr. Ihering, Geist d. Roem. Rechts, Section 48, III. p. 116 (Fr. transl.).

331/1 Cr. Ihering, Geist d. Roem. Rechts, Section 48, III. p. 116 (Fr. transl.).

331/2 See, however, the language of Crompton, J. in S.C., I B. & S. 877. Cf. Kent, Comm. (12th ed.), 479, n. 1, A (c).

331/2 See, however, the wording of Crompton, J. in S.C., I B. & S. 877. Cf. Kent, Comm. (12th ed.), 479, n. 1, A (c).

331/3 Behn v. Burness, 3 B. & S. 751, 755, 756.

331/3 Behn v. Burness, 3 B. & S. 751, 755, 756.

334 (return)

334 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

334/1 Cf. Anglo-Egyptian Navigation Co. v. Rennie, L.R. 10 C.P. 271.

334/1 See Anglo-Egyptian Navigation Co. v. Rennie, L.R. 10 C.P. 271.

334/2 Ellen v. Topp, 6 Exch. 424.

334/2 Ellen v. Topp, 6 Exch. 424.

335 (return)

335 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

335/1 Contracts (2d Ed.), Section 106, and passim.

335/1 Contracts (2d Ed.), Section 106, and throughout.

336 (return)

336 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

336/1 Chanter v. Hopkins, 4 M. & W. 399, 404. Possibly Behn v. Burness, stated above, might have been dealt with in this way. The ship tendered was not a ship which had been in the port of Amsterdam at the date of the contract. It was therefore not such a ship as the contract called for.

336/1 Chanter v. Hopkins, 4 M. & W. 399, 404. It's possible that Behn v. Burness, mentioned above, could have been handled this way. The ship offered wasn't one that had been in the port of Amsterdam at the time of the contract. Therefore, it wasn't the kind of ship that the contract required.

336/2 Heyworth v. Hutchinson, L.R. 2 Q.B.447, criticised in Benj. Sales (2d ed.), pp. 742 et seq.

336/2 Heyworth v. Hutchinson, L.R. 2 Q.B.447, criticized in Benj. Sales (2d ed.), pp. 742 et seq.

336/3 See Thomas v. Cadwallader, Willes, 496; Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Sections 116, 140. This is put as a case of equivalence by Mr. Langdell (Contr., Section 116); but the above explanation is believed to be the true one. It will be noticed that this is hardly a true case of condition, but merely a limitation of the scope of the tenant's promise. So a covenant to serve as apprentice in a trade, which the other party covenants to teach, can only be performed if the other will teach, and must therefore be limited to that event. Cf. Ellen v. Topp, 6 Exch. 424.

336/3 See Thomas v. Cadwallader, Willes, 496; Langd. Contr. (2d ed.), Sections 116, 140. Mr. Langdell describes this as a case of equivalence (Contr., Section 116), but the above explanation is thought to be the accurate one. It should be noted that this is not really a true case of condition, but rather a limitation on the scope of the tenant's promise. For example, a covenant to serve as an apprentice in a trade, which the other party agrees to teach, can only be fulfilled if the other person actually teaches, and must therefore be restricted to that situation. Cf. Ellen v. Topp, 6 Exch. 424.

337 (return)

337 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

337/1 Langdell, Contracts (2d ed.), Section 127. Cf. Roberts v. Brett, 11 H. L. C. 337.

337/1 Langdell, Contracts (2d ed.), Section 127. Cf. Roberts v. Brett, 11 H. L. C. 337.

339 (return)

339 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

339/1 Graves v. Legg, 9 Exch. 709. Cf. Lang. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 33, p. 1004. Mr. Langdell says that a bought note, though part of a bilateral contract, is to be treated as unilateral, and that it may be presumed that the language of the contract relied on was that of a bought note, and thus a condition in favor of the defendant, who made it. I do not quite understand how this can be assumed when the declaration states a bilateral contract, and the question arose on demurrer to a plea, which also states that the plaintiff "was by the agreement bound to declare" the names. How remote the explanation is from the actual ground of decision will be seen.

339/1 Graves v. Legg, 9 Exch. 709. Cf. Lang. Contr. (2d ed.), Section 33, p. 1004. Mr. Langdell says that a bought note, even though it’s part of a bilateral contract, should be seen as unilateral. It can be assumed that the language of the contract relied upon was that of a bought note, making it a condition in favor of the defendant who created it. I don't quite get how this can be assumed when the declaration states a bilateral contract, especially since the issue came up on demurrer to a plea, which also mentions that the plaintiff “was by the agreement bound to declare” the names. The gap between this explanation and the actual basis for the decision is significant.

341 (return)

341 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

341/1 Recht des Besitzes, Section 11, p. 184, n. 1 (7th ed.), Eng. tr. 124, n. t.

341/1 Right of Possession, Section 11, p. 184, n. 1 (7th ed.), Eng. tr. 124, n. t.

342 (return)

342 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

342/1 Inst. II. Section 157.

342/1 Inst. II. Sec. 157.

342/2 "In suis heredibus evidentius apparet continuationem dominii eo rem perdueere, ut nulla videatur hereditas fuisse, quasi olim hi domini essent, qui etiam vivo patre quodammodo domini existimantur, unde etiam filius familias appellatur sicut pater familias, sola nota hae adiecta, per quam distinguitur genitor ab eo qui genitus sit. itaque post mortem patris non hereditatem percipere videntur, sed magis liberam bonorum administrationem consequuntur hac ex causa licet non sint heredes instituti, domini sunt: nec obstat, quod licet eos exheredare, quod et occidere licebat." D. 28.2. 11. Cf. Plato, Laws, [Greek characters]

342/2 "It clearly shows in their heirs the continuation of ownership, as if there really was no inheritance at all, just as these owners were once considered to be, even while their father was alive, hence the term 'filius familias' is used for a son just like 'pater familias' for a father, distinguished only by a note indicating the difference between the parent and the child. Therefore, after the father's death, they don't seem to receive an inheritance, but rather gain the free management of the goods; even if they are not formally recognized as heirs, they still hold ownership. It doesn’t matter that they can be disinherited, as it was also permissible to kill them." D. 28.2. 11. Cf. Plato, Laws, [Greek characters]

343 (return)

343 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

343/1 Laveleye, Propriety, 24, 202, 205, 211, n. 1, 232; Norton, L.C. Hindu Law of Inheritance, p. 193.

343/1 Laveleye, Propriety, 24, 202, 205, 211, n. 1, 232; Norton, L.C. Hindu Law of Inheritance, p. 193.

343/2 D. 50. 16. 208.

343/2 D. 50. 16. 208.

343/3 D. 41. 1. 34. Cf. D. 41. 3. 40; Bract., fol. 8 a, 44 a.

343/3 D. 41. 1. 34. See D. 41. 3. 40; Bract., fol. 8 a, 44 a.

343/4 D. 43. 24. 13, Section 5.

343/4 D. 43. 24. 13, Section 5.

344 (return)

344 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

344/1 Germania, c. 20.

344/1 Germania, c. 20.

345 (return)

345 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

345/1 Littleton, Section 337; Co. Lit. 209, a, b; Y.B. 8 Ed. IV. 5, 6, pl. 1; Keilway, 44 a (17 Hen. VII.); Lord North v. Butts, Dyer, 139 b, 140 a, top; Overton v. Sydall, Popham, 120, 121; Boyer v. Rivet, 3 Bulstr. 317, 321; Bain v. Cooper, 1 Dowl. Pr. Cas. N. s. 11, 14.

345/1 Littleton, Section 337; Co. Lit. 209, a, b; Y.B. 8 Ed. IV. 5, 6, pl. 1; Keilway, 44 a (17 Hen. VII.); Lord North v. Butts, Dyer, 139 b, 140 a, top; Overton v. Sydall, Popham, 120, 121; Boyer v. Rivet, 3 Bulstr. 317, 321; Bain v. Cooper, 1 Dowl. Pr. Cas. N. s. 11, 14.

345/2 Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 2, pl. 4.

345/2 Y.B. 48 Ed. III. 2, pl. 4.

346 (return)

346 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

346/1 Vermoegensrechtlichen Klagen, 88, 89.

346/1 Asset-related lawsuits, 88, 89.

346/2 Proc. de la Lex Salica, tr. Thevenin, p. 72 and n. 1.

346/2 Proc. de la Lex Salica, tr. Thevenin, p. 72 and n. 1.

347 (return)

347 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

347/1 Ethelred, II. 9; Cnut, II. 73; Essays in Ang. Sax. Law, pp. 221 et seq.

347/1 Ethelred, II. 9; Cnut, II. 73; Essays in Ang. Sax. Law, pp. 221 et seq.

347/2 1 Spence, Eq. 189, note, citing Hickes, Dissert. Epist., p. 57.

347/2 1 Spence, Eq. 189, note, citing Hickes, Dissert. Epist., p. 57.

347/3 Glanv., Lib. VII. c. 2 (Beames, p. 150).

347/3 Glanv., Lib. VII. c. 2 (Beames, p. 150).

347/4 Ibid., c. 8 (Beames, p. 168).

347/4 Ibid., c. 8 (Beames, p. 168).

347/5 Reg. Maj., Lib. II. c. 39.

347/5 Reg. Maj., Lib. II. c. 39.

348 (return)

348 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

348/1 Fol. 61 a.

348/1 Fol. 61 a.

348/2 Sachsensp., II. 60, Section 2, cited in Essays in Ang. Sax. Law, p. 221; Grand Cust. de Norm., c. 88.

348/2 Sachsensp., II. 60, Section 2, cited in Essays in Ang. Sax. Law, p. 221; Grand Cust. de Norm., c. 88.

348/3 Britt., fol. 64 b (Nich. ed. 163); Fleta, Lib. II. c. 62, Section 10. Cf. Bract., fol. 37 b, Section 10.

348/3 Britt., fol. 64 b (Nich. ed. 163); Fleta, Lib. II. c. 62, Section 10. Cf. Bract., fol. 37 b, Section 10.

348/4 Bracton, fol. 61 a, b. "Item quaero an testator legare possit actiones suas? Et verum est quod non, de debitis quae in vita testatoris convicta non fuerunt nec recognita, sed hujusmodi actiones competunt haeredibus. Cum antera convicta sint et recognita, tune sunt quasi in bonis testatoris, et competunt executoribus in foro ecclesiastico. Si autem competant haeredibus, ut praedictum est, in foro seculari debent terminari, quia antequam communicantur et in foro debito, non pertinet ad executores, ut in foro ecclesiastico convincantur."

348/4 Bracton, fol. 61 a, b. "I ask whether a testator can bequeath their legal claims. The truth is that they cannot, regarding debts that were neither established nor acknowledged during the testator’s lifetime; such claims belong to the heirs. However, if they were established and acknowledged, then they are considered as part of the testator's estate and belong to the executors in the ecclesiastical court. If they belong to the heirs, as previously mentioned, they must be settled in the secular court because, before they are communicated and in the appropriate court, it does not fall to the executors to be tried in the ecclesiastical court."

349 (return)

349 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

349/1 Bracton, fol. 62a.

349/1 Bracton, fol. 62a.

349/2 Y.B. 20 & 21 Ed. I. 232; cf. ib. 312.

349/2 Y.B. 20 & 21 Ed. I. 232; cf. ib. 312.

349/3 Oates v. Frith, Hob. 130. Cf. Y.B. 5 Hen. VII. 18, pl. 12; Popham, J., in Overton v. Sydall, Poph. 120, 121 (E. 39 El.); Boyer v. Rivet, 3 Bulstr. 317, 319-322; Brooker's Case, Godb. 376, 380 (P. 3 Car. I.).

349/3 Oates v. Frith, Hob. 130. See also Y.B. 5 Hen. VII. 18, pl. 12; Popham, J., in Overton v. Sydall, Poph. 120, 121 (E. 39 El.); Boyer v. Rivet, 3 Bulstr. 317, 319-322; Brooker's Case, Godb. 376, 380 (P. 3 Car. I.).

349/4 Bain v. Cooper, 1 Dowl. Pract. Cas. N. s. 11, 14. Cf. Y.B. 14 Hen. VIII. pl. 5, at fol. 10.

349/4 Bain v. Cooper, 1 Dowl. Pract. Cas. N. s. 11, 14. Cf. Y.B. 14 Hen. VIII. pl. 5, at fol. 10.

350 (return)

350 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

350/1 Bract., fol. 66 b, 76 b, and passim; Y.B. 20 Ed. I. 226, 200; Littleton, Section 241. The same thing was said where there were several executors: "They are only in the place of one person." Y.B. 8 Ed. IV. 5,pl. 1.

350/1 Bract., fol. 66 b, 76 b, and passim; Y.B. 20 Ed. I. 226, 200; Littleton, Section 241. The same thing was stated when there were several executors: "They are only in the position of one person." Y.B. 8 Ed. IV. 5, pl. 1.

350/2 Comm. 385.

350/2 Comm. 385.

350/3 Cf. Glanv., Lib. VII. c. 3; F. N. B. 21 L; Dyer, 4 b, 5 a.

350/3 Cf. Glanv., Lib. VII. c. 3; F. N. B. 21 L; Dyer, 4 b, 5 a.

351 (return)

351 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

351/1 Cf. Bract., fol. 80 b.

351/1 Cf. Bract., fol. 80 b.

351/2 Charta Divis. Reg. Franc., Art. IX. & VIII. Cf. 3 Laferriere, Hist. du Droit Francais, 408, 409.

351/2 Charta Divis. Reg. Franc., Art. IX. & VIII. Cf. 3 Laferriere, Hist. du Droit Francais, 408, 409.

351/3 Glanv., Lib. IX. c. 1 (Beames, pp. 218, 220); Bract., fol. 79 b.

351/3 Glanv., Lib. IX. c. 1 (Beames, pp. 218, 220); Bract., fol. 79 b.

352 (return)

352 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

352/1 Brooker's Case, Godbolt, 376, 377, pl. 465.

352/1 Brooker's Case, Godbolt, 376, 377, pl. 465.

352/2 Dyer, 1 b. Cf. Bain v. Cooper, 1 Dowl. Pr. C. N. s. 11, 12.

352/2 Dyer, 1 b. See Bain v. Cooper, 1 Dowl. Pr. C. N. s. 11, 12.

354 (return)

354 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

354/1 In the American Law Review for October, 1872, VII. 49, 50, I mentioned one or two indications of this fact. But I have since had the satisfaction of finding it worked out with such detail and learning in Ihering's Geist des Roemischen Rechts, Sections 10, 48, that I cannot do better than refer to that work, only adding that for my purposes it is not necessary to go so far as Ihering, and that he does not seem to have been led to the conclusions which it is my object to establish. See, further, Clark, Early Roman Law, 109, 110; Laferriere, Hist. du Droit Frang., I. 114 et seq.; D. 1.5. 4, Section 3; Gaii Inst. IV. Section 16; ib. II. Section 69.

354/1 In the American Law Review for October 1872, VII. 49, 50, I pointed out a couple of signs of this fact. However, I’ve since found it elaborated with such detail and scholarship in Ihering's Geist des Roemischen Rechts, Sections 10, 48, that I must refer to that work, adding only that for my purposes, I don't need to follow Ihering's conclusions fully, and it seems he wasn't led to the same conclusions I'm trying to establish. See also, Clark, Early Roman Law, 109, 110; Laferriere, Hist. du Droit Frang., I. 114 et seq.; D. 1.5. 4, Section 3; Gaii Inst. IV. Section 16; ib. II. Section 69.

356 (return)

356 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

356/1 Erbvertraege, I. 15 et seq.

356/1 Inheritance Agreements, I. 15 et seq.

356/2 Hist. du Droit Franc., IV. 500.

356/2 Hist. du Droit Franc., IV. 500.

356/3 "Quantum dare voluerit aut totam furtunam eui voluerit dare . . . nec minus nec majus nisi quantum ei creditum est." Lex Sal. (Merkel), XLVI.

356/3 "Whoever wishes to take a risk or wants to give away their entire fortune... neither less nor more than what has been entrusted to them." Lex Sal. (Merkel), XLVI.

356/4 Lex Sal. (Merkel), Cap. XLVI., De adfathamire; Sohm, Frank. Reichs- u. Gerichtsverfassung, 69.

356/4 Lex Sal. (Merkel), Cap. XLVI., De adfathamire; Sohm, Frank. Reichs- u. Gerichtsverfassung, 69.

356/6 Beseler, Erbvertraege, I. 101, 102, 105.

356/6 Beseler, Erbverträge, I. 101, 102, 105.

357 (return)

357 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

357/1 "Omnem facultatem suam. . . seu cuicunque libet de proximis vel extraneis, adoptare in hereditatem vel in adfatimi vel per scripturarum seriem seu per traditionem." L. Rib. Cap. L. (al. XLVIII.); cf. L. Thuring. XIII. So Capp. Rib. Section 7: "Qui filios non habuerit et aliurn quemlibet heredem facere sibi voluerit coram rege . . . traditionem faclat."

357/1 "Anyone can use all their resources to adopt anyone they choose, whether from close relations or outsiders, into their inheritance, either through written documents or by transfer." L. Rib. Cap. L. (al. XLVIII.); cf. L. Thuring. XIII. So Capp. Rib. Section 7: "If someone does not have children and wants to name another as their heir in front of the king... they can proceed with the transfer."

357/2 Ed. Roth., cap. 174, 157; cf. lb. 369, 388; Liutpr. III. 16 (al. 2), VI. 155 (al. 102). Cf. Beseler, Erbvertraege, I. 108 et seq., esp. 116-118. Compare the charter of A.D. 713, "Offero . . . S. P. ecclesia quam mihi heredem constitui." (Mem. di Lucca V. b. No. 4.) Troya III. No. 394, cited Heusler, Gewere, 45, 46. Cf. ib. 484. This, no doubt, was due to Roman influence, but it recalls what Sir Henry Maine quotes from Elphinstone's History of India (I. 126), as to sale by a member of one of the village communities: "The purchaser steps exactly into his place, and takes up all his obligations." Ancient Law, ch. 8, pp. 263, 264.

357/2 Ed. Roth., cap. 174, 157; cf. lb. 369, 388; Liutpr. III. 16 (al. 2), VI. 155 (al. 102). Cf. Beseler, Erbvertraege, I. 108 et seq., esp. 116-118. Compare the charter of A.D. 713, "Offero . . . S. P. ecclesia quam mihi heredem constitui." (Mem. di Lucca V. b. No. 4.) Troya III. No. 394, cited Heusler, Gewere, 45, 46. Cf. ib. 484. This, no doubt, was due to Roman influence, but it recalls what Sir Henry Maine quotes from Elphinstone's History of India (I. 126), about the sale by a member of one of the village communities: "The purchaser steps exactly into his place and takes up all his obligations." Ancient Law, ch. 8, pp. 263, 264.

357/3 (Merkel) Cap. LVIII., De chrenecruda. Sohm, Frank. R. u. G. Verf., 117.

357/3 (Merkel) Cap. LVIII., De chrenecruda. Sohm, Frank. R. u. G. Verf., 117.

358 (return)

358 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

358/1 A.D. 679: "Sicuti tibi donata est ira tene et posteri tui." Kemble, Cod. Dip., I. 21, No. xvi. Uhtred, A.D. 767: "Quam is semper possideat et post se cui voluerit heredum relinquat." Ib. I. 144, cxvxi. ("Cuilibet heredi voluerit relinquat" is very common in the later charters; ib. V. 155, MLXXXIL; lb. VI. 1, MCCXVIIL; it). 31, MCCXXX.; lb. 38, MCCXXXIV.; and passim. This may be broader than cui voluerit herealum.) Offa, A.D. 779: "Ut se viverite habe . . . deat. et post se suoe propinquitatis homini cui ipse vo . . . possidendum libera utens potestate relinquat." Ib. I. 164, 165, CXXXVII. Aethilbald, A.D. 736: "Ita ut quamdiu vixerit potestatem habeat tenendi ac possidendi cuicumque voluerit vel eo vivo vel certe post obitum suum relinquendi." Ib. I. 96, LXXX.; cf. ib. V. 53, MXIV. Cuthred of Kent, A.D. 805: "Cuicumque hominum voluerit in aeternam libertatem derelinquat." Ib. I. 232, CXC. "Ut habeat libertatem commutandi vel donandi in vita sua et post ejus obiturn teneat facultatem relinquendi cuicumque volueris." Ib. I. 233, 234, CXCI.; cf. ib. V. 70, MXXXI. Wiglaf of Mercia, Aug. 28, A.D. 831: "Seu vendendum ant commutandum i cuicumque ei herede placuerit dereliaquendum." Ib. I. 294, CCXXVII.

358/1 A.D. 679: "Just as anger is given to you, hold on to it and to your descendants." Kemble, Cod. Dip., I. 21, No. xvi. Uhtred, A.D. 767: "So that he may always possess it and leave it to whichever heir he wishes." Ib. I. 144, cxvxi. ("To whichever heir he wants to leave it" is very common in the later charters; ib. V. 155, MLXXXIL; lb. VI. 1, MCCXVIIL; it). 31, MCCXXX.; lb. 38, MCCXXXIV.; and passim. This may be broader than "to whichever he wanted to" here.) Offa, A.D. 779: "So that while he is alive, he should be... capable, and after his death, he freely leaves it to his relative, whoever he wants to... to possess it with full power." Ib. I. 164, 165, CXXXVII. Aethilbald, A.D. 736: "So that as long as he lives, he has the authority to hold and possess it for whoever he wishes, whether while he is alive or certainly after his death." Ib. I. 96, LXXX.; cf. ib. V. 53, MXIV. Cuthred of Kent, A.D. 805: "To whomever he wants, he should leave it for eternal freedom." Ib. I. 232, CXC. "So that he has the freedom to change or give away during his lifetime and, after his death, holds the ability to leave it to anyone he chooses." Ib. I. 233, 234, CXCI.; cf. ib. V. 70, MXXXI. Wiglaf of Mercia, Aug. 28, A.D. 831: "Either to sell or exchange with whomever his heir prefers to leave it to." Ib. I. 294, CCXXVII.

359 (return)

359 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

359/1 "W. et heredibus suis, videlicet quos heredes constituerit." Memorials of Hexham, Surtees Soc. Pub., 1864, II. 88.

359/1 "W. and his heirs, specifically those he has appointed as heirs." Memorials of Hexham, Surtees Soc. Pub., 1864, II. 88.

359/2 Cf. Y.B. 27 Ass., fol. 135, pl. 25. Under the Welsh laws the champion in a cause decided by combat acquired the rights of the next of kin, the next of kin being the proper champion. Lea, Superstition and Force (3d Ed.), 165. Cf. ib. 161, n. 1; ib. 17.

359/2 Cf. Y.B. 27 Ass., fol. 135, pl. 25. According to Welsh laws, the champion in a battle for a cause gained the rights of the next of kin, who was the rightful champion. Lea, Superstition and Force (3d Ed.), 165. Cf. ib. 161, n. 1; ib. 17.

361 (return)

361 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

361/1 D. 38. 8. 1, pr.

361/1 D. 38. 8. 1, pr.

361/2 "Cum is, qui ex edicto bonorum possessionem petiit, ficto se herede agit." Gaii Inst. IV. Section 34. Cf. Ulp. Fragm. XXVIII. Section 12; D. 37. 1. 2. So the fidei commissarius, who was a praetorian successor (D. 41. 4. 2, Section 19; 10. 2. 24), "in similitudinem heredis consistit." Nov. 1. 1, Section 1. Cf. Just. Inst. 2. 24, pr., and then Gaius, II. Sections 251, 252.

361/2 "When someone seeks possession of assets based on a decree, they're acting as if they are the heir." Gaii Inst. IV. Section 34. See also Ulp. Fragm. XXVIII. Section 12; D. 37. 1. 2. Similarly, the fidei commissarius, who was a praetorian successor (D. 41. 4. 2, Section 19; 10. 2. 24), "exists similarly to an heir." Nov. 1. 1, Section 1. See also Just. Inst. 2. 24, pr., and then Gaius, II. Sections 251, 252.

361/3 Gaii Inst. II. Sections 102 et seq. Cf. ib. Sections 252, 35.

361/3 Gaii Inst. II. Sections 102 and following. See also ib. Sections 252, 35.

361/4 Gaii Inst. IV Section 35: "Similiter et bonorum emptor ficto se herede agit." Cf. ib. Sections 144, 145. Keller, Roemische Civilprocess, Section 85, III. But cf. Scheurl, Lehrb. der Inst., Section 218, p. 407 (6th ed.).

361/4 Gaii Inst. IV Section 35: "In the same way, the purchaser of goods acts as if he is the heir." Cf. ib. Sections 144, 145. Keller, Roemische Civilprocess, Section 85, III. But cf. Scheurl, Lehrb. der Inst., Section 218, p. 407 (6th ed.).

361/5 Paulus in D. 50. 17. 128.

361/5 Paulus in D. 50. 17. 128.

362 (return)

362 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

362/1 "In re legata in accessione temporis quo testator possedit, legatarius quodammodo quasi heres est." D. 41. 3. 14, Section 1.

362/1 "In regards to the bequest in relation to the time during which the testator held it, the legatee is, in a way, almost like an heir." D. 41. 3. 14, Section 1.

362/2 D. 41.1.62; 43. 3. 1, Section 6; Gaii Inst. II. Section 97; Just. Inst. 2. 10, Section 11.

362/2 D. 41.1.62; 43. 3. 1, Section 6; Gaii Inst. II. Section 97; Just. Inst. 2. 10, Section 11.

363 (return)

363 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

363/1 "[Accessiones possessionum] plane tribuuntur his qui in locum aliorum succedunt sive ex contractu sive voluntate: heredibus enum et his, qui successorum loco habentur, datur accessio testatoris. Itaque si mihi vendideris servum utar accesssione tua." D. 44.3.14, Sections 1, 2.

363/1 "[Accessiones possessionum] are clearly granted to those who succeed others, whether by contract or will: it is given to heirs and those in the place of successors, the testator's accessions are granted. Therefore, if you sell me a servant, I will benefit from your accession." D. 44.3.14, Sections 1, 2.

363/2 "Ab eo . . . in cujus locum hereditate vel emptione aliove quo iure successi." D. 43. 19. 3, Section 2.

363/2 "From him . . . in whose place I have succeeded by inheritance or purchase or by any other right." D. 43. 19. 3, Section 2.

363/3 D. 50. 4. 1, Section 4. Cf. Cic. de Off. 3. 19. 76; Gaii Inst. IV. Section 34.

363/3 D. 50. 4. 1, Section 4. Cf. Cic. de Off. 3. 19. 76; Gaii Inst. IV. Section 34.

363/4 C. 2. 3. 21; C. 6. 16. 2; cf. D. 38. 8. 1, pr.

363/4 C. 2. 3. 21; C. 6. 16. 2; cf. D. 38. 8. 1, pr.

364 (return)

364 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

364/1 "In locum successisse accipimus sive per universitatem sive in rem sit successum." D. 43. 3. 1, Section 13. Cf. D. 21.3.3, Section 1; D. 12.2.7&8;D. 39. 2. 24, Section 1.

364/1 "We understand that a succession occurs either by universal succession or in relation to the property." D. 43. 3. 1, Section 13. See also D. 21.3.3, Section 1; D. 12.2.7&8; D. 39. 2. 24, Section 1.

364/2 D. 41.2. 13, Sections 1, 11. Other cases put by Ulpian may stand on a different fiction. After the termination of a precarium, for instance, fingitur fundus nunquam fuisse possessus ab ipso detentore. Gothofred, note 14 (Elz. ed.). But cf. Puchta, in Weiske, R. L., art. Besitz, p. 50, and D. 41.2.13, Section7.

364/2 D. 41.2. 13, Sections 1, 11. Other cases mentioned by Ulpian might be based on a different assumption. For example, after a precarium ends, it's as if the land was never held by the person in possession. Gothofred, note 14 (Elz. ed.). But see Puchta, in Weiske, R. L., art. Besitz, p. 50, and D. 41.2.13, Section 7.

364/3 Inst. 2. 6, Sections 12, 13. Cf. D. 44. 3. 9. See, for a fuller statement, 11 Am. Law Rev. 644, 645.

364/3 Inst. 2. 6, Sections 12, 13. Cf. D. 44. 3. 9. See, for a fuller statement, 11 Am. Law Rev. 644, 645.

365 (return)

365 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

365/1 Recht des Besitzes, Section11 (7th ed.), p. 184, n. 1, Eng. tr. 124, n. t.

365/1 Right of Possession, Section 11 (7th ed.), p. 184, n. 1, Eng. tr. 124, n. t.

365/2 Paulus, D. 8. 6. 18, Section 1. This seems to be written of a rural servitude (aqua) which was lost by mere disuse, without adverse user by the servient owner.

365/2 Paulus, D. 8. 6. 18, Section 1. This appears to describe a rural servitude (water) that was lost simply due to lack of use, without any opposing use by the owner of the servient property.

365/3 Hermogenianus, D. 21. 3. 3; Exe. rei jud., D. 44. 2. 9, Section 2; ib. 28; ib. 11, Sections 3, 9; D. 10. 2. 25, Section 8; D. 46. 8. 16, Section I; Keller, Roem. Civilproc., Section 73. Cf. Bracton, fol. 24 b, Section 1 ad fin.

365/3 Hermogenianus, D. 21. 3. 3; Exe. rei jud., D. 44. 2. 9, Section 2; ib. 28; ib. 11, Sections 3, 9; D. 10. 2. 25, Section 8; D. 46. 8. 16, Section I; Keller, Roem. Civilproc., Section 73. Cf. Bracton, fol. 24 b, Section 1 ad fin.

365/4 "Recte a me via uti prohibetur et interdictum ei inutile est, quia a me videtur vi vel clam vel precario possidere, qui ab auctore meo vitiose possidet. nam et Pedius scribit, si vi aut clam aut precario ab co sit usus, in cuius locum hereditate vel emptione aliove quo lure suceessi, idem esse dicendum: cum enim successerit quis in locum eorum, aequum non est nos noceri hoc, quod adversus eum non nocuit, in cuius locum successimus." D. 43. 19. 3, Section 2. The variation actore, argued for by Savigny, is condemned by Mommsen, in his edition of the Digest, —it seems rightly.

365/4 "It's prohibited for me to use the path, and the prohibition is meaningless to him because it seems that he is occupying it either by force, secretly, or temporarily, having taken possession from my wrongdoer. Pedius also writes that if someone uses the property by force, secretly, or temporarily, from another who possesses it wrongfully, the same should apply when they take over by inheritance, purchase, or any other legal means. Since someone succeeds another in their place, it's only fair that we are not harmed by something that did not harm the person we succeeded." D. 43. 19. 3, Section 2. The variation proposed by Savigny is rejected by Mommsen in his edition of the Digest, and it seems justifiable.

365/5 D. 12. 2. 7 & 8.

365/5 D. 12. 2. 7 & 8.

366 (return)

366 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

366/1 Ulpian, D. 39. 2. 24, Section1. Cf. D. 8. 5.7; D. 39. 2. 17, Section 3, n. 79 (Elzevir ed.); Paulus, D. 2. 14. 17, Section 5.

366/1 Ulpian, D. 39. 2. 24, Section1. Cf. D. 8. 5.7; D. 39. 2. 17, Section 3, n. 79 (Elzevir ed.); Paulus, D. 2. 14. 17, Section 5.

366/2 "Cum quis in alii locum successerit non est aequum ei nocere hoc, quod adversus eum non nocuit, in cujus locum successit. Plerumque emptoris eadem causa esse debet circa petendum ac defendendum, quae fuit auctoris." Ulp. D. 50. 17. 156, Sections 2, 3. "Qui in ius dominiumve alterius succedit, iure ejus uti debet." Paulus, D. 50. 17. 177. "Non debeo melioris condieionis esse, quam auctor meus, a quo ius in me transit." Paulus, D. 50. 17. 175, Section 1. "Quod ipsis qui contraxerunt obstat, et successoribus eoturn obstabit." Ulp. D. 50. 17. 143. "Nemo plus iuris ad alium transferre potest, quam ipse haberet." Ulp. D. 50. 17. 54; Bract., fol. 31 b. Cf. Decret. Greg. Lib. II. Tit. XIII. c. 18, De rest. spoliat.: "Cum spoliatori quasi succedat in vitium." Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, p. 179. Windscheid, Pand., Section 162 a, n. 10.

366/2 "If someone takes the place of another, it's not fair for them to be harmed by something that did not harm the person they are replacing. Generally, the buyer should have the same rights in seeking and defending as the original seller had." Ulp. D. 50. 17. 156, Sections 2, 3. "Anyone who succeeds to the rights or ownership of another must use those rights as the original person would." Paulus, D. 50. 17. 177. "I should not be in a better position than my predecessor, from whom the right passes to me." Paulus, D. 50. 17. 175, Section 1. "What stands against those who entered into a contract will also stand against their successors." Ulp. D. 50. 17. 143. "No one can transfer more rights to another than they themselves possess." Ulp. D. 50. 17. 54; Bract., fol. 31 b. Cf. Decret. Greg. Lib. II. Tit. XIII. c. 18, De rest. spoliat.: "As if the one who took is succeeding in the wrongdoing." Bruns, R. d. Besitzes, p. 179. Windscheid, Pand., Section 162 a, n. 10.

366/3 "Ne vitiosae quidam possessioni ulla potest accedere: sed nec vitiosa ei, quse vitiosa non est." D. 41. 2. 13, Section 13.

366/3 "No flawed possession can be added to it: nor can it be faulty, which is not flawed." D. 41. 2. 13, Section 13.

367 (return)

367 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

367/1 Hill v. Ellard, 3 Salk. 279. Cf. Withers v. Iseham, Dyer, 70 a, 70 b, 71 a; Gateward's Case, 6 Co. Rep. 59b, 60b; Y.B. 20 & 21 Ed. I 426; 205; 12 Hen. IV. 7.

367/1 Hill v. Ellard, 3 Salk. 279. Cf. Withers v. Iseham, Dyer, 70 a, 70 b, 71 a; Gateward's Case, 6 Co. Rep. 59b, 60b; Y.B. 20 & 21 Ed. I 426; 205; 12 Hen. IV. 7.

368 (return)

368 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

368/1 Doe v. Barnard, 13 Q.B.945, 952, 953, per Cur., Patteson, J. Cf. Asher v. Whitlock, L.R. 1 Q.B.1, 3, 6, 7.

368/1 Doe v. Barnard, 13 Q.B.945, 952, 953, per Cur., Patteson, J. Cf. Asher v. Whitlock, L.R. 1 Q.B.1, 3, 6, 7.

368/2 See, further, Sawyer v. Kendall, 10 Cush. 241; 2 Bl. Comm. 263 et seq.; 3 Ch. Pl. 1119 (6th Am. ed.); 3 Kent, 444, 445; Angell, Limitations, ch. 31, Section 413. Of course if a right had already been acquired before the disseisin different considerations would apply. If the right claimed is one of those which are regarded as incident to land, as explained in the following Lecture, the disseisor will have it. Jenk. Cent. 12, First Cent. Case 21.

368/2 See, further, Sawyer v. Kendall, 10 Cush. 241; 2 Bl. Comm. 263 et seq.; 3 Ch. Pl. 1119 (6th Am. ed.); 3 Kent, 444, 445; Angell, Limitations, ch. 31, Section 413. Of course, if a right was already established before the wrongful dispossession, other factors would come into play. If the claimed right is one of those considered to be tied to the land, as explained in the following Lecture, the person who wrongfully took possession will hold it. Jenk. Cent. 12, First Cent. Case 21.

370 (return)

370 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

370/1 Ared v. Watkin, Cro. Eliz. 637; S.C., ib. 651. Cf. Y.B. 5 Hen. VII. 18, pl. 12; Dyer, 4 b, n. (4).

370/1 Ared v. Watkin, Cro. Eliz. 637; S.C., ib. 651. Cf. Y.B. 5 Hen. VII. 18, pl. 12; Dyer, 4 b, n. (4).

370/2 Roe v. Hayley, 12 East, 464, 470 (1810).

370/2 Roe v. Hayley, 12 East, 464, 470 (1810).

371 (return)

371 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

371/1 Boyer v. Rivet, 3 Bulstr. 317, 321.

371/1 Boyer v. Rivet, 3 Bulstr. 317, 321.

372 (return)

372 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

372/1 Essays in A. S. Law, 219.

372/1 Essays in A. S. Law, 219.

372/2 "Per medium," Bracton, fol. 37b, Section10 ad fin.

372/2 "Per medium," Bracton, fol. 37b, Section 10 ad fin.

374 (return)

374 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

374/1 Bract., fol. 17 b. Cf. Fleta, III. c. 14, Section 6.

374/1 Bract., fol. 17 b. Cf. Fleta, III. c. 14, Section 6.

374/2 See, further, Middlemore v. Goodale, Cro. Car. 503, stated infra, p. 379.

374/2 See, further, Middlemore v. Goodale, Cro. Car. 503, mentioned below, p. 379.

374/3 See also Bract., fol. 380 b, 381. "Et quod de haeredibus dicitur, idem dici poterit de assignatis .... Et quod assignatis fieri debet warrantia per modum donationis: probatur in itinere W. de Ralegh in Com. Warr. circa finem rotuli, et hoc maxime, si primus dominus capitalis, et primus feoffator, ceperit homagium et servitium assignati." Cf. Fleta, VI. Section 6; Moore, 93, pl. 230; Sheph. Touchst. 199, 200. As to the reason which led to the mention of assigns, cf. Bract., fol. 20 b, Section 1; 1 Britt. (Nich.), 223, 312.

374/3 See also Bract., fol. 380 b, 381. "And what is said about heirs can also be said about assignees.... And what must be done for assignees is to provide a warranty by way of a donation: this is proven in the case of W. de Ralegh in Com. Warr. near the end of the roll, especially if the original owner and the initial feoffor have accepted the homage and service of the assignee." Cf. Fleta, VI. Section 6; Moore, 93, pl. 230; Sheph. Touchst. 199, 200. As for the reason that led to the mention of assignees, see Bract., fol. 20 b, Section 1; 1 Britt. (Nich.), 223, 312.

375 (return)

375 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

375/1 I do not stop to inquire whether this was due to the statute of Quia Emptores, by which the assign was made to hold directly of the first grantor, or whether some other explanation must be found. Cf. Bract., fol. 37 b; c. 14, Sections 6, 11; VI. c. 28, Section 4; 1 Britton (Nich.), 256, [100 b].

375/1 I don’t pause to ask if this was because of the statute of Quia Emptores, which required the assignee to hold directly from the original grantor, or if there’s another explanation. Cf. Bract., fol. 37 b; c. 14, Sections 6, 11; VI. c. 28, Section 4; 1 Britton (Nich.), 256, [100 b].

375/2 Fleta, III. c. 14, Section 6, fol. 197; 1 Britton (Nich.), 223, 233, 244, 255, 312; Co. Lit. 384 b; Y.B. 20 Ed. I. 232; Abbr. Placit., fol. 308, 2d col., Dunelm, rot. 43; Y.B. 14 Hen. IV. 5, 6.

375/2 Fleta, III. c. 14, Section 6, fol. 197; 1 Britton (Nich.), 223, 233, 244, 255, 312; Co. Lit. 384 b; Y.B. 20 Ed. I. 232; Abbr. Placit., fol. 308, 2d col., Dunelm, rot. 43; Y.B. 14 Hen. IV. 5, 6.

377 (return)

377 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

377/1 Fol. 67 a; cf. 54 a.

377/1 Fol. 67 a; cf. 54 a.

377/2 Fol. 381; supra, p. 874, n. 3.

377/2 Fol. 381; see above, p. 874, n. 3.

378 (return)

378 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

378/1 Cf. Pincombe v. Rudge, Hobart, 3; Bro. Warrantia Carte, pl. 8; S.C., Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 14, pl. 5.

378/1 Cf. Pincombe v. Rudge, Hobart, 3; Bro. Warrantia Carte, pl. 8; S.C., Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 14, pl. 5.

378/2 Y.B. 50 Ed. III. 12b & 13.

378/2 Y.B. 50 Ed. III. 12b & 13.

378/3 Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 3, pl. 14, per Belknap, arguendo.

378/3 Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 3, pl. 14, by Belknap, in argument.

378/4 Noke v. Awder, Cro. Eliz. 373; S.C., ib. 436. Cf. Lewis v. Campbell, 8 Taunt. 715; S.C., 3 J. B. Moore, 35.

378/4 Noke v. Awder, Cro. Eliz. 373; S.C., ib. 436. Cf. Lewis v. Campbell, 8 Taunt. 715; S.C., 3 J. B. Moore, 35.

379 (return)

379 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

379/1 Middlemore v. Goodale, Cro. Car. 503; S.C., ib. 505, Sir William Jones, 406.

379/1 Middlemore v. Goodale, Cro. Car. 503; S.C., ib. 505, Sir William Jones, 406.

379/2 Harper v. Bird, T. Jones, 102 (Pasch. 30 Car. II.). These cases show an order of development parallel to the history of the assignment of other contracts not negotiable.

379/2 Harper v. Bird, T. Jones, 102 (Pasch. 30 Car. II.). These cases demonstrate a progression that aligns with the historical development of the assignment of other non-negotiable contracts.

380 (return)

380 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

380/1 Andrew v. Pearce, 4 Bos. & Pul. 158 (1805).

380/1 Andrew v. Pearce, 4 Bos. & Pul. 158 (1805).

383 (return)

383 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

383/1 Austin, Jurisprudence, II. p. 842 (3d ed.).

383/1 Austin, Jurisprudence, II. p. 842 (3d ed.).

383/2 "Quoniam non personae, sed praedia deberent, neque adquiri libertas neque remitti servitus per partem poterit." D. 8. 3. 34, pr.

383/2 "Because it should be the property, not the people, that are obligated, neither freedom can be acquired nor servitude can be released in part." D. 8. 3. 34, pr.

383/3 "Qui fundum alienum bona fide emit, itinere quod ei fundo debetur usus est: retinetur id ius itineris: atque etiam, si precario aut vi deiecto domino possidet: fundus enim qualiter se habens ita, cum in suo habitu possessus est, ius non deperit, neque refert, iuste nec ne possideat qui talem eum possidet." D. 8. 6. 12.

383/3 "Who purchases another person's land in good faith and uses the path that is owed to that land retains the right to that path. Even if they possess it precariously or against the will of the rightful owner: the land, no matter its condition, maintains its rights as long as it is possessed in its original state. It doesn't matter whether the person possessing it does so lawfully or unlawfully." D. 8. 6. 12.

383/4 Elzevir ed., n. 51, ad loc. cit.; Cicero de L. Agr. 3. 2. 9.

383/4 Elzevir ed., n. 51, ad loc. cit.; Cicero de L. Agr. 3. 2. 9.

383/5 D. 50. 16, 86. Cf. Ulpian, D. 41. 1. 20, Section 1; D. 8. 3. 23, Section 2.

383/5 D. 50. 16, 86. See Ulpian, D. 41. 1. 20, Section 1; D. 8. 3. 23, Section 2.

383/6 Inst. 2. 3, Section 1.

383/6 Inst. 2. 3, Section 1.

384 (return)

384 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

384/1 D. 8. 1. 14, pr. Cf. Elzevir ed., n. 58, "Et sic jura . . . accessiones ease possunt corporum."

384/1 D. 8. 1. 14, pr. Cf. Elzevir ed., n. 58, "And thus the laws . . . accessories can rest on bodies."

384/2 "Cum fundus fundo servit." D. 8. 4. 12. Cf. D. 8. 5. 20, Section 1; D. 41. 1. 2O, Section 1.

384/2 "When land serves land." D. 8. 4. 12. See also D. 8. 5. 20, Section 1; D. 41. 1. 20, Section 1.

384/3 Jurisprudence, II. p. 847 (3d ed.).

384/3 Jurisprudence, II. p. 847 (3rd ed.).

384/4 Cf. Windscheid, Pand., Section 57, n. 10 (4th ed.), p. 150.

384/4 Cf. Windscheid, Pand., Section 57, n. 10 (4th ed.), p. 150.

385 (return)

385 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

385/1 Fol. 10b, Section 3.

385/1 Fol. 10b, Sec. 3.

385/2 Fol. 220b, Section 1.

385/2 Fol. 220b, Sec. 1.

386 (return)

386 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

386/1 Fol. 221.

386/1 Fol. 221.

386/2 Fol. 219a, b.

386/2 Fol. 219a, b.

386/3 Fol. 102a, b.

386/3 Fol. 102a, b.

386/4 Fol. 226 b, Section 13. All these passages assume that a right has been acquired and inheres in the land.

386/4 Fol. 226 b, Section 13. All these passages assume that a right has been obtained and is attached to the land.

387 (return)

387 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

387/1 Fol. 53 a; cf. 59 b, ad fin., 242 b.

387/1 Fol. 53 a; cf. 59 b, at the end, 242 b.

387/2 "Nihil praescribitur nisi quod possidetur," cited from Hale de Jur. Maris, p. 32, in Blundell v. Catterall, 5 B. & Ald. 268, 277.

387/2 "Nothing is prescribed except what is possessed," cited from Hale de Jur. Maris, p. 32, in Blundell v. Catterall, 5 B. & Ald. 268, 277.

388 (return)

388 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

388/1 Bract., fol. 46b; cf. 17b, 18, 47 b, 48.

388/1 Bract., fol. 46b; cf. 17b, 18, 47 b, 48.

388/2 Fol. 81, 81 b, 79 b, 80 b.

388/2 Fol. 81, 81 b, 79 b, 80 b.

388/3 Fol. 24 b, 26, 35 b, 86, 208 b, &c. Cf. F. N. B. 123, E; Laveleye, Propriete, 67, 68, 116.

388/3 Fol. 24 b, 26, 35 b, 86, 208 b, &c. Cf. F. N. B. 123, E; Laveleye, Propriete, 67, 68, 116.

388/4 Abbr. Plac. 110; rot. 22, Devon. (Hen. III.}.

388/4 Abbr. Plac. 110; rot. 22, Devon. (Hen. III.}.

388/5 Stockwell v. Hunter, 11 Met. (Mass.) 448.

388/5 Stockwell v. Hunter, 11 Met. (Mass.) 448.

389 (return)

389 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

389/1 Keilway, 130 b, pl. 104.

389/1 Keilway, 130 b, pl. 104.

389/2 Keilway, 113 a, pl. 45; Dyer, 2b.

389/2 Keilway, 113 a, pl. 45; Dyer, 2b.

389/3 Keilway, 113a, pl. 45. Cf. Y.B. 33-35 Ed. I. 70; 45 Ed. III. 11, 12.

389/3 Keilway, 113a, pl. 45. See also Y.B. 33-35 Ed. I. 70; 45 Ed. III. 11, 12.

389/4 Litt. Section 589.

389/4 Litt. Section 589.

389/5 Keilway, 2 a, pl. 2 ad fin. (12 Hen. VII.). But cf. Y.B. 6 Hen. VII. 14, pl. 2 ad fin.

389/5 Keilway, 2 a, pl. 2 at the end (12 Hen. VII.). But see Y.B. 6 Hen. VII. 14, pl. 2 at the end.

389/6 4 Laferriere, Hist. du Droit. Franc. 442; Bracton, fol. 53a.

389/6 4 Laferriere, Hist. du Droit. Franc. 442; Bracton, fol. 53a.

390 (return)

390 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

390/1 Cf. Co. Lit. 322 b, et seq.; Y.B. 6 Hen. VII. 14, pl. 2 ad fin.

390/1 Cf. Co. Lit. 322 b, et seq.; Y.B. 6 Hen. VII. 14, pl. 2 ad fin.

390/2 Daintry v. Brocklehurst, 3 Exch. 207.

390/2 Daintry v. Brocklehurst, 3 Exch. 207.

390/3 Y.B. 5 Hen. VII. 18, pl. 12.

390/3 Y.B. 5 Hen. VII. 18, pl. 12.

391 (return)

391 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

391/1 Y.B. 9 Hen. VI. 16, pl. 7.

391/1 Y.B. 9 Hen. VI. 16, pl. 7.

391/2 Y.B. 14 Hen. VI. 26, pl. 77.

391/2 Y.B. 14 Hen. VI. 26, pl. 77.

391/3 Y.B. 5 Hen. VII. 18, pl. 12.

391/3 Y.B. 5 Hen. VII. 18, pl. 12.

391/4 Cf. Theloall, Dig. I. c. 21, pl. 9.

391/4 Cf. Theloall, Dig. I. c. 21, pl. 9.

391/5 Buskin v. Edmunds, Cro. Eliz. 636.

391/5 Buskin v. Edmunds, Cro. Eliz. 636.

391/6 Harper v. Bird, T. Jones, 102 (30 Car. II.).

391/6 Harper v. Bird, T. Jones, 102 (30 Car. II.).

391/7 Bolles v. Nyseham, Dyer, 254 b; Porter v. Swetnam, Style, 406; S.C., ib. 431.

391/7 Bolles v. Nyseham, Dyer, 254 b; Porter v. Swetnam, Style, 406; S.C., ib. 431.

391/8 3 Bl. Comm. 231, 232.

391/8 3 Bl. Comm. 231, 232.

392 (return)

392 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

392/1 Yielding v. Fay, Cro. Eliz. 569.

392/1 Yielding v. Fay, Cro. Eliz. 569.

392/2 Pakenham's Case, Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 3, pl. 14; Prior of Woburn's Case, 22 Hen. VI. 46, pl. 36; Williams's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 72 b, 73 a; Slipper v. Mason, Nelson's Lutwyche, 43, 45 (top).

392/2 Pakenham's Case, Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 3, pl. 14; Prior of Woburn's Case, 22 Hen. VI. 46, pl. 36; Williams's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 72 b, 73 a; Slipper v. Mason, Nelson's Lutwyche, 43, 45 (top).

392/3 F. N. B. 127; Nowel v. Smith, Cro. Eliz. 709; Star v. Rookesby, 1 Salk. 335, 336; Lawrence v. Jenkins, L.R. 8 Q.B.274.

392/3 F. N. B. 127; Nowel v. Smith, Cro. Eliz. 709; Star v. Rookesby, 1 Salk. 335, 336; Lawrence v. Jenkins, L.R. 8 Q.B.274.

392/4 Dyer, 24 a, pl. 149; F. N. B. 180 N.

392/4 Dyer, 24 a, pl. 149; F. N. B. 180 N.

393 (return)

393 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

393/1 F. N. B. 128 D, E; Co. Lit. 96 b. It is assumed that, when an obligation is spoken of as falling upon the land, it is understood to be only a figure of speech. Of course rights and obligations are confined to human beings.

393/1 F. N. B. 128 D, E; Co. Lit. 96 b. It is assumed that, when people talk about an obligation applying to the land, it's just a way of speaking. Clearly, rights and obligations belong only to human beings.

393/2 Keilway, 145 b, 146, pl. 15; Sir Henry Nevil's Case, Plowd. 377, 381; Chudleigh's Case, 1 Co. Rep. 119 b, 122 b.

393/2 Keilway, 145 b, 146, pl. 15; Sir Henry Nevil's Case, Plowd. 377, 381; Chudleigh's Case, 1 Co. Rep. 119 b, 122 b.

393/3 F. N. B. 180 N.; Co. Lit. 385 a; Spencer's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 16 a, 17 b; Pakenham's Case, Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 3, pl. 14; Keilway, 145 b, 146, pl. 15; Comyns's Digest, Covenant (B, 3).

393/3 F. N. B. 180 N.; Co. Lit. 385 a; Spencer's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 16 a, 17 b; Pakenham's Case, Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 3, pl. 14; Keilway, 145 b, 146, pl. 15; Comyns's Digest, Covenant (B, 3).

394 (return)

394 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

394/1 Holms v. Seller, 3 Lev. 305; Rowbotham v. Wilson, 8 H. L. C. 348; Bronson v. Coffin, 108 Mass. 175, 180. Cf. Bro. Covenant, pl. 2.

394/1 Holms v. Seller, 3 Lev. 305; Rowbotham v. Wilson, 8 H. L. C. 348; Bronson v. Coffin, 108 Mass. 175, 180. Cf. Bro. Covenant, pl. 2.

394/2 Y.B. 21 Ed. III. 2, pl. 5; F. N. B. 180 N.

394/2 Y.B. 21 Ed. III. 2, pl. 5; F. N. B. 180 N.

394/3 The action is case in the Prior of Woburn's Case, Y.B. 22 Hen. VI. 46, pl. 36. In F. N. B. 128 E, n. (a), it is said that a curia claudenda only lay upon a prescriptive right, and that if the duty to fence was by indenture the plaintiff was put to his writ of covenant. But see below, pp. 396, 400.

394/3 The action is based on the Prior of Woburn's Case, Y.B. 22 Hen. VI. 46, pl. 36. In F. N. B. 128 E, n. (a), it is stated that a curia claudenda only applies to a prescriptive right, and that if the obligation to fence was defined by an agreement, the plaintiff had to rely on his writ of covenant. But see below, pp. 396, 400.

394/4 Y.B. 32 & 33 Ed. I. 430.

394/4 Y.B. 32 & 33 Ed. I. 430.

395 (return)

395 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

395/1 Y.B. 20 Ed. I. 360.

395/1 Y.B. 20 Ed. I. 360.

395/2 Y.B. 32 & 33 Ed. I. 516.

395/2 Y.B. 32 & 33 Ed. I. 516.

395/3 "Quia res cum homine [obviously a misprint for onere] transit ad quemcunque." Fol. 382, 382 b.

395/3 "Because the thing passes with the person to anyone." Fol. 382, 382 b.

395/4 Lib. VI. c. 23, Section 17.

395/4 Lib. VI. c. 23, Section 17.

395/5 Pakenham's Case, Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 3, pl. 14.

395/5 Pakenham's Case, Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 3, pl. 14.

395/6 Sugd. V. & P. (14th ed.), 587; Rawle, Covenants for Title (4th ed.), p. 314. Cf. Vyvyan v. Arthur, 1 B. & C. 410; Sharp v. Waterhouse, 7 El. & Bl. 816, 823.

395/6 Sugd. V. & P. (14th ed.), 587; Rawle, Covenants for Title (4th ed.), p. 314. Cf. Vyvyan v. Arthur, 1 B. & C. 410; Sharp v. Waterhouse, 7 El. & Bl. 816, 823.

396 (return)

396 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

396/1 Co. Lit. 385 a.

396/1 Co. Lit. 385 a.

396/2 Cf. Finchden as to rent in Y. B, 45 Ed. III. 11, 12.

396/2 Cf. Finchden regarding rent in Y. B, 45 Ed. III. 11, 12.

396/3 Cf. Y.B. 50 Ed. III. 12, 13, pl. 2.

396/3 Cf. Y.B. 50 Ed. III. 12, 13, pl. 2.

397 (return)

397 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

397/1 Covenant, pl. 17.

397/1 Agreement, pl. 17.

397/2 There is a colon here in both editions of the Year Books, marking the beginning of a new argument.

397/2 There is a colon here in both editions of the Year Books, indicating the start of a new argument.

397/3 Pakenham's Case, Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 3, pl. 14.

397/3 Pakenham's Case, Y.B. 42 Ed. III. 3, pl. 14.

398 (return)

398 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

398/1 Bro. Covenant, pl. 5. Cf. Spencer's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 16 a, 17 b, 18 a.

398/1 Bro. Covenant, pl. 5. Cf. Spencer's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 16 a, 17 b, 18 a.

398/2 Horne's Case, Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 6, pl. 25.

398/2 Horne's Case, Y.B. 2 Hen. IV. 6, pl. 25.

399 (return)

399 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

399/1 "Quod conceditur." Cf. Spencer's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 16 a, 18 a.

399/1 "What is granted." See Spencer's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 16 a, 18 a.

399/2 It was quite possible that two liabilities should exist side by side. Bro. Covenant, pl. 32; Brett v. Cumberland, Cro. Jac. 521, 523.

399/2 It was entirely possible for two liabilities to exist simultaneously. Bro. Covenant, pl. 32; Brett v. Cumberland, Cro. Jac. 521, 523.

399/3 1 Co. Rep. 122 b; S.C., sub nom. Dillon v. Fraine, Popham, 70, 71.

399/3 1 Co. Rep. 122 b; S.C., sub nom. Dillon v. Fraine, Popham, 70, 71.

400 (return)

400 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

400/1 Essays in Ang. Sax. Law, 248.

400/1 Essays in Anglo-Saxon Law, 248.

400/2 Y.B. 22 Ed. I. 494, 496.

400/2 Y.B. 22 Ed. I. 494, 496.

400/3 Y.B. 4 Ed. III. 57, pl. 71; S.C., 7 Ed. III. 65, pl. 67.

400/3 Y.B. 4 Ed. III. 57, pl. 71; S.C., 7 Ed. III. 65, pl. 67.

401 (return)

401 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

401/1 Bract., fol. 17 b, 37 b; Fleta, III. c. 14, Section 6; 1 Britton (Nich.), 223, 233, 244, 255, 312; Abbrev. Plac. p. 308, col 2, Dunelm, rot. 43 (33 I.); Y. B, 20 Ed. I. 232; Co. Lit. 384 b.

401/1 Bract., fol. 17 b, 37 b; Fleta, III. c. 14, Section 6; 1 Britton (Nich.), 223, 233, 244, 255, 312; Abbrev. Plac. p. 308, col 2, Dunelm, rot. 43 (33 I.); Y. B, 20 Ed. I. 232; Co. Lit. 384 b.

401/2 Hyde v. Dean of Windsor, Cro. Eliz. 552.

401/2 Hyde v. Dean of Windsor, Cro. Eliz. 552.

401/3 Spencer's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 16 a. Cf. Minshill v. Oakes, 2 H. & N. 793, 807.

401/3 Spencer's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 16 a. Cf. Minshill v. Oakes, 2 H. & N. 793, 807.

402 (return)

402 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

402/1 Hyde v. Dean of Windsor, Cro. Eliz. 552, 553; S.C., ib. 457. Cf. Bally v. Wells, 3 Wilson, 25, 29.

402/1 Hyde v. Dean of Windsor, Cro. Eliz. 552, 553; S.C., ib. 457. Cf. Bally v. Wells, 3 Wilson, 25, 29.

402/2 Dean of Windsor's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 24 a; S.C., Moore, 399. Cf. Bro. Covenant, pl. 32. Cf. further, Conan v. Kemise, W. Jones, 245 (7 Car. I.).

402/2 Dean of Windsor's Case, 5 Co. Rep. 24 a; S.C., Moore, 399. Cf. Bro. Covenant, pl. 32. Cf. further, Conan v. Kemise, W. Jones, 245 (7 Car. I.).

403 (return)

403 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

403/1 F. N. B. 181 N; Sir Henry Nevil's Case, Plowden, 377, 381.

403/1 F. N. B. 181 N; Sir Henry Nevil's Case, Plowden, 377, 381.

403/2 Ewre v. Strickland, Cro. Jac. 240. Cf. Brett v. Cumberland, 1 Roll R. 359, 360 "al comen ley"; S.C., Cro. Jac. 399, 521.

403/2 Ewre v. Strickland, Cro. Jac. 240. Cf. Brett v. Cumberland, 1 Roll R. 359, 360 "al comen ley"; S.C., Cro. Jac. 399, 521.

403/3 Cockson v. Cock, Cro. Jac. 125.

403/3 Cockson v. Cock, Cro. Jac. 125.

403/4 Sale v. Kitchingham, 10 Hod. 158 (E. 12 Anne).

403/4 Sale v. Kitchingham, 10 Hod. 158 (E. 12 Anne).

403/5 Supra, pp. 396, 398, 400. Cf., however, Lord Wensleydale, in Rowbotham v. Wilson, 8 H. L. C. 348, 362, and see above, p. 391, as to rents.

403/5 Supra, pp. 396, 398, 400. Compare, however, Lord Wensleydale, in Rowbotham v. Wilson, 8 H. L. C. 348, 362, and see above, p. 391, regarding rents.

404 (return)

404 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

404/1 4 Kent (12th ed.), 480, n. 1.

404/1 4 Kent (12th ed.), 480, n. 1.

404/2 It is used in a somewhat different sense is describing the relation between a tenant for life or years and a reversioner. Privity between them follows as an accidental consequence of their being as one tenant, and sustaining a single persona between them.

404/2 It is used in a somewhat different sense when describing the relationship between a life tenant or a tenant for years and a reversioner. The privity between them arises as an unintended result of their being regarded as one tenant and sharing a single persona.

406 (return)

406 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

406/1 Rowbotham v. Wilson, 8 H. L. C. 348, 362 (Lord Wensleydale).

406/1 Rowbotham v. Wilson, 8 H. L. C. 348, 362 (Lord Wensleydale).

406/2 Harbidge v. Warwick, 3 Exch. 552, 556.

406/2 Harbidge v. Warwick, 3 Exch. 552, 556.

406/3 Rowbotham v. Wilson, 8 El. & Bl. 123, 143, 144.

406/3 Rowbotham v. Wilson, 8 El. & Bl. 123, 143, 144.

404/4 5 Co. Rep. 16, a.

404/4 5 Co. Rep. 16, a.

407 (return)

407 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

407/1 Y.B. 8 Ed. IV. 5, 6, pl. 1; 22 Ed. IV. 6, pl. 18. Cf. 5 Ed. IV. 7, pl. 16.

407/1 Y.B. 8 Ed. IV. 5, 6, pl. 1; 22 Ed. IV. 6, pl. 18. Cf. 5 Ed. IV. 7, pl. 16.

407/2 Cf. Keilway, 42 b, 46 b; 2 Bl. Comm. 329.

407/2 Cf. Keilway, 42 b, 46 b; 2 Bl. Comm. 329.

408 (return)

408 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

408/1 Y.B. 14 Hen. VIII. 6, pl. 5. Cf. Chudleigh's Case, 1 Co. Rep. 120a, 122 b; S.C., nom. Dillon v. Fraine, Popham, 70-72.

408/1 Y.B. 14 Hen. VIII. 6, pl. 5. Cf. Chudleigh's Case, 1 Co. Rep. 120a, 122 b; S.C., nom. Dillon v. Fraine, Popham, 70-72.

408/2 Lewin, Trusts, Ch. I. (7th ed.), pp. 16, 15.

408/2 Lewin, Trusts, Ch. I. (7th ed.), pp. 16, 15.

408/3 4 Inst. 85; Gilb. Uses (Sugd.), 429, n. (6); Lewin, Trusts (7th ed.), pp. 15, 228.

408/3 4 Inst. 85; Gilb. Uses (Sugd.), 429, n. (6); Lewin, Trusts (7th ed.), pp. 15, 228.

408/4 Burgess v. Wheate, 1 Eden, 177, 203, 246.

408/4 Burgess v. Wheate, 1 Eden, 177, 203, 246.

408/5 Lewin, Trusts, Introd. (7th ed.), p. 3.

408/5 Lewin, Trusts, Introd. (7th ed.), p. 3.

408/6 1 Rich. III. c. 1. Cf. Rex v. Holland, Aleyn, 14, Maynard's arg.; Bro. Feoffements al Uses, pl. 44; Gilb. Uses, 26* (Sugd. ed., 50).

408/6 1 Rich. III. c. 1. Cf. Rex v. Holland, Aleyn, 14, Maynard's arg.; Bro. Feoffements al Uses, pl. 44; Gilb. Uses, 26* (Sugd. ed., 50).

409 (return)

409 (__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__)

409/1 4th Inst. 85; S.C., Dyer, 869, pl. 50; Jenk. Cent. 6, c. 30. Cf. Gilb. Uses, 198* (Sugd. ed. 399).

409/1 4th Inst. 85; S.C., Dyer, 869, pl. 50; Jenk. Cent. 6, c. 30. Cf. Gilb. Uses, 198* (Sugd. ed. 399).

409/2 Gilb. Uses, 35* (Sugd. ed. 70).

409/2 Gilb. Uses, 35* (Sugd. ed. 70).

409/3 Theloall's Dig., I. 16, pl. 1.

409/3 Theloall's Dig., I. 16, pl. 1.








Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!