This is a modern-English version of Moral Principles in Education, originally written by Dewey, John. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.

Riverside Educational Monographs

Riverside Educator Guides

EDITED BY HENRY SUZZALLO
SOMETIME PROFESSOR OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION TEACHERS COLLEGE, COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY, AND PRESIDENT OF THE UNIVERSITY OF WASHINGTON

EDITED BY HENRY SUZZALLO
FORMER PROFESSOR OF EDUCATION PHILOSOPHY TEACHERS COLLEGE, COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY, AND PRESIDENT OF THE UNIVERSITY OF WASHINGTON

MORAL PRINCIPLES IN EDUCATION

BY

BY

JOHN DEWEY
PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY

JOHN DEWEY
PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY AT COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY

Pub Device

Pub Device

HOUGHTON MIFFLIN COMPANY

HOUGHTON MIFFLIN COMPANY

BOSTON · NEW YORK · CHICAGO · DALLAS
SAN FRANCISCO

BOSTON · NEW YORK · CHICAGO · DALLAS
SAN FRANCISCO

The Riverside Press Cambridge

The Riverside Press, Cambridge

 

INTRODUCTION

Education as a public business

It is one of the complaints of the schoolmaster that the public does not defer to his professional opinion as completely as it does to that of practitioners in other professions. At first sight it might seem as though this indicated a defect either in the public or in the profession; and yet a wider view of the situation would suggest that such a conclusion is not a necessary one. The relations of education to the public are different from those of any other professional work. Education is a public business with us, in a sense that the protection and restoration of personal health or legal rights are not. To an extent characteristic of no other institution, save that of the state itself, the school has power to modify the social order. And under our political system, it is the right of each individual to have a voice in the making of social policies as, indeed, he has a vote in the determination of political affairs. If this  be true, education is primarily a public business, and only secondarily a specialized vocation. The layman, then, will always have his right to some utterance on the operation of the public schools.

It is one of the issues that schoolteachers face that the public does not respect their professional opinion as much as it does for those in other professions. At first glance, it might seem like this points to a flaw either in the public or in the teaching profession; however, a broader look at the situation suggests that this conclusion isn’t necessarily true. The relationship between education and the public is different from that of any other professional field. Education is a public matter for us, in a way that the protection and restoration of personal health or legal rights aren’t. To an extent unique to no other institution, except for the state itself, the school has the power to change the social order. And within our political system, it is each person's right to have a say in the creation of social policies just like he has a vote in political matters. If this   is true, then education is fundamentally a public concern, and only secondarily a specialized profession. The public will always have the right to voice their opinions about how public schools operate.

Education as expert service

I have said “some utterance,” but not “all”; for school-mastering has its own special mysteries, its own knowledge and skill into which the untrained layman cannot penetrate. We are just beginning to recognize that the school and the government have a common problem in this respect. Education and politics are two functions fundamentally controlled by public opinion. Yet the conspicuous lack of efficiency and economy in the school and in the state has quickened our recognition of a larger need for expert service. But just where shall public opinion justly express itself, and what shall properly be left to expert judgment?

I’ve mentioned “some statements,” but not “all”; because teaching has its own unique mysteries, and its own knowledge and skills that the untrained person can’t grasp. We’re just starting to realize that schools and the government share a common issue in this sense. Education and politics are two functions that are fundamentally influenced by public opinion. Still, the clear lack of efficiency and effectiveness in both the school system and the state has highlighted our need for expert help. But where should public opinion be fairly represented, and what should be left to expert judgment?

The relations of expert opinion and public opinion

In so far as broad policies and ultimate ends affecting the welfare of all are to be determined,  the public may well claim its right to settle issues by the vote or voice of majorities. But the selection and prosecution of the detailed ways and means by which the public will is to be executed efficiently must remain largely a matter of specialized and expert service. To the superior knowledge and technique required here, the public may well defer.

In terms of broad policies and ultimate goals that impact everyone's well-being, the public certainly has the right to decide issues through majority voting or opinion. However, choosing and implementing the specific methods and strategies for effectively carrying out the public's will should mostly be handled by specialists and experts. The public may understandably rely on their superior knowledge and skills in this area.

In the conduct of the schools, it is well for the citizens to determine the ends proper to them, and it is their privilege to judge of the efficacy of results. Upon questions that concern all the manifold details by which children are to be converted into desirable types of men and women, the expert schoolmaster should be authoritative, at least to a degree commensurate with his superior knowledge of this very complex problem. The administration of the schools, the making of the course of study, the selection of texts, the prescription of methods of teaching, these are matters with which the people, or their representatives upon boards of education, cannot deal save with danger of becoming mere meddlers.

In running the schools, it's important for the citizens to decide what goals are appropriate for them, and it's their right to evaluate how effective the outcomes are. On issues that involve all the various details needed to turn children into well-rounded adults, the school expert should have authority, at least to a level that reflects their greater knowledge of this complex issue. The management of the schools, the design of the curriculum, the choice of textbooks, and the methods of teaching are matters that the public, or their representatives on school boards, should approach cautiously to avoid being seen as intrusive.

 The discussion of moral education an illustration of mistaken views of laymen

Nowhere is the validity of this distinction between education as a public business and education as an expert professional service brought out more clearly than in an analysis of the public discussion of the moral work of the school. How frequently of late have those unacquainted with the special nature of the school proclaimed the moral ends of education and at the same time demanded direct ethical instruction as the particular method by which they were to be realized! This, too, in spite of the fact that those who know best the powers and limitations of instruction as an instrument have repeatedly pointed out the futility of assuming that knowledge of right constitutes a guarantee of right doing. How common it is for those who assert that education is for social efficiency to assume that the school should return to the barren discipline of the traditional formal subjects, reading, writing, and the rest! This, too, regardless of the fact that it has taken a century of educational evolution  to make the course of study varied and rich enough to call for those impulses and activities of social life which need training in the child. And how many who speak glowingly of the large services of the public schools to a democracy of free and self-reliant men affect a cynical and even vehement opposition to the “self-government of schools”! These would not have the children learn to govern themselves and one another, but would have the masters rule them, ignoring the fact that this common practice in childhood may be a foundation for that evil condition in adult society where the citizens are arbitrarily ruled by political bosses.

Nowhere is the validity of the distinction between education as a public enterprise and education as a specialized professional service clearer than in the examination of the public discourse on the moral role of schools. Recently, people unfamiliar with the unique nature of schools have often proclaimed the moral goals of education while simultaneously demanding direct ethical instruction as the specific method to achieve these goals! This, despite the fact that those who understand the strengths and limitations of instruction have repeatedly pointed out the futility of assuming that knowing what is right guarantees doing what is right. It's common for those who claim education is for social efficiency to believe that schools should return to the outdated discipline of traditional subjects like reading, writing, and others! This happens without acknowledging that it has taken a century of educational development   to create a curriculum rich and varied enough to foster the social impulses and activities that need nurturing in children. Moreover, many who praise the significant contributions of public schools to a democracy of independent and self-reliant individuals often display a cynical and even strong opposition to the "self-governance of schools"! They do not want children to learn how to govern themselves and one another; instead, they prefer that authority figures control them, ignoring that this common practice in childhood may lay the groundwork for the harmful situation in adult society where citizens are ruled by political leaders with unchecked power.

One need not cite further cases of the incompetence of the lay public to deal with technical questions of school methods. Instances are plentiful to show that well-meaning people, competent enough to judge of the aims and results of school work, make a mistake in insisting upon the prerogative of directing the technical aspects of education with a dogmatism that would not characterize their statements regarding any other special field of knowledge or action.

One doesn’t need to provide more examples of the public's inability to handle technical questions about school methods. There are plenty of instances showing that well-meaning individuals, who are capable of evaluating the goals and outcomes of education, often err by insisting on their right to dictate the technical details of teaching with a certainty they wouldn’t display in any other specialized area of knowledge or action.

 A fundamental understanding of moral principles in education

Nothing can be more useful than for the public and the teaching profession to understand their respective functions. The teacher needs to understand public opinion and the social order, as much as the public needs to comprehend the nature of expert educational service. It will take time to draw the boundary lines that will be conducive to respect, restraint, and efficiency in those concerned; but a beginning can be made upon fundamental matters, and nothing so touches the foundations of our educational thought as a discussion of the moral principles in education.

Nothing is more important than for the public and the teaching profession to grasp their respective roles. Teachers need to understand public opinion and social structure, just as the public needs to appreciate what expert educational services offer. It will take time to establish clear boundaries that promote respect, restraint, and efficiency among those involved, but we can start with the basics. Nothing impacts our educational beliefs more than a conversation about the moral principles in education.

It is our pleasure to present a treatment of them by a thinker whose vital influence upon the reform of school methods is greater than that of any of his contemporaries. In his discussion of the social and psychological factors in moral education, there is much that will suggest what social opinion should determine, and much that will indicate what must be left to the trained teacher and school official.

It’s our pleasure to present a discussion by a thinker whose influence on changing school methods is stronger than that of any of his peers. In his exploration of the social and psychological aspects of moral education, he offers many insights into what social opinion should influence, as well as what should be left to the trained teachers and school officials.

THE MORAL PURPOSE OF THE SCHOOL

THE MORAL PURPOSE OF THE SCHOOL

 
I
I

THE MORAL PURPOSE OF THE SCHOOL

An English contemporary philosopher has called attention to the difference between moral ideas and ideas about morality. “Moral ideas” are ideas of any sort whatsoever which take effect in conduct and improve it, make it better than it otherwise would be. Similarly, one may say, immoral ideas are ideas of whatever sort (whether arithmetical or geographical or physiological) which show themselves in making behavior worse than it would otherwise be; and non-moral ideas, one may say, are such ideas and pieces of information as leave conduct uninfluenced for either the better or the worse. Now “ideas about morality” may be morally indifferent or immoral or moral. There is nothing in the nature of ideas about morality, of information about honesty or purity or kindness which automatically transmutes such ideas into good character or good conduct.

A contemporary English philosopher has pointed out the difference between moral ideas and ideas about morality. “Moral ideas” refer to any concepts that influence behavior positively, making it better than it would be otherwise. Likewise, immoral ideas are any concepts (whether they involve numbers, geography, or biology) that lead to behavior being worse than it might otherwise be; and non-moral ideas are those that do not affect behavior at all, neither for better nor worse. Now, “ideas about morality” can be morally neutral, immoral, or moral. There is nothing inherent in ideas about morality, or in information about honesty, purity, or kindness, that automatically transforms such ideas into good character or good behavior.

 This distinction between moral ideas, ideas of any sort whatsoever that have become a part of character and hence a part of the working motives of behavior, and ideas about moral action that may remain as inert and ineffective as if they were so much knowledge about Egyptian archæology, is fundamental to the discussion of moral education. The business of the educator—whether parent or teacher—is to see to it that the greatest possible number of ideas acquired by children and youth are acquired in such a vital way that they become moving ideas, motive-forces in the guidance of conduct. This demand and this opportunity make the moral purpose universal and dominant in all instruction—whatsoever the topic. Were it not for this possibility, the familiar statement that the ultimate purpose of all education is character-forming would be hypocritical pretense; for as every one knows, the direct and immediate attention of teachers and pupils must be, for the greater part of the time, upon intellectual matters. It is out of the question to keep direct moral considerations constantly uppermost. But it is not  out of the question to aim at making the methods of learning, of acquiring intellectual power, and of assimilating subject-matter, such that they will render behavior more enlightened, more consistent, more vigorous than it otherwise would be.

 This distinction between moral ideas, which are ideas that have become part of a person's character and thus influence their behavior, and ideas about moral action that may remain as inactive and ineffective as knowledge about Egyptian archaeology, is essential to the discussion of moral education. The role of the educator—whether a parent or a teacher—is to ensure that as many ideas as possible that children and young people acquire are learned in such a meaningful way that they become driving ideas and motivation for guiding their actions. This requirement and opportunity make the moral purpose universal and central in all teaching—regardless of the subject. Without this potential, the common claim that the ultimate goal of all education is character development would be insincere; as everyone knows, teachers' and students' primary focus must largely be on intellectual matters most of the time. It is impractical to keep direct moral considerations at the forefront consistently. However, it is not  unreasonable to aim for methods of learning, acquiring intellectual skills, and absorbing subject matter that make behavior more informed, more consistent, and more vigorous than it would otherwise be.

The same distinction between “moral ideas” and “ideas about morality” explains for us a source of continual misunderstanding between teachers in the schools and critics of education outside of the schools. The latter look through the school programmes, the school courses of study, and do not find any place set apart for instruction in ethics or for “moral teaching.” Then they assert that the schools are doing nothing, or next to nothing, for character-training; they become emphatic, even vehement, about the moral deficiencies of public education. The schoolteachers, on the other hand, resent these criticisms as an injustice, and hold not only that they do “teach morals,” but that they teach them every moment of the day, five days in the week. In this contention the teachers in principle are in the right; if they are in the wrong, it is not because special periods are not set aside for what  after all can only be teaching about morals, but because their own characters, or their school atmosphere and ideals, or their methods of teaching, or the subject-matter which they teach, are not such in detail as to bring intellectual results into vital union with character so that they become working forces in behavior. Without discussing, therefore, the limits or the value of so-called direct moral instruction (or, better, instruction about morals), it may be laid down as fundamental that the influence of direct moral instruction, even at its very best, is comparatively small in amount and slight in influence, when the whole field of moral growth through education is taken into account. This larger field of indirect and vital moral education, the development of character through all the agencies, instrumentalities, and materials of school life is, therefore, the subject of our present discussion.

The same difference between “moral ideas” and “ideas about morality” helps us understand a constant misunderstanding between teachers in schools and education critics outside of schools. The critics look through school programs and curricula but don’t see any designated time for ethics or “moral teaching.” They then claim that schools are doing very little, if anything, for character development and become quite vocal about the moral shortcomings of public education. On the flip side, teachers feel that these critiques are unfair, insisting that they do teach morals—not just in specific lessons but throughout the entire school day, five days a week. In principle, the teachers are right; if they’re wrong, it’s not because there aren’t specific times set aside for what ends up being just teaching about morals, but because their own character, the school environment and ideals, their teaching methods, or the content they cover, lack the detail necessary to connect intellectual outcomes with character in a way that influences behavior. Therefore, without going into the limits or value of what’s often called direct moral instruction (or, more accurately, instruction about morals), we can establish that the impact of direct moral teaching, even at its best, is relatively small and limited in influence when considering the broader scope of moral development through education. This larger domain of indirect and meaningful moral education—the growth of character through all the various elements, tools, and experiences of school life—is what we will discuss now.

THE MORAL TRAINING GIVEN BY THE SCHOOL COMMUNITY

 II
 II

THE MORAL TRAINING GIVEN BY THE SCHOOL COMMUNITY

There cannot be two sets of ethical principles, one for life in the school, and the other for life outside of the school. As conduct is one, so also the principles of conduct are one. The tendency to discuss the morals of the school as if the school were an institution by itself is highly unfortunate. The moral responsibility of the school, and of those who conduct it, is to society. The school is fundamentally an institution erected by society to do a certain specific work,—to exercise a certain specific function in maintaining the life and advancing the welfare of society. The educational system which does not recognize that this fact entails upon it an ethical responsibility is derelict and a defaulter. It is not doing what it was called into existence to do, and what it pretends to do. Hence the entire structure of the school in general and its concrete workings in particular need  to be considered from time to time with reference to the social position and function of the school.

There can't be two sets of ethical principles, one for life in school and another for life outside of it. Just as behavior is unified, so too are the principles of behavior. The tendency to discuss school morals as if the school were a separate institution is really unfortunate. The moral responsibility of the school and those who run it is to society. The school is basically an institution created by society to perform a specific role—to fulfill a certain function in sustaining life and promoting the welfare of society. An educational system that fails to acknowledge this reality and the ethical responsibility it brings is neglectful and in default. It isn't doing what it was established to do and what it claims to do. Therefore, the overall structure of the school and its specific operations need   to be reviewed periodically in relation to the school's social position and function.

The idea that the moral work and worth of the public school system as a whole are to be measured by its social value is, indeed, a familiar notion. However, it is frequently taken in too limited and rigid a way. The social work of the school is often limited to training for citizenship, and citizenship is then interpreted in a narrow sense as meaning capacity to vote intelligently, disposition to obey laws, etc. But it is futile to contract and cramp the ethical responsibility of the school in this way. The child is one, and he must either live his social life as an integral unified being, or suffer loss and create friction. To pick out one of the many social relations which the child bears, and to define the work of the school by that alone, is like instituting a vast and complicated system of physical exercise which would have for its object simply the development of the lungs and the power of breathing, independent of other organs and functions. The child is an organic whole, intellectually, socially, and morally, as well as physically. We must take  the child as a member of society in the broadest sense, and demand for and from the schools whatever is necessary to enable the child intelligently to recognize all his social relations and take his part in sustaining them.

The idea that the moral value and significance of the public school system should be measured by its social impact is a common belief. However, it's often viewed in a way that's too narrow and restrictive. The school’s role in society is usually limited to preparing students for citizenship, and citizenship is often interpreted too narrowly as just the ability to vote wisely, a willingness to follow laws, and so on. But it’s pointless to constrict the ethical responsibility of schools in this manner. A child is a single entity, and they must either live their social life as a complete, unified individual or face difficulties and create tension. Focusing on just one of the many social connections a child has and defining the school’s role by that alone is like implementing an elaborate system of physical training aimed solely at developing the lungs and breathing abilities, without considering other organs and functions. A child is a complete being—intellectually, socially, morally, and physically. We need to view the child as a part of society in the broadest sense and demand from schools what is necessary to help the child understand all their social connections and participate in maintaining them.

To isolate the formal relationship of citizenship from the whole system of relations with which it is actually interwoven; to suppose that there is some one particular study or mode of treatment which can make the child a good citizen; to suppose, in other words, that a good citizen is anything more than a thoroughly efficient and serviceable member of society, one with all his powers of body and mind under control, is a hampering superstition which it is hoped may soon disappear from educational discussion.

To separate the formal idea of citizenship from the entire system of relationships it's connected to; to believe there is a specific study or method that can turn a child into a good citizen; to think, in other words, that a good citizen is anything more than a fully capable and useful member of society, someone who has all their physical and mental abilities under control, is a limiting belief that we hope will soon fade from educational debates.

The child is to be not only a voter and a subject of law; he is also to be a member of a family, himself in turn responsible, in all probability, for rearing and training of future children, thereby maintaining the continuity of society. He is to be a worker, engaged in some occupation which will be of use to society, and which will maintain his own independence and self-respect. He is to be  a member of some particular neighborhood and community, and must contribute to the values of life, add to the decencies and graces of civilization wherever he is. These are bare and formal statements, but if we let our imagination translate them into their concrete details, we have a wide and varied scene. For the child properly to take his place in reference to these various functions means training in science, in art, in history; means command of the fundamental methods of inquiry and the fundamental tools of intercourse and communication; means a trained and sound body, skillful eye and hand; means habits of industry, perseverance; in short, habits of serviceableness.

The child is not just going to be a voter and a citizen of the law; he is also going to be part of a family, likely responsible for raising and educating future children, thus ensuring the continuity of society. He will be a worker, involved in a job that benefits society and helps him maintain his independence and self-respect. He will be a member of a specific neighborhood and community, and he must contribute to the values of life, enhancing the decencies and qualities of civilization wherever he is. These are basic and formal statements, but if we use our imagination to visualize them in real-life scenarios, we create a broad and diverse picture. For the child to properly fulfill these various roles, he needs education in science, art, and history; he must master essential methods of inquiry and the basic tools of interaction and communication; he needs a well-trained and healthy body, and skilled hands and eyes; he must develop habits of hard work and perseverance; in short, habits of being useful.

Moreover, the society of which the child is to be a member is, in the United States, a democratic and progressive society. The child must be educated for leadership as well as for obedience. He must have power of self-direction and power of directing others, power of administration, ability to assume positions of responsibility. This necessity of educating for leadership is as great on the industrial as on the political side.

Moreover, the society that the child will be a part of in the United States is a democratic and progressive one. The child needs to be educated for leadership as well as for following rules. They must have the ability to direct themselves and lead others, have administrative skills, and be capable of taking on responsibilities. The need to educate for leadership is just as important in the workplace as it is in politics.

New inventions, new machines, new methods of  transportation and intercourse are making over the whole scene of action year by year. It is an absolute impossibility to educate the child for any fixed station in life. So far as education is conducted unconsciously or consciously on this basis, it results in fitting the future citizen for no station in life, but makes him a drone, a hanger-on, or an actual retarding influence in the onward movement. Instead of caring for himself and for others, he becomes one who has himself to be cared for. Here, too, the ethical responsibility of the school on the social side must be interpreted in the broadest and freest spirit; it is equivalent to that training of the child which will give him such possession of himself that he may take charge of himself; may not only adapt himself to the changes that are going on, but have power to shape and direct them.

New inventions, new machines, and new methods of transportation and communication are completely transforming the landscape year after year. It's completely impossible to prepare a child for any fixed role in life. Education that's based, either consciously or unconsciously, on this idea ends up not preparing future citizens for any role at all; instead, it turns them into useless bystanders, dependents, or actual obstacles to progress. Rather than taking care of themselves and others, they become individuals who need to be taken care of. Here, too, the school has a moral obligation to consider its social impact in the broadest and most open way; it means training the child in such a way that they gain self-possession, enabling them to take charge of their own lives, adapt to ongoing changes, and even have the power to shape and direct those changes.

Apart from participation in social life, the school has no moral end nor aim. As long as we confine ourselves to the school as an isolated institution, we have no directing principles, because we have no object. For example, the end of education is said to be the harmonious development  of all the powers of the individual. Here no reference to social life or membership is apparent, and yet many think we have in it an adequate and thoroughgoing definition of the goal of education. But if this definition be taken independently of social relationship we have no way of telling what is meant by any one of the terms employed. We do not know what a power is; we do not know what development is; we do not know what harmony is. A power is a power only with reference to the use to which it is put, the function it has to serve. If we leave out the uses supplied by social life we have nothing but the old “faculty psychology” to tell what is meant by power and what the specific powers are. The principle reduces itself to enumerating a lot of faculties like perception, memory, reasoning, etc., and then stating that each one of these powers needs to be developed.

Aside from participating in social life, the school doesn't have a moral purpose or goal. As long as we see the school as a separate entity, we lack guiding principles because we have no clear objective. For instance, the goal of education is often described as the balanced development of all an individual's abilities. Here, there’s no mention of social life or belonging, yet many believe this provides a complete and adequate definition of education's purpose. However, if we consider this definition without the context of social relationships, we can't really understand what any of the terms mean. We don’t know what a "power" is; we don’t know what "development" is; we don’t know what "harmony" is. A power only has meaning in relation to how it's used and the role it plays. If we ignore the uses informed by social life, we’re left with the outdated concept of “faculty psychology” to explain what powers are and what the specific abilities are. This principle simply lists various faculties like perception, memory, reasoning, etc., and then claims that each of these powers needs to be developed.

Education then becomes a gymnastic exercise. Acute powers of observation and memory might be developed by studying Chinese characters; acuteness in reasoning might be got by discussing the scholastic subtleties of the Middle  Ages. The simple fact is that there is no isolated faculty of observation, or memory, or reasoning any more than there is an original faculty of blacksmithing, carpentering, or steam engineering. Faculties mean simply that particular impulses and habits have been coördinated or framed with reference to accomplishing certain definite kinds of work. We need to know the social situations in which the individual will have to use ability to observe, recollect, imagine, and reason, in order to have any way of telling what a training of mental powers actually means.

Education then becomes a workout. Sharp observation and memory can be improved by studying Chinese characters; reasoning skills can be honed by discussing the complex ideas of the Middle  Ages. The simple fact is that there isn't a separate skill for observation, memory, or reasoning, just like there isn't a unique skill for blacksmithing, carpentry, or steam engineering. Skills simply mean that specific impulses and habits have been coordinated or developed to achieve certain specific types of work. We need to understand the social situations where individuals will have to use their ability to observe, remember, imagine, and reason, to truly grasp what training mental skills actually entails.

What holds in the illustration of this particular definition of education holds good from whatever point of view we approach the matter. Only as we interpret school activities with reference to the larger circle of social activities to which they relate do we find any standard for judging their moral significance.

What is shown in this illustration of this specific definition of education is valid from any perspective we consider. We only find a standard for judging their moral significance when we interpret school activities in relation to the broader context of social activities they connect to.

The school itself must be a vital social institution to a much greater extent than obtains at present. I am told that there is a swimming school in a certain city where youth are taught to swim without going into the water, being repeatedly  drilled in the various movements which are necessary for swimming. When one of the young men so trained was asked what he did when he got into the water, he laconically replied, “Sunk.” The story happens to be true; were it not, it would seem to be a fable made expressly for the purpose of typifying the ethical relationship of school to society. The school cannot be a preparation for social life excepting as it reproduces, within itself, typical conditions of social life. At present it is largely engaged in the futile task of Sisyphus. It is endeavoring to form habits in children for use in a social life which, it would almost seem, is carefully and purposely kept away from vital contact with the child undergoing training. The only way to prepare for social life is to engage in social life. To form habits of social usefulness and serviceableness apart from any direct social need and motive, apart from any existing social situation, is, to the letter, teaching the child to swim by going through motions outside of the water. The most indispensable condition is left out of account, and the results are correspondingly partial.

The school itself needs to become a crucial social institution much more than it is right now. I’ve heard about a swimming school in a certain city where young people are taught to swim without actually getting into the water, repeatedly practicing the different movements required for swimming. When one of the young men trained this way was asked what he did when he got into the water, he simply replied, “Sunk.” This story is true; if it weren’t, it would seem like a fable aimed at illustrating the ethical connection between school and society. The school cannot truly prepare students for social life unless it replicates typical social conditions within itself. Currently, it's mainly stuck in a pointless cycle. It’s trying to instill habits in children for a social life that seems deliberately kept from meaningful interaction with the child in training. The only way to truly prepare for social life is to actively participate in it. Teaching habits of social usefulness and service apart from any direct social need and context, apart from any real social situation, is exactly like teaching a child to swim by practicing movements outside of the water. The essential condition is completely ignored, and the outcomes are predictably limited.

 The much lamented separation in the schools of intellectual and moral training, of acquiring information and growing in character, is simply one expression of the failure to conceive and construct the school as a social institution, having social life and value within itself. Except so far as the school is an embryonic typical community life, moral training must be partly pathological and partly formal. Training is pathological when stress is laid upon correcting wrong-doing instead of upon forming habits of positive service. Too often the teacher’s concern with the moral life of pupils takes the form of alertness for failures to conform to school rules and routine. These regulations, judged from the standpoint of the development of the child at the time, are more or less conventional and arbitrary. They are rules which have to be made in order that the existing modes of school work may go on; but the lack of inherent necessity in these school modes reflects itself in a feeling, on the part of the child, that the moral discipline of the school is arbitrary. Any conditions that compel the teacher to take note of failures rather than of healthy growth  give false standards and result in distortion and perversion. Attending to wrong-doing ought to be an incident rather than a principle. The child ought to have a positive consciousness of what he is about, so as to judge his acts from the standpoint of reference to the work which he has to do. Only in this way does he have a vital standard, one that enables him to turn failures to account for the future.

 The often sad separation in schools between intellectual and moral education, between gaining knowledge and developing character, is simply a reflection of the failure to see and create the school as a social institution that has its own social life and value. Unless the school functions as a small, typical community, moral education will be partly reactive and partly superficial. Moral training is reactive when it focuses more on correcting wrong behavior instead of building habits of positive contribution. Too often, teachers focus on the moral aspects of students' lives by watching for failures to follow school rules and routines. When viewed through the lens of a child's development at the moment, these rules are often conventional and arbitrary. They are guidelines created to keep the current ways of schooling in motion; however, the lack of inherent necessity in these methods leads children to feel that the moral discipline in school is arbitrary. Any circumstances that force teachers to pay more attention to failures than to healthy growth  provide false standards and lead to distortion and confusion. Addressing wrongdoing should be an exception, not a rule. Children should have a clear understanding of what they are doing, allowing them to assess their actions based on the work they need to accomplish. Only then do they have a meaningful standard, one that helps them learn from their mistakes for the future.

By saying that the moral training of the school is formal, I mean that the moral habits currently emphasized by the school are habits which are created, as it were, ad hoc. Even the habits of promptness, regularity, industry, non-interference with the work of others, faithfulness to tasks imposed, which are specially inculcated in the school, are habits that are necessary simply because the school system is what it is, and must be preserved intact. If we grant the inviolability of the school system as it is, these habits represent permanent and necessary moral ideas; but just in so far as the school system is itself isolated and mechanical, insistence upon these moral habits is more or less unreal, because the  ideal to which they relate is not itself necessary. The duties, in other words, are distinctly school duties, not life duties. If we compare this condition with that of the well-ordered home, we find that the duties and responsibilities that the child has there to recognize do not belong to the family as a specialized and isolated institution, but flow from the very nature of the social life in which the family participates and to which it contributes. The child ought to have the same motives for right doing and to be judged by the same standards in the school, as the adult in the wider social life to which he belongs. Interest in community welfare, an interest that is intellectual and practical, as well as emotional—an interest, that is to say, in perceiving whatever makes for social order and progress, and in carrying these principles into execution—is the moral habit to which all the special school habits must be related if they are to be animated by the breath of life.

By saying that the moral training in schools is formal, I mean that the moral habits currently emphasized are created specifically for that purpose. Even the habits of being on time, being consistent, working hard, not interfering with others' work, and being reliable with assigned tasks, which are specifically taught in schools, are necessary only because of the nature of the school system and must be kept intact. If we accept the school system as it is, these habits represent permanent and essential moral ideas; however, since the school system is isolated and mechanical, stressing these moral habits is somewhat unrealistic because the ideal they relate to is not inherently necessary. These duties are distinctly school-related, not duties for life. When we compare this situation with that of a well-structured home, we find that the duties and responsibilities a child must recognize there are not limited to the family as a separate institution but arise from the very nature of the social life in which the family is involved and to which it contributes. The child should have the same motivations for doing the right thing and be judged by the same standards in school as an adult in the broader social life they are part of. Interest in community welfare—an interest that is intellectual, practical, and emotional—meaning being aware of what contributes to social order and progress, and putting these principles into action, is the moral habit to which all the specific school habits must be connected if they are to have real significance.

THE MORAL TRAINING FROM METHODS OF INSTRUCTION

THE MORAL EDUCATION THROUGH TEACHING METHODS

 III
III

THE MORAL TRAINING FROM METHODS OF INSTRUCTION

The principle of the social character of the school as the basic factor in the moral education given may be also applied to the question of methods of instruction,—not in their details, but their general spirit. The emphasis then falls upon construction and giving out, rather than upon absorption and mere learning. We fail to recognize how essentially individualistic the latter methods are, and how unconsciously, yet certainly and effectively, they react into the child’s ways of judging and of acting. Imagine forty children all engaged in reading the same books, and in preparing and reciting the same lessons day after day. Suppose this process constitutes by far the larger part of their work, and that they are continually judged from the standpoint of what they are able to take in in a study hour and reproduce in a recitation hour. There is next to no  opportunity for any social division of labor. There is no opportunity for each child to work out something specifically his own, which he may contribute to the common stock, while he, in turn, participates in the productions of others. All are set to do exactly the same work and turn out the same products. The social spirit is not cultivated,—in fact, in so far as the purely individualistic method gets in its work, it atrophies for lack of use. One reason why reading aloud in school is poor is that the real motive for the use of language—the desire to communicate and to learn—is not utilized. The child knows perfectly well that the teacher and all his fellow pupils have exactly the same facts and ideas before them that he has; he is not giving them anything at all. And it may be questioned whether the moral lack is not as great as the intellectual. The child is born with a natural desire to give out, to do, to serve. When this tendency is not used, when conditions are such that other motives are substituted, the accumulation of an influence working against the social spirit is much larger than we have any idea of,—especially when the burden  of work, week after week, and year after year, falls upon this side.

The principle of the school's social nature as the key factor in moral education can also be applied to teaching methods,—not in their specifics, but their general approach. The focus shifts to creating and sharing, rather than simply taking in information and rote learning. We often fail to see how fundamentally individualistic the latter methods are, and how they unconsciously, yet surely and effectively, influence the child's judgment and behavior. Picture forty kids all reading the same books and preparing the same lessons day after day. If this process makes up most of their work, and they're constantly assessed based on what they can absorb during study time and repeat during recitation, there's almost no   chance for any social division of labor. Each child has no chance to create something unique that they can share with the group while also engaging in the work of others. Everyone is tasked with doing the same work and producing the same results. The social spirit isn't nurtured,—in fact, as the purely individualistic method takes hold, it diminishes from lack of use. One reason reading aloud in school is ineffective is that the true motivation for using language—the desire to share and learn—is not tapped into. The child knows perfectly well that the teacher and classmates have the same facts and ideas in front of them; he isn't giving them anything. It can be argued that the moral deficit is as significant as the intellectual one. A child is born with a natural urge to share, create, and help. When this urge is ignored, and conditions force other motivations, the buildup of influences undermining the social spirit is far greater than we realize,—especially when the burden   of work, week after week, and year after year, weighs heavily on this aspect.

But lack of cultivation of the social spirit is not all. Positively individualistic motives and standards are inculcated. Some stimulus must be found to keep the child at his studies. At the best this will be his affection for his teacher, together with a feeling that he is not violating school rules, and thus negatively, if not positively, is contributing to the good of the school. I have nothing to say against these motives so far as they go, but they are inadequate. The relation between the piece of work to be done and affection for a third person is external, not intrinsic. It is therefore liable to break down whenever the external conditions are changed. Moreover, this attachment to a particular person, while in a way social, may become so isolated and exclusive as to be selfish in quality. In any case, the child should gradually grow out of this relatively external motive into an appreciation, for its own sake, of the social value of what he has to do, because of its larger relations to life, not pinned down to two or three persons.

But the lack of nurturing a social spirit isn't the only issue. Individualistic motives and standards are also taught. Some incentive needs to be found to keep the child engaged in their studies. At best, that incentive might be their affection for their teacher, along with the understanding that they're not breaking school rules, and thus, even if unintentionally, contributing to the school's well-being. I have nothing against these motives as far as they go, but they're not enough. The connection between the assigned task and affection for a third person is external, not intrinsic. Therefore, it can easily fall apart whenever external conditions change. Additionally, this attachment to one specific person, while somewhat social, can become so isolated and exclusive that it turns selfish. In any case, the child should gradually move beyond this relatively superficial motivation to genuinely appreciate the social value of what they’re doing, recognizing its broader connections to life, not just tied to a couple of individuals.

 But, unfortunately, the motive is not always at this relative best, but mixed with lower motives which are distinctly egoistic. Fear is a motive which is almost sure to enter in,—not necessarily physical fear, or fear of punishment, but fear of losing the approbation of others; or fear of failure, so extreme as to be morbid and paralyzing. On the other side, emulation and rivalry enter in. Just because all are doing the same work, and are judged (either in recitation or examination with reference to grading and to promotion) not from the standpoint of their personal contribution, but from that of comparative success, the feeling of superiority over others is unduly appealed to, while timid children are depressed. Children are judged with reference to their capacity to realize the same external standard. The weaker gradually lose their sense of power, and accept a position of continuous and persistent inferiority. The effect upon both self-respect and respect for work need not be dwelt upon. The strong learn to glory, not in their strength, but in the fact that they are stronger. The child is prematurely launched into the region of individualistic  competition, and this in a direction where competition is least applicable, namely, in intellectual and artistic matters, whose law is coöperation and participation.

 But, unfortunately, motives aren't always at their best; often, they're mixed with lower, self-serving motives. Fear is a common motive; it might not just be physical fear or fear of punishment, but the fear of losing others' approval or the fear of failure, which can become overwhelming and paralyzing. On the flip side, competition and rivalry come into play. When everyone is doing the same work and being evaluated (whether in recitation or exams) based on their relative success rather than their individual contributions, the drive to feel superior to others is unfairly stimulated, while shy kids feel disheartened. Children are measured against the same external standards. The weaker gradually lose their sense of empowerment and accept a continuous state of inferiority. The impact on both self-respect and respect for work is significant. The stronger ones come to take pride not in their abilities but in the fact that they're superior. Children are thrust too soon into a world of individual competition, especially in areas like intellectual and artistic pursuits, where cooperation and participation should be the focus.  

Next, perhaps, to the evils of passive absorption and of competition for external standing come, perhaps, those which result from the eternal emphasis upon preparation for a remote future. I do not refer here to the waste of energy and vitality that accrues when children, who live so largely in the immediate present, are appealed to in the name of a dim and uncertain future which means little or nothing to them. I have in mind rather the habitual procrastination that develops when the motive for work is future, not present; and the false standards of judgment that are created when work is estimated, not on the basis of present need and present responsibility, but by reference to an external result, like passing an examination, getting promoted, entering high school, getting into college, etc. Who can reckon up the loss of moral power that arises from the constant impression that nothing is worth doing in itself, but only as a preparation for something  else, which in turn is only a getting ready for some genuinely serious end beyond? Moreover, as a rule, it will be found that remote success is an end which appeals most to those in whom egoistic desire to get ahead—to get ahead of others—is already only too strong a motive. Those in whom personal ambition is already so strong that it paints glowing pictures of future victories may be touched; others of a more generous nature do not respond.

Next, maybe second to the issues of being passively absorbed and competing for outside recognition, are those that come from the constant focus on preparing for a distant future. I'm not talking about the waste of energy and excitement that happens when children, who mostly live in the moment, are urged to think about a vague and uncertain future that doesn’t mean much to them. Instead, I’m thinking about the habit of procrastination that develops when the reason for working is future-oriented rather than present-focused; and the misleading standards of judgment that arise when work is assessed not based on immediate needs and responsibilities but rather according to an external outcome, like passing a test, getting a promotion, entering high school, or getting into college, etc. Who can measure the loss of moral strength that comes from the constant idea that nothing has value on its own, but only as a preparation for something else, which in turn is just preparing for some truly serious goal beyond? Furthermore, it usually turns out that distant success is something that appeals most to those whose selfish desire to get ahead— to get ahead of others—is already a strong motivation. Those whose personal ambition is so intense that it creates bright visions of future victories may be influenced; others with a more generous nature may not react at all.

I cannot stop to paint the other side. I can only say that the introduction of every method that appeals to the child’s active powers, to his capacities in construction, production, and creation, marks an opportunity to shift the centre of ethical gravity from an absorption which is selfish to a service which is social. Manual training is more than manual; it is more than intellectual; in the hands of any good teacher it lends itself easily, and almost as a matter of course, to development of social habits. Ever since the philosophy of Kant, it has been a commonplace of æsthetic theory, that art is universal; that it is not the product of purely personal desire or appetite,  or capable of merely individual appropriation, but has a value participated in by all who perceive it. Even in the schools where most conscious attention is paid to moral considerations, the methods of study and recitation may be such as to emphasize appreciation rather than power, an emotional readiness to assimilate the experiences of others, rather than enlightened and trained capacity to carry forward those values which in other conditions and past times made those experiences worth having. At all events, separation between instruction and character continues in our schools (in spite of the efforts of individual teachers) as a result of divorce between learning and doing. The attempt to attach genuine moral effectiveness to the mere processes of learning, and to the habits which go along with learning, can result only in a training infected with formality, arbitrariness, and an undue emphasis upon failure to conform. That there is as much accomplished as there is shows the possibilities involved in methods of school activity which afford opportunity for reciprocity, coöperation, and positive personal achievement.

I can’t take the time to discuss the other side. All I can say is that introducing methods that engage a child's active abilities—especially in building, producing, and creating—creates a chance to shift the focus from selfish absorption to social service. Manual training is more than just hands-on work; it's more than just intellectual engagement. In the hands of a good teacher, it naturally leads to the development of social habits. Since Kant's philosophy, it has been a common belief in aesthetic theory that art is universal; it’s not just a product of personal desire or appetite, or something that can be owned individually, but rather has a value shared by everyone who perceives it. Even in schools that focus heavily on moral considerations, the methods of study and recitation can often stress appreciation over power, fostering an emotional readiness to learn from others rather than developing the enlightened skills needed to carry forward the values that made those experiences meaningful in the past. In any case, the separation between instruction and character continues in our schools (despite the efforts of individual teachers) because of a disconnect between learning and doing. Trying to attach real moral effectiveness to just the processes of learning and the habits associated with it leads only to training that feels formal, arbitrary, and focused too much on conformity. The fact that we achieve as much as we do shows the potential in school activities that allow for reciprocity, cooperation, and genuine personal achievement.

THE SOCIAL NATURE OF THE COURSE OF STUDY

THE SOCIAL NATURE OF THE STUDY PROGRAM

 IV
 IV

THE SOCIAL NATURE OF THE COURSE OF STUDY

In many respects, it is the subject-matter used in school life which decides both the general atmosphere of the school and the methods of instruction and discipline which rule. A barren “course of study,” that is to say, a meagre and narrow field of school activities, cannot possibly lend itself to the development of a vital social spirit or to methods that appeal to sympathy and coöperation instead of to absorption, exclusiveness, and competition. Hence it becomes an all important matter to know how we shall apply our social standard of moral value to the subject-matter of school work, to what we call, traditionally, the “studies” that occupy pupils.

In many ways, the topics we cover in school shape the overall vibe of the school and influence the teaching methods and discipline that are in place. A dull "curriculum," meaning a limited and narrow range of school activities, can't possibly foster a lively social spirit or encourage methods that promote empathy and teamwork instead of focus, exclusivity, and competition. Therefore, it's crucial to understand how we will apply our social standards of moral value to the subjects taught in school, what we traditionally refer to as the "studies" that engage students.

A study is to be considered as a means of bringing the child to realize the social scene of action. Thus considered it gives a criterion for selection of material and for judgment of values. We have  at present three independent values set up: one of culture, another of information, and another of discipline. In reality, these refer only to three phases of social interpretation. Information is genuine or educative only in so far as it presents definite images and conceptions of materials placed in a context of social life. Discipline is genuinely educative only as it represents a reaction of information into the individual’s own powers so that he brings them under control for social ends. Culture, if it is to be genuinely educative and not an external polish or factitious varnish, represents the vital union of information and discipline. It marks the socialization of the individual in his outlook upon life.

A study should be seen as a way to help the child understand the social environment they live in. This perspective provides a standard for choosing materials and assessing their value. Right now, we have   three independent values: one related to culture, another to information, and a third to discipline. In reality, these only point to three aspects of understanding society. Information is truly educational only if it presents clear images and ideas of materials within a social context. Discipline is genuinely educational only to the extent that it channels information into the individual's own abilities, allowing them to manage these abilities for social purposes. Culture, to be truly educational and not just a superficial decoration or artificial layer, represents the essential connection between information and discipline. It signifies the individual's socialization in their perspective on life.

This point may be illustrated by brief reference to a few of the school studies. In the first place, there is no line of demarkation within facts themselves which classifies them as belonging to science, history, or geography, respectively. The pigeon-hole classification which is so prevalent at present (fostered by introducing the pupil at the outset into a number of different studies contained in different text-books) gives an utterly erroneous  idea of the relations of studies to one another and to the intellectual whole to which all belong. In fact, these subjects have to do with the same ultimate reality, namely, the conscious experience of man. It is only because we have different interests, or different ends, that we sort out the material and label part of it science, part of it history, part geography, and so on. Each “sorting” represents materials arranged with reference to some one dominant typical aim or process of the social life.

This point can be demonstrated by briefly referencing a few school subjects. First of all, there’s no clear boundary within the facts themselves that categorizes them as science, history, or geography. The common practice of sorting subjects into categories (which is encouraged by introducing students to various topics through different textbooks) leads to a completely misleading idea of how these studies relate to one another and to the overall knowledge they all contribute to. In reality, these subjects all connect to the same fundamental experience: human consciousness. We only sort and label the material as science, history, geography, etc., because we have different interests or objectives. Each "sorting" reflects materials organized around a specific goal or process of social life.

This social criterion is necessary, not only to mark off studies from one another, but also to grasp the reasons for each study,—the motives in connection with which it shall be presented. How, for example, should we define geography? What is the unity in the different so-called divisions of geography,—mathematical geography, physical geography, political geography, commercial geography? Are they purely empirical classifications dependent upon the brute fact that we run across a lot of different facts? Or is there some intrinsic principle through which the material is distributed under these various  heads,—something in the interest and attitude of the human mind towards them? I should say that geography has to do with all those aspects of social life which are concerned with the interaction of the life of man and nature; or, that it has to do with the world considered as the scene of social interaction. Any fact, then, will be geographical in so far as it has to do with the dependence of man upon his natural environment, or with changes introduced in this environment through the life of man.

This social criterion is essential, not only to differentiate studies from one another but also to understand the reasons behind each study—the motives associated with how it will be presented. How, for instance, should we define geography? What is the common thread among the different so-called divisions of geography—mathematical geography, physical geography, political geography, commercial geography? Are they merely empirical classifications based on the sheer fact that we encounter various facts? Or is there some inherent principle that organizes the material into these different categories—something related to the interests and mindset of humans toward them? I would argue that geography pertains to all aspects of social life that involve the interaction between humanity and nature; or, in other words, it relates to the world viewed as the stage for social interaction. Therefore, any fact will be considered geographical to the extent that it pertains to the dependence of humans on their natural environment or to the changes made in this environment through human activity.

The four forms of geography referred to above represent, then, four increasing stages of abstraction in discussing the mutual relation of human life and nature. The beginning must be social geography, the frank recognition of the earth as the home of men acting in relations to one another. I mean by this that the essence of any geographical fact is the consciousness of two persons, or two groups of persons, who are at once separated and connected by their physical environment, and that the interest is in seeing how these people are at once kept apart and brought together in their actions by the instrumentality of the physical environment.  The ultimate significance of lake, river, mountain, and plain is not physical but social; it is the part which it plays in modifying and directing human relationships. This evidently involves an extension of the term commercial. It has to do not simply with business, in the narrow sense, but with whatever relates to human intercourse and intercommunication as affected by natural forms and properties. Political geography represents this same social interaction taken in a static instead of in a dynamic way; taken, that is, as temporarily crystallized and fixed in certain forms. Physical geography (including under this not simply physiography, but also the study of flora and fauna) represents a further analysis or abstraction. It studies the conditions which determine human action, leaving out of account, temporarily, the ways in which they concretely do this. Mathematical geography carries the analysis back to more ultimate and remote conditions, showing that the physical conditions of the earth are not ultimate, but depend upon the place which the world occupies in a larger system. Here, in other words, are traced, step by step, the links  which connect the immediate social occupations and groupings of men with the whole natural system which ultimately conditions them. Step by step the scene is enlarged and the image of what enters into the make-up of social action is widened and broadened; at no time is the chain of connection to be broken.

The four forms of geography mentioned earlier represent four increasing levels of abstraction in discussing the connection between human life and nature. We start with social geography, which openly acknowledges the earth as the home of people interacting with each other. By this, I mean that the essence of any geographic fact is the awareness of two individuals, or two groups of people, who are both separated and connected by their physical surroundings. The focus is on understanding how these people are kept apart and brought together in their actions through their physical environment. The ultimate significance of lakes, rivers, mountains, and plains is not just physical but social; it relates to how these features shape and direct human relationships. This clearly broadens the definition of commerce. It pertains not just to business in the narrow sense but to everything related to human interaction and communication as influenced by natural features and properties. Political geography looks at this same social interaction, but in a static rather than dynamic way; it is viewed as temporarily fixed in certain forms. Physical geography—encompassing not just physiography but also the study of plants and animals—offers a deeper analysis or abstraction. It examines the conditions that determine human actions while temporarily setting aside how these actions concretely take place. Mathematical geography traces the analysis back to more fundamental and distant conditions, showing that the physical conditions of the earth are not final, but depend on the earth's position within a larger system. Here, we can see, step by step, the connections that link the immediate social activities and groupings of people with the entire natural system that ultimately shapes them. Gradually, the scene expands, and the understanding of what contributes to social action is broadened; at no point should the chain of connection be severed.

It is out of the question to take up the studies one by one and show that their meaning is similarly controlled by social considerations. But I cannot forbear saying a word or two upon history. History is vital or dead to the child according as it is, or is not, presented from the sociological standpoint. When treated simply as a record of what has passed and gone, it must be mechanical, because the past, as the past, is remote. Simply as the past there is no motive for attending to it. The ethical value of history teaching will be measured by the extent to which past events are made the means of understanding the present,—affording insight into what makes up the structure and working of society to-day. Existing social structure is exceedingly complex. It is practically impossible for the child to attack it en  masse and get any definite mental image of it. But type phases of historical development may be selected which will exhibit, as through a telescope, the essential constituents of the existing order. Greece, for example, represents what art and growing power of individual expression stand for; Rome exhibits the elements and forces of political life on a tremendous scale. Or, as these civilizations are themselves relatively complex, a study of still simpler forms of hunting, nomadic, and agricultural life in the beginnings of civilization, a study of the effects of the introduction of iron, and iron tools, reduces the complexity to simpler elements.

It’s not feasible to go through each study one by one and demonstrate how their meaning is influenced by social factors. However, I can’t help but say a few things about history. History is either crucial or irrelevant to a child depending on whether it’s presented from a sociological perspective. When it’s treated merely as a record of what has happened, it becomes mechanical, because the past is distant. As simply the past, there is no reason to pay attention to it. The ethical value of teaching history will depend on how well past events help us understand the present, providing insights into the structure and functioning of society today. The current social structure is extremely complex. It’s almost impossible for a child to approach it as a whole and form a clear mental image of it. However, we can choose key phases of historical development that will illustrate, like through a telescope, the essential components of the existing order. Greece, for instance, represents what art and the increasing power of individual expression stand for; Rome showcases the elements and forces of political life on a grand scale. Alternatively, since these civilizations are themselves relatively complicated, examining simpler forms of hunting, nomadic, and agricultural life from the beginnings of civilization, or studying the impact of the introduction of iron and iron tools, simplifies the complexity into more fundamental elements.

One reason historical teaching is usually not more effective is that the student is set to acquire information in such a way that no epochs or factors stand out in his mind as typical; everything is reduced to the same dead level. The way to secure the necessary perspective is to treat the past as if it were a projected present with some of its elements enlarged.

One reason history teaching isn't usually more effective is that students learn information in a way where no specific time periods or factors really stick out to them; everything feels flat and the same. To get the right perspective, we should approach the past as if it were a future version of the present, highlighting some of its elements more.

The principle of contrast is as important as that of similarity. Because the present life is so  close to us, touching us at every point, we cannot get away from it to see it as it really is. Nothing stands out clearly or sharply as characteristic. In the study of past periods, attention necessarily attaches itself to striking differences. Thus the child gets a locus of imagination, through which he can remove himself from the pressure of present surrounding circumstances and define them.

The principle of contrast is just as important as similarity. Since our current life feels so close to us, impacting us at every turn, we can't escape it to see it for what it truly is. Nothing stands out clearly or distinctly as being characteristic. In studying past eras, our focus naturally shifts to noticeable differences. This way, a child develops an imaginative perspective, allowing them to distance themselves from the stresses of their current environment and articulate those experiences.

History is equally available in teaching the methods of social progress. It is commonly stated that history must be studied from the standpoint of cause and effect. The truth of this statement depends upon its interpretation. Social life is so complex and the various parts of it are so organically related to one another and to the natural environment, that it is impossible to say that this or that thing is the cause of some other particular thing. But the study of history can reveal the main instruments in the discoveries, inventions, new modes of life, etc., which have initiated the great epochs of social advance; and it can present to the child types of the main lines of social progress, and can set before him what have been the chief difficulties and obstructions in the way of  progress. Once more this can be done only in so far as it is recognized that social forces in themselves are always the same,—that the same kind of influences were at work one hundred and one thousand years ago that are now working,—and that particular historical epochs afford illustration of the way in which the fundamental forces work.

History is also useful in teaching the methods of social progress. It's often said that history should be studied from the perspective of cause and effect. The validity of this statement varies based on how it’s interpreted. Social life is so complex and its various elements are so interconnected with each other and the natural environment that it's impossible to pinpoint that one specific thing caused another. However, studying history can highlight the key factors involved in the discoveries, inventions, new ways of living, etc., that have sparked the great periods of social advancement; it can show children examples of the main paths of social progress, and can outline the major challenges and barriers to  progress. This can only be achieved if we recognize that social forces themselves remain constant—that the same types of influences were at play a hundred or a hundred thousand years ago as they are today—and that specific historical periods illustrate how fundamental forces operate.

Everything depends, then, upon history being treated from a social standpoint; as manifesting the agencies which have influenced social development and as presenting the typical institutions in which social life has expressed itself. The culture-epoch theory, while working in the right direction, has failed to recognize the importance of treating past periods with relation to the present,—as affording insight into the representative factors of its structure; it has treated these periods too much as if they had some meaning or value in themselves. The way in which the biographical method is handled illustrates the same point. It is often treated in such a way as to exclude from the child’s consciousness (or at least not sufficiently to emphasize) the social  forces and principles involved in the association of the masses of men. It is quite true that the child is easily interested in history from the biographical standpoint; but unless “the hero” is treated in relation to the community life behind him that he sums up and directs, there is danger that history will reduce itself to a mere exciting story. Then moral instruction reduces itself to drawing certain lessons from the life of the particular personalities concerned, instead of widening and deepening the child’s imagination of social relations, ideals, and means.

Everything depends on viewing history from a social perspective, as it reveals the forces that have shaped social development and showcases the typical institutions through which social life has expressed itself. The culture-epoch theory, while moving in the right direction, has overlooked the importance of connecting past periods to the present, offering insights into the key elements of its framework; it has treated these past periods as if they had inherent meaning or value. The way the biographical method is applied illustrates this same issue. Often, it is presented in a way that minimizes (or at least does not sufficiently emphasize) the social forces and principles involved in the interaction of large groups of people. It's true that children are easily engaged with history from a biographical viewpoint; however, unless “the hero” is connected to the community life that he represents and leads, there is a risk that history will become merely an exciting story. Consequently, moral education turns into just drawing certain lessons from the lives of specific individuals, rather than broadening and deepening the child's understanding of social relationships, ideals, and methods.

It will be remembered that I am not making these points for their own sake, but with reference to the general principle that when a study is taught as a mode of understanding social life it has positive ethical import. What the normal child continuously needs is not so much isolated moral lessons upon the importance of truthfulness and honesty, or the beneficent results that follow from a particular act of patriotism, as the formation of habits of social imagination and conception.

It’s important to note that I’m not making these points just for the sake of it, but to highlight the broader idea that when a subject is taught to help understand social life, it has a positive ethical significance. What a typical child really needs is not just separate moral lessons about the importance of honesty and truthfulness, or the good outcomes that stem from acts of patriotism, but rather the development of habits related to social imagination and understanding.

I take one more illustration, namely, mathematics. This does, or does not, accomplish its  full purpose according as it is, or is not, presented as a social tool. The prevailing divorce between information and character, between knowledge and social action, stalks upon the scene here. The moment mathematical study is severed from the place which it occupies with reference to use in social life, it becomes unduly abstract, even upon the purely intellectual side. It is presented as a matter of technical relations and formulæ apart from any end or use. What the study of number suffers from in elementary education is lack of motivation. Back of this and that and the other particular bad method is the radical mistake of treating number as if it were an end in itself, instead of the means of accomplishing some end. Let the child get a consciousness of what is the use of number, of what it really is for, and half the battle is won. Now this consciousness of the use of reason implies some end which is implicitly social.

I’ll provide one more example: mathematics. This achieves, or fails to achieve, its full purpose depending on whether it is presented as a social tool. The ongoing divide between information and character, between knowledge and social action, is evident here. Once mathematical study is disconnected from its relevance to social life, it becomes overly abstract, even on an intellectual level. It is shown as just a matter of technical relationships and formulas without any real purpose or application. The main issue with how number is taught in elementary education is the lack of motivation. Behind various ineffective methods lies the fundamental mistake of treating number as an end in itself, rather than as a means to achieve some goal. If children can understand the purpose of numbers and what they’re truly for, half the battle is won. This understanding of the use of reason implies a goal that is inherently social.

One of the absurd things in the more advanced study of arithmetic is the extent to which the child is introduced to numerical operations which have no distinctive mathematical principles characterizing  them, but which represent certain general principles found in business relationships. To train the child in these operations, while paying no attention to the business realities in which they are of use, or to the conditions of social life which make these business activities necessary, is neither arithmetic nor common sense. The child is called upon to do examples in interest, partnership, banking, brokerage, and so on through a long string, and no pains are taken to see that, in connection with the arithmetic, he has any sense of the social realities involved. This part of arithmetic is essentially sociological in its nature. It ought either to be omitted entirely, or else be taught in connection with a study of the relevant social realities. As we now manage the study, it is the old case of learning to swim apart from the water over again, with correspondingly bad results on the practical side.

One of the ridiculous things in more advanced arithmetic study is how a child is introduced to number operations that don’t have any unique mathematical principles defining them. Instead, these operations reflect general principles found in business scenarios. Training a child in these operations while ignoring the actual business contexts where they apply or the social conditions that make these business activities necessary isn’t math or common sense. The child is expected to solve examples related to interest, partnerships, banking, brokerage, and so on, without any effort made to ensure they understand the social realities involved. This part of arithmetic is fundamentally sociological. It should either be removed entirely or taught alongside a study of the relevant social realities. As it stands now, it's just like trying to learn to swim without ever getting in the water, leading to poor practical outcomes.

In concluding this portion of the discussion, we may say that our conceptions of moral education have been too narrow, too formal, and too pathological. We have associated the term ethical with certain special acts which are labeled virtues  and are set off from the mass of other acts, and are still more divorced from the habitual images and motives of the children performing them. Moral instruction is thus associated with teaching about these particular virtues, or with instilling certain sentiments in regard to them. The moral has been conceived in too goody-goody a way. Ultimate moral motives and forces are nothing more or less than social intelligence—the power of observing and comprehending social situations,—and social power—trained capacities of control—at work in the service of social interest and aims. There is no fact which throws light upon the constitution of society, there is no power whose training adds to social resourcefulness that is not moral.

In wrapping up this part of the discussion, we can say that our views on moral education have been too limited, too formal, and too focused on problems. We’ve tied the term ethical to specific actions that are labeled as virtues   and separated them from the larger group of other actions, while also distancing them from the everyday thoughts and motivations of the children who perform them. Moral instruction has thus been linked to teaching about these specific virtues or instilling certain feelings about them. The moral aspect has been seen in a way that's too self-righteous. Ultimately, moral motives and forces are simply social intelligence—the ability to observe and understand social situations—and social power—developed skills for gaining control—working toward social interests and goals. No fact that sheds light on society’s makeup, and no force whose training enhances social resourcefulness, is anything other than moral.

I sum up, then, this part of the discussion by asking your attention to the moral trinity of the school. The demand is for social intelligence, social power, and social interests. Our resources are (1) the life of the school as a social institution in itself; (2) methods of learning and of doing work; and (3) the school studies or curriculum. In so far as the school represents, in its own  spirit, a genuine community life; in so far as what are called school discipline, government, order, etc., are the expressions of this inherent social spirit; in so far as the methods used are those that appeal to the active and constructive powers, permitting the child to give out and thus to serve; in so far as the curriculum is so selected and organized as to provide the material for affording the child a consciousness of the world in which he has to play a part, and the demands he has to meet; so far as these ends are met, the school is organized on an ethical basis. So far as general principles are concerned, all the basic ethical requirements are met. The rest remains between the individual teacher and the individual child.

To wrap up this part of the discussion, I ask you to focus on the moral core of the school. We need social intelligence, social power, and social interests. Our resources are (1) the school’s life as a social institution; (2) methods of learning and doing work; and (3) the school subjects or curriculum. As long as the school embodies, in its own spirit, a true community life; as long as what we call school discipline, governance, order, etc., reflect this inherent social spirit; as long as the methods used connect with the active and constructive abilities, allowing the child to engage and contribute; and as long as the curriculum is chosen and organized to give the child an understanding of the world they must navigate and the challenges they will face; to the extent that these goals are achieved, the school is structured on an ethical foundation. In terms of general principles, all fundamental ethical requirements are fulfilled. The rest is up to the individual teacher and the individual child.

 THE PSYCHOLOGICAL ASPECT OF MORAL EDUCATION

 THE PSYCHOLOGICAL ASPECT OF MORAL EDUCATION


THE PSYCHOLOGICAL ASPECT OF MORAL EDUCATION

So far we have been considering the make-up of purposes and results that constitute conduct—its “what.” But conduct has a certain method and spirit also—its “how.” Conduct may be looked upon as expressing the attitudes and dispositions of an individual, as well as realizing social results and maintaining the social fabric. A consideration of conduct as a mode of individual performance, personal doing, takes us from the social to the psychological side of morals. In the first place, all conduct springs ultimately and radically out of native instincts and impulses. We must know what these instincts and impulses are, and what they are at each particular stage of the child’s development, in order to know what to appeal to and what to build upon. Neglect of this principle may give a mechanical imitation of moral conduct, but the imitation will be ethically  dead, because it is external and has its centre without, not within, the individual. We must study the child, in other words, to get our indications, our symptoms, our suggestions. The more or less spontaneous acts of the child are not to be thought of as setting moral forms to which the efforts of the educator must conform—this would result simply in spoiling the child; but they are symptoms which require to be interpreted: stimuli which need to be responded to in directed ways; material which, in however transformed a shape, is the only ultimate constituent of future moral conduct and character.

So far, we've been looking at the purposes and outcomes that make up behavior—its “what.” But behavior also involves a certain method and spirit—its “how.” Behavior can be seen as expressing the attitudes and dispositions of an individual, while also achieving social outcomes and supporting the social fabric. Examining behavior as a form of individual action, or personal doing, shifts our focus from the social aspect to the psychological aspect of morals. First of all, all behavior ultimately and fundamentally comes from innate instincts and impulses. We need to understand what these instincts and impulses are and how they develop at each stage of a child's growth to know what to appeal to and what to build upon. Ignoring this principle may lead to a superficial imitation of moral behavior, but this imitation will be ethically  dead because it is external and originates outside the individual, not from within. We must study the child, in other words, to gain our insights, our signs, our cues. The more or less spontaneous actions of the child should not be seen as setting moral standards to which the educator must conform—doing so would simply spoil the child; rather, they are signs that need to be interpreted: stimuli that require responses in directed ways; material that, regardless of how it is transformed, is the only essential building block for future moral behavior and character.

Then, secondly, our ethical principles need to be stated in psychological terms because the child supplies us with the only means or instruments by which to realize moral ideals. The subject-matter of the curriculum, however important, however judiciously selected, is empty of conclusive moral content until it is made over into terms of the individual’s own activities, habits, and desires. We must know what history, geography, and mathematics mean in psychological terms, that is, as modes of personal experiencing, before  we can get out of them their moral potentialities.

Then, secondly, we need to express our ethical principles in psychological terms because children provide us with the only means or tools to achieve moral ideals. The subject matter of the curriculum, no matter how important or carefully chosen, lacks meaningful moral content until it's translated into the individual's own actions, habits, and desires. We must understand what history, geography, and mathematics mean in psychological terms, that is, as ways of personal experience, before   we can extract their moral potential.

The psychological side of education sums itself up, of course, in a consideration of character. It is a commonplace to say that the development of character is the end of all school work. The difficulty lies in the execution of the idea. And an underlying difficulty in this execution is the lack of a clear conception of what character means. This may seem an extreme statement. If so, the idea may be conveyed by saying that we generally conceive of character simply in terms of results; we have no clear conception of it in psychological terms—that is, as a process, as working or dynamic. We know what character means in terms of the actions which proceed from it, but we have not a definite conception of it on its inner side, as a system of working forces.

The psychological aspect of education ultimately boils down to understanding character. It's often said that developing character is the main goal of all schoolwork. The challenge lies in how we implement this idea. One underlying issue with this implementation is that we lack a clear understanding of what character truly means. This might sound like an exaggeration. If it does, the point can be made by saying that we usually think of character only in terms of outcomes; we don’t have a clear understanding of it in psychological terms—that is, as a process, as something active and dynamic. We recognize what character means through the actions that come from it, but we don’t have a clear idea of its inner workings as a system of driving forces.

(1) Force, efficiency in execution, or overt action, is one necessary constituent of character. In our moral books and lectures we may lay the stress upon good intentions, etc. But we know practically that the kind of character we hope to build up through our education is one that not  only has good intentions, but that insists upon carrying them out. Any other character is wishy-washy; it is goody, not good. The individual must have the power to stand up and count for something in the actual conflicts of life. He must have initiative, insistence, persistence, courage, and industry. He must, in a word, have all that goes under the name “force of character.” Undoubtedly, individuals differ greatly in their native endowment in this respect. None the less, each has a certain primary equipment of impulse, of tendency forward, of innate urgency to do. The problem of education on this side is that of discovering what this native fund of power is, and then of utilizing it in such a way (affording conditions which both stimulate and control) as to organize it into definite conserved modes of action—habits.

(1) Strength, effectiveness in action, or taking direct steps is one essential part of character. In our moral books and lectures, we might emphasize good intentions, and so on. But we know from experience that the type of character we aim to develop through education is one that not only has good intentions but also insists on following through. Any other character is weak; it's just nice, not genuinely good. An individual must have the ability to stand up and make an impact in the real challenges of life. They need to have initiative, determination, perseverance, courage, and hard work. In short, they must possess what we call “force of character.” Of course, people vary greatly in their natural abilities in this area. Nonetheless, everyone has some basic level of drive, a forward momentum, and an innate urge to take action. The challenge in education is to identify what this natural source of power is and then to use it in a way that provides conditions that both stimulate and regulate it, ultimately organizing it into consistent patterns of behavior—habits.

(2) But something more is required than sheer force. Sheer force may be brutal; it may override the interests of others. Even when aiming at right ends it may go at them in such a way as to violate the rights of others. More than this, in sheer force there is no guarantee for the right  end. Efficiency may be directed towards mistaken ends and result in positive mischief and destruction. Power, as already suggested, must be directed. It must be organized along social channels; it must be attached to valuable ends.

(2) But simply using raw power isn't enough. Raw power can be harsh; it can disregard other people's interests. Even when trying to achieve good outcomes, it can do so in a way that violates the rights of others. Furthermore, relying solely on raw power doesn't ensure a positive outcome. Effectiveness can be misused and lead to harm and chaos. As mentioned before, power needs direction. It must be organized through social means; it must be tied to meaningful goals.

This involves training on both the intellectual and emotional side. On the intellectual side we must have judgment—what is ordinarily called good sense. The difference between mere knowledge, or information, and judgment is that the former is simply held, not used; judgment is knowledge directed with reference to the accomplishment of ends. Good judgment is a sense of respective or proportionate values. The one who has judgment is the one who has ability to size up a situation. He is the one who can grasp the scene or situation before him, ignoring what is irrelevant, or what for the time being is unimportant, who can seize upon the factors which demand attention, and grade them according to their respective claims. Mere knowledge of what the right is, in the abstract, mere intentions of following the right in general, however praiseworthy in themselves, are never a substitute for this  power of trained judgment. Action is always in the concrete. It is definite and individualized. Except, therefore, as it is backed and controlled by a knowledge of the actual concrete factors in the situation in which it occurs, it must be relatively futile and waste.

This involves training both the mind and emotions. On the intellectual side, we need judgment—what we usually call good sense. The difference between just having knowledge or information and having judgment is that the former is simply held, not used; judgment is knowledge applied to achieve goals. Good judgment is an understanding of relative or proportional values. A person with judgment can assess a situation. They can understand what’s happening around them, ignoring what’s irrelevant or temporarily unimportant, and focus on the elements that need attention, ranking them based on their importance. Simply knowing what is right in theory, or having the intention to do what’s right in general, no matter how commendable, can never replace this trained judgment. Action is always concrete. It is specific and individual. Therefore, unless it is supported and guided by an understanding of the real factors in the situation, it is likely to be ineffective and wasted.

(3) But the consciousness of ends must be more than merely intellectual. We can imagine a person with most excellent judgment, who yet does not act upon his judgment. There must not only be force to ensure effort in execution against obstacles, but there must also be a delicate personal responsiveness,—there must be an emotional reaction. Indeed, good judgment is impossible without this susceptibility. Unless there is a prompt and almost instinctive sensitiveness to conditions, to the ends and interests of others, the intellectual side of judgment will not have proper material to work upon. Just as the material of knowledge is supplied through the senses, so the material of ethical knowledge is supplied by emotional responsiveness. It is difficult to put this quality into words, but we all know the difference between the character which is hard and  formal, and one which is sympathetic, flexible, and open. In the abstract the former may be as sincerely devoted to moral ideas as is the latter, but as a practical matter we prefer to live with the latter. We count upon it to accomplish more by tact, by instinctive recognition of the claims of others, by skill in adjusting, than the former can accomplish by mere attachment to rules.

(3) But being aware of goals has to be more than just intellectual. We can picture someone with excellent judgment who still doesn't act on their judgment. There needs to be not only the drive to follow through despite challenges, but also a personal sensitivity—there has to be an emotional response. In fact, good judgment can't happen without this sensitivity. Without an immediate and almost instinctive awareness of situations, of the goals and needs of others, the intellectual part of judgment won't have the right material to work with. Just like knowledge comes from our senses, ethical understanding comes from our emotional responsiveness. It’s hard to describe this quality in words, but we all recognize the difference between a character that is stiff and formal and one that is empathetic, adaptable, and open. In theory, the former may be just as genuinely committed to moral principles as the latter, but practically, we prefer to associate with the latter. We rely on it to achieve more through tact, instinctively recognizing the needs of others, and skillful adjustments than the former can achieve through merely following rules.

Here, then, is the moral standard, by which to test the work of the school upon the side of what it does directly for individuals. (a) Does the school as a system, at present, attach sufficient importance to the spontaneous instincts and impulses? Does it afford sufficient opportunity for these to assert themselves and work out their own results? Can we even say that the school in principle attaches itself, at present, to the active constructive powers rather than to processes of absorption and learning? Does not our talk about self-activity largely render itself meaningless because the self-activity we have in mind is purely “intellectual,” out of relation to those impulses which work through hand and eye?

Here’s the moral standard for assessing how the school impacts individuals directly. (a) Does the school system today place enough importance on natural instincts and impulses? Does it provide enough opportunities for these to express themselves and achieve their own outcomes? Can we even say that the school currently focuses more on active, constructive abilities rather than on just absorbing and learning information? Doesn’t our discussion about self-activity lose meaning because the self-activity we’re thinking of is purely “intellectual,” disconnected from the impulses that involve physical actions and observation?

 Just in so far as the present school methods fail to meet the test of such questions moral results must be unsatisfactory. We cannot secure the development of positive force of character unless we are willing to pay its price. We cannot smother and repress the child’s powers, or gradually abort them (from failure of opportunity for exercise), and then expect a character with initiative and consecutive industry. I am aware of the importance attaching to inhibition, but mere inhibition is valueless. The only restraint, the only holding-in, that is of any worth is that which comes through holding powers concentrated upon a positive end. An end cannot be attained excepting as instincts and impulses are kept from discharging at random and from running off on side tracks. In keeping powers at work upon their relevant ends, there is sufficient opportunity for genuine inhibition. To say that inhibition is higher than power, is like saying that death is more than life, negation more than affirmation, sacrifice more than service.

 As long as the current educational methods fail to address these moral questions, the outcomes will be disappointing. We can't foster a strong character unless we're ready to invest in it. We can't stifle and suppress a child's abilities or gradually diminish them (due to lack of opportunities to use them) and then expect to see a character that's proactive and consistently dedicated. I understand the importance of inhibition, but simple inhibition is pointless. The only kind of restraint that is valuable is the one that focuses energy on a positive goal. A goal can't be reached unless instincts and urges are kept from being wasted and veering off course. By directing energies towards relevant goals, there is ample opportunity for real inhibition. To claim that inhibition is superior to power is like saying that death is greater than life, negation is greater than affirmation, or sacrifice is greater than service.

(b) We must also test our school work by finding whether it affords the conditions necessary  for the formation of good judgment. Judgment as the sense of relative values involves ability to select, to discriminate. Acquiring information can never develop the power of judgment. Development of judgment is in spite of, not because of, methods of instruction that emphasize simple learning. The test comes only when the information acquired has to be put to use. Will it do what we expect of it? I have heard an educator of large experience say that in her judgment the greatest defect of instruction to-day, on the intellectual side, is found in the fact that children leave school without a mental perspective. Facts seem to them all of the same importance. There is no foreground or background. There is no instinctive habit of sorting out facts upon a scale of worth and of grading them.

(b) We also need to evaluate our schoolwork by checking if it creates the right conditions   for developing good judgment. Judgment, as the understanding of relative values, requires the ability to choose and discern. Simply gaining information will never build the power of judgment. The growth of judgment happens despite, not because of, teaching methods that focus on rote learning. The real test comes when we need to apply the knowledge we've gained. Will it work as we expect? I've heard a seasoned educator say that in her view, the biggest flaw in today's instruction, on the intellectual side, is that kids leave school without a clear mental perspective. To them, all facts seem equally important. There’s no clear distinction between what’s central and what’s background. They lack an instinctive habit of sorting facts based on their value and ranking them accordingly.

The child cannot get power of judgment excepting as he is continually exercised in forming and testing judgments. He must have an opportunity to select for himself, and to attempt to put his selections into execution, that he may submit them to the final test, that of action. Only thus can he learn to discriminate that which promises  success from that which promises failure; only thus can he form the habit of relating his purposes and notions to the conditions that determine their value. Does the school, as a system, afford at present sufficient opportunity for this sort of experimentation? Except so far as the emphasis of the school work is upon intelligent doing, upon active investigation, it does not furnish the conditions necessary for that exercise of judgment which is an integral factor in good character.

The child can't develop his judgment unless he's constantly engaged in making and testing decisions. He needs the chance to choose for himself and to try to carry out those choices so he can put them to the ultimate test: action. Only in this way can he learn to distinguish what might lead to  success from what might lead to failure; only then can he develop the habit of connecting his goals and ideas to the conditions that affect their worth. Does the school, as a system, currently provide enough opportunities for this kind of experimentation? Unless the focus of schoolwork is on thoughtful doing and active exploration, it doesn't create the necessary environment for the exercise of judgment, which is a key part of good character.

(c) I shall be brief with respect to the other point, the need of susceptibility and responsiveness. The informally social side of education, the æsthetic environment and influences, are all-important. In so far as the work is laid out in regular and formulated ways, so far as there are lacking opportunities for casual and free social intercourse between pupils and between the pupils and the teacher, this side of the child’s nature is either starved, or else left to find haphazard expression along more or less secret channels. When the school system, under plea of the practical (meaning by the practical the narrowly utilitarian),  confines the child to the three R’s and the formal studies connected with them, shuts him out from the vital in literature and history, and deprives him of his right to contact with what is best in architecture, music, sculpture, and picture, it is hopeless to expect definite results in the training of sympathetic openness and responsiveness.

(c) I'll be brief regarding the other point, which is the need for sensitivity and responsiveness. The informal social aspect of education, including the aesthetic environment and influences, is crucial. When the curriculum is structured and systematic, and there are limited opportunities for casual and open social interactions among students or between students and teachers, this aspect of a child’s nature is either neglected or left to express itself in random, often hidden ways. When the school system, under the guise of practicality (meaning a narrow, utilitarian approach), confines children to just the three R’s and the formal studies associated with them, cutting them off from the vital experiences in literature and history, and denying them access to the best in architecture, music, sculpture, and art, it’s unrealistic to expect meaningful outcomes in developing their capacity for empathy and responsiveness.

What we need in education is a genuine faith in the existence of moral principles which are capable of effective application. We believe, so far as the mass of children are concerned, that if we keep at them long enough we can teach reading and writing and figuring. We are practically, even if unconsciously, skeptical as to the possibility of anything like the same assurance in morals. We believe in moral laws and rules, to be sure, but they are in the air. They are something set off by themselves. They are so very “moral” that they have no working contact with the average affairs of every-day life. These moral principles need to be brought down to the ground through their statement in social and in psychological  terms. We need to see that moral principles are not arbitrary, that they are not “transcendental”; that the term “moral” does not designate a special region or portion of life. We need to translate the moral into the conditions and forces of our community life, and into the impulses and habits of the individual.

What we need in education is a real belief in the existence of moral principles that can be effectively applied. We believe that, for most children, if we keep at it long enough, we can teach them reading, writing, and math. However, we are, perhaps unconsciously, doubtful about whether we can have the same certainty regarding morals. We believe in moral laws and rules, certainly, but they seem abstract. They exist separately from everyday life. They are so very “moral” that they lack a practical connection to the daily realities we face. These moral principles need to be grounded by expressing them in social and psychological terms. We need to understand that moral principles are not arbitrary; they aren’t “transcendental.” The term “moral” shouldn’t refer to a specific area of life. We need to translate the moral into the dynamics and forces of our community life, as well as into the impulses and habits of individuals.

All the rest is mint, anise, and cummin. The one thing needful is that we recognize that moral principles are real in the same sense in which other forces are real; that they are inherent in community life, and in the working structure of the individual. If we can secure a genuine faith in this fact, we shall have secured the condition which alone is necessary to get from our educational system all the effectiveness there is in it. The teacher who operates in this faith will find every subject, every method of instruction, every incident of school life pregnant with moral possibility.

All the rest is mint, anise, and cumin. The one essential thing is that we recognize that moral principles are real, just like other forces are real; that they are inherent in community life and in the individual's structure. If we can establish a genuine belief in this fact, we will have created the necessary condition to get the full effectiveness out of our educational system. The teacher who works with this conviction will find that every subject, every teaching method, and every incident in school life is full of moral potential.

 OUTLINE

  1. THE MORAL PURPOSE OF THE SCHOOL
    1. Moral ideas and ideas about morality 1
    2. Moral education and direct moral instruction 3
  2. THE MORAL TRAINING GIVEN BY THE SCHOOL COMMUNITY
    1. The unity of social ethics and school ethics 7
    2. A narrow and formal training for citizenship 8
    3. School life should train for many social relations 9
    4. It should train for self-direction and leadership 10
    5. There is no harmonious development of powers apart from social situations 11
    6. School activities should be typical of social life 13
    7. Moral training in the schools tends to be pathological and formal 15
  3. THE MORAL TRAINING FROM METHODS OF INSTRUCTION
    1. Active social service as opposed to passive individual absorption 21
    2. The positive inculcation of individualistic motives and standards 23
    3. The evils of competition for external standing 24
    4. The moral waste of remote success as an end 25
    5. The worth of active and social modes of learning 26
  4.  THE SOCIAL NATURE OF THE COURSE OF STUDY
    1. The nature of the course of study influences the conduct of the school 31
    2. School studies as means of realizing social situations 31
    3. School subjects are merely phases of a unified social life 32
    4. The meaning of subjects is controlled by social considerations 33
    5. Geography deals with the scenes of social interaction 33
    6. Its various forms represent increasing stages of abstraction 34
    7. History is a means for interpreting existing social relations 36
    8. It presents type phases of social development 37
    9. It offers contrasts, and consequently perspective 37
    10. It teaches the methods of social progress 38
    11. The failure of certain methods of teaching history 39
    12. Mathematics is a means to social ends 40
    13. The sociological nature of business arithmetic 41
    14. Summary: The moral trinity of the school 42
  5. THE PSYCHOLOGICAL ASPECT OF MORAL EDUCATION
    1. Conduct as a mode of individual performance 47
    2. Native instincts and impulses are the sources of conduct 47
    3. Moral ideals must be realized in persons 48
    4.  Character as a system of working forces 49
    5. Force as a necessary constituent of character 49
    6. The importance of intellectual judgment or good sense 50
    7. The capacity for delicate emotional responsiveness 52
    8. Summary: The ethical standards for testing the school 53
    9. Conclusion: The practicality of moral principles 57

 RIVERSIDE EDUCATIONAL MONOGRAPHS

  • General Educational Theory
    • Coolidge’s
      Coolidge's
      America’s Need for Education.
    • Dewey’s
      Dewey's
      Interest and Effort in Education.
    • Dewey’s
      Dewey's
      Moral Principles in Education.
    • Eliot’s
      Eliot's
      Education for Efficiency.
    • Eliot’s
      Eliot's
      The Tendency to the Concrete and Practical in Modern Education.
    • Emerson’s
      Emerson's
      Education and other Selections.
    • Fiske’s
      Fiske's
      The Meaning of Infancy.
    • Horne’s
      Horne's
      The Teacher as Artist.
    • Hyde’s
      Hyde's
      The Teacher’s Philosophy in and out of School.
    • Judd’s
      Judd's
      The Evolution of a Democratic School System.
    • Meredith’s
      Meredith's
      The Educational Bearings of Modern Psychology.
    • Palmer’s
      Palmer's
      The Ideal Teacher.
    • Palmer’s
      Palmer's
      Trades and Professions.
    • Palmer’s
      Palmer's
      Ethical and Moral Instruction in Schools.
    • Prosser’s
      Prosser's
      The Teacher and Old Age.
    • Stockton’s
      Stockton's
      Project Work in Education.
    • Stratton’s
      Stratton's
      Developing Mental Power.
    • Terman’s
      Terman's
      The Teacher’s Health.
    • Thorndike’s
      Thorndike’s
      Individuality.
    • Trow’s
      Trow's
      Scientific Method in Education.
  • Administration and Supervision
    • Bett’s
      Bett's
      New Ideals in Rural Schools.
    • Bloomfield’s
      Bloomfield’s
      The Vocational Guidance of Youth.
    • Cabot’s
      Cabot's
      Volunteer Help to the Schools.
    • Cole’s
      Cole's
      Industrial Education in the Elementary School.
    • Cubberley’s
      Cubberley's
      Changing Conceptions of Education.
    • Cubberley’s
      Cubberley's
      The Improvement of Rural Schools.
    • Dooley’s
      Dooley's
      The Education of the Ne’er-Do-Well.
    • Gates’s
      Gates'
      The Management of Smaller Schools.
    • Hines’s
      Hines's
      Measuring Intelligence.
    • Koos’s
      Koos's
      The High-School Principal.
    • Lewis’s
      Lewis's
      Democracy’s High School.
    • Maxwell’s
      Maxwell's
      The Observation of Teaching.
    • Maxwell’s
      Maxwell's
      The Selection of Textbooks.
    • Miller
      Miller
      and
      Charles’s
      Charles's
      Publicity and the Public School.
    • Perry’s
      Perry’s
      The Status of the Teacher.
    •  
      Russell’s
      Russell's
      Economy in Secondary Education.
    • Smith’s
      Smith’s
      Establishing Industrial Schools.
    • Snedden’s
      Snedden’s
      The Problem of Vocational Guidance.
    • Weeks’s
      Weeks's
      The People’s School.
  • Method
    • Andress’s
      Andress's
      The Teaching of Hygiene in the Grades.
    • Atwood’s
      Atwood’s
      The Theory and Practice of the Kindergarten.
    • Bailey’s
      Bailey's
      Art Education.
    • Betts’s
      Betts’
      The Recitation.
    • Cooley’s
      Cooley's
      Language Teaching in the Grades.
    • Dougherty’s
      Dougherty's
      How to Teach Phonics.
    • Earhart’s
      Earhart's
      Teaching Children to Study.
    • Evans’s
      Evans'
      The Teaching of High School Mathematics.
    • Fairchild’s
      Fairchild's
      The Teaching of Poetry in the High School.
    • Freeman’s
      Freeman's
      The Teaching of Handwriting.
    • Haliburton
      Haliburton
      and
      Smith’s
      Smith's
      Teaching Poetry in the Grades.
    • Hartwell’s
      Hartwell's
      The Teaching of History.
    • Hawley’s
      Hawley’s
      Teaching English in Junior High Schools.
    • Haynes’s
      Haynes's
      Economics in the Secondary School.
    • Hill’s
      Hill's
      The Teaching of Civics.
    • Jenkins’s
      Jenkins'
      Reading in the Primary Grades.
    • Kendall
      Kendall
      and
      Stryker’s
      Stryker's
      History in the Elementary School.
    • Kilpatrick’s
      Kilpatrick’s
      The Montessori System Examined.
    • Leonard’s
      Leonard's
      English Composition as a Social Problem.
    • Losh
      Losh
      and
      Weeks’s
      Weeks's
      Primary Number Projects.
    • Palmer’s
      Palmer's
      Self-Cultivation in English.
    • Ridgley’s
      Ridgley’s
      Geographic Principles.
    • Ruediger’s
      Ruediger’s
      Vitalized Teaching.
    • Sharp’s
      Sharp's
      Teaching English in High Schools.
    • Stockton’s
      Stockton's
      Project Work in Education.
    • Suzzallo’s
      Suzzallo's University Library
      The Teaching of Primary Arithmetic.
    • Suzzallo’s
      Suzzallo Library
      The Teaching of Spelling.
    • Swift’s
      Swift's
      Speech Defects in School Children.
    • Tuell’s
      Tuell's
      The Study of Nations.
    • Wilson’
      Wilson's
      s What Arithmetic Shall We Teach?

HOUGHTON MIFFLIN COMPANY

HOUGHTON MIFFLIN COMPANY


Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!