This is a modern-English version of Relativity: The Special and General Theory, originally written by Einstein, Albert. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.

cover

Relativity: The Special and General Theory

by Albert Einstein

Authorised Translation by Robert W. Lawson


ALBERT EINSTEIN REFERENCE ARCHIVE

ALBERT EINSTEIN REFERENCE ARCHIVE

RELATIVITY: THE SPECIAL AND GENERAL THEORY

RELATIVITY: THE SPECIAL AND GENERAL THEORY

BY ALBERT EINSTEIN

BY ALBERT EINSTEIN

Written: 1916 (this revised edition: 1924)

Written: 1916 (this updated edition: 1924)

Source: Relativity: The Special and General Theory (1920)

Source: Relativity: The Special and General Theory (1920)

Publisher: Methuen & Co Ltd

Publisher: Methuen & Co Ltd

First Published: December, 1916

First Published: December 1916

Translated: Robert W. Lawson (Authorised translation)

Translated: Robert W. Lawson (Authorized translation)

Transcription/Markup: Brian Basgen

Transcription/Markup: Brian Basgen

Transcription to text: Gregory B. Newby

Transcription to text: Gregory B. Newby

Thanks to: Einstein Reference Archive (marxists.org)

Thanks to: Einstein Reference Archive (marxists.org)

The Einstein Reference Archive is online at:

The Einstein Reference Archive is available online at:

http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/einstein/index.htm

http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/einstein/index.htm

Contents

Preface

Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity
I. Physical Meaning of Geometrical Propositions
II. The System of Co-ordinates
III. Space and Time in Classical Mechanics
IV. The Galileian System of Co-ordinates
V. The Principle of Relativity (in the Restricted Sense)
VI. The Theorem of the Addition of Velocities employed in Classical Mechanics
VII. The Apparent Incompatability of the Law of Propagation of Light with the Principle of Relativity
VIII. On the Idea of Time in Physics
IX. The Relativity of Simultaneity
X. On the Relativity of the Conception of Distance
XI. The Lorentz Transformation
XII. The Behaviour of Measuring-Rods and Clocks in Motion
XIII. Theorem of the Addition of Velocities. The Experiment of Fizeau
XIV. The Heuristic Value of the Theory of Relativity
XV. General Results of the Theory
XVI. Experience and the Special Theory of Relativity
XVII. Minkowski’s Four-dimensional Space

Part II: The General Theory of Relativity
XVIII. Special and General Principle of Relativity
XIX. The Gravitational Field
XX. The Equality of Inertial and Gravitational Mass as an Argument for the General Postulate of Relativity
XXI. In What Respects are the Foundations of Classical Mechanics and of the Special Theory of Relativity Unsatisfactory?
XXII. A Few Inferences from the General Principle of Relativity
XXIII. Behaviour of Clocks and Measuring-Rods on a Rotating Body of Reference
XXIV. Euclidean and non-Euclidean Continuum
XXV. Gaussian Co-ordinates
XXVI. The Space-Time Continuum of the Special Theory of Relativity Considered as a Euclidean Continuum
XXVII. The Space-Time Continuum of the General Theory of Relativity is Not a Euclidean Continuum
XXVIII. Exact Formulation of the General Principle of Relativity
XXIX. The Solution of the Problem of Gravitation on the Basis of the General Principle of Relativity

Part III: Considerations on the Universe as a Whole
XXX. Cosmological Difficulties of Newton’s Theory
XXXI. The Possibility of a “Finite” and yet “Unbounded” Universe
XXXII. The Structure of Space According to the General Theory of Relativity

Appendices:
I. Simple Derivation of the Lorentz Transformation (supplementary to section XI)
II. Minkowski’s Four-Dimensional Space (“World”) (supplementary to section XVII)
III. The Experimental Confirmation of the General Theory of Relativity
IV. The Structure of Space According to the General Theory of Relativity (supplementary to section XXXII)
V. Relativity and the Problem of Space

Note: The fifth Appendix was added by Einstein at the time of the fifteenth re-printing of this book; and as a result is still under copyright restrictions so cannot be added without the permission of the publisher.

Note: The fifth Appendix was added by Einstein during the fifteenth re-printing of this book; therefore, it is still under copyright restrictions and cannot be included without the publisher's permission.

PREFACE

The present book is intended, as far as possible, to give an exact insight into the theory of Relativity to those readers who, from a general scientific and philosophical point of view, are interested in the theory, but who are not conversant with the mathematical apparatus of theoretical physics. The work presumes a standard of education corresponding to that of a university matriculation examination, and, despite the shortness of the book, a fair amount of patience and force of will on the part of the reader. The author has spared himself no pains in his endeavour to present the main ideas in the simplest and most intelligible form, and on the whole, in the sequence and connection in which they actually originated. In the interest of clearness, it appeared to me inevitable that I should repeat myself frequently, without paying the slightest attention to the elegance of the presentation. I adhered scrupulously to the precept of that brilliant theoretical physicist L. Boltzmann, according to whom matters of elegance ought to be left to the tailor and to the cobbler. I make no pretence of having withheld from the reader difficulties which are inherent to the subject. On the other hand, I have purposely treated the empirical physical foundations of the theory in a “step-motherly” fashion, so that readers unfamiliar with physics may not feel like the wanderer who was unable to see the forest for the trees. May the book bring some one a few happy hours of suggestive thought!

The current book aims to provide a clear understanding of the theory of Relativity to readers who are generally interested in the topic from a scientific and philosophical standpoint but aren't familiar with the math involved in theoretical physics. It assumes an educational background equivalent to a university entrance exam, and despite being a short book, it requires a good amount of patience and determination from the reader. The author has worked hard to present the main ideas in the simplest and most understandable way, following the order and connections in which they originally developed. For clarity's sake, I've found it necessary to repeat myself often, without worrying too much about how polished it sounds. I adhered strictly to the advice of the brilliant theoretical physicist L. Boltzmann, who stated that concerns about elegance are best left to tailors and cobblers. I don't pretend to have shielded the reader from the inherent challenges of the subject. However, I have intentionally given less attention to the empirical physical foundations of the theory, so that those unfamiliar with physics won't feel like someone lost in the woods. I hope this book provides its readers with some enjoyable moments of thoughtful reflection!

December, 1916

December 1916

A. EINSTEIN

A. EINSTEIN

PART I: THE SPECIAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY

I.
PHYSICAL MEANING OF GEOMETRICAL PROPOSITIONS

In your schooldays most of you who read this book made acquaintance with the noble building of Euclid’s geometry, and you remember—perhaps with more respect than love—the magnificent structure, on the lofty staircase of which you were chased about for uncounted hours by conscientious teachers. By reason of our past experience, you would certainly regard everyone with disdain who should pronounce even the most out-of-the-way proposition of this science to be untrue. But perhaps this feeling of proud certainty would leave you immediately if some one were to ask you: “What, then, do you mean by the assertion that these propositions are true?” Let us proceed to give this question a little consideration.

In your school days, most of you who read this book became familiar with the impressive world of Euclid’s geometry, and you probably remember—maybe with more respect than affection—the grand structure where dedicated teachers chased you up and down the long staircase for countless hours. Because of our past experiences, you would likely look down on anyone who dared to claim even the most obscure idea in this field was false. But maybe this sense of confident pride would fade instantly if someone were to ask you: “What do you mean when you say these statements are true?” Let’s take a moment to think about this question.

Geometry sets out from certain conceptions such as “plane,” “point,” and “straight line,” with which we are able to associate more or less definite ideas, and from certain simple propositions (axioms) which, in virtue of these ideas, we are inclined to accept as “true.” Then, on the basis of a logical process, the justification of which we feel ourselves compelled to admit, all remaining propositions are shown to follow from those axioms, i.e. they are proven. A proposition is then correct (“true”) when it has been derived in the recognised manner from the axioms. The question of “truth” of the individual geometrical propositions is thus reduced to one of the “truth” of the axioms. Now it has long been known that the last question is not only unanswerable by the methods of geometry, but that it is in itself entirely without meaning. We cannot ask whether it is true that only one straight line goes through two points. We can only say that Euclidean geometry deals with things called “straight lines,” to each of which is ascribed the property of being uniquely determined by two points situated on it. The concept “true” does not tally with the assertions of pure geometry, because by the word “true” we are eventually in the habit of designating always the correspondence with a “real” object; geometry, however, is not concerned with the relation of the ideas involved in it to objects of experience, but only with the logical connection of these ideas among themselves.

Geometry starts with certain concepts like “plane,” “point,” and “straight line,” which we can associate with fairly clear ideas, along with some basic propositions (axioms) that we tend to accept as “true” based on these ideas. Then, through a logical process that we feel we must acknowledge, all other propositions are shown to stem from those axioms, meaning they are proven. A proposition is considered correct (“true”) when it has been derived in the accepted way from the axioms. Therefore, the question of whether individual geometric propositions are “true” comes down to the “truth” of the axioms. It has long been recognized that this last question cannot be answered using the methods of geometry and that it is, in fact, meaningless. We cannot ask whether it is true that only one straight line passes through two points. We can only state that Euclidean geometry concerns itself with entities called “straight lines,” each of which is described as being uniquely determined by two points on it. The term “true” does not align with the statements of pure geometry, because we usually use “true” to refer to a correspondence with a “real” object; however, geometry is not focused on the relationship between the ideas it involves and objects of experience, but rather on the logical connections among these ideas themselves.

It is not difficult to understand why, in spite of this, we feel constrained to call the propositions of geometry “true.” Geometrical ideas correspond to more or less exact objects in nature, and these last are undoubtedly the exclusive cause of the genesis of those ideas. Geometry ought to refrain from such a course, in order to give to its structure the largest possible logical unity. The practice, for example, of seeing in a “distance” two marked positions on a practically rigid body is something which is lodged deeply in our habit of thought. We are accustomed further to regard three points as being situated on a straight line, if their apparent positions can be made to coincide for observation with one eye, under suitable choice of our place of observation.

It’s easy to see why we still feel the need to call geometric propositions “true.” Geometric concepts match pretty closely with actual objects in nature, and those objects are clearly the main reason these ideas exist. Geometry should avoid taking this path to maintain the strongest possible logical coherence. For instance, the practice of seeing a “distance” as two distinct points on a mostly rigid object is deeply ingrained in our way of thinking. We also tend to view three points as being on a straight line if their apparent positions can line up for observation with one eye, depending on where we’re looking from.

If, in pursuance of our habit of thought, we now supplement the propositions of Euclidean geometry by the single proposition that two points on a practically rigid body always correspond to the same distance (line-interval), independently of any changes in position to which we may subject the body, the propositions of Euclidean geometry then resolve themselves into propositions on the possible relative position of practically rigid bodies.[1] Geometry which has been supplemented in this way is then to be treated as a branch of physics. We can now legitimately ask as to the “truth” of geometrical propositions interpreted in this way, since we are justified in asking whether these propositions are satisfied for those real things we have associated with the geometrical ideas. In less exact terms we can express this by saying that by the “truth” of a geometrical proposition in this sense we understand its validity for a construction with rule and compasses.

If we follow our usual way of thinking, and we add the idea that the distance between two points on a nearly rigid object always remains the same, no matter how we move that object, then the ideas of Euclidean geometry can be understood as statements about the possible relative positions of nearly rigid objects. This updated geometry should be treated as a branch of physics. We can now reasonably question the “truth” of these geometric statements as we've interpreted them, since it's valid to ask if these statements hold true for the real objects we've linked to the geometrical concepts. In simpler terms, we can say that by the “truth” of a geometric statement in this context, we mean its validity for a construction using a straightedge and compass.

[1]
It follows that a natural object is associated also with a straight line. Three points A, B and C on a rigid body thus lie in a straight line when the points A and C being given, B is chosen such that the sum of the distances AB and BC is as short as possible. This incomplete suggestion will suffice for the present purpose.

[1]
It follows that a natural object is also linked to a straight line. Three points A, B, and C on a rigid body lie in a straight line when the points A and C are given, and B is selected so that the total distances AB and BC are minimized. This brief suggestion will be enough for our current needs.

Of course the conviction of the “truth” of geometrical propositions in this sense is founded exclusively on rather incomplete experience. For the present we shall assume the “truth” of the geometrical propositions, then at a later stage (in the general theory of relativity) we shall see that this “truth” is limited, and we shall consider the extent of its limitation.

Of course, the belief in the “truth” of geometric propositions is based purely on somewhat incomplete experience. For now, we will assume the “truth” of these geometric propositions, but later on (in the general theory of relativity), we will discover that this “truth” has its limits, and we will examine how far those limits go.

II.
THE SYSTEM OF CO-ORDINATES

On the basis of the physical interpretation of distance which has been indicated, we are also in a position to establish the distance between two points on a rigid body by means of measurements. For this purpose we require a “distance” (rod S) which is to be used once and for all, and which we employ as a standard measure. If, now, A and B are two points on a rigid body, we can construct the line joining them according to the rules of geometry; then, starting from A, we can mark off the distance S time after time until we reach B. The number of these operations required is the numerical measure of the distance AB. This is the basis of all measurement of length.[2]

Based on the physical interpretation of distance mentioned earlier, we can determine the distance between two points on a rigid body through measurements. To do this, we need a “distance” (rod S) that we will use consistently as a standard measure. If A and B are two points on a rigid body, we can draw the line connecting them using geometric rules; then, starting from A, we can measure out the distance S repeatedly until we reach B. The number of times we perform this operation gives us the numerical measure of the distance AB. This is the foundation of all length measurements.[2]

[2]
Here we have assumed that there is nothing left over i.e. that the measurement gives a whole number. This difficulty is got over by the use of divided measuring-rods, the introduction of which does not demand any fundamentally new method.

[2]
Here we assume that there’s nothing remaining, i.e. that the measurement results in a whole number. This issue is resolved by using divided measuring rods, whose introduction doesn’t require any fundamentally new method.

Every description of the scene of an event or of the position of an object in space is based on the specification of the point on a rigid body (body of reference) with which that event or object coincides. This applies not only to scientific description, but also to everyday life. If I analyse the place specification “Trafalgar Square, London”[3] I arrive at the following result. The earth is the rigid body to which the specification of place refers; “Trafalgar Square, London” is a well-defined point, to which a name has been assigned, and with which the event coincides in space.[4]

Every description of a scene or the location of an object in space relies on identifying a specific point on a solid object (reference body) that coincides with that scene or object. This applies not just in scientific contexts but also in everyday life. If I break down the location "Trafalgar Square, London"[3], I come to this conclusion: the Earth is the solid object referred to in the location specification; "Trafalgar Square, London" is a clearly defined point that has been given a name, which corresponds to the event in space.[4]

[3]
I have chosen this as being more familiar to the English reader than the “Potzdammer Platz, Berlin,” which is referred to in the original. (R. W. L.)

[3]
I have picked this because it's more familiar to English readers than the “Potsdamer Platz, Berlin,” mentioned in the original. (R. W. L.)

[4]
It is not necessary here to investigate further the significance of the expression “coincidence in space.” This conception is sufficiently obvious to ensure that differences of opinion are scarcely likely to arise as to its applicability in practice.

[4]
There's no need to dig deeper into what "coincidence in space" means. This idea is pretty clear, so it's unlikely that there will be differing opinions about how it applies in real life.

This primitive method of place specification deals only with places on the surface of rigid bodies, and is dependent on the existence of points on this surface which are distinguishable from each other. But we can free ourselves from both of these limitations without altering the nature of our specification of position. If, for instance, a cloud is hovering over Trafalgar Square, then we can determine its position relative to the surface of the earth by erecting a pole perpendicularly on the Square, so that it reaches the cloud. The length of the pole measured with the standard measuring-rod, combined with the specification of the position of the foot of the pole, supplies us with a complete place specification. On the basis of this illustration, we are able to see the manner in which a refinement of the conception of position has been developed.

This basic way of specifying locations only applies to points on the surface of solid objects and relies on having distinguishable points on that surface. However, we can overcome both of these limitations without changing how we define position. For example, if a cloud is hovering over Trafalgar Square, we can find its position in relation to the Earth's surface by putting up a pole vertically on the Square that reaches the cloud. The length of the pole, measured with a standard measuring stick, along with the location of the base of the pole, gives us complete information about the location. This example shows how our understanding of position has been refined.

(a) We imagine the rigid body, to which the place specification is referred, supplemented in such a manner that the object whose position we require is reached by the completed rigid body.

(a) We envision the rigid body, to which the location specification pertains, enhanced in such a way that the object whose position we need is accessed by the completed rigid body.

(b) In locating the position of the object, we make use of a number (here the length of the pole measured with the measuring-rod) instead of designated points of reference.

(b) To find the position of the object, we use a number (in this case, the length of the pole measured with the measuring rod) instead of specific points of reference.

(c) We speak of the height of the cloud even when the pole which reaches the cloud has not been erected. By means of optical observations of the cloud from different positions on the ground, and taking into account the properties of the propagation of light, we determine the length of the pole we should have required in order to reach the cloud.

(c) We talk about the height of the cloud even when the pole reaching it hasn't been set up. Through optical observations of the cloud from various points on the ground, and considering how light travels, we figure out how long the pole would need to be to reach the cloud.

From this consideration we see that it will be advantageous if, in the description of position, it should be possible by means of numerical measures to make ourselves independent of the existence of marked positions (possessing names) on the rigid body of reference. In the physics of measurement this is attained by the application of the Cartesian system of co-ordinates.

From this perspective, it’s clear that it would be beneficial if, when describing position, we could rely on numerical measures to become independent of specific marked positions (with names) on the reference rigid body. In measurement physics, this is achieved through the use of the Cartesian coordinate system.

This consists of three plane surfaces perpendicular to each other and rigidly attached to a rigid body. Referred to a system of co-ordinates, the scene of any event will be determined (for the main part) by the specification of the lengths of the three perpendiculars or co-ordinates (x, y, z) which can be dropped from the scene of the event to those three plane surfaces. The lengths of these three perpendiculars can be determined by a series of manipulations with rigid measuring-rods performed according to the rules and methods laid down by Euclidean geometry.

This consists of three flat surfaces that are at right angles to each other and firmly attached to a solid object. In relation to a coordinate system, the details of any event will mainly be determined by specifying the lengths of the three perpendiculars or coordinates (x, y, z) that can be measured from the event location to those three flat surfaces. The lengths of these three perpendiculars can be found using a series of measurements with rigid measuring sticks, following the rules and techniques established by Euclidean geometry.

In practice, the rigid surfaces which constitute the system of co-ordinates are generally not available; furthermore, the magnitudes of the co-ordinates are not actually determined by constructions with rigid rods, but by indirect means. If the results of physics and astronomy are to maintain their clearness, the physical meaning of specifications of position must always be sought in accordance with the above considerations.[5]

In reality, the rigid surfaces that make up the coordinate system are usually not accessible; in addition, the values of the coordinates are not actually established using rigid rods, but rather by indirect methods. To keep the results of physics and astronomy clear, we must always look for the physical meaning of position specifications based on these considerations.[5]

[5]
A refinement and modification of these views does not become necessary until we come to deal with the general theory of relativity, treated in the second part of this book.

[5]
We only need to refine and modify these views when we discuss the general theory of relativity, which is covered in the second part of this book.

We thus obtain the following result: Every description of events in space involves the use of a rigid body to which such events have to be referred. The resulting relationship takes for granted that the laws of Euclidean geometry hold for “distances;” the “distance” being represented physically by means of the convention of two marks on a rigid body.

We can therefore conclude the following: Every way we describe events in space requires a solid object to which those events are linked. This relationship assumes that the laws of Euclidean geometry apply to "distances," with "distance" being physically represented through the convention of two marks on a solid object.

III.
SPACE AND TIME IN CLASSICAL MECHANICS

The purpose of mechanics is to describe how bodies change their position in space with “time.” I should load my conscience with grave sins against the sacred spirit of lucidity were I to formulate the aims of mechanics in this way, without serious reflection and detailed explanations. Let us proceed to disclose these sins.

The purpose of mechanics is to explain how objects move through space over "time." I would be burdening my conscience with serious offenses against the sacred spirit of clarity if I were to state the goals of mechanics this way, without careful thought and thorough explanations. Let's move on to reveal these offenses.

It is not clear what is to be understood here by “position” and “space.” I stand at the window of a railway carriage which is travelling uniformly, and drop a stone on the embankment, without throwing it. Then, disregarding the influence of the air resistance, I see the stone descend in a straight line. A pedestrian who observes the misdeed from the footpath notices that the stone falls to earth in a parabolic curve. I now ask: Do the “positions” traversed by the stone lie “in reality” on a straight line or on a parabola? Moreover, what is meant here by motion “in space”? From the considerations of the previous section the answer is self-evident. In the first place we entirely shun the vague word “space,” of which, we must honestly acknowledge, we cannot form the slightest conception, and we replace it by “motion relative to a practically rigid body of reference.” The positions relative to the body of reference (railway carriage or embankment) have already been defined in detail in the preceding section. If instead of “body of reference” we insert “system of co-ordinates,” which is a useful idea for mathematical description, we are in a position to say: The stone traverses a straight line relative to a system of co-ordinates rigidly attached to the carriage, but relative to a system of co-ordinates rigidly attached to the ground (embankment) it describes a parabola. With the aid of this example it is clearly seen that there is no such thing as an independently existing trajectory (lit. “path-curve”[6], but only a trajectory relative to a particular body of reference.

It's not clear what we mean by "position" and "space" here. I'm standing at the window of a train that's moving smoothly, and I drop a stone onto the bank without tossing it. Ignoring air resistance, I see the stone fall straight down. A passerby on the sidewalk sees the stone fall in a curved path. I now ask: Do the "positions" the stone travels through actually form a straight line or a curve? Also, what do we mean by motion "in space"? From the discussions in the previous section, the answer is obvious. First, we avoid the vague term "space," which, to be honest, we can't fully grasp, and instead use "motion relative to a practically rigid reference body." The positions relative to the reference body (the train or the bank) have already been defined in detail in the earlier section. If we replace "reference body" with "coordinate system," which is useful for mathematical descriptions, we can say: The stone travels in a straight line relative to a coordinate system firmly attached to the train, but relative to a coordinate system firmly attached to the ground (the bank), it follows a parabolic path. This example clearly shows that there is no such thing as a trajectory that exists independently (literally "path-curve"[6]), but only a trajectory relative to a specific reference body.

[6]
That is, a curve along which the body moves.

[6]
In other words, a path that the body follows.

In order to have a complete description of the motion, we must specify how the body alters its position with time; i.e. for every point on the trajectory it must be stated at what time the body is situated there. These data must be supplemented by such a definition of time that, in virtue of this definition, these time-values can be regarded essentially as magnitudes (results of measurements) capable of observation. If we take our stand on the ground of classical mechanics, we can satisfy this requirement for our illustration in the following manner. We imagine two clocks of identical construction; the man at the railway-carriage window is holding one of them, and the man on the footpath the other. Each of the observers determines the position on his own reference-body occupied by the stone at each tick of the clock he is holding in his hand. In this connection we have not taken account of the inaccuracy involved by the finiteness of the velocity of propagation of light. With this and with a second difficulty prevailing here we shall have to deal in detail later.

To have a complete description of motion, we need to specify how the body changes its position over time; i.e. for every point on the path, we must indicate the time at which the body is located there. This information must be accompanied by a definition of time that allows these time values to be viewed essentially as quantities (results of measurements) that can be observed. If we base our analysis on classical mechanics, we can demonstrate this requirement as follows. We imagine two identical clocks; the person by the train window is holding one, and the person on the sidewalk has the other. Each observer notes the position of the stone on their reference body at each tick of their respective clock. In this context, we have not considered the inaccuracies due to the finite speed of light. We will address this and another complication in detail later.

IV.
THE GALILEIAN SYSTEM OF CO-ORDINATES

As is well known, the fundamental law of the mechanics of Galilei-Newton, which is known as the law of inertia, can be stated thus: A body removed sufficiently far from other bodies continues in a state of rest or of uniform motion in a straight line. This law not only says something about the motion of the bodies, but it also indicates the reference-bodies or systems of coordinates, permissible in mechanics, which can be used in mechanical description. The visible fixed stars are bodies for which the law of inertia certainly holds to a high degree of approximation. Now if we use a system of co-ordinates which is rigidly attached to the earth, then, relative to this system, every fixed star describes a circle of immense radius in the course of an astronomical day, a result which is opposed to the statement of the law of inertia. So that if we adhere to this law we must refer these motions only to systems of coordinates relative to which the fixed stars do not move in a circle. A system of co-ordinates of which the state of motion is such that the law of inertia holds relative to it is called a “Galileian system of co-ordinates.” The laws of the mechanics of Galilei-Newton can be regarded as valid only for a Galileian system of co-ordinates.

As is well known, the basic principle of the mechanics established by Galileo and Newton, known as the law of inertia, can be stated as follows: A body that is far enough away from other bodies will remain at rest or continue to move in a straight line at a constant speed. This law not only describes the motion of objects but also defines the reference bodies or coordinate systems that are acceptable in mechanics for mechanical descriptions. The visible fixed stars are entities for which the law of inertia holds true to a high degree of accuracy. If we use a coordinate system that is firmly attached to the Earth, then, relative to this system, every fixed star seems to trace out a circle of enormous radius over the course of an astronomical day, which contradicts the statement of the law of inertia. Therefore, if we stick to this law, we can only consider these motions in relation to coordinate systems where the fixed stars do not move in a circle. A coordinate system for which the law of inertia applies is called a “Galileian system of coordinates.” The laws of mechanics established by Galileo and Newton can be considered valid only within a Galileian coordinate system.

V.
THE PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY (IN THE RESTRICTED SENSE)

In order to attain the greatest possible clearness, let us return to our example of the railway carriage supposed to be travelling uniformly. We call its motion a uniform translation (“uniform” because it is of constant velocity and direction, “translation” because although the carriage changes its position relative to the embankment yet it does not rotate in so doing). Let us imagine a raven flying through the air in such a manner that its motion, as observed from the embankment, is uniform and in a straight line. If we were to observe the flying raven from the moving railway carriage. we should find that the motion of the raven would be one of different velocity and direction, but that it would still be uniform and in a straight line. Expressed in an abstract manner we may say: If a mass m is moving uniformly in a straight line with respect to a co-ordinate system K, then it will also be moving uniformly and in a straight line relative to a second co-ordinate system K′ provided that the latter is executing a uniform translatory motion with respect to K. In accordance with the discussion contained in the preceding section, it follows that:

To achieve the clearest understanding, let's go back to our example of a train carriage that's moving at a constant speed. We call its motion a uniform translation ("uniform" because it has a steady speed and direction, "translation" because, while the carriage is changing its position relative to the ground, it isn't rotating). Now, imagine a raven flying through the air in such a way that, from the perspective of the ground, its motion appears straight and consistent. If we were to observe the flying raven from the moving train carriage, we would see that the raven's motion would have a different speed and direction, but it would still be straight and consistent. To put it simply: If a mass m is moving uniformly in a straight line with respect to a coordinate system K, then it will also move uniformly and in a straight line relative to another coordinate system K′ as long as that system is also moving at a constant speed in relation to K. Based on the discussion in the previous section, it follows that:

If K is a Galileian co-ordinate system. then every other co-ordinate system K′ is a Galileian one, when, in relation to K, it is in a condition of uniform motion of translation. Relative to K′ the mechanical laws of Galilei-Newton hold good exactly as they do with respect to K.

If K is a Galilean coordinate system, then any other coordinate system K′ is also Galilean if it is in a state of uniform translation relative to K. With respect to K′, the mechanical laws of Galilei-Newton apply just as they do with K.

We advance a step farther in our generalisation when we express the tenet thus: If, relative to K, K′ is a uniformly moving co-ordinate system devoid of rotation, then natural phenomena run their course with respect to K′ according to exactly the same general laws as with respect to K. This statement is called the principle of relativity (in the restricted sense).

We take a further step in our generalization when we state the idea like this: If, relative to K, K′ is a coordinate system that moves uniformly without rotation, then natural phenomena occur in K′ according to the same general laws as they do in K. This statement is known as the principle of relativity (in the restricted sense).

As long as one was convinced that all natural phenomena were capable of representation with the help of classical mechanics, there was no need to doubt the validity of this principle of relativity. But in view of the more recent development of electrodynamics and optics it became more and more evident that classical mechanics affords an insufficient foundation for the physical description of all natural phenomena. At this juncture the question of the validity of the principle of relativity became ripe for discussion, and it did not appear impossible that the answer to this question might be in the negative.

As long as people believed that all natural events could be explained using classical mechanics, there was no reason to question the validity of the principle of relativity. However, with the recent advances in electrodynamics and optics, it became increasingly clear that classical mechanics does not provide a strong enough basis for fully describing natural phenomena. At this point, the validity of the principle of relativity was ready for debate, and it seemed possible that the answer to this question could be no.

Nevertheless, there are two general facts which at the outset speak very much in favour of the validity of the principle of relativity. Even though classical mechanics does not supply us with a sufficiently broad basis for the theoretical presentation of all physical phenomena, still we must grant it a considerable measure of “truth,” since it supplies us with the actual motions of the heavenly bodies with a delicacy of detail little short of wonderful. The principle of relativity must therefore apply with great accuracy in the domain of mechanics. But that a principle of such broad generality should hold with such exactness in one domain of phenomena, and yet should be invalid for another, is a priori not very probable.

Nevertheless, there are two main points that strongly support the validity of the principle of relativity. Even though classical mechanics doesn't provide a sufficiently broad foundation for fully explaining all physical phenomena, we still have to acknowledge that it has a significant amount of “truth,” as it accurately describes the movements of heavenly bodies with impressive detail. Therefore, the principle of relativity must be applicable with high precision in the realm of mechanics. However, it seems unlikely that a principle so broadly applicable could be accurate in one area of study while being invalid in another.

We now proceed to the second argument, to which, moreover, we shall return later. If the principle of relativity (in the restricted sense) does not hold, then the Galileian co-ordinate systems K, K′, K″, etc., which are moving uniformly relative to each other, will not be equivalent for the description of natural phenomena. In this case we should be constrained to believe that natural laws are capable of being formulated in a particularly simple manner, and of course only on condition that, from amongst all possible Galileian co-ordinate systems, we should have chosen one (K0) of a particular state of motion as our body of reference. We should then be justified (because of its merits for the description of natural phenomena) in calling this system “absolutely at rest,” and all other Galileian systems K “in motion.” If, for instance, our embankment were the system K0 then our railway carriage would be a system K, relative to which less simple laws would hold than with respect to K0. This diminished simplicity would be due to the fact that the carriage K would be in motion (i.e. “really”)with respect to K0. In the general laws of nature which have been formulated with reference to K, the magnitude and direction of the velocity of the carriage would necessarily play a part. We should expect, for instance, that the note emitted by an organpipe placed with its axis parallel to the direction of travel would be different from that emitted if the axis of the pipe were placed perpendicular to this direction.

We now move on to the second argument, which we will revisit later. If the principle of relativity (in the limited sense) doesn’t hold, then the Galilean coordinate systems K, K′, K″, etc., which are moving uniformly relative to each other, won’t be equivalent for describing natural phenomena. In that case, we would have to believe that natural laws can be expressed in a particularly straightforward way, but only if we choose one specific Galilean coordinate system (K0) to serve as our reference point. We could then rightfully call this system “absolutely at rest” and label all other Galilean systems K as “in motion.” For example, if our embankment is system K0, then our railway carriage would be a system K, for which the laws would be less straightforward compared to those with respect to K0. This reduced simplicity would arise because the carriage K would be moving (“really”) in relation to K0. In the general laws of nature formulated with reference to K, the speed and direction of the carriage would need to be considered. For instance, we would expect that the sound produced by an organ pipe placed with its axis parallel to the direction of travel would differ from that produced if the axis of the pipe were perpendicular to that direction.

Now in virtue of its motion in an orbit round the sun, our earth is comparable with a railway carriage travelling with a velocity of about 30 kilometres per second. If the principle of relativity were not valid we should therefore expect that the direction of motion of the earth at any moment would enter into the laws of nature, and also that physical systems in their behaviour would be dependent on the orientation in space with respect to the earth. For owing to the alteration in direction of the velocity of revolution of the earth in the course of a year, the earth cannot be at rest relative to the hypothetical system K0 throughout the whole year. However, the most careful observations have never revealed such anisotropic properties in terrestrial physical space, i.e. a physical non-equivalence of different directions. This is very powerful argument in favour of the principle of relativity.

Due to its motion in an orbit around the sun, our earth can be compared to a train traveling at about 30 kilometers per second. If the principle of relativity didn't hold true, we would expect that the Earth's direction of motion at any moment would influence the laws of nature and that physical systems would behave differently based on their orientation in space with respect to the Earth. Because the direction of the Earth's orbital velocity changes throughout the year, the Earth cannot be considered stationary relative to the hypothetical system K0 all year long. However, meticulous observations have never shown any differences in terrestrial physical space, i.e. a physical inequality of different directions. This is a strong argument in favor of the principle of relativity.

VI.
THE THEOREM OF THE ADDITION OF VELOCITIES EMPLOYED IN CLASSICAL MECHANICS

Let us suppose our old friend the railway carriage to be travelling along the rails with a constant velocity v, and that a man traverses the length of the carriage in the direction of travel with a velocity w. How quickly or, in other words, with what velocity W does the man advance relative to the embankment during the process? The only possible answer seems to result from the following consideration: If the man were to stand still for a second, he would advance relative to the embankment through a distance v equal numerically to the velocity of the carriage. As a consequence of his walking, however, he traverses an additional distance w relative to the carriage, and hence also relative to the embankment, in this second, the distance w being numerically equal to the velocity with which he is walking. Thus in total he covers the distance W = v + w relative to the embankment in the second considered. We shall see later that this result, which expresses the theorem of the addition of velocities employed in classical mechanics, cannot be maintained; in other words, the law that we have just written down does not hold in reality. For the time being, however, we shall assume its correctness.

Let’s assume our old friend, the train carriage, is traveling along the tracks at a constant speed v, and a man is walking the length of the carriage in the direction it's moving at a speed w. How fast, or in other words, what speed W does the man move relative to the ground during this time? The only answer seems to come from this idea: If the man were to stand still for a second, he would move relative to the ground a distance v, equal to the speed of the carriage. Because he is walking, he covers an additional distance w relative to the carriage, and therefore also relative to the ground, in this second, with w being equal to his walking speed. So altogether, he covers the distance W = v + w relative to the ground in that second. We will see later that this result, which represents the theorem of adding speeds used in classical mechanics, isn’t actually correct; in other words, the law we’ve just laid out doesn't hold in reality. For now, though, we’ll assume it is accurate.

VII.
THE APPARENT INCOMPATIBILITY OF THE LAW OF PROPAGATION OF LIGHT WITH THE PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY

There is hardly a simpler law in physics than that according to which light is propagated in empty space. Every child at school knows, or believes he knows, that this propagation takes place in straight lines with a velocity c = 300,000 km./sec. At all events we know with great exactness that this velocity is the same for all colours, because if this were not the case, the minimum of emission would not be observed simultaneously for different colours during the eclipse of a fixed star by its dark neighbour. By means of similar considerations based on observations of double stars, the Dutch astronomer De Sitter was also able to show that the velocity of propagation of light cannot depend on the velocity of motion of the body emitting the light. The assumption that this velocity of propagation is dependent on the direction “in space” is in itself improbable.

There’s probably no simpler law in physics than how light travels in empty space. Every kid in school knows, or thinks they know, that this travel happens in straight lines at a speed of c = 300,000 km/s. In any case, we know with great accuracy that this speed is the same for all colors. If it weren’t, we wouldn’t observe the minimum emission happening simultaneously for different colors during a fixed star’s eclipse by its dark neighbor. Through similar reasoning based on observations of double stars, the Dutch astronomer De Sitter also demonstrated that the speed of light doesn’t depend on the speed of the object emitting it. It’s also unlikely that this speed is affected by direction “in space.”

In short, let us assume that the simple law of the constancy of the velocity of light c (in vacuum) is justifiably believed by the child at school. Who would imagine that this simple law has plunged the conscientiously thoughtful physicist into the greatest intellectual difficulties? Let us consider how these difficulties arise.

In short, let's assume that the basic principle of the constant speed of light c (in a vacuum) is something a schoolchild reasonably believes. Who would have thought that this simple principle has caused the most significant intellectual challenges for serious physicists? Let’s look at how these challenges come about.

Of course we must refer the process of the propagation of light (and indeed every other process) to a rigid reference-body (co-ordinate system). As such a system let us again choose our embankment. We shall imagine the air above it to have been removed. If a ray of light be sent along the embankment, we see from the above that the tip of the ray will be transmitted with the velocity c relative to the embankment. Now let us suppose that our railway carriage is again travelling along the railway lines with the velocity v, and that its direction is the same as that of the ray of light, but its velocity of course much less. Let us inquire about the velocity of propagation of the ray of light relative to the carriage. It is obvious that we can here apply the consideration of the previous section, since the ray of light plays the part of the man walking along relatively to the carriage. The velocity W of the man relative to the embankment is here replaced by the velocity of light relative to the embankment. w is the required velocity of light with respect to the carriage, and we have

Of course, we need to refer the process of light propagation (and really every other process) to a fixed reference point (coordinate system). For this reference point, let's choose our embankment again. We'll imagine that the air above it has been removed. If a ray of light is sent along the embankment, we can see from the above that the tip of the ray will be transmitted at velocity c relative to the embankment. Now, let's assume our railway carriage is traveling along the railway tracks at a velocity v, and its direction matches that of the ray of light, but its velocity is, of course, much less. Let's examine the velocity of light's propagation relative to the carriage. It's clear that we can use the analysis from the previous section, since the ray of light acts like the person walking relative to the carriage. The velocity W of the person relative to the embankment is now replaced by the velocity of light relative to the embankment. w is the desired velocity of light with respect to the carriage, and we have

w = c – v.

w = c - v.

The velocity of propagation ot a ray of light relative to the carriage thus comes out smaller than c.

The speed of a light ray relative to the carriage is therefore less than c.

But this result comes into conflict with the principle of relativity set forth in Section V. For, like every other general law of nature, the law of the transmission of light in vacuo [in vacuum] must, according to the principle of relativity, be the same for the railway carriage as reference-body as when the rails are the body of reference. But, from our above consideration, this would appear to be impossible. If every ray of light is propagated relative to the embankment with the velocity c, then for this reason it would appear that another law of propagation of light must necessarily hold with respect to the carriage—a result contradictory to the principle of relativity.

But this result conflicts with the principle of relativity described in Section V. Like every other general law of nature, the law of light transmission in vacuum must, according to the principle of relativity, be the same for the railway carriage as a reference frame as when the rails are the reference frame. However, based on our previous discussion, this seems impossible. If every beam of light travels relative to the embankment at the speed of c, then it seems another law of light propagation must apply to the carriage, which contradicts the principle of relativity.

In view of this dilemma there appears to be nothing else for it than to abandon either the principle of relativity or the simple law of the propagation of light in vacuo. Those of you who have carefully followed the preceding discussion are almost sure to expect that we should retain the principle of relativity, which appeals so convincingly to the intellect because it is so natural and simple. The law of the propagation of light in vacuo would then have to be replaced by a more complicated law conformable to the principle of relativity. The development of theoretical physics shows, however, that we cannot pursue this course. The epoch-making theoretical investigations of H. A. Lorentz on the electrodynamical and optical phenomena connected with moving bodies show that experience in this domain leads conclusively to a theory of electromagnetic phenomena, of which the law of the constancy of the velocity of light in vacuo is a necessary consequence. Prominent theoretical physicists were therefore more inclined to reject the principle of relativity, in spite of the fact that no empirical data had been found which were contradictory to this principle.

Given this dilemma, it seems we have no choice but to abandon either the principle of relativity or the basic law of light propagation in vacuo. Those of you who have closely followed the previous discussion are likely expecting us to keep the principle of relativity, which is appealing to the mind because it's so natural and straightforward. In that case, the law of light propagation in vacuo would need to be replaced with a more complex law that aligns with the principle of relativity. However, the progress of theoretical physics indicates that we can't take that path. The groundbreaking theoretical work by H. A. Lorentz on the electrodynamical and optical phenomena related to moving bodies shows that experience in this area leads definitively to a theory of electromagnetic phenomena, of which the law of the constancy of the speed of light in vacuo is an essential outcome. Therefore, leading theoretical physicists were more likely to dismiss the principle of relativity, even though no empirical data had been found that contradicted this principle.

At this juncture the theory of relativity entered the arena. As a result of an analysis of the physical conceptions of time and space, it became evident that in reality there is not the least incompatibilitiy between the principle of relativity and the law of propagation of light, and that by systematically holding fast to both these laws a logically rigid theory could be arrived at. This theory has been called the special theory of relativity to distinguish it from the extended theory, with which we shall deal later. In the following pages we shall present the fundamental ideas of the special theory of relativity.

At this point, the theory of relativity made its entrance. After analyzing the physical ideas of time and space, it became clear that there is actually no conflict between the principle of relativity and the law of light propagation, and that by consistently adhering to both these principles, we could develop a logically coherent theory. This theory is known as the special theory of relativity to differentiate it from the broader theory, which we will discuss later. In the pages that follow, we will outline the key concepts of the special theory of relativity.

VIII.
ON THE IDEA OF TIME IN PHYSICS

Lightning has struck the rails on our railway embankment at two places A and B far distant from each other. I make the additional assertion that these two lightning flashes occurred simultaneously. If I ask you whether there is sense in this statement, you will answer my question with a decided “Yes.” But if I now approach you with the request to explain to me the sense of the statement more precisely, you find after some consideration that the answer to this question is not so easy as it appears at first sight.

Lightning has hit the tracks on our railway embankment at two places A and B that are far apart. I further assert that these two lightning strikes happened at the same time. If I ask you whether this statement makes sense, you would answer me with a definite “Yes.” However, if I then ask you to explain the meaning of that statement in more detail, you’ll realize after some thought that the answer to that question is more complicated than it seems at first glance.

After some time perhaps the following answer would occur to you: “The significance of the statement is clear in itself and needs no further explanation; of course it would require some consideration if I were to be commissioned to determine by observations whether in the actual case the two events took place simultaneously or not.” I cannot be satisfied with this answer for the following reason. Supposing that as a result of ingenious considerations an able meteorologist were to discover that the lightning must always strike the places A and B simultaneously, then we should be faced with the task of testing whether or not this theoretical result is in accordance with the reality. We encounter the same difficulty with all physical statements in which the conception “simultaneous” plays a part. The concept does not exist for the physicist until he has the possibility of discovering whether or not it is fulfilled in an actual case. We thus require a definition of simultaneity such that this definition supplies us with the method by means of which, in the present case, he can decide by experiment whether or not both the lightning strokes occurred simultaneously. As long as this requirement is not satisfied, I allow myself to be deceived as a physicist (and of course the same applies if I am not a physicist), when I imagine that I am able to attach a meaning to the statement of simultaneity. (I would ask the reader not to proceed farther until he is fully convinced on this point.)

After a while, you might come to this conclusion: “The meaning of the statement is obvious and doesn’t need more explanation; naturally, it would need some thought if I were asked to find out through observation whether the two events actually happened at the same time or not.” I can’t accept this answer for one main reason. Let’s say that through clever reasoning, a skilled meteorologist finds out that lightning always strikes locations A and B at the same moment. We would then need to test whether this theoretical conclusion matches reality. We face the same challenge with all physical statements where the concept of “simultaneous” is involved. The physicist cannot grasp this concept until there’s a way to find out if it holds true in a specific situation. Therefore, we need a definition of simultaneity that provides a method for determining through experiment whether both lightning strikes happened at the same time. If this requirement isn’t met, I am misled as a physicist (and it applies even if I’m not a physicist) when I think I can understand the meaning of simultaneity. (I would ask the reader not to go any further until fully convinced of this point.)

After thinking the matter over for some time you then offer the following suggestion with which to test simultaneity. By measuring along the rails, the connecting line AB should be measured up and an observer placed at the mid-point M of the distance AB. This observer should be supplied with an arrangement (e.g. two mirrors inclined at 90°) which allows him visually to observe both places A and B at the same time. If the observer perceives the two flashes of lightning at the same time, then they are simultaneous.

After thinking it over for a while, you suggest a way to test simultaneity. By measuring along the tracks, the connecting line AB should be measured, and an observer should be placed at the midpoint M of the distance AB. This observer should have a setup (e.g. two mirrors positioned at 90°) that lets them see both points A and B at the same time. If the observer sees the two flashes of lightning simultaneously, then they are simultaneous.

I am very pleased with this suggestion, but for all that I cannot regard the matter as quite settled, because I feel constrained to raise the following objection: “Your definition would certainly be right, if only I knew that the light by means of which the observer at M perceives the lightning flashes travels along the length AM with the same velocity as along the length BM. But an examination of this supposition would only be possible if we already had at our disposal the means of measuring time. It would thus appear as though we were moving here in a logical circle.”

I really like this suggestion, but I can't consider the matter completely settled because I feel I need to raise the following point: “Your definition would definitely be correct if only I knew that the light the observer at M sees the lightning flashes with travels along the length AM at the same speed as along the length BM. However, examining this assumption would only be possible if we already had a way to measure time. So, it seems like we’re going around in circles logically.”

After further consideration you cast a somewhat disdainful glance at me—and rightly so—and you declare: “I maintain my previous definition nevertheless, because in reality it assumes absolutely nothing about light. There is only one demand to be made of the definition of simultaneity, namely, that in every real case it must supply us with an empirical decision as to whether or not the conception that has to be defined is fulfilled. That my definition satisfies this demand is indisputable. That light requires the same time to traverse the path AM as for the path BM is in reality neither a supposition nor a hypothesis about the physical nature of light, but a stipulation which I can make of my own freewill in order to arrive at a definition of simultaneity.”

After thinking it over, you give me a somewhat scornful look—and justifiably so—and you state: “I still stand by my previous definition, because it doesn’t assume anything about light at all. The only requirement for the definition of simultaneity is that it must provide an empirical decision on whether or not the concept being defined is met in every real case. It's undeniable that my definition meets this requirement. The idea that light takes the same amount of time to travel the path AM as it does for the path BM is not a supposition nor a hypothesis about the physical nature of light; it is simply a stipulation I can make at my discretion to develop a definition of simultaneity.”

It is clear that this definition can be used to give an exact meaning not only to two events, but to as many events as we care to choose, and independently of the positions of the scenes of the events with respect to the body of reference[7] (here the railway embankment). We are thus led also to a definition of “time” in physics. For this purpose we suppose that clocks of identical construction are placed at the points A, B and C of the railway line (co-ordinate system) and that they are set in such a manner that the positions of their pointers are simultaneously (in the above sense) the same. Under these conditions we understand by the “time” of an event the reading (position of the hands) of that one of these clocks which is in the immediate vicinity (in space) of the event. In this manner a time-value is associated with every event which is essentially capable of observation.

It's clear that this definition can provide a precise meaning not just to two events, but to as many events as we choose, regardless of where the events are positioned in relation to the reference body[7] (in this case, the railway embankment). This leads us to a definition of “time” in physics. For this, we assume that clocks of the same design are placed at points A, B, and C along the railway line (coordinate system) and that they are synchronized so that the positions of their hands are the same at the same moment. Under these conditions, we define the “time” of an event as the reading (the position of the hands) of the clock that is closest (in space) to the event. This way, every event that can be observed gets a time value associated with it.

[7]
We suppose further that, when three events A, B and C occur in different places in such a manner that, if A is simultaneous with B, and B is simultaneous with C (simultaneous in the sense of the above definition), then the criterion for the simultaneity of the pair of events A, C is also satisfied. This assumption is a physical hypothesis about the law of propagation of light; it must certainly be fulfilled if we are to maintain the law of the constancy of the velocity of light in vacuo.

[7]
We further assume that, when three events A, B, and C happen in different locations in such a way that if A occurs at the same time as B, and B occurs at the same time as C (simultaneous in the sense defined above), then the condition for the simultaneity of the pair of events A, C is also met. This assumption is a physical hypothesis about how light propagates; it must definitely hold true if we are to uphold the principle of the constancy of the speed of light in vacuo.

This stipulation contains a further physical hypothesis, the validity of which will hardly be doubted without empirical evidence to the contrary. It has been assumed that all these clocks go at the same rate if they are of identical construction. Stated more exactly: When two clocks arranged at rest in different places of a reference-body are set in such a manner that a particular position of the pointers of the one clock is simultaneous (in the above sense) with the same position, of the pointers of the other clock, then identical “settings” are always simultaneous (in the sense of the above definition).

This stipulation includes an additional physical assumption, which is unlikely to be questioned without evidence to the contrary. It is assumed that all these clocks run at the same rate if they are built the same way. To put it more clearly: When two clocks positioned at rest in different locations of a reference body are set in such a manner that a specific position of the hands of one clock is simultaneous (as defined above) with the same position of the hands of the other clock, then identical “settings” are always simultaneous (in the sense defined above).

IX.
THE RELATIVITY OF SIMULTANEITY

Up to now our considerations have been referred to a particular body of reference, which we have styled a “railway embankment.” We suppose a very long train travelling along the rails with the constant velocity v and in the direction indicated in Fig 1. People travelling in this train will with a vantage view the train as a rigid reference-body (co-ordinate system); they regard all events in reference to the train. Then every event which takes place along the line also takes place at a particular point of the train. Also the definition of simultaneity can be given relative to the train in exactly the same way as with respect to the embankment. As a natural consequence, however, the following question arises:

Up to now, our discussions have focused on a specific reference point that we’ve called a “railway embankment.” We imagine a very long train moving along the tracks at a constant speed v in the direction shown in Fig 1. Passengers on this train will see it as a solid reference frame (coordinate system) and will view all events in relation to the train. Thus, every event occurring along the track also occurs at a particular point on the train. Additionally, we can define simultaneity in relation to the train in exactly the same way as we do concerning the embankment. Consequently, the following question arises:

image001

Are two events (e.g. the two strokes of lightning A and B) which are simultaneous with reference to the railway embankment also simultaneous relatively to the train? We shall show directly that the answer must be in the negative.

Are two events (e.g., the two lightning strikes A and B) that are simultaneous concerning the railway embankment also simultaneous relative to the train? We will show directly that the answer must be no.

When we say that the lightning strokes A and B are simultaneous with respect to be embankment, we mean: the rays of light emitted at the places A and B, where the lightning occurs, meet each other at the mid-point M of the length AB of the embankment. But the events A and B also correspond to positions A and B on the train. Let M′ be the mid-point of the distance AB on the travelling train. Just when the flashes (as judged from the embankment) of lightning occur, this point M′ naturally coincides with the point M but it moves towards the right in the diagram with the velocity v of the train. If an observer sitting in the position M′ in the train did not possess this velocity, then he would remain permanently at M, and the light rays emitted by the flashes of lightning A and B would reach him simultaneously, i.e. they would meet just where he is situated. Now in reality (considered with reference to the railway embankment) he is hastening towards the beam of light coming from B, whilst he is riding on ahead of the beam of light coming from A. Hence the observer will see the beam of light emitted from B earlier than he will see that emitted from A. Observers who take the railway train as their reference-body must therefore come to the conclusion that the lightning flash B took place earlier than the lightning flash A. We thus arrive at the important result:

When we say that the lightning strikes A and B happen simultaneously from the perspective of the embankment, we mean that the light rays from points A and B, where the lightning strikes, meet at the midpoint M between A and B on the embankment. But the events A and B also relate to points A and B on the train. Let M′ be the midpoint of the distance AB on the moving train. Just when the flashes of lightning occur (as seen from the embankment), this point M′ aligns with point M but then shifts to the right in the diagram at the speed v of the train. If an observer sitting at point M′ on the train didn't have this velocity, they'd stay at M, and the light rays from the lightning strikes A and B would reach them at the same time, meaning they'd meet right where the observer is. In reality (from the perspective of the railway embankment), this observer is moving toward the light coming from B while getting ahead of the light coming from A. So, the observer will see the light emitted from B before they see the one from A. Therefore, observers using the train as their reference point must conclude that the lightning strike B occurred before the lightning strike A. We thus reach the important conclusion:

Events which are simultaneous with reference to the embankment are not simultaneous with respect to the train, and vice versa (relativity of simultaneity). Every reference-body (co-ordinate system) has its own particular time; unless we are told the reference-body to which the statement of time refers, there is no meaning in a statement of the time of an event.

Events that are happening at the same time in relation to the embankment are not happening at the same time for the train, and vice versa (the relativity of simultaneity). Each reference frame (coordinate system) has its own specific time; unless we know the reference frame to which the time statement refers, a statement about the time of an event is meaningless.

Now before the advent of the theory of relativity it had always tacitly been assumed in physics that the statement of time had an absolute significance, i.e. that it is independent of the state of motion of the body of reference. But we have just seen that this assumption is incompatible with the most natural definition of simultaneity; if we discard this assumption, then the conflict between the law of the propagation of light in vacuo and the principle of relativity (developed in Section VII) disappears.

Before the theory of relativity, physics generally assumed that time had an absolute meaning, meaning it was independent of the motion of the observer. However, we just saw that this assumption doesn’t align with the most straightforward definition of simultaneity. If we let go of this assumption, the conflict between the law of light propagation in a vacuum and the principle of relativity (explained in Section VII) goes away.

We were led to that conflict by the considerations of Section VI, which are now no longer tenable. In that section we concluded that the man in the carriage, who traverses the distance w per second relative to the carriage, traverses the same distance also with respect to the embankment in each second of time. But, according to the foregoing considerations, the time required by a particular occurrence with respect to the carriage must not be considered equal to the duration of the same occurrence as judged from the embankment (as reference-body). Hence it cannot be contended that the man in walking travels the distance w relative to the railway line in a time which is equal to one second as judged from the embankment.

We were led to that conflict by the points made in Section VI, which are now no longer valid. In that section, we concluded that the man in the carriage, who moves at a speed of w per second relative to the carriage, covers the same distance with respect to the embankment in each second of time. However, based on the earlier points, the time taken for a specific event relative to the carriage should not be considered the same as the duration of that same event as perceived from the embankment (as the reference point). Therefore, it cannot be argued that the man, while walking, covers the distance w relative to the railway line in a duration equal to one second as observed from the embankment.

Moreover, the considerations of Section VI are based on yet a second assumption, which, in the light of a strict consideration, appears to be arbitrary, although it was always tacitly made even before the introduction of the theory of relativity.

Moreover, the points discussed in Section VI are based on a second assumption that, upon closer examination, seems arbitrary, even though it was always implicitly accepted before the theory of relativity was introduced.

X.
ON THE RELATIVITY OF THE CONCEPTION OF DISTANCE

Let us consider two particular points on the train [8] travelling along the embankment with the velocity v, and inquire as to their distance apart. We already know that it is necessary to have a body of reference for the measurement of a distance, with respect to which body the distance can be measured up. It is the simplest plan to use the train itself as reference-body (co-ordinate system). An observer in the train measures the interval by marking off his measuring-rod in a straight line (e.g. along the floor of the carriage) as many times as is necessary to take him from the one marked point to the other. Then the number which tells us how often the rod has to be laid down is the required distance.

Let’s look at two specific points on train [8] moving along the embankment at a speed of v, and find out how far apart they are. We already know that we need a reference object to measure distance, which allows us to measure from that object. The easiest way is to use the train itself as the reference object (coordinate system). An observer inside the train measures the distance by laying down a measuring rod in a straight line (like along the floor of the carriage) as many times as needed to go from one marked point to the other. The number of times the rod has to be placed down gives us the distance we need.

[8]
e.g. the middle of the first and of the hundredth carriage.

[8]
e.g. the middle of the first and the hundredth carriage.

It is a different matter when the distance has to be judged from the railway line. Here the following method suggests itself. If we call A′ and B′ the two points on the train whose distance apart is required, then both of these points are moving with the velocity v along the embankment. In the first place we require to determine the points A and B of the embankment which are just being passed by the two points A′ and B′ at a particular time t—judged from the embankment. These points A and B of the embankment can be determined by applying the definition of time given in Section VIII. The distance between these points A and B is then measured by repeated application of the measuring-rod along the embankment.

It’s different when you have to figure out the distance from the railway line. In this case, the following method makes sense. If we label A′ and B′ as the two points on the train whose distance apart we need, then both of these points are moving at a speed of v along the embankment. First, we need to identify the points A and B on the embankment that the two points A′ and B′ are passing at a specific time t, as observed from the embankment. We can find points A and B on the embankment by using the definition of time provided in Section VIII. The distance between points A and B is then measured by repeatedly using a measuring rod along the embankment.

A priori it is by no means certain that this last measurement will supply us with the same result as the first. Thus the length of the train as measured from the embankment may be different from that obtained by measuring in the train itself. This circumstance leads us to a second objection which must be raised against the apparently obvious consideration of Section VI. Namely, if the man in the carriage covers the distance w in a unit of time—measured from the train,—then this distance—as measured from the embankment is not necessarily also equal to w.

A priori, it's not at all certain that this last measurement will give us the same result as the first. So, the length of the train measured from the embankment might be different from what we get by measuring inside the train itself. This brings us to a second objection that we need to raise against the seemingly obvious point from Section VI. Specifically, if the person in the carriage covers the distance w in a unit of time—measured from the train—then this distance—as measured from the embankment—isn't necessarily equal to w.

XI.
THE LORENTZ TRANSFORMATION

The results of the last three sections show that the apparent incompatibility of the law of propagation of light with the principle of relativity (Section VII) has been derived by means of a consideration which borrowed two unjustifiable hypotheses from classical mechanics; these are as follows:

The results of the last three sections show that the apparent conflict between the law of light propagation and the principle of relativity (Section VII) has come from using two questionable assumptions taken from classical mechanics; these are as follows:

(1) The time-interval (time) between two events is independent of the condition of motion of the body of reference.

(1) The time between two events is not affected by the motion of the reference body.

(2) The space-interval (distance) between two points of a rigid body is independent of the condition of motion of the body of reference.

(2) The distance between two points of a rigid body doesn’t depend on how that body is moving.

If we drop these hypotheses, then the dilemma of Section VII disappears, because the theorem of the addition of velocities derived in Section VI becomes invalid. The possibility presents itself that the law of the propagation of light in vacuo may be compatible with the principle of relativity, and the question arises: How have we to modify the considerations of Section VI in order to remove the apparent disagreement between these two fundamental results of experience? This question leads to a general one. In the discussion of Section VI we have to do with places and times relative both to the train and to the embankment. How are we to find the place and time of an event in relation to the train, when we know the place and time of the event with respect to the railway embankment? Is there a thinkable answer to this question of such a nature that the law of transmission of light in vacuo does not contradict the principle of relativity? In other words: Can we conceive of a relation between place and time of the individual events relative to both reference-bodies, such that every ray of light possesses the velocity of transmission c relative to the embankment and relative to the train? This question leads to a quite definite positive answer, and to a perfectly definite transformation law for the space-time magnitudes of an event when changing over from one body of reference to another.

If we set aside these hypotheses, then the dilemma from Section VII goes away, because the theorem about adding velocities that we explained in Section VI no longer applies. It raises the possibility that the law of light propagation in a vacuum might align with the principle of relativity, and we need to ask: How do we need to adjust the ideas from Section VI to resolve the apparent conflict between these two essential truths from experience? This leads us to a broader question. In Section VI, we deal with locations and times that are relative to both the train and the embankment. How can we determine the location and time of an event in terms of the train when we already have its location and time with respect to the railway embankment? Is there a conceivable way to answer this question that allows the law of light transmission in a vacuum to coexist without conflicting with the principle of relativity? In other words: Can we imagine a relationship between the locations and times of individual events relative to both reference points, so that every light ray maintains a speed of c relative to both the embankment and the train? This question leads us to a clear positive answer, and to a straightforward transformation law for the space-time characteristics of an event when switching from one reference frame to another.

Before we deal with this, we shall introduce the following incidental consideration. Up to the present we have only considered events taking place along the embankment, which had mathematically to assume the function of a straight line. In the manner indicated in Section II we can imagine this reference-body supplemented laterally and in a vertical direction by means of a framework of rods, so that an event which takes place anywhere can be localised with reference to this framework. Similarly, we can imagine the train travelling with the velocity v to be continued across the whole of space, so that every event, no matter how far off it may be, could also be localised with respect to the second framework. Without committing any fundamental error, we can disregard the fact that in reality these frameworks would continually interfere with each other, owing to the impenetrability of solid bodies. In every such framework we imagine three surfaces perpendicular to each other marked out, and designated as “co-ordinate planes” (“co-ordinate system”). A co-ordinate system K then corresponds to the embankment, and a co-ordinate system K′ to the train. An event, wherever it may have taken place, would be fixed in space with respect to K by the three perpendiculars x, y, z on the co-ordinate planes, and with regard to time by a time value t. Relative to K′, the same event would be fixed in respect of space and time by corresponding values x′, y′, z′, t′, which of course are not identical with x, y, z, t. It has already been set forth in detail how these magnitudes are to be regarded as results of physical measurements.

Before we move on, let's touch on an important point. Until now, we’ve only looked at things happening along the embankment, which we’ve mathematically treated as a straight line. As discussed in Section II, we can envision this reference body expanded laterally and vertically through a framework of rods, allowing us to pinpoint an event that occurs anywhere in relation to this framework. Similarly, we can think of the train moving at speed v as continuing infinitely, meaning any event, regardless of its distance, could also be located concerning this second framework. Without making any major errors, we can ignore the fact that, in reality, these frameworks would constantly interact with each other due to the solidness of physical bodies. In each of these frameworks, we can picture three surfaces that are at right angles to one another, referred to as “coordinate planes” (or “coordinate system”). A coordinate system K corresponds to the embankment, while a coordinate system K′ pertains to the train. An event, wherever it occurs, would be defined in space according to K by the three perpendiculars x, y, z on the coordinate planes, and in terms of time by a time value t. In relation to K′, the same event would be defined in terms of space and time by corresponding values x′, y′, z′, t′, which are, of course, not the same as x, y, z, t. It has already been thoroughly explained how these quantities should be understood as results of physical measurements.

image002

Obviously our problem can be exactly formulated in the following manner. What are the values x′, y′, z′, t′, of an event with respect to K′, when the magnitudes x, y, z, t, of the same event with respect to K are given? The relations must be so chosen that the law of the transmission of light in vacuo is satisfied for one and the same ray of light (and of course for every ray) with respect to K and K′. For the relative orientation in space of the co-ordinate systems indicated in the diagram (Fig. 2), this problem is solved by means of the equations:

Clearly, we can frame our problem like this. What are the values x′, y′, z′, t′ of an event in relation to K′ when the values x, y, z, t of the same event in relation to K are given? The relationships need to be structured so that the law of light transmission in a vacuum is upheld for the same light ray (and indeed for every ray) concerning both K and K′. The solution to this problem, given the relative spatial orientation of the coordinate systems shown in the diagram (Fig. 2), can be found using the following equations:

image003

y′ = y

y′ = y

z′ = z

z′ = z

image004

This system of equations is known as the “Lorentz transformation.”[9]

This system of equations is called the "Lorentz transformation."[9]

[9]
A simple derivation of the Lorentz transformation is given in Appendix I.

[9]
A straightforward explanation of the Lorentz transformation can be found in Appendix I.

If in place of the law of transmission of light we had taken as our basis the tacit assumptions of the older mechanics as to the absolute character of times and lengths, then instead of the above we should have obtained the following equations:

If instead of the law of light transmission we had based our work on the unspoken assumptions of older mechanics regarding the absolute nature of time and distance, we would have arrived at the following equations:

x′ = xvt

x′ = xvt

y′ = y

y′ = y

z′ = z

z′ = z

t′ = t

t′ = t

This system of equations is often termed the “Galilei transformation.” The Galilei transformation can be obtained from the Lorentz transformation by substituting an infinitely large value for the velocity of light c in the latter transformation.

This system of equations is often called the “Galilei transformation.” The Galilei transformation can be derived from the Lorentz transformation by replacing the speed of light c with an infinitely large value in the latter transformation.

Aided by the following illustration, we can readily see that, in accordance with the Lorentz transformation, the law of the transmission of light in vacuo is satisfied both for the reference-body K and for the reference-body K′. A light-signal is sent along the positive x-axis, and this light-stimulus advances in accordance with the equation

Aided by the following illustration, we can easily see that, according to the Lorentz transformation, the law of light transmission in vacuo holds true for both the reference body K and the reference body K′. A light signal is sent along the positive x-axis, and this light stimulus travels according to the equation

x = ct,

x = ct,

i.e. with the velocity c. According to the equations of the Lorentz transformation, this simple relation between x and t involves a relation between x′ and t′. In point of fact, if we substitute for x the value ct in the first and fourth equations of the Lorentz transformation, we obtain:

i.e. at the speed c. Based on the equations of the Lorentz transformation, this straightforward relationship between x and t also includes a relationship between x′ and t′. In fact, if we replace x with the value ct in the first and fourth equations of the Lorentz transformation, we get:

image005

from which, by division, the expression

from which, by division, the expression

x′ = ct′

x′ = ct′

immediately follows. If referred to the system K′, the propagation of light takes place according to this equation. We thus see that the velocity of transmission relative to the reference-body K′ is also equal to c. The same result is obtained for rays of light advancing in any other direction whatsoever. Of cause this is not surprising, since the equations of the Lorentz transformation were derived conformably to this point of view.

immediately follows. If referred to the system K′, the propagation of light happens according to this equation. We can see that the speed of transmission relative to the reference body K′ is also equal to c. The same result is achieved for rays of light moving in any direction at all. Of course, this isn't surprising since the equations of the Lorentz transformation were derived based on this perspective.

XII.
THE BEHAVIOUR OF MEASURING-RODS AND CLOCKS IN MOTION

Place a metre-rod in the x′-axis of K′ in such a manner that one end (the beginning) coincides with the point x′ = 0 whilst the other end (the end of the rod) coincides with the point x′ = 1. What is the length of the metre-rod relatively to the system K? In order to learn this, we need only ask where the beginning of the rod and the end of the rod lie with respect to K at a particular time t of the system K. By means of the first equation of the Lorentz transformation the values of these two points at the time t = 0 can be shown to be

Place a meter stick along the x′-axis of K′ so that one end (the starting point) lines up with the point x′ = 0 and the other end (the end of the stick) lines up with the point x′ = 1. What is the length of the meter stick compared to the system K? To find this out, we just need to see where the start and end of the stick are positioned in relation to K at a specific time t in the K system. Using the first equation of the Lorentz transformation, we can establish the values of these two points at the time t = 0 to be

image006

the distance between the points being

the distance between the points being

image007

But the metre-rod is moving with the velocity v relative to K. It therefore follows that the length of a rigid metre-rod moving in the direction of its length with a velocity v is

But the meter stick is moving with a speed v relative to K. It follows that the length of a rigid meter stick moving in the direction of its length at a speed v is

image008

of a metre. The rigid rod is thus shorter when in motion than when at rest, and the more quickly it is moving, the shorter is the rod. For the velocity v = c we should have

of a meter. The rigid rod is shorter when it's moving than when it's at rest, and the faster it moves, the shorter the rod becomes. For the speed v = c, we should have

image009

and for still greater velocities the square-root becomes imaginary. From this we conclude that in the theory of relativity the velocity c plays the part of a limiting velocity, which can neither be reached nor exceeded by any real body.

and for even greater speeds, the square root becomes imaginary. From this, we conclude that in the theory of relativity, the velocity c acts as a limiting speed that no real object can reach or surpass.

Of course this feature of the velocity c as a limiting velocity also clearly follows from the equations of the Lorentz transformation, for these became meaningless if we choose values of v greater than c.

Of course, this characteristic of the speed c as a maximum speed also clearly comes from the equations of the Lorentz transformation, because these would become meaningless if we choose values of v greater than c.

If, on the contrary, we had considered a metre-rod at rest in the x-axis with respect to K, then we should have found that the length of the rod as judged from K′ would have been

If, on the other hand, we had looked at a meter stick that was stationary along the x-axis relative to K, we would have found that the length of the stick as measured from K′ would have been

image010

this is quite in accordance with the principle of relativity which forms the basis of our considerations.

this aligns perfectly with the principle of relativity, which is the foundation of our discussions.

A priori it is quite clear that we must be able to learn something about the physical behaviour of measuring-rods and clocks from the equations of transformation, for the magnitudes z, y, x, t, are nothing more nor less than the results of measurements obtainable by means of measuring-rods and clocks. If we had based our considerations on the Galileian transformation we should not have obtained a contraction of the rod as a consequence of its motion.

Beforehand it’s pretty clear that we need to learn something about how measuring rods and clocks behave physically from the transformation equations, because the values z, y, x, t are simply the results of measurements taken with measuring rods and clocks. If we had based our thoughts on the Galilean transformation, we wouldn’t have seen a contraction of the rod as a result of its motion.

Let us now consider a seconds-clock which is permanently situated at the origin (x′ = 0) of K′. t′ = 0 and t′ = 1 are two successive ticks of this clock. The first and fourth equations of the Lorentz transformation give for these two ticks:

Let’s now look at a second clock that is always located at the origin (x′ = 0) of K′. t′ = 0 and t′ = 1 are two consecutive ticks of this clock. The first and fourth equations of the Lorentz transformation provide the results for these two ticks:

t = 0

t = 0

and

and

image011

As judged from K, the clock is moving with the velocity v; as judged from this reference-body, the time which elapses between two strokes of the clock is not one second, but

As seen from K, the clock is ticking at a speed of v; from this reference point, the time that passes between two ticks of the clock isn't one second, but

image012

seconds, i.e. a somewhat larger time. As a consequence of its motion the clock goes more slowly than when at rest. Here also the velocity c plays the part of an unattainable limiting velocity.

seconds, i.e. a somewhat larger time. As a result of its motion, the clock runs slower than when it’s stationary. Here, too, the velocity c serves as an unreachable maximum speed.

XIII.
THEOREM OF THE ADDITION OF VELOCITIES. THE EXPERIMENT OF FIZEAU

Now in practice we can move clocks and measuring-rods only with velocities that are small compared with the velocity of light; hence we shall hardly be able to compare the results of the previous section directly with the reality. But, on the other hand, these results must strike you as being very singular, and for that reason I shall now draw another conclusion from the theory, one which can easily be derived from the foregoing considerations, and which has been most elegantly confirmed by experiment.

Now in practice, we can only move clocks and measuring rods at speeds that are small compared to the speed of light. Because of this, we will hardly be able to directly compare the results from the previous section with reality. However, these results are certainly very interesting, and for that reason, I will now draw another conclusion from the theory. This conclusion can easily be derived from the previous considerations and has been beautifully confirmed through experiments.

In Section VI we derived the theorem of the addition of velocities in one direction in the form which also results from the hypotheses of classical mechanics. This theorem can also be deduced readily from the Galilei transformation (Section XI). In place of the man walking inside the carriage, we introduce a point moving relatively to the co-ordinate system K′ in accordance with the equation

In Section VI, we derived the theorem on adding velocities in one direction, which also comes from the principles of classical mechanics. This theorem can also be easily derived from the Galilean transformation (Section XI). Instead of the person walking inside the carriage, we introduce a point moving relative to the coordinate system K′ according to the equation

x′ = wt′

x′ = wt′

By means of the first and fourth equations of the Galilei transformation we can express x′ and t′ in terms of x and t, and we then obtain

By using the first and fourth equations of the Galilean transformation, we can express x′ and t′ in terms of x and t, and we then get

x = (v + w)t

x = (v + w)t

This equation expresses nothing else than the law of motion of the point with reference to the system K (of the man with reference to the embankment). We denote this velocity by the symbol W, and we then obtain, as in Section VI,

This equation represents nothing more than the motion law of the point concerning the system K (the person in relation to the embankment). We represent this velocity with the symbol W, and then we find, as in Section VI,

W = v + w . . . . . . . (A).

W = v + w . . . . . . . (A).

But we can carry out this consideration just as well on the basis of the theory of relativity. In the equation

But we can also approach this consideration using the theory of relativity. In the equation

x′ = wt′

x′ = wt′

we must then express x′ and t′ in terms of x and t, making use of the first and fourth equations of the Lorentz transformation. Instead of the equation (A) we then obtain the equation

we need to express x′ and t′ in terms of x and t, using the first and fourth equations of the Lorentz transformation. Instead of equation (A), we get the equation

image013

which corresponds to the theorem of addition for velocities in one direction according to the theory of relativity. The question now arises as to which of these two theorems is the better in accord with experience. On this point we are enlightened by a most important experiment which the brilliant physicist Fizeau performed more than half a century ago, and which has been repeated since then by some of the best experimental physicists, so that there can be no doubt about its result. The experiment is concerned with the following question. Light travels in a motionless liquid with a particular velocity w. How quickly does it travel in the direction of the arrow in the tube T (see the accompanying diagram, Fig. 3) when the liquid above mentioned is flowing through the tube with a velocity v?

which corresponds to the theorem of addition for velocities in one direction according to the theory of relativity. The question now arises as to which of these two theorems aligns better with experience. We are informed on this matter by a crucial experiment conducted by the brilliant physicist Fizeau over half a century ago, which has since been repeated by some of the best experimental physicists, leaving no doubt about its outcome. The experiment addresses the following question: Light moves in a stationary liquid at a specific speed w. How fast does it travel in the direction of the arrow in the tube T (see the attached diagram, Fig. 3) when the aforementioned liquid is flowing through the tube at a speed v?

image014

In accordance with the principle of relativity we shall certainly have to take for granted that the propagation of light always takes place with the same velocity w with respect to the liquid, whether the latter is in motion with reference to other bodies or not. The velocity of light relative to the liquid and the velocity of the latter relative to the tube are thus known, and we require the velocity of light relative to the tube.

In line with the principle of relativity, we must assume that light always travels at the same speed w with respect to the liquid, regardless of whether the liquid is moving in relation to other objects. We know the speed of light relative to the liquid and the speed of the liquid relative to the tube, so we need the speed of light relative to the tube.

It is clear that we have the problem of Section VI again before us. The tube plays the part of the railway embankment or of the co-ordinate system K, the liquid plays the part of the carriage or of the co-ordinate system K′, and finally, the light plays the part of the man walking along the carriage, or of the moving point in the present section. If we denote the velocity of the light relative to the tube by W, then this is given by the equation (A) or (B), according as the Galilei transformation or the Lorentz transformation corresponds to the facts. Experiment[10] decides in favour of equation (B) derived from the theory of relativity, and the agreement is, indeed, very exact. According to recent and most excellent measurements by Zeeman, the influence of the velocity of flow v on the propagation of light is represented by formula (B) to within one per cent.

It’s clear that we’re facing the issue from Section VI again. The tube acts like the railway embankment or the coordinate system K, the liquid acts like the carriage or the coordinate system K′, and finally, light acts like the person walking down the carriage or the moving point in this section. If we denote the speed of light relative to the tube as W, it can be expressed using equation (A) or (B), depending on whether the Galilean transformation or the Lorentz transformation aligns with the facts. Experiment[10] supports equation (B), which is derived from the theory of relativity, and the match is indeed very precise. According to recent, high-quality measurements by Zeeman, the effect of the flow speed v on light propagation is captured by formula (B) to within one percent.

[10]
Fizeau found

[10]
Fizeau discovered

image015

where

where

image016

is the index of refraction of the liquid. On the other hand, owing to the smallness of

is the index of refraction of the liquid. On the other hand, due to the smallness of

image017

as compared with 1, we can replace (B) in the first place by

as compared with 1, we can replace (B) in the first place with

image018

or to the same order of approximation by

or to the same order of approximation by

image019

which agrees with Fizeau’s result.

which aligns with Fizeau’s result.

Nevertheless we must now draw attention to the fact that a theory of this phenomenon was given by H. A. Lorentz long before the statement of the theory of relativity. This theory was of a purely electrodynamical nature, and was obtained by the use of particular hypotheses as to the electromagnetic structure of matter. This circumstance, however, does not in the least diminish the conclusiveness of the experiment as a crucial test in favour of the theory of relativity, for the electrodynamics of Maxwell-Lorentz, on which the original theory was based, in no way opposes the theory of relativity. Rather has the latter been developed trom electrodynamics as an astoundingly simple combination and generalisation of the hypotheses, formerly independent of each other, on which electrodynamics was built.

Nevertheless, we need to highlight that H. A. Lorentz presented a theory about this phenomenon long before the theory of relativity was formulated. This theory was purely based on electrodynamics and was derived from specific hypotheses about the electromagnetic structure of matter. However, this fact does not lessen the significance of the experiment as a critical test supporting the theory of relativity, since the electrodynamics of Maxwell-Lorentz, which the original theory was built upon, does not contradict the theory of relativity at all. Instead, the latter has emerged from electrodynamics as a remarkably simple combination and generalization of the previously independent hypotheses that formed the foundation of electrodynamics.

XIV.
THE HEURISTIC VALUE OF THE THEORY OF RELATIVITY

Our train of thought in the foregoing pages can be epitomised in the following manner. Experience has led to the conviction that, on the one hand, the principle of relativity holds true and that on the other hand the velocity of transmission of light in vacuo has to be considered equal to a constant c. By uniting these two postulates we obtained the law of transformation for the rectangular co-ordinates x, y, z and the time t of the events which constitute the processes of nature. In this connection we did not obtain the Galilei transformation, but, differing from classical mechanics, the Lorentz transformation.

Our thoughts in the previous pages can be summarized like this. Experience has convinced us that, on one hand, the principle of relativity is valid, and on the other hand, the speed of light in a vacuum must be treated as a constant c. By combining these two ideas, we derived the transformation law for the rectangular coordinates x, y, z and the time t of the events that make up natural processes. In this context, we didn’t arrive at the Galilean transformation but, unlike classical mechanics, we found the Lorentz transformation.

The law of transmission of light, the acceptance of which is justified by our actual knowledge, played an important part in this process of thought. Once in possession of the Lorentz transformation, however, we can combine this with the principle of relativity, and sum up the theory thus:

The law of light transmission, which is supported by our current understanding, played a significant role in this line of thinking. However, once we have the Lorentz transformation, we can merge this with the principle of relativity and summarize the theory like this:

Every general law of nature must be so constituted that it is transformed into a law of exactly the same form when, instead of the space-time variables x, y, z, t of the original coordinate system K, we introduce new space-time variables x′, y′, z′, t′ of a co-ordinate system K′. In this connection the relation between the ordinary and the accented magnitudes is given by the Lorentz transformation. Or in brief: General laws of nature are co-variant with respect to Lorentz transformations.

Every general law of nature must be structured in such a way that it transforms into a law of exactly the same form when we replace the space-time variables x, y, z, t from the original coordinate system K with new space-time variables x′, y′, z′, t′ from a coordinate system K′. In this context, the relationship between the ordinary and the accented magnitudes is defined by the Lorentz transformation. In short: General laws of nature are covariant with respect to Lorentz transformations.

This is a definite mathematical condition that the theory of relativity demands of a natural law, and in virtue of this, the theory becomes a valuable heuristic aid in the search for general laws of nature. If a general law of nature were to be found which did not satisfy this condition, then at least one of the two fundamental assumptions of the theory would have been disproved. Let us now examine what general results the latter theory has hitherto evinced.

This is a clear mathematical requirement that the theory of relativity places on natural laws, and because of this, the theory serves as a useful tool in the pursuit of general laws of nature. If a general law of nature were discovered that didn't meet this requirement, then at least one of the two main assumptions of the theory would have been proven wrong. Now, let's look at the general outcomes that this theory has revealed so far.

XV.
GENERAL RESULTS OF THE THEORY

It is clear from our previous considerations that the (special) theory of relativity has grown out of electrodynamics and optics. In these fields it has not appreciably altered the predictions of theory, but it has considerably simplified the theoretical structure, i.e. the derivation of laws, and—what is incomparably more important—it has considerably reduced the number of independent hypotheses forming the basis of theory. The special theory of relativity has rendered the Maxwell-Lorentz theory so plausible, that the latter would have been generally accepted by physicists even if experiment had decided less unequivocally in its favour.

It's clear from our earlier discussions that the (special) theory of relativity has emerged from electrodynamics and optics. In these areas, it hasn't significantly changed the predictions of the theory, but it has greatly simplified the theoretical framework, i.e. the development of laws, and—more importantly—it has significantly decreased the number of independent assumptions that underlie the theory. The special theory of relativity has made the Maxwell-Lorentz theory so credible that it would likely have been widely accepted by physicists even if experiments hadn't been so overwhelmingly in its favor.

Classical mechanics required to be modified before it could come into line with the demands of the special theory of relativity. For the main part, however, this modification affects only the laws for rapid motions, in which the velocities of matter v are not very small as compared with the velocity of light. We have experience of such rapid motions only in the case of electrons and ions; for other motions the variations from the laws of classical mechanics are too small to make themselves evident in practice. We shall not consider the motion of stars until we come to speak of the general theory of relativity. In accordance with the theory of relativity the kinetic energy of a material point of mass m is no longer given by the well-known expression

Classical mechanics needed to be updated before it could align with the requirements of the special theory of relativity. For the most part, though, this update only impacts the laws concerning fast motions, where the speeds of matter v are not very low compared to the speed of light. We only encounter such fast motions in the case of electrons and ions; for other types of motion, the deviations from classical mechanics are too minimal to notice in practice. We won't discuss the motion of stars until we address the general theory of relativity. According to the theory of relativity, the kinetic energy of a mass m is no longer represented by the familiar formula.

image020

but by the expression

but by the expression

image021

This expression approaches infinity as the velocity v approaches the velocity of light c. The velocity must therefore always remain less than c, however great may be the energies used to produce the acceleration. If we develop the expression for the kinetic energy in the form of a series, we obtain

This expression goes to infinity as the speed v gets closer to the speed of light c. Therefore, the speed must always be less than c, no matter how much energy is used to create the acceleration. If we expand the expression for kinetic energy into a series, we get

image022

When

When

image023

is small compared with unity, the third of these terms is always small in comparison with the second, which last is alone considered in classical mechanics. The first term mc2 does not contain the velocity, and requires no consideration if we are only dealing with the question as to how the energy of a point-mass; depends on the velocity. We shall speak of its essential significance later.

is small compared to unity, the third of these terms is always small compared to the second, which is the only one considered in classical mechanics. The first term mc2 doesn’t include velocity and doesn’t need to be taken into account if we’re only looking at how the energy of a point mass depends on velocity. We’ll discuss its essential significance later.

The most important result of a general character to which the special theory of relativity has led is concerned with the conception of mass. Before the advent of relativity, physics recognised two conservation laws of fundamental importance, namely, the law of the conservation of energy and the law of the conservation of mass these two fundamental laws appeared to be quite independent of each other. By means of the theory of relativity they have been united into one law. We shall now briefly consider how this unification came about, and what meaning is to be attached to it.

The most important outcome of the special theory of relativity is related to the idea of mass. Before relativity came along, physics acknowledged two key conservation laws: the law of conservation of energy and the law of conservation of mass. These two laws seemed completely separate from each other. However, through the theory of relativity, they have been combined into a single law. We will now briefly look at how this unification occurred and what it means.

The principle of relativity requires that the law of the conservation of energy should hold not only with reference to a co-ordinate system K, but also with respect to every co-ordinate system K′ which is in a state of uniform motion of translation relative to K, or, briefly, relative to every “Galileian” system of co-ordinates. In contrast to classical mechanics; the Lorentz transformation is the deciding factor in the transition from one such system to another.

The principle of relativity states that the law of conservation of energy applies not just to a coordinate system K, but also to every coordinate system K′ that is moving uniformly in relation to K, or simply put, to every “Galilean” coordinate system. Unlike classical mechanics, the Lorentz transformation is the key element when moving from one of these systems to another.

By means of comparatively simple considerations we are led to draw the following conclusion from these premises, in conjunction with the fundamental equations of the electrodynamics of Maxwell: A body moving with the velocity v, which absorbs[11] an amount of energy E0 in the form of radiation without suffering an alteration in velocity in the process, has, as a consequence, its energy increased by an amount

By using relatively straightforward ideas, we can conclude from these premises, along with the basic equations of Maxwell's electrodynamics: An object moving at a speed v, which absorbs[11] a certain amount of energy E0 in the form of radiation without changing its speed in the process, will have its energy increased by an amount

image024

[11]
E0 is the energy taken up, as judged from a co-ordinate system moving with the body.

[11]
E0 is the energy absorbed, as observed from a coordinate system moving with the body.

In consideration of the expression given above for the kinetic energy of the body, the required energy of the body comes out to be

In light of the expression provided above for the kinetic energy of the body, the energy required for the body turns out to be

image025

Thus the body has the same energy as a body of mass

Thus the body has the same energy as a mass body.

image026

moving with the velocity v. Hence we can say: If a body takes up an amount of energy E0, then its inertial mass increases by an amount

moving with the speed v. So we can say: If a body absorbs an amount of energy E0, then its inertial mass increases by an amount

image027

the inertial mass of a body is not a constant but varies according to the change in the energy of the body. The inertial mass of a system of bodies can even be regarded as a measure of its energy. The law of the conservation of the mass of a system becomes identical with the law of the conservation of energy, and is only valid provided that the system neither takes up nor sends out energy. Writing the expression for the energy in the form

the inertial mass of a body isn't constant; it changes based on the body's energy. The inertial mass of a group of bodies can actually be seen as a measure of their energy. The law of conservation of mass for a system becomes the same as the law of conservation of energy and only holds true if the system neither absorbs nor emits energy. Writing the expression for the energy in the form

image028

we see that the term mc2, which has hitherto attracted our attention, is nothing else than the energy possessed by the body[12] before it absorbed the energy E0.

we see that the term mc2, which has caught our attention so far, is simply the energy that the body[12] had before it absorbed the energy E0.

[12]
As judged from a co-ordinate system moving with the body.

[12]
As seen from a coordinate system moving with the body.

A direct comparison of this relation with experiment is not possible at the present time (1920; see[Note], p. 48), owing to the fact that the changes in energy E0 to which we can subject a system are not large enough to make themselves perceptible as a change in the inertial mass of the system.

A direct comparison of this relationship with experiments isn't possible right now (1920; see[Note], p. 48) because the changes in energy E0 that we can apply to a system aren't large enough to be noticeable as a change in the inertial mass of the system.

image027

is too small in comparison with the mass m, which was present before the alteration of the energy. It is owing to this circumstance that classical mechanics was able to establish successfully the conservation of mass as a law of independent validity.

is too small compared to the mass m that existed before the energy change. This is why classical mechanics successfully established the conservation of mass as a law with its own validity.

[Note]
The equation E = mc2 has been thoroughly proved time and again since this time.

[Note]
The equation E = mc2 has been proven over and over again since then.

Let me add a final remark of a fundamental nature. The success of the Faraday-Maxwell interpretation of electromagnetic action at a distance resulted in physicists becoming convinced that there are no such things as instantaneous actions at a distance (not involving an intermediary medium) of the type of Newton’s law of gravitation.

Let me add one last important point. The success of the Faraday-Maxwell interpretation of electromagnetic action at a distance led physicists to believe that there’s no such thing as instantaneous action at a distance (without an intermediary medium) like Newton’s law of gravitation.

According to the theory of relativity, action at a distance with the velocity of light always takes the place of instantaneous action at a distance or of action at a distance with an infinite velocity of transmission. This is connected with the fact that the velocity c plays a fundamental role in this theory. In Part II we shall see in what way this result becomes modified in the general theory of relativity.

According to the theory of relativity, action at a distance at the speed of light always replaces instantaneous action at a distance or action at a distance with infinite speed of transmission. This is linked to the fact that the speed c is central to this theory. In Part II, we will explore how this outcome changes in the general theory of relativity.

XVI.
EXPERIENCE AND THE SPECIAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY

To what extent is the special theory of relativity supported by experience? This question is not easily answered for the reason already mentioned in connection with the fundamental experiment of Fizeau. The special theory of relativity has crystallised out from the Maxwell-Lorentz theory of electromagnetic phenomena. Thus all facts of experience which support the electromagnetic theory also support the theory of relativity. As being of particular importance, I mention here the fact that the theory of relativity enables us to predict the effects produced on the light reaching us from the fixed stars. These results are obtained in an exceedingly simple manner, and the effects indicated, which are due to the relative motion of the earth with reference to those fixed stars are found to be in accord with experience. We refer to the yearly movement of the apparent position of the fixed stars resulting from the motion of the earth round the sun (aberration), and to the influence of the radial components of the relative motions of the fixed stars with respect to the earth on the colour of the light reaching us from them. The latter effect manifests itself in a slight displacement of the spectral lines of the light transmitted to us from a fixed star, as compared with the position of the same spectral lines when they are produced by a terrestrial source of light (Doppler principle). The experimental arguments in favour of the Maxwell-Lorentz theory, which are at the same time arguments in favour of the theory of relativity, are too numerous to be set forth here. In reality they limit the theoretical possibilities to such an extent, that no other theory than that of Maxwell and Lorentz has been able to hold its own when tested by experience.

To what extent is the special theory of relativity supported by experience? This question isn't easy to answer for the reasons already mentioned regarding Fizeau's fundamental experiment. The special theory of relativity has emerged from the Maxwell-Lorentz theory of electromagnetic phenomena. Therefore, all experiential facts that support the electromagnetic theory also support the theory of relativity. Notably, the theory of relativity allows us to predict the effects produced on the light coming from the fixed stars. These results are derived in a very straightforward way, and the indicated effects, which are due to the relative motion of the Earth in relation to those fixed stars, align with experience. We refer to the annual movement of the apparent position of the fixed stars resulting from the Earth's orbit around the sun (aberration) and the influence of the radial components of the relative motions of the fixed stars in relation to Earth on the color of the light we receive from them. The latter effect appears as a slight shift in the spectral lines of the light we get from a fixed star, compared to the same spectral lines produced by a terrestrial light source (Doppler effect). The experimental evidence supporting the Maxwell-Lorentz theory, which also supports the theory of relativity, is too extensive to detail here. In reality, these arguments limit the theoretical possibilities so much that no other theory besides Maxwell and Lorentz's has been able to stand up to experimental testing.

But there are two classes of experimental facts hitherto obtained which can be represented in the Maxwell-Lorentz theory only by the introduction of an auxiliary hypothesis, which in itself—i.e. without making use of the theory of relativity—appears extraneous.

But there are two types of experimental facts that have been obtained so far which can only be represented in the Maxwell-Lorentz theory by introducing an additional hypothesis that, on its own—i.e. without relying on the theory of relativity—seems unrelated.

It is known that cathode rays and the so-called β-rays emitted by radioactive substances consist of negatively electrified particles (electrons) of very small inertia and large velocity. By examining the deflection of these rays under the influence of electric and magnetic fields, we can study the law of motion of these particles very exactly.

It is known that cathode rays and the so-called β-rays released by radioactive substances are made up of negatively charged particles (electrons) that have very little mass and high speed. By looking at how these rays are deflected by electric and magnetic fields, we can examine the motion of these particles very precisely.

In the theoretical treatment of these electrons, we are faced with the difficulty that electrodynamic theory of itself is unable to give an account of their nature. For since electrical masses of one sign repel each other, the negative electrical masses constituting the electron would necessarily be scattered under the influence of their mutual repulsions, unless there are forces of another kind operating between them, the nature of which has hitherto remained obscure to us.[13] If we now assume that the relative distances between the electrical masses constituting the electron remain unchanged during the motion of the electron (rigid connection in the sense of classical mechanics), we arrive at a law of motion of the electron which does not agree with experience. Guided by purely formal points of view, H. A. Lorentz was the first to introduce the hypothesis that the form of the electron experiences a contraction in the direction of motion in consequence of that motion. the contracted length being proportional to the expression

In dealing with these electrons theoretically, we run into the issue that electrodynamic theory alone can't explain their nature. Since like electrical charges repel each other, the negative charges that make up the electron would naturally spread apart due to their mutual repulsion, unless there are other forces at play between them, the specifics of which remain unclear to us.[13] If we assume that the distances between the electrical charges making up the electron stay the same while the electron is in motion (a rigid connection in the classical mechanics sense), we come up with a motion law for the electron that doesn't fit with what we observe. Following a purely formal approach, H. A. Lorentz was the first to propose the idea that the shape of the electron contracts in the direction of motion as a result of that motion, with the contracted length being proportional to the expression

image029

This, hypothesis, which is not justifiable by any electrodynamical facts, supplies us then with that particular law of motion which has been confirmed with great precision in recent years.

This hypothesis, which cannot be justified by any electrodynamical facts, provides us with that specific law of motion that has been confirmed with great precision in recent years.

[13]
The general theory of relativity renders it likely that the electrical masses of an electron are held together by gravitational forces.

[13]
The general theory of relativity makes it likely that the electrical masses of an electron are held together by gravitational forces.

The theory of relativity leads to the same law of motion, without requiring any special hypothesis whatsoever as to the structure and the behaviour of the electron. We arrived at a similar conclusion in Section XIII in connection with the experiment of Fizeau, the result of which is foretold by the theory of relativity without the necessity of drawing on hypotheses as to the physical nature of the liquid.

The theory of relativity results in the same law of motion, without needing any specific assumptions about the structure and behavior of the electron. We reached a similar conclusion in Section XIII regarding Fizeau's experiment, the outcome of which is predicted by the theory of relativity without the need to rely on assumptions about the liquid's physical nature.

The second class of facts to which we have alluded has reference to the question whether or not the motion of the earth in space can be made perceptible in terrestrial experiments. We have already remarked in Section V that all attempts of this nature led to a negative result. Before the theory of relativity was put forward, it was difficult to become reconciled to this negative result, for reasons now to be discussed. The inherited prejudices about time and space did not allow any doubt to arise as to the prime importance of the Galileian transformation for changing over from one body of reference to another. Now assuming that the Maxwell-Lorentz equations hold for a reference-body K, we then find that they do not hold for a reference-body K′ moving uniformly with respect to K, if we assume that the relations of the Galileian transformation exist between the co-ordinates of K and K′. It thus appears that, of all Galileian co-ordinate systems, one (K) corresponding to a particular state of motion is physically unique. This result was interpreted physically by regarding K as at rest with respect to a hypothetical æther of space. On the other hand, all coordinate systems K′ moving relatively to K were to be regarded as in motion with respect to the æther. To this motion of K′ against the æther (“æther-drift” relative to K′) were attributed the more complicated laws which were supposed to hold relative to K′. Strictly speaking, such an æther-drift ought also to be assumed relative to the earth, and for a long time the efforts of physicists were devoted to attempts to detect the existence of an æther-drift at the earth’s surface.

The second category of facts we mentioned refers to whether the Earth's motion in space can be detected in experiments on Earth. As we pointed out in Section V, all attempts to do this have resulted in negative outcomes. Before the theory of relativity was proposed, it was hard to accept these negative results for reasons that we will discuss now. The deep-seated beliefs about time and space created no doubt about the critical importance of the Galilean transformation for switching from one frame of reference to another. Assuming that the Maxwell-Lorentz equations apply to a reference frame K, we find they don’t apply to a reference frame K′ moving uniformly relative to K, if we assume that the Galilean transformation relations exist between the coordinates of K and K′. It seems that, of all Galilean coordinate systems, one (K) that corresponds to a specific state of motion is physically unique. This result was physically interpreted by viewing K as being at rest relative to a hypothetical ether of space. Meanwhile, all coordinate systems K′ that move relative to K were considered to be in motion concerning the ether. This motion of K′ against the ether ("ether-drift" relative to K′) was believed to account for the more complex laws thought to apply relative to K′. Strictly speaking, such ether-drift should also be considered relative to the Earth, and for a long time, physicists focused on trying to detect the existence of ether-drift at the Earth's surface.

In one of the most notable of these attempts Michelson devised a method which appears as though it must be decisive. Imagine two mirrors so arranged on a rigid body that the reflecting surfaces face each other. A ray of light requires a perfectly definite time T to pass from one mirror to the other and back again, if the whole system be at rest with respect to the æther. It is found by calculation, however, that a slightly different time T′ is required for this process, if the body, together with the mirrors, be moving relatively to the æther. And yet another point: it is shown by calculation that for a given velocity v with reference to the æther, this time T′ is different when the body is moving perpendicularly to the planes of the mirrors from that resulting when the motion is parallel to these planes. Although the estimated difference between these two times is exceedingly small, Michelson and Morley performed an experiment involving interference in which this difference should have been clearly detectable. But the experiment gave a negative result—a fact very perplexing to physicists. Lorentz and FitzGerald rescued the theory from this difficulty by assuming that the motion of the body relative to the æther produces a contraction of the body in the direction of motion, the amount of contraction being just sufficient to compensate for the difference in time mentioned above. Comparison with the discussion in Section XII shows that also from the standpoint of the theory of relativity this solution of the difficulty was the right one. But on the basis of the theory of relativity the method of interpretation is incomparably more satisfactory. According to this theory there is no such thing as a “specially favoured” (unique) co-ordinate system to occasion the introduction of the æther-idea, and hence there can be no æther-drift, nor any experiment with which to demonstrate it. Here the contraction of moving bodies follows from the two fundamental principles of the theory, without the introduction of particular hypotheses; and as the prime factor involved in this contraction we find, not the motion in itself, to which we cannot attach any meaning, but the motion with respect to the body of reference chosen in the particular case in point. Thus for a co-ordinate system moving with the earth the mirror system of Michelson and Morley is not shortened, but it is shortened for a co-ordinate system which is at rest relatively to the sun.

In one of the most notable attempts, Michelson came up with a method that seemed like it could provide a definitive answer. Picture two mirrors set up on a solid structure so that their reflective surfaces face each other. A beam of light takes a specific time T to travel from one mirror to the other and back, if the entire system is stationary relative to the ether. However, calculations reveal that a slightly different time T′ is required if the structure, along with the mirrors, is moving relative to the ether. Additionally, it is shown through calculations that for a given speed v with respect to the ether, this time T′ differs depending on whether the structure is moving perpendicularly to the mirrors or parallel to them. Although the estimated difference between these two times is incredibly small, Michelson and Morley conducted an interference experiment where this difference should have been clearly noticeable. Surprisingly, the experiment yielded a negative result, which baffled physicists. Lorentz and FitzGerald offered a resolution to this issue by proposing that the motion of the body relative to the ether causes a contraction along the direction of motion, with the amount of contraction precisely enough to offset the time difference mentioned earlier. Comparing this with the discussion in Section XII shows that this solution also aligns with the theory of relativity. However, from the perspective of relativity, the way of interpretation is far more satisfactory. According to this theory, there is no “specially favored” (unique) coordinate system to justify the ether concept, so there's no ether drift or any experiment to prove it. Here, the contraction of moving bodies arises from the two fundamental principles of the theory, without needing any specific hypotheses. Instead of focusing on motion itself, which lacks meaning, we look at motion relative to the chosen reference frame. Thus, for a coordinate system moving with the Earth, the Michelson and Morley mirror setup is not contracted, but it is contracted for a coordinate system that is stationary relative to the sun.

XVII.
MINKOWSKI’S FOUR-DIMENSIONAL SPACE

The non-mathematician is seized by a mysterious shuddering when he hears of “four-dimensional” things, by a feeling not unlike that awakened by thoughts of the occult. And yet there is no more common-place statement than that the world in which we live is a four-dimensional space-time continuum.

The average person gets a strange feeling when they hear about "four-dimensional" concepts, a sensation similar to thoughts about the mysterious. And yet, it's a pretty standard statement that the world we live in is a four-dimensional space-time continuum.

Space is a three-dimensional continuum. By this we mean that it is possible to describe the position of a point (at rest) by means of three numbers (co-ordinates) x, y, z, and that there is an indefinite number of points in the neighbourhood of this one, the position of which can be described by co-ordinates such as x1, y1, z1, which may be as near as we choose to the respective values of the co-ordinates x, y, z, of the first point. In virtue of the latter property we speak of a “continuum,” and owing to the fact that there are three co-ordinates we speak of it as being “three-dimensional.”

Space is a three-dimensional continuum. This means that we can describe the position of a point (at rest) using three numbers (coordinates) x, y, z, and there are countless other points nearby that can be described with coordinates like x1, y1, z1, which can be as close as we want to the respective values of x, y, z for the first point. Because of this property, we call it a “continuum,” and since there are three coordinates, we refer to it as “three-dimensional.”

Similarly, the world of physical phenomena which was briefly called “world” by Minkowski is naturally four dimensional in the space-time sense. For it is composed of individual events, each of which is described by four numbers, namely, three space co-ordinates x, y, z, and a time co-ordinate, the time value t. The “world” is in this sense also a continuum; for to every event there are as many “neighbouring” events (realised or at least thinkable) as we care to choose, the co-ordinates x1, y1, z1, t1 of which differ by an indefinitely small amount from those of the event x, y, z, t originally considered. That we have not been accustomed to regard the world in this sense as a four-dimensional continuum is due to the fact that in physics, before the advent of the theory of relativity, time played a different and more independent rôle, as compared with the space coordinates. It is for this reason that we have been in the habit of treating time as an independent continuum. As a matter of fact, according to classical mechanics, time is absolute, i.e. it is independent of the position and the condition of motion of the system of co-ordinates. We see this expressed in the last equation of the Galileian transformation (t′ = t).

Similarly, the realm of physical phenomena that Minkowski briefly referred to as the “world” is naturally four-dimensional in the space-time context. It's made up of individual events, each described by four numbers: three spatial coordinates x, y, z, and a time coordinate, the time value t. The “world” is also a continuum; for every event, there are countless “neighboring” events (either realized or at least conceivable) that we can choose, with coordinates x1, y1, z1, t1 differing by an infinitely small amount from those of the originally considered event x, y, z, t. Our reluctance to view the world as a four-dimensional continuum stems from the fact that in physics, prior to the development of the theory of relativity, time served a different and more independent role compared to spatial coordinates. This is why we have traditionally treated time as an independent continuum. In fact, according to classical mechanics, time is absolute, i.e. it doesn't depend on the position and motion of the coordinate system. We see this reflected in the last equation of the Galilean transformation (t′ = t).

The four-dimensional mode of consideration of the “world” is natural on the theory of relativity, since according to this theory time is robbed of its independence. This is shown by the fourth equation of the Lorentz transformation:

The four-dimensional way of looking at the “world” makes sense in the theory of relativity, as this theory takes away time's independence. This is indicated by the fourth equation of the Lorentz transformation:

image030

Moreover, according to this equation the time difference Δt′ of two events with respect to K′ does not in general vanish, even when the time difference Δt of the same events with reference to K vanishes. Pure “space-distance” of two events with respect to K results in “time-distance ” of the same events with respect to K. But the discovery of Minkowski, which was of importance for the formal development of the theory of relativity, does not lie here. It is to be found rather in the fact of his recognition that the four-dimensional space-time continuum of the theory of relativity, in its most essential formal properties, shows a pronounced relationship to the three-dimensional continuum of Euclidean geometrical space.[14] In order to give due prominence to this relationship, however, we must replace the usual time co-ordinate t by an imaginary magnitude

Moreover, according to this equation, the time difference Δt′ between two events with respect to K′ generally does not disappear, even when the time difference Δt between the same events in reference to K does vanish. The pure “space-distance” of two events in relation to K results in a “time-distance” of those same events in relation to K. However, Minkowski's discovery, which was important for the formal development of the theory of relativity, is not found here. It lies rather in his recognition that the four-dimensional space-time continuum of the theory of relativity, in its most essential formal properties, has a significant relationship to the three-dimensional continuum of Euclidean geometric space.[14] To adequately highlight this relationship, we must replace the usual time coordinate t with an imaginary quantity.

image031

proportional to it. Under these conditions, the natural laws satisfying the demands of the (special) theory of relativity assume mathematical forms, in which the time co-ordinate plays exactly the same role as the three space co-ordinates. Formally, these four co-ordinates correspond exactly to the three space co-ordinates in Euclidean geometry. It must be clear even to the non-mathematician that, as a consequence of this purely formal addition to our knowledge, the theory perforce gained clearness in no mean measure.

proportional to it. Under these conditions, the natural laws that meet the requirements of the (special) theory of relativity take on mathematical forms where the time coordinate has the same significance as the three spatial coordinates. Formally, these four coordinates match the three spatial coordinates found in Euclidean geometry. It should be clear even to someone without a math background that this purely formal enhancement to our understanding significantly improved the clarity of the theory.

[14]
Cf. the somewhat more detailed discussion in Appendix II.

[14]
See the more detailed discussion in Appendix II.

These inadequate remarks can give the reader only a vague notion of the important idea contributed by Minkowski. Without it the general theory of relativity, of which the fundamental ideas are developed in the following pages, would perhaps have got no farther than its long clothes. Minkowski’s work is doubtless difficult of access to anyone inexperienced in mathematics, but since it is not necessary to have a very exact grasp of this work in order to understand the fundamental ideas of either the special or the general theory of relativity, I shall leave it here at present, and revert to it only towards the end of Part II.

These inadequate comments can only give the reader a vague idea of the important concept introduced by Minkowski. Without it, the general theory of relativity, which is explored in the following pages, might not have progressed beyond its early form. Minkowski’s work is definitely challenging for anyone not well-versed in mathematics, but since you don't need a very detailed understanding of his work to grasp the core ideas of either the special or general theory of relativity, I’ll set it aside for now and return to it later in Part II.

PART II: THE GENERAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY

XVIII.
SPECIAL AND GENERAL PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY

The basal principle, which was the pivot of all our previous considerations, was the special principle of relativity, i.e. the principle of the physical relativity of all uniform motion. Let as once more analyse its meaning carefully.

The fundamental principle, which was the centerpiece of all our earlier discussions, was the special principle of relativity, i.e. the principle of the physical relativity of all uniform motion. Let's analyze its meaning carefully once again.

It was at all times clear that, from the point of view of the idea it conveys to us, every motion must be considered only as a relative motion. Returning to the illustration we have frequently used of the embankment and the railway carriage, we can express the fact of the motion here taking place in the following two forms, both of which are equally justifiable:

It was always clear that, in terms of the idea it presents to us, any motion should be seen as a relative motion. Referring back to the example we've often used of the embankment and the train carriage, we can express the motion happening here in these two ways, both of which are equally valid:

(a) The carriage is in motion relative to the embankment,

(a) The carriage is moving in relation to the embankment,

(b) The embankment is in motion relative to the carriage.

(b) The embankment is moving in relation to the carriage.

In (a) the embankment, in (b) the carriage, serves as the body of reference in our statement of the motion taking place. If it is simply a question of detecting or of describing the motion involved, it is in principle immaterial to what reference-body we refer the motion. As already mentioned, this is self-evident, but it must not be confused with the much more comprehensive statement called “the principle of relativity,” which we have taken as the basis of our investigations.

In (a) the embankment, in (b) the carriage, acts as the reference point in our description of the motion happening. If the goal is just to identify or explain the motion involved, it doesn't really matter which reference point we use. As already noted, this is obvious, but it shouldn't be mistaken for the broader concept known as “the principle of relativity,” which we have used as the foundation of our research.

The principle we have made use of not only maintains that we may equally well choose the carriage or the embankment as our reference-body for the description of any event (for this, too, is self-evident). Our principle rather asserts what follows: If we formulate the general laws of nature as they are obtained from experience, by making use of

The principle we've used states that we can just as easily choose the carriage or the embankment as our reference point for describing any event (this is also obvious). Our principle actually claims the following: If we define the general laws of nature based on our experiences, by using

(a) the embankment as reference-body,

the embankment as reference point,

(b) the railway carriage as reference-body,

(b) the train carriage as reference body,

then these general laws of nature (e.g. the laws of mechanics or the law of the propagation of light in vacuo) have exactly the same form in both cases. This can also be expressed as follows: For the physical description of natural processes, neither of the reference bodies K, K′ is unique (lit. “specially marked out”) as compared with the other. Unlike the first, this latter statement need not of necessity hold a priori; it is not contained in the conceptions of “motion” and “reference-body” and derivable from them; only experience can decide as to its correctness or incorrectness.

then these general laws of nature (e.g. the laws of mechanics or the law of the propagation of light in a vacuum) have exactly the same form in both cases. This can also be stated as follows: For the physical description of natural processes, neither of the reference bodies K or K′ is unique (literally “specially marked out”) compared to the other. Unlike the first, this latter statement does not have to be true a priori; it is not contained in the concepts of “motion” and “reference body” and cannot be derived from them; only experience can determine its correctness or incorrectness.

Up to the present, however, we have by no means maintained the equivalence of all bodies of reference K in connection with the formulation of natural laws. Our course was more on the following Iines. In the first place, we started out from the assumption that there exists a reference-body K, whose condition of motion is such that the Galileian law holds with respect to it: A particle left to itself and sufficiently far removed from all other particles moves uniformly in a straight line. With reference to K (Galileian reference-body) the laws of nature were to be as simple as possible. But in addition to K, all bodies of reference K′ should be given preference in this sense, and they should be exactly equivalent to K for the formulation of natural laws, provided that they are in a state of uniform rectilinear and non-rotary motion with respect to K; all these bodies of reference are to be regarded as Galileian reference-bodies. The validity of the principle of relativity was assumed only for these reference-bodies, but not for others (e.g. those possessing motion of a different kind). In this sense we speak of the special principle of relativity, or special theory of relativity.

Up to now, we definitely haven't kept the equivalence of all reference frames K when it comes to formulating natural laws. Our approach went more like this: first, we assumed there exists a reference frame K, where the Galilean law holds true. A particle that is on its own and far enough from other particles moves in a straight line at a constant speed. In relation to K (the Galilean reference frame), the laws of nature were meant to be as straightforward as possible. However, in addition to K, all reference frames K′ should also be prioritized in this way, and they should be exactly equivalent to K for formulating natural laws, as long as they are in a state of uniform straight-line and non-rotational motion relative to K; all these reference frames should be considered Galilean reference frames. The validity of the principle of relativity was assumed only for these reference frames, but not for others (e.g. those with different kinds of motion). In this context, we refer to the special principle of relativity, or the special theory of relativity.

In contrast to this we wish to understand by the “general principle of relativity” the following statement: All bodies of reference K, K′, etc., are equivalent for the description of natural phenomena (formulation of the general laws of nature), whatever may be their state of motion. But before proceeding farther, it ought to be pointed out that this formulation must be replaced later by a more abstract one, for reasons which will become evident at a later stage.

In contrast to this, we want to understand the “general principle of relativity” as follows: All reference bodies K, K′, etc., are equivalent for describing natural phenomena (the formulation of the general laws of nature), regardless of their state of motion. However, before moving forward, it’s important to note that this formulation will later need to be replaced with a more abstract one, for reasons that will become clear later on.

Since the introduction of the special principle of relativity has been justified, every intellect which strives after generalisation must feel the temptation to venture the step towards the general principle of relativity. But a simple and apparently quite reliable consideration seems to suggest that, for the present at any rate, there is little hope of success in such an attempt; Let us imagine ourselves transferred to our old friend the railway carriage, which is travelling at a uniform rate. As long as it is moving uniformly, the occupant of the carriage is not sensible of its motion, and it is for this reason that he can without reluctance interpret the facts of the case as indicating that the carriage is at rest, but the embankment in motion. Moreover, according to the special principle of relativity, this interpretation is quite justified also from a physical point of view. If the motion of the carriage is now changed into a non-uniform motion, as for instance by a powerful application of the brakes, then the occupant of the carriage experiences a correspondingly powerful jerk forwards. The retarded motion is manifested in the mechanical behaviour of bodies relative to the person in the railway carriage. The mechanical behaviour is different from that of the case previously considered, and for this reason it would appear to be impossible that the same mechanical laws hold relatively to the non-uniformly moving carriage, as hold with reference to the carriage when at rest or in uniform motion. At all events it is clear that the Galileian law does not hold with respect to the non-uniformly moving carriage. Because of this, we feel compelled at the present juncture to grant a kind of absolute physical reality to non-uniform motion, in opposition to the general principle of relativity. But in what follows we shall soon see that this conclusion cannot be maintained.

Since the introduction of the special principle of relativity has been validated, anyone seeking a broader understanding must feel tempted to take the leap toward the general principle of relativity. However, a straightforward and seemingly dependable consideration suggests that, at least for now, there's little hope for success in such an effort. Let's picture ourselves in our old friend, the railway carriage, which is moving at a steady speed. As long as it's moving uniformly, the person in the carriage is unaware of its motion, allowing them to comfortably interpret the situation as if the carriage is at rest while the embankment is moving. Furthermore, according to the special principle of relativity, this interpretation is also physically justified. If the carriage's motion suddenly changes to an uneven one, like when the brakes are applied forcefully, the occupant will feel a strong jolt forward. This change in motion is evident in how objects behave relative to the person in the carriage. The mechanical behavior differs from the previous scenario, making it seem impossible for the same mechanical laws to apply to a non-uniformly moving carriage as they do when the carriage is at rest or moving uniformly. It's clear that the Galilean law doesn't hold for the non-uniformly moving carriage. Because of this, we feel compelled at this moment to acknowledge a sort of absolute physical reality to non-uniform motion, which contradicts the general principle of relativity. However, soon we will see that this conclusion cannot be upheld.

XIX.
THE GRAVITATIONAL FIELD

“If we pick up a stone and then let it go, why does it fall to the ground?” The usual answer to this question is: “Because it is attracted by the earth.” Modern physics formulates the answer rather differently for the following reason. As a result of the more careful study of electromagnetic phenomena, we have come to regard action at a distance as a process impossible without the intervention of some intermediary medium. If, for instance, a magnet attracts a piece of iron, we cannot be content to regard this as meaning that the magnet acts directly on the iron through the intermediate empty space, but we are constrained to imagine—after the manner of Faraday—that the magnet always calls into being something physically real in the space around it, that something being what we call a “magnetic field.” In its turn this magnetic field operates on the piece of iron, so that the latter strives to move towards the magnet. We shall not discuss here the justification for this incidental conception, which is indeed a somewhat arbitrary one. We shall only mention that with its aid electromagnetic phenomena can be theoretically represented much more satisfactorily than without it, and this applies particularly to the transmission of electromagnetic waves. The effects of gravitation also are regarded in an analogous manner.

“If we pick up a stone and then let it go, why does it fall to the ground?” The typical answer to this question is: “Because it is attracted by the Earth.” Modern physics explains this differently for a few reasons. After carefully studying electromagnetic phenomena, we now see action at a distance as a process that requires some intermediary medium. For example, when a magnet attracts a piece of iron, we can't simply say the magnet acts directly on the iron through empty space. Instead, we are led to imagine—following Faraday’s ideas—that the magnet creates something physically real in the space around it, which we call a “magnetic field.” This magnetic field then affects the piece of iron, causing it to move toward the magnet. We won't explore the justification for this additional concept here, as it is somewhat arbitrary. However, it's worth noting that it helps us represent electromagnetic phenomena much more effectively, especially concerning the transmission of electromagnetic waves. The effects of gravitation are also viewed in a similar way.

The action of the earth on the stone takes place indirectly. The earth produces in its surrounding a gravitational field, which acts on the stone and produces its motion of fall. As we know from experience, the intensity of the action on a body dimishes according to a quite definite law, as we proceed farther and farther away from the earth. From our point of view this means: The law governing the properties of the gravitational field in space must be a perfectly definite one, in order correctly to represent the diminution of gravitational action with the distance from operative bodies. It is something like this: The body (e.g. the earth) produces a field in its immediate neighbourhood directly; the intensity and direction of the field at points farther removed from the body are thence determined by the law which governs the properties in space of the gravitational fields themselves.

The way the earth affects the stone happens indirectly. The earth creates a gravitational field around it, which pulls on the stone and causes it to fall. As we know from experience, the strength of this effect on an object decreases according to a specific law as we move further away from the earth. From our perspective, this means that the law governing the properties of the gravitational field in space must be very precise to accurately reflect how gravitational influence decreases with distance from the sources of that influence. It works like this: The body (e.g., the earth) generates a field directly in its immediate vicinity; the strength and direction of the field at points further away from the body are determined by the law that governs the characteristics of gravitational fields in space.

In contrast to electric and magnetic fields, the gravitational field exhibits a most remarkable property, which is of fundamental importance for what follows. Bodies which are moving under the sole influence of a gravitational field receive an acceleration, which does not in the least depend either on the material or on the physical state of the body. For instance, a piece of lead and a piece of wood fall in exactly the same manner in a gravitational field (in vacuo), when they start off from rest or with the same initial velocity. This law, which holds most accurately, can be expressed in a different form in the light of the following consideration.

In contrast to electric and magnetic fields, the gravitational field has a remarkable property that is fundamentally important for what follows. Objects moving solely under the influence of a gravitational field experience an acceleration, which does not depend at all on the material or the physical state of the object. For example, a piece of lead and a piece of wood fall in exactly the same way in a gravitational field (in vacuo), whether they start from rest or with the same initial velocity. This law, which is very precise, can be expressed differently considering the following.

According to Newton’s law of motion, we have

According to Newton’s law of motion, we have

(Force) = (inertial mass) x (acceleration),

(Force) = (inertial mass) x (acceleration),

where the “inertial mass” is a characteristic constant of the accelerated body. If now gravitation is the cause of the acceleration, we then have

where the “inertial mass” is a constant characteristic of the accelerated object. If gravitation is the reason for the acceleration, we then have

(Force) = (gravitational mass) x (intensity of the gravitational field),

(Force) = (gravitational mass) x (strength of the gravitational field),

where the “gravitational mass” is likewise a characteristic constant for the body. From these two relations follows:

where the “gravitational mass” is also a constant characteristic of the body. From these two relationships, it follows:

image032

If now, as we find from experience, the acceleration is to be independent of the nature and the condition of the body and always the same for a given gravitational field, then the ratio of the gravitational to the inertial mass must likewise be the same for all bodies. By a suitable choice of units we can thus make this ratio equal to unity. We then have the following law: The gravitational mass of a body is equal to its inertial mass.

If we now consider what we've learned from experience, the acceleration is independent of the characteristics and state of the object, and it is always the same within a specific gravitational field. Therefore, the ratio of gravitational mass to inertial mass must also be consistent for all objects. By picking appropriate units, we can make this ratio equal to one. We then establish this law: The gravitational mass of an object is equal to its inertial mass.

It is true that this important law had hitherto been recorded in mechanics, but it had not been interpreted. A satisfactory interpretation can be obtained only if we recognise the following fact: The same quality of a body manifests itself according to circumstances as “inertia” or as “weight” (lit. “heaviness”). In the following section we shall show to what extent this is actually the case, and how this question is connected with the general postulate of relativity.

It’s true that this important law has been noted in mechanics, but it hasn’t been interpreted. A clear interpretation can only be achieved if we acknowledge the following fact: The same quality of a body shows itself depending on the situation as “inertia” or as “weight” (literally “heaviness”). In the next section, we will demonstrate the extent to which this is actually the case and how this issue is related to the general principle of relativity.

XX.
THE EQUALITY OF INERTIAL AND GRAVITATIONAL MASS AS AN ARGUMENT FOR THE GENERAL POSTULATE OF RELATIVITY

We imagine a large portion of empty space, so far removed from stars and other appreciable masses, that we have before us approximately the conditions required by the fundamental law of Galilei. It is then possible to choose a Galileian reference-body for this part of space (world), relative to which points at rest remain at rest and points in motion continue permanently in uniform rectilinear motion. As reference-body let us imagine a spacious chest resembling a room with an observer inside who is equipped with apparatus. Gravitation naturally does not exist for this observer. He must fasten himself with strings to the floor, otherwise the slightest impact against the floor will cause him to rise slowly towards the ceiling of the room.

We picture a vast area of empty space, so far away from stars and other significant masses, that it roughly matches the conditions outlined by Galilei's fundamental law. This allows us to select a Galilean reference frame for this part of space (the universe), where objects at rest stay at rest and objects in motion keep moving in a straight line at a constant speed. Let's imagine a large chest that looks like a room, with an observer inside who has some equipment. In this scenario, gravity doesn’t affect the observer. They would need to tie themselves to the floor; otherwise, even a slight bump against the floor would send them slowly floating up toward the ceiling of the room.

To the middle of the lid of the chest is fixed externally a hook with rope attached, and now a “being” (what kind of a being is immaterial to us) begins pulling at this with a constant force. The chest together with the observer then begin to move “upwards” with a uniformly accelerated motion. In course of time their velocity will reach unheard-of values—provided that we are viewing all this from another reference-body which is not being pulled with a rope.

To the center of the chest's lid, an external hook is attached with a rope, and now a "being" (the type of being doesn't matter to us) starts pulling on it with a steady force. The chest, along with the observer, begins to move "upwards" with a consistent acceleration. Over time, their speed will reach unimaginable levels—assuming we're observing all of this from another reference point that isn't being pulled by the rope.

But how does the man in the chest regard the Process? The acceleration of the chest will be transmitted to him by the reaction of the floor of the chest. He must therefore take up this pressure by means of his legs if he does not wish to be laid out full length on the floor. He is then standing in the chest in exactly the same way as anyone stands in a room of a home on our earth. If he releases a body which he previously had in his land, the accelertion of the chest will no longer be transmitted to this body, and for this reason the body will approach the floor of the chest with an accelerated relative motion. The observer will further convince himself that the acceleration of the body towards the floor of the chest is always of the same magnitude, whatever kind of body he may happen to use for the experiment.

But how does the man in the chest perceive the Process? The acceleration of the chest will be passed on to him through the reaction of the chest floor. Therefore, he must brace himself with his legs if he doesn’t want to be sprawled out flat on the floor. He is then standing in the chest just like anyone stands in a room at home here on Earth. If he drops an object that he had in his hands, the chest's acceleration won’t be transmitted to that object, which is why the object will fall towards the floor of the chest with an accelerated relative motion. The observer will also confirm that the acceleration of the object towards the floor of the chest remains constant, regardless of what kind of object he uses for the experiment.

Relying on his knowledge of the gravitational field (as it was discussed in the preceding section), the man in the chest will thus come to the conclusion that he and the chest are in a gravitational field which is constant with regard to time. Of course he will be puzzled for a moment as to why the chest does not fall in this gravitational field. just then, however, he discovers the hook in the middle of the lid of the chest and the rope which is attached to it, and he consequently comes to the conclusion that the chest is suspended at rest in the gravitational field.

Relying on his understanding of the gravitational field (as discussed in the previous section), the man in the chest will conclude that he and the chest are in a gravitational field that remains constant over time. Naturally, he will be confused for a moment about why the chest doesn't fall in this gravitational field. However, just then, he notices the hook in the center of the lid of the chest and the rope tied to it, leading him to realize that the chest is suspended and not moving in the gravitational field.

Ought we to smile at the man and say that he errs in his conclusion? I do not believe we ought to if we wish to remain consistent; we must rather admit that his mode of grasping the situation violates neither reason nor known mechanical laws. Even though it is being accelerated with respect to the “Galileian space” first considered, we can nevertheless regard the chest as being at rest. We have thus good grounds for extending the principle of relativity to include bodies of reference which are accelerated with respect to each other, and as a result we have gained a powerful argument for a generalised postulate of relativity.

Should we smile at the man and say he's wrong in his conclusion? I don't think we should if we want to stay consistent; we need to acknowledge that his way of understanding the situation doesn't contradict reason or known mechanical laws. Even though it's accelerating compared to the initially considered "Galileian space," we can still see the chest as being at rest. This gives us solid reasons to expand the principle of relativity to encompass reference bodies that are accelerating in relation to each other, and as a result, we've gained a strong argument for a generalized postulate of relativity.

We must note carefully that the possibility of this mode of interpretation rests on the fundamental property of the gravitational field of giving all bodies the same acceleration, or, what comes to the same thing, on the law of the equality of inertial and gravitational mass. If this natural law did not exist, the man in the accelerated chest would not be able to interpret the behaviour of the bodies around him on the supposition of a gravitational field, and he would not be justified on the grounds of experience in supposing his reference-body to be “at rest.”

We need to take note that the possibility of this way of interpreting things relies on the basic property of the gravitational field, which causes all objects to accelerate at the same rate, or, in other words, on the principle that inertial mass and gravitational mass are equal. If this natural law didn't exist, a person in the accelerating room wouldn't be able to understand the behavior of the objects around them by assuming there's a gravitational field, and they wouldn't have a valid basis in experience for considering their reference point to be “at rest.”

Suppose that the man in the chest fixes a rope to the inner side of the lid, and that he attaches a body to the free end of the rope. The result of this will be to stretch the rope so that it will hang “vertically” downwards. If we ask for an opinion of the cause of tension in the rope, the man in the chest will say: “The suspended body experiences a downward force in the gravitational field, and this is neutralised by the tension of the rope; what determines the magnitude of the tension of the rope is the gravitational mass of the suspended body.” On the other hand, an observer who is poised freely in space will interpret the condition of things thus: “The rope must perforce take part in the accelerated motion of the chest, and it transmits this motion to the body attached to it. The tension of the rope is just large enough to effect the acceleration of the body. That which determines the magnitude of the tension of the rope is the inertial mass of the body.” Guided by this example, we see that our extension of the principle of relativity implies the necessity of the law of the equality of inertial and gravitational mass. Thus we have obtained a physical interpretation of this law.

Suppose the man in the chest ties a rope to the inside of the lid and attaches an object to the free end of the rope. This will stretch the rope so that it hangs “vertically” downwards. If we ask for an opinion on the cause of the tension in the rope, the man in the chest will say: “The suspended object feels a downward force in the gravitational field, and this is balanced by the tension in the rope; the amount of tension in the rope is determined by the gravitational mass of the suspended object.” On the other hand, an observer floating freely in space will interpret the situation this way: “The rope has to participate in the accelerated motion of the chest, and it transmits this motion to the object attached to it. The tension in the rope is just enough to make the object accelerate. What determines the amount of tension in the rope is the inertial mass of the object.” This example shows that extending the principle of relativity implies the necessity of the law stating that inertial and gravitational mass are equal. Thus, we have provided a physical interpretation of this law.

From our consideration of the accelerated chest we see that a general theory of relativity must yield important results on the laws of gravitation. In point of fact, the systematic pursuit of the general idea of relativity has supplied the laws satisfied by the gravitational field. Before proceeding farther, however, I must warn the reader against a misconception suggested by these considerations. A gravitational field exists for the man in the chest, despite the fact that there was no such field for the co-ordinate system first chosen. Now we might easily suppose that the existence of a gravitational field is always only an apparent one. We might also think that, regardless of the kind of gravitational field which may be present, we could always choose another reference-body such that no gravitational field exists with reference to it. This is by no means true for all gravitational fields, but only for those of quite special form. It is, for instance, impossible to choose a body of reference such that, as judged from it, the gravitational field of the earth (in its entirety) vanishes.

From our examination of the accelerating chest, we understand that a general theory of relativity must provide significant insights into the laws of gravitation. In fact, the systematic exploration of the general concept of relativity has given us the laws governing the gravitational field. However, before going further, I need to caution the reader against a misunderstanding that these considerations might suggest. A gravitational field exists for the person in the chest, even though there was no such field for the coordinate system initially selected. Now, we might easily think that the presence of a gravitational field is always just an apparent phenomenon. We might also assume that, regardless of the type of gravitational field that may be present, we could always pick another reference body so that no gravitational field exists with respect to it. This is not true for all gravitational fields, but only for specific types. For example, it is impossible to select a reference body such that, from that perspective, the gravitational field of the Earth (in its entirety) disappears.

We can now appreciate why that argument is not convincing, which we brought forward against the general principle of relativity at the end of Section XVIII. It is certainly true that the observer in the railway carriage experiences a jerk forwards as a result of the application of the brake, and that he recognises, in this the non-uniformity of motion (retardation) of the carriage. But he is compelled by nobody to refer this jerk to a “real” acceleration (retardation) of the carriage. He might also interpret his experience thus: “My body of reference (the carriage) remains permanently at rest. With reference to it, however, there exists (during the period of application of the brakes) a gravitational field which is directed forwards and which is variable with respect to time. Under the influence of this field, the embankment together with the earth moves non-uniformly in such a manner that their original velocity in the backwards direction is continuously reduced.”

We can now see why that argument isn't convincing, which we mentioned against the general principle of relativity at the end of Section XVIII. It's definitely true that the observer in the train experiences a jolt forward when the brakes are applied, and he recognizes this as the non-uniform motion (deceleration) of the train. However, no one forces him to attribute this jolt to a “real” acceleration (deceleration) of the train. He could also interpret his experience this way: “My reference frame (the train) is staying still. However, in relation to it, during the time the brakes are applied, there is a gravitational field that acts forward and changes over time. Due to this field, the ground and the Earth move in a non-uniform way, causing their original backward velocity to decrease continuously.”

XXI.
IN WHAT RESPECTS ARE THE FOUNDATIONS OF CLASSICAL MECHANICS AND OF THE SPECIAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY UNSATISFACTORY?

We have already stated several times that classical mechanics starts out from the following law: Material particles sufficiently far removed from other material particles continue to move uniformly in a straight line or continue in a state of rest. We have also repeatedly emphasised that this fundamental law can only be valid for bodies of reference K which possess certain unique states of motion, and which are in uniform translational motion relative to each other. Relative to other reference-bodies K the law is not valid. Both in classical mechanics and in the special theory of relativity we therefore differentiate between reference-bodies K relative to which the recognised “laws of nature” can be said to hold, and reference-bodies K relative to which these laws do not hold.

We have already mentioned several times that classical mechanics starts with the following principle: Material particles that are far enough apart from other particles continue to move uniformly in a straight line or remain at rest. We have also stressed that this fundamental principle is only valid for reference bodies K that have specific unique states of motion and are in uniform translational motion relative to one another. This principle does not hold for other reference bodies K. Therefore, in both classical mechanics and the special theory of relativity, we distinguish between reference bodies K for which the established "laws of nature" apply, and reference bodies K for which these laws do not apply.

But no person whose mode of thought is logical can rest satisfied with this condition of things. He asks: “How does it come that certain reference-bodies (or their states of motion) are given priority over other reference-bodies (or their states of motion)? What is the reason for this preference?” In order to show clearly what I mean by this question, I shall make use of a comparison.

But no one who thinks logically can be okay with this situation. They ask, “Why do certain reference points (or their states of motion) get priority over others (or their states of motion)? What’s the reason for this preference?” To clarify what I mean by this question, I’ll use a comparison.

I am standing in front of a gas range. Standing alongside of each other on the range are two pans so much alike that one may be mistaken for the other. Both are half full of water. I notice that steam is being emitted continuously from the one pan, but not from the other. I am surprised at this, even if I have never seen either a gas range or a pan before. But if I now notice a luminous something of bluish colour under the first pan but not under the other, I cease to be astonished, even if I have never before seen a gas flame. For I can only say that this bluish something will cause the emission of the steam, or at least possibly it may do so. If, however, I notice the bluish something in neither case, and if I observe that the one continuously emits steam whilst the other does not, then I shall remain astonished and dissatisfied until I have discovered some circumstance to which I can attribute the different behaviour of the two pans.

I’m standing in front of a gas stove. Next to each other on the stove are two pans that look so similar that one could easily be mistaken for the other. Both are half full of water. I notice that steam is continuously rising from one pan, but not from the other. This surprises me, even though I’ve never seen a gas stove or a pan before. However, when I see a bluish light under the first pan but not under the other, I stop being surprised, even though I’ve never seen a gas flame before. I can only assume that this bluish light is what causes the steam to rise, or at least it might. But if I don’t see the bluish light in either case, and I notice that one pan is continuously steaming while the other is not, I’ll stay surprised and frustrated until I find a reason for the different behavior of the two pans.

Analogously, I seek in vain for a real something in classical mechanics (or in the special theory of relativity) to which I can attribute the different behaviour of bodies considered with respect to the reference systems K and K′.[15] Newton saw this objection and attempted to invalidate it, but without success. But E. Mach recognised it most clearly of all, and because of this objection he claimed that mechanics must be placed on a new basis. It can only be got rid of by means of a physics which is conformable to the general principle of relativity, since the equations of such a theory hold for every body of reference, whatever may be its state of motion.

Similarly, I look in vain for something real in classical mechanics (or the special theory of relativity) to explain the different behavior of objects when considering the reference systems K and K′.[15] Newton recognized this objection and tried to challenge it, but he wasn't successful. E. Mach understood it most clearly, and due to this objection, he argued that mechanics needed to be established on a new foundation. This issue can only be resolved with a physics that aligns with the general principle of relativity, as the equations of such a theory apply to every reference body, regardless of its state of motion.

[15]
The objection is of importance more especially when the state of motion of the reference-body is of such a nature that it does not require any external agency for its maintenance, e.g. in the case when the reference-body is rotating uniformly.

[15]
The objection is particularly important when the motion of the reference body is such that it doesn't need any outside force to keep going, e.g. when the reference body is rotating at a constant speed.

XXII.
A FEW INFERENCES FROM THE GENERAL PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY

The considerations of Section XX show that the general principle of relativity puts us in a position to derive properties of the gravitational field in a purely theoretical manner. Let us suppose, for instance, that we know the space-time “course” for any natural process whatsoever, as regards the manner in which it takes place in the Galileian domain relative to a Galileian body of reference K. By means of purely theoretical operations (i.e. simply by calculation) we are then able to find how this known natural process appears, as seen from a reference-body K′ which is accelerated relatively to K. But since a gravitational field exists with respect to this new body of reference K′, our consideration also teaches us how the gravitational field influences the process studied.

The considerations in Section XX show that the general principle of relativity allows us to determine properties of the gravitational field purely theoretically. For example, let’s assume we know the space-time “path” for any natural process, concerning how it occurs in the Galilean framework relative to a Galilean reference body K. Through purely theoretical operations (i.e. just by calculation), we can find out how this known natural process appears from the perspective of a reference body K′ that is accelerated compared to K. However, since a gravitational field exists in relation to this new reference body K′, our analysis also reveals how the gravitational field affects the process we're studying.

For example, we learn that a body which is in a state of uniform rectilinear motion with respect to K (in accordance with the law of Galilei) is executing an accelerated and in general curvilinear motion with respect to the accelerated reference-body K′ (chest). This acceleration or curvature corresponds to the influence on the moving body of the gravitational field prevailing relatively to K. It is known that a gravitational field influences the movement of bodies in this way, so that our consideration supplies us with nothing essentially new.

For example, we see that a body moving at a constant speed in a straight line with respect to K (according to Galileo's law) is actually moving in an accelerated, and generally curved, path with respect to the accelerated reference body K′ (chest). This acceleration or curvature comes from the effect of the gravitational field that exists relative to K. It's well understood that a gravitational field affects how bodies move like this, so this analysis doesn’t really give us any new insights.

However, we obtain a new result of fundamental importance when we carry out the analogous consideration for a ray of light. With respect to the Galileian reference-body K, such a ray of light is transmitted rectilinearly with the velocity c. It can easily be shown that the path of the same ray of light is no longer a straight line when we consider it with reference to the accelerated chest (reference-body K′). From this we conclude, that, in general, rays of light are propagated curvilinearly in gravitational fields. In two respects this result is of great importance.

However, we get a new result that is fundamentally important when we consider a ray of light in a similar way. In relation to the Galilean reference frame K, that ray of light travels in a straight line at a speed of c. It's easy to demonstrate that the path of the same ray of light is no longer straight when we look at it from the perspective of the accelerated frame (reference frame K′). From this, we conclude, that, in general, rays of light move in curved paths in gravitational fields. This result is significant in two ways.

In the first place, it can be compared with the reality. Although a detailed examination of the question shows that the curvature of light rays required by the general theory of relativity is only exceedingly small for the gravitational fields at our disposal in practice, its estimated magnitude for light rays passing the sun at grazing incidence is nevertheless 1.7 seconds of arc. This ought to manifest itself in the following way. As seen from the earth, certain fixed stars appear to be in the neighbourhood of the sun, and are thus capable of observation during a total eclipse of the sun. At such times, these stars ought to appear to be displaced outwards from the sun by an amount indicated above, as compared with their apparent position in the sky when the sun is situated at another part of the heavens. The examination of the correctness or otherwise of this deduction is a problem of the greatest importance, the early solution of which is to be expected of astronomers.[16]

In the first place, it can be compared with reality. Although a detailed examination of the question shows that the bending of light rays required by the general theory of relativity is only extremely small for the gravitational fields we encounter in practice, its estimated magnitude for light rays passing the sun at grazing incidence is still 1.7 seconds of arc. This should manifest in the following way: Seen from Earth, certain fixed stars seem to be near the sun and can therefore be observed during a total solar eclipse. At these times, these stars should appear slightly displaced outward from the sun by the amount mentioned above, compared to their apparent position in the sky when the sun is located in another part of the heavens. Verifying whether this deduction is correct or not is a matter of great importance, and astronomers are expected to solve it soon.[16]

[16]
By means of the star photographs of two expeditions equipped by a Joint Committee of the Royal and Royal Astronomical Societies, the existence of the deflection of light demanded by theory was first confirmed during the solar eclipse of 29th May, 1919. (Cf. Appendix III.)

[16]
Using star photographs from two expeditions organized by a Joint Committee of the Royal and Royal Astronomical Societies, the existence of the light bending predicted by theory was first confirmed during the solar eclipse on May 29, 1919. (Cf. Appendix III.)

In the second place our result shows that, according to the general theory of relativity, the law of the constancy of the velocity of light in vacuo, which constitutes one of the two fundamental assumptions in the special theory of relativity and to which we have already frequently referred, cannot claim any unlimited validity. A curvature of rays of light can only take place when the velocity of propagation of light varies with position. Now we might think that as a consequence of this, the special theory of relativity and with it the whole theory of relativity would be laid in the dust. But in reality this is not the case. We can only conclude that the special theory of relativity cannot claim an unlimited domain of validity; its results hold only so long as we are able to disregard the influences of gravitational fields on the phenomena (e.g. of light).

In addition, our findings indicate that, according to the general theory of relativity, the principle of the constant speed of light in a vacuum—one of the two main assumptions in the special theory of relativity that we've mentioned frequently—doesn't hold true in all situations. Light rays can only bend if the speed of light changes based on location. You might think this means that the special theory of relativity, and the entire theory of relativity, would be completely debunked. However, that's not the case. We can only conclude that the special theory of relativity doesn't have an unlimited range of validity; its conclusions remain valid only as long as we can ignore the effects of gravitational fields on various phenomena (e.g., light).

Since it has often been contended by opponents of the theory of relativity that the special theory of relativity is overthrown by the general theory of relativity, it is perhaps advisable to make the facts of the case clearer by means of an appropriate comparison. Before the development of electrodynamics the laws of electrostatics were looked upon as the laws of electricity. At the present time we know that electric fields can be derived correctly from electrostatic considerations only for the case, which is never strictly realised, in which the electrical masses are quite at rest relatively to each other, and to the co-ordinate system. Should we be justified in saying that for this reason electrostatics is overthrown by the field-equations of Maxwell in electrodynamics? Not in the least. Electrostatics is contained in electrodynamics as a limiting case; the laws of the latter lead directly to those of the former for the case in which the fields are invariable with regard to time. No fairer destiny could be allotted to any physical theory, than that it should of itself point out the way to the introduction of a more comprehensive theory, in which it lives on as a limiting case.

Since critics of the theory of relativity often claim that the general theory of relativity disproves the special theory of relativity, it might be helpful to clarify the situation through a relevant comparison. Before the rise of electrodynamics, the laws of electrostatics were considered the main laws of electricity. Nowadays, we understand that electric fields can only be accurately derived from electrostatic principles in the specific case—never fully realized—where the electrical masses are completely at rest in relation to one another and to the coordinate system. Should we conclude that electrostatics is invalidated by Maxwell's field equations in electrodynamics? Not at all. Electrostatics is actually included in electrodynamics as a limiting case; the laws of electrodynamics lead directly to those of electrostatics when the fields remain constant over time. No greater fate could be given to any physical theory than to have it naturally indicate the path to a more comprehensive theory, in which it continues to exist as a limiting case.

In the example of the transmission of light just dealt with, we have seen that the general theory of relativity enables us to derive theoretically the influence of a gravitational field on the course of natural processes, the laws of which are already known when a gravitational field is absent. But the most attractive problem, to the solution of which the general theory of relativity supplies the key, concerns the investigation of the laws satisfied by the gravitational field itself. Let us consider this for a moment.

In the example of light transmission we just discussed, we've seen that the general theory of relativity allows us to theoretically understand how a gravitational field affects natural processes, the rules of which we already know in the absence of a gravitational field. However, the most intriguing issue that the general theory of relativity helps us explore is the investigation of the laws that govern the gravitational field itself. Let's take a moment to consider this.

We are acquainted with space-time domains which behave (approximately) in a “Galileian” fashion under suitable choice of reference-body, i.e. domains in which gravitational fields are absent. If we now refer such a domain to a reference-body K′ possessing any kind of motion, then relative to K′ there exists a gravitational field which is variable with respect to space and time.[17] The character of this field will of course depend on the motion chosen for K′. According to the general theory of relativity, the general law of the gravitational field must be satisfied for all gravitational fields obtainable in this way. Even though by no means all gravitationial fields can be produced in this way, yet we may entertain the hope that the general law of gravitation will be derivable from such gravitational fields of a special kind. This hope has been realised in the most beautiful manner. But between the clear vision of this goal and its actual realisation it was necessary to surmount a serious difficulty, and as this lies deep at the root of things, I dare not withhold it from the reader. We require to extend our ideas of the space-time continuum still farther.

We are familiar with space-time areas that behave (roughly) in a "Galilean" way when we choose the right reference body, that is, areas where there are no gravitational fields. If we now relate such an area to a reference body K′ that has any kind of motion, then in relation to K′ there exists a gravitational field that changes with space and time. The nature of this field will, of course, depend on the motion chosen for K′. According to the general theory of relativity, the general law of the gravitational field must hold true for all gravitational fields that can be derived this way. Even though not all gravitational fields can be created this way, we can still hope that the general law of gravitation can be derived from these specific types of gravitational fields. This hope has been beautifully fulfilled. However, between the clear vision of this goal and its actual realization, we had to overcome a significant challenge, and since this challenge is fundamental, I cannot keep it from the reader. We need to expand our understanding of the space-time continuum even further.

[17]
This follows from a generalisation of the discussion in Section XX.

[17]
This is based on a generalization of the discussion in Section XX.

XXIII.
BEHAVIOUR OF CLOCKS AND MEASURING-RODS ON A ROTATING BODY OF REFERENCE

Hitherto I have purposely refrained from speaking about the physical interpretation of space- and time-data in the case of the general theory of relativity. As a consequence, I am guilty of a certain slovenliness of treatment, which, as we know from the special theory of relativity, is far from being unimportant and pardonable. It is now high time that we remedy this defect; but I would mention at the outset, that this matter lays no small claims on the patience and on the power of abstraction of the reader.

So far, I have intentionally avoided discussing the physical interpretation of space and time data in relation to the general theory of relativity. As a result, I acknowledge that I've been somewhat careless, which, as we learned from the special theory of relativity, is not insignificant or excusable. It’s time to address this shortcoming; however, I want to point out from the start that this topic requires a good deal of patience and the ability to think abstractly from the reader.

We start off again from quite special cases, which we have frequently used before. Let us consider a space time domain in which no gravitational field exists relative to a reference-body K whose state of motion has been suitably chosen. K is then a Galileian reference-body as regards the domain considered, and the results of the special theory of relativity hold relative to K. Let us suppose the same domain referred to a second body of reference K′, which is rotating uniformly with respect to K. In order to fix our ideas, we shall imagine K′ to be in the form of a plane circular disc, which rotates uniformly in its own plane about its centre. An observer who is sitting eccentrically on the disc K′ is sensible of a force which acts outwards in a radial direction, and which would be interpreted as an effect of inertia (centrifugal force) by an observer who was at rest with respect to the original reference-body K. But the observer on the disc may regard his disc as a reference-body which is “at rest”; on the basis of the general principle of relativity he is justified in doing this. The force acting on himself, and in fact on all other bodies which are at rest relative to the disc, he regards as the effect of a gravitational field. Nevertheless, the space-distribution of this gravitational field is of a kind that would not be possible on Newton’s theory of gravitation.[18] But since the observer believes in the general theory of relativity, this does not disturb him; he is quite in the right when he believes that a general law of gravitation can be formulated—a law which not only explains the motion of the stars correctly, but also the field of force experienced by himself.

We start again from some specific cases that we've often discussed before. Let’s consider a spacetime area where there’s no gravitational field relative to a reference body K whose motion has been appropriately chosen. K acts as a Galilean reference body for the area in question, and the results of special relativity apply to K. Now let’s take the same area but refer it to a second reference body K′, which is rotating steadily in relation to K. To visualize this, let’s imagine K′ as a flat circular disc rotating uniformly around its center. An observer sitting off-center on the disc K′ feels a force pushing outward radially, which an observer at rest relative to the original reference body K would interpret as inertial force (centrifugal force). However, the observer on the disc might view his disc as a "stationary" reference body; based on the general principle of relativity, he is justified in this belief. The force acting on him, and on all other objects at rest relative to the disc, is seen as the effect of a gravitational field. Still, the way this gravitational field is distributed in space wouldn’t align with Newton’s theory of gravitation.[18] But since the observer trusts in the general theory of relativity, this doesn’t unsettle him; he is entirely correct in believing that a general law of gravitation can be formulated—a law that not only accurately explains the movement of the stars but also the force field he experiences.

[18]
The field disappears at the centre of the disc and increases proportionally to the distance from the centre as we proceed outwards.

[18]
The field fades away at the center of the disk and grows proportionally as we move outward from the center.

The observer performs experiments on his circular disc with clocks and measuring-rods. In doing so, it is his intention to arrive at exact definitions for the signification of time- and space-data with reference to the circular disc K′, these definitions being based on his observations. What will be his experience in this enterprise?

The observer conducts experiments on his circular disc using clocks and measuring rods. His goal is to create precise definitions for the meaning of time and space data related to the circular disc K′, based on his observations. What will he encounter in this endeavor?

To start with, he places one of two identically constructed clocks at the centre of the circular disc, and the other on the edge of the disc, so that they are at rest relative to it. We now ask ourselves whether both clocks go at the same rate from the standpoint of the non-rotating Galileian reference-body K. As judged from this body, the clock at the centre of the disc has no velocity, whereas the clock at the edge of the disc is in motion relative to K in consequence of the rotation. According to a result obtained in Section XII, it follows that the latter clock goes at a rate permanently slower than that of the clock at the centre of the circular disc, i.e. as observed from K. It is obvious that the same effect would be noted by an observer whom we will imagine sitting alongside his clock at the centre of the circular disc. Thus on our circular disc, or, to make the case more general, in every gravitational field, a clock will go more quickly or less quickly, according to the position in which the clock is situated (at rest). For this reason it is not possible to obtain a reasonable definition of time with the aid of clocks which are arranged at rest with respect to the body of reference. A similar difficulty presents itself when we attempt to apply our earlier definition of simultaneity in such a case, but I do not wish to go any farther into this question.

To begin with, he places one of two identical clocks at the center of a circular disc and the other on the edge of the disc, so they are stationary relative to it. We now ask ourselves whether both clocks tick at the same rate from the perspective of the non-rotating Galilean reference frame K. From this frame, the clock at the center of the disc has no velocity, while the clock at the edge of the disc is moving relative to K because of the rotation. According to a result found in Section XII, this means that the clock at the edge ticks more slowly than the clock at the center of the circular disc, i.e. as seen from K. It's clear that the same effect would be observed by someone sitting next to the clock at the center of the circular disc. Therefore, on our circular disc, or, to generalize, in any gravitational field, a clock will tick faster or slower depending on its position (at rest). For this reason, it's not possible to define time reasonably using clocks that are stationary with respect to the reference body. We encounter a similar issue when we try to apply our earlier definition of simultaneity in this situation, but I don’t want to delve deeper into this topic.

Moreover, at this stage the definition of the space co-ordinates also presents insurmountable difficulties. If the observer applies his standard measuring-rod (a rod which is short as compared with the radius of the disc) tangentially to the edge of the disc, then, as judged from the Galileian system, the length of this rod will be less than 1, since, according to Section XII, moving bodies suffer a shortening in the direction of the motion. On the other hand, the measuring-rod will not experience a shortening in length, as judged from K, if it is applied to the disc in the direction of the radius. If, then, the observer first measures the circumference of the disc with his measuring-rod and then the diameter of the disc, on dividing the one by the other, he will not obtain as quotient the familiar number π = 3.14 . . ., but a larger number,[19] whereas of course, for a disc which is at rest with respect to K, this operation would yield π exactly. This proves that the propositions of Euclidean geometry cannot hold exactly on the rotating disc, nor in general in a gravitational field, at least if we attribute the length 1 to the rod in all positions and in every orientation. Hence the idea of a straight line also loses its meaning. We are therefore not in a position to define exactly the co-ordinates x, y, z relative to the disc by means of the method used in discussing the special theory, and as long as the co-ordinates and times of events have not been defined, we cannot assign an exact meaning to the natural laws in which these occur.

Moreover, at this stage, defining the space coordinates presents major challenges. If the observer uses their standard measuring rod (which is short compared to the radius of the disc) tangentially at the edge of the disc, then, according to the Galilean system, the length of this rod will appear shorter than 1, since, as mentioned in Section XII, moving objects experience a shortening in the direction of their motion. On the other hand, the measuring rod will not appear shorter when viewed from K if it is applied to the disc along the radius. If the observer first measures the circumference of the disc with their measuring rod and then measures the diameter, dividing the two measurements will not yield the familiar number π = 3.14..., but a larger number, [19], while for a disc that is stationary relative to K, this operation would yield exactly π. This demonstrates that the principles of Euclidean geometry cannot hold precisely on the rotating disc, or generally in a gravitational field, at least if we assign the length 1 to the rod in all positions and orientations. Therefore, the concept of a straight line also loses its meaning. As a result, we cannot precisely define the coordinates x, y, z relative to the disc using the method employed in discussing the special theory, and as long as the coordinates and times of events have not been defined, we cannot assign an exact meaning to the natural laws in which these occur.

[19]
Throughout this consideration we have to use the Galileian (non-rotating) system K as reference-body, since we may only assume the validity of the results of the special theory of relativity relative to K (relative to K′ a gravitational field prevails).

[19]
Throughout this discussion, we need to use the Galilean (non-rotating) system K as our reference point because we can only assume that the results of the special theory of relativity hold true relative to K (relative to K′, a gravitational field exists).

Thus all our previous conclusions based on general relativity would appear to be called in question. In reality we must make a subtle detour in order to be able to apply the postulate of general relativity exactly. I shall prepare the reader for this in the following paragraphs.

Thus, all our previous conclusions based on general relativity seem to be questioned. In reality, we need to take a subtle detour to apply the postulate of general relativity correctly. I will prepare the reader for this in the following paragraphs.

XXIV.
EUCLIDEAN AND NON-EUCLIDEAN CONTINUUM

The surface of a marble table is spread out in front of me. I can get from any one point on this table to any other point by passing continuously from one point to a “neighbouring” one, and repeating this process a (large) number of times, or, in other words, by going from point to point without executing “jumps.” I am sure the reader will appreciate with sufficient clearness what I mean here by “neighbouring” and by “jumps” (if he is not too pedantic). We express this property of the surface by describing the latter as a continuum.

The surface of a marble table lies before me. I can move from any point on this table to any other point by continuously passing from one "neighboring" point to another and repeating this process many times, or in other words, by moving from point to point without making any "jumps." I’m sure the reader understands clearly what I mean by "neighboring" and "jumps" (unless they’re being overly critical). We describe this characteristic of the surface by calling it a continuum.

Let us now imagine that a large number of little rods of equal length have been made, their lengths being small compared with the dimensions of the marble slab. When I say they are of equal length, I mean that one can be laid on any other without the ends overlapping. We next lay four of these little rods on the marble slab so that they constitute a quadrilateral figure (a square), the diagonals of which are equally long. To ensure the equality of the diagonals, we make use of a little testing-rod. To this square we add similar ones, each of which has one rod in common with the first. We proceed in like manner with each of these squares until finally the whole marble slab is laid out with squares. The arrangement is such, that each side of a square belongs to two squares and each corner to four squares.

Let’s imagine that we have a lot of small rods that are all the same length, and their lengths are short compared to the size of the marble slab. When I say they are the same length, I mean that one can be placed on top of another without the ends sticking out. Next, we lay down four of these small rods on the marble slab to form a quadrilateral shape (a square), with the diagonals being the same length. To check that the diagonals are equal, we use a small testing rod. We then add more squares, each sharing one rod with the first square. We keep doing this with each of these squares until the entire marble slab is covered in squares. The setup is such that each side of a square is part of two squares, and each corner is part of four squares.

It is a veritable wonder that we can carry out this business without getting into the greatest difficulties. We only need to think of the following. If at any moment three squares meet at a corner, then two sides of the fourth square are already laid, and, as a consequence, the arrangement of the remaining two sides of the square is already completely determined. But I am now no longer able to adjust the quadrilateral so that its diagonals may be equal. If they are equal of their own accord, then this is an especial favour of the marble slab and of the little rods, about which I can only be thankfully surprised. We must experience many such surprises if the construction is to be successful.

It’s truly amazing that we can manage this task without running into huge problems. We just need to consider this: If at any time three squares come together at a corner, then two sides of the fourth square are already placed, which means the positioning of the other two sides is completely determined. However, I can no longer adjust the quadrilateral so that its diagonals are equal. If they happen to be equal on their own, then that’s a special gift from the marble slab and the little rods, and I can only be pleasantly surprised by that. We need to encounter many such surprises if the project is going to succeed.

If everything has really gone smoothly, then I say that the points of the marble slab constitute a Euclidean continuum with respect to the little rod, which has been used as a “distance” (line-interval). By choosing one corner of a square as “origin” I can characterise every other corner of a square with reference to this origin by means of two numbers. I only need state how many rods I must pass over when, starting from the origin, I proceed towards the “right” and then “upwards,” in order to arrive at the corner of the square under consideration. These two numbers are then the “Cartesian co-ordinates” of this corner with reference to the “Cartesian co-ordinate system” which is determined by the arrangement of little rods.

If everything has really gone smoothly, then I believe that the points on the marble slab form a Euclidean continuum in relation to the little rod, which has been used as a "distance" (line segment). By selecting one corner of a square as the "origin," I can define every other corner of that square in relation to this origin using two numbers. I just need to say how many rods I need to pass over when, starting from the origin, I move "to the right" and then "upwards" to reach the corner of the square in question. These two numbers are then the "Cartesian coordinates" of this corner in relation to the "Cartesian coordinate system," which is defined by the arrangement of the little rods.

By making use of the following modification of this abstract experiment, we recognise that there must also be cases in which the experiment would be unsuccessful. We shall suppose that the rods “expand” by in amount proportional to the increase of temperature. We heat the central part of the marble slab, but not the periphery, in which case two of our little rods can still be brought into coincidence at every position on the table. But our construction of squares must necessarily come into disorder during the heating, because the little rods on the central region of the table expand, whereas those on the outer part do not.

By using the following modification of this abstract experiment, we acknowledge that there will also be situations where the experiment fails. We will assume that the rods “expand” by an amount proportional to the rise in temperature. We heat the center of the marble slab, but not the edges, so two of our small rods can still align at every point on the table. However, our arrangement of squares will inevitably become messed up during the heating because the small rods in the center of the table expand, while those on the outer part do not.

With reference to our little rods—defined as unit lengths—the marble slab is no longer a Euclidean continuum, and we are also no longer in the position of defining Cartesian co-ordinates directly with their aid, since the above construction can no longer be carried out. But since there are other things which are not influenced in a similar manner to the little rods (or perhaps not at all) by the temperature of the table, it is possible quite naturally to maintain the point of view that the marble slab is a “Euclidean continuum.” This can be done in a satisfactory manner by making a more subtle stipulation about the measurement or the comparison of lengths.

With reference to our small rods—defined as unit lengths—the marble slab is no longer a perfect Euclidean space, and we can’t directly define Cartesian coordinates using them since that construction is not possible anymore. However, since there are other elements that aren’t similarly affected by the table's temperature (or maybe not affected at all), it makes sense to maintain the perspective that the marble slab is a “Euclidean continuum.” This can be achieved satisfactorily by making a more nuanced agreement about how we measure or compare lengths.

But if rods of every kind (i.e. of every material) were to behave in the same way as regards the influence of temperature when they are on the variably heated marble slab, and if we had no other means of detecting the effect of temperature than the geometrical behaviour of our rods in experiments analogous to the one described above, then our best plan would be to assign the distance one to two points on the slab, provided that the ends of one of our rods could be made to coincide with these two points; for how else should we define the distance without our proceeding being in the highest measure grossly arbitrary? The method of Cartesian coordinates must then be discarded, and replaced by another which does not assume the validity of Euclidean geometry for rigid bodies.[20] The reader will notice that the situation depicted here corresponds to the one brought about by the general postulate of relativity (Section XXIII).

But if rods of all kinds (i.e., made from every material) acted the same way regarding temperature influence when placed on a variably heated marble slab, and if we had no other way to detect the effect of temperature aside from the geometric behavior of our rods in experiments similar to the one described above, then our best approach would be to assign the distance between two points on the slab, as long as the ends of one of our rods could line up with these two points; otherwise, how would we define the distance without our process being highly arbitrary? The method of Cartesian coordinates would then need to be set aside, replaced by another method that doesn't rely on the validity of Euclidean geometry for rigid bodies.[20] The reader will notice that the situation described here matches the one resulting from the general postulate of relativity (Section XXIII).

[20]
Mathematicians have been confronted with our problem in the following form. If we are given a surface (e.g. an ellipsoid) in Euclidean three-dimensional space, then there exists for this surface a two-dimensional geometry, just as much as for a plane surface. Gauss undertook the task of treating this two-dimensional geometry from first principles, without making use of the fact that the surface belongs to a Euclidean continuum of three dimensions. If we imagine constructions to be made with rigid rods in the surface (similar to that above with the marble slab), we should find that different laws hold for these from those resulting on the basis of Euclidean plane geometry. The surface is not a Euclidean continuum with respect to the rods, and we cannot define Cartesian co-ordinates in the surface. Gauss indicated the principles according to which we can treat the geometrical relationships in the surface, and thus pointed out the way to the method of Riemann of treating multi-dimensional, non-Euclidean continuum. Thus it is that mathematicians long ago solved the formal problems to which we are led by the general postulate of relativity.

[20]
Mathematicians have faced our problem in the following way. If we have a surface (like an ellipsoid) in three-dimensional Euclidean space, then there is a two-dimensional geometry for this surface, just like there is for a flat surface. Gauss took on the challenge of exploring this two-dimensional geometry from the ground up, without relying on the fact that the surface is part of a three-dimensional Euclidean continuum. If we visualize constructions being made with rigid rods on the surface (similar to what we did with the marble slab), we would find that different rules apply for these rods compared to those based on Euclidean plane geometry. The surface isn't a Euclidean continuum concerning the rods, and we can't define Cartesian coordinates on the surface. Gauss outlined the principles we can use to understand the geometric relationships on the surface, effectively paving the way for Riemann's method of dealing with multi-dimensional, non-Euclidean continua. Therefore, mathematicians solved the formal problems connected to the general postulate of relativity long ago.

XXV.
GAUSSIAN CO-ORDINATES

image033

According to Gauss, this combined analytical and geometrical mode of handling the problem can be arrived at in the following way. We imagine a system of arbitrary curves (see Fig. 4) drawn on the surface of the table. These we designate as u-curves, and we indicate each of them by means of a number. The Curves u = 1, u = 2 and u = 3 are drawn in the diagram. Between the curves u = 1 and u = 2 we must imagine an infinitely large number to be drawn, all of which correspond to real numbers lying between 1 and 2. We have then a system of u-curves, and this “infinitely dense” system covers the whole surface of the table. These u-curves must not intersect each other, and through each point of the surface one and only one curve must pass. Thus a perfectly definite value of u belongs to every point on the surface of the marble slab. In like manner we imagine a system of v-curves drawn on the surface. These satisfy the same conditions as the u-curves, they are provided with numbers in a corresponding manner, and they may likewise be of arbitrary shape. It follows that a value of u and a value of v belong to every point on the surface of the table. We call these two numbers the co-ordinates of the surface of the table (Gaussian co-ordinates). For example, the point P in the diagram has the Gaussian co-ordinates u = 3, v = 1. Two neighbouring points P and P′ on the surface then correspond to the co-ordinates

According to Gauss, this combined analytical and geometric approach to the problem can be explained like this. We visualize a system of arbitrary curves (see Fig. 4) drawn on the surface of the table. We call these u-curves and label each of them with a number. The curves u = 1, u = 2, and u = 3 are shown in the diagram. Between the curves u = 1 and u = 2, we need to imagine an infinite number of curves drawn in between, all corresponding to real numbers that fall between 1 and 2. This gives us a system of u-curves, and this “infinitely dense” system covers the entire surface of the table. These u-curves must not cross each other, and through each point on the surface, only one curve can pass. Therefore, every point on the surface of the marble slab has a specific value of u associated with it. Similarly, we imagine a system of v-curves drawn on the surface. These fulfill the same conditions as the u-curves, are labeled with numbers in a corresponding way, and can also take on arbitrary shapes. This means that every point on the surface of the table has a value of u and a value of v. We refer to these two numbers as the coordinates of the table's surface (Gaussian coordinates). For instance, the point P in the diagram has the Gaussian coordinates u = 3, v = 1. Two neighboring points P and P′ on the surface then correspond to the coordinates

P: u, v

P′: u + du, v + dv,

P′: u + du, v + dv,

where du and dv signify very small numbers. In a similar manner we may indicate the distance (line-interval) between P and P′, as measured with a little rod, by means of the very small number ds. Then according to Gauss we have

where du and dv represent very small values. Similarly, we can express the distance (line interval) between P and P′, as measured with a small rod, using the very small number ds. Then, according to Gauss, we have

ds2 = g11du2 + 2g12du dv + g22dv2,

ds2 = g11du2 + 2g12du dv + g22dv2,

where g11, g12, g22, are magnitudes which depend in a perfectly definite way on u and v. The magnitudes g11, g12 and g22, determine the behaviour of the rods relative to the u-curves and v-curves, and thus also relative to the surface of the table. For the case in which the points of the surface considered form a Euclidean continuum with reference to the measuring-rods, but only in this case, it is possible to draw the u-curves and v-curves and to attach numbers to them, in such a manner, that we simply have:

where g11, g12, g22 are values that clearly depend on u and v. The values g11, g12, and g22 determine how the rods behave in relation to the u-curves and v-curves, and therefore also in relation to the surface of the table. This is only applicable when the points on the surface form a Euclidean continuum concerning the measuring rods; only in this situation can we draw the u-curves and v-curves and assign numbers to them, so that we simply have:

ds2 = du2 + dv2

ds2 = du2 + dv2

Under these conditions, the u-curves and v-curves are straight lines in the sense of Euclidean geometry, and they are perpendicular to each other. Here the Gaussian coordinates are simply Cartesian ones. It is clear that Gauss co-ordinates are nothing more than an association of two sets of numbers with the points of the surface considered, of such a nature that numerical values differing very slightly from each other are associated with neighbouring points “in space.”

Under these conditions, the u-curves and v-curves are straight lines in the sense of Euclidean geometry, and they are perpendicular to each other. Here, the Gaussian coordinates are basically Cartesian coordinates. It’s clear that Gaussian coordinates are just a way of connecting two sets of numbers with the points on the surface being considered, such that numerical values that are very similar to each other are linked to nearby points “in space.”

So far, these considerations hold for a continuum of two dimensions. But the Gaussian method can be applied also to a continuum of three, four or more dimensions. If, for instance, a continuum of four dimensions be supposed available, we may represent it in the following way. With every point of the continuum, we associate arbitrarily four numbers, x1, x2, x3, x4, which are known as “co-ordinates.” Adjacent points correspond to adjacent values of the coordinates. If a distance ds is associated with the adjacent points P and P′, this distance being measurable and well defined from a physical point of view, then the following formula holds:

So far, these considerations apply to a two-dimensional continuum. However, the Gaussian method can also be used for a continuum of three, four, or more dimensions. For example, if we assume a four-dimensional continuum, we can represent it as follows. We associate four numbers, x1, x2, x3, x4, with each point in the continuum, which are called "coordinates." Points that are next to each other correspond to nearby values of the coordinates. If a distance ds is linked to the adjacent points P and P′, and this distance is measurable and well-defined from a physical perspective, then the following formula applies:

ds2 = g11dx12 + 2g12dx1dx2 . . . . + g44dx42,

ds2 = g11dx12 + 2g12dx1dx2 . . . . + g44dx42,

where the magnitudes g11, etc., have values which vary with the position in the continuum. Only when the continuum is a Euclidean one is it possible to associate the co-ordinates x1 . . x4. with the points of the continuum so that we have simply

where the values g11, etc., change based on the position in the continuum. It's only when the continuum is Euclidean that we can link the coordinates x1 . . x4 with the points of the continuum in a straightforward way.

ds2 = dx12 + dx22 + dx32 + dx42.

ds2 = dx12 + dx22 + dx32 + dx42.

In this case relations hold in the four-dimensional continuum which are analogous to those holding in our three-dimensional measurements.

In this case, the relationships exist in the four-dimensional continuum, similar to those in our three-dimensional measurements.

However, the Gauss treatment for ds2 which we have given above is not always possible. It is only possible when sufficiently small regions of the continuum under consideration may be regarded as Euclidean continua. For example, this obviously holds in the case of the marble slab of the table and local variation of temperature. The temperature is practically constant for a small part of the slab, and thus the geometrical behaviour of the rods is almost as it ought to be according to the rules of Euclidean geometry. Hence the imperfections of the construction of squares in the previous section do not show themselves clearly until this construction is extended over a considerable portion of the surface of the table.

However, the Gauss treatment for ds2 that we discussed earlier isn't always feasible. It's only applicable when small enough regions of the continuum can be viewed as Euclidean spaces. For instance, this clearly applies to the marble surface of the table and the local temperature variations. The temperature remains nearly constant over a small area of the slab, making the geometric behavior of the rods almost align with the principles of Euclidean geometry. Therefore, the flaws in the square construction mentioned in the previous section don’t become evident until this construction is spread over a sizable part of the table's surface.

We can sum this up as follows: Gauss invented a method for the mathematical treatment of continua in general, in which “size-relations” (“distances” between neighbouring points) are defined. To every point of a continuum are assigned as many numbers (Gaussian coordinates) as the continuum has dimensions. This is done in such a way, that only one meaning can be attached to the assignment, and that numbers (Gaussian coordinates) which differ by an indefinitely small amount are assigned to adjacent points. The Gaussian coordinate system is a logical generalisation of the Cartesian co-ordinate system. It is also applicable to non-Euclidean continua, but only when, with respect to the defined “size” or “distance,” small parts of the continuum under consideration behave more nearly like a Euclidean system, the smaller the part of the continuum under our notice.

We can summarize this as follows: Gauss created a method for mathematically handling continuous systems in general, where “size-relations” (the “distances” between neighboring points) are defined. Each point in a continuum is assigned as many numbers (Gaussian coordinates) as there are dimensions in that continuum. This is done in a way that allows only one interpretation of the assignment, ensuring that numbers (Gaussian coordinates) that differ by an infinitely small amount are assigned to adjacent points. The Gaussian coordinate system is a logical extension of the Cartesian coordinate system. It can also be applied to non-Euclidean continua, but only when, regarding the defined “size” or “distance,” small sections of the continuum behave more like a Euclidean system, the smaller the section of the continuum we are observing.

XXVI.
THE SPACE-TIME CONTINUUM OF THE SPECIAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY CONSIDERED AS A EUCLIDEAN CONTINUUM

We are now in a position to formulate more exactly the idea of Minkowski, which was only vaguely indicated in Section XVII. In accordance with the special theory of relativity, certain co-ordinate systems are given preference for the description of the four-dimensional, space-time continuum. We called these “Galileian co-ordinate systems.” For these systems, the four co-ordinates x, y, z, t, which determine an event or—in other words—a point of the four-dimensional continuum, are defined physically in a simple manner, as set forth in detail in the first part of this book. For the transition from one Galileian system to another, which is moving uniformly with reference to the first, the equations of the Lorentz transformation are valid. These last form the basis for the derivation of deductions from the special theory of relativity, and in themselves they are nothing more than the expression of the universal validity of the law of transmission of light for all Galileian systems of reference.

We can now better articulate Minkowski's idea, which was only vaguely mentioned in Section XVII. According to the special theory of relativity, some coordinate systems are favored for describing the four-dimensional space-time continuum. We refer to these as “Galilean coordinate systems.” In these systems, the four coordinates x, y, z, t, which represent an event or a point in the four-dimensional continuum, are defined in a straightforward physical way, as detailed in the first part of this book. To move from one Galilean system to another that is uniformly moving relative to the first, the equations of Lorentz transformation apply. These equations are fundamental for deriving conclusions from the special theory of relativity, and they essentially express the universal validity of the light transmission law for all Galilean reference systems.

Minkowski found that the Lorentz transformations satisfy the following simple conditions. Let us consider two neighbouring events, the relative position of which in the four-dimensional continuum is given with respect to a Galileian reference-body K by the space co-ordinate differences dx, dy, dz and the time-difference dt. With reference to a second Galileian system we shall suppose that the corresponding differences for these two events are dx′, dy′, dz′, dt′. Then these magnitudes always fulfill the condition.[21]

Minkowski discovered that the Lorentz transformations meet the following straightforward conditions. Let's look at two nearby events, whose relative position in the four-dimensional continuum is defined in relation to a Galilean reference frame K by the spatial coordinate differences dx, dy, dz and the time difference dt. For a second Galilean system, we'll assume that the corresponding differences for these two events are dx′, dy′, dz′, dt′. These quantities always satisfy the condition.[21]

[21]
Cf. Appendixes I and II. The relations which are derived there for the co-ordinates themselves are valid also for co-ordinate differences, and thus also for co-ordinate differentials (indefinitely small differences).

[21]
See Appendixes I and II. The relationships found for the coordinates themselves also apply to coordinate differences, and therefore also to coordinate differentials (infinitely small differences).

dx2 + dy2 + dz2c2dt2 = dx′2 + dy′2 + dz′2c2dt′2.

dx2 + dy2 + dz2c2dt2 = dx′2 + dy′2 + dz′2c2dt′2.

The validity of the Lorentz transformation follows from this condition. We can express this as follows: The magnitude

The validity of the Lorentz transformation comes from this condition. We can put it this way: The magnitude

ds2 = dx2 + dy2 + dz2c2 dt2,

ds² = dx² + dy² + dz² – c² dt²,

which belongs to two adjacent points of the four-dimensional space-time continuum, has the same value for all selected (Galileian) reference-bodies. If we replace x, y, z,

which belongs to two adjacent points of the four-dimensional space-time continuum, has the same value for all chosen (Galilean) reference bodies. If we replace x, y, z,

image034

by x1, x2, x3, x4, we also obtain the result that

by x1, x2, x3, x4, we also get the result that

ds2 = dx12 + dx22 + dx32 + dx42.

ds² = dx₁² + dx₂² + dx₃² + dx₄².

is independent of the choice of the body of reference. We call the magnitude ds the “distance” apart of the two events or four-dimensional points.

is independent of the choice of the reference frame. We refer to the magnitude ds as the “distance” between the two events or four-dimensional points.

Thus, if we choose as time-variable the imaginary variable

Thus, if we select the imaginary variable as the time-variable

image035

instead of the real quantity t, we can regard the space-time contintium—accordance with the special theory of relativity—as a “Euclidean” four-dimensional continuum, a result which follows from the considerations of the preceding section.

instead of the actual quantity t, we can view the space-time continuum—in line with the special theory of relativity—as a “Euclidean” four-dimensional continuum, a conclusion that comes from the discussions in the previous section.

XXVII.
THE SPACE-TIME CONTINUUM OF THE GENERAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY IS NOT A EUCLIDEAN CONTINUUM

In the first part of this book we were able to make use of space-time co-ordinates which allowed of a simple and direct physical interpretation, and which, according to Section XXVI, can be regarded as four-dimensional Cartesian co-ordinates. This was possible on the basis of the law of the constancy of the velocity of light. But according to Section XXI the general theory of relativity cannot retain this law. On the contrary, we arrived at the result that according to this latter theory the velocity of light must always depend on the co-ordinates when a gravitational field is present. In connection with a specific illustration in Section XXIII, we found that the presence of a gravitational field invalidates the definition of the coordinates and the time, which led us to our objective in the special theory of relativity.

In the first part of this book, we used space-time coordinates that allowed for a simple and direct physical interpretation, which, according to Section XXVI, can be viewed as four-dimensional Cartesian coordinates. This was possible based on the principle that the speed of light is constant. However, as stated in Section XXI, the general theory of relativity cannot maintain this principle. Instead, we discovered that, under this theory, the speed of light must always depend on the coordinates when a gravitational field is present. In Section XXIII, with a specific example, we found that the presence of a gravitational field disrupts the definition of coordinates and time, guiding us toward our goals in the special theory of relativity.

In view of the resuIts of these considerations we are led to the conviction that, according to the general principle of relativity, the space-time continuum cannot be regarded as a Euclidean one, but that here we have the general case, corresponding to the marble slab with local variations of temperature, and with which we made acquaintance as an example of a two-dimensional continuum. Just as it was there impossible to construct a Cartesian co-ordinate system from equal rods, so here it is impossible to build up a system (reference-body) from rigid bodies and clocks, which shall be of such a nature that measuring-rods and clocks, arranged rigidly with respect to one another, shall indicate position and time directly. Such was the essence of the difficulty with which we were confronted in Section XXIII.

Considering the results of these discussions, we are convinced that, according to the general principle of relativity, the space-time continuum cannot be seen as a Euclidean one. Instead, we have a general case that mirrors the marble slab with local temperature variations, which we previously used as an example of a two-dimensional continuum. Just as it was impossible to create a Cartesian coordinate system using equal rods in that scenario, it is also impossible here to establish a system (reference frame) made up of rigid bodies and clocks, where measuring rods and clocks, arranged rigidly with respect to one another, would indicate position and time directly. This was the core of the challenge we faced in Section XXIII.

But the considerations of Sections XXV and XXVI show us the way to surmount this difficulty. We refer the four-dimensional space-time continuum in an arbitrary manner to Gauss co-ordinates. We assign to every point of the continuum (event) four numbers, x1, x2, x3, x4 (co-ordinates), which have not the least direct physical significance, but only serve the purpose of numbering the points of the continuum in a definite but arbitrary manner. This arrangement does not even need to be of such a kind that we must regard x1, x2, x3, as “space” co-ordinates and x4, as a “time” co-ordinate.

But the discussions in Sections XXV and XXVI point us toward overcoming this challenge. We refer the four-dimensional space-time continuum in an arbitrary way to Gauss coordinates. We assign four numbers, x1, x2, x3, x4 (coordinates), to each point of the continuum (event). These numbers have no direct physical meaning; they simply help us label the points in the continuum in a specific but arbitrary way. This setup doesn’t even have to categorize x1, x2, x3 as “space” coordinates and x4 as a “time” coordinate.

The reader may think that such a description of the world would be quite inadequate. What does it mean to assign to an event the particular co-ordinates x1, x2, x3, x4, if in themselves these co-ordinates have no significance? More careful consideration shows, however, that this anxiety is unfounded. Let us consider, for instance, a material point with any kind of motion. If this point had only a momentary existence without duration, then it would to described in space-time by a single system of values x1, x2, x3, x4. Thus its permanent existence must be characterised by an infinitely large number of such systems of values, the co-ordinate values of which are so close together as to give continuity; corresponding to the material point, we thus have a (uni-dimensional) line in the four-dimensional continuum. In the same way, any such lines in our continuum correspond to many points in motion. The only statements having regard to these points which can claim a physical existence are in reality the statements about their encounters. In our mathematical treatment, such an encounter is expressed in the fact that the two lines which represent the motions of the points in question have a particular system of co-ordinate values, x1, x2, x3, x4, in common. After mature consideration the reader will doubtless admit that in reality such encounters constitute the only actual evidence of a time-space nature with which we meet in physical statements.

The reader might think that this description of the world is quite inadequate. What does it really mean to assign specific coordinates x1, x2, x3, x4 to an event, especially if those coordinates hold no significance on their own? However, a closer look reveals that this concern is misplaced. For instance, let’s consider a material point in any kind of motion. If this point only existed for a moment without any duration, it could be represented in space-time by a single set of values x1, x2, x3, x4. Therefore, its lasting existence must be defined by an infinite number of such sets of values, with the coordinate values being so closely spaced that they create continuity; for the material point, this corresponds to a (one-dimensional) line in the four-dimensional continuum. Similarly, any of those lines in our continuum correspond to many points in motion. The only claims regarding these points that can genuinely be said to have physical existence are, in fact, statements about their interactions. In our mathematical framework, such an interaction is represented by the two lines, which denote the motions of the respective points, sharing a specific set of coordinate values, x1, x2, x3, x4. After careful thought, the reader will likely agree that such interactions are the only real evidence of a time-space nature that we encounter in physical statements.

When we were describing the motion of a material point relative to a body of reference, we stated nothing more than the encounters of this point with particular points of the reference-body. We can also determine the corresponding values of the time by the observation of encounters of the body with clocks, in conjunction with the observation of the encounter of the hands of clocks with particular points on the dials. It is just the same in the case of space-measurements by means of measuring-rods, as a little consideration will show.

When we described the motion of a material point in relation to a reference body, we were simply talking about the interactions of this point with specific points on the reference body. We can also figure out the corresponding time values by observing the interactions of the body with clocks, along with watching how the clock hands interact with specific points on the dials. The same applies to measuring distances with measuring rods, as a little thought will make clear.

The following statements hold generally: Every physical description resolves itself into a number of statements, each of which refers to the space-time coincidence of two events A and B. In terms of Gaussian co-ordinates, every such statement is expressed by the agreement of their four co-ordinates x1, x2, x3, x4. Thus in reality, the description of the time-space continuum by means of Gauss co-ordinates completely replaces the description with the aid of a body of reference, without suffering from the defects of the latter mode of description; it is not tied down to the Euclidean character of the continuum which has to be represented.

The following statements are generally true: Every physical description can be broken down into several statements, each referring to the space-time coincidence of two events A and B. Using Gaussian coordinates, each statement is expressed through the alignment of their four coordinates x1, x2, x3, x4. Therefore, the description of the space-time continuum using Gauss coordinates entirely replaces the use of a reference body for description, avoiding the shortcomings of that method; it is not limited by the Euclidean nature of the continuum that needs to be represented.

XXVIII.
EXACT FORMULATION OF THE GENERAL PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY

We are now in a position to replace the provisional formulation of the general principle of relativity given in Section XVIII by an exact formulation. The form there used, “All bodies of reference K, K′, etc., are equivalent for the description of natural phenomena (formulation of the general laws of nature), whatever may be their state of motion,” cannot be maintained, because the use of rigid reference-bodies, in the sense of the method followed in the special theory of relativity, is in general not possible in space-time description. The Gauss co-ordinate system has to take the place of the body of reference. The following statement corresponds to the fundamental idea of the general principle of relativity: “All Gaussian co-ordinate systems are essentially equivalent for the formulation of the general laws of nature.

We can now replace the temporary version of the general principle of relativity from Section XVIII with an exact version. The earlier statement, “All reference bodies K, K′, etc., are equivalent for describing natural phenomena (formulating the general laws of nature), regardless of their state of motion,” isn’t valid anymore, because using rigid reference bodies, as done in the special theory of relativity, is generally not possible in the description of space-time. The Gauss coordinate system should replace the reference body. The following statement reflects the core idea of the general principle of relativity: “All Gaussian coordinate systems are essentially equivalent for formulating the general laws of nature.

We can state this general principle of relativity in still another form, which renders it yet more clearly intelligible than it is when in the form of the natural extension of the special principle of relativity. According to the special theory of relativity, the equations which express the general laws of nature pass over into equations of the same form when, by making use of the Lorentz transformation, we replace the space-time variables x, y, z, t, of a (Galileian) reference-body K by the space-time variables x′, y′, z′, t′, of a new reference-body K′. According to the general theory of relativity, on the other hand, by application of arbitrary substitutions of the Gauss variables x1, x2, x3, x4, the equations must pass over into equations of the same form; for every transformation (not only the Lorentz transformation) corresponds to the transition of one Gauss co-ordinate system into another.

We can express this general principle of relativity in another way that makes it even clearer than when it's presented as a natural extension of the special principle of relativity. According to the special theory of relativity, the equations that represent the fundamental laws of nature change into equations of the same form when we use the Lorentz transformation to swap the space-time variables x, y, z, t from a (Galilean) reference frame K with the space-time variables x′, y′, z′, t′ from a new reference frame K′. However, according to the general theory of relativity, through the use of arbitrary substitutions of the Gauss variables x1, x2, x3, x4, the equations must also change into equations of the same form; each transformation (not just the Lorentz transformation) corresponds to the shift from one Gauss coordinate system to another.

If we desire to adhere to our “old-time” three-dimensional view of things, then we can characterise the development which is being undergone by the fundamental idea of the general theory of relativity as follows: The special theory of relativity has reference to Galileian domains, i.e. to those in which no gravitational field exists. In this connection a Galileian reference-body serves as body of reference, i.e. a rigid body the state of motion of which is so chosen that the Galileian law of the uniform rectilinear motion of “isolated” material points holds relatively to it.

If we want to stick to our old-school three-dimensional perspective, we can describe the evolution of the core idea of the general theory of relativity like this: The special theory of relativity applies to Galilean domains, i.e. those without a gravitational field. In this context, a Galilean reference body acts as the point of reference, i.e. a solid object whose state of motion is selected so that the Galilean law of uniform straight-line motion of "isolated" material points applies relative to it.

Certain considerations suggest that we should refer the same Galileian domains to non-Galileian reference-bodies also. A gravitational field of a special kind is then present with respect to these bodies (cf. Sections XX and XXIII).

Certain considerations suggest that we should also refer the same Galilean domains to non-Galilean reference bodies. A specific type of gravitational field is then present concerning these bodies (see Sections XX and XXIII).

In gravitational fields there are no such things as rigid bodies with Euclidean properties; thus the fictitious rigid body of reference is of no avail in the general theory of relativity. The motion of clocks is also influenced by gravitational fields, and in such a way that a physical definition of time which is made directly with the aid of clocks has by no means the same degree of plausibility as in the special theory of relativity.

In gravitational fields, there are no rigid bodies with Euclidean properties; therefore, the imaginary rigid body of reference isn’t useful in the general theory of relativity. The movement of clocks is also affected by gravitational fields, in a way that a physical definition of time, made directly using clocks, doesn’t have the same level of credibility as it does in the special theory of relativity.

For this reason non-rigid reference-bodies are used, which are as a whole not only moving in any way whatsoever, but which also suffer alterations in form ad lib. during their motion. Clocks, for which the law of motion is of any kind, however irregular, serve for the definition of time. We have to imagine each of these clocks fixed at a point on the non-rigid reference-body. These clocks satisfy only the one condition, that the “readings” which are observed simultaneously on adjacent clocks (in space) differ from each other by an indefinitely small amount. This non-rigid reference-body, which might appropriately be termed a “reference-mollusc”, is in the main equivalent to a Gaussian four-dimensional co-ordinate system chosen arbitrarily. That which gives the “mollusc” a certain comprehensibility as compared with the Gauss co-ordinate system is the (really unjustified) formal retention of the separate existence of the

For this reason, non-rigid reference bodies are used, which as a whole are not only moving in any way possible but also undergo changes in shape ad lib. during their motion. Clocks, which can operate under any kind of motion law, no matter how irregular, are used to define time. We need to think of each of these clocks fixed at a point on the non-rigid reference body. These clocks meet only one condition: the “readings” that are observed simultaneously on adjacent clocks (in space) differ from each other by an indefinitely small amount. This non-rigid reference body, which could be fittingly called a “reference mollusc,” is essentially equivalent to an arbitrarily chosen Gaussian four-dimensional coordinate system. What gives the “mollusc” a certain clarity compared to the Gauss coordinate system is the (actually unjustified) formal retention of the separate existence of the

space co-ordinates as opposed to the time co-ordinate. Every point on the mollusc is treated as a space-point, and every material point which is at rest relatively to it as at rest, so long as the mollusc is considered as reference-body. The general principle of relativity requires that all these molluscs can be used as reference-bodies with equal right and equal success in the formulation of the general laws of nature; the laws themselves must be quite independent of the choice of mollusc.

space coordinates instead of the time coordinate. Every point on the mollusk is treated as a space-point, and every material point that is at rest relative to it is considered at rest, as long as the mollusk is viewed as the reference body. The general principle of relativity states that all these mollusks can be used as reference bodies with equal validity and equal effectiveness in formulating the general laws of nature; the laws themselves must be completely independent of the choice of mollusk.

The great power possessed by the general principle of relativity lies in the comprehensive limitation which is imposed on the laws of nature in consequence of what we have seen above.

The incredible strength of the general principle of relativity comes from the wide-ranging restrictions it places on the laws of nature due to what we've discussed above.

XXIX.
THE SOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM OF GRAVITATION ON THE BASIS OF THE GENERAL PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY

If the reader has followed all our previous considerations, he will have no further difficulty in understanding the methods leading to the solution of the problem of gravitation.

If the reader has kept up with all our earlier points, they will have no trouble understanding the methods that lead to solving the problem of gravity.

We start off on a consideration of a Galileian domain, i.e. a domain in which there is no gravitational field relative to the Galileian reference-body K. The behaviour of measuring-rods and clocks with reference to K is known from the special theory of relativity, likewise the behaviour of “isolated” material points; the latter move uniformly and in straight lines.

We begin by looking at a Galilean domain, i.e. a space where there’s no gravitational field relative to the Galilean reference body K. The behavior of measuring rods and clocks in relation to K is understood from the special theory of relativity, as is the behavior of "isolated" material points; the latter move uniformly and in straight lines.

Now let us refer this domain to a random Gauss coordinate system or to a “mollusc” as reference-body K′. Then with respect to K′ there is a gravitational field G (of a particular kind). We learn the behaviour of measuring-rods and clocks and also of freely-moving material points with reference to K′ simply by mathematical transformation. We interpret this behaviour as the behaviour of measuring-rods, clocks and material points under the influence of the gravitational field G. Hereupon we introduce a hypothesis: that the influence of the gravitational field on measuring-rods, clocks and freely-moving material points continues to take place according to the same laws, even in the case where the prevailing gravitational field is not derivable from the Galileian special case, simply by means of a transformation of co-ordinates.

Now, let's refer to this area as a random Gauss coordinate system or a "mollusc" as the reference body K′. In relation to K′, there is a gravitational field G (of a specific type). We can understand the behavior of measuring rods, clocks, and freely-moving objects in relation to K′ simply through mathematical transformation. We interpret this behavior as how measuring rods, clocks, and material points act under the influence of the gravitational field G. Next, we propose a hypothesis: that the influence of the gravitational field on measuring rods, clocks, and freely-moving objects continues to operate under the same laws, even when the existing gravitational field is not derived from the Galilean special case through a transformation of coordinates.

The next step is to investigate the space-time behaviour of the gravitational field G, which was derived from the Galileian special case simply by transformation of the coordinates. This behaviour is formulated in a law, which is always valid, no matter how the reference-body (mollusc) used in the description may be chosen.

The next step is to examine how the gravitational field G behaves over space and time, which was obtained from the Galilean special case just by changing the coordinates. This behavior is expressed in a law that is always applicable, regardless of how the reference body (mollusc) used in the description is selected.

This law is not yet the general law of the gravitational field, since the gravitational field under consideration is of a special kind. In order to find out the general law-of-field of gravitation we still require to obtain a generalisation of the law as found above. This can be obtained without caprice, however, by taking into consideration the following demands:

This law is not yet the general law of the gravitational field, since the gravitational field we’re looking at is a specific type. To determine the general law of gravitation, we still need to develop a broader version of the law mentioned above. This can be done reasonably by taking into account the following requirements:

(a) The required generalisation must likewise satisfy the general postulate of relativity.

(a) The necessary generalization must also meet the general principle of relativity.

(b) If there is any matter in the domain under consideration, only its inertial mass, and thus according to Section XV only its energy is of importance for its effect in exciting a field.

(b) If there’s any matter in the area being discussed, only its inertial mass, and therefore according to Section XV, only its energy is important for its effect in generating a field.

(c) Gravitational field and matter together must satisfy the law of the conservation of energy (and of impulse).

(c) The gravitational field and matter must together follow the law of conservation of energy (and momentum).

Finally, the general principle of relativity permits us to determine the influence of the gravitational field on the course of all those processes which take place according to known laws when a gravitational field is absent i.e. which have already been fitted into the frame of the special theory of relativity. In this connection we proceed in principle according to the method which has already been explained for measuring-rods, clocks and freely moving material points.

Finally, the general principle of relativity allows us to figure out how the gravitational field affects all those processes that occur according to known laws when there is no gravitational field, meaning they have already been integrated into the framework of the special theory of relativity. In this regard, we follow the same method that has already been explained for measuring sticks, clocks, and freely moving objects.

The theory of gravitation derived in this way from the general postulate of relativity excels not only in its beauty; nor in removing the defect attaching to classical mechanics which was brought to light in Section XXI; nor in interpreting the empirical law of the equality of inertial and gravitational mass; but it has also already explained a result of observation in astronomy, against which classical mechanics is powerless.

The theory of gravitation developed from the general principle of relativity is impressive not just because of its elegance; it also fixes the flaws in classical mechanics that were pointed out in Section XXI; it interprets the empirical law that inertial and gravitational mass are equal; but it has also already provided an explanation for an astronomical observation that classical mechanics cannot address.

If we confine the application of the theory to the case where the gravitational fields can be regarded as being weak, and in which all masses move with respect to the coordinate system with velocities which are small compared with the velocity of light, we then obtain as a first approximation the Newtonian theory. Thus the latter theory is obtained here without any particular assumption, whereas Newton had to introduce the hypothesis that the force of attraction between mutually attracting material points is inversely proportional to the square of the distance between them. If we increase the accuracy of the calculation, deviations from the theory of Newton make their appearance, practically all of which must nevertheless escape the test of observation owing to their smallness.

If we limit the application of the theory to situations where the gravitational fields can be considered weak, and where all masses move at speeds that are much slower than the speed of light, we get the Newtonian theory as a first approximation. This means we arrive at this theory without any special assumptions, while Newton had to suggest that the force of attraction between two objects is inversely proportional to the square of the distance between them. As we refine our calculations, we see differences from Newton's theory, but almost all of these differences are too small to be detected through observation.

We must draw attention here to one of these deviations. According to Newton’s theory, a planet moves round the sun in an ellipse, which would permanently maintain its position with respect to the fixed stars, if we could disregard the motion of the fixed stars themselves and the action of the other planets under consideration. Thus, if we correct the observed motion of the planets for these two influences, and if Newton’s theory be strictly correct, we ought to obtain for the orbit of the planet an ellipse, which is fixed with reference to the fixed stars. This deduction, which can be tested with great accuracy, has been confirmed for all the planets save one, with the precision that is capable of being obtained by the delicacy of observation attainable at the present time. The sole exception is Mercury, the planet which lies nearest the sun. Since the time of Leverrier, it has been known that the ellipse corresponding to the orbit of Mercury, after it has been corrected for the influences mentioned above, is not stationary with respect to the fixed stars, but that it rotates exceedingly slowly in the plane of the orbit and in the sense of the orbital motion. The value obtained for this rotary movement of the orbital ellipse was 43 seconds of arc per century, an amount ensured to be correct to within a few seconds of arc. This effect can be explained by means of classical mechanics only on the assumption of hypotheses which have little probability, and which were devised solely for this purponse.

We need to point out one of these discrepancies. According to Newton’s theory, a planet orbits the sun in an ellipse that would keep its position relative to the fixed stars, if we could ignore the movement of the fixed stars themselves and the influence of the other planets involved. Therefore, if we adjust the observed motion of the planets for these two factors, and if Newton’s theory is strictly accurate, we should get an orbit for the planet that is an ellipse fixed with respect to the fixed stars. This prediction, which can be tested very precisely, has been confirmed for all the planets except one, with the level of accuracy achievable with today's delicate observations. The only exception is Mercury, the planet closest to the sun. Since Leverrier's time, it's been known that the ellipse representing Mercury's orbit, after correcting for the mentioned influences, isn't stationary with respect to the fixed stars; instead, it rotates very slowly within the plane of the orbit and in the same direction as the orbital motion. The calculated rate of this orbital ellipse's rotation is 43 seconds of arc per century, with certainty to within a few seconds of arc. This phenomenon can only be explained by classical mechanics if we assume hypotheses that are highly unlikely and were created just for this explanation.

On the basis of the general theory of relativity, it is found that the ellipse of every planet round the sun must necessarily rotate in the manner indicated above; that for all the planets, with the exception of Mercury, this rotation is too small to be detected with the delicacy of observation possible at the present time; but that in the case of Mercury it must amount to 43 seconds of arc per century, a result which is strictly in agreement with observation.

Based on the general theory of relativity, it's been found that the orbit of every planet around the sun must rotate as described above; for all the planets except Mercury, this rotation is too small to be detected with the level of precision available today; however, for Mercury, it amounts to 43 seconds of arc per century, which perfectly matches observations.

Apart from this one, it has hitherto been possible to make only two deductions from the theory which admit of being tested by observation, to wit, the curvature of light rays by the gravitational field of the sun,[22] and a displacement of the spectral lines of light reaching us from large stars, as compared with the corresponding lines for light produced in an analogous manner terrestrially (i.e. by the same kind of atom).[23] These two deductions from the theory have both been confirmed.

Aside from this one, so far there's been only two deductions from the theory that can be tested by observation: the bending of light rays by the sun's gravitational field, [22] and a shift in the spectral lines of light coming from distant stars, compared to the corresponding lines for light produced in a similar way on Earth (i.e. by the same type of atom). [23] Both of these deductions from the theory have been confirmed.

[22]
First observed by Eddington and others in 1919. (Cf. Appendix III).

[22]
First noticed by Eddington and others in 1919. (See Appendix III).

[23]
Established by Adams in 1924. (Cf. p. 132)

[23]
Founded by Adams in 1924. (See p. 132)

PART III: CONSIDERATIONS ON THE UNIVERSE AS A WHOLE

XXX.
COSMOLOGICAL DIFFICULTIES OF NEWTON’S THEORY

Part from the difficulty discussed in Section XXI, there is a second fundamental difficulty attending classical celestial mechanics, which, to the best of my knowledge, was first discussed in detail by the astronomer Seeliger. If we ponder over the question as to how the universe, considered as a whole, is to be regarded, the first answer that suggests itself to us is surely this: As regards space (and time) the universe is infinite. There are stars everywhere, so that the density of matter, although very variable in detail, is nevertheless on the average everywhere the same. In other words: However far we might travel through space, we should find everywhere an attenuated swarm of fixed stars of approrimately the same kind and density.

Apart from the difficulty mentioned in Section XXI, there's a second major issue in classical celestial mechanics, which, to my knowledge, was first thoroughly discussed by the astronomer Seeliger. When we think about how to view the universe as a whole, the first answer that comes to mind is this: In terms of space (and time), the universe is infinite. There are stars everywhere, so while the density of matter varies significantly in detail, on average, it's essentially the same everywhere. In other words, no matter how far we travel through space, we would find an scattered array of fixed stars that are approximately of the same type and density.

This view is not in harmony with the theory of Newton. The latter theory rather requires that the universe should have a kind of centre in which the density of the stars is a maximum, and that as we proceed outwards from this centre the group-density of the stars should diminish, until finally, at great distances, it is succeeded by an infinite region of emptiness. The stellar universe ought to be a finite island in the infinite ocean of space.[24]

This perspective doesn't align with Newton's theory. That theory suggests the universe should have a sort of center where the density of stars is highest, and as we move away from this center, the density of stars should decrease until, at vast distances, it is replaced by an infinite void. The star-filled universe should be a finite island in the infinite sea of space.[24]

[24]
Proof—According to the theory of Newton, the number of “lines of force” which come from infinity and terminate in a mass m is proportional to the mass m. If, on the average, the mass density ρ0 is constant throughout the universe, then a sphere of volume V will enclose the average mass ρ0V. Thus the number of lines of force passing through the surface F of the sphere into its interior is proportional to ρ0V. For unit area of the surface of the sphere the number of lines of force which enters the sphere is thus proportional to ρ0V/F or to ρ0R. Hence the intensity of the field at the surface would ultimately become infinite with increasing radius R of the sphere, which is impossible.

[24]
Proof—According to Newton's theory, the number of “lines of force” that come from infinity and end at a mass m is proportional to the mass m. If, on average, the mass density ρ0 is constant throughout the universe, then a sphere with volume V will contain the average mass ρ0V. Therefore, the number of lines of force passing through the surface F of the sphere into its interior is proportional to ρ0V. For each unit area of the sphere's surface, the number of lines of force that enter the sphere is proportional to ρ0V/F or to ρ0R. Consequently, the intensity of the field at the surface would ultimately become infinite as the radius R of the sphere increases, which is not possible.

This conception is in itself not very satisfactory. It is still less satisfactory because it leads to the result that the light emitted by the stars and also individual stars of the stellar system are perpetually passing out into infinite space, never to return, and without ever again coming into interaction with other objects of nature. Such a finite material universe would be destined to become gradually but systematically impoverished.

This idea isn’t really satisfying on its own. It’s even less satisfying because it suggests that the light from the stars, and even individual stars in the stellar system, is constantly drifting out into infinite space, never to come back and never to interact with other natural objects again. A finite material universe like this would gradually become systematically depleted.

In order to escape this dilemma, Seeliger suggested a modification of Newton’s law, in which he assumes that for great distances the force of attraction between two masses diminishes more rapidly than would result from the inverse square law. In this way it is possible for the mean density of matter to be constant everywhere, even to infinity, without infinitely large gravitational fields being produced. We thus free ourselves from the distasteful conception that the material universe ought to possess something of the nature of a centre. Of course we purchase our emancipation from the fundamental difficulties mentioned, at the cost of a modification and complication of Newton’s law which has neither empirical nor theoretical foundation. We can imagine innumerable laws which would serve the same purpose, without our being able to state a reason why one of them is to be preferred to the others; for any one of these laws would be founded just as little on more general theoretical principles as is the law of Newton.

To get out of this dilemma, Seeliger proposed a change to Newton’s law, suggesting that over large distances, the gravitational attraction between two masses decreases more quickly than what the inverse square law predicts. This allows for the average density of matter to remain constant everywhere, even out to infinity, without creating infinitely large gravitational fields. This way, we can avoid the uncomfortable idea that the material universe needs to have some sort of center. However, we achieve freedom from the fundamental issues mentioned at the cost of altering and complicating Newton’s law, which lacks both empirical and theoretical support. We can think of countless laws that would accomplish the same goal, and we can't really say why one of them should be favored over the others; each of these laws would not be based on broader theoretical principles any more than Newton's law is.

XXXI.
THE POSSIBILITY OF A “FINITE” AND YET “UNBOUNDED” UNIVERSE

But speculations on the structure of the universe also move in quite another direction. The development of non-Euclidean geometry led to the recognition of the fact, that we can cast doubt on the infiniteness of our space without coming into conflict with the laws of thought or with experience (Riemann, Helmholtz). These questions have already been treated in detail and with unsurpassable lucidity by Helmholtz and Poincaré, whereas I can only touch on them briefly here.

But ideas about the structure of the universe also take a different turn. The development of non-Euclidean geometry led to the realization that we can question the infinity of our space without conflicting with logical reasoning or our experiences (Riemann, Helmholtz). These topics have already been explored in depth and with exceptional clarity by Helmholtz and Poincaré, while I can only touch on them briefly here.

In the first place, we imagine an existence in two dimensional space. Flat beings with flat implements, and in particular flat rigid measuring-rods, are free to move in a plane. For them nothing exists outside of this plane: that which they observe to happen to themselves and to their flat “things” is the all-inclusive reality of their plane. In particular, the constructions of plane Euclidean geometry can be carried out by means of the rods e.g. the lattice construction, considered in Section XXIV. In contrast to ours, the universe of these beings is two-dimensional; but, like ours, it extends to infinity. In their universe there is room for an infinite number of identical squares made up of rods, i.e. its volume (surface) is infinite. If these beings say their universe is “plane,” there is sense in the statement, because they mean that they can perform the constructions of plane Euclidean geometry with their rods. In this connection the individual rods always represent the same distance, independently of their position.

First, we imagine a world in two-dimensional space. Flat beings with flat tools, especially flat rigid measuring rods, can move freely in a plane. For them, nothing exists outside of this plane; what they observe happening to themselves and their flat “things” is the complete reality of their plane. Specifically, the constructions of plane Euclidean geometry can be done using the rods, e.g. the lattice construction mentioned in Section XXIV. Unlike ours, their universe is two-dimensional, but similar to ours, it stretches out to infinity. In their universe, there's enough space for an infinite number of identical squares made up of rods, i.e. its volume (or surface area) is infinite. When these beings say their universe is “plane,” it makes sense to them because they mean they can perform the constructions of plane Euclidean geometry with their rods. In this context, each rod consistently represents the same distance, regardless of its position.

Let us consider now a second two-dimensional existence, but this time on a spherical surface instead of on a plane. The flat beings with their measuring-rods and other objects fit exactly on this surface and they are unable to leave it. Their whole universe of observation extends exclusively over the surface of the sphere. Are these beings able to regard the geometry of their universe as being plane geometry and their rods withal as the realisation of “distance”? They cannot do this. For if they attempt to realise a straight line, they will obtain a curve, which we “three-dimensional beings” designate as a great circle, i.e. a self-contained line of definite finite length, which can be measured up by means of a measuring-rod. Similarly, this universe has a finite area that can be compared with the area, of a square constructed with rods. The great charm resulting from this consideration lies in the recognition of the fact that the universe of these beings is finite and yet has no limits.

Let's now look at another two-dimensional existence, but this time on a spherical surface instead of a flat plane. The flat beings with their measuring rods and other objects fit perfectly on this surface, and they can’t leave it. Their entire universe of observation is limited to the surface of the sphere. Can these beings see the geometry of their universe as flat geometry, with their rods actually representing "distance"? No, they can't. If they try to perceive a straight line, what they get instead is a curve, which we "three-dimensional beings" call a great circle, meaning a closed line of a specific finite length, which can be measured with a measuring rod. Likewise, this universe has a finite area that can be compared to the area of a square made with rods. The intriguing insight from this idea is the realization that the universe of these beings is finite and yet has no edges.

But the spherical-surface beings do not need to go on a world-tour in order to perceive that they are not living in a Euclidean universe. They can convince themselves of this on every part of their “world,” provided they do not use too small a piece of it. Starting from a point, they draw “straight lines” (arcs of circles as judged in three dimensional space) of equal length in all directions. They will call the line joining the free ends of these lines a “circle.” For a plane surface, the ratio of the circumference of a circle to its diameter, both lengths being measured with the same rod, is, according to Euclidean geometry of the plane, equal to a constant value π, which is independent of the diameter of the circle. On their spherical surface our flat beings would find for this ratio the value

But the beings on the spherical surface don’t need to travel the world to realize they’re not living in a Euclidean universe. They can figure this out from any part of their “world,” as long as they don’t use too small a section. Starting from a point, they draw “straight lines” (which are arcs of circles when viewed in three-dimensional space) of equal length in every direction. They’ll refer to the line connecting the free ends of these lines as a “circle.” In a flat surface, the ratio of a circle's circumference to its diameter, with both measurements taken with the same rod, is, according to Euclidean geometry of the plane, a constant value π, which doesn’t change with the circle’s diameter. On their spherical surface, our flat beings would find that this ratio has the value

image036

i.e. a smaller value than π, the difference being the more considerable, the greater is the radius of the circle in comparison with the radius R of the “world-sphere.” By means of this relation the spherical beings can determine the radius of their universe (“world”), even when only a relatively small part of their worldsphere is available for their measurements. But if this part is very small indeed, they will no longer be able to demonstrate that they are on a spherical “world” and not on a Euclidean plane, for a small part of a spherical surface differs only slightly from a piece of a plane of the same size.

i.e. a smaller value than π, and the bigger the difference, the larger the radius of the circle compared to the radius R of the “world-sphere.” Using this relationship, spherical beings can figure out the radius of their universe (“world”), even if they only have a relatively small section of their worldsphere to measure. However, if that part is really tiny, they won’t be able to show that they are on a spherical “world” and not on a Euclidean plane, because a small section of a spherical surface looks only slightly different from a similarly sized piece of a plane.

Thus if the spherical surface beings are living on a planet of which the solar system occupies only a negligibly small part of the spherical universe, they have no means of determining whether they are living in a finite or in an infinite universe, because the “piece of universe” to which they have access is in both cases practically plane, or Euclidean. It follows directly from this discussion, that for our sphere-beings the circumference of a circle first increases with the radius until the “circumference of the universe” is reached, and that it thenceforward gradually decreases to zero for still further increasing values of the radius. During this process the area of the circle continues to increase more and more, until finally it becomes equal to the total area of the whole “world-sphere.”

So, if the spherical beings are living on a planet that's part of a solar system that occupies only a tiny fraction of the spherical universe, they have no way of knowing whether they exist in a finite or infinite universe. This is because the “piece of universe” they can observe is effectively flat or Euclidean in both cases. This discussion leads to the conclusion that for our sphere beings, the circumference of a circle initially increases with the radius until it reaches the "circumference of the universe." After that point, it gradually decreases to zero as the radius continues to grow. Meanwhile, the area of the circle keeps increasing until it eventually matches the total area of the entire “world-sphere.”

Perhaps the reader will wonder why we have placed our “beings” on a sphere rather than on another closed surface. But this choice has its justification in the fact that, of all closed surfaces, the sphere is unique in possessing the property that all points on it are equivalent. I admit that the ratio of the circumference c of a circle to its radius r depends on r, but for a given value of r it is the same for all points of the “worldsphere”; in other words, the “world-sphere” is a “surface of constant curvature.”

Perhaps the reader will wonder why we have placed our “beings” on a sphere instead of another closed surface. But this choice is justified because, of all closed surfaces, the sphere is unique in that all points on it are equivalent. I acknowledge that the ratio of the circumference c of a circle to its radius r depends on r, but for a given value of r, it is the same for all points on the “worldsphere”; in other words, the “world-sphere” is a “surface of constant curvature.”

To this two-dimensional sphere-universe there is a three-dimensional analogy, namely, the three-dimensional spherical space which was discovered by Riemann. its points are likewise all equivalent. It possesses a finite volume, which is determined by its “radius” (2π2R3). Is it possible to imagine a spherical space? To imagine a space means nothing else than that we imagine an epitome of our “space” experience, i.e. of experience that we can have in the movement of “rigid” bodies. In this sense we can imagine a spherical space.

To this two-dimensional sphere-universe, there's a three-dimensional counterpart, which is the three-dimensional spherical space that Riemann discovered. Its points are also all equivalent. It has a finite volume, defined by its “radius” (2π2R3). Is it possible to visualize a spherical space? To visualize a space simply means we are creating a summary of our “space” experience, i.e. the experiences we can have while moving “rigid” bodies. In this sense, we can visualize a spherical space.

Suppose we draw lines or stretch strings in all directions from a point, and mark off from each of these the distance r with a measuring-rod. All the free end-points of these lengths lie on a spherical surface. We can specially measure up the area (F) of this surface by means of a square made up of measuring-rods. If the universe is Euclidean, then F = 4πr2; if it is spherical, then F is always less than 4πr2. With increasing values of r, F increases from zero up to a maximum value which is determined by the “world-radius,” but for still further increasing values of r, the area gradually diminishes to zero. At first, the straight lines which radiate from the starting point diverge farther and farther from one another, but later they approach each other, and finally they run together again at a “counter-point” to the starting point. Under such conditions they have traversed the whole spherical space. It is easily seen that the three-dimensional spherical space is quite analogous to the two-dimensional spherical surface. It is finite (i.e. of finite volume), and has no bounds.

Suppose we draw lines or stretch strings in all directions from a point and measure a distance r from each of these with a ruler. All the free end-points of these lengths lie on a spherical surface. We can specifically measure the area (F) of this surface using a square made of rulers. If the universe is flat (Euclidean), then F = 4πr2; if it is curved (spherical), then F is always less than 4πr2. As r increases, F grows from zero up to a maximum value set by the “world-radius,” but if r continues to increase, the area gradually decreases back to zero. Initially, the straight lines radiating from the starting point spread further apart, but eventually, they start to come closer together and finally converge again at a “counter-point” to the starting point. In this scenario, they have covered the entire spherical space. It’s clear that three-dimensional spherical space is quite similar to two-dimensional spherical surfaces. It is finite (i.e. has a finite volume) and has no boundaries.

It may be mentioned that there is yet another kind of curved space: “elliptical space.” It can be regarded as a curved space in which the two “counter-points” are identical (indistinguishable from each other). An elliptical universe can thus be considered to some extent as a curved universe possessing central symmetry.

It’s worth mentioning that there’s another type of curved space: “elliptical space.” This can be viewed as a curved space where the two “counter-points” are identical (indistinguishable from one another). An elliptical universe can therefore be seen as a curved universe with central symmetry to some degree.

It follows from what has been said, that closed spaces without limits are conceivable. From amongst these, the spherical space (and the elliptical) excels in its simplicity, since all points on it are equivalent. As a result of this discussion, a most interesting question arises for astronomers and physicists, and that is whether the universe in which we live is infinite, or whether it is finite in the manner of the spherical universe. Our experience is far from being sufficient to enable us to answer this question. But the general theory of relativity permits of our answering it with a moderate degree of certainty, and in this connection the difficulty mentioned in Section XXX finds its solution.

It follows from what’s been discussed that we can imagine closed spaces without limits. Among these, spherical space (and elliptical space) stands out for its simplicity since all points on it are equal. This raises an intriguing question for astronomers and physicists: is the universe we live in infinite, or is it finite like a spherical universe? Our experience doesn’t give us enough information to answer this question conclusively. However, the general theory of relativity allows us to respond with some level of certainty, and in this regard, the challenge mentioned in Section XXX finds its resolution.

XXXII.
THE STRUCTURE OF SPACE ACCORDING TO THE GENERAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY

According to the general theory of relativity, the geometrical properties of space are not independent, but they are determined by matter. Thus we can draw conclusions about the geometrical structure of the universe only if we base our considerations on the state of the matter as being something that is known. We know from experience that, for a suitably chosen co-ordinate system, the velocities of the stars are small as compared with the velocity of transmission of light. We can thus as a rough approximation arrive at a conclusion as to the nature of the universe as a whole, if we treat the matter as being at rest.

According to the general theory of relativity, the geometric properties of space aren't independent; they're influenced by matter. This means we can only draw conclusions about the geometric structure of the universe if we start with a known state of matter. From our experience, we see that in a properly chosen coordinate system, the speeds of the stars are small compared to the speed of light. Therefore, we can roughly conclude the overall nature of the universe if we consider the matter to be at rest.

We already know from our previous discussion that the behaviour of measuring-rods and clocks is influenced by gravitational fields, i.e. by the distribution of matter. This in itself is sufficient to exclude the possibility of the exact validity of Euclidean geometry in our universe. But it is conceivable that our universe differs only slightly from a Euclidean one, and this notion seems all the more probable, since calculations show that the metrics of surrounding space is influenced only to an exceedingly small extent by masses even of the magnitude of our sun. We might imagine that, as regards geometry, our universe behaves analogously to a surface which is irregularly curved in its individual parts, but which nowhere departs appreciably from a plane: something like the rippled surface of a lake. Such a universe might fittingly be called a quasi-Euclidean universe. As regards its space it would be infinite. But calculation shows that in a quasi-Euclidean universe the average density of matter would necessarily be nil. Thus such a universe could not be inhabited by matter everywhere; it would present to us that unsatisfactory picture which we portrayed in Section XXX.

We already know from our earlier discussion that the behavior of measuring rods and clocks is affected by gravitational fields, meaning by the distribution of matter. This alone is enough to rule out the possibility of Euclidean geometry being exactly valid in our universe. However, it's conceivable that our universe only slightly differs from a Euclidean one, and this idea seems even more likely since calculations indicate that the structure of surrounding space is affected only minimally by masses, even those as large as our sun. We might imagine that, in terms of geometry, our universe is similar to a surface that is unevenly curved in its individual areas but does not significantly deviate from a flat plane, like the rippled surface of a lake. Such a universe could fittingly be called a quasi-Euclidean universe. In terms of space, it would be infinite. However, calculations show that in a quasi-Euclidean universe, the average density of matter would necessarily be nil. Therefore, such a universe couldn't be filled with matter everywhere; it would present us with that unsatisfactory picture we described in Section XXX.

If we are to have in the universe an average density of matter which differs from zero, however small may be that difference, then the universe cannot be quasi-Euclidean. On the contrary, the results of calculation indicate that if matter be distributed uniformly, the universe would necessarily be spherical (or elliptical). Since in reality the detailed distribution of matter is not uniform, the real universe will deviate in individual parts from the spherical, i.e. the universe will be quasi-spherical. But it will be necessarily finite. In fact, the theory supplies us with a simple connection[25] between the space-expanse of the universe and the average density of matter in it.

If the universe has an average density of matter greater than zero, even if that difference is tiny, then it can't be quasi-Euclidean. Instead, calculations show that if matter is evenly distributed, the universe would have to be spherical (or elliptical). Since the actual distribution of matter is not uniform, the real universe will differ in specific areas from being perfectly spherical, meaning it will be quasi-spherical. However, it will definitely be finite. In fact, the theory gives us a straightforward link[25] between the universe's spatial extent and the average density of matter within it.

[25]
For the radius R of the universe we obtain the equation

[25]
For the radius R of the universe, we get the equation

image037

The use of the C.G.S. system in this equation gives 2/k = 1.08 x 1027; ρ is the average density of the matter and k is a constant connected with the Newtonian constant of gravitation.

The C.G.S. system used in this equation results in 2/k = 1.08 x 1027; ρ represents the average density of the matter, and k is a constant related to the Newtonian gravitational constant.

APPENDICES

APPENDIX I
SIMPLE DERIVATION OF THE LORENTZ TRANSFORMATION
(SUPPLEMENTARY TO SECTION XI)

For the relative orientation of the co-ordinate systems indicated in Fig. 2, the x-axes of both systems permanently coincide. In the present case we can divide the problem into parts by considering first only events which are localised on the x-axis. Any such event is represented with respect to the co-ordinate system K by the abscissa x and the time t, and with respect to the system K′ by the abscissa x′ and the time t′. We require to find x′ and t′ when x and t are given.

For the relative orientation of the coordinate systems shown in Fig. 2, the x-axes of both systems always line up. In this case, we can break the problem into parts by first looking only at events that are located on the x-axis. Each of these events is represented in the coordinate system K by the coordinate x and the time t, and in the system K′ by the coordinate x′ and the time t′. We need to find x′ and t′ when x and t are given.

A light-signal, which is proceeding along the positive axis of x, is transmitted according to the equation

A light signal traveling along the positive x-axis is transmitted according to the equation

x = ct

x = ct

or

or

xct = 0 . . . . . (1).

xct = 0 . . . . . (1).

Since the same light-signal has to be transmitted relative to K′ with the velocity c, the propagation relative to the system K′ will be represented by the analogous formula

Since the same light signal has to be transmitted relative to K′ at the speed c, the propagation relative to the system K′ will be represented by the similar formula

x′ct′ = 0 . . . . . (2)

x′ct′ = 0 . . . . . (2)

Those space-time points (events) which satisfy (1) must also satisfy (2). Obviously this will be the case when the relation

Those space-time points (events) that meet (1) must also meet (2). It's clear that this will happen when the relation

(x′ct′) = λ(xct) . . . (3).

(x′ct′) = λ(xct) . . . (3).

is fulfilled in general, where λ indicates a constant; for, according to (3), the disappearance of (xct) involves the disappearance of (x′ct′).

is fulfilled in general, where λ represents a constant; for, according to (3), the vanishing of (xct) means the vanishing of (x′ct′).

If we apply quite similar considerations to light rays which are being transmitted along the negative x-axis, we obtain the condition

If we apply similar ideas to light rays that are traveling along the negative x-axis, we get the condition

(x′ + ct′) = (x + ct) . . . (4).

(x′ + ct′) = (x + ct) . . . (4).

By adding (or subtracting) equations (3) and (4), and introducing for convenience the constants a and b in place of the constants λ and μ where

By adding (or subtracting) equations (3) and (4), and introducing the constants a and b instead of the constants λ and μ where

image038

and

and

image039

we obtain the equations

we get the equations

image040

We should thus have the solution of our problem, if the constants a and b were known. These result from the following discussion.

We would have the solution to our problem if we knew the constants a and b. These come from the following discussion.

For the origin of K′ we have permanently x′ = 0, and hence according to the first of the equations (5)

For the origin of K′ we have permanently x′ = 0, and so according to the first of the equations (5)

image041

If we call v the velocity with which the origin of K′ is moving relative to K, we then have

If we call v the speed at which the origin of K′ is moving in relation to K, we then have

image042

The same value v can be obtained from equations (5), if we calculate the velocity of another point of K′ relative to K, or the velocity (directed towards the negative x-axis) of a point of K with respect to K′. In short, we can designate v as the relative velocity of the two systems.

The same value v can be obtained from equations (5) if we calculate the velocity of another point of K′ relative to K, or the velocity (pointing towards the negative x-axis) of a point of K with respect to K′. In short, we can refer to v as the relative velocity of the two systems.

Furthermore, the principle of relativity teaches us that, as judged from K, the length of a unit measuring-rod which is at rest with reference to K′ must be exactly the same as the length, as judged from K′, of a unit measuring-rod which is at rest relative to K. In order to see how the points of the x′-axis appear as viewed from K, we only require to take a “snapshot” of K′ from K; this means that we have to insert a particular value of t (time of K), e.g. t = 0. For this value of t we then obtain from the first of the equations (5)

Furthermore, the principle of relativity tells us that, from the perspective of K, the length of a measuring rod that is at rest with respect to K′ must be exactly the same as the length, from the perspective of K′, of a measuring rod that is at rest relative to K. To understand how the points on the x′-axis look from K, we just need to take a “snapshot” of K′ from K; this means we need to set a specific value for t (the time in K), e.g. t = 0. For this value of t, we then obtain from the first of the equations (5)

x′ = ax

x′ = ax

Two points of the x′-axis which are separated by the distance Δx′ = 1 when measured in the K′ system are thus separated in our instantaneous photograph by the distance

Two points on the x′-axis that are 1 unit apart when measured in the K′ system are shown in our current photograph to be separated by the distance

image043

But if the snapshot be taken from K′(t′ = 0), and if we eliminate t from the equations (5), taking into account the expression (6), we obtain

But if the snapshot is taken from K′(t′ = 0), and if we remove t from the equations (5), considering the expression (6), we get

image044

From this we conclude that two points on the x-axis separated by the distance 1 (relative to K) will be represented on our snapshot by the distance

From this, we conclude that two points on the x-axis, separated by a distance of 1 (relative to K), will appear on our snapshot as the distance

image045

But from what has been said, the two snapshots must be identical; hence Δx in (7) must be equal to Δx′ in (7a), so that we obtain

But from what has been said, the two snapshots must be identical; hence Δx in (7) must be equal to Δx′ in (7a), so that we obtain

image046

The equations (6) and (7b) determine the constants a and b. By inserting the values of these constants in (5), we obtain the first and the fourth of the equations given in Section XI.

The equations (6) and (7b) figure out the constants a and b. By plugging in the values of these constants into (5), we get the first and the fourth of the equations listed in Section XI.

image047

Thus we have obtained the Lorentz transformation for events on the x-axis. It satisfies the condition

Thus we have obtained the Lorentz transformation for events on the x-axis. It satisfies the condition

x′2c2t′2 = x2c2t2 . . . . . . (8a).

x′2c2t′2 = x2c2t2 . . . . . . (8a).

The extension of this result, to include events which take place outside the x-axis, is obtained by retaining equations (8) and supplementing them by the relations

The extension of this result, to include events that occur outside the x-axis, is achieved by keeping equations (8) and adding to them the relations

image048

In this way we satisfy the postulate of the constancy of the velocity of light in vacuo for rays of light of arbitrary direction, both for the system K and for the system K′. This may be shown in the following manner.

In this way, we fulfill the assumption that the speed of light in vacuo is constant for light rays coming from any direction, both for system K and for system K′. We can demonstrate this as follows.

We suppose a light-signal sent out from the origin of K at the time t = 0. It will be propagated according to the equation

We assume a light signal is sent out from the origin of K at time t = 0. It will travel according to the equation

image049

or, if we square this equation, according to the equation

or, if we square this equation, according to the equation

x2 + y2 + z2c2t2 = 0 . . . . . (10).

x2 + y2 + z2c2t2 = 0 . . . . . (10).

It is required by the law of propagation of light, in conjunction with the postulate of relativity, that the transmission of the signal in question should take place—as judged from K′—in accordance with the corresponding formula

It is required by the law of light propagation, along with the principle of relativity, that the transmission of the signal in question should happen—as seen from K′—according to the corresponding formula.

r′ = ct′

r′ = ct′

or,

or,

x′2 + y′2 + z′2c2t′2 = 0 . . . . . . (10a).

x′2 + y′2 + z′2c2t′2 = 0 . . . . . . (10a).

In order that equation (10a) may be a consequence of equation (10), we must have

In order for equation (10a) to be a result of equation (10), we need to have

x′2 + y′2 + z′2c2t′2 = σ (x2 + y2 + z2c2t2) (11).

x′2 + y′2 + z′2c2t′2 = σ (x2 + y2 + z2c2t2) (11).

Since equation (8a) must hold for points on the x-axis, we thus have σ = 1. It is easily seen that the Lorentz transformation really satisfies equation (11) for σ = 1; for (11) is a consequence of (8a) and (9), and hence also of (8) and (9). We have thus derived the Lorentz transformation.

Since equation (8a) must apply to points on the x-axis, we have σ = 1. It's clear that the Lorentz transformation satisfies equation (11) for σ = 1; equation (11) is derived from (8a) and (9), and consequently from (8) and (9) as well. Therefore, we've derived the Lorentz transformation.

The Lorentz transformation represented by (8) and (9) still requires to be generalised. Obviously it is immaterial whether the axes of K′ be chosen so that they are spatially parallel to those of K. It is also not essential that the velocity of translation of K′ with respect to K should be in the direction of the x-axis. A simple consideration shows that we are able to construct the Lorentz transformation in this general sense from two kinds of transformations, viz. from Lorentz transformations in the special sense and from purely spatial transformations. which corresponds to the replacement of the rectangular co-ordinate system by a new system with its axes pointing in other directions.

The Lorentz transformation described by (8) and (9) still needs to be generalized. It doesn't really matter whether the axes of K′ are chosen to be spatially parallel to those of K. It's also not crucial that the direction of translation of K′ with respect to K aligns with the x-axis. A straightforward consideration shows that we can create the Lorentz transformation in this broader context from two types of transformations: specifically, from Lorentz transformations in the narrow sense and from purely spatial transformations, which involve changing the rectangular coordinate system to a new system with axes oriented in different directions.

Mathematically, we can characterise the generalised Lorentz transformation thus:

Mathematically, we can describe the generalized Lorentz transformation like this:

It expresses x′, y′, x′, t′, in terms of linear homogeneous functions of x, y, x, t, of such a kind that the relation

It expresses x′, y′, x′, t′ in terms of linear homogeneous functions of x, y, x, t in such a way that the relation

x′2 + y′2 + z′2c2t′2 = x2 + y2 + z2c2t2 (11a).

x′2 + y′2 + z′2c2t′2 = x2 + y2 + z2c2t2 (11a).

is satisficd identically. That is to say: If we substitute their expressions in x, y, x, t, in place of x′, y′, x′, t′, on the left-hand side, then the left-hand side of (11a) agrees with the right-hand side.

is satisfied identically. In other words: If we replace their expressions in x, y, x, t with x′, y′, x′, t′ on the left side, then the left side of (11a) matches the right side.

APPENDIX II
MINKOWSKI’S FOUR-DIMENSIONAL SPACE (“WORLD”)
(SUPPLEMENTARY TO SECTION XVII)

We can characterise the Lorentz transformation still more simply if we introduce the imaginary

We can describe the Lorentz transformation even more straightforwardly if we bring in the imaginary

image031

in place of t, as time-variable. If, in accordance with this, we insert

in place of t, as a time-variable. If we insert

image050

and similarly for the accented system K′, then the condition which is identically satisfied by the transformation can be expressed thus:

and similarly for the accented system K′, the condition that is always met by the transformation can be stated as follows:

x12 + x22 + x32 + x42 = x12 + x22 + x32 + x42 (12).

x12 + x22 + x32 + x42 = x12 + x22 + x32 + x42 (12).

That is, by the afore-mentioned choice of “coordinates,” (11a) [see the end of Appendix II] is transformed into this equation.

That is, by the previously mentioned choice of “coordinates,” (11a) [see the end of Appendix II] is changed into this equation.

We see from (12) that the imaginary time co-ordinate x4, enters into the condition of transformation in exactly the same way as the space co-ordinates x1, x2, x3. It is due to this fact that, according to the theory of relativity, the “time” x4, enters into natural laws in the same form as the space co ordinates x1, x2, x3.

We can see from (12) that the imaginary time coordinate x4 is involved in the transformation conditions in exactly the same way as the spatial coordinates x1, x2, x3. It's because of this that, according to the theory of relativity, the “time” x4 is incorporated into natural laws in the same way as the spatial coordinates x1, x2, x3.

A four-dimensional continuum described by the “co-ordinates” x1, x2, x3, x4, was called “world” by Minkowski, who also termed a point-event a “world-point.” From a “happening” in three-dimensional space, physics becomes, as it were, an “existence” in the four-dimensional “world.”

A four-dimensional continuum defined by the coordinates x1, x2, x3, x4, was referred to as the “world” by Minkowski, who also called a point-event a “world-point.” From an event in three-dimensional space, physics transforms into, in a sense, an “existence” in the four-dimensional “world.”

This four-dimensional “world” bears a close similarity to the three-dimensional “space” of (Euclidean) analytical geometry. If we introduce into the latter a new Cartesian co-ordinate system (x′1, x′2, x′3) with the same origin, then x′1, x′2, x′3, are linear homogeneous functions of x1, x2, x3 which identically satisfy the equation

This four-dimensional “world” is very similar to the three-dimensional “space” of (Euclidean) analytical geometry. If we add a new Cartesian coordinate system (x′1, x′2, x′3) from the same origin, then x′1, x′2, x′3 are linear homogeneous functions of x1, x2, x3 that satisfy the equation.

x12 + x22 + x32 = x12 + x22 + x32

x12 + x22 + x32 = x12 + x22 + x32

The analogy with (12) is a complete one. We can regard Minkowski’s “world” in a formal manner as a four-dimensional Euclidean space (with an imaginary time coordinate); the Lorentz transformation corresponds to a “rotation” of the co-ordinate system in the four-dimensional “world.”

The analogy with (12) is a complete one. We can think of Minkowski’s “world” in a formal way as a four-dimensional Euclidean space (with an imaginary time coordinate); the Lorentz transformation corresponds to a “rotation” of the coordinate system in the four-dimensional “world.”

APPENDIX III
THE EXPERIMENTAL CONFIRMATION OF THE GENERAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY

From a systematic theoretical point of view, we may imagine the process of evolution of an empirical science to be a continuous process of induction. Theories are evolved and are expressed in short compass as statements of a large number of individual observations in the form of empirical laws, from which the general laws can be ascertained by comparison. Regarded in this way, the development of a science bears some resemblance to the compilation of a classified catalogue. It is, as it were, a purely empirical enterprise.

From a systematic theoretical perspective, we can think of the evolution of an empirical science as an ongoing process of induction. Theories are formed and summarized as statements based on numerous individual observations in the form of empirical laws, from which general laws can be derived through comparison. Viewed this way, the development of a science is somewhat similar to creating a classified catalog. It is essentially a purely empirical undertaking.

But this point of view by no means embraces the whole of the actual process; for it slurs over the important part played by intuition and deductive thought in the development of an exact science. As soon as a science has emerged from its initial stages, theoretical advances are no longer achieved merely by a process of arrangement. Guided by empirical data, the investigator rather develops a system of thought which, in general, is built up logically from a small number of fundamental assumptions, the so-called axioms. We call such a system of thought a theory. The theory finds the justification for its existence in the fact that it correlates a large number of single observations, and it is just here that the “truth” of the theory lies.

But this perspective definitely doesn’t capture the entire process; it overlooks the crucial role of intuition and deductive reasoning in the development of precise science. Once a science has moved past its early stages, theoretical progress is no longer just about organizing information. Instead, guided by empirical data, the researcher develops a system of thought that is generally constructed logically from a few fundamental assumptions, known as axioms. We refer to this system of thought as a theory. The theory validates its existence by correlating a large number of individual observations, and it is precisely here that the “truth” of the theory resides.

Corresponding to the same complex of empirical data, there may be several theories, which differ from one another to a considerable extent. But as regards the deductions from the theories which are capable of being tested, the agreement between the theories may be so complete that it becomes difficult to find any deductions in which the two theories differ from each other. As an example, a case of general interest is available in the province of biology, in the Darwinian theory of the development of species by selection in the struggle for existence, and in the theory of development which is based on the hypothesis of the hereditary transmission of acquired characters.

Corresponding to the same set of empirical data, there can be multiple theories that vary significantly from one another. However, when it comes to the testable deductions from these theories, the agreement can be so tight that it becomes hard to find any deductions where the two theories differ. For instance, an example of general interest is found in the field of biology, specifically in the Darwinian theory of species development through selection in the struggle for existence, and in the development theory based on the idea of hereditary transmission of acquired traits.

We have another instance of far-reaching agreement between the deductions from two theories in Newtonian mechanics on the one hand, and the general theory of relativity on the other. This agreement goes so far, that up to the present we have been able to find only a few deductions from the general theory of relativity which are capable of investigation, and to which the physics of pre-relativity days does not also lead, and this despite the profound difference in the fundamental assumptions of the two theories. In what follows, we shall again consider these important deductions, and we shall also discuss the empirical evidence appertaining to them which has hitherto been obtained.

We have another case of significant agreement between the conclusions drawn from two theories in Newtonian mechanics on one side, and the general theory of relativity on the other. This agreement is so strong that, until now, we've only been able to find a few conclusions from the general theory of relativity that can be investigated, and which the physics from before relativity also supports, despite the deep differences in the fundamental assumptions of the two theories. In what follows, we will again look at these important conclusions, and we will also discuss the empirical evidence related to them that has been gathered so far.

(a) Motion of the Perihelion of Mercury

According to Newtonian mechanics and Newton’s law of gravitation, a planet which is revolving round the sun would describe an ellipse round the latter, or, more correctly, round the common centre of gravity of the sun and the planet. In such a system, the sun, or the common centre of gravity, lies in one of the foci of the orbital ellipse in such a manner that, in the course of a planet-year, the distance sun-planet grows from a minimum to a maximum, and then decreases again to a minimum. If instead of Newton’s law we insert a somewhat different law of attraction into the calculation, we find that, according to this new law, the motion would still take place in such a manner that the distance sun-planet exhibits periodic variations; but in this case the angle described by the line joining sun and planet during such a period (from perihelion—closest proximity to the sun—to perihelion) would differ from 360°. The line of the orbit would not then be a closed one but in the course of time it would fill up an annular part of the orbital plane, viz. between the circle of least and the circle of greatest distance of the planet from the sun.

According to Newtonian mechanics and Newton’s law of gravitation, a planet orbiting the sun describes an ellipse around it, or more accurately, around the common center of gravity of the sun and the planet. In this system, the sun, or the common center of gravity, is located at one of the foci of the orbital ellipse. This means that over the course of a planet's year, the distance between the sun and the planet increases from a minimum to a maximum and then decreases back to a minimum. If we replace Newton’s law with a slightly different law of attraction in our calculations, we find that, according to this new law, the motion would still show periodic variations in the distance between the sun and the planet; however, in this scenario, the angle formed by the line connecting the sun and the planet during such a period (from perihelion—closest approach to the sun—to perihelion) would not equal 360°. Consequently, the orbit would not be closed, but rather, over time, it would trace out an annular region in the orbital plane, specifically between the circle of closest approach and the circle of farthest distance from the sun.

According also to the general theory of relativity, which differs of course from the theory of Newton, a small variation from the Newton-Kepler motion of a planet in its orbit should take place, and in such away, that the angle described by the radius sun-planet between one perhelion and the next should exceed that corresponding to one complete revolution by an amount given by

According to the general theory of relativity, which is obviously different from Newton's theory, there should be a small deviation from the Newton-Kepler motion of a planet in its orbit. This deviation should occur in such a way that the angle formed by the radius from the sun to the planet between one perihelion and the next should be greater than that corresponding to a complete revolution by an amount given by

image051

(N.B.—One complete revolution corresponds to the angle 2π in the absolute angular measure customary in physics, and the above expression given the amount by which the radius sun-planet exceeds this angle during the interval between one perihelion and the next.) In this expression a represents the major semi-axis of the ellipse, e its eccentricity, c the velocity of light, and T the period of revolution of the planet. Our result may also be stated as follows: According to the general theory of relativity, the major axis of the ellipse rotates round the sun in the same sense as the orbital motion of the planet. Theory requires that this rotation should amount to 43 seconds of arc per century for the planet Mercury, but for the other Planets of our solar system its magnitude should be so small that it would necessarily escape detection.[26]

(N.B.—One complete revolution corresponds to the angle 2π in the standard angular measurement used in physics, and the expression above shows how much the radius sun-planet exceeds this angle during the time between one perihelion and the next.) In this expression, a represents the major semi-axis of the ellipse, e its eccentricity, c the speed of light, and T the planet's period of revolution. We can also express our result like this: According to the general theory of relativity, the major axis of the ellipse rotates around the sun in the same direction as the planet's orbital motion. Theory suggests that this rotation should be 43 seconds of arc per century for the planet Mercury, but for the other planets in our solar system, its amount should be so small that it would go unnoticed.[26]

[26]
Especially since the next planet Venus has an orbit that is almost an exact circle, which makes it more difficult to locate the perihelion with precision.

[26]
Especially since the next planet, Venus, has an orbit that is nearly a perfect circle, which makes it harder to pinpoint the perihelion accurately.

In point of fact, astronomers have found that the theory of Newton does not suffice to calculate the observed motion of Mercury with an exactness corresponding to that of the delicacy of observation attainable at the present time. After taking account of all the disturbing influences exerted on Mercury by the remaining planets, it was found (Leverrier: 1859; and Newcomb: 1895) that an unexplained perihelial movement of the orbit of Mercury remained over, the amount of which does not differ sensibly from the above mentioned +43 seconds of arc per century. The uncertainty of the empirical result amounts to a few seconds only.

In fact, scientists have discovered that Newton's theory isn't enough to accurately calculate Mercury's observed motion with the precision we can achieve today. After considering all the gravitational effects from other planets on Mercury, it was found (Leverrier: 1859; and Newcomb: 1895) that there was still an unexplained shift in Mercury's orbit, which is about the same as the previously mentioned +43 seconds of arc per century. The margin of error in this empirical result is just a few seconds.

(b) Deflection of Light by a Gravitational Field

image052

In Section XXII it has been already mentioned that according to the general theory of relativity, a ray of light will experience a curvature of its path when passing through a gravitational field, this curvature being similar to that experienced by the path of a body which is projected through a gravitational field. As a result of this theory, we should expect that a ray of light which is passing close to a heavenly body would be deviated towards the latter. For a ray of light which passes the sun at a distance of Δ sun-radii from its centre, the angle of deflection (α) should amount to

In Section XXII, it has already been mentioned that according to the general theory of relativity, a beam of light will curve its path when it passes through a gravitational field. This curvature is similar to what happens when an object moves through a gravitational field. Because of this theory, we would expect that a beam of light passing close to a celestial body would be pulled towards it. For a beam of light that passes the sun at a distance of Δ sun-radii from its center, the angle of deflection (α) should amount to

image053

It may be added that, according to the theory, half of this deflection is produced by the Newtonian field of attraction of the sun, and the other half by the geometrical modification (“curvature”) of space caused by the sun.

It can also be noted that, according to the theory, half of this deflection is caused by the gravitational pull of the sun, and the other half is due to the bending of space (“curvature”) caused by the sun.

This result admits of an experimental test by means of the photographic registration of stars during a total eclipse of the sun. The only reason why we must wait for a total eclipse is because at every other time the atmosphere is so strongly illuminated by the light from the sun that the stars situated near the sun’s disc are invisible. The predicted effect can be seen clearly from the accompanying diagram. If the sun (S) were not present, a star which is practically infinitely distant would be seen in the direction D1, as observed front the earth. But as a consequence of the deflection of light from the star by the sun, the star will be seen in the direction D2, i.e. at a somewhat greater distance from the centre of the sun than corresponds to its real position.

This result can be tested experimentally by capturing photographs of stars during a total solar eclipse. We have to wait for a total eclipse because at any other time, the atmosphere is so brightly lit by sunlight that the stars near the sun’s disc are not visible. The expected effect is illustrated clearly in the accompanying diagram. If the sun (S) were not there, a star that is practically infinitely distant would be seen in the direction D1 from Earth. However, due to the bending of light from the star caused by the sun, the star will actually be seen in the direction D2, which is a bit farther from the center of the sun than where it really is.

In practice, the question is tested in the following way. The stars in the neighbourhood of the sun are photographed during a solar eclipse.

In practice, the question is tested like this: The stars near the sun are photographed during a solar eclipse.

In addition, a second photograph of the same stars is taken when the sun is situated at another position in the sky, i.e. a few months earlier or later. As compared with the standard photograph, the positions of the stars on the eclipse-photograph ought to appear displaced radially outwards (away from the centre of the sun) by an amount corresponding to the angle a.

In addition, a second photo of the same stars is taken when the sun is in a different spot in the sky, i.e. a few months earlier or later. Compared to the standard photo, the positions of the stars on the eclipse photo should seem shifted outward (away from the center of the sun) by an amount that matches the angle a.

We are indebted to the [British] Royal Society and to the Royal Astronomical Society for the investigation of this important deduction. Undaunted by the [first world] war and by difficulties of both a material and a psychological nature aroused by the war, these societies equipped two expeditions—to Sobral (Brazil), and to the island of Principe (West Africa)—and sent several of Britain’s most celebrated astronomers (Eddington, Cottingham, Crommelin, Davidson), in order to obtain photographs of the solar eclipse of 29th May, 1919. The relative discrepancies to be expected between the stellar photographs obtained during the eclipse and the comparison photographs amounted to a few hundredths of a millimetre only. Thus great accuracy was necessary in making the adjustments required for the taking of the photographs, and in their subsequent measurement.

We owe a debt of gratitude to the [British] Royal Society and the Royal Astronomical Society for exploring this important conclusion. Despite the challenges posed by the [First World] War, as well as both material and psychological difficulties caused by the conflict, these societies organized two expeditions—to Sobral (Brazil) and the island of Principe (West Africa)—and sent some of Britain’s most renowned astronomers (Eddington, Cottingham, Crommelin, Davidson) to capture images of the solar eclipse on May 29, 1919. The expected discrepancies between the stellar photographs taken during the eclipse and the comparison photographs were only a few hundredths of a millimeter. Therefore, great precision was crucial for making the necessary adjustments when taking the photographs and in their subsequent measurements.

The results of the measurements confirmed the theory in a thoroughly satisfactory manner. The rectangular components of the observed and of the calculated deviations of the stars (in seconds of arc) are set forth in the following table of results:

The results of the measurements confirmed the theory in a completely satisfactory way. The rectangular components of the observed and calculated deviations of the stars (in seconds of arc) are shown in the following table of results:

image054

(c) Displacement of Spectral Lines Towards the Red

In Section XXIII it has been shown that in a system K′ which is in rotation with regard to a Galileian system K, clocks of identical construction, and which are considered at rest with respect to the rotating reference-body, go at rates which are dependent on the positions of the clocks. We shall now examine this dependence quantitatively. A clock, which is situated at a distance r from the centre of the disc, has a velocity relative to K which is given by

In Section XXIII, it has been demonstrated that in a system K′ that is rotating with respect to a Galilean system K, identical clocks that are at rest relative to the rotating reference frame operate at different rates depending on their positions. We will now look at this relationship in more detail. A clock positioned at a distance r from the center of the disc has a velocity relative to K represented by

v = ωr,

v = ωr,

where ω represents the angular velocity of rotation of the disc K′ with respect to K. If v0, represents the number of ticks of the clock per unit time (“rate” of the clock) relative to K when the clock is at rest, then the “rate” of the clock (v) when it is moving relative to K with a velocity v, but at rest with respect to the disc, will, in accordance with Section XII, be given by

where ω represents the angular velocity of rotation of the disc K′ in relation to K. If v0 is the number of ticks of the clock per unit of time (“rate” of the clock) relative to K when the clock is at rest, then the “rate” of the clock (v) while moving relative to K at a velocity v, but stationary with respect to the disc, will, according to Section XII, be given by

image055

or with sufficient accuracy by

or with enough accuracy by

image056

This expression may also be stated in the following form:

This expression can also be written like this:

image057

If we represent the difference of potential of the centrifugal force between the position of the clock and the centre of the disc by φ, i.e. the work, considered negatively, which must be performed on the unit of mass against the centrifugal force in order to transport it from the position of the clock on the rotating disc to the centre of the disc, then we have

If we express the difference in potential of the centrifugal force between the clock's position and the center of the disc as φ, i.e. the work, viewed negatively, that needs to be done on each unit of mass against the centrifugal force to move it from the clock's position on the rotating disc to the center of the disc, then we have

image058

From this it follows that

So, it follows that

image059

In the first place, we see from this expression that two clocks of identical construction will go at different rates when situated at different distances from the centre of the disc. This result is also valid from the standpoint of an observer who is rotating with the disc.

In the first place, this expression shows us that two clocks built the same way will run at different speeds when they are placed at different distances from the center of the disc. This result also holds true for an observer who is rotating with the disc.

Now, as judged from the disc, the latter is in a gravitational field of potential φ, hence the result we have obtained will hold quite generally for gravitational fields. Furthermore, we can regard an atom which is emitting spectral lines as a clock, so that the following statement will hold:

Now, based on the disc, it’s in a gravitational field of potential φ, so the result we’ve obtained applies generally to gravitational fields. Additionally, we can think of an atom that’s emitting spectral lines as a clock, so the following statement will be true:

An atom absorbs or emits light of a frequency which is dependent on the potential of the gravitational field in which it is situated.

An atom absorbs or emits light at a frequency that depends on the strength of the gravitational field it is in.

The frequency of an atom situated on the surface of a heavenly body will be somewhat less than the frequency of an atom of the same element which is situated in free space (or on the surface of a smaller celestial body).

The frequency of an atom located on the surface of a celestial body will be slightly lower than the frequency of an atom of the same element that is found in free space (or on the surface of a smaller celestial body).

Now φ = – K (M/r), where K is Newton’s constant of gravitation, and M is the mass of the heavenly body. Thus a displacement towards the red ought to take place for spectral lines produced at the surface of stars as compared with the spectral lines of the same element produced at the surface of the earth, the amount of this displacement being

Now φ = – K (M/r), where K is Newton’s gravitational constant, and M is the mass of the celestial body. Therefore, there should be a shift toward the red for spectral lines generated at the surface of stars compared to the spectral lines of the same element created at the surface of the Earth, with the extent of this shift being

image060

For the sun, the displacement towards the red predicted by theory amounts to about two millionths of the wave-length. A trustworthy calculation is not possible in the case of the stars, because in general neither the mass M nor the radius r are known.

For the sun, the shift toward the red that theory predicts is about two millionths of the wavelength. A reliable calculation isn't possible for the stars, since in general neither the mass M nor the radius r is known.

It is an open question whether or not this effect exists, and at the present time (1920) astronomers are working with great zeal towards the solution. Owing to the smallness of the effect in the case of the sun, it is difficult to form an opinion as to its existence. Whereas Grebe and Bachem (Bonn), as a result of their own measurements and those of Evershed and Schwarzschild on the cyanogen bands, have placed the existence of the effect almost beyond doubt, while other investigators, particularly St. John, have been led to the opposite opinion in consequence of their measurements.

It’s still uncertain whether this effect actually exists, and right now (1920), astronomers are intensely working toward finding a solution. Because the effect is so small in the case of the sun, it's hard to form a definitive opinion about its existence. While Grebe and Bachem (Bonn), based on their own measurements as well as those of Evershed and Schwarzschild on the cyanogen bands, have nearly confirmed the existence of the effect, other researchers, especially St. John, have reached the opposite conclusion based on their own measurements.

Mean displacements of lines towards the less refrangible end of the spectrum are certainly revealed by statistical investigations of the fixed stars; but up to the present the examination of the available data does not allow of any definite decision being arrived at, as to whether or not these displacements are to be referred in reality to the effect of gravitation. The results of observation have been collected together, and discussed in detail from the standpoint of the question which has been engaging our attention here, in a paper by E. Freundlich entitled “Zur Prüfung der allgemeinen Relativitäts-Theorie” (Die Naturwissenschaften, 1919, No. 35, p. 520: Julius Springer, Berlin).

Mean displacements of lines toward the less refracted end of the spectrum are definitely shown by statistical studies of the fixed stars; however, so far, the analysis of the available data does not allow for a clear conclusion on whether these displacements are really due to the effects of gravity. The results of observations have been compiled and discussed in detail regarding the question we’ve been focusing on here in a paper by E. Freundlich titled “Zur Prüfung der allgemeinen Relativitäts-Theorie” (Die Naturwissenschaften, 1919, No. 35, p. 520: Julius Springer, Berlin).

At all events, a definite decision will be reached during the next few years. If the displacement of spectral lines towards the red by the gravitational potential does not exist, then the general theory of relativity will be untenable. On the other hand, if the cause of the displacement of spectral lines be definitely traced to the gravitational potential, then the study of this displacement will furnish us with important information as to the mass of the heavenly bodies.[27]

At any rate, a clear decision will be made in the next few years. If the shift of spectral lines towards the red due to gravitational potential doesn’t happen, then the general theory of relativity won't hold up. On the flip side, if we can clearly link the shift of spectral lines to gravitational potential, then examining this shift will give us key insights into the mass of celestial bodies.[27]

[27]
The displacement of spectral lines towards the red end of the spectrum was definitely established by Adams in 1924, by observations on the dense companion of Sirius, for which the effect is about thirty times greater than for the Sun. R.W.L.—translator

[27]
The shift of spectral lines towards the red side of the spectrum was clearly demonstrated by Adams in 1924, through observations of the dense companion of Sirius, where the effect is about thirty times more pronounced than for the Sun. R.W.L.—translator

APPENDIX IV
THE STRUCTURE OF SPACE ACCORDING TO THE GENERAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY
(SUPPLEMENTARY TO SECTION XXXII)

Since the publication of the first edition of this little book, our knowledge about the structure of space in the large (“cosmological problem”) has had an important development, which ought to be mentioned even in a popular presentation of the subject.

Since the release of the first edition of this small book, our understanding of the structure of space on a large scale (“cosmological problem”) has significantly advanced, which should be noted even in an accessible overview of the topic.

My original considerations on the subject were based on two hypotheses:

My initial thoughts on the topic were based on two assumptions:

(1) There exists an average density of matter in the whole of space which is everywhere the same and different from zero.

(1) There is an average density of matter throughout all of space that is consistent everywhere and greater than zero.

(2) The magnitude (“radius”) of space is independent of time.

(2) The size (“radius”) of space is not affected by time.

Both these hypotheses proved to be consistent, according to the general theory of relativity, but only after a hypothetical term was added to the field equations, a term which was not required by the theory as such nor did it seem natural from a theoretical point of view (“cosmological term of the field equations”).

Both of these hypotheses turned out to be consistent with the general theory of relativity, but only after a hypothetical term was added to the field equations, a term that wasn’t necessary according to the theory itself and didn’t seem logical from a theoretical standpoint (“cosmological term of the field equations”).

Hypothesis (2) appeared unavoidable to me at the time, since I thought that one would get into bottomless speculations if one departed from it.

Hypothesis (2) seemed unavoidable to me at the time because I believed that straying from it would lead to endless speculation.

However, already in the ’twenties, the Russian mathematician Friedman showed that a different hypothesis was natural from a purely theoretical point of view. He realized that it was possible to preserve hypothesis (1) without introducing the less natural cosmological term into the field equations of gravitation, if one was ready to drop hypothesis (2). Namely, the original field equations admit a solution in which the “world radius” depends on time (expanding space). In that sense one can say, according to Friedman, that the theory demands an expansion of space.

However, back in the ’20s, the Russian mathematician Friedman demonstrated that an alternative hypothesis was more natural from a strictly theoretical perspective. He understood that it was possible to maintain hypothesis (1) without adding the less natural cosmological term to the gravitational field equations, if one was willing to abandon hypothesis (2). Specifically, the original field equations allow for a solution in which the “world radius” changes over time (expanding space). In this way, Friedman argued that the theory requires the expansion of space.

A few years later Hubble showed, by a special investigation of the extra-galactic nebulae (“milky ways”), that the spectral lines emitted showed a red shift which increased regularly with the distance of the nebulae. This can be interpreted in regard to our present knowledge only in the sense of Doppler’s principle, as an expansive motion of the system of stars in the large—as required, according to Friedman, by the field equations of gravitation. Hubble’s discovery can, therefore, be considered to some extent as a confirmation of the theory.

A few years later, Hubble demonstrated through a detailed study of extra-galactic nebulae ("milky ways") that the spectral lines emitted showed a red shift that consistently increased with the distance of the nebulae. This can only be understood with our current knowledge in light of Doppler’s principle, indicating an expanding motion of the star system on a large scale—as required by the field equations of gravitation, according to Friedman. Hubble’s discovery can thus be seen as a partial confirmation of the theory.

There does arise, however, a strange difficulty. The interpretation of the galactic line-shift discovered by Hubble as an expansion (which can hardly be doubted from a theoretical point of view), leads to an origin of this expansion which lies “only” about 109 years ago, while physical astronomy makes it appear likely that the development of individual stars and systems of stars takes considerably longer. It is in no way known how this incongruity is to be overcome.

There is, however, a strange difficulty. The interpretation of the galactic line-shift discovered by Hubble as an expansion (which is hard to doubt from a theoretical perspective) suggests that this expansion originated “only” about 109 years ago, while physical astronomy indicates that the development of individual stars and star systems likely takes much longer. It is unclear how this contradiction can be resolved.

I further want to remark that the theory of expanding space, together with the empirical data of astronomy, permit no decision to be reached about the finite or infinite character of (three-dimensional) space, while the original “static” hypothesis of space yielded the closure (finiteness) of space.

I also want to point out that the theory of expanding space, along with the observational data from astronomy, doesn't allow us to decide if three-dimensional space is finite or infinite, while the original “static” hypothesis of space suggested that space is closed (finite).

K = co-ordinate system

K = coordinate system

x, y = two-dimensional co-ordinates

x, y = 2D coordinates

x, y, z = three-dimensional co-ordinates

x, y, z = 3D coordinates

x, y, z, t = four-dimensional co-ordinates

x, y, z, t = four-dimensional coordinates

t = time

t = time

I = distance

Distance

v = velocity

v = speed

F = force

F = force

G = gravitational field

G = gravity field


Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!